18
The pleasure principle: later developments

The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Page 2: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Utilitarianism: key scholars

Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)

John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)

Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

G. E. Moore (1873–1958)

Karl Popper (1902–1994)

Richard Brandt (1910–1997)

R. M. Hare (1919–2002)

Peter Singer (1946–)

Page 3: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Utilitarianism: key terms

Act utilitarianism

Consequentialist

Hedonic calculus

Hedonism

Ideal Utilitarianism

Interest Utilitarianism

Negative Utilitarianism

Preference utilitarianism

Principle of utility

Qualitative

Quantitative

Rule utilitarianism

Teleological

Universalisability

Page 4: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Henry Sidgwick (1)

Sidgwick argues that the balance of pleasure over pain is the ultimate goal of ethical

decisions.

His argument is closer to Bentham than to Mill, as he questions how it is possible to

distinguish between higher and lower order pleasures, and how we can distinguish

one higher order pleasure from another.

However, Sidgwick does argue that the process of deciding is intuitive — we make

self-evident judgements about what we ought to do.

Page 5: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Henry Sidgwick (2)

He argued that justice is the similar and injustice the dissimilar treatment of similar

cases: ‘whatever action any of us judges to be right for himself, he implicitly judges

to be right for all similar persons in similar circumstances.’

So it is wrong for person A to treat person B in a way in which it would be wrong for B

to treat A, simply on the grounds that they are two different individuals and without

there being any difference in their circumstances or their natures.

Saying that people must act according to just laws raises the issue of which laws are

just and sits uncomfortably with the principle of utility and the act utilitarian position.

Page 6: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Ideal utilitarianism

A utilitarian theory that denies that the sole object of moral concern is the

maximising of pleasure or happiness.

In G. E. Moore’s version of ideal utilitarianism in Principia Ethica (1903), it is

aesthetic experiences and relations of friendship that have intrinsic value, and

therefore ought to be sought and promoted.

Consciousness of pain, hatred or contempt of what is good or beautiful, and the love,

admiration or enjoyment of what is evil or ugly are the three things that have

intrinsic disvalue and should therefore be shunned and prevented.

It was Hastings Rashdall (1858–1924) in The Theory of Good and Evil (1907) who first

used ‘ideal utilitarianism’ for non-hedonistic utilitarianism of this kind.

Page 7: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Negative utilitarianism (1)

The term negative utilitarianism was coined by Sir Karl Popper.

The concept of negative utilitarianism was foreshadowed earlier, e.g. in the work of

Edmund Gurney (1847–88).

It has obvious affinity with Buddhism.

However, it has been argued that negative utilitarianism could lead to mass

euthanasia, although this implication has been disputed.

Popper’s ‘negative utilitarian’ principle is that we should act to minimise suffering

rather than maximise pleasure.

Classical utilitarian philosophers such as Sidgwick had explicitly argued for the moral

symmetry of happiness and suffering.

Complications aside, they supposed that increases in happiness, and reductions in

suffering, are essentially of equal value when of equal magnitude.

Page 8: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Negative utilitarianism (2)

Popper disagreed. He believed that the practical consequences of the supposed

moral symmetry were also dangerous:

‘Philosophers should consider the fact that the greatest happiness principle can

easily be made an excuse for a benevolent dictatorship. We should replace it by a

more modest and more realistic principle: the principle that the fight against

avoidable misery should be a recognized aim of public policy, while the increase of

happiness should be left, in the main, to private initiative.’

Page 9: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Negative utilitarianism (3)

‘I believe that there is, from the ethical point of view, no symmetry between

suffering and happiness, or between pain and pleasure.

Both the greatest happiness principle of the Utilitarians and Kant’s principle, promote

other people’s happiness…[and] seem to me (at least in their formulations)

fundamentally wrong in this point, which is, however, not one for rational argument…

In my opinion…human suffering makes a direct moral appeal for help, while there is

no similar call to increase the happiness of a man who is doing well anyway.’

Popper, K. (1952) The Open Society and Its Enemies

Page 10: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Negative utilitarianism (4)

Popper believed that by acting to minimise suffering, we avoid the terrible risks of

‘utopianism’, by which he had in mind the communist and fascist dictatorships of the

twentieth century.

‘Those who promise us paradise on earth never produced anything but a hell.’

A staunch advocate of the ‘open society’, Popper defended ‘piecemeal social

engineering’ rather than grandiose state planning.

Page 11: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Negative utilitarianism (5)

Ironically, the full realisation of a negative utilitarian ethic depends inescapably on

the ‘utopian’ planning that Popper abhorred.

Only a global bio-engineering project of unparalleled ambition could bring about the

eradication of suffering throughout the living world — not piecemeal social

engineering.

In seeking to liberate the world from the tyranny of pain, negative utilitarianism is no

less ‘totalitarian’ in its policy implications than communism or fascism, albeit vastly

more compassionate.

Page 12: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Preference utilitarianism

An act utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the maximising of pleasure

and minimising of pain.

A rule utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the keeping of rules derived

from utility.

A preference (or interest) utilitarian judges moral actions according to whether

they fit in with the preferences of the individuals involved. This approach to

utilitarianism asks:

‘What is in my own interest? What would I prefer in this situation? Which outcome

would I prefer?’

However, because utilitarianism aims to create the greatest good for the greatest

number, it is necessary to consider the preferences of others in order to achieve this.

Page 13: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

R. M. Hare

Hare argues that in moral decision making we need to consider our own preferences

and those of others: ‘equal preferences count equally, whatever their content.’

People are happy when they get what they prefer but this may clash with the

preferences of others.

Hare says we need to ‘stand in someone else’s shoes’ and try to imagine what

someone else might prefer.

We should treat everyone, including ourselves, with impartiality — he also argues for

universalisability.

Page 14: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Peter Singer

Singer suggests that people should take the viewpoint of an impartial spectator

combined with a broadly utilitarian approach.

‘Our own preferences cannot count any more than the preferences of others’ and so,

in acting morally, we should take account of all the people affected by our actions.

For Singer, the ‘best possible consequences’ means what is in the best interests of

the individuals concerned.

He is not considering what increases pleasure and diminishes pain.

This principle of equal consideration of preferences or interests acts like a pair of

scales — everyone’s preferences or interests are weighed equally.

Page 15: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Richard Brandt

Richard Brandt talks about the preferences someone would have if they had gone

through a process of cognitive psychotherapy and explored all the reasons for their

preferences and rejected any they felt were not true to their real values.

He argued that the morality someone would then accept would be a form of

utilitarianism — with their preferences free from any psychological blocks and them

in full possession of all the facts.

Such a person would not, therefore, be influenced by advertising.

Page 16: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Strengths of utilitarianism

It is straightforward and based on the single principle of minimising pain and

maximising pleasure and happiness.

It relates to actions that can be observed in the real world.

Its consequentialism is also a strength, as when we act it is only natural to weigh up

the consequences.

Utilitarianism’s acceptance of the universal principle is essential for any ethical

system.

The idea of promoting the ‘well-being’ of the greatest number is also important.

Preference utilitarianism also gives the valuable principle of being an impartial

observer. It is important to think about others’ interests or preferences as long as

one also includes behaving justly.

Page 17: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Weaknesses of utilitarianism (1)

It is good to consider the consequences of our actions, but these are difficult to

predict with any accuracy.

Utilitarianism can also be criticised because it seems to ignore the importance of

duty. An act may be right or wrong for reasons other than the amount of good or evil

it produces.

Utilitarianism can also advocate injustice.

Another weakness is the emphasis on pleasure or happiness. If I seek my own

happiness it is impossible for me to seek general happiness and to do what I ought to

do.

Page 18: The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)

The pleasure principle: later developments

Weaknesses of utilitarianism (2)

The qualitative and quantitative approaches pose problems, as all we can really do is

guess the units of pleasure — how do we measure one pleasure against another?

Utilitarianism does not consider motives and intentions and so rejects the principle of

treating people with intrinsic value. Utilitarianism can be seen as too impersonal and

does not consider the rights of individuals in its attempt to look for the ‘greater

good’.