50
Utilitarianism Jon Mayled

Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) G.E

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Utilitarianism

Jon Mayled

Page 2: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Utilitarianism – Key Scholars

Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) G.E. Moore (1873 –1958) Karl Popper (1902 –1994) Richard Brandt (1910–1997) R.M. Hare (1919–2002) Peter Singer (1946– )

Page 3: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Utilitarianism – Key Terms Act Utilitarianism Consequentialist Hedonic calculus Hedonism Ideal Utilitarianism Interest

Utilitarianism Negative

Utilitarianism

Preference Utilitarianism

Principle of utility Qualitative Quantitative Rule Utilitarianism Teleological Universalisability

Page 4: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

The School of Athens - Raphael

Page 5: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Hedonism The idea that ‘good’ is defined in terms

of pleasure and happiness makes utilitarianism a hedonistic theory.

Plato and Aristotle both agreed that ‘good’ equated with the greatest happiness, while the Epicureans stressed ‘pleasure’ as the main aim of life.

The ultimate end of human desires and actions, according to Aristotle, is happiness and though pleasure sometimes accompanies this, it is not the chief aim of life.

Pleasure is not the same as happiness, as happiness results from the use of reason and cultivating the virtues. It is only if we take pleasure in good activities that pleasure itself is good.

Page 6: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Jeremy Bentham

Page 7: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Bentham According to Bentham, the most moral acts

are those that maximise pleasure and minimise pain. This has sometimes been called the ‘utilitarian calculus’. An act would be moral if it brings the greatest amount of pleasure and the least amount of pain.

Bentham said: ‘An act is right if it delivers more pleasure than pain and wrong if it brings about more pain than pleasure.’

By adding up the amounts of pleasure and pain for each possible act we should be able to choose the good thing to do.

Happiness = pleasure minus pain

Page 8: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Bentham – the Hedonic Calculus 1 the intensity of the pleasure

(how deep) 2 the duration of the pleasure

caused (how long) 3 the certainty of the pleasure

(how certain or uncertain) 4 the remoteness of the pleasure

(how near or far) 5 the chance of a succession of

pleasures (how continuous) 6 the purity of the pleasure (how

secure) 7 the extent of the pleasure (how

universal).

Page 9: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Bentham’s Utility Bentham’s Utilitarianism is a universal

hedonism – the highest good is the greatest happiness for the greatest number.

Actions are judged as a means to an end. What is right is that which is calculated to bring

about the greatest balance of good over evil, where good is defined as pleasure or happiness.

Bentham’s view is described as Act Utilitarianism.

Bentham argued that we should be guided by the principle of utility and not by rules.

Page 10: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Act Utilitarianism

What would be the problems if everyone acted as an Act Utilitarian all the time?

Are all actions only good because they have good results?

Page 11: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

John Stuart Mill

Page 12: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Greatest Happiness Principle Mill said: ‘The Greatest Happiness Principle holds

that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain and the privation of pleasure.’

‘Some kinds of pleasures are more desirable and more valuable than others, it would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is not also considered as well as quantity.’

Here Mill differs from Bentham’s quantitative approach.

Page 13: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Quality of Pleasure According to Mill, quality of pleasure employs the

use of the higher faculties. He is answering the objection to Bentham’s

approach that utilitarians are just pleasure-seekers.

Mill says that the quality of pleasure that satisfies a human is different from that which satisfies an animal. People are capable of more than animals, so it takes more to make a human happy.

Therefore, a person will always choose higher quality, human pleasures, and reject all the merely animal pleasures.

Page 14: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Quality of Pleasure Few human creatures would consent to be

changed into any of the lower animals for a promise of the fullest allowance of the beast’s pleasures.

…It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool or the pig are of a different opinion, it is because they only know their side of the question.

Page 15: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Questions: Suppose a surgeon could use the organs of one

healthy patient to save the lives of several others. Would the surgeon be justified in killing the healthy patient for the sake of the others?

You are an army officer who has just captured an enemy soldier who knows where a secret time bomb is planted. If it explodes it will kill thousands. Will it be morally permissible to torture the soldier so that he reveals the bomb’s location? If you knew where the soldier’s children were, would it also be permissible to torture them to get him to reveal the bomb’s whereabouts?

Page 16: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Universalisability Mill says that in order to derive the principle of

the greatest good (happiness) for the greatest number we need the principle of universalisability.

He says: ‘Each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, is a good to the aggregate of all persons.’

This means: What is right or wrong for one person in a situation is

right or wrong for all. Each person desires his own happiness. Therefore

each person ought to aim at his happiness. Therefore everyone ought to aim at the happiness of

everyone.

Page 17: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Universalisability To move from each person to everyone is a fallacy. Mill makes this move because he wants to justify

‘the greatest number’. This can mean that Utilitarianism demands that

people put the interests of the group before their own interests, and Mill compares this to the Golden Rule of Jesus of Nazareth. ‘In everything do to others as you would have them do to

you; for this is the law and the prophets.’ (Matthew 7:12) Mill also separates the question of the motive and

the morality of the action. There is nothing wrong with self-interest if it produces the right action.

Page 18: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Rule Utilitarianism Another aspect of Mill’s approach is the idea

that there need to be some moral rules in order to establish social order and justice – but the rules should be those which, if followed universally, would most likely produce the greatest happiness.

Mill has been seen as a Rule Utilitarian in contrast to Bentham’s Act Utilitarianism – though Mill never discussed Act or Rule Utilitarianism in these terms.

Page 19: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Bentham v. Mill

Page 20: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Bentham v. Mill

Page 21: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Act v. Rule Utilitarianism The distinction is to do with what the principle

of utility is applied to.

According to Act Utilitarianism the principle is applied directly to a particular action in a particular circumstance.

According to Rule Utilitarianism the principle is applied to a selection of a set of rules which are in turn used to determine what to do in particular situations.

Page 22: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Act Utilitarianism

Page 23: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Weaknesses of Act Utilitarianism It is difficult to predict the consequences.

There is the potential to justify any act.

There is difficulty in defining pleasure.

There is no defence for minorities.

It is impractical to say that we should calculate the morality of each choice.

Page 24: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Rule Utilitarianism

Page 25: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Weak & Strong Rule Utilitarianism Rule Utilitarianism enables us to establish rules

which will promote the happiness of humanity and will generally be right in most circumstances (e.g. telling the truth, keeping your promises).

Strong Rule Utilitarians believe that these derived rules should never be disobeyed.

Weak Rule Utilitarians say that although there should be generally accepted rules or guidelines, they should not always be adhered to indefinitely. There may be situations where the better consequence might be achieved by disregarding the rule.

Page 26: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Weaknesses of Rule Utilitarianism It is difficult to predict the consequences. It is difficult to define what constitutes happiness. There is no defence for minorities. To invoke rules means that the approach

becomes deontological not teleological. Followers of Rule Utilitarianism can either be strict

rule-followers or rule-modifiers. Strict rule-followers can be irrational: obeying the

rule even when disobeying it will produce more happiness.

Rule-modifiers can end up being no different from Act Utilitarians.

Page 27: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Henry Sidgwick

Page 28: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Henry Sidgwick Sidgwick argues that the balance of pleasure

over pain is the ultimate goal of ethical decisions.

His argument is closer to Bentham than to Mill, as he questions how it is possible to distinguish between higher and lower order pleasures, and how we can distinguish one higher order pleasure from another.

However, Sidgwick does argue that the process of deciding is intuitive – we make self-evident judgements about what we ought to do.

Page 29: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Henry Sidgwick He argued that justice is the similar and injustice

the dissimilar treatment of similar cases: ‘whatever action any of us judges to be right for himself, he implicitly judges to be right for all similar persons in similar circumstances’.

So it is wrong for person A to treat person B in a way in which it would be wrong for B to treat A, simply on the grounds that they are two different individuals and without there being any difference in their circumstances or their natures.

Saying that people must act according to just laws raises the issue of which laws are just and sits uncomfortably with the principle of utility and the Act Utilitarian position.

Page 30: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

G.E. Moore

Page 31: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Ideal Utilitarianism A Utilitarian theory which denies that the sole

object of moral concern is the maximising of pleasure or happiness.

In G.E. Moore’s version of Ideal Utilitarianism in Principia Ethica 1903, it is aesthetic experiences and relations of friendship that have intrinsic value, and therefore ought to be sought and promoted.

Consciousness of pain, hatred or contempt of what is good or beautiful, and the love, admiration or enjoyment of what is evil or ugly are the three things that have intrinsic disvalue and should therefore be shunned and prevented.

Page 32: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Ideal Utilitarianism

It was Hastings Rashdall (1858-1924) in The Theory of Good and Evil (1907) who first used ‘ideal utilitarianism’ for non-hedonistic utilitarianism of this kind.

Page 33: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism

Page 34: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism The term Negative Utilitarianism was coined

by Sir Karl Popper. The concept of negative utilitarianism was

foreshadowed earlier e.g. in the work of Edmund Gurney (1847-88).

It has obvious affinity with Buddhism. However, it has been argued that Negative

Utilitarianism could lead to mass euthanasia, although this implication has been disputed.

Page 35: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism Popper’s ‘negative utilitarian’ principle is that

we should act to minimise suffering rather than maximise pleasure.

Classical utilitarian philosophers such as Sidgwick had explicitly argued for the moral symmetry of happiness and suffering.

Complications aside, they supposed that increases in happiness, and reductions in suffering, are essentially of equal value when of equal magnitude.

Page 36: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism Popper disagreed. He believed that the practical consequences of

the supposed moral symmetry were also dangerous.

“Philosophers should consider the fact that the greatest happiness principle can easily be made an excuse for a benevolent dictatorship. We should replace it by a more modest and more realistic principle: the principle that the fight against avoidable misery should be a recognized aim of public policy, while the increase of happiness should be left, in the main, to private initiative.”

Page 37: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism “I believe that there is, from the ethical point of view,

no symmetry between suffering and happiness, or between pain and pleasure.

Both the greatest happiness principle of the Utilitarians and Kant’s principle, promote other people’s happiness..., [and] seem to me (at least in their formulations) fundamentally wrong in this point, which is, however, not one for rational argument....

In my opinion... human suffering makes a direct moral appeal for help, while there is no similar call to increase the happiness of a man who is doing well anyway.”

Karl Popper (The Open Society and Its Enemies, 1952)

Page 38: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism Popper believed that by acting to minimise

suffering, we avoid the terrible risks of ‘utopianism’, by which he had in mind the communist and fascist dictatorships of the twentieth century. “Those who promise us paradise on earth never

produced anything but a hell.” A staunch advocate of the ‘open society’,

Popper defended ‘piecemeal social engineering’ rather than grandiose state planning.

Page 39: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Negative Utilitarianism Ironically, the full realisation of a negative

utilitarian ethic depends inescapably on the ‘utopian’ planning that Popper abhorred.

Only a global bio-engineering project of unparalleled ambition could bring about the eradication of suffering throughout the living world - not piecemeal social engineering.

In seeking to liberate the world from the tyranny of pain, Negative Utilitarianism is no less ‘totalitarian’ in its policy implications than communism or fascism, albeit vastly more compassionate.

Page 40: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Preference Utilitarianism

Singer Hare Brandt

Page 41: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Preference Utilitarianism An Act Utilitarian judges right or wrong according

to the maximising of pleasure and minimising of pain.

A Rule Utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the keeping of rules derived from utility.

A Preference (or Interest) Utilitarian judges moral actions according to whether they fit in with the preferences of the individuals involved. This approach to Utilitarianism asks: What is in my own interest? What would I prefer in this

situation? Which outcome would I prefer?’ However, because Utilitarianism aims to create the greatest good for the greatest number, it is necessary to consider the preferences of others in order to achieve this.

Page 42: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

R M Hare Hare argues that in moral decision-making we

need to consider our own preferences and those of others. ‘equal preferences count equally, whatever their

content’. People are happy when they get what they prefer

but this may clash with the preferences of others. Hare says we need to ‘stand in someone else’s

shoes’ and try to imagine what someone else might prefer.

We should treat everyone, including ourselves, with impartiality – he also argues for universalisability.

Page 43: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Peter Singer Singer suggests that people should take the viewpoint

of an impartial spectator combined with a broadly utilitarian approach.

‘Our own preferences cannot count any more than the preferences of others’ and so, in acting morally, we should take account of all the people affected by our actions.

For Singer, the ‘best possible consequences’ means what is in the best interests of the individuals concerned.

He is not considering what increases pleasure and diminishes pain.

This principle of equal consideration of preferences or interests acts like a pair of scales – everyone’s preferences or interests are weighed equally.

Page 44: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Richard Brandt Richard Brandt talks about the preferences

someone would have if they had gone through a process of cognitive psychotherapy and explored all the reasons for their preferences and rejected any they felt were not true to their real values.

He argued that the morality someone would then accept would be a form of Utilitarianism – with their preferences free from any psychological blocks and them in full possession of all the facts.

Such a person would not, therefore, be influenced by advertising.

Page 45: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Does it work?

Page 46: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Strengths of Utilitarianism It is straightforward and based on the single principle

of minimising pain and maximising pleasure and happiness.

It relates to actions which can be observed in the real world.

Its consequentialism is also a strength, as when we act it is only natural to weigh up the consequences.

Utilitarianism’s acceptance of the universal principle is essential for any ethical system.

The idea of promoting the ‘well-being’ of the greatest number is also important.

Preference Utilitarianism also gives the valuable principle of being an impartial observer. It is important to think about others’ interests or preferences as long as one also includes behaving justly.

Page 47: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Weaknesses of Utilitarianism It is good to consider the consequences of our

actions, but these are difficult to predict with any accuracy.

Utilitarianism can also be criticised because it seems to ignore the importance of duty. An act may be right or wrong for reasons other than the amount of good or evil it produces.

Utilitarianism can also advocate injustice. Another weakness is the emphasis on pleasure

or happiness. If I seek my own happiness it is impossible for me to seek general happiness and to do what I ought to do.

Page 48: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Weaknesses of Utilitarianism The qualitative and quantitative approaches

pose problems, as all we can really do is guess the units of pleasure – how do we measure one pleasure against another?

Utilitarianism does not consider motives and intentions and so rejects the principle of treating people with intrinsic value. Utilitarianism can be seen as too impersonal and does not consider the rights of individuals in its attempt to look for the ‘greater good’.

Page 49: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Summary

Utilitarianism has some major weaknesses as far as duty, justice, motives, intentions and consequences are concerned, and the principles of ‘the greatest good for the greatest number’ and ‘treating people as a means to an end’ are rather dubious moral principles.

Page 50: Utilitarianism Jon Mayled. Utilitarianism – Key Scholars  Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)  John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)  Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)  G.E

Utilitarianism