Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    1/24

    R. van der Pluijm

    The organisational studies?

    Solving the unification of the potential pluralistic concept of organisation

    For thousands of years, man had to work for a living and therefore had to live in an organisation.

    This fact hasn't changed a bit since. However, the type of work we have to do and the number of

    people working together in a group have been increasing since the industrial revolution. Therefore,

    it is not strange that people developed an academic discipline about people working, which is called

    organisation theory or organisational studies. Still, even though the total labour force of the world

    exceeds three billion people, there is little to few philosophical literature to be found on this topic.

    Adam Smith, who is regarded as more of an economist than as a philosopher, wrote on the topic in

    his hallmarkThe Wealth of Nations, in which he discusses the division of labour and suggests tobase a new form of organisational structure based on labour. Then, it took until the late nineteenth

    century until Max Weber wrote on rational organisations.

    From the 1920s onwards, organisation theory became a separate discipline. Although philosophers

    of science haven't paid much attention to the field of organisation theory, this doesn't mean nothing

    has been written on this topic. Especially since the 1970s, a lot of change has been brought to this

    field of study. From functionalist theories, via ecological and institutional theories to postmodern

    theories, a diverse field of methods to describe organisations have emerged. As within the

    philosophy of science, there is a large debate regarding explanatory value and the nature of an

    organisation within these theories. One important question within this debate is the paradigm

    incommensurability thesis: it is possible to join these theories regarding organisations, even though

    they seem to conflict with each other under some circumstances? I think philosophers of science

    can bring new structure into the ongoing debate, which has developed from a wide range of

    scholars, not in the least the continental, post-structural philosophers such as Michel Foucault and

    Jacques Derrida (Clegg & Hardy, 1999). The discussion within the philosophy of social science

    regarding interpretativism versus causalism (Kincaid, 2002), naturalism versus anti-naturalism and

    holism versus individualism will help to realise the grave differences between these theories and

    will help us to look at the paradigm incommensurability thesis, which is basically a question about

    the unity of organisational studies.

    My goal will be to, by placing the organisational debate within the framework of the philosophy of

    science on explanation, show how we can unify the organisational studies by appealing to a

    Wittgensteinian interpretation of the concept of organisation for a pluralistic conception of

    organisation.

    -1-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    2/24

    R. van der Pluijm A short introduction into organisation theory

    The article will follow the following structure. Before any analysis is made, there will be a

    preliminary introduction into organisation theory, to insure the reader will be able to follow the

    actual analysis. Here, I will not explain these theories in-depth, but will simply give an introductory

    description in order to understand the existence of the paradigm incommensurability debate: how

    can organisation theory as a discipline see multiple competing schools of thought all as valid

    theories?

    Second, I will be looking at each of the main focusses within the debate, drawing upon an

    distinction of meta-narratives of Rationality, Integration, Market, Power, Knowledge and Justice.

    When then the stage is set, it is time to move on towards an analysis of the discussion. I will place

    the debate by the organisational studies within the framework of the philosophy of social science,

    describing the position of the six meta-narratives into the debates on naturalism vs anti-naturalism,

    interpretativism vs causalism and holism vs individualism. The strong theoretical differences and

    aims will be shown by these debates.

    To analyse the paradigm incommensurability debate, I will draw an analogy with the current

    debates in the philosophy about causation. Within the debates of causation, there are interesting

    points made about monism, pluralism and concept-pluralism, which are pretty much the same

    positions as defended in the organisational studies.

    Afterwards, I will suggest another conception of an organisation, drawing on Wittgenstein's notion

    of family resemblance. This will enlighten why some of the theories are seemingly incompatible

    and will also show why we should look at the domain of the question to determine which field is

    appropriate.

    A short introduction into organisation theory

    I will largely base this introduction on the introductory article for Studying organizations: theory

    and method by Stewart R. Clegg and Cynthia Hardy (Clegg & Hardy, 1999). Their article focusses

    on the debates in organization theory from the last hundred years, paying most attention to the last

    thirty. It will provide us with a basic notion of the debate and will set the stage enough to in order to

    be able to discuss the basic conception of an explanation within the organisational studies.

    Organisation theory is interested in determining the nature of an organisation, looks at factors

    influencing this nature and tries to determine the most effective way to organise a group of people.

    Nowadays, a number of these theories aim at commercial firms, but this is not necessary the case,

    since it is possible to look at other types of organisations e.g. the organisation within prisons and

    governments. Topics of study include (but are not limited to) the influence of leadership, the

    -2-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    3/24

    R. van der Pluijm A short introduction into organisation theory

    distribution of power, the influence of culture, the effectiveness of hierarchical structures, business

    strategies and communication intra- and intercompany. One basic assumption in this theory is the

    orderly and unitary nature of the organisation1. Here, the organisation is a rational decision

    making system, based on consensus and coherence. The task of a researcher then is to collect

    objective data concerning the way organization functions around goal orientation and

    maintenance. Typically, the research method follows the normal science model, in which the nature

    of organizational reality is represented and expressed through a formal research design;

    quantitative data facilitate validation, reliability and replicability; a steady accumulation and

    building of empirically generated knowledge derives from a limited number of theoretical

    assumptions.2Organisation theory tries to simulate the empirical sciences in a fashion comparable

    to sociology and economy.

    The paragraph I wrote above would be a standard description if we would currently be living in the

    beginning of the 1970s. It is the method as ascribed by the so-called functionalist and normal

    science research methods, under which population ecology, organisational economics and

    contingency theory among others fall3. However, as noted above, academics in the organisational

    studies have radically changed their view on their own field of study since then. From different

    angles the rationality claims were attacked. The first attacks came from within the scientific

    schools4

    themselves, arguing for a 'bounded rationality' conception (Gigerenzer, 2006) and an

    ecological view on organisation. Later attacks even attacked the scientific method itself. From one

    side the socio-psychological attack from both the Marxist and the post-modernist (such as Foucault,

    Derrida and Lyotard) attacked the rationality status of the individual (and the post-modernist on

    their account also attacked the Marxist universal claim).

    Clegg and Hardy after discussing the attacks described above, discuss how, by emphasising these

    features of an organisation, it wasn't at all clear what organisation theory as an academic discipline

    encompasses. One major consequence

    5

    of these differences was the so-called 'paradigmincommensurability' of the different theories. It meant that, while all these different theories have

    different forms of explanations, in an ideal world all these theories should lead to the same advice

    when used by consultants in social praxis. More specifically, paradigm incommensurability argues

    that theories are by definition either subjective or objective in approach and researchers should

    1 Clegg & Hardy 1999, p1.

    2 Clegg & Hardy 1999, p2.

    3 Ibid idem.

    4 i.e. schools which argue for the same methods as within the sociological and economical sciences, i.e. 'number

    crunching'.5 Clegg & Hardy 1999, p5. Cf the 2005 paper by Michael Reed for an example (Reed, 2005)

    -3-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    4/24

    R. van der Pluijm A short introduction into organisation theory

    therefore choose between these theories (Willmott, 1993). Three different standpoints were

    defended. One group found this incommensurability unacceptable, and tried, through the use of

    sophisticated philosophical and linguistic discourse6 to solve the issue. The second group argued

    for high standards, even called quasi-religious in the literature7, for any bridge over the paradigm

    gap, while the third saw this as an argument against the new interpretative accounts of organisation

    theory: if they cannot be matched with the conventional accounts, they are simply wrong.

    These new theories about organisations own their existence upon three main changes within

    organisations that Clegg and Hardy discuss. First, they emphasise the transition from bureaucracy to

    networks or clusters. No longer large companies have a centralised hierarchy 8, but they choose for

    cooperation, building intra-organisational networks to ensure demand and supply, but also ensuring

    growth and quality control in order to enter the network itself. Specialised tasks are often

    outsourced at companies within the network itself. Even great firms have to choose to decentralise

    in order to ensure the knowledge base and total quality management. Second, due to this

    decentralisation, new technologies become essential to handle the large amount of information,

    which is to be distributed along the internal network. Last, the importance of the hierarchy changes:

    These organizations are characterized by openness, trust, empowerment and commitment [...]

    collaborative, open decision-making eliminates the inefficiency of traditional hierarchical styles of

    secrecy, sycophany and sabotage.9

    As shown above, organisation theory is a large landscape of different theories, all emphasising

    certain aspects of organisations. Now that we've seen the general history of organisation theory and

    a description of the incommensurability debate, we can have a closer look at the prominent theories

    in the organisational studies themselves.

    Six groups of organisation theories

    In order to group the different organisation theories, I will draw on an interesting paper by Michael

    Reed (Reed, 1999), in which he divides the theories in six different narratives10: Rationality,

    Integration, Market, Power, Knowledge and Justice. But first, Reed introduces a preliminary

    discussion in which the importance of historical and social contexts is stressed. These contexts were

    also discussed above where new insights from other disciplines was influential on the forming of

    6 Ibid idem.

    7 Ibid idem. But see also Willmott 1993, p 681, who maintains that this group actually wanted to keep the paradigm

    incommensurability alive.

    8 Clegg & Hardy 1999, p10.

    9 Ibid idem.10 Reed 1999, p28.

    -4-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    5/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    new theories. These contexts are essential to understand the development of these theories. Reed

    even goes further, stating that [I]n short, theory making is a historically located intellectual

    practice directed at assembling and mobilizing ideational, material and institutional resources to

    legitimate certain knowledge claims and the political projects which flow from them.11 His

    argument is that theory making is strongly rhetorical in nature. There is no link to conceptual

    appropriateness or truthfulness. However, Reed stresses that this doesn't mean we do not have any

    method to analyse all these theories, since we would lack a recognized, collective basis12 Instead,

    although we only have a grounded rationality of negotiated rules and norms which do not

    have the same universal claim which we think to have in the natural sciences, but it nontheless

    establishes a identifiable framework of procedures and practices 'that provide for their own

    relevant discourse about proof'13. What remains then are shared, although revisable,

    methodological procedures by which the meta-narratives and their theories can be discussed and

    negotiated14.

    After these preliminaries, it is time for the qualification Reed and others (Morgan and Stanley) use

    to divide the discipline in six meta-narratives.

    Historically, the first theories that developed focussed on rationality. In this classical organisation

    theory model, developed around the 1900s, organisations are rational human constructs which

    should be able to control human social uproar. The main thought behind this is that organisations

    place individuals into a framework of socio-economic location, authority and behaviour15. In

    other words, dividing workforce is what an organisation consists of. The solution for this division is

    an effective administration, which is researched using empirical tests to determine social laws.

    Here, social research is modelled after the natural sciences: through controlled environments, we

    can establish rules about the effectiveness of various forms of bureaucracy which should lead to

    higher efficiency. This view takes the concept of 'Human Resource' quite literally and therebydismisses any questions regarding emotions or values of the workforce16. More specifically, these

    morals will have to be [...] transformed into engineering tasks amenable to technical solutions

    [...].17

    11 Ibid, p27, emphasis added.

    12 Ibid idem.

    13 Ibid idem.

    14 Reed 1999, p27.

    15 Ibid, p29.

    16 Herbert Simon paraphrased this in the following way: [The] rational individual is, and must be, an organised and

    institutionalized individual. (Reed, 1999, p29)17 Reed, p29

    -5-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    6/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    Another striking fact of this theory of organisation is its strong anti-democratic tendencies. Once the

    basics of the organisation are established based on the scientific laws which are grounded on

    research, no political or moral debate can amend this theory to make it more adapted to the values

    we have.

    While newer forms of organisation theory within this meta-narrative attacked the rationalising

    methods by introducing the concept of 'bounded rationality', this doesn't mean that certain features

    of an organisation which were dismissed by the classical organisation theories, such as culture,

    morality and emotions, were rehabilitated. According to the bounded rationality thesis, these are all

    [...]random, extraneous variables beyond the influence, much less control, of rational cognitive

    processes and organizational procedures18. It did change the role for experts interpretations: any

    role for these results is taken over by 'heuristics', rules by which an bounded rational agent should

    act. The organisation structure should be formed to accommodate these heuristics. Since all humans

    use some package of heuristics, these are enough to explain behaviour and to structure the

    organisation. In short, this type of organisation theory took away the intuitive craft andchanged

    it into a codified and analyzable body of knowledge that traded on the immensely powerful

    cultural capital and symbolism of 'science'.19

    As a reaction to the deterministic character of the classical organisation theory, a more evolutionary

    or organicistic theory, focussed on integration, was presented in the 1940s and 1950s. Also, it was

    again a reaction to the rationalistic character as presented in the classical organisation theories. For

    the organicists, an organisation can be seen as a bridge law(Kincaid, 1997) between mass sociology

    and the individual. It was again seen as a method [...] to address the problem of social integration

    and the implications for the maintenance of social order in a more stable and uncertain world. 20

    The organicists sought not to develop a theory from outside or above, but instead in accordance

    with the wishes and the needs of the working class. It strived actively for a feeling of community

    21

    .This communal feeling is also emphasised by Reed when he talks about what is understood by an

    organicist as an effective organisation: The 'good' society and the effective organisation are

    defined in relation to their capacity to facilitate and sustain the socio-psychological reality of

    spontaneous cooperation and social stability in the face of economic, political and technological

    18 Ibid, p30.

    19 Reed 1999, p30.

    20 Reed 1999, p30.21 Ibid idem.

    -6-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    7/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    changes that threaten the integration of the individual and the group into the wider community. 22

    This meant that the organisation was actually seen analogous to an organism. The organisational

    structures where therefore not strict and determined, but rather spontaneous. Just as in evolutionary

    theory an animal adapts to its environment, the structure of the organisation changes in order to

    preserve the equilibrium, which is the situation in which there is social stability and spontaneous

    cooperation. The focus of empirical research is therefore put on these spontaneous emergent and

    normatively sanctioned structures in the organisation.23

    From the combination of both classical organisation theory and this organicist theory came about

    the most dominant theory probably until now: the functionalist theory. Structural functionalism

    argued for two approaches, one internalistic which was focussed on organisational design and one

    externalistic which was focussed on environmental uncertainty 24. The correct combination of these

    two factors should lead to stability and growth. This method makes it possible to explain and

    control 'both its internal dynamics and its institutional consequences25. Note that within

    functionalist theory, other than the organicist theory, still the old assumptions regarding morals and

    values reside: functionalist theory assumes that it is possible to reduce these feelings to technical

    problems which can be solved through effective organisational design. Underneath this lies an

    assumption ofvalue homogeneity: as all people within an organisation have the same morals and

    values, these can be incorporated as one value into the system26

    . The above named contingency

    theory is a development of the functionalist theory, which focusses on managerial ethics, which

    should be able to solve any of the political or institutional issues left.27

    Where the classical organisation theory tried to calculate in terms of workload, the market

    perspective tries to explain how the assumption of neo-classical economics, in which, due to the

    rationality of individual agents and the market mechanisms itself (such as supplies and demand),

    why organisations exist as they have no role in a system with such mechanisms and agents.However, it was realised that this was an ideal realisation. The new role for organisations was

    placed in the reduction of transaction costs: organisations are seen in this view as mediators for

    naturally inclined suspicious trade partners28. As Reed notes, the conception of agents is still

    22 Ibid, p31.

    23 Ibid idem.

    24 Ibid idem.

    25 Ibid, p32.

    26 Reed 1999, p32.

    27 Ibid idem.28 Ibid, p33.

    -7-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    8/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    'boundedly' rational here. So, the only striving for individuals in an organisation is cost

    effectiveness and efficiency, and organisations are seen as 'organically' in the sense that they try to

    adapt to their environment. In sum, [O]rganisations are an automatic response to[...] the need for

    formally free and equal economic agents to negotiate and monitor contracts in complex market

    transactions which cannot be accommodated in existing institutional arrangements.29

    Like the structure theory, market theories do pay attention to social power struggles, albeit highly

    abstract. More specifically, the whole organisation has the same values and social order, which

    means that there can be no internal moral or power struggles.

    All the former theories choose to either neglect social and moral values, to reduce these values to

    marginal uncertainty factors or to control them by designing a power distribution. The following

    theories reject the view that power struggles and / or social and moral values can be reduced or

    neglected. The first of these theories focus on power and are mostly based on the social theories on

    dominance and distribution of power by Weber and Machiavelli and later by Foucault30. The neo-

    Weberian analysis is aimed at describing the interaction between societies and organisations and

    their role in producing power structures. The Foucaultian influence can be seen when looking at the

    micro-political processes which compete with established regimes, which is illuminating in its

    perspective on detailed processes. However, it isn't as fit to describe existing, broadly based

    organisational mechanisms, should these be incorporated in the existing rhetorics. One of the aims

    of these theories is to give a typology of the different forms of power. One example is the difference

    between 'manipulative power' and 'hegemonic power'. The former is the use of 'backdoor politics'

    by already powerful groups, which is meant to remove from the agenda items which are against the

    interest of the group in question. The latter aims at protecting the existing values in consulting,

    which limits the interests and thus choices which can be made31.

    One specific problem with which these theory have to deal with is the relation between powerstruggles on organisational level and the power struggles on individual level. This has been

    attempted by focussing on the middle level, by which sectoral levels mediate between governmental

    policies and the implementation on local domains. What still remains is the [...] explanatory

    range of a power framework with limited capacity to deal with the material, cultural and political

    complexities of organizational change.32

    29 Ibid idem.

    30 Ibid, p34.

    31 Reed 1999, p35.32 Ibid idem.

    -8-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    9/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    Based on the works of the French postmodernists, the knowledge meta-narrative focusses on the

    'totalitarian' claim by the first three theories. They attack the universal claim both by these theorists

    and by theories interested in power such as Marxism. Instead, they see organisations as susceptible

    to internal decay, seeing them as contingent and unstable institutional practice. Universality is

    replaced by contingency in both the knowledge about our organisations as for the organisations

    themselves. No ontological status is reserved for both of them. The modern organisations are seen

    as the result of temporary negotiations. Further, explanation is not aimed at traditional powers such

    as class and state, but instead cultural and technical mechanisms are emphasised.

    In total, [...] 'organization' becomes a portable carrier of the socio-technical knowledge and skills

    through which particular patterns of social relationships emerge and reproduce themselves in

    specific material and social circumstances.33

    It should be noted that many different forms of postmodernist theories exist. Roughly, two

    categories can be distinguished (Kildutt and Mehra, 1997). The first, called the 'sceptical

    postmodernists' focus on critiquing the other theories instead of offering an alternative to the

    empirical sciences. The second, more moderate form, called the 'affirmative postmodernists', think

    one can distinguish between good and bad theories. It [..] would underscore novelty and reflexity

    as it looks to the richness of difference and concentrates on the unusual, the singular and the

    original.

    In a reaction on this decentralised postmodern position, new institutionalists reacted by stressing the

    organisation as an institutional structure where power and authority resides. They also attack the

    'rationality myths', lay focus on cognitive and cultural explanations, and have [...] an interest in

    properties of supraindividual units of analysis that cannot be reduced to aggregations or direct

    consequences of individuals' attributes or motives.34 Next to these cultural explanations,

    structural, historical and contextual positioning of the groups values and interests instead of themicrolevel practices are being stressed. Still, we do have to account for the personal level interests.

    The analytical and the political, the local and the global aspects of organisation have to be

    connected in order to do justice to the complex of organisations present in the uncertain world. In

    Reed's words, The analytical structured narrative of organizational justice and democracy seeks

    to reconnect the study of locally contextualized discourses and practices with institutionalized

    orders of power, authority and control which have a societal rationale and historical dynamic that

    33 Ibid, p36.34 Ibid, p37.

    -9-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    10/24

    R. van der Pluijm Six groups of organisation theories

    cannot be understood, much less explained, through a limited focus on 'everyday' interaction and

    event. It forces us to rediscover the vital link between practical demands and intellectual needs of

    the study of organisations [].

    This last sentence is interesting, while it implicitly raises an objection against organisation theories

    which focus only on the theoretical demands of the academic. As organisations are social practices

    we not only encounter in everyday life, but which we also try to manipulate and make perfect, this

    can be read as some sort of moral request that we should try not to lose the connection with the

    practical.

    In the above, a description is given of the large number of theories which comprise the discipline of

    organisation theory. It is now time to look at the debates in the philosophy of science an link the

    meta-narratives to these debates. One thing that we should keep in mind are the radically different

    approaches which have been argued for. The paradigm incommensurability which was mentioned in

    the last paragraph can be very well understood when one looks at these different approaches. This

    surely will influence the debates on reductionism, but also the other discussions which are prevalent

    in the philosophy of social science.

    Paradigm irreductionismLet us first look at some of the general discussions going on in the philosophy of social science,

    which has been done by Kincaid in his 2002 paper (Kincaid, 2002). In this paper, Kincaid

    distinguishes four different issues which are currently discussed in this discipline35:

    Naturalism versus. antinaturalism: can and should social science use the same criteria as the

    natural sciences for explanations, and, related, may we give social science the same status as

    the social sciences?

    Interpretativism versus. causalism: when the social sciences try to explain phenomena, can

    they do this the same way as the natural sciences do, i.e. 'causal explanation' or 'quantitative

    explanation' or should we opt for another method, such as interpretations?

    Instrumentalism versus. realism: do the concepts and models in the social sciences refer to

    objective features in the real world or is this connection rather loose, i.e. do these models

    have but an illuminating value?

    35 Kincaid 2002, p291.

    -10-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    11/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    Holism versus. individualism: is it possible to have the same explanatory value when we

    speak in terms of individuals instead of in irreducible social entities?

    I will discuss three of these as they are relevant to the paradigm incommensurability debate. These

    are the naturalism versus anti-naturalism, the interpretationalism versus causalism and the holism

    versus individualism debate. While the instrumentalism versus realism debate is interesting, it

    focusses mainly on the role of social science for researchers and doesn't as much tell us anything

    about the content of explanations and the requirements we should have for an explanation. Instead,

    it questions whether social science thinks explanation is relevant at all (and whether it should

    actually focus on prediction). As this essay focusses on explanation content, this quesiton, however

    interesting, falls outside the scope of this article. Moreover, I want to introduce an extra point of

    discussion which is prevalent in the discussions in the philosophy of science and which I find to be

    of far more importance in the discussion of the organisational studies, especially the paradigm

    incom;mensurability debate:

    Monism versus pluralism: When we are talking about our concept of discussion, in this case

    an organisation, are we talking about one concept or multiple concepts?

    Let us now look at the discussions within the philosoophy of social science. What becomes apparent

    is that the different meta-narratives take in different positions within these fundamental debates.

    This shows why the paradigm incommensurability debate is such an active debate as such strong

    differences create strong obstacles regarding both the unity of the meta-narratives into

    organisational study and the potential commensurability of the meta-narratives.

    Mimic physical science: naturalist causalism versus anti-naturalist

    interpretationism

    The naturalism versus antinaturalism debate and the interpretationism versus causalism debate are

    closely intertwined. The first debate is aimed at the scientific status of social research, the second on

    the contents of explanations in social research. The basic premise remains the same: natural

    sciences have an inherent virtue, because they have objective methods to enquire about the value-

    neutral contingent facts of the world. If the social sciences want to confirm to these supposedly

    high standards, then social sciences should develop methods which give us ordinary causal

    explanations, just as the natural sciences. Any other explanation, i.e. which are 'biased' by

    interpretations, would not suffice for this standard, since its interpreted data would by definition

    -11-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    12/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    include human values.

    A prime example of an attempt to 'give a naturalistic standard' to the social sciences is the

    'behaviouristic school of thought' which was dominant in especially psychology in the 1950's and

    1960's, but also has its branches in economics and other social sciences, of which some of its ideas

    are found attractive by structural functionalism and contingency theory. The basic idea behind

    behaviouristic analysis is an input and output analysis, a thought which is easily understood when

    we look at animal psychology. One of the problems of animal psychology is the 'other minds'-

    problem: we cannot know an animals needs and desires nor its feelings and pains. Therefore, the

    only way to research animals is by looking at their behaviour: by placing a cat between vegetable

    food and meat, we can infer that a cat is a carnivore, since it will eat the meat. We do not conclude

    anything about its feelings (e.g. that it is hungry), since this belongs to the black box between the

    input and the output. Similarly, instead of trying to explain by looking at the black box of processes

    which disturb an organisation from good functioning, instead one could look at how organisations

    respond to certain changes and look at influences that bring about positive changes.

    On the other hand, philosophers have given two reasons for the impossibility for such causal

    explanation. The first reason denies causal explanations because social phenomena are not tightly

    connected to their physical counterparts, as we have the problem of multiple realisation: the same

    social phenomenon can be realised by different physical phenomena. Therefore, we do not have

    conclusive evidence that the same type of laws existing in the physical realm will also exist in the

    social realm, as it is possible these multiple physical instantiations have nothing else in common

    than being associated with the same social phenomenon. As social phenomena still supervene on

    physical, they can only have analysable laws if these laws supervene on the physical laws, which is

    exactly what is denied by the multiple realisation problem36. The second argument, first given by

    Charles Taylor, argues that the social sciences can only use interpreted data, because they are not

    about behaviour but about action. For him, to follow the natural sciences standard is like suggestingthat there is a metaphysical existence of 'raw' or 'brute' data in the social sciences, i.e. data which

    isn't affected by human interpretation. However, as actions are always intended in themselves, and

    exactly these actions are the subject of social scientific research, how is it then possible to arrive at

    uninterpreted knowledge, since the field itself is value-laden? Therefore, we should use

    interpretations as our explanation content37.

    36 Kincaid 2002, p292.37 Ibid idem. See also Taylor 1994, p186-187.

    -12-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    13/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    One final remark here is necessary. The distinction I made above between naturalist causalism and

    anti-naturalist interpretationism is of course stereotypical. Some of the theories do not fit into this

    description. However, I believe these couples are often if not always agreed upon within the current

    debates in the philosophy of science. I think Kincaid would agree here as he argues that both are

    different arguments against the same scientific status for both natural and social sciences38.

    The meta-narratives of Rationality, Integration and Market all take in the naturalistic causal

    position. These theories strive for a normal science theory, with two organisational proposals and

    one economic proposal as its candidate which has a mathematical system and the possibility of a

    testing environment. This focus on main science theories is strongly linked to the ontological

    commitment by these theories. Within the Rationality meta-narrative, it was argued that

    organisation theory should give an objectively determined most effective configuration which

    should be forced upon the organisation itself. It suggests that this 'objectively determined most

    effective configuration' should be obtained by empirical research and is universally applicable, i.e.

    applicable to any organisation. Here there is a similarity with the natural sciences: the Rationality

    meta-narrative searches for 'universal social laws' which ground a certain organisational

    configuration. Within this narrative, there is no discussion about this presupposition.

    Within the Integration narrative, objective research is possible due to the organicist nature of an

    organisation. The main assumption here is that actions by organisations are effectively the same as

    made by an individual who struggles for survival within an unknown and uncertain world. Due to

    these uncertainty factors, individuals (and more generally organisms) use another method, called

    'heuristics', which are analogous to rules of thumb. Humans, as an organism, constantly use

    heuristics, which can be examined. As mentioned above, organicists suggest that we should analyse

    organisations by looking at these spontaneously generated methods. More precisely, it rejects any

    suggestions that we could analyse an organisation in terms of individuals and instead propose that

    we cannot designate any component which of the single processes is more essential for theexistence of the organisation than another.

    Structural functionalism, the most dominant approach until today, can be analysed as a form of

    'organisational pluralism': while it handles external factors similarly to the Integration meta-

    narrative as it acknowledges the uncertainty of the outside world, internal factors are handled by

    organisation design as with the Rationality meta-narrative. This also means that cultural factors and

    power struggles are reduced to a technical problem solvable by the internal system. This also leads

    38 Ibid, p291.

    -13-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    14/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    to the assumption that an organisation culture, when established, will never change again, except

    when initiated by a change in organisation design by the expert in question. This is the

    behaviouristic theory at work: organisation culture is a part of the behaviouristic 'black box',

    therefore we may only look at changes brought about by the system, not at the phenomenon itself.

    Within the Market meta-narrative, cultural influences are still assumed to have either no impact or a

    'fixed impact' on calculation of extra costs: in the latter case it is translated into a quantitative value

    which represents the cultural factor within models as one of the 'random uncertainty factors' where

    in the former case the organisation theory is thought of as able to handle such cultural influences,

    where it is assigned a certain value to be able to fit it into the calculation. As such, it tries to

    subsume everything into the mathematical theoretical framework in order to infer causal claims. As

    with neo-classical economics, of which it is a specialisation, it aims at holding the high standards by

    offering an abstract, but strong mathematical framework which has great causal explanatory power.

    Often these organisational proposals appeal to statistical research to measure objectively

    effectiveness. As shown above, all three meta-narratives also reduce organisation culture and power

    struggles to marginal issues, which can be handled inside the system. The result is almost always a

    static conception of these aspects which seem to be susceptible to change over time. As both are

    characteristics of human relations which are partially bound to cultural, social and historical

    contingencies39

    , we cannot find uninterpreted figures (or 'brute data', as Taylor calls it (Taylor,

    1971)) within the culture and power issues. As these three proposals search for this brute data, they

    are struggling with incorporating these items into their explanatory framework.

    The meta-narrative of Power holds an ambiguous position when we look at the distinction between

    naturalistic causalism and anti-naturalistic interpretativism. The Neo-Weberian theories do not fall

    into this stereotypical distinction. Weber thought he could give an objective analysis of socially

    produced organisational factors(Bellamy, 2003), without resorting to only a descriptive analysis,instead leaning on a special method of sympathetic understanding, commonly labelled with the

    German term Verstehen40. This call forVerstehen bears resemblance with Gadamers (and therefore

    with Taylor's) idea of an hermeneutic circle, in which the researcher tries to interpret the

    phenomenon in question into its 'intersubjective meaning'(Taylor 1994), with a researcher whose

    research also is comprised of intersubjective meanings. For Weber, however, this does not mean that

    objective evidence is impossible. Even though it might be so that human values are personal choice,

    39 Clegg & Hardy 1999, p1-2.40 Kincaid 2002, p291.

    -14-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    15/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    it is still an empirical fact that some of these values become realised in organisational practice.

    Weber clearly embraces the naturalistic view, but does not hold that we need to cite causes as our

    explanation content in order to hold the same standard of the natural sicences. More strongly, for

    Weber it would be a fundamental mistake to cite causes, as this does not recognize that human

    actions are based on personal choice.

    The second position of which the Power meta-narrative consists of, the Foucaultian view, clearly

    chooses an interpretative, anti-naturalistic standpoint. One of the main points in these postmodern

    theories, and therefore also of the meta-narrative of Knowledge, is that within all social sciences we

    have some historical, social or cultural presuppositions which decide on whether we choose on or

    another option and that we cannot prevent these presuppositions from entering our theoretical

    frameworks. Therefore, all the results we get from our research are by definition historically,

    socially or culturally contingent, especially within the social sciences, as the researchers themselves

    have a historical, sociological and cultural background. It may seem that the Foucaultian theory

    about power struggles and the Knowledge meta-narrative presented by Derrida and Lyotard as

    described here take in more or less the same position as Taylor with his argument for

    interpretativism which is described above. The main difference between these two positions is that

    while Taylor, following Gadamer, suggests that it at least in theory is possible to understand one's

    own assumptions41

    , the postmodernists do not see any reason to believe that we will discover our

    own assumptions as we will always try to look at the system while we are still in the system itself.

    Moreover, this view also means that organisations themselves are just socially and historically

    contingent practices, which factors need to be made explicit (Kilduff & Mehra, 1997). These

    differences seem to be more ontological than epistemological, however, as both encourage radical

    research of one's own presuppositions in order to create awareness of the contingent factors which

    played a role in the analysis (Taylor 1994; Kilduff & Mehra, 1997).

    The last meta-narrative, Justice focusses on interpretative analysis. This is especially true of theorganisational level, on which it tries to explain the influences of cultures of the higher (societal)

    level on the current level. While they focus on the role of organisation structures, this focus is based

    on the political and social factors causing the optimal organisation structures, making again [...]

    the historical structural and contextual positioning of actors[...]42 the main object of focus, which

    need the interpretative focus. However, as with the Neo-Weberian theories, this may lead to

    objective knowledge about effective ways of organisation design. When the meta-narrative of

    41 Taylor 1994, p198-199.42 Reed 1999, p37.

    -15-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    16/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    Power may be associated with the (continental) post-modern tradition in philosophy, the meta-

    narrative of Justice may be associated with the (American) pragmatist tradition.

    What is important to learn from these two debates is that, as these theories tend to focus on

    particular aspects of the organisation, each of them has to either make abstract one or more aspects

    of an orgnanisation in order to incorporate these aspects into the theory or has to ignore them

    completely. Where the Market perspective focusses on the economical action, it has to abstract the

    cultural and sociological aspects of the organisation. This is especially true for those perspectives

    which aim at holding the high standards of the natural sciences, as the social and cultural practices

    are too diverse to incorporate into the framework. On the other hand, those narratives who focus on

    interpretations tend to loose sight of the economical and technical administrative design aspects of

    an organisation, as they tend to emphasise on the cultural and sociological aspects. This is most

    apparent within the Foucaultian theories, as they only aim at small scale social practices. There is

    one caveat here, though. One of the main points of some of the postmodern theories is exactly that

    any organisation design is socially and historically contingent and would therefore argue that any

    technical description is inadequate to describe the this contingent nature.

    Reductionism: the individualism versus holism versus collectivism debate

    The individualism versus holism debate has already been firmly debated within the organisational

    studies themselves43. The basic premise of the individualism position is one of theory

    reductionism44: One theory can be reduced to another if it can subsume all explanatory value of the

    other theory under its own without using technical terms used which refer to entities from the other

    theory. With individualism, the main question is whether it is possible to describe individual

    behaviour without resorting to social concepts.

    There are two important differences between the debate within the organisational studies and the

    debate within philosophy of social science in general. First, the organisational studies attach a moral

    component to this debate, arguing that individualism promotes the status of human autonomy 45.

    Second, next to the individualism and holism position, the organisational studies have an even more

    radical position on the 'non-individual' side of the debate, which is collectivism. This position

    denies any individual factors as components of the organisation; these simply become some form of

    figure into the calculation46.

    43 Ibid, p41.

    44 Kincaid 1997, p5.

    45 Reed 1999, p41.46 Reed 1999, p41

    -16-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    17/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    The individualist position is argued for most strongly by the market perspective. The Market meta-

    narrative has some similarities with neo-classical economics. A basic assumption with both is that

    they need to idealize in large proportions some incalculable aspect of their research topic in order to

    be able to predict within the mathematical framework. Within neo-classical economics, one of these

    aspects is human rationality47. Calculations are based on a so-called optimalisation strategy, which

    suggests that people always calculate where e.g. one should buy a product. Should there be a lack

    of information (e.g. not all prices are known) or lack of resources (limited amount of time), instead

    people optimise their usage of the lacking resource, e.g. by calculating the number of shops which

    can be visited before a decision has to be made. This condition is called 'optimalisation under

    constraints'. Also, neo-classical economics assume some basics regarding markets, which are

    focussed on full competition and equilibrium outcomes (e.g. law of supply and demand) and are

    often assumed to have freely available information, although this information still may be lacking

    due to constraints as above. It is assumed that it is this framework that can give the strongest

    explanatory power48. Within the Market meta-narrative, the aspects which are reduced to single

    variables are culture and human rationality. The Market meta-narrative tries to position the role of

    organisations in the neo-classical economical framework. As noted above, this is problematic, since

    in the ideal situation, there would be no need for organisations within the economy. However,

    within the Market meta-narrative, it is acknowledged that this ideal situation does not hold in all

    situations. It is not just the human rationality claim that is rebutted; often, it is taken into account

    that not all parties give full information regarding their products. Put more strongly, the human

    rationality claim is the last claim that is often still silently acknowledged, generally supported by

    the 'as if'-argument: even though people do not act rationally, the results are still corresponding to

    the results in another close metaphysical world in which people do indeed behave rational.

    The Integration narrative is on the other end of the spectrum. Here, the organisation is referred to as

    an organism itself and research aims only at the relation between organisations and the outsideworld. Little to no attention is paid to the individual components, as organisation development and

    functioning is researched without looking at them. The organisation design is effectively enforced

    on the individuals, who can just 'sit back, watch and endure'.

    All of the other meta-narratives fall under the holism debate. Some of them focus more on the role

    of the individual within the organisational practices (such as the Neo-Weberian power struggles and

    the Foucaultian individual practices), but all need the social, historical and cultural terminology and

    47 Kincaid 1997, p93.48 Ibid idem.

    -17-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    18/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    concepts in order to explain how the individual positions itself within the society. Others focus

    more on the role of the organisation itself, such as the Knowledge and Rationality meta-narratives,

    but both need the conception of the individual, either to argue for the 'unusual' and contingent

    changes within organisations (Knowledge) or to have a rational object which is the main building

    block or resource of the organisational framework. Note that the main difference between

    Rationality and Integration is that while Rationality imposes a strong rationalised and abstract

    picture of an individual, individuals and their labour are still taken into account when designing an

    effective organisation strategy; within Integration the organisation itself is the individual which is

    studied.

    The last two paragraphs shows a strong distinction between the different meta-narratives. What's

    more, there are no narratives which position themselves continually on the same location within the

    debate. This suggests that the discussions which are dominant in the organisational studies are

    fundamental discussions on how we should interpret the status of the social sciences and their

    explanations.

    The most interesting position are the naturalistic holists, since when a theory is wanting to hold the

    same status and obey to the high standards of the natural sciences, these sciences are often marked

    as a candidate for reduction (and thus for individualism), as it is easier to relate the higher level

    explanation to the lower level explanation. If organisation theory would hold the same standards

    and would produce the same law-like causes as e.g. individual psychology, it would be an ideal

    candidate for reduction, since it would appear that these law-like causes are supervening on

    individual causes. It could be used as an empirical argument against the thesis that organisational

    studies would be too open ended to behave in law-like ways, although the problem of multiple

    realisation would have to be tackled.

    Now that the differences between the meta-narratives are placed into the fundamental debates into

    the philosophy of social science, we can finally look at the paradigm incommensurability debate

    itself.

    Monism versus pluralism: comparison with the causality debate

    The paradigm incommensurability debate is an important debate because of the apparent inability to

    join explanations from different meta-narratives, as it is possible that they conflict, which would

    pose a problem for the unity of organisational studies. Perhaps one of the problems of answering

    -18-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    19/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    this question, and thereby offering a solution to the paradigm problem of organisation theory, is

    located within the question for the concept of the organisation. What is at stake here is whether we

    should opt for a pluralistic view on the nature of an organisation theory. I think we can make an

    analogy here with another discussion in the philosophy of science which is the discussion on

    causation. Let us therefore make a short sidestep to the philosophical debate of causation.

    One of the currently defended views on causation is a pluralistic conception of causation: ever since

    Hume introduced his regularity account of causation, all monist theories have failed to grasp the

    account of causation in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, mostly due to sophisticated

    counterexamples. A number of philosophers have argued that all these monist theories fail is

    because there is no the account of causation and have given conceptual reasons for this (Reiss,

    2009): theories of causation were all based on the methodology by which they were presumably

    discovered. There were probabilistic accounts of causation, since statistic correlation suggests that

    there was a relation between the cause and the effect. The regularity account is basically the

    common sense way we learn about causation: always close in space-time, each time in the same

    way with each time first the cause and then the effect. However, our methods of discovery tell us

    nothing about the concept itself. Also, Reiss argues against methodological pluralism, the view that

    we can have multiple ways to discover causes, but only one concept. According to Reiss, it is

    methodologically possible to have cases in which two theoretical components give both other

    intuitions: according to rule A there is no causation, but according to rule B there is. This would

    mean that the theory contradicts itself. Therefore, he argues, we need concept pluralism. Another,

    more practical test for concept pluralism is this: if we would have concept pluralism, this should

    mean that our ordinary language would suggest that we have multiple uses for cause. Compare our

    usage of 'cause' with our usage of 'hot'. We can certainly askDo you mean 'hot' as in very warm or

    do you mean 'hot' as in very sharp?, but some philosophers argue that this isn't the case with

    causation (Godfrey-Smith, 2007).

    The pluralist debate on causation, an certainly the discussion between conceptual pluralism and

    methodological pluralism is a debate which we recognise within the discussion on organisation

    theory as the paradigm discussions. Recall our three different standpoints within the paradigm

    discussion. There was one group who rejected all other theories and only accepted conservative

    views, mostly contingency theory, on organisation theory. This position within the debates on

    causation is held by monist theories of causation: both hold that the concept in question is but one

    -19-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    20/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    concept and there is only one preferred method to determine this concept.

    A second group tries through philosophical and linguistic analysis to try to bridge the gap. This

    position is comparable with methodological pluralism. Both visions hold that, although we use

    different methods, all these methods tell us something else about the same concept. By

    philosophical analysis we can determine how these theories relate and which theory is applicable in

    which situation.

    The third and last group wanted to retain the diversity, arguing that it [...]emancipates

    organizational analysis from 'the necessity for interminable justifications of different ontological,

    epistemological and methodological approaches' [(Jackson & Carter, 1991)]:110.49This position

    is comparable to the concept-pluralism in the debates on causation. Both see the concept in question

    as irreducibly plural, having multiple concepts. However, instead of giving conceptual arguments as

    the philosophers of conceptual causal pluralism do, the quoted sentence emphasises the

    consequences for social praxis. It is as if these authors are saying: discussion is pointless, let us just

    keep using our plural concepts, as they all have merits, each showing the discussion from another

    approach. We would otherwise just have discussions which would continue unendlessly. Also, it is

    argued, that each of these different approaches should have the ability to continue to develop on

    their own, instead of being pushed away by the more prominent theories50.

    Before I will evaluate these discussions in the organisational studies, it is important to realise that,

    although a comparison with the debate on causality is quite easy to show, there are a number of

    fundamental differences between these two debates.

    First of all, causation is a far more abstract concept as an organisation is. Although we can say of

    both that we never have seen an empirical proof of an organisation, we are certain that organisations

    exist and, given any description of a number of persons working together under certain rules, we

    will surely all have the same intuition about what an organisation is. With causation however, this is

    a wholly different story. There are numerous counter-examples in which we either aren't surewhether it is a case of causation or we have competing intuitions (Hitchcock, 2003).

    Second, an organisation is an institutional practice, determined by conventions, and thus has a

    distinct humanistic nature. Most people will grant that causation has a human component, i.e. that

    part of the meaning we address to causation is not part of the world, but only a few philosophers

    have defended that causality is only humanistic in nature51.

    49 Willmott 1993, p681-682.

    50 Reed 1999, p26.51 Menzies & Price have defended such an opinion, but it has not been well-received.

    -20-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    21/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    With these remarks in mind, let us now look at the three alternatives in the paradigm

    incommensurability debate. The 'monist option', in which we simply disregard the other theories as

    unscientific, looks unconvincing. When we look at contingency theory, one of the prime candidates

    according to its defenders (Donaldson, 1999) to fulfil the role of all other theories, it reduces

    cultural and power struggle issues to simple technical issues. This theory then fails to give an

    analysis of multiple power sources and cultural influences influencing each other. Moreover, it takes

    for granted some strong assumptions regarding human rationality and the homogeneity of value

    means52.

    The second option, the sophisticated philosophical analysis to bridge the gap I have identified with

    methodological pluralism looks more promising. Within the philosophy of causation, this position

    has been seen as problematic, as it is hard to see that we have a priori (and therefore conceptual)

    reasons to argue that no counter-example exists in which some of the theoretical components yield

    different results than other. Simply put, philosophers of causation argue that the project which is

    attempted by these organisational theorists will fail for this reason. I am not certain that this also

    holds for organisation theory, however, and this is due to the less abstract nature of an organisation.

    Still, it is epistemically undesirable that we have multiple theories of which we do not know when

    which theory holds, as this would suggest that we sometimes cannot determine which theory to use.

    Finally, the arguments given for the third theory, concept-pluralism, may have practical importance,

    but is not strong, again on practical grounds. On practical grounds it can be problematic that we

    have no grounds to reject theories, since it allows unscientific and pseudo-theories to emerge for

    which we lack the tools to refute them. Moreover, without debates with other competing theories,

    these theories cannot develop to their fullest. A more theoretical argument is that we do think there

    are better and worse theories. When introducing such relativism, which almost looks as

    isolationism, it suggests that we have no reason to assume that these differences exist, albeit on a

    contextual scale.

    Organisation as a 'family resemblance'; stressing the question

    Of the three theories described above, the second one, arguing for methodological pluralism, seems

    to have the strongest position. However, this would suggest a singular conception of an

    organisation, something which does not seem to coincide with the strong fundamental differences

    shown in the discussions within the philosophy of science. But if this singular conception is wrong,

    how then can we 'save' the organisational studies from falling apart?

    52 Reed 1999, p32.

    -21-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    22/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    I want to suggest one idea which was put forward by Godfrey-Smith in his discussion of causal

    theories. His idea is that we could analyse the concept of causation by looking at it as an family

    resemblance concept, meaning that, even though some of the aspects of causality have nothing in

    common, they can have relation to each other via a third theory with which they do have something

    in common (Godfrey-Smith, 2007)(Wittgenstein, 1963). Please look at the following table to

    illuminate this concept:

    Rationality Market Power

    Type of explanation Causal

    explanation

    Causal

    explanation

    Interpretations

    Individualism/

    Holism

    Holism Individualism Holism

    Focus of practice Organisational

    practices

    Individual

    practices

    Individual

    practices

    Here, while these three meta-narratives do not have any singular aspect in common, all share some

    aspect with all the others. Should organisation theory be a family resemblance concept, each of

    these theories should have one of these points in common with each other, but there would be no

    point which is common by all.

    The positive side of this conception is that it does explain why there are differences between each of

    the theories in question. Each of them focusses on one aspect, a characteristic which we already saw

    in the discussion regarding naturalism/anti-naturalism and interpretativism/causalism, but lacks

    some of the other. The major drawback is that it also doesn't bring us any closer to a unification of

    organisational studies. Within this conception of organisation, although it is clear why we have such

    different thoughts about how we should look at an organisation, it does not tell us which theory we

    should use at any given time.

    I think we should opt for a more pragmatic view here. All of these theories emphasise different

    aspects of an organisation. While some of these may conflict, this can easily be explained: some use

    strong abstractions on a certain level, which may inflict inconsistencies on a lower level, but will

    not be apparent on another level. However, we do have a mechanic to tell what theory we should

    use: it is dependent on the question we ask ourselves and the information we would like to receive.

    When we want to ask ourselves about the financial consequences for reorganising, we should op for

    a Market meta-narrative, which will transform any data into financial figures. If we want to know

    the cultural problematic, we should use a theory from the power or knowledge meta-narrative, or

    perhaps the justice meta-narrative.

    -22-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    23/24

    R. van der Pluijm Paradigm irreductionism

    It may seem that this position is utterly relativistic. However, I do not feel that this is the case. First,

    utterly weak theories will always have another theory which is able to give a more informing

    explanation then the weak theory, making its applicability zero. Second, we may still appeal to

    (likeliness of) truth-conditions; a theory which is unable to give a reasonable answer in the current

    organisational situation is simply useless(Van Fraassen, 1977).

    One thing we should learn about the short suggestion above is the importance for organisational

    consultants and researchers to firmly establish the context and scope of the research they are about

    to begin. As the field of organisational study is a wide and diverse field, full of different tools, we

    should first determine whether we are looking at a nail or a screw before picking out our toolbox.

    Bibliography

    Alvesson, M., & Deetz, S. (1999). Critical Theory and Postmodernism: Approaches to

    Organizational Studies. In S. Clegg & C. Hardy, Studying Organisation, Theory and Method(pp.

    202-229). London: SAGE Publications Ltd.

    Bellamy, R. (2003). The advent of the masses and the making of the modern theory of

    democracy. In T. Ball & R. Bellamy, The Cambridge history of twentieth-century political thought(1st., pp. 70-103). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Clegg, S., & Hardy, C. (1999). Introduction. In S. Clegg & C. Hardy, Studying organization:

    theory & method(pp. 1-23). London: Sage Publications Ltd.

    Donaldson, L. (1999). The Normal Science of Structural Contingency Theory. In S. Clegg &

    C. Hardy, Studying organization: theory & method(pp. 68-87). London: Sage Publications Ltd.

    Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Bounded and rational. Contemporary debates in cognitive science,115-133.

    Godfrey-Smith, P. (2007). Causal pluralism. In P. Menzies, H. Beebee, & C. Hitchcock,

    Oxford Handbook of Causation (forthcoming) (1st., p. 15). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Retrieved from http://www.people.fas.harvard.edu/~pgs/CausalPluralismPGS-07-Final.pdf.

    Hannan, M., & Freeman, J. (1984). Structural inertia and organizational change.American

    sociological review, 49(2), 149164. JSTOR. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/2095567.

    Hitchcock, C. (2003). Of humean bondage. The British Journal for the Philosophy of .

    Retrieved from http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/abstract/54/1/1.

    Jackson, N., & Carter, P. (1991). In defence of paradigm incommensurability. OrganizationStudies, 12(1), 109. EGOS. Retrieved from http://oss.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/12/1/109.

    Kilduff, M., & Mehra, A. (1997). Postmodernism and organizational research.Academy of

    Management Review, 453481. JSTOR. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/259330.

    Kincaid, H. (1997).Individualism and the unity of science: essays on reduction,

    explanation, and the special sciences. Rowman & Littlefield Inc. Retrieved from

    -23-

  • 8/9/2019 Scientific Explanations in Organisational Studies

    24/24

    R. van der Pluijm Bibliography

    http://scholar.google.com/scholar?

    cluster=6564002865719978815&hl=nl&as_sdt=2000&as_vis=1#1.

    Kincaid, H. (2002). Social Sciences. In P. Machamer & M. Silberstein, The Blackwell guide

    to the philosophy of science (p. 1). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Reed, M. (1999). Organizational theorizing: a historically contested terrain. In S. R. Clegg

    & C. Hardy, Studying organization: theory & method(pp. 26-50). London: Sage Publications Ltd.

    Reed, M. (2005). Reflections on the'Realist Turn'in Organization and Management Studies.

    Journal of Management Studies, 42(8), 16211644. John Wiley & Sons. Retrieved from

    http://www3.interscience.wiley.com/journal/118735581/abstract.

    Reiss, J. (2009). Causation in the social sciences: Evidence, inference, and purpose.

    Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Retrieved from

    http://pos.sagepub.com/cgi/rapidpdf/0048393108328150v1.pdf.

    Turner, S., & Roth, P. (2003). The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of the social sciences .

    Wiley-Blackwell.

    Van Fraassen, B. (1977). The pragmatics of explanation.American Philosophical Quarterly,

    14(2), 143150. JSTOR. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/20009661.

    Willmott, H. (1993). Breaking the Paradigm Mentality. Organization studies, 14(5), 681-

    720.

    Wittgenstein, L. (1963).Philosophical Investigations/Philosophische Untersuchungen. (G.

    Anscombe(Translator). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    van den Berg, P., & Wilderom, C. (2004). Defining, measuring, and comparing

    organisational cultures.Applied Psychology, 53(4), 570582. John Wiley & Sons. Retrieved from

    http://www3.interscience.wiley.com/journal/118775052/abstract.

    (Turner & Roth, 2003)(Alvesson & Deetz, 1999)(Hannan & Freeman, 1984)(van den Berg &

    Wilderom, 2004)

    -24-