Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    1/46

    1

    Time, Speed, and Delays in Environmental Crises

    Reflections on the Time of Slime

    Astrid SchraderSarah Lawrence College, [email protected]

    DRAFT

    For UC Berkeley Environmental Politics Colloquium

    March 11, 2011

    (Please do not cite or circulate beyond the colloquium)

    In a keynote lecture for the 2007 annual meeting of the British Sociological

    Association, Bruno Latour wonders How can we read in the newspapers that we as

    humans might be responsible for 30 or 40% of species extinction, without this effecting

    a change in our identity and ourrelationships? (Latour 2007) How can we

    reconcile an idea of the human, Latour asks, as so big, so powerful and as dangerous

    to our life support system as the impact of a major meteorite and on other hand we

    are so little, so powerless, a mere scratch on the surface of the Earth? (ibid) Latour

    formulates these questions in response to James Lovelocks gloomy prognosis for the

    survival of humanity in the face of climate change in his bookTheRevenge of Gaia

    (Lovelock 2007).

    Latours questions point to an inherent contradiction in systems theories that

    forget to ask how and to what extent we can know the rest of nature. From an

    evolutionary perspective we are certainly part of nature, but as ostensibly the only

    beings with histories, cultures, and technologies that are threatening the livelihood of

    many other taxa we must surely recognize our domination of the rest nature.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    2/46

    2

    Slowing Down: Recognizing Human Domination?

    In her Presidential Address at the 1997 Annual Meeting of the American

    Association of the Advancement of Science, marine ecologist Jane Lubchenco (now the

    head of NOAA) proposed a new social contract for science. After a detailed review of

    the dramatic changes human culture has imposed on nature during the last few decades,

    Lubchenco states, The current and growing extent of dominance of the planet will

    require new kinds of knowledge and applicationknowledge to reduce the rate at

    which we alter the Earth system (Lubchenco 1998, 495). Part of the Contract,

    Lubchenco suggests, should be that scientists will exercise good judgment,

    wisdom, and humility. It is difficult to know what Lubchenco meant by new

    knowledge that reduces the rate at which we alter the Earth system, but she was

    probably not recommending developing more technologies that would postpone

    environmental decision-making into an indefinite future. Yet, immediately after her call

    for scientific humility, we are told that The Contract should recognize the extent of

    human domination of the planet (495).

    The recognition of human domination over rest nature seems exactly where the

    majority of efforts in environmental research are directed. The proliferation of maps

    that measure and display the so-called human footprint as the degree of human

    disturbances to wild nature is only one example among many that reinforce our

    alleged power over nature (Sanderson et al. 2002).1

    In spite of the acknowledgment that

    1Recent efforts include the human disturbance index , which used digitized maps from Rand-McNally atlases and other sources to classify areas as human-dominated, partially disturbed, orundisturbed; according to that index, nearly three-quarters of the habitable surface of the planet isdisturbed at least in part by human use (Sanderson et al. 2002).See also (Kareiva et al. 2007) for a recent review of the domestication of nature and a proposal of howto quantify ecosystem services.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    3/46

    3

    human domination of the planet is at the heart of environmental problems, human

    domination is often discursively reinforced through the maintenance of a fundamental

    nature/culture distinction. The premise is, as Nigel Clark puts it, that left to itself,

    nature is docile; it maintains its given forms and functions (Clark 2002, 107).

    Ironically, such a premise is reinforced by dynamical system theories that picture nature

    as self-making, or self-regulating that, more often than not aim at displacing

    anthropocentric accounts of the environment. The cell, the body, the organism, the

    ecosystem, nature, life, everything has become a (cybernetic) system nestled within a

    hierarchy of larger systems. Each system is characterized in relation to the other by its

    function or economic role, culminating in the global system, also called Gaia (or Earth

    System, as Lubchenco called it), which no longer has an environment.

    And, why is it exactly, asks Clark,that there is so much political purchase to

    be had from the idea of natures undoing at the hands of culture, and so little currency

    in considering the things life achieves on its own account (see Wilson, 1996)? And why

    is it that after all the vexing of the nature/culture binary, we are still so much more

    comfortable tracking the impact of globalization on the biophysical world than we are

    with any consideration of a biological or geological contribution to the global

    contours? (Clark 2002, 104). While the targets of Clarks critique view nature as

    passive and immobile (exemplified in Ulrich Becks account of risk society),2 system

    theoretical approaches to ecology posit nature as active and multiple: composed of

    multiple hierarchically organized interacting systems. I would like to suggest that part

    of the answer to Clarks question lies in insufficient attention to conceptions of time in

    attempts to deconstruct the nature/culture binary. What distinguishes humans from the

    2 See (Szerszynski et al. 1996) for compelling critiques of Becks Risk Society.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    4/46

    4

    rest of nature is no longer mobility versus stasis or activity versus passivity but the rate

    of change that our technologies enable. At the center of the current environmental

    crisis, and perhaps any perception of crisis, is the question of speed. What distinguishes

    humans from the rest of nature is no longer mobility versus stasis or activity versus

    passivity but the rate of change that our technologies enable.

    Moving beyond the mere affirmation of the activity of nonhuman nature, in this

    paper, I attempt to link an epistemological anthropocentrism that opposes historically

    flexible human knowledge to its atemporal object of study to a political

    anthropocentrism that presupposes our time as the unalterable movement ofHomo

    Economicus. My inquiry is greatly informed by Jacques Derridas arguments that our

    conception of time hinges on a fundamental distinction between human and nonhuman

    animals and that this very distinction perceives scientific knowledge production as a

    teleological process, progressively approaching the truth of the object as it is by itself.

    In such a case, the object of knowledge is necessarily assumed to be static.

    The first part of the paper draws on research with Harmful Algal Blooms

    (HABs), illustrating and motivating a connection between an epistemological and a

    political anthropocentrism. I argue that the scientific detection of harmful algae, which

    attempts to fix nonhuman nature in an other time maps onto a particular

    anthropocentric concerns with our political economies. .

    In the second part, I explore how such a link might be enabled by specific

    conception of time inherent to system theoretical approaches that consider nature or

    life itself as a teleological process toward increasing complexity. In different

    enactments of self-producing systems, natural evolution is either opposed to cultural or

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    5/46

    5

    technical evolution, or the latter is naturalized as inevitable. The focus of my discussion

    hence will be on the role of time in maintaining the duality between human society and

    the rest of nature within a framework of systems theories that consider life - from the

    cell to the planet - composed of hierarchies of self-producing organisms.

    Expanding Dead Zones in the Ocean: Going Backwards

    In 2006, theLA Timeslaunched a five part series titled Altered Oceans, documenting

    the crisis in the seas.3 In Part I of the Pulitzer Prize winning series, A Primeval Tide

    of Toxins, environmental reporter Kenneth Weiss suggests that humans are pushing

    the oceans back to the dawn of evolution, [f]ish, corals and marine mammals are

    dying while algae, bacteria and jellyfish are growing unchecked. For Weiss, the

    alarming rate of anthropogenic nutrient pollution in the ocean is squeezing out complex

    animals and plants, leaving oxygen depleted zones that are only hospitable to so-called

    primitive organisms. Weiss suggests that pollution is reversing the natural arrow of

    time: evolution [is] running in reverse, returning to the primeval seas of hundreds of

    millions of years ago (Weiss 2006). Referring to the overpopulation of our oceans

    with microscopic algae, marine ecologist and paleontologist Jeremy Jackson of the

    Scripps Institution of Oceanography at the University of California in San Diego agrees

    with Weiss, and characterizes the current ecological transformation of the oceans as the

    rise of slime. What assumptions about time and slime animate such pronouncements?

    Converting sunlight into biomass, microscopic algae are considered primary

    producers of life not only in the ocean, but of all life on earth. Due to the increased

    pollution of coastal waters their productivity has gotten out of hand. In order to

    3 Available at http://www.latimes.com/news/local/la-oceans-series,0,7783938.special; last accessed Feb.,2011.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    6/46

    6

    reproduce algae need not only sunlight but also nutrients such as nitrogen and

    phosphate. Agricultural run-off containing plant fertilizers and waste from industrial

    animal farms have supplied coastal waters and estuaries with a large dose of these

    nutrients. The result is an increased frequency and severity of what historically have

    been called red tides.4 Descriptions of red tides appear in the Bible and in Captain

    Cooks travel journals, suggesting that their seasonal occurrence is natural, rather

    than a symptom of human-induced environmental change (D. M. Anderson et al. 2002).

    This, however, no longer seems to hold for the expanded category of Harmful Algal

    Blooms (HABs).

    Algal blooms are considered harmful in two distinct but overlapping ways -

    through the production of high biomass and the production of toxins. Public health

    officials are most concerned with species of toxic dinoflagellates, whose toxin can

    accumulate in shellfish, which upon human consumption can lead to serious illnesses.

    On the other hand, when massive amounts of algae can no longer be eaten by predators,

    their decomposition consumes enough oxygen to suffocate many other ocean dwellers.

    According to the latest estimate, about 400 dead zones worldwide suffocate major

    taxa of life in the ocean (Diaz and Rosenberg 2008). The largest and oldest dead zone

    in U.S. waters has been observed in the Gulf of Mexico at the opening of the

    Mississippi River. Its expansion appears to announce the collapse of the fishing

    industry in that area within a few decades (Jackson et al. 2001). 5

    4 Because not all algal blooms render themselves visible through color changes of the sea, marinescientists no longer speak of red tides but of Harmful Algal Blooms (or HABs).5 Depending on the model used, ecologists quarrel about whether the total breakdown of the fishingindustry is to be expected within the next few decades or whether it may take another century.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    7/46

    7

    These dead zones are, however, not dead at all. In fact they are full of life

    just not the kind of life we want. We prefer big fish and pretty corrals (Jackson

    2008). Jackson elaborates: A dead zone is an ecosystem, which lacks all the kinds

    of animals we want, and has all the kinds of animals we dont want, and has all these

    toxic microbes.6 For Jackson, the notion of slime refers not only refer to the

    sliminess of some of the organisms that thrive under conditions of oxygen depletion,

    but is also a figure for the excesses and overproductions of modern life, referring to

    what is morally filthy or otherwise disgusting (Oxford English Dictionary, entry for

    slime, online edition). The rise of slime is also disease, Jackson affirms, the excess

    nutrients, the excess production that fuels the wrong kinds of microbes that kill the

    organisms we want like corals and fish.7

    Jacksons portrayal of the rise of slimecaptured succinctly by Weiss

    subtitle of theLA Timesarticle as The Run-Off from Modern Life Is Feeding an

    Explosion of Primitive Organisms propagated rapidly through the popular press.

    Discover Magazinerated the rise of slime number 4 of the top 100 Environmental

    News Stories of 2008.8 While the figure of slime seems to be effective in spreading

    concerns about the dire conditions of our oceans, I argue, however, that the rise of

    slime invokes a logic of time that works against Jacksons and many other

    environmental scientists affirmation that nutrient loadings to coastal waters need to be

    reduced now (Rabalais et al. 2009, emphasis added).

    6 Interview with Jeremy Jackson available athttp://www.learner.org/courses/envsci/scientist/transcripts/jackson.html, accessed Feb, 2011.7Ibid.8 Available online at http://discovermagazine.com/2009/jan/004,accessed Feb., 2011

    http://www.learner.org/courses/envsci/scientist/transcripts/jackson.htmlhttp://discovermagazine.com/2009/jan/004http://discovermagazine.com/2009/jan/004http://www.learner.org/courses/envsci/scientist/transcripts/jackson.html
  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    8/46

    8

    What kind of politics of time associates nature with a particular state of

    affairs in the past? As Johannes Fabian states in Time and the Other, referring to

    other cultures, as object of anthropology, the absence of the other from our Time has

    been his mode of presence in our discourseas an object and victim (154). And, the

    only agents of history are the ones that hold economic and technological power. Such

    an evolutionary temporalization (Fabian 1983, 11) informs both the discursive and

    technological re/construction of harmful algal species.

    Research into harmful algal blooms faces a dilemma similar to the one we are

    familiar with from debates about climate change: namely, the sorting out of human

    versus natural contributions to the occurrence of red tides. According to Jackson, we

    are not only encountering a period of reduced economic activity, but are witnessing a

    great Anthropocene mass extinction in the oceans (Jackson 2008). As a

    paleoecologist, Jackson worries that nature has become too relativistic; we need a better

    understanding what wasnatural, he claims, rather than recalibrating the baseline upon

    which human influences are compared to the state of nature in every generation of

    ecologist (Jackson 2001, 5416). Moreover, he writes, Our concept of what is natural

    today is based on personal experience at the expense of historical perspective. Thus,

    natural means the way things were when we first saw them or exploited them, and

    unnatural means all subsequent change (Jackson 2001, 5412). Hence, for Jackson,

    the importance of paleoecology, which seeks to establish a baseline according to the

    limits of scientific (or anecdotal) retrodiction into the past. But if the consequences of

    HABs are an expression ofevolution running in reverse, we must be careful not to go

    back too far otherwise the current state of our oceans might appear natural. What

    seems problematic with such an assertion is not only the affirmation of human power

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    9/46

    9

    over the rest of nature -- that is, the power to change the direction of evolution -- but

    also the very assumption that evolution has a direction at all, equating simplicity (e.g.

    slime) with the past and complexity (diversity and big fish) with the future.

    Marine scientists make no attempt to hide the anthropocentrism in the notion of

    harmful algal blooms. Harmfulness means either directly harmful to human health or

    the altering of ecosystems in ways humans do not like (Cullen 2008, 1). But what

    exactly is meant by this abstract category human in this case? A look at the National

    Oceanic and Atmospheric Administrations(NOAAs) harmful algae website is

    revealing: under the human dimension of harmful algal blooms, NOOA lists the

    reduction of economic impacts of HABs as the foremost priority.9

    We learn that the

    annual economic loss in the U.S. due to HABs sums up to $82 million - with major

    losses in the commercial fishing industry and the public health sector and noticeable

    losses due to a decline in tourism and coastal monitoring expenses. According to this

    and similar calculations, the economic threat of the dead zone, however, does not

    match the surplus value the agricultural industry produces through the utilization of

    excess nitrogen - even if the projected loss of the entire Gulf of Mexico fishing

    industry, which some ecologists take for granted, would be taken into account. As one

    commentator remarks, Its hard to weigh the benefit of protecting the gulfs $3 billion

    fishing industry, which supports at least 40,000 jobs, against costs incurred by the $98

    billion Mississippi Basin farm economy, which supports almost a million farmers

    (Malakoff 1998).

    Ecologists from the Virginia Institute of Marine Science use a slightly different

    currency to calculate the contribution of blooming algae toward a recession in the

    9http://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/HumanDimensionsStrategyv08.aspx,

    accessed Feb., 2011

    http://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/HumanDimensionsStrategyv08.aspxhttp://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/HumanDimensionsStrategyv08.aspxhttp://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/HumanDimensionsStrategyv08.aspx
  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    10/46

    10

    overall productivity of oceanic life. Diaz and Rosenberg, for example, estimate the loss

    in productivity in metric tons of carbon as potential food energy due to the suffocation

    of larger organismsthe secondary producers - in the dead zones (Diaz and Rosenberg

    2008). Such a single currency of harmfulness - measured either in loss of US dollars or

    in the loss of carbon biomass for consumption at the top of the food chain - structures

    the main research agenda in harmful algae science.

    Along with the algae the biomonitoring industry is blooming (Donald M.

    Anderson and Ramsdell 2005). While environmental policy decisions are indefinitely

    delayed because of the impossibility of figuring out whose nitrogen it is that is feeding

    the hypoxic zone, (Malakoff 1998), monitoring technologies seem to approach real-

    time. In close collaboration with the National Aeronautics Space Administration

    (NASA), marine scientists develop satellite imaging technologies and robotic

    underwater DNA-samplers in order to detect emerging algal blooms before they reach

    the coast (Olson et al. 2003). As stated on NOAAs website A shift from light

    microscopy to molecular approaches for quantifying harmful algal bloom (HAB)

    species has been driven by the need to expedite sample processing while increasing

    detection sensitivity and accuracy.10

    The assumption that species of microorganisms

    could be captured in their living presence, as they have always been, however,

    effectively narrows the kind of possible responses to the nutrient pollution of coastal

    waters. As soon as an early warning system is in place, fisheries can be closed in time,

    seafood can be withdrawn from the market, beaches can be evacuated, aquaculture

    cages can be dragged out of the toxic zones, without ever having to alter nutrient flows

    into the oceans. What is becoming predictable with real time technologies is not the

    10http://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/abs_MERHAB.aspx#compHabAccessed Feb., 2011

    http://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/abs_MERHAB.aspx#compHabhttp://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/abs_MERHAB.aspx#compHabhttp://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/abs_MERHAB.aspx#compHabhttp://www.cop.noaa.gov/stressors/extremeevents/hab/current/abs_MERHAB.aspx#compHab
  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    11/46

    11

    future itself, but perhaps its anthropo-economic shape or form. These mitigation efforts

    of the potentially harmful effects to human economies rely on the hope of the detection

    ofa species presence that has previously been tagged harmful. Most harmful algal

    species however object to such an objectification.

    The most sophisticated visualization and genomic technologies fail to bring

    harmful dinoflagellates into a present as such. Reducing the microorganism to either

    a series of genes or to points of biomass (identifiable through their chlorophyll content),

    the speedy detection technologies cannot capture their harmful performances.

    Conceivably,writes a team of marine ecologists, once the ecological requirements

    for each species are known, it would be easy to predict its occurrence. Unfortunately,

    they continue, the real world is more complicated.Indeed, the net growth

    performance of a species is affected by complex interactions with other organisms In

    fact, it is becoming increasingly evident that phytoplankton life strategies and their

    interactions with the surrounding environment may reach a degree of complexity

    unexpected for unicellular organisms (Zingone 2000). In this account our slimy past

    appears to be too complex to be brought into the present. For Donald Anderson of the

    Woods Hole Oceanographic Institute, however, the major problem with the forecast of

    a HAB event is not an unmanageable complexity that could possibly be reduced with

    improved monitoring and modeling technologies, but relates to an inherent

    unpredictability in the behavior of the microorganisms themselves. As Anderson

    affirms, an important aspect of many HAB species is their reliance on life history

    transformations for bloom initiation and decline. Many HAB species have dormant,

    cyst stages in their life histories, which remain in bottom sediments when

    environmental conditions are unsuitable for growth and germinate when conditions

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    12/46

    12

    improve, cable of suddenly populating the water column with a large number of cells.

    More important, however, than the temporal suspension of movement and growth is,

    according to Anderson, the environmental regulation of cell division. Many

    dinoflagellate species can switch between sexual and asexual reproduction depending

    on nutrient availability and the stage of a particular bloom. And, at least for some of

    these HAB species such a switching between modes of reproduction has been shown to

    depend not only on current environmental conditions but also on their nutritional and

    reproductive histories (see Schrader 2010). Thus, in becoming toxic or making-more-

    of-themselves at an accelerated rate, the dinos change who they are. The trouble with

    HAB species is that boundaries between organisms and environment are anything but

    clear; they not simply adapt to environmental changes, but transform their harmful

    species beings in dynamic intra-actions with their environments. Neither their

    presence nor their movements can be captured as such. What Donna Haraway calls

    the dance linking kin and kind (Haraway 2008, 17) becomes a spatiotemporal

    entanglement of productive and reproductive processes that are irresolvable in real

    time. Harmful dinoflagellates dont pre-exist our technoscientific intervention, nor are

    they produced by them; their beings cannot be determined without incorporating

    specific matters of concern into their scientific enactment; how we get to know them

    matter to what they become. In this context, the figure of slime becomes a sign of that

    which slips away from containment (Helmreich 2007); the excessive slime refuses to

    be drawn into techno-scientific representability. The HAB species historicity requires

    us rethink the time of slime that can no longer be ours alone.

    [Im not trying to make an argument against the development of speedy

    monitoring technologies (at least not as long as all funding for HAB research are

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    13/46

    13

    devoted to it), but against the perceived need for physical evidence of a quantifiable

    species being captured in its living presence before any policy decisions could be

    made.]

    For decades, marine ecologists have argued that nitrogen from agricultural run-

    offs due to the overuse of fertilizers and waste from Concentrated Animal Feeding

    Operations (CAFOs) are the major causes of the increased frequency of toxic algal

    blooms and the expansion of the dead zone in the Gulf of Mexico (D.F. Boesch and

    Brinsfield 2000; Donald F. Boesch 2002; Carpenter et al. 1998; Ferber 2001). In a

    recently published a consensus document, a group of harmful algae experts (Heisler et

    al. 2008) cite multiple examples demonstrating both total algal biomass and HAB

    occurrence decreases after reduction in nutrient input and underscore that prevention

    of large blooms through nutrient control is far preferable than attempts to eradicate

    HABs once they are established. The EPA, however, recommends voluntary measures

    for agricultural nitrogen reduction in the Mississippi Basin. And, such a

    recommendation took the EPA nearly a decade to formulate into an Action Plan.

    Meanwhile, according to Jackson, the area of the hypoxic zone has doubled in the past

    20 years to 20,000 km2, and the rate of increase in area is a linear function of nitrogen

    loading from the Mississippi drainage (Jackson 2008, 11461). The 2008 Gulf of

    Mexico Hypoxia Action Plan footnotes an earlier goal to shrink the dead zone to a size

    of 5000 km2 by 2015 with the remark that this is probably no longer achievable.11 The

    11The Gulf of Mexico Hypoxia Action Plan (available at) was required by The HarmfulAlgal Bloom and Hypoxia Research and Control Act of 1998 (HABHRCA, Public Law 108-456). In2001, federal and state officials finally agreed on a plan to reduce the size of the Gulf of Mexico deadzone to 5,000 km2. The 2001 Action Plan was highly contested by the agriculture industry. Claiming tolisten to all the stakeholders, it took the interagency Gulf of Mexico/Mississippi River WatershedNutrient Task Force another seven years to formulate an updated plan. The 2008 Gulf Hypoxia Action

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    14/46

    14

    EPA's Science Advisory Board states that to reduce hypoxia in the Gulf, a systems

    view, looking at all sources and effects, is needed (EPA Science Advisory Board

    2008: ii).12

    Even if it is clear that all sources and effects can never be determined,

    emphasizing the complexity of the system in question has been proven an effective

    strategy to postpone policy decisions indefinitely.

    Anthropologist Bill Maurer argues that when both ecology and economy

    become complex adaptive systems, postmodern capitalism appears as inevitable,

    natural state of human economic affairs (Maurer 1995, 116). In the following I ask,

    what logic of time is able to unify eco-logical/nomical systems with

    historical/evolutionary narratives of progress such that nature becomes inextricably

    linked to the past and capitalist re-productivities appear naturalized in turn.

    Gaia in Crisis: Lovelocks Call to Weapons

    James Lovelock characterizes his recent bookThe Revenge of Gaia as a wake-

    up call about the impending catastrophe of global warming. From the inventor of Gaia

    Theory, we learn that Gaia is extremely sick; sheGaia, the name of a goddess, is of

    course female! - has a fever, and if we continue business as usual, few of the teeming

    billions now living will survive (Lovelock 2007, 61). One of Lovelocks early

    articulations proposes that Gaia is a complex entity involving the earths atmosphere,

    biosphere, oceans and soil. The totality constitutes a feedback or cybernetic system

    which seeks an optimal physical and chemical environment for the biota (Lovelock,

    1972) (Margulis and Lovelock 1974). Lovelock continues: The period we are now in

    Plan apparently incorporates changes in agriculture due to the increased demand for biofuels,reassessing previous and now seemingly too optimistic goals.12 The EPA Science Advisory Board report on Hypoxia in the Northern Gulf of Mexico is available at , accessed Feb, 2011.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    15/46

    15

    is close to a crisis point for Gaia (Lovelock 2007, 43). This crisis point marks the

    failure of Gaias self-regulation mechanisms; negative feedbacks that used to assure

    Gaias equilibrium (or homeostasis) turn into positive feedbacks or runaway effects.

    This, Lovelock maintains, is already happening to Gaias temperature control system.

    All systems known to affect climate are now in positive feedback, he claims, such

    that any addition of heat from any source will be amplified (34). Gaia herself will not

    die, Lovelock assures his readers, but the odds of survival ofour civilization are slim.

    The evidence coming in from the watchers of the world, Lovelock proclaims, brings

    news of an imminent shift in our climate towards one that can easily be described as

    Hell: so hot, so deadly that only a handful of the teeming billions now alive will

    survive (147).13 According to him, the apocalypse appears certain; the only open

    question is when it will arrive.

    For science studies scholar Eileen Crist, The Revenge of Gaia is only one of the

    most extreme examples of apocalyptic thinking that she finds deeply ingrained in

    current discourses of global climate change (Crist 2007).14 Such a vision of the end,

    which implies a particular orientation towards the future as certain but yet unspecified

    time, cannot be reduced to a particular religious conviction of one of the promoters of

    Gaia theory, but appears to be a direct consequence of the teleology inherent in

    cybernetic systems theory. According to Crist, systemic thinking contributes to the

    13

    The watchers of the world are no longer a few scientific outsiders who cannot make up their mindswhich side of the same coin they prefer: romantic holism or ultimate control. Rather, as Gaia theorists donot cease to point out, Gaia theory has made it into mainstream science and has found internationalapproval under the guise of Earth System Science. In 2001, the Amsterdam Declaration on GlobalChange put forward by the heads of four international global change research programs and signed bynumerous scientists, states as fact: the Earth System behaves as a single, self-regulating systemcomprised of physical, chemical, biological and human components (Lenton 2004; see also Lovelock2007, 25).14 Susan Harding makes a similar point about Al Gores deeply religious environmentalism in AnInconvenient Truth (Harding 2006).

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    16/46

    16

    framing of global warming as theproblem of our time, diverting all attention to an

    Earth-shattering calamity at some unspecified future time at the expense of

    environmental problems humans and other species are already facing now.

    Moreover, Crist observes that the framing of climate change as imminent

    planetary emergency encourages the restriction of proposed solutions to the

    technical realm (Crist 2007, 33). She cites a 2006 Wiredarticle titled Rebooting the

    Ecosystem, which assures us that luckily, a growing number of scientists are thinking

    moreaggressively, developing incredibly ambitious technical fixes to cool theplanet

    (Crist 2007, 49). So much for the scientific humility Lubchenco calls for.

    Lovelock goes even further and suggests that climate change has to be fought

    like a war. At the early stages of the climate war, he writes, we have to make sure

    our defenses against climate change are in place before the attack begins (Lovelock

    2007, 13). Given his rhetoric of war, it is hardly surprising that Lovelock supports large

    scale geo-engineering projects as perhaps the only effective means to protect us from

    the powerful enemy (Lovelock 2007, 13).

    But who or what are the two opposing forces at war? In times of peace, Gaia is

    a living all-encompassing superorganism, a species of one (Barlow and Volk 1992),

    in which humans are certainly meant to be included -- at least ordinary humans who,

    unlike astronauts or systems modelers, do not have the privilege of viewing Gaia from

    outer space. However, it is not only difficult to imagine how this species of one

    evolves without companion, as population biologists have pointed out, but also how it

    could get so terribly disturbedout of balance as it is - without external influences. As

    Lovelock implies and Barry Commoner makes clear, Gaia must be thought of as

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    17/46

    17

    divided into two worlds: the natural ecosphere, the thin skin of air, water, and soil and

    the plants and animals that live in it, and the man-made technosphere (Commoner

    quoted in Luke 1995, 61). Only under this condition is it possible to think of a climate

    war. As humans in the technosphere disrupt the ecosphere, the ecosphere responds

    with equally or more disruptive secondary effects in the technosphere (Luke 1995,

    61).

    Ironically, then, the powerful enemy is supposed to be fought with the same

    kind of weapons - human technologies - that supposedly turned the negative feedback

    controls of self-regulating Gaia into positive feedbacks at the first place. In this view,

    the human is simultaneously an invasive species from which nature has to be protected

    and the savior of the environment, enabling a protection from himself through a

    further acceleration of external technological interventions. Jacques Derrida calls this

    logic autoimmunity, whereby a living being, in quasi-suicidalfashion, itself works

    to destroy its own protection, to immunize itselfagainstits own immunity

    (Borradori et al. 2003, 94). What is put at risk by this terrifying autoimmunitary logic

    is nothing less than the existence of the world, of the worldwide itself (98-99). In other

    words, while it threatens to destroy the world itself, this kind of autoimmunity calls into

    question the very existence of the world as a self, thatis Gaia as a species of one.

    While I think Crist is right to draw attention to environmental changes that are

    already affecting human and nonhuman populations now, the counter-narrative she

    proposes shares many of tenets of the global emergency view of the Gaia theorists she

    critiques. Crist writes, The most pernicious dimension of this representation [climate

    change as apocalypse] is that of occluding the reality we are (and have been) immersed

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    18/46

    18

    in here and nownamely, the simplification-cum-homogenization of life on Earth

    (Crist 2007, 48).

    Her affirmation of a simplification of ecosystems as the real problem of the

    current environmental crisis is in danger of complicity with the kind of systemic

    thinking that views the future as (uncertain yet predictable) telos, whose logical

    necessity, as Crist asserts, quoting Horkheimer and Adorno, remains tied to

    domination, as both its reflection and its tool (Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of

    Enlightenment, p. 37 quoted in Crist 2007, 54).

    To think of the human-induced spread of weedy species, as Crist calls the

    surviving generalists, in terms of a simplification of life supports the teleological logic

    of an evolutionary reversal, assuming that nature left to itself, demonstrates an

    evolutionary tendency of complexity increasing with time (Schneider and Sagan

    2005, 7).

    A fetishization of complexity as uninterrogated ethical good makes it

    impossible to ask who or what constitutes that we that prefers the big fish and pretty

    corals. Or formulated the other way around, such a view takes for granted that what

    we prefer coincides with what is commercially interesting. This association is,

    however, precisely what Crist (and Jackson, as noted before) tries to avoid when she

    writes, The real problemthe industrial-consumer complex that is overhauling the

    world in an orgy of exploitation, overproduction, and wasteis treated with kid gloves,

    taken as given, and regarded as beyond the reaches of effective challenge (Crist 2007,

    55) In order to understand better why attention to the diminishing biodiversity as

    progressive simplification is not a persuasive counter-narrative to an apocalyptic view

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    19/46

    19

    of climate change, we have to dig a little deeper into systems theories and consider the

    view of life in a second-order incarnation of cybernetic systems.

    Life as Self-producing Ecosystem

    Biologist Lynn Margulis, who initially collaborated with Lovelock and co-

    authored the Gaia hypothesis of the 1970s, seems now to have a rather different view of

    Gaia than her British colleague. Marguliss theory of ecological evolution highlights

    the active role of all organisms in nature in maintaining their livelihood. Her aim is to

    de-center the human not only as the pinnacle of evolution but also as steward or

    controller of nature. In their co-authored books What is Life? andAcquiring Genomes ,

    Margulis and science writer Dorian Sagan provide us with a wealth of examples of how

    the smallest organisms -- from bacteria, protists, fungi, and termites to squids -- self-

    maintain their living conditions by actively constructing their environments. We learn,

    for example, of the invention ofgenetic engineering by bacteria, of fungis agriculture,

    and of the architectonical skills of termites -- skills that make human technologies seem

    primitive. Margulis and Sagan directly contradict Lovelocks contention, shared by

    many environmentalists, that technology began with the human invention of fire and

    everything bad that is happening to our planet now followed from that. Humans, we

    are told, are special, Margulis and Sagan write somewhat cynically, We have, at least

    in Western culture, a tradition of seeing ourselves as being in position of moral

    stewardship over the rest of the life. Even in the absence of God, we imagine ourselves

    to possess a unique capacity to destroy the planet (via nuclear weaponry) or to swiftly

    change atmosphere and climate (Margulis and Sagan 1995, 221).

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    20/46

    20

    For Margulis, Gaia is not the living feedback system of Lovelocks first-order

    cybernetics; rather Gaia is symbiosis seen from space (Margulis 1986, 189). Such an

    assertion does not provide any relief from the paradoxical position the human assumes

    as located simultaneously within and outside of Gaia as observer, but for now the focus

    is on symbiosis. Symbiosis is a close association of organisms of different kinds

    making a living together, an association that can be mutually beneficial, exploitative (as

    in parasitism) or neutral. The point is that multiple organisms co-habit within and

    outside of bounded individuals. InAcquiring Genomes,Margulis and Sagan argue that

    the completely self-contained individual is a myth that needs to be replaced by a

    more flexible description (Margulis and Sagan 2003, 19). They view organisms less as

    autonomous individuals than as ecosystems: that is, as communities of bodies

    exchanging matter, energy and information with each other (23). The anthropocentric

    view that posits the human as pinnacle of evolution appears to be replaced with a bio-

    or ecocentric view. While Margulis and Sagan hold that individuality as well as

    competition are political terms inappropriate for biology,

    15

    they regard the

    maintenance of a (composite) self as a unity as the very foundation of life.

    For Margulis, Gaia is no longer a homeostatic system that tends towards a stable

    equilibrium as Lovelock supposes, but a homeorrhetic system. The word

    homeorrhetic is a composition of the Greek words homosmeaning same and rhysis

    meaning flow (editors note in Serres 1983). Homeorhesis [sic] is the process

    version of homeostasis (Gilbert 2000, 731), the term was coined by Waddington in

    15 This assertion is awkward, given thatAcquiring Genomes is full of metaphors borrowed from politicaleconomy. People are walking assemblages of microorganisms, a sort of loose committee (19). Not onlydoes evolution proceed through corporate mergers (72), it is also marked by an increasing division oflabor (48).

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    21/46

    21

    referring to the stability of developmental trajectories (Keller 2002, 190). In this view,

    Gaias self is no longer static; rather the process of self-regulation is what is

    preserved. Margulis writes, Gaian regulation, like the physiology of an embryo, is

    more homeorrhetic than homeostatic in that the internally-organized system regulates

    around moving, rather than fixed-from-the-outside, setpoints (Margulis 1990, 866).

    Margulis articulates her homeorrhetic version of a self-regulating ecosphere

    around the concept of autopoiesis, which she adopts from the Chilean cognitive

    biologists Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela.16

    Autopoiesis literally means

    self-making. Autopoiesis relies on a recursive or circular logic. An autopoietic

    system generates the components that produce its own organization (Hayles 1999).

    According to Maturana and Varela, the internal organization of a system defines the

    systems class identity. Any interaction between the autopoeitic unit and an

    environment is controlled such that the organization of the system is conserved.

    Maturana and Varela refer to the identity preserving interactions as organizational

    closure. The internal (currently actualized) configuration of the system determines or

    16 For some commentators such a move from a stable equilibrium to a dynamic equilibrium or from first-order cybernetic to a second-order cybernetic system makes a tremendous difference in terms of itsethical and political purchase. Cary Wolfe, for example, reads Maturana and Varelas autopoeitic theoryas relativistic. He then can claim that the charges brought forward against the totalitarian implications offirst-order systems theory as appropriable for technocratic management of society and nature (CarolynMerchant quoted in Wolfe 1995) or global environmental surveillance (Luke 1995) do not apply tosecond-order cybernetics. But then he points to the political danger of considering all points of view asequally valid, as if this were not a form of totalitarianism. My reading is more aligned with Katherine

    Hayles, who sees Maturana and Varela as wiggling between relativism and realism, never being able toresolve the paradox entailed in their notion of reflexivity. In other words, the (political) problem resideswithin their epistemology rather being merely a political consequence of a possible appropriation.Adding a degree of freedom (or two as Terrence Deacon does for example (Deacon 2003)) makes atheory of self-referentiality more interesting and certainly more complex, but does little to address thebasic dilemma of circularity turning into dialectical contradictions only apparently resolved on the nextlevel in a hierarchy of emergences. (How many epis do we want to add to the phenomenon before werealize, as Susan Oyama did, that the entire structure needs an overhaul rather just some fine-tuning(Oyama 2003)? As discussed in detail in (Schrader 2010), Barads notion of an intra-actively producedphenomenon provides an alternative to the hierarchical structure of systems theory (Barad 2007).

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    22/46

    22

    selects the kind of interaction with an environment. While the environment plays a

    cameo role in this scenario - it functions merely as a trigger for structural changes - the

    organism actively selects environmental patterns to which it will respond with

    structural changes such that its identity is maintained (Maturana and Varela 1998,

    169).17

    Maturana and Varela conceive of living systems in terms of the processes that

    realized them, and not in terms of the relationship with an environment (Maturana and

    Varela 1998, 12).

    For Margulis, the autopoeitic story of active self-maintenance is particularly

    attractive to counter the gene-centered Neo-Darwinian account of evolution (which

    combines Mendels genetics with Darwins account of gradual evolution via natural

    selection), which she finds reductionist, zoocentric, repressive and simply wrong

    (Margulis 1990). Nobody has ever shown, she maintains, that random mutation in gene

    frequencies accumulate and that this would lead to speciation. As an alternative,

    Margulis proposes symbiosis to be the driving force of evolution. According to her

    theory, new species originate through the acquisition of genomes from formerly

    independent microorganisms or bacteria that the larger organisms incorporate without

    digesting. It is now well-established that mitochondria within the eukaryote cell

    originated from bacteria. However, whether all speciation events can be attributed to

    symbiogenesis remains highly controversial. The main point here, however, is that

    according to Margulis, life does not adapt to a passive physicochemical environment

    17In Cary Wolfes reading of Maturana and Varela the interplay between organizational closure andstructural openness implies openness from closure (Wolfe cited in Haraway 2008, 317). In my reading,there is a clear hierarchy between organization and structure. Structural openness is only possible in sofar as it does not affect the fundamental organization of the organism, that is, its autopoiesis. ForMaturana and Varela, interactions with an environment are clearly secondary to self-maintainingprocesses, which is central to the very idea of autopoiesis. Autopoiesis happens within the horizon of apresent.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    23/46

    23

    as most neodarwinians assume; instead life actively produces and modifies its

    surroundings (Margulis 1990, 866).

    Marguliss second attack against Neo-Darwinism concerns the presumed

    activity of selfish genes. In Richard Dawkinss famous view, any ecological

    interactions are subordinated to the genes desire to be reproduced in the next

    generation. The urge to replicate would trigger competition for resources (Eldredge

    2003, 24). Against this, Margulis and Sagan hold that genes cannot be selfish: they are

    not autopoietic units, since they do not have membranes that would distinguish them

    from their environment. All autopoeitic entities are surrounded by membranes that are

    semipermeable in that, like gate-keepers, or custom officials, they permit passage of

    only certain chemicals (Margulis 1986, 11). Thus genes are not alive. For Margulis

    and Sagan, the minimal autopoietic unit is the cell and its first representatives are

    bacteria. Life began with bacteria.

    For bacteria to count as living organisms, life must not be defined by genetic

    identities, since bacteria freely exchange genes with each other (this is called lateral

    gene transfer). For that reason bacteria do not have a species, according to Margulis

    and Sagan, but are certainly alive. The argument sounds persuasive. What they

    presuppose, however, is that inheritance is necessarily and exclusively genetic. The

    fluidity of bacteria is defined against the stability of genetic reproduction. Their

    decentering of the gene is limited to rendering reproduction secondary for the definition

    of life, while holding on to a fundamental separation of productive, metabolic processes

    and reproductive, genetic processes. A series of problems will follow from that.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    24/46

    24

    Thus, rather than denouncing the oppositional hierarchy between genealogy and

    ecology, Margulis and Sagan reverse the order of things. Life is not defined by

    reproduction, but by autopoiesis. Without autopoietic behavior, organic beings are

    not alive (Margulis and Sagan 1995, 17). Self-maintenance must precede

    reproduction. For a population to evolve, its members must reproduce. Yet before

    any organic being can reproduce, it must first self-maintain (Margulis and Sagan 1995,

    19).

    Too focused on countering and dismissing the gene-centered view of the Neo-

    Darwinian synthesis, Margulis and Sagan miss out on the great opportunity their theory

    of symbiogenesis provides to deconstruct from within biology the liberal humanist

    notion of individuality. Instead of highlighting that any self is always already

    inhabited by multiple past and present others, as her theory of symbiosis suggests, we

    learn that self-maintenance is the first and only goal of life.

    In place of competitive individualism, Margulis and Sagan affirm a functional

    teleology. They argue that Darwin threw the baby out with the bathwater when, in

    getting rid of divine purpose, he denied life any kind of purpose (Margulis and Sagan

    1995, 224). For Margulis and Sagan, the purpose and the very foundation of life is self-

    maintenance, the maintenance of the functional integrity of a bounded self, which can

    be internally multiple, but is nevertheless clearly distinguishable from its environment.

    Instead of giving up the humanist notion of self-interest, choice, and purpose, Margulis

    and Sagan grant them to microorganisms too. All living beings may share our own

    feeling of free will (Margulis and Sagan 1995, 217). As Rich Doyle asserts, the theory

    of autopoiesis is placed firmly within an Aristotelian tradition that saw organisms as

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    25/46

    25

    wholes mobilized by their purpose or telos, but with a difference: the purpose of an

    organism is autonomy itself (Doyle 2003, 37).

    Autopoiesis and Time

    While Margulis and Sagan seek to connect the purposefulness of autopoeitic

    systems to their account of evolution, such a move sits somewhat uneasily with

    Maturana and Varelas account of autopoiesis. According to Katherine Hayles, the

    circular self-reflective structure of autopoiesis prevents it from an articulation with an

    evolutionary line. In Marguliss account, evolution is not gradual, nor does it proceed

    in a linear fashion, but in genomic jumps. The problem remains, however, that for

    autopoietic systems there is only the present and the ongoing processes in which it

    engages (Hayles 1995, 76). Past, future and time exist only for the observer

    (Maturana and Varela quoted in Hayles 1999, 139). The observer is itself constituted as

    an autopoeitic system through the act of observation. It is however, a special system

    that recursively generates representations of its interactions with the system it observes.

    The interactions with the representations of the interaction then constitute the human

    subject as observer (Hayles 1999, 144). While this still seems to be circular,

    temporality hinges on the fact that the domain of interaction is always larger than that

    of representation (ibid.). Time is constituted through the failure of exact

    representation. Without the capability of an observing system observing itself

    observing there would be no time.

    Representation hinges on the existence of what Maturana and Varela call a

    linguistic domain, which in turn presupposes the existence of a social structure, in

    which symbolic communication among members of a social unity becomes possible

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    26/46

    26

    (Maturana and Varela 1998, 193). Neither a social structure nor the ability to

    communicate is confined to the realm of human beings, but the emergence of a society

    presupposes, in Maturana and Varelas view, a nervous system with a specific

    plasticity. There arent any societies of microbes. The formation of society requires

    what they call a third order structural coupling between autopoeitic units (as distinct

    from a second-order-structural coupling that is responsible for the formation

    multicelluar organisms). Social life becomes possible when interactions between

    organisms become recurrent in the course of their ontogeny (Wolfe 2003, 37). In

    addition to recurrence, ontogenetic variations are necessary for the emergence and

    maintenance of a social system, which is constituted as interactions between different

    organisms of the same class identity. Individual ontogenies become part of co-

    ontogenies of organisms that each preserve their organization, giv[ing] rise to a new

    phenomenological domain (Maturana and Varela 1998, 180). The formation of a

    society is thus an emergent phenomenon that allows bidirectional communication

    across the systems boundary, constituted through the relations between individual

    autopoeitic units.

    Cary Wolfe is right to affirm that autopoeitic systems are not grounded in a

    dichotomy between human and nonhuman (Wolfe 1995). A new fundamental

    distinction, however, is introduced that classifies organisms according to their possible

    modes of inheritance based on their ability to communicate with each other, which in

    turn hinges on the plasticity of their nervous system.18 Only when there is

    (bidirectional) communication between the inside of the system and an outside, can

    18 This second order distinction between the different modes of inheritance can be seen as a consequenceof the hierarchical distinction between system and environment, that is, the privilege of self-maintenanceover interactions with an environment.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    27/46

    27

    there be time and representation.19

    As long as the environment is reduced to a mere

    trigger for structural changes, genealogical changes are impossible to conceive of.

    We Have Never Been Individuals

    Developmental biologist Scott Gilbert points out that environmentally

    dependent development is precluded in Marguliss account of autopoiesis. Gilbert

    asserts: Lynn Margulis has championed symbiosis in evolution, yet she sees

    symbioses between autopoietic (self-developing) entities. He continues: But if

    developmental symbioses represent the rule and not merely the exceptional case, then

    the entire notion ofautopoiesis must be abandoned. We are not adults entering into

    symbiotic relationships with other adults or microbes. Rather, the processes that made

    us adults are already the interactions between us and our microbes (Gilbert 2002, 213).

    The possibility of interactions between us and our microbes (or between

    microbes and their prey) during development, which Gilbert calls interspecies

    epigenesis (Gilbert quoted in Haraway 2008, 32), is precluded by the hierarchical

    structure of systems theory. According to the theory of autopoiesis, any inheritable

    transmission of traits must come from inside the organism, that is, its genome, unless

    recurrent interactions between organisms lead to the transcendence of the biological

    world through the formation of a social world. Interactions between organisms in the

    course of ontogeny cannot possibly affect the being of either one of the organisms.

    19There is of course a certain kind of communication between system and environment in any case, ifone would call a systems selective responses to environmental triggers a communication. But thiskind of communication is rather single-sided; it can be hardly viewed as interaction. Interactions becomepossible only between autopoietic entities and only when these are recurrent can one speak ofcommunication in the sense we usually understand this term.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    28/46

    28

    The oppositional hierarchy between self-maintenance and reproduction

    demands that if memory is not internal to the organism, it must be located in a distinct

    phenomenological domain. Only language, culture, or society20

    could feedback onto the

    ontogeny of an organism, but only after they have been isolated from the interacting

    bodies that constituted them. The presumption of an operational closure or internal

    teleology in Marguliss terms, precludes, the embryonic co-construction of the

    physical bodies. And this, Gilbert asserts, has many more implications because it

    means that we were never individuals (Gilbert quoted in Haraway 2008, 32).

    Gilberts critique must not be constrained to symbiotic interactions during

    development, but holds for any environmental interactions that affect the being or

    mode of inheritance of an organism, whether this is defined by a particular metabolism

    or the mode of reproduction. Due to the oppositional hierarchy between ecology and

    genealogical changes, autopoiesis cannot account for development at all other than in

    terms of structural changes that leave the systems organization or its class identity

    intact. If the purpose of life is to maintain a systems metabolism, any modification of

    it must be associated with death; and any modification of the mode of reproduction or

    life history processes must be associated with either evolution or extinction of the

    species. The assumption is, as biologist Franois Jacob succinctly summarizes, [t]he

    [genetic] program cannot receive lessons from experience (Jacob cited in Beardsworth

    1996). But how can there be a program without experience? What or who comes first?

    Susan Oyama reminds us of the undecidability between a first time and a recurrence in

    20 Language, culture, or society must not be understood as exclusively belonging to the realms ofhumans; the division is drawn differently in this second-order systems theory. However, inviting somenonhumans into these human categories based on their cognitive abilities does not make a difference thatmatters. Maturana and Varelas theory of autopoiesis fixes the terms of comparison between species inrelation to the human. I see the move here from first-order to second-order systems theory as a movefrom fixing selves to fixing relations.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    29/46

    29

    development. She writes, transmission, whether of genes or culture is supposed to

    produce developmental regularity, but , it actually presupposes such regularity.

    Something is judged to have been transmitted when it reappears (195). Oyamas

    comment hints at the Derridean structure of iterability, that is, that any assumption of a

    unit presumes it repeatability as its very definition.

    At the heart of the problem is the positing of a spatially bounded individual,

    whether static or dynamic, defined either by essence or process, that prevents thinking

    matter and energy transfer together with informational exchanges across generations.

    This is a direct consequence of the claims that identity formation must precede

    reproduction, which remains an internal genetic affair. The inability to articulate

    genealogical and ecological phenomena together is not only a failure to account for

    well-known, empirically established behaviors, but has ethical and political

    implications. The superiority of the human and a nature/culture division are

    reintroduced through different modes of inheritance.

    As discussed above, in many dinoflagellate species that contribute to harmful

    algal blooms, modifications of modes of reproductions due to altered environmental

    circumstances are the rule rather than the exception. In addition, many heterotrophic

    (those that live on the organic compounds of other critters) dino species complement

    their metabolism through the temporary acquisition of photosynthesizers. In Margulis

    and Sagans account, such a temporal change in survival strategy is inconceivable. The

    assumption of an internal teleology suggests that what they call corporate mergers are

    irreversible, and environment-dependent opportunistic cooperations are ruled out.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    30/46

    30

    Life history transformations can only be explained when both context- and

    history-dependencies are taken into account. In order to account for symbiosis or any

    other environmental contributions to development, we do not only have to give up

    the notion of autopoiesis, but also the very idea of interactions implying preexisting

    entities at a particular moment in time. Interspecies epigenesis is better understood as

    intra-activity in Barads sense, in which the agencies do not pre-exist their activities.

    As philosopher of science, Joe Rouse points out, the study of mutual interacting

    systems in which both systems are modified tacitly presupposes a standpoint outside

    the interaction themselves, from which both modifications are equivalent (Rouse 2002,

    272). In other words, tracking the changing meanings of interacting systems in time,

    presupposes a general framework of already unified human time (external to particular

    happenings), making such an outside view possible.

    The Thermodynamic Economy of Life

    While for Maturana and Varela, time exists only for an observer, as a

    consequence of self-reflexive observation (see Hayles 1999, 139), Margulis and Sagan

    postulate an immanent being of time as underlying all living processes. They

    circumvent the problem Maturana and Varelas articulation of autopoiesis has with

    evolutionary changes in supplementing autopoiesis with the second law of

    thermodynamics.21 In order to map the internal teleology that manifests itself as a

    future-directedness present in all living beings (Margulis and Sagan 1995, 17)

    onto an evolutionary arrow of time, Margulis and Sagan help themselves to one of

    21 Such a move is possible only because, unlike Maturana and Varela, Margulis and Sagan do notattempt to develop a coherent epistemology and thus leave the vexing question of observation aside.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    31/46

    31

    the most contested laws of physics.22

    Paradoxically, in this view, the being of time is

    simultaneously atemporal and directed toward a future that unifies complexity,

    diversity and productivity.

    In their bookAcquiring Genomes, they summarize their view as follows:

    Not only the development of ecosystems but the entire direction of evolution is informed by thethermodynamic mandate, the law of nature to reduce ambient gradients. In ecosystems,evolution, and economies we note an increase in complexity in, for example, the total number ofspecies spread over a larger volume, increasing differentiation of division of labor, moredeveloped and complex computer networks, and increasing functional integration of materialand energy flows such as gas, electricity, water and sewage in urban development (Margulis andSagan 2003, 48).

    Margulis and Sagan thus effectively collapse ecological and evolutionary changes -

    production and reproduction - into an economic unity and map the efficiency of

    ecological productivity onto an evolutionary direction of time.

    In an attempt to provide a counter-narrative to the Neo-Darwinist imagination

    that subordinates productive activities to the reproduction of selfish genes, in which the

    urge to replicate would trigger competition for resources (see Eldredge 2003, 24),

    Margulis and Sagan provide the global economy with an alternative biological

    foundation. Their economy is driven less by competition than by the freedom to choose

    corporate partners such that the most efficient energy-converters prevail. All life-

    sustaining intra-actions are reduced to the thermodynamic economy of matter and

    energy exchange. Instead of treating ecological interactions as if they are all about

    perpetuating genetic information into the next generation, as Richard Dawkins proposes

    22 The second law of thermodynamics posits an irreversible increase in entropy (the loss of energy foruseful work) for closed systems near a thermodynamical equilibrium. While physicists andphilosophers still debate if and under what conditions the second law is applicable to living open systemsfar from equilibrium, the Nobel-prize-winning work of Ilya Prigogine suggests that the local constructionof so-called dissipative structures increases the rate of entropy production in their environment.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    32/46

    32

    (Eldredge 1992, 6), Margulis and Sagan treat genealogical relations as if they are all

    about the maximizing of the efficiency of economic interactions.

    The purpose of life and the driver of evolution lies in the construction of

    mechanisms or structures for ever more efficient gradient reduction in order to more

    effectively accomplish the natural goal of entropy production (Schneider and Sagan

    2005, xv). Over time organisms and ecosystems become progressively more

    differentiated. With increasing complexity of its internal organization a system

    becomes more efficient in erasing differences in its environment. Thus, life no longer

    just thrives to maintain itself, but evolves towards greater efficiency in gradient

    reduction of its environment. Self-maintaining life becomes a conquest of the most

    efficient energy exchanges. The survival of the fittest becomes the survival of the

    fastest entropy (or waste) producer. As a result of more efficient gradient reduction,

    complexification becomes an end in itself and an ethical good.

    From this it follows directly that the evolution of life seems to accelerate

    (Margulis and Sagan 2003, 43). Lifes peculiarities and human technologies, Margulis

    and Sagan assert, do seem to expand at an accelerating rate of change as we come

    from the past and toward the present (ibid.). Just like the movement of capital in

    economic globalization, life needed to get faster or more mobile, and so it did, and the

    manner in which it did so logically followed from what went before (Maurer 2001,

    470).

    In other words, through a collapse of production and reproduction, it appears as

    if Time [itself] accomplished or brought about things in the course of evolution

    (Fabian 1983, 15), as if the means of production [were] already produced (see

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    33/46

    33

    Helmreich 2007, 294). Given these assumptions, an assessment of harmfulness in algae

    blooms in terms of loss of productive biocapital seems to follow naturally. The very

    possibility to ask to whom the ecological transformations of our oceans matter is

    effaced when the means of comparison between past and future states of the ocean are

    presupposed.

    But if that view were correct, if life, technology, and capital were all so well

    adjusted in their natural movements, we wouldnt be talking about an environmental

    crisis. Not everybody, it seems, can keep up with presumed global rates of

    acceleration. As Crist remarks, the greater the speed of environmental change, the

    more the adaptive ability of organisms is challenged. Anthropogenic climate change is

    unfolding faster than episodes of the pastfar faster than many species can or will be

    able to handle (Crist 2007, 44).

    For Derrida the question would be how to prevent the ontologizing of such a

    disadjustment into an injustice; in other words, how to respond without re-constructing

    an ontological difference between human culture and its natural others. If Margulis is

    correct that microorganisms have technologies, how did human technology become so

    much faster to begin with?

    The Speed of Human Time

    Philosopher and new media theorist Bernard Stiegler links the increasing speed

    of human technologies to a general acceleration of global changes. With Stiegler, the

    apocalyptic view of the environmental crisis can becomes associated with an

    acceleration of human time that is fundamentally distinct from the

    genetically/informationally programmed rhythms of the rest of nature. In Technics and

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    34/46

    34

    Time, Stiegler rethink technics as time in the face of the acceleration of technology that

    threatens our culture (see also Bennington 2000; Stiegler 1998).

    According to Stiegler (and Derrida), for there to be time there must be

    diffrance (a differing/deferral) betweenphysis and tekhn. Diffrance is the

    articulation of the living with the non-living (Derrida 1982). This also means that there

    must be memory before any division between nature and culture, humanity and

    animality. While for Derrida diffrance is quasi-transcendental -- neither in nor beyond

    history, but its condition of possibility -- Stiegler tries to locate diffrance as a

    particular stage of life within evolutionary history. Hence for Stiegler, there is a

    rupture betweenphysis and tekhn within history. Following paleontologist Leroi-

    Gourhans description of the process of humanization, Stiegler associates this rupture

    with the emergence of the human, who is marked by the co-evolution of brain and tool.

    For Stiegler, the emergence of the human coincides with an exteriorization of

    memory as technology. The human did not invent technology but is constituted as

    technology. Before the emergence of human and technology, memory would have been

    located entirely within the living being as genetic program. The relationship between

    an organism and its environment would be genetically fixed. (This is not very different

    from Maturana and Varelas postulate of operational closure for a living system, even

    though they would not want to associate this closure with a genetic program.) As a

    result of the exteriorization of memory an archive is born that defines the human

    species particular relation to time (see Wills 2006, 241). The human being is

    essentially prosthetic (Stiegler 1998, 179). In this way, Stiegler can claim that the

    human is constituted by technology and that technics is time. Now time itself has a

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    35/46

    35

    history and can be associated with a speed, the speed of technology. Stiegler then

    rethinks speed in terms of technological transformations. The point of Stieglers move,

    as I read it, is to be able to structurally distinguish between different kinds of

    technologies associated with different cultural historical periods, as for example

    between analog and digital technologies. In Stieglers account, the possibility of a

    periodization of different kinds of technologies comes at the price of a renewed

    fundamental distinction between the human and its animal other.

    Stiegler hence builds his analysis of the acceleration of time associated with

    technological domination and globalization on the distinction of fundamentally

    different modes of inheritance associated with humanity and animality. According to

    him, [h]umans die but their histories remain -- this is the big difference between

    mankind and other life forms (Stiegler 2003). Stiegler is here not thinking of the

    individual memories we have of our deceased grandparents, but of the memories we

    make available to future generations through books, films, databases, and other archival

    technologies. In addition to technologies specifically designed as archives, which

    Stiegler calls mnemotechnical systems, any technical object functions as memory

    device, such as a piece of pottery or a tool, enabling future generations to

    inherit/remember experiences they never lived (Stiegler 2003). Such a mode of

    inheritance transcends the presumed genetic programming of other animals. So far, this

    is not very different from the kind of epigenetic memory Maturana and Varela associate

    with the plasticity of the nervous system as condition for the emergence of society. For

    Stiegler, however, this kind of memory is explicitly linked to technics as an

    exteriorization of human evolution, which he calls epiphilogenesis. He describes

    epiphilogenesis as sedimentation of succession of epigeneses or alternatively an

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    36/46

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    37/46

    37

    Stiegler presumes that the speed of technology is correlated to the precision of

    technology, the enhanced precision is achieved through an enhanced manipulation of

    the object to be recorded. For Stiegler the promise of real-time technologies lies in

    their calculability as force against shortsighted economic calculations. Like the Gaia

    theorists, for Stiegler the hope of technology lies in more and better control of

    technological calculations.

    If , however, as it seems in HAB research, the speed of technoscience and the

    speed of policy decisions are inversely proportional, such that the faster the former the

    slower the latter proceeds, the very idea of an acceleration of time seems to prevent

    environmental decision making. Such a disproportionality might be just an effect of the

    very illusion ofreal-time that built on the assumption that there once was a nature all

    by itself. Promising ever greater exactness and control, real-time technologies seek

    their own disappearance as technology through the erasure of time. In fact, real-time

    technology is an oxymoron.

    As Derrida points out, it makes no sense tofetishize the concept of

    acceleration: there isnt a single acceleration. The danger of assuming an objective

    speed which is continuous and which gets progressively faster is the erasure of

    differences of rhythm, heterogeneous accelerations that also manifest themselves

    within technological developments (Derrida 2002, 249-50).

    Conclusion: Is There Hope in The Rise of The Slime?

    As noted above, major research efforts into HAB research focus on monitoring

    and control. According to Lovelocks story, Gaia is a system in need of global

    management. In Lovelocks narrative, Gaia resembles less a sick organism than what

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    38/46

    38

    Timothy Luke calls an ensemble of eco-knowledge and geo-power ( Luke 1995).

    While suggesting urgency and emergency, Lovelocks apocalyptic narrative

    strategically promotes delays: oriented towards the future catastrophe, it diverts from

    any engagements with environmental problems humans and nonhumans are facing

    now. The options we are facing in this scenario are either risking the world or giving-up

    on the idea that there is a self, a world itself. As Marilyn Strathern remarks, Nature as

    ground for the meaning of cultural practices can no longer be taken for granted if

    Nature itself is regarded as having to be protected and promoted (Strathern 1992, 177).

    In more fluid accounts of systems theories, I have discussed two opposing

    movements in terms of their modes of inheritance. In Margulis and Sagans account,

    human technologies and their accelerations are naturalized through the collapse of

    evolutionary (internal temporal changes) and economic (external spatial changes)

    interactions. Theres no fundamental distinction between human and other animals, but

    their relationship is fixed in terms of increasing complexity. The question of an

    environmental problem cannot even arise, since everything moves in synch as

    determined by the second law of thermodynamics. The rise of the slime cant possibly

    be bad news, since a) the slime always already had all the power it deserves and b)

    everything moves only in accordance to Gaias internal organization that maintains

    itself. As Derrida would say, once one has named a telos, theres no distinction between

    opinion or belief and knowledge: that is, there is no more space for an environmental

    critique (Derrida 1984).

    Maturana and Varela and Stiegler maintain the opposition between internal

    genetic memory and an external technical or cultural memory. In one case the

    externalization of memory is associated with cognitive ability, in the other with

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    39/46

    39

    technology, and in both cases with the beginning of time (as subjective illusion in the

    former and as objective reality in the latter case). Natural evolution, if that term would

    even make sense in their accounts, is timeless. Thus, no matter how fast the speed of

    technology, it is always out of sync with nature by its very definition. If that is a mark

    of a crisis then we are living in a permanent one.

    What could be the meaning of the rise of the slime with which this pager

    began? For Lovelock it might be a warning that a sustainable fishery is an illusion. For

    Margulis and Sagan, it might be an affirmation of bacterial power, and their more

    advanced genetic engineering technologies. My hope is that the rise of slime may

    become an opportunity to reconfigure the time of slime that is, now - and ask anew

    to whom the ecological transformations of our oceans matter.

    My point is not a specific answer, but the very possibility to pose the question

    that has been effaced by assumptions about the unalterable movement of the global

    economy of our time. Any preconception of our time that fixes the relationship

    between nature and culture, whether in terms of complexity, cognitive ability, or speed,

    effaces the possibility to ask who are the we that get to eat the big fish? As Donna

    Haraway remarks, there will be no nature without justice (Haraway 2004, 86), which

    also means, as Jean Luc Nancy asserts, Our time means precisely, first of all, a

    certain suspension of time, of time conceived as always flowing. A pure flow of time

    could not be ours (Nancy 1990, 155).

    For Margulis and Sagan, the most significant difference between humans and

    other animals is self-deception; we are the only beings accomplished enough to fully

    fool ourselves, they write (Margulis and Sagan 1995, 221). I do not think they mean

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    40/46

    40

    by this that we are the only ones capable of reflexivity or the making of metalinguistic

    distinctions, e.g. to pretend pretense, as Lacan proposes, or the only beings who can

    observe themselves observing. Rather they imply that we keep fooling ourselves by

    assuming that we are or could be in control of the rest of nature. Would it be possible to

    build responsible environmental science around the insight that humans are in fact not

    in control? This would require giving up not only the idea that humans create

    technologies, but also that human nature could be circumscribed by a privileged

    relationship to technology. Technology would not only be an intervention into the

    rhythms of the relationship between humans and the rest of nature, but would become

    an apparatus in the Baradian sense, reconfiguring the dynamics and topologies of

    human/nature relations in every intra-action. In Derridas terms, it would require us to

    re-think the relation between knowing and acting .. . between the invention that finds

    what was already there and the one that produces new mechanisms and new spaces

    (Derrida 1984, 23). Perhaps that is what Lubchenco meant by producing knowledge

    that reduces the rate of change. It might require remembering with Derrida that an

    originary technicity inhabits all life and matter, rendering all boundary construction --

    scientific or otherwise -- an impossible ethical and political act. Scientific responsibility

    is that impossible possibility.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    41/46

    41

    References

    Anderson, D. M., P. M. Glibert, and J. M. Burkholder (2002), 'Harmful Algal Bloomsand Eutrophication: Nutrient Sources, Composition, and Consequences',Estuaries, 25 (4B), pp. 704-26.

    Anderson, Donald M. and John S . Ramsdell (2005), 'Harrness: A Framework for HabResearch and Monitoring in the United States for the Next Decade',Oceanography, 18 (2), pp. 238-44.

    Barad, Karen (2007),Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and theEntanglement of Matter and Meaning; Durham: Duke University Press.

    Barlow, Connie and Tyler Volk (1992), 'Gaia and Evolutionary Biology',BioScience,42 (9), pp. 686-93.

    Beardsworth, Richard (1996), 'Nietzsche, Freud and the Complexity of the Human:

    Towards a Philosophy of Digestion', Tekhnema, 3 (3)., accessed Aug., 2008.

    --- (1998a), 'The Temporal Object', Tekhnema, 4 (4)., accessed Aug., 2008.

    --- (1998b), 'Thinking Technicity', Cultural Value, 2 (1), pp. 70-86.

    Bennington, Geoffrey (2000), 'Emergencies', inInterrupting Derrida, New York:Routledge, pp. 162-79.

    Boesch, D.F. and R.B. Brinsfield (2000), 'Coastal Eutrophication and Agriculture:Contributions and Solutions', inBiological Resource Management: ConnectingScience and Policy, eds. E. Balzs, et al., Berlin: Springer, pp. 93-115.

    Boesch, Donald F. (2002), 'Challenges and Opportunities for Science in ReducingNutrient Overenrichment of Coastal Ecosystems',Estuaries 25 (4B), pp. 886-900.

    Borradori, Giovanna, Jrgen Habermas, and Jacques Derrida (2003), Philosophy in aTime of Terror : Dialogues with Jrgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida ;Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Carpenter, S. R., et al. (1998), 'Nonpoint Pollution of Surface Waters with Phosphorusand Nitrogen',Ecological Applications, 8 (3), pp. 559-68.

    Clark, Nigel (2002), 'The Demon-Seed: Bioinvasion as the Unsettling of EnvironmentalCosmopolitanism', Theory Culture Society, 19 (1-2), pp. 101-25.

    Crist, Eileen (2007), 'Beyond the Climate Crisis: A Critique of Climate ChangeDiscourse', Telos, 141, pp. 2955.

    http://tekhnema.free.fr/3Beardsworth.htm%3ehttp://tekhnema.free.fr/3Beardsworth.htm%3ehttp://tekhnema.free.fr/4Beardsworth.htm%3ehttp://tekhnema.free.fr/4Beardsworth.htm%3ehttp://tekhnema.free.fr/4Beardsworth.htm%3ehttp://tekhnema.free.fr/3Beardsworth.htm%3e
  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    42/46

    42

    Cullen, J.J. (2008), 'Observation and Prediction of Harmful Algae Blooms', inReal-Time Coastal Observing Systems for Ecosystem Dynamics and Harmful Algal

    Blooms, eds. M. Babin, C.S. Roesler, and J.J. Cullen, Paris, France: UNESCOPublishing, pp. 1-41.

    Deacon, Terrence W. (2003), 'The Hierarchic Logic of Emergence: Untangling the

    Interdependence of Evolution and Self-Organization', inEvolution andLearning : The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered, eds. Bruce H. Weber and David J.Depew, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 273-308.

    Derrida, Jacques (1982), 'Diffrance', inMargins of Philosophy, Chicago: University ofChicago Press, pp. 3-27.

    --- (1984), 'No Apocalypse, Not Now (Full Speed Ahead, Seven Missiles, SevenMissives)',Diacritics, 14 (2), pp. 20-31.

    --- (2002), 'Nietzsche and the Machine: An Interview with Richard Beardsworth', inNegotiations: Interventions and Interviews 1971-2001, Stanford, CA: Stanford

    University Press, pp. 215-56.

    Diaz, Robert J. and Rutger Rosenberg (2008), 'Spreading Dead Zones andConsequences for Marine Ecosystems', Science, 321 (5891), 926 - 29.

    Doyle, Richard (2003), Wetwares : Experiments in Postvital Living; Minneapolis, MN:University of Minnesota Press.

    Eldredge, Niles (1992), 'Where the Twain Meet Causal Intersections between theGenealogical and Ecological Real', in Systematics, Ecology, and theBiodiversity Crisis: Causal Intersections between the Genealogical and

    Ecological Realms ed. Niles Eldredge, New York: Columbia University Press,pp. 1-14.

    --- (2003), 'The Sloshing Bucket: How the Physical Realm Controls Evolution', inEvolutionary Dynamics : Exploring the Interplay of Selection, Accident,

    Neutrality, and Function, eds. James P. Crutchfield and Peter Schuster, Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 3-32.

    Fabian, Johannes (1983), Time and the Other: How Anthropology Makes Its Object:Columbia University Press.

    Ferber, Dan (2001), 'Keeping the Stygian Waters at Bay', Science, 291 (5506), pp. 968 -

    73.

    Gilbert, Scott F. (2000), 'Diachronic Biology Meets Evo-Devo: C. H. Waddington'sApproach to Evolutionary Developmental Biology',American Zoologist, 40 (5),pp. 72937.

    --- (2002), 'The Genome in Its Ecological Context: Philosophical Perspectives onInterspecies Epigenesis',Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci., 981, pp. 20218.

  • 7/31/2019 Schrader EnvironmentalCrisis

    43/46

    43

    Hansen, Mark (2004), ''Realtime Synthesis' and the Diffrance of the Body:Technocultural Studies in the Wake of Deconstruction', Culture Machine, (6).,accessed Aug., 2008.

    Haraway, Donna J. (2004), 'The Promises of Monsters: A Regenerative Politics for

    Inappropriate/D Others', in The Haraway Reader, New York: Routledge, pp.63-124.

    --- (2008), When Species Meet; Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Harding, Susan (2006), 'Environmental Evangelism in an Inconvenient Truth', TheMultispecies Salon (University of Californ