106
Two Modalities of Case Assignment in Sakha Mark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There are two competing ideas about how morphological case is assigned in the recent generative literature. The standard view, developed by Chomsky, is that case is assigned by designated functional heads to the closest NP under an Agree relation. The alternative, proposed by Marantz 1991 and others, is that case is assigned to one NP if there is a second NP in the same local domain. We present evidence from the Turkic language Sakha that these two approaches to case theory are complementary. Specifically, we argue that accusative case and dative case in Sakha are assigned by Marantz-style configurational rules that do not refer to functional categories. Crucial evidence for this comes from passives, agentive nominalizations, subject raising, possessor raising, and case assignment in PPs. In contrast, nominative and genitive case are assigned by functional heads (T and D) in the Chomskian way; this is needed to explain the relationship between case marking and agreement in Sakha. We conclude that two distinct systems of case assignment can coexist peacefully, not only in Universal Grammar, but even in the grammar of particular languages. 1. Introduction In the generative syntax literature, there coexist two major ideas about how morphological case markers come to be 1

Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Two Modalities of Case Assignment in Sakha

Mark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova

Rutgers University

February, 2008

Abstract: There are two competing ideas about how morphological case is assigned in the recent generative literature. The standard view, developed by Chomsky, is that case is assigned by designated functional heads to the closest NP under an Agree relation. The alternative, proposed by Marantz 1991 and others, is that case is assigned to one NP if there is a second NP in the same local domain. We present evidence from the Turkic language Sakha that these two approaches to case theory are complementary. Specifically, we argue that accusative case and dative case in Sakha are assigned by Marantz-style configurational rules that do not refer to functional categories. Crucial evidence for this comes from passives, agentive nominalizations, subject raising, possessor raising, and case assignment in PPs. In contrast, nominative and genitive case are assigned by functional heads (T and D) in the Chomskian way; this is needed to explain the relationship between case marking and agreement in Sakha. We conclude that two distinct systems of case assignment can coexist peacefully, not only in Universal Grammar, but even in the grammar of particular languages.

1. Introduction

In the generative syntax literature, there coexist two major ideas about how

morphological case markers come to be associated with individual noun phrases in ways

that reflect aspects of the syntactic structures those noun phrases appear in.

The more common idea is that structural case features are assigned to NPs by

nearby functional heads. For example, nominative case might be assigned by (finite) T

to the nearest NP that T c-commands. In a similar manner, accusative case might be

assigned by (active, transitive) v to the nearest NP it c-commands, genitive case might be

assigned by (possessive) D to the nearest NP, dative case might be assigned by (certain)

P(s), and so on. This is the view of Chomsky (2000, 2001) and his many followers

1

Page 2: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

within the Minimalist Program. It is also the result of a fairly direct (although long and

complex) line of development from the first Chomskian ideas about case assignment,

presented in Chomsky 1981. This is the “governing” view that is usually adopted by

generative researchers when their interests touch on case theory but it is not their primary

area of study. See also Legate 2008 for a recent defense of this approach.

There is however an “official opposition” to this governing view, which has won

a few seats in the Parliament of generative theory. This is the idea that case assigned to

noun phrases on a configurational basis. More specifically, what case a particular NP has

typically depends on this view on whether there are other NPs (“case competitors”) in the

same local domain or not. For example, accusative case might be assigned to the lower

of two NPs in a clause, whereas (in another language) ergative case is assigned to the

higher of two NPs in a clause. If there is only one NP in the clause, a different case

might be assigned—the unmarked case, nominative or absolutive. In this sort of theory,

functional heads play no direct role in case assignment, although they play an indirect

role in helping to define the relevant domains. (The notion “same clause” might be

defined in terms of the projections of a designated functional head such as T, for

example.) The first and purest proposal of this sort is by Marantz (1991). Bittner and

Hale’s (1996) rather intricate case theory also has this core idea as an important part of its

inspiration. More recently, Marantz’s conception has been adopted in work by Bobaljik

(to appear), and is reasserted at length and developed by McFadden (2004), among

others. It thus has some popularity among those linguists for Case theory is a primary

object of study.

2

Page 3: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

As far as we know, these two different conceptions of how morphological case

works have always been conceived of as rivals, with each aspiring to capture all

(structural) case assignment phemonena in its own way. But it is logically possible that

they are in fact complementary. That would be true if it could be shown that some cases

are assigned by functional heads in the Chomskian way, whereas other cases are assigned

by a configurational algorithm in Marantz’s sense. Moreover, there are two different

grains of linguistic description at which this complementary could exist. The goal of this

paper is to argue in favor of this last view, that the two modalities of case assignment not

only coexist side by side in Universal Grammar, but they can even coexist internal to the

same language. This we do by a relatively detailed analysis of case assignment in the

Sakha language (also called Yakuts), a Turkic language spoken in Northern Siberia.

Descriptively speaking, Sakha has four distinct cases that we take to be structural:

nominative, accusative, dative, and genitive. Some very ordinary examples are:

(1) a. Min kel-li-m.

I-nom come-past-1sg

‘I came.’

b. Min yt-y kör-dü-m.

I dog-acc see-past-1sg

‘I saw the dog.’

c. Misha Masha-qa at-y bier-de

Misha Masha-DAT horse-ACC give-past.3

‘Misha gave Masha a horse.’

3

Page 4: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Our claim is that this four-case system divides neatly in half. Accusative and dative case

are assigned by the configurational rules stated in (2).

(2) a. If there are two NPs in the same VP-phase and neither is marked for case,

value the case feature of higher NP as dative.

b. If there are two NPs in the same phase and neither is marked for case,

value the case feature of the lower NP as accusative.

We assume the usual definitions of “higher” and “lower” in terms of c-command: NP X

is higher than NP Y if and only if X c-commands Y, and NP X is lower than NP Y if and

only if Y c-commands X. The rules in (2) are “Marantzian” in the sense that what is

crucial for the assignment of case to a given NP is whether or not there is a second NP in

the same domain or not, and if so what the relative structural configuration between the

two NPs is. No direct role is attributed to which functional categories are present in local

environment. In contrast, we claim that functional categories are deeply involved in the

assignment of nominative and genitive case, as expressed in (3).

(3) a. T values the case of NP as nominative if and only if T Agrees with NP.

b. D values the case of NP as genitive if and only if D Agrees with NP.

These are exactly the sorts of case assignment rules that are put forward in Chomsky

(2000, 2001), and we adopt his theory of the Agree relation. In this way, the elements of

two prior theories are combined within the grammar of a single language.1

There is a clear superficial difference between the two types of case in Sakha that

gives our position some a priori plausibility. The Chomskian approach is built around the

intuition that case and agreement are two sides of the same abstract linguistic relationship

(Agree), which holds between a functional head and a nearby noun phrase. Agreement

4

Page 5: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

on the functional head is the transferring of phi-features from the NP to the functional

head as a result of the relation being established, whereas case marking on the NP is the

transferring of a case feature (or perhaps just a category feature) from the functional head

to the NP as a result of the same relationship. For nominative and genitive, the idea that

case and agreement are intimately related in this way is attractively transparent in Sakha:

nominative NPs in a clause go along with subject agreement on the finite verb (see

(1a,b)), and genitive NPs within a DP go along with possessive agreement on the noun.

This is built into (3). But there is no comparable “object” agreement to make visible a

relationship between an NP with accusative or dative case and any particular functional

head; unlike nominative and genitive NPs, accusative and dative NPs are never agreed

with in Sakha. This makes it not implausible, we think, that accusative and dative case

are assigned in a different way from nominative and genitive, a way that does not depend

on functional heads. In other words, the superficial different in overt agreement could in

fact be a hint as to the two different modalities of case assignment that are at work here.

We present some stronger morphosyntactic arguments that this is correct.

We develop our argument as follows. First we provide some minimal

morphological background in section 2. We then concentrate on the rules that assign

accusative and dative case in (2), showing a range of phenomena that they account for

and pointing out why these configurational rules are more satisfactory than the standard

Chomskian alternative (section 3). This exploration starts with simple transitive and

ditransitive constructions, proceeds through causatives, anticausatives, passives, and

nominalizations, ending with some complex data from a set of raising constructions. We

then pose the question of whether case assignment in Sakha is configurational all the way

5

Page 6: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

down. We argue that the answer is no (section 4). While it is not hard to give a

Marantzian account of nominative and genitive case in Sakha in isolation, this view does

not explain the interaction between case and agreement that is found in the language. In

particular, the Chomskian rules in (3) capture the broad generalization that it is never

possible for two functional heads to agree with the same noun phrase in Sakha, whereas a

Marantzian alternative does not. We thus conclude that there are essentially two different

case systems, coexisting peacefully in Sakha (section 4). Throughout the paper, we keep

the attention entirely on Sakha, and make no claims about how case is assigned in other

languages. Looking at Sakha itself is enough, we claim, to function as a sort of existence

proof that both kinds of case assignment are attested in Universal Grammar; this then can

form the basis for more typologically oriented studies in the future, which seek to learn

about how these two kinds of case marking are distributed across languages.

2. Background on the Morphology of Case

Some background will help the reader to understand the examples. Sakha is an SOV,

head-final language with agglutinative morphology, rather free word order, and extensive

vowel harmony. In these respects, it is not unlike its better-known relative, Turkish.

Much information about this language can be gleaned from Vinokurova 2005, which we

build on and follow in many particulars, especially the work on accusative case in chapter

6. See also Krueger 1962 and Stachowski and Menz 1988 for basic information.

Accusative and dative case have relatively straightforward morphological

exponents in Sakha, although both have many surface allomorphs as a result of

phonological processes. Accusative case is generally marked by /I/ after a consonant and

6

Page 7: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

/nI/ after a vowel, the high vowel harmonizing with the vowels of the stem in frontness

and roundness, as in Turkish. Dative is generally marked by /kA/, with the nonhigh

vowel undergoing harmony and the consonant also subject to various phonological

changes. As in many languages, NPs in nominative case are morphologically unmarked,

with no overt affix. In section 3, we take up the question of whether these NPs are

assigned case in the syntax, which is spelled out with the null string in the morphology,

or whether they are simply left uncase marked.

Genitive case was not illustrated in (1), because it raises some special

morphological issues in Sakha. All other Turkic languages have a robust genitive case

suffix (e.g. –(n)In in Turkish), but this has been largely lost in Sakha (Stachowski and

Menz 1998:421). As a result, an NP with genitive case is indistinguishable on the surface

from an NP with nominative case in most environments. But there is an important

exception. Many Turkic languages have special allomorphs of the case markers when

they follow (third person) possessive agreement markers (Stachowski and Menz

1998:422). This is true for Sakha as well; for example, accusative is realized as /n/ after

a possessive suffix, dative is realized as /qar/, and so on. Nominative is realized as /Ø/

even after the possessive suffix. But genitive is not; after a possessive suffix, the genitive

is (like the accusative) realized as /n/ (Krueger 1962:77). The genitive in Sakha thus has

no distinct endings of its own, but it can be seen to be different from nominative when the

NP in question is possessed and it can be seen to be different from accusative when the

NP is not possessed, as shown in (4).

(4) a. Masha-(Ø) öl-lö; Masha-(Ø) aqa-ta-(Ø) öl-lö.

Masha-NOM die-PAST.3sS Masha-GEN father-3s-NOM die-PAST.3sS

7

Page 8: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘Masha died.’ ‘Masha’s father died.’

b. Min Masha-ny kör-dü-m; Min Masha-(Ø) aqa-ty-n kör-dü-m

Min Masha-ACC see-PST-1sS; Min Masha-GEN akha-3sP-ACC see-PST-1sS

‘I saw Masha.’ ‘I saw Masha’s father.’

c. Masha-(Ø) at-a; Masha-(Ø) aqa-ty-n at-a

Masha-GEN horse-3sP Masha-GEN father-3sP-GEN horse-3sP

‘Masha’s horse’ ‘Masha’s father’s horse’

We thus assume that genitive still exists as a distinct value of the case feature in Sakha

syntax. The allomorphy of the case markers can be accounted for with in a Distributed

Morphology-like framework (Halle and Marantz 1993) by a system of morphological

spell-out rules like those in (5).

(5) a. case /GAr/ / POSS ____ [dat]

b. case /n/ / POSS ____ [acc/gen]

c. case /GA/ / ___[dat]

d. case /(n)I/ / ___[acc]

e. case Ø (elsewhere)

Other, more theory internal evidence for saying that genitive case still exists in Sakha can

be seen in the coherence of the account that this allows us to construct in section 4 below.

For completeness, we note that Sakha also has several inherent cases, including

ablative, instrumental, comitative, etc.. These are related to particular semantic roles, and

never participate in syntactic alternations that we know of. Like most other investigators

into case theory, we assume that this is a different phenomenon, and do not include it in

our analysis. More specifically, we tentatively follow McFadden (2004) in assuming that

8

Page 9: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

the inherent case markers are either postpositions themselves, or they are special cases

assigned by various null postpositions. Some instances of dative case in Sakha also fall

into this category—especially those on location and time-denoting expressions. (These

bear locative case in other Turkic languages, but this form has also been lost in Sakha

(Stachowski and Menz 1998:421).)

3. The configurational case marking of objects

We begin with demonstrating the virtues of the configurational rules for the assignment

of dative and accusative case given in (2). Our exposition moves from the relatively

simple and straightforward data, for which Sakha is no different from many other

languages, to the more complex and surprising data, where the advantages of our

proposal can be seen the most clearly.

3.1 Simple active sentences

It comes as no surprise that the objects of simple active dyadic predicates in Sakha are

marked in accusative case, triadic predicates have one object in accusative case and one

object in dative case, and the subjects of most predicates bear neither accusative or

dative. (1) presented some relevant examples; (6) gives a few more.

(6) a. Min ülel-ii-bin.

I-nom work-aor-1sg

‘I worked.’

b. Erel kinige-ni atyylas-ta.

Erel book-acc buy-past.3

‘Erel bought the book.’

9

Page 10: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

c. Masha aqa-ty-gar suruk-u yyt-ta.

Masha father-3sP-DAT letter-ACC send-PAST.3

‘Masha sent her father a letter.’

And, not surprisingly, these simple patterns follow from our rules in (2). In sentences

like (6c) there are two NPs inside the VP. Therefore the structurally higher one—the

goal argument—is marked dative by (2a).2 In sentences like (6b) there is only one NP in

the VP domain, the subject being generated outside VP in Spec, vP. Therefore, (2a) does

not apply. Nor does (2b) apply in the VP domain, since there is only one NP in VP. The

clause as a whole does contain more than one NP, however. Hence (2b) applies on the

CP phase/cycle, marking the lower NP (the direct object) as accusative.

2 If goal and benefactive expressions are generated in the specifier of a Applicative head,

different from the core Verb, then we must consider the ApplP to be a kind of extended

VP, with the maximal VP (i.e, ApplP) constituteing the lower phase. We see no

objection to this analysis, but neither is there any overt applicative morpheme in Sakha

that calls out for it.

1 In addition to their other differences, the two types of case theory are generally held to

apply in different components of the grammar. Chomsky’s case assignment by

functional categories is held to take place in syntax, whereas Marantz (1991) assumes

that his configurational case assignment rules apply at PF. As far as we can see, the

nature of the case assignment rules is independent of what component of the grammar

they apply in. We assume that both (2) and (3) happen in the narrow syntax; in fact (2)

can apply so as to bleed the application of (3) as we shall see. See also Legate (2008) for

arguments against applying case assignment only at PF.

10

Page 11: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

A technical detail of the rules in (2) helps to account for a somewhat less trivial

property of case marking in Sakha. Like Turkish and quite a few other languages, Sakha

is a differential object marking language—a language in which not all direct objects bear

the same kind of case marking. The accusative case marker –(n)I only appears on NPs

that receive a definite and/or specific interpretation (Vinokurova 2005:322). When the

thematic object is indefinite, then it bears no case suffix, as shown in (8).

(7) a. Erel kinige atyylas-ta.

Erel book-Ø buy-past.3

‘Erel bought a book/books.’

b. Min saharxaj sibekki-(ni) ürgee-ti-m.

I yellow flower-(acc) buy-past-1sg

‘I picked (the/a certain) yellow flower(s).’

A way of capturing this phenomenon emerges from (2) if we assume that the locality

domains in which case competition is evaluated are crucially phases in something like

Chomsky’s sense. There are two phases in an ordinary clause, CP and (let us assume)

VP.3 The indefinite object stays strictly inside the VP phase, and so is never in the same

domain as the subject. Since the object and the subject each are the only NPs in their

respective domains, both are left unmarked by the rules in (2). In contrast, definite

objects undergo object shift, away from the verb, to escape the domain of existential

closure (Diesing 1992 and much related work). This movement places the object inside

the same domain as the subject. The two now count as case competitors for one another,

and accusative case is assigned to the lower NP, the object as shown in (9b). (Notice that

it does not matter for these purposes whether the subject moves to Spec, TP or not.)

11

Page 12: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

(8) a. [[ Erel [VP book buy ] v ] T ] (=(6b)) phase 1 phase 2

b. [[ Erel [VP book [VP t buy ] v ] T ] (=(7a)) phase 2 phase 1

Some support for this view that syntactic movement plays a role in whether an

object is marked accusative or not comes from the interaction of case marking and word

order with respect to adverbs. Objects that are not marked for case must follow VP-

adverbs like ‘thoroughly’ and ‘quickly’ whereas objects with accusative case come

before this class of adverbs in the unmarked order; the paradigm in (8) is typical.

(9) a. Masha salamaat-*(y) türgennik sie-te.

Masha porridge-ACC quickly eat-past.3

‘Masha ate the porridge quickly.’

b. Masha türgennik salamaat-(#y) sie-te.

Masha quickly porridge-acc eat-past.3

‘Masha ate porridge quickly.’

Accusative on ‘porridge’ only if it bears contrastive focus

Assuming that these adverbs are generated at the left edge of the VP, they reveal whether

the movement shown in (7) has happened or not, and show that this movement

determines the case marking in the manner described in (2b). One complication—which

we take to be minor—is that accusative case marking on the post adverbial object in (8b)

is not strictly impossible, but is given a special interpretation, as having contrastive focus

on the accusative-marked object. We tentatively assume that this is not a syntactically

simple structure; rather this particular surface string can only derived by a series of

12

Page 13: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

movements into the Left Periphery, driven by considerations of focus and topic

movement (see Vinokurova 2005:xx for a possible derivation).

The same dependence of accusative case marking on object shift can be seen in

ditransitive clauses in Sakha. The goal in such clauses is always marked dative, whereas

the theme can be unmarked or accusative depending on both its specificity and its

position with respect to the goal. When the theme is unmarked for case, it must be a

nonspecific indefinite and must follow the goal; when the theme is marked for case, it is

specific or definite and comes before the goal unless additional, focus driven movements

also take place:

(10) a. Min Masha-qa kinige-(#ni) bier-di-m.

I Masha-DAT book-ACC give-PAST-1sS

‘I sent Masha books/a book.’

b. Min kinige-*(ni) Masha-qa bier-di-m.

Masha book-ACC Masha-DAT give-PAST-1sS

‘I gave the book to Masha.’

Prior to any (relevant) movement, the theme and the goal/benefactive are both in VP,

with the goal/benefactive c-commanding the theme. (This can be shown using standard

Barss-Lasnik-Larson tests involving pronominal binding (Barss and Lasnik 1986, Larson

1988).) (2a) then assigns dative to the goal/benefactive NP on the VP cycle. (2a) is

ordered before (2b) by the general (Paninian) ‘Elsewhere’ condition, because (2a) is a

more specific rule than (2b), limited to applying in only one kind of phase (VP). Once

(2a) applies, it has the effect of bleeding the application of (2b) in the VP cycle, since

only NPs that are unmarked for case are visible to the case competition. Hence, the

13

Page 14: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

theme is not automatically marked accusative simply by virtue of being in the same VP

as the goal. If no movement happens, then the theme never enters the CP phase, (2b)

never applies, and accusative case is not assigned. This results in sentences like (9a).

Alternatively, the theme NP can undergo object shift to the edge of the VP phase, thereby

crossing the goal and escaping the domain of existential closure. If it does, then it is

visible on the CP phase, as is the subject Masha. The two are case competitors, and

accusative is assigned to the theme, the lower of the two NPs. In this way, examples like

(9b) are derived.

(11) a. [[ Erel [VP Masha-DAT book buy ] v ] T ] (=(10a)) phase 1 phase 2

b. [[ Erel [VP book-ACC [VP Masha-DAT t buy ] v ] T ] (=(10b)) phase 2 phase 1

Note that it may well be possible to move the goal NP out of the VP proper into the CP

phase, for reasons of specificity or whatever. However, this will not affect its case

marking, because it is already marked as dative by (2a) on the VP cycle, and such case

marking is indelible (see section 4). It thus follows from our rules that there is

differential object marking in Sakha, but not “differential indirect object marking.”

Given that movement of the object into the CP phase can feed accusative case

marking, we need to consider what happens when the object moves to a higher position

than the thematic subject. This kind of “scrambling” may not be as common in Sakha as

it is in Japanese and some other head final languages, but it is possible, as shown in (12).

(12) Deriebine-ni orospuonnjuk-tar xalaa-byt-tar.

village-acc robber-pl raid-RepPast-pl/*raid-RepPast

‘Some robbers raided the village.’

14

Page 15: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Notice that, in point of fact, the case marking does not change with the word order: it is

the object that is marked accusative in (12) (as in (1b) and (6b)), and not the subject. In

fact, (2b) might predict accusative case marking on the subject if the object moved

directly to the highest position in the clause. Fortunately, though, the logic of phase

theory comes to the rescue, ruling out direct movement. Chomsky’s Phase

Impenetrability Condition tells us that a NP can only move from inside a phase like VP

into a higher phase by first moving to the edge of the lower phase. Given this, a sentence

like (12) must have a representation in like in (13).

(13) [TP village [TP robbers ... [VP <village> [VP <village> raid]] -PAST ]] phase 2 ACC phase 1

There must thus be an occurrence of ‘village’ that is lower than the subject ‘robbers’ and

yet accessible on the CP cycle, as well as the visible occurrence of ‘village’ that is higher

than ‘robbers’. (2b) will apply at the point of the derivation when ‘village’ is at the edge

of VP and lower than the thematic subject, assigning ‘village’ accusative case.4 That case

is then carried along if ‘village’ undergoes further movement. Since case marked NPs

don’t count as case competitors, the scrambled accusative object doesn’t induce

accusative case on the subject, even after it moves to a position higher than the subject.

This reasoning also applies to other kind of movement of the object into the CP domain:

hence the wh-movement (for example) relative clauses also does not affect the

assignment of accusative case in Sakha.

4 There would be other ways to achieve this result that depend less on the exact sequence

of operations in a derivation. For example, one could say that NPs in A-bar positions—

including the object in pre-subject position—do not count for the rules in (2). We do not

investigate the pros and cons of the various technical possibilities here.

15

Page 16: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Of course, these data do not distinguish our configurational theory of accusative

and dative case assignment from the view that accusative case (at least) is assigned by the

functional head v. All these facts have familiar analyses in that framework. So far, all

we have done is show that the configurational rules in (2) are contenders.

3.2 Case marking of thematic subjects

It is an elementary consequence of a case competition account like (2) that truly monadic

predicates should never have accusative or dative case arguments in Sakha. This follows

because the rules in (2) only assign accusative or dative case to an NP if there is another

NP in the same domain, and that will never be the case if the predicate is monadic. And

indeed we know of no intransitive verbs that take dative or accusative subjects in Sakha;

even verbs with experiencer arguments have nominative subjects:

(14) Masha-(*qa/*ni) accykt(aa)-yyr.

Masha-(*DAT/*ACC) hunger-aor

‘Masha hungers.’

Sakha is different in this regard from languages like Icelandic, which has a good number

of one-place predicates with quirky-case subjects.

In contrast, the rules in (2) do permit the possibility that there could be special

dyadic predicates that have dative case “subjects” in Sakha. This could arise when two

NPs are generated inside VP, but there is no NP with an agent role generated in Spec, vP.

In that situation, dative case would be assigned by (2a) to the highest thematic position in

the clause, resulting in a dative NP that might act like a grammatical subject in some

respects. Sakha does not have many predicates like this, in comparison with other

languages. Psych verbs, for example, consistently have a nominative-accusative case

16

Page 17: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

frame, like Modern English and not Icelandic. But Sakha does have a handful of dative

subject verbs from other semantic domains, including baar, ‘have’ and naada ‘need’:

(15) a. Ej-iexe massyyna baar.

you-DAT car exist

‘You have a car.’

b. Miexe massyyna naada.

I-DAT car need.

‘I need a/the car.’

There is binding evidence that the dative arguments in these sentences c-command the

bare arguments, and not vice versa, so they are worthy of being called dative subjects.5

Note also that the lower argument in these sentences is unmarked, not accusative, as

expected given that when (2a) applies it bleeds the application of (2b), as we already saw

in our discussion of ditransitive constructions.

There is one other, more systematic circumstance in which a thematic subject can

be assigned accusative or dative case: this is in morphological causative constructions.

Sakha has a productive causative suffix –t/-tar that attaches to many different kinds of

verb roots. As in many other languages, when an intransitive verb appears in the

causative construction, its thematic subject is marked with accusative case (if it is definite

or specific); when a transitive verb appears in the causative construction, its thematic

subject can be marked with dative case (see Vinokurova 2005:306-312 for more

examples):6

(16) a. Sardaana Aisen-y/*qe yta(a)-t-ta. (compare: Aisen ytaa-ta)

Sardaana Aisen-acc/*DAT cry-caus-past.3 Aisen cry-past.3

17

Page 18: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘Sardaana made Aissen cry.’ ‘Aissen cried.’

b. Misha Masha-qa miin-i sie-t-te.

Misha Masha-DAT soup-(ACC) eat-caus-past.3

‘Misha made Masha eat (the) soup.’

This follows readily from the case-marking rules in (2). Agent phrases are usually the

highest NPs in the clause, and they aren’t contained in VP; hence they usually do not

qualify for dative or accusative case. But the causative morpheme is an additional

predicative element; it integrates the agent of the verb root into a larger VP that it heads,

and it licenses a still higher argument, the causer. Since, the agent of the base verb is

now contained in the maximal VP, it receives dative case if (and only if) there is another,

lower NP inside that VP—in other words, if and only if the base verb is transitive. If the

lower verb is not transitive, then the agent of the lower verb is the only NP inside the VP

headed by the causative morpheme. If it stays inside the VP, it remains unmarked, but if

it shifts to the edge of the VP to receive a definite or specific reading, then it enters the

same domain as the higher causer NP; then the lower agent is marked accusative. Many

different structures have been proposed for morphological causative constructions, and

many of them would fit fine with this analysis; perhaps the simplest is the one in (17).

(17) a. [[vP Sardaana [CausP Aisen [VP cry ] cause ] v ] Past ] phase 2 (ACC) phase 1

b. [[vP Masha [CausP Misha [VP soup eat ] cause ] v ] Past ] phase 2 DAT (ACC) phase 1

The fact that dative case is used on the causee if and only if there is another lower NP is

perhaps the strongest reason for saying that dative case can be a structural case in Sakha,

18

Page 19: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

since it is not so plausible to say that the agent NP is theta-marked by a null postposition

in this structure and only this structure.

Although this range of facts fits well with our configurational rules of case

assignment, there are still familiar ways of capturing them within the theory that has case

assigned by functional heads as well. So we have still not found evidence that chooses

between these two approaches. We are now however ready to consider those areas in

which case assignment in Sakha is somewhat different from that of more familiar

languages—areas in which the distinctive advantages of (2) become more clear.

3.3 Passive and case assignment

Like many other languages, Sakha has (at least) two distinct detransitivizing

constructions, the anticausative and the passive. (18) shows a simple transitivity

alternation, with (18b) the detransitivized, anticausative member of the pair (Vinokurova

2005:285).

(18) a. Min oloppoh-u aldjat-ty-m.

I chair-acc break-past-1sg

‘I broke the chair.’

b. Caakky/*Caakky-ny aldjan-na.

cup/*cup-acc break-past.3

‘The cup broke.’

Note that the theme argument cannot be marked accusative in (18b), whereas it can be in

(18a). This is entirely expected: the intransitive version of ‘break’ does not have an agent

generated in Spec, vP. As a result, there is thus no case competitor for the theme

argument in the CP phase, and it is not marked accusative by (2b).

19

Page 20: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

What is interesting about this is that it contrasts with the passive. Unlike the

anticausative in Sakha and the passive in familiar Western European languages, the

theme argument in a Sakha passive can be marked accusative, although it can also be

nominative (Vinokurova 2005:336-338) as shown in (19).

(19) a. Caakky/Caakky-ny aldjat-ylyn-na.

cup-Ø/cup-acc break-pass-past.3

The cup was broken.

b. Kinige/kinige-ni aaq-ylyn-na. (compare (6b))

book-Ø/book-acc read-pass-past.3

‘The/a book was read.’

In fact, it is not entirely unexpected that there would be such a difference, given our

proposal. Whereas the agent argument is completely suppressed in anticausatives, it is

well-known that the agent of a passive sentence can still present syntactically and

semantically in various ways (e.g., the well-known contrast *The ship sank to collect the

insurance vs. The ship was sunk to collect the insurance). Thus we can say that, since

the agent is still present in the passive—say as a PROarb, in the specifier of the v headed

by the passive morpheme (Collins xxx)—it can still count as a case-competitor for the

definite object, triggering accusative case on it. In contrast, there is no agent phrase that

c-commands the theme at any syntactic level of representation in an anticausative. It thus

follows that theme cannot be accusative in (18b).

In fact, essentially the same contrast can be seen internal to the passive

construction in Sakha. Vinokurova 2005:336 compares passives that have an accusative

theme with passives that have a nominative theme. She shows that passive clauses with

20

Page 21: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

an accusative theme show clear implicit argument effects: they can contain purposive

clauses, agent-oriented adverbs, instrumental phrases, and the like. In contrast, passives

in which the definite/specific theme is marked nominative show no such signs of having

an implicit agent argument:7

(20) a. *Caakky sorujan ötüje-nen aldjat-ylyn-na.

cup intentionally hammer-instrum break-pass-past.3

‘The cup was intentionally broken with a hammer.’

b. Caakky-ny sorujan ötüje-nen aldjat-ylyn-na.

cup-acc intentionally hammer-instrum break-pass-past.3

‘The cup was broken intentionally with a hammer.’

We thus posit representations like those in (21) for the sentences in (20).

(21) a. [[vP -- (*intentionally) [VP cup [VP t break ]] PASS/AC ] past ]

b. [vP PROarb (intentionally) [VP cup-ACC [VP t break ]] PASS ] past

Given this sort of difference in representation, the rule in (2b) applies as written to assign

accusative case to cup in (21b) but not in (21a).

This configurational account can be compared with the standard view in which

accusative case is assigned by v. Most of the same results follow, given the usual

stipulation that only theta-role assigning v assign Acc case (Burzio’s Generalization)

(Burzio 1986). But the standard view would have to apply Burzio’s Generalization in a

particularly strong way. For these data, it is not enough that there be a general correlation

between functional heads that assign accusative case and functional heads that license an

agent role in the syntax. Rather, there has to be a very specific correlation, such that what

looks like the very same functional head (the passive voice marker) assigns accusative

21

Page 22: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

case when it has an NP in its specifier position and not when it doesn’t. As always with

Burzio’s Generalization, there is no obvious conceptual reason why these two logically

distinct properties of v should be packaged together in this way. This makes more

conceptual sense within a case competition theory such as (2). The data suggest that it is

not what functional heads are present that is crucial, but whether a second noun phrase is

present, and (2) expresses why this should be much more directly and reasonably.

Finally, consider the assignment of dative case in passive clauses in Sakha.

Unlike accusative case, dative case is unaffected by passive morphology in Sakha. When

a triadic verb is passivized, the argument that would have been dative in the active

sentence is still dative in the passive sentence, while the argument that would have been

accusative can either be accusative, as in (22), or unmarked nominative, as in (23).

(22) Masha-qa surug-u yyt-ylyn-na.

Masha-DAT letter-ACC send-PASS-PAST.3

‘Masha was sent a letter.’

(23) Suruk Misha-qa yyt-ylyn-na.

letter Misha-DAT send-PASS-PAST

‘The letter was sent to Misha.’

Alternative structures in which the goal argument is marked nominative in a passive are

generally rejected by native speakers (e.g. *Masha suruk yyt-ylyn-na (Masha letter send-

PASS-PAST.3) ‘Masha was sent a letter.’)8

This pattern is just what is predicted by the rules in (2). The replacement of an

active v by a passive one can affect whether there is an agent argument in vP. However,

it has no effect on the internal structure of VP. Since dative case is assigned to the higher

22

Page 23: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

argument on the VP domain, it is assigned in the same way regardless of what sort of v

head is merged later, an active one or a passive one. Continuing to assume that dative

case-marking is indelible, it follows that the same argument gets dative in a passive

sentence as in an active one. In the meantime, whether the theme object is marked

accusative or not depends on two factors—whether it object shifts out of VP, and whether

there is a PROarb in Spec of the passive voice phrase—exactly as in simple transitive

structures with no third argument. A relevant structure would be as shown in (24).

(24) [[vP (PRO) [VP letter [VP Misha ti send ]] PASS ] PAST] (ACC) DAT phase 2 phase 1

Notice that in our theory there is no need to stipulate that passive morphology

“absorbs” structural accusative case but not structural dative case, as was done in some

GB-era versions of case theory. This asymmetry in the two kinds of case assignment

follows directly from the basic formulation of the two rules in (2)—particularly the fact

that dative case assignment happens on the VP cycle, whereas accusative assignment

happens on the CP cycle.

3.4 Agentive nominalizations

Consider next case assignment in agentive nominalizations. Sakha has a productive

morpheme aaccy, which is used to derive agentive nominals from verb roots; it is similar

in many respects to the derivational morpheme er in English (Vinokurova 2005:123-124).

But there is one striking difference: unlike in English, the thematic object of such a

nominalization has accusative case, as shown in (25).

(25) a. Masha [ynaq-y kör-ööccü- nü] najmylas-ta

Masha Cow-ACC watch-aaccy-ACC hired

23

Page 24: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘Masha hired a cowherd.’

b. [Terilte-ni salaj-aaccy] kel-le

company-acc manage-AAccY come-past.3

‘The manager of the company came.’

In English, we normally say that accusative case is not available for the object of the

nominalized verb because the verbal functional head v that assigns that case is absent in

these structures; they contain nominal functional heads like number and determiner, but

not verbal ones. Where then does the accusative case come from in Sakha?

One might try to save the functional head theory of case assignment by saying

that the structure of the agentive nominals is different in Sakha from in English. Perhaps

in Sakha the nominalizing morpheme selects not for a bare VP, but rather some larger

extended projection of the verb, that includes the assigner of structural case. In the

domain of event-denoting nominalizations, this a familiar possibility: many languages

have both “derived nominals” and “gerunds”, where the latter contains more verbal

structure than the former (Rome’s vicious destruction of Carthage, versus Rome’s

viciously destroying Carthage). The problem is that there is, apparently, no similar

distinction in the domain of agent-denoting nominals: for example, English has the

vicious destroyer of Carthage but nothing like *the viciously destroyer Carthage. Sakha

is like English in this respect: other than the accusative case assignment under study,

there is no sign that agentive nominals contain any verbal/clausal structure higher than

the verb root. For example, vP-internal adverbs are not felicitous in agentive nominals:

(26) a. (*Ücügejdik) terilte-ni (*ücügejdik) salaj-aaccy kel-le.

(*well) company-acc (*well) manage-AAccY come-past.3sg

24

Page 25: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘The one who manages the company well came.’

b. djie-ni (*bütünnüü/*xat) kyraaskal-aaccy

house-ACC (*completely/*again) paint-AACCY

the painter of the house (*completely) (*again)

Also impossible in this kind of nominalization are aspectual suffixes ((27a)), negation

((27b)), and passive morphology ((27c)).

(27) a. *Suruj-baxt(aa)-aaccy kel-le (no aspectual suffix)

write-ACCEL-AG.NOM come-PAST

‘A quick writer came.’

d. *Suruj-um-aaccy kel-le. (no negation)

write-NEG-AG.NOM come-PAST.3

‘The one who doesn’t write came, the non-writer came.’

e. *tal-yll-aaccy (no voice morphology)

choose-PASS-AG.NOM

‘the one who is chosen’

So agentive nominals in Sakha do not contain an extended verb phrase structure the way

that gerunds do in English and other languages (including Sakha).

Based on facts like these, Baker and Vinokurova (2007) analyze –AAccY as a

nominal head that selects a VP complement and no more, as shown in (28).

(28)

25

NP

VP N

NP V -aaccy <agent> cow watch<theme>

Page 26: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

There is no sign of a v in a structure like (28) that can assign accusative case to the NP

object—a problem for the Chomskian case theory. In contrast, the configurational case

theory based on the notion of case competition does not depend on there being certain

functional categories present. As long as there is some syntactic realization of an agent

distinct from the theme argument, that could be enough to trigger accusative on the

object. We assume that there is such a syntactically represented agent in these nominals.

There are two possibilities as to what it is: it could be an empty category such as PROarb

in the specifier of aaccy, parallel to the “implicit agent” found in passive sentences, or it

could be the nominal head –AACCY itself. We leave open which of these is correct.

Note that differential object marking occurs in agentive nominals too. For

example, (29) is possible without accusative case marking on the thematic object ‘cow’:

(29) Ynax-(y)kör-ööccü kel-le

cow-(ACC) watch-NOM come-PAST

‘The watcher of (the) cow(s) came.’

Moreover, the alternation seems to be keyed to definiteness/specificity, just as it is in

clauses. With accusative case, the subject in (29) refers to a person who has been put in

charge of a specific cow; without accusative case it can mean someone who has the

profession of watching cows in general. Thus, given the logic of our account of

differential object marking in clauses, the VP in (28) must also count as a phase distinct

from any phase defined by the NP (or DP) as a whole. If the object NP stays in this

phase, (2b) does not apply and the object remains unmarked for case. But object shift can

26

Page 27: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

optionally apply, moving the object to the edge of the phase so that it is visible in the

same domain as the nominalizer –aaccy itself. Then (2b) does assign accusative case.

Finally, consider dative case assignment in agentive noun phrases in Sakha.

Given that they have a VP node (although no higher verbal structure), dative case

assignment should be a possibility whenever there are two unmarked DPs in the VP.

This is a correct result: dative case is possible on the goal argument when an agentive

nominalization is formed from a ditransitive verb, as in (30).

(30) oqo-lor-go emp bier-eecci ol tur-ar

Children-DATmedicine give-AACCY there stand-AOR

A giver of medicine to children is over there.

However, when we include freely generated benefactive expressions in the picture, we

find a contrast that is not apparent in the clausal domain. When the nominalized verb is

transitive, including a dative expression is sometimes possible as in (30), but when the

verb is an unergative verb, the benefactive expression is at best awkward:

(31) a. ?/??/*Masha-qa ülelee-cci kelle.

Masha-DAT work-AACCYcame

The one who works for Masha came, The worker for Masha came.

(OK: Masha-qa work-AOR-1sS ‘I work for Masha’)

b. ??presideŋ-ŋa kömölöh-ööccü

??President-DAT help-AACCy

The helper of the president.

(OK: pres-DAT help-AOR-1sS ‘I help the president’)

27

Page 28: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

We take this to be support for our case assignment rule in (2a), which says that structural

dative case is assigned to an NP only if that NP c-commands a distinct NP within the VP.

That condition is satisfied in (30), but it is not satisfied in (31); there is no other NP that

the benefactive c-commands to justify it having dative case. Unergative verbs like

‘work’ can appear with dative case NPs in clauses, but we conjectured (see note 5) that

this was not the result of structural dative case assigned by (2a); rather it was inherent

dative case assigned by a null P. Now many languages do not permit a PP to modify an

NP, and Sakha is one of these:

(32) *ambaar-y tula kürüö

*barn-ACC around fence

‘the fence around the barn’

Having a benefactive PP in the nominal domain is thus ruled out on independent

grounds.9 As a result, the only kind of dative case that can appear inside a nominal is

structural dative case. The contrast between (30) and (31) thus supports the idea that

structural dative case depends on there being a case competitor—a truth we already

observed in morphological causatives and dative subject constructions.

3.5 Raising of Subjects in Sakha

We come now to perhaps the most spectacular evidence in favor of the case competition

account of accusative case assignment in Sakha: the “raising to object” construction

described in Vinokurova 2005:sec. 6.10, but not fully explained there. Vinokurova

shows that an NP that moves into the matrix clause can be marked with accusative case.

Such movement is possible out of both finite and nonfinite clauses:

(33) a. Min ehigi/ehigi-ni bügün kyaj-yax-xyt dien erem-mit-im.

28

Page 29: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

I you/you-ACC today win-FUT-2pl that hope-PAST-1sg

‘I hoped you would win today.’

b. Min ehigi/ehigi-ni bügün kyaj-byk-kyt-yn ihit-ti-im.

I you/you-ACC today win-PTPL-2pl-ACC heard-PAST-1sg

‘I heard that you won today.’ (p. 361)

Vinokurova gives evidence that the subject of the embedded clause leaves the embedded

clause and enters the matrix clause if and only if it is marked with accusative case. Her

evidence comes from word order with respect to adverbs that modify the matrix verb, and

from negative polarity licensing, which is strictly clause bound in Sakha:

(34) a. Sardaana (Aisen-y) beqehee [bügün (*Aisen-y) kel-er dien] ihit-te.

Sardaana (A.-ACC) yesterday today (A.-ACC) come-AOR that hear-past.3

‘Sardaana heard yesterday that Aissen is coming today.’(p. 363)

b. Min kim-i daqany kyaj-da dien isti-be-ti-m.

I who-ACC PRT win-PAST.3 that hear-NEG-PAST-1sg

‘I didn’t hear of anybody that they won.’ (p. 364)

The judgments reverse if accusative case is not marked on the thematic subject of the

lower verb: then Aisen is only possible after the higher time adverb ‘yesterday’, and the

negative polarity item kim daqany is only possible if negation is on the lower verb.

At first glance, it would seem that either the case competition theory or the

assignment by functional head theory could explain this sort of data. Within a

competition theory, raising the subject from the embedded CP into the matrix CP places

it in the same phase as the subject of the matrix clause. Rule (2b) then applies to mark

the lower subject as accusative. Within a functional head theory, one might suppose that

29

Page 30: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

accusative case is assigned by the v of the matrix clause; raising the subject takes it out of

the lower CP phase and makes it close enough to v to be case marked by it. Both

accounts are natural enough, and attribute the effect to the PIC in similar ways.

What is striking, however, is that raising to object can take place even when there

is no functional head in the matrix clause which could be the source of accusative case.

(35) shows raising into a matrix clause whose predicate is the intransitive member of a

transitivity alternating verb (xomot ‘make sad’ vs. xomoj ‘become sad’; tönnör ‘make

return’ vs. tönün ‘return’), hence an unaccusative verb.

(35) a. Keskil Aisen-y [kel-be-t dien] xomoj-do.

Keskil Aisen-ACC come-NEG-AOR that become.sad-past.3sS

Keskil became sad that Aisen is not coming. (p. 366)

b. Masha Misha-ny [yaldj-ya dien] tönün-ne

Masha Misha-ACC fall.sick-FUT that return-PAST.3sS

‘Masha returned (for fear) that Misha would fall sick.’

The v associated with these unaccusative verbs cannot assign accusative case on standard

assumptions; if it did, the standard theory would lose its account of (18b). Nevertheless,

accusative case marking in (35) is possible. Similarly, (36) shows that an NP can raise

out of the embedded clause and be marked with accusative case even when the matrix

verb is a passive with no implicit agent argument.

(36) Sargy Masha-ny [t tönn-üö dien] erenner-ilin-ne.

Sargy Masha-ACC [t return-FUT dien] promise-PASS-past.3

‘Sargy was promised that Masha would return.’

30

Page 31: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

This datum too is unexpected on the standard view that accusative case is assigned by a

particular functional head (i.e. transitive v).

In contrast, the case competition view easily extends to the data in (35) and (36).

When the subject of the lower clause raises into the higher clause, it enters the same

domain as the (derived) subject of the matrix clause. This NP is a case competitor for the

raised subject, licensing the accusative case marking on it. Functional heads do not come

into the account; all that matters is that there is another noun phrase in the matrix clause.

It is also possible for an NP to get accusative case by moving to the edge of an

adjunct clause.10 (37) gives examples of this kind. Note that this can happen even when

the matrix clause is transitive. The result is two distinct accusative case marked noun

phrases, something that is otherwise extremely limited in Sakha.

(37) a. Masha [Misha-ny kel-ie dien] djie-ni xomuj-da.

3 Note on controversies about vP versus VP as the smaller phase; Fox and Pesetsky 2004,

etc.

5 We note that baar and naada are adjectival predicates, not true verbs, but take this to be

largely irrelevant to the point at hand. Sakha also has predicates (both verbs and

adjectives) that take nominative subjects and dative internal arguments, including ‘pray

to’, ‘bow to’, ‘help’, and ‘come to’; (i) is an example.

(i) Misha-Ø Masha-qa toŋxoj-do

Misha-Nom Masha-DAT bow-PAST.3sS

‘Misha bowed to Masha.’

With these predicates, the nominative arugment asymmetrically c-commands the dative

argument, whereas it is the other way around in (15).

31

Page 32: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Masha [Misha-ACC come-FUT that] house-ACC tidy-PAST.3

‘Masha tidied up the house (thinking) that Misha would come.’ (p. 368)

b. Masha Kesha-qa [Misha-ny aaq-ya dien] kinige-ni bier-de.

Masha Kesha-DAT [Misha-ACC read-FUT that] book-ACC give-past.3

‘Masha gave Kesha the book so that Misha would read it.’ (p. 368)

Note that our rule for assigning dative case in (2a) cannot account for dative on

the internal argument in (i). Rather, we must analyze this as an instance of inherent

dative case being assigned by a null postposition. This is not implausible, given that

some overt postpositions clearly assign dative case in Sakha as an idiosyncratic lexical

property (e.g. ojuur-ga dieri (forest-DAT until) ‘up to the forest’). We thus follow the

lead of Emonds (1985), McFadden (2004) and others by assuming that Sakha also has

one or more null Ps that can assign dative case (as well as locative, temporal, or

benefactive theta-roles). The dative expression in (i) must be one of these. Some

evidence in favor of this view is that dative expressions like the one in (i) are not good in

nominalizations, whereas structurally marked dative NPs are; see section 3.4 for some

discussion.

6 Vinokurova 2005 shows that when the base verb is transitive, its thematic subject can

also be marked with accusative case or with instrumental case. As an oblique case,

instrumental falls outside the domain of this inquiry. We might be able to include the

possibility of accusative case on the causee in our analysis by tinkering with our

assumptions about what counts as the “inner phase” in causative constructions. In (17b)

we assume that the maximal VP, including the projection of the causative morpheme is

the inner phase; this yields dative case on the causee. But suppose that the minimal VP

32

Page 33: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

These examples are awkward for the view that case is assigned by functional heads,

because there is only one transitive v that could be a source for accusative case in the

matrix clauses in (58). Given that case assignment by a functional category is usually

one-to-one, this v cannot assign case both to the object of the matrix verb and the raised

subject of the embedded verb. (If one changed this assumption, then it would be hard to

could also count as a phase. Then there would be no VP phase that contains both the

causee and the thematic object, so (2a) would not apply, and dative case would not be

assigned. However, the causee and the thematic object could still object shift into the CP

phase; when they do, (2a) assigns them both accusative case, because they are c-

commanded by the causer.

7As expected, anticausatives are like agentless passives in these respects: they also cannot

have adverbs like ‘intentionally’ or instrumental NPs: *Caakky sorujan ötüje-nen aldjan-

na. ‘The cup intentionally broke with a hammer.’

8 We have noted some minor variability in this judgment. Some speakers marginally

accept some examples of this form, depending on the lexical verb being used, while other

speakers reject them entirely. We assume that such sentences are basically bad.

9 Many transitive verbs are also uncomfortable with a benefactive NP in dative case in the

related agentive nominal; for example, (i) is closer in status to (31) than to (30).

(i) ??Masha-qa miin-i ast-aaccy

Masha-DAT soup-ACC cook-AACCY

‘the maker of soup for Masha’

We conclude that the benefactive NP associated with ‘cook’ is also the complement of a

null PP that assigns inherent dative case; such PPs can of course appear with transitive

33

Page 34: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

explain why the two objects of a simple triadic verbs like give and send cannot both be

assigned accusative case in Sakha; compare section 3.1 above.) In contrast, the case

assignment rule in (2b) does not lead to any expectation that accusative case assignment

must be unique. It is perfectly imaginable that there will be two NPs that move into a

single CP domain, both of which are c-commanded by a third NP that is base-generated

in that higher domain. Then both will be marked for accusative case. That is precisely

what we see in (37), where subject raising and object shift both feed accusative case

assignment in the same clause.

There is one very instructive situation in which an NP raised out of an embedded

clause cannot be marked as accusative. That is when the matrix clause is an impersonal

predicate like ‘be certain’ or ‘be necessary’, which has at most an expletive subject.

Raising NP out of the clausal argument of these predicates is possible, as shown by order

with respect to adverbs. Nevertheless, the raised NP in these circumstances must be

unmarked for case, and cannot have the accusative suffix:

(38) Masha/*Masha-ny bügün munnjax-xa [ehiil Moskva-qa bar-ar-a] cuolkaj buol-la.

Masha/*Masha-acc today meeting-dat [next.year Moscow-dat go-aor-3] certain

be(come)-past.3

verbs as well as with intransitives. A possible implication of this is that Sakha does not

have an Applicative head that can assign benefactive roles to an NP in its specifier, as

some other languages do (note that there is no benefactive applicative affix in Sakha,

similar to the one found in Bantu languages). If it did, we would expect (i) to be good, on

a par with (30). Rather, the “free benefactive” theta role can only be assigned by a

postpositional head in Sakha, which is sometimes overt and sometimes covert.

34

Page 35: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘It became clear today at the meeting that Masha will go to Moscow next year.’

Thus while the transitivity of the matrix verb is not crucial to the licensing of accusative

case, it is crucial that there be a competing NP in the matrix clause. This is important

confirming evidence in favor of the case competition account.

Finally, consider the implications of subject raising for the dative case

assignment. Vinokurova 2005:367 observes that when the subject of the complement

clause of a verb like ‘promise’ raises into the matrix clause, the other internal argument

of ‘promise’ cannot be marked accusative, but must be marked dative:

(39) Sargy Keskil-i [Aisen kel-ie dien] erenner-de.

Sargy Keskil-ACC Aisen come-FUT that promise-PAST.3

‘Sargy promised Keskil that Aissen will come.’

(40) Sargy Keskil-ge/*i Aisen-y [ t kel-ie dien] erenner-de.

Sargy Keskil-DAT/*ACC Aisen-ACC come-FUT that promise-PAST.3

‘Sargy promised Keskil that Aissen will come.’

Our case assignment rules put us in a position to understand why this is. The clausal

complement of ‘promise’ is its innermost argument; it is generated inside the matrix VP.

When an NP raises to the edge of this CP, it becomes visible in the matrix VP phase. The

matrix verb is ‘promise’ also selects for an NP argument, which is also inside the VP—a

goal-like argument that expresses the one who is promised. This goal argument c-

commands the clausal argument, and it c-commands the subject NP that has raised to the

edge of the CP. The conditions specified by (2a) thus apply, and dative case is assigned

‘promise’s NP argument. From the edge of the embedded CP, the subject of the lower

clause can move on to the edge of the matrix VP; when it does, it becomes visible in the

35

Page 36: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

matrix CP phase, and is marked accusative because it is c-commanded by the matrix

subject. What is not possible is for the lower subject to be marked accusative without the

promisee being marked dative. That would require the lower subject to move directly

from the lower CP phase into the higher CP phase, without entering the matrix VP phase;

such a derivation would violate the Phase Impenetrability Condition. In contrast, the

adjunct clauses in (37) are generated outside the matrix VP, and are not c-commanded by

the internal argument of the matrix verb. When NP raises to the edge of the adjunct

clause, it does not become visible on the matrix VP phase, but only on the matrix CP

phase. Hence, raising from an adjunct clause does not feed dative case assignment inside

VP, whereas raising from a complement clause can.

We take all this to be good support that the various details of our proposal fit

together in the appropriate way. We think it would be very difficult for a classical theory

in which case is assigned by designated functional heads to capture this range of facts.

3.6 Raising of Possessors

Sakha has second kind of raising construction, which is somewhat similar to the subject

raising construction, but which also has some important differences. This is the so-called

possessor raising construction. Vinokurova (2005:146-151) discusses it only for the

existential predicate baar, but it is possible with a wide selection of unaccusative verbs.

This construction provides some further support for our dative case assignment rule.

It is of course possible for a possessor to form a constituent with the possessed NP

in Sakha. When this happens, the possessor is contiguous with the possessed NP, and the

possessor is in genitive case (unmarked and homophonous with the nominative, except

when the possessor itself is possessed). A simple base-line examples of this is (41).:\

36

Page 37: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

(41) Beqehee Misha at-a öl-lö.

yesterday Misha-dat horse-3 die-past.3

‘Misha’s horse died yesterday.’

But under certain conditions, it is also possible for the possessor to raise out of the

possessed NP, so that it is separated from the possessor by (for example) an adverbial

modifier of the matrix clause. When this happens, the raised possessor can either bear

dative case, as in (42), or unmarked nominative case, as in (43).

(42) a. Misha-qa beqehee at-a öl-lö.

Misha-dat yesterday horse-3 die-past.3

‘Misha’s horse died on him yesterday.’

b. Masha-qa beqehee vaza-lar-a aldjan-na/aldjan-ny-lar.

Masha-DAT yesterday vase-pl-3 break-past.3/break-past-pl

‘Masha’s pots broke on her yesterday.’

(43) a. Masha aaspyt tüün yt-a öl-lö.

Masha last.night dog-3s die-Past.3

Masha’s dog died last night.

b. Masha emiske massyyna-ta aldja-n-na

Masha suddenly car-3s break-INT-PAST.3sS

‘Masha’s car suddenly broke down.’

Prima facie evidence that these are raising constructions comes from the fact that they are

impossible if there is no possessive agreement on the head noun of the theme argument,

or if the possessive agreement agrees with something other than the “raised” NP:

(44) a. *Masha-(qa) beqehee massyyna-m aldjan-na

37

Page 38: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Masha-(DAT) yesterday car-1sS break-PAST.3sS

‘My car broke down on Masha yesterday.’

b. *Misha-(qa) beqehee at öl-lö.

Misha-dat yesterday horse die-past.3

‘The horse died on Misha yesterday.’

Hence, there must at minimum be some kind of binding/chain formation relationship

between the “raised” NP and the syntactic possessor of the theme for the construction to

be interpretable. We tentatively assume that it is a movement relationship, although this

is not absolutely crucial to our analysis.

Why does the raised possessor get nominative case in some sentences and dative

case in others? Pursuing the idea that these are instances of structural case, it must be

because the structures of (42) and (43) are slightly different. In fact, our rule of dative

case assignment in (2a) tells us what the difference must be. Structural dative case is

assigned to an NP only if that NP is inside VP, and there is another NP inside VP that it

c-commands. We thus conjecture that the landing sights of the two types of possessor

raising are slightly different. In one case, the possessor raises to a position that is high in

VP but still fully contained in VP—such as Spec, VP (or perhaps Spec, ApplP). In the

other case, the possessor raises higher, out of the VP phase all together. The two

structures are compared in (45).

(45) a. [TP Mishai Adverb1 [VP Adverb2 [DP ti [NP horse] D+AGR ] die ] PAST]--

Phase 2 Phase 1

b. [TP Adverb1 [VP Mishai Adverb2 [DP ti [VP horse] D+AGR ] die ] PST] DAT

Phase 2 Phase 1

38

Page 39: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

In (45b), Misha receives dative case on the VP phase, because it is contained in that

phase and c-commands the theme NP, which is also in that phase. In contrast, there is

only one NP in the VP phase in the (45a) structure, so dative case assignment does not

apply. Moreover, the theme object cannot undergo object shift in this construction (it

must be adjacent to the verb, not separated from it by an adverb). As a result, there is

only one NP in the CP phase as well—the raised possessor—and accusative case is not

assigned either. These structures would thus give as the different case patterns that we

observe in (42) and (43), using only our well-established rules of case assignment.

If (45) is correct, we might be able to confirm that there is a structural difference

between the two kinds of possessor raising constructions through careful use of adverbs.

Both sorts of possessor raising should cross over adverbs properly contained in VP; these

are important for showing that the possessor has raised out of DP in the first place. But

there might also be a class of adverbs—adverbs generated in TP or some other

constituent larger than VP—which reveal a different. The prediction would be that the

nominative-type possessor raising should cross these adverbs more easily than the dative

type possessor raising, because the nominative type targets a crucially higher position. In

fact, there are data that confirm this. Both types of possessor raising can cross manner

adverbs like ‘suddenly’, but nominative possessor raising is more comfortable than dative

possessor raising when crossing time adverbs like ‘yesterday’, as shown in (46).

(46) a. beqehee Masha/Masha-qa emiske massyyna-ta aldjanna

yesterday Masha/Masha-DAT suddenly car-3s break.

Yesterday Masha’s car suddenly broke on her.

39

Page 40: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

b. Masha/??Masha-qa beqehee emiske massyyna-ta aldjanna

Masha/??Masha-DAT yesterday suddenly car-3s break.

Yesterday Masha’s car suddenly broke on her.

Similarly, a nominative raised possessor is more comfortable than a dative raised

possessor in front of a modal adverb like ‘probably’:

(47) Masha/??Masha-qa baqar massyyna-ta aldjan-ya

Masha/??Masha-DAT probably car-3s break-FUT.3sS

Masha’s car will probably break.

See also Vinokurova 2005:xx, where it is observed that nominative possessor raising can

cross a locative adjunct bearing dative case, but dative possessor raising cannot. It should

be noted that the examples with dative raised possessors in front of high adverbs are not

entirely out, nor should we expect them to be; there is always the possibility of additional

scrambling and focus movement that would move the dative NP from its case position in

(45b). But abstracting away from this, the difference between nominative possessor

raising and dative possessor raising seems clear, and goes in the predicted direction. The

dative possessor raising construction in particular is it is another example of structural

dative case assignment, also attributable to the rule in (2a).

3.7 Case assignment in PPs

Finally, we consider an interesting alternation in the kind of case found in certain PPs in

Sakha. The class of postpositions is a rather heterogeneous one in Sakha. Many things

that would be expressed by PPs in other languages are expressed either by oblique cases

or by “auxiliary nouns”. Moreover, some of the Ps that there are are derived historically

either from locative nouns or from participial verbs. Given this, it is not surprising that

40

Page 41: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

the case assigning properties of Ps are also rather heterogeneous. We assume that most

of them are simply lexically specified as assigning one particular inherent case; for some

of them, it is genitive (kurkuk, like; tuxary, during; nöNüö, through); for others, dative

(dieri, until; dyly ‘like’); for others, ablative (taxsa ‘over, beyond; syltaan, because of);

for others, accusative (Byha ‘during’, kytta ‘with’ and nöŋüö ‘over’). We take this to be

of no particular interest for our investigation into structural case.

There are, however, three postpositions whose objects undergo an alternation.

The objects of these Ps can be marked with accusative case, or with genitive case:

(48) a. Tyan-(ny) kurdat djie köst-ör.

forest-ACC through house appear-AOR

‘A house appears through the forest.’

b. Masha djie-(ni) tula türgennik süür-de

Misha house-ACC around quickly run-PAST.3

‘Misha ran quickly around the house.’

c. Masha tünnük-(ü) utary olor-do

Masha window-ACC opposite sit-PAST.3

‘Masha sat opposite the window.’

We claim that when these PP objects bear accusative case, this is the result of structural

accusative case being assigned in accordance with rule (6b). The crucial evidence for this

is what happens when PPs headed by these Ps modify impersonal verbs that have no

thematic subject. When this happens, their complement cannot have accusative case:

(49) a. Ambaar-(*y) tula itii.

barn-ACC around hot

41

Page 42: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

‘It is hot around the barn.’

b. Tünnük-(*ü) utary tymnyy.

window-acc opposite cold

‘It is cold opposite the window.’

This somewhat peculiar fact can be made to follow on the case competition approach. In

(48) there is another NP argument of the verb which can function as the case competitor

for the object of P, licensing accusative, whereas in (49) there is not. The contrast

between (48) and (49) is strongly reminiscent of the contrast between raising a subject

into a matrix clause that has its own subject ((xx)) as compared to raising a subject into a

matrix clause with a subjectless impersonal predicate ((xx)). And like those sentences,

the contrast between (48) and (49) gives strong support for the case competition theory.

To flesh out the account, something should be said about the fact that accusative

marking is optional in the examples in (48). What does this depend on? Interestingly, the

factors that condition this optionality are not the same as those that determine whether the

direct object of the verb is accusative or not. It does not have to do with the definiteness

of the object: even in a sentence like ‘Misha sat opposite Masha’, accusative is optional

on the proper name object, whereas accusative case is required on a proper name serving

as the direct object of a verb. Nor is the optionality related to the position of the PP with

respect to adverbs: the PP can come before or after an adverb, and accusative case

marking on the object is optional in both orders (I house-(ACC) around quickly ran; I

quickly house(ACC) around ran). We tentatively assume that the PP as a whole is always

generated outside the VP phase. The optionality of accusative case assignment then has

to do, we suggest, with the phase status of the PP itself. We claim that these particular P

42

Page 43: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

heads optionally count as phases.11 When the PP is a phase, its object is in a different

phase from the subject of the clause, so the accusative case marking rule does not apply;

the object either remains unmarked or gets lexical (genitive) case from P. When the PP is

not a phase, the object of the P is visible on the matrix CP phase. If the matrix CP

contains another NP, as in (48), then accusative case is assigned to the object of P by

(2b). If, however, the matrix CP does not contain another DP, as in (49), accusative case

marking does not apply. This accounts for the observed range of facts. Once again the

number of NPs in the clause proves to be crucial, as predicted by the configurational

account, whereas exactly which functional heads are present is not particularly crucial.

4. Nominative and Genitive: the relationship to agreement

So far, we have considered accusative and dative case in some detail, arguing that they

are assigned by configurational rules rather by functional categories. Now we turn to

nominative and genitive case in Sakha, to see how they are assigned.

If one’s only goal was to account for the distribution of case suffixes on NPs in

Sakha, it would be easy to extend the configurational account of case assignment to

nominative and genitive NPs. It is not hard to formulate rules like those in (2) for these

cases; indeed, those rules would essentially be just the complements of the rules that we

already have. For example, we could say that genitive case is assigned to the highest NP

in a DP phase, otherwise nominative case is assigned to the highest NP in any phase (this

rule will be blocked by the more specific rules of dative and genitive assignment; cf.

Marantz 1991). An alternative, more radical but potentially more insightful approach

could be to say that there really is no nominative or genitive case in Sakha; what we call

43

Page 44: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

nominative and genitive NPs are simply those NPs which are not assigned dative or

accusative case by the rules in (2). This could account for both the default nature of these

cases in Sakha (they are used wherever no other case is called for) and the fact that these

cases are (usually) not marked by any overt morphological exponent. Some refinements

might be needed, but we see no reason why a purely configurational approach along these

lines could not be made to work.

Case marking does not exist in isolation, however; there are also related

morphosyntactic phenomena, such as agreement. The true theory of case should not only

explain case marking itself, but also its interaction with as agreement. Indeed,

Chomsky’s (2000, 2001) approach is precisely intended to account for the close

relationship between case and agreement that exists in many languages, by claiming that

case and agreement are two sides of the same coin; both are reflexes of establishing an

abstract relationship (Agree) between a functional head that is missing phi-features and

an NP that is missing case features. Capturing the close relationship between case and

agreement is not an issue for accusative and dative marked objects in Sakha, because

there is no agreement with objects in this language. But the issue does arise for

nominative and genitive “subjects”, because these are agreed with in Sakha. More

specifically, nominative (unmarked) subjects agree with Tense suffixed to the verb, as

seen in the examples throughout this paper, whereas genitive possessor agree with D

suffixed to the possessed noun, as shown in (50) (Vinokurova 2005:133).

(50) min oloppoh-um; en oloppoh-uŋ; kini oloppoh-o, etc.

I chair-1sP you chair-2sP s/he chair-3sP

‘my chair; your chair; his/her chair’

44

Page 45: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Similarly, the nominative or genitive subject of a gerund/nominatization agrees with a D

suffixed to the nominalized verb, and the nominative or genitive subject of a relative

clause agrees with a D suffixed to the head noun (see (xx) below). In this section, we

argue that careful consideration of these case-agreement correspondences shows that the

Chomskian analysis of nominative and genitive case should be adopted.

Another way of stating this is as follows. We know that a linguistic relationship

(Chomsky’s Agree) is established between the subject and T in clausal structures and

between the possessor and D in nominal structures (also between the subject and D in

complex NPs) because we observe agreement between the NP and the functional head.

The question, then, is whether there is any payoff for thinking of case assignment as the

other side of this existing relationship between functional head and NP, the functional

head valuing an unspecified case feature of the NP at the same time as the NP values

unspecified agreement features on the functional head. If so, then the standard

minimalist conception would be supported in this subdomain. We argue that there is

such a pay-off, and this justifies the familiar case rules in (51), repeated from (3) above:

(51) a. T values the case of NP as nominative if and only if T Agrees with NP.

b. D values the case of NP as genitive if and only if D Agrees with NP.

4.1 Overt genitive marking and agreement in relative clauses

First, there is one small corner of Sakha grammar in which one can see the

interdependence of overt case and agreement fairly directly. This is in a particular kind

of relative clauses. Relative clauses in Sakha must be nonfinite, participial clauses, not

fully tensed clauses. The participial verb does not itself agree with the subject of the

relative clause, the way that a finite verb would. Instead, agreement with the subject of

45

Page 46: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

the relative clause shows up on the D that is suffixed to the head of the relative clause

(see Krause xxx for a crosslinguistic study of this sort of relative clause). (52) gives two

examples; notice also that when the subject of the relative clause is a possessed NP, it can

be seen to bear overt genitive case (compare section 2).12

(52) a. Masha aqa-ty-n atyylas-pyt at-a

Masha father-3s-GEN buy-PAST.PTPL horse-3sP

‘The horse that Masha’s father bought’

b. bihigi sie-bit balyk-pyt

we(GEN) eat-past fish-1pP

‘the fish that we ate’

There is, however, no agreement on the head noun with the subject of the relative

clause when that subject itself is the extracted constituent, as shown in (53).

(53) at-y atyylas-pyt kyys (*kyyh-a)

horse-ACC buy-PAST.PTPL girl (*girl-3s)

‘the girl who bought the horse’

This is a fairly standard kind of “Anti-agreement Effect”: agreement with the subject is

suppressed when that subject undergoes wh-movement; see Ouhalla 1993 for an analysis

in these terms of related Turkish.

What makes this relevant for our purposes is the fact that agreement with the

subject of a relative clause is also suppressed when a proper subpart of the subject is

extracted to form the head of the relative clause:

(54) Kergen-e oqo-lor-go kinige-ler-i bier-bit ucuutal-(*a)

46

Page 47: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Wife-3s child-PL-DAT book-PL-ACC give-PAST teacher-3s

‘the teacher whose wife gave books to the children’

This is also found in Turkish and at least some other AAE-manifesting languages

(Ouhalla 1993, Kornfilt 1997); presumably whatever rules out agreement in (53) should

be generalized to rule it out in (54) as well. We do not take a stand here on what this

principle should be.

The crucial fact for our purposes is that the subject in a relative clause like

(54) cannot be marked genitive, in contrast with the subject in (52a).

(55) *kergen-i-n oqo-lor-go kinige-ler-i bier-bit ucuutal

wife-3s-GEN child-PL-DAT book-PL-ACC give-PAST teacher

‘the teacher whose wife gave books to the children’

We see then that overt genitive case marking in Sakha is impossible in the very same

construction in which agreement on D is ruled out. This strongly suggests that genitive

case assignment and agreement on D are intimately related, as in the Chomskian view. If

genitive case were assigned configurationally to the highest NP in DP in (52a), without

regard to whether an Agree relationship is permitted with the head of the DP, then there

would be no reason why the same configurational rule should fail to give genitive case to

the parallel NP in (55). Furthermore, if we say that genitive case and agreement on D

are two sides of the same coin, then it is at least plausible to extend that view to

nominative case and agreement on T, given that the agreement processes are parallel.

4.2 Agreement and Overt Case Marking

47

Page 48: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Another relevant fact about agreement in Sakha is that T and D never agree with an NP

that has already been marked accusative or dative NP on that phase or a previous phase.

For T, this condition is especially evident in passives of ditransitive verbs. When

the theme object becomes nominative, T can agree with it ((56a)). But when the theme

argument is marked accusative, the verb cannot agree with either internal argument, and

must show default third singular morphology ((56b)).

(56) a. At-tar Masha-qa ber-ilin-ni-ler

Horse-pl Masha-dat give-pass-past-pl

The horses were given to Masha.

b. Oqo-lor-go at-tar-y ber-ilin-ne/*ber-ilin-ni-ler

Child-pl-dat horse-pl-acc give-pass-past.3sg/*give-pass-past-pl

The children were given horses.

This is also seen in passives of monotransitive verbs: if the thematic object is marked

with accusative case, it does not agree with T; if it is not marked accusative, it does.

(57) a. Oloppos-tor aldjat-ylyn-ny-lar.

chair-PL break-PASS-PAST-PL

‘Chairs were broken.’

b. Oloppos-tor-u aldjat-ylyn-na. (*aldjat-ylyn-ny-lar)

chair-PL-ACC break-PASS-PAST.3

‘Chairs were broken.’

Nor can T agree with the dative subject of a verb like ‘need’; rather, it must look past the

dative subject and agree with the lower argument, which is not marked for case by (2a,b).

(58) a. Oqo-lor-go üüt naada-(*lar)

48

Page 49: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Child-PL-DAT milk need-PL

‘The children need milk.’

b. Masha-qa kinige-ler naada-lar.

Masha-DAT book-PL need-PL

‘Masha needs the books.’

Finally, T cannot agree a raised possessor that has dative case; it can only agree with the

uncase-marked NP that the possessor was raised from in examples like (59).

(59) #Oqo-lor-go djie-ler-e umaj-dy-lar.

Child-pl-dat house-pl-3 burn-past-pl

Bad as: ‘The children’s house burnt’, agreement with the possessor

OK only as: ‘The children’s houses burnt’, with agreement with the theme

So T never agrees with an NP that has already been assigned accusative or dative case.

Similar facts hold for D. In a derived nominalization, for example, D can agree

with the thematic subject of the verb root:

(60) Masha terilte-ni salaj-yy-ta

Masha company-ACC manage-YY-3s

Masha’s managing the company

The agent of such a nominalization can also be left implicit, as in (60), in which case

there is no agreement with the agent (at least overtly).

(61) a. Terilte-ni salaj-yy

Company-acc manage-nom

‘management of the company’

b. Oqo-qo em-i bier-ii

49

Page 50: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Child-DAT medicine-ACC give-YY

‘the giving of medicine to children’

What is not possible is for the agent to be left implicit, while D agrees with the

accusative-marked theme or the dative-marked goal, as shown in (62). These examples

are grammatical, but only if agreement is construed as being with a pro-dropped agent

argument.13

(62) a. #Terilte-ni salaj-yy-ta

Company-acc manage-nom-3sg

Not: ‘the management of the company’ (OK as ‘his/her management …)

b. #oqo-lor-go em-i bier-ii-ler-e

#Child-PL-DAT medicine-ACC give-YY-pl-3

The giving of medicine to children (OK as their giving medicine to children).

One can compare the nominalization of an active verb in which the subject is left implicit

with the nominalization of a passive verb, as shown in (63). The two are thematically

similar, in that no agent is expressed overtly, but the theme phrase is accusative in (62a)

and is not marked with accusative case in (63). Correlated with this difference in case

marking is the fact that D agrees with the theme argument in (63) but not in (62a).

(63) Terilte-Ø sala(j)-ll-yy-ta

Company-Ø manage-PASS-YY-3s

The company’s being managed

This pattern also true for agentive nominals of the sort discussed in section 3.4:

these also can have accusative marked objects, and they can bear an agreeing D, but the

D cannot agree with the accusative object; it could only agree with a possessor:

50

Page 51: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

(64) Terilte-ni salaj-aaccy-(#ta)

company-acc manage-ER-3s

Bad as: ‘the manager of the company’; OK as ‘his/her company-manager’

A similar range of facts can be constructed in relative clauses: the D realized on

the head of the relative cannot agree with an accusative or dative NP inside the relative

clause. For example, when one extracts the object from a dative subject construction, the

D associated with the head of the relative clause does not agree with the dative subject,

even though such Ds do agree with subjects that are not marked for case (compare (52)).

(65) Kihie-xe naada massyyna-(*ta)

Person-DAT need car-(*3s)

‘The car that the person needs’

Overall, then, we see that there is a relatively rich array of facts that fall under the

generalization that T and D cannot agree with an NP that has already been marked for

case. Why should that be? On the Chomskian conception as expressed in (51), this

follows immediately: T and D agree with an NP if and only they value the case feature of

that NP. They cannot value the case feature of the NP if it has already been valued by a

previous application of (2a) or (2b). Therefore, they cannot agree with such an NP either.

This looks like good evidence that case marking and agreement are intertwined in Sakha

for those functional heads that are involved in agreement at all.14

4.3 Case marking and the absence of double agreement in Sakha

There is a known alternative to the Chomskian approach to the facts surveyed in the

previous section. This alternative would stick with the idea that case marking is done

purely configurationally, and make agreement dependent on case marking. It would deny

51

Page 52: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

that T and D assign case to NP, but maintain that they can agree with NP only if it is not

overtly marked for case. There would thus be a one-way dependence of agreement on

case, but not a full two-way codependence of agreement and case, as there is in the

Chomskian vision. Bobaljik (to appear) adopts this approach explicitly, and so do many

descriptive and theoretical treatments in passing (e.g., for Hindi).

But this intermediate view still misses an important generalization. All things

being equal, it would predict that two different functional heads could agree with the

same NP in Sakha, as long as the NP was unmarked for case (and as long as the locality

conditions on case assignment were satisfied). In contrast, the Chomskian approach

predicts that this will not happen: if the first functional head agrees with NP, then it also

values the case feature of that NP, even if case is not spelled out overtly at PF. Assuming

that case marking is unique and unchangeable,15 the second functional head cannot also

value the case feature of the already-valued NP; therefore it cannot agree with the NP.

In fact, the prediction of the Chomskian view is the accurate one: it seems to be

systematically impossible to have two distinct heads agree with the same argument in

Sakha. This is true even though there is range of constructions in which one can easily

imagine agreement happening twice if that were allowed. For example, in the possessor

raising construction where the raised possessor remains unmarked for case, the raised NP

triggers agreement on the possessed noun, but it cannot also trigger agreement on T.

(66) Oqo-lor (beqehee) at-tar-a öl-lö/*öl-lü-ler.

child-PL (yesterday) horse-pl-3 die-past.3/*die-past-pl

‘The children’s horse died yesterday.’

(Plural only OK as: The children’s horses died yesterday.)

52

Page 53: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

This fact does not follow simply from saying that T and D must both agree with

unmarked NPs. It does follow if we say that D marks the NP with genitive before it

raises. Then, T cannot mark it as nominative, and therefore T cannot agree with it.

The same pattern can be seen when the subject NP of a lower clause raises into

the matrix clause of a verb that takes no thematic subject. The raised NP bears no overt

case marker in this situation, as discussed in connection with (34) above. The embedded

verb agrees with the moved NP, but the main clause predicate cannot:16

(67) a. Oqo-lor bügün beqehee kyaj-byt-tar-a cuolkajdan-na/* -ny-lar.

child-pl today yesterday win-past-pl-3 become.clear-past.3sS/*-past-3pS

‘Today it became clear that the children won yesterday.’

b. En bügün [ ten beqehee kyaj-byt-yŋ] cuolkajdan-na/*-ny-ŋ.

you today yesterday win-past-2sg become.certain-past.3/* -past-2sg

‘Today it became certain [that you won yesterday].’

The ban against agreeing twice with the same NP is also observable in

nominalizations, where the higher agreement-bearing head is D rather than T. Thus the

nominalization of the possessor raising structure in (66) is also bad with agreement on D.

(68) [Oqo-lor at-tar-yn öl-üü-ler-e] miigin xomot-to.

children-PL horse-pl-3.gen die-YY-pl-3 me.ACC upset-past.3

Bad as: The children having their horse die on them upset me.

(OK only as The children’s horses’ dying upset me.)

Similarly, the nominalization of the raising constructions in (67) is bad when there is

agreement on D with the raised NP; the construction is possible only if the nominalized

verb has 3s agreement, with the participial clause as a whole, not with the raised subject.

53

Page 54: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

(69) Oqo-lor beqehee kyaj-byt-tar-yn cuolkajdan-yy-ta/*cuolkajdan-yy-lar-a

child-pl yesterday win-past-pl-3.gen become.clear-YY-3/*become-clear-YY-pl-3

‘It’s becoming certain that the children won yesterday.’

(lit. ‘The children’s becoming certain to have won yesterday.’)

The four constructions considered so far all have agreement on the lower T or D

head, but not on the higher T or D head. There are also constructions that have

agreement on the higher head—but these systematically lack agreement on the lower

head. For example, Sakha has a second type of subject-to-subject raising, with the

predicate translated as ‘seems’. This forms an interesting minimal pair with (67), in that

there is agreement on the matrix verb ‘seems’ but not on the embedded verb.

(70) Min (Masha-qa) sylaj-byt-(*ym) kurduk köst-ö-bün.

I Masha-DAT become.tired-PAST-1sS like seem-AOR-1sS

‘I seem (to Masha) to be tired.’

Note that the participial clause that is the complement of the P kurduk ‘like’ can bear

agreement in non-raising contexts, so agreement is not out for morphological reasons:

(71) ?Masha en oxtu-but-un kurduk oqun-na.

Masha you fall-PAST-2sS like fall-Past.3sS

‘Masha fell like (in the same way that) you fell.’

Another minimal pair comes from noun complement constructions with a head

noun like ‘rumor’. ‘Rumor’ can select a full CP complement headed by the C dien, or it

can select a participial complement. When it has a full CP complement, the embedded

verb agrees with its subject, but there is no agreement on the D associated with ‘rumor’;

when it has a participial complement, there is agreement on the D but not on the verb:

54

Page 55: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

(72) a. En djoro kiehe-qe kel-er-(*iŋ) surax-yŋ

You party-DAT come-PTPL-(*2sS) rumor-2s

‘the rumor that you are coming to the party’

b. En djoro kiehe-qe kel-ieq-i ŋ dien surax-(*yŋ)

You party come-Fut-2sS dien rumor-(*2s)

‘the rumor that you will come to the party’

Again, it is perfectly possible for participles to bear agreement with their subjects in other

syntactic contexts. For example, participles in Sakha bear subject agreement when they

are used as the sole predicate of the matrix clause, as shown in (73).

(73) Min bil-er-im

I know-AOR-1sg

‘I used to know.’

Min alta-qa ahaa-byt-ym

I six-DAT eat-past-1sg

‘I ate at 6:00.’

En aaq-yaq-yŋ.

You read-FUT-2sg

‘You will read.’

So (72a) with double agreement does not violate simple morphological principles.

Finally, Sakha has a variety of complex tenses, consisting of a participle and an

auxiliary. In all such combinations, agreement shows up on the auxiliary but not also on

the participle, even though agreement can attach to the participle, as seen in (73):

(74) Min bil-er(*-im) e-ti-m

55

Page 56: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

I know-AOR-1sS aux-past-1sS

‘I used to know.’

Min alta-qa ahaa-byt(-*ym) e-ti-m.

I six-DAT eat-Past.PPL-1sS aux-1sg

‘I had already eaten at 6:00.’

En aaq-yax(-*yŋ) e-ti-ŋ.

You read-FUT aux-past-2sg

‘You would read.’

This is by no means a universal condition; there are quite a few languages that allow

double agreement in participle-plus-auxiliary constructions, including many Bantu

languages, Burushaski, Fijian, Tukang Besi, Georgian, and others (see Baker 2008:ch.5)

for discussion). Some of these languages also have double agreement in subject-to-

subject raising constructions like (70). But in Sakha this kind of double agreement is not

possible, and systematically so.17

We conclude that the idea that T assigns nominative, D assigns genitive, and

agreement is dependent on case assignment has a rich array of consequences in Sakha.

Could the same pattern be captured without assuming that case assignment happens in

this way? Technically yes, it could be done. Suppose that NP agrees in the embedded

domain, before raising into a higher domain. Then it must be marked somehow to show

that it has already undergone agreement, and is not eligible to undergo agreement again.

What kind of marking would this be? From the Chomskian perspective, that is exactly

the role of the case feature: an NP with valued case has been agreed with; an NP with an

unvalued case feature has not been and is still eligible for agreement. So this way of

56

Page 57: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

developing the alternative makes it almost nondistinct from the Chomskian theory.

While it is possible to assume that there is a novel “bookkeeping” feature of this kind and

deny that it has any relationship to case marking, we think it is reasonable to put the

burden of proof on a theorist who wants to maintain this, given that case is an

independently needed feature of NPs and it is sufficient to do this job.

There is one complication that we must mention before closing. We were careful

to say that T and D cannot agree with an NP that has already been marked for case in

Sakha. As far as we know, this is true. However, it is possible for accusative and dative

case to assigned to an NP that has been agreed with in a previous phase of the derivation.

This happens, for example, in raising to object constructions, where an NP agrees with T

in the embedded clause, is marked nominative there (we assume), raises into the matrix

clause, and then is marked accusative by rule (2b). (75) is an example of this.

(75) Min ehigi-ni bügün kyaj-yax-xyt dien erem-mit-im. (=(xx))

I you-ACC today win-FUT-2pl that hope-PAST-1sg

‘I hoped you would win today.’

Apparently, then, accusative case can overwrite nominative case, even though nominative

case cannot overwrite accusative (or genitive, or even another instance of nominative).

Similarly, in the dative possessor raising construction shown in (76) (repeated from

section 2.7), the possessor NP agrees with D in DP, is (we assume) marked genitive,

raises into the matrix VP, and is marked dative by rule (2a).

(76) a. Misha-qa beqehee at-a öl-lö.

Misha-dat yesterday horse-3sP die-past.3

‘Misha’s horse died on him yesterday.’

57

Page 58: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Accusative case can even overwrite genitive case: this happens when a possessor raises

out of NP into the CP domain of an embedded clause, and then out of the embedded

clause into the matrix CP. An example is in (77).

(77) Min Masha-ny (beqehee) yt-a öl-büt-ün ihit-ti-

m

I Masha-ACC (yesterday) dog-3sP die-PPL-3s.ACC heard-1sS

‘I heard of Masha yesterday that her dog died.’

These are the only kinds of structures in which there is agreement with an NP that is case

marked accusative or dative.

The upshot of these examples is that we oversimplified somewhat when we said

that case marking on NPs is unique and indelible. We now discover that the two

modalities of case assignment differ in their relative strengths. Case marking by

functional categories is a relatively delicate affair: it can only happen when the NP in

question has an unvalued case feature. In contrast, case marking by configuration is more

forceful: it can change a case feature that has already been assigned by another process.

This pattern can be captured by stating the principles as follows:

(78) a. NP can Agree with X only if NP has an unvalued case feature.

b. If NP Agrees with X, its case feature is valued by X.

In fact, these statements are standard parts of Chomsky’s theory. What is distinctive

about our view is that there is another way of getting case, which is independent of

agreeing with a functional category. That is the configurational rules in (2). Since this

case does not come from agreement by (78b), it is not limited by the condition on

agreement in (78a). It then more or less follows that only this type of case marking can

58

Page 59: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

change the value of a case feature that has already been assigned. This is a somewhat

mechanical result that is perhaps not worth bragging about too much. But we take this

asymmetry between nominative and genitive on the one hand (which can’t be assigned to

NPs that already have a case value) and accusative and dative on the other (which can be)

to be further support for our general claim that there are two types of case assignment

both in operation in the same grammar.

10 Apparently the NP does not raise out of an adjunct clause, as witnessed by the

impossibility of the NP moving across a matrix adverb as well as lack of NPI licensing by

the matrix verb. Note that moving the NP to the edge of the lower clause is enough to

make it visible on the matrix CP phase, given Chomsky’s Phase Impenetrability

Condition. Presumably full-fledged movement out of the adjunct clause is blocked by the

adjunct island condition or whatever more general principle it reduces to.

11An alternative could be that the NP objects of these Ps are optionally allowed to move to

the edge of the PP phases, whereas the objects of other Ps cannot do this.

12Interestingly, the subject in sentences like (52a) can also be marked with nominative

case instead of genitive case. (The difference is only visible when the subject is a

possessed noun, as it is in (52a).) We tentatively assume that it is a morphological

phenomenon: the NP is genitive in the syntax, but the rule that inserts /n/ ((5b)) is only

obligatory when a genitive NP is adjacent to the agreeing noun. There is some data to

support this (genitive /n/ is less obligatory even in a phrase like Masha father-3s-(n) big

farm). We acknowledge that something more interesting could be at work here, however.

13 Again, an alternative analysis might be possible for some of these facts. For example,

one might say that there is a covert subject in (94) that (a) triggers accusative case on the

object, but (b) intervenes between D and the object, preventing agreement between the

59

Page 60: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

Finally, we close with a remark on the unmarked objects of transitive verbs.

What case do they have—if any? They clearly don’t have a case assigned by the

configurational rules (2a) or (2b). On the other hand, they are not related to (visible)

agreement in the way that subjects and possessors are. In particular, they do not agree

with T or D or any other functional head. Hence, there can be no argument that they

receive case that comes from the interplay of case and overt agreement. Thus, there is no

two. That is not implausible for (95), but somewhat less plausible for (97), where no

PRO subject would be possible. More generally, current theory provides no firm

guarantee that every nominal that counts as a case competitor for the object, licensing

accusative case, will also count as an intervener, blocking a functional head from

agreeing with the object. Hence, stating the relationship between agreement and case

marking more directly seems desirable. Finally, the relative clause example in (98)

cannot be explained by defective intervention at all, since the dative subject is closer to

the agreeing D than the unmarked object (as can be shown by standard c-command tests).

14 Compare also Baker 2008:ch.5, where it is argued that agreement is dependent on their

being a case-valuing relationship between the head and the agreeing NP in some

languages but not others, as a parametric difference. In Baker’s terms, the data in this

section show that the “Case-Dependency of Agreement Parameter” is set Yes in Sakha,

as it is in Turkish. (In contrast, Sakha seems to be different from Turkish in that the

Direction of Agreement Parameter is set No in Sakha.)

15 But see (xx) below for a systematic counterexample to this assumption.

16 One might imagine that agreement on the matrix T is ruled out in (67) because the

movement is a kind of A-bar scrambling, not raising to an A position, and T can only

agree with A-positions. But this is probably not true. The raising has several properties

60

Page 61: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

reason to say that they are assigned case in the syntax at all. If we were set on

maintaining the idea that all NPs must get case in the syntax (the Case Filter), we could

devise a mechanism that gave them case easily enough. But we have not needed to

stipulate that all NPs get case at any point in our exploration, and there are well-known

gaps in the case assignment rules anyway (for example, “Hanging Topics” in left-

peripheral positions are possible in many languages, but are not assigned case). We

know of nothing to be gained saying that the indefinite objects or transitive verbs are case

marked, beyond a certain kind of theoretical uniformity. Once we understand the internal

of A-movement rather than A-bar movement. First, only the subject of the embedded

clause can move into the matrix clause in this way. Second, the subject of the embedded

clause can not cross a dative argument of the matrix clause. Together, these facts show

that the raising obeys the kind of locality expected of A-movement, such that the NP

cannot move over another A-position (cf. Rizzi 1990), not the kind of locality expected of

A-bar movement. Finally, if one raises the NP over an adjunct PP in the matrix, the NP

can bind reflexives and pronominal variables inside the PP. The raised position thus

counts as an A-position for binding and crossover, and should for agreement as well.

17 A fuller account would of course need to explain why the sole agreement is found on

the lower head in some constructions but on the higher head in others. We suspect that

agreement always happens on the lowest possible head, and this bleeds the possibility of

agreement on higher functional heads. Constructions like (70), (72), and (74) have

agreement on the higher head because there happens to be no lower head that could bear

the agreement in the structure particular constructions. Nevertheless, they are still useful

to drive home the point that agreement on a higher head is perfectly fine in Sakha as long

as it is not bled by agreement on a lower head.

61

Page 62: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

logic of the configurational case marking system in Sakha, it is clear enough why these

NPs fall outside it. Similarly, once we understand the internal logic of the functional

head case marking system, it is clear enough why these NPs fall outside of it as well.

Hence it is plausible to say that such NPs simply fall between the cracks defined by the

two types of case assignment. There are no serious consequences to this, beyond the fact

that the NPs receive no case suffix. We thus assume that there is no overarching case

filter in Sakha, and no guarantee that every NP will get case. The two systems of case

cover most NPs in the language, but not necessarily all of them. Another type of NP that

apparently falls through the cracks is the subject of a relative clause whose possessor has

been extracted, as discussed in section 4.1. It is conceivable that there are other gaps too

—possibly the object of Ps that are always phases but have no lexical case to assign.

5. Conclusion

We have shown that there are two kinds of structural case in Sakha, each with its own

logic. Nominative and genitive are assigned by functional heads (D and T) and go along

with agreement. Accusative and dative are not assigned by functional heads, but rather

by configurational case marking algorithms, and (consequently) they are never agreed

with. This is a hybrid theory, like Chomsky’s for two of the structural cases, but like

Marantz’s for the other two. Languages seem to be consistent as to whether functional

heads need to case mark NPs in order to agree with them or not; for example, both T and

D have this property in Sakha. But languages need not be consistent in how the various

NPs of the language are assigned case in the first place.

62

Page 63: Notes on the Assignment of Morphological Case in Sakhamabaker/papers to add/sakha_case... · Web viewMark Baker and Nadya Vinokurova Rutgers University February, 2008 Abstract: There

References

Baker, Mark. 2008. The syntax of agreement and concord. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Barss, Andrew, and Lasnik, Howard. 1986. A note on anaphora and double objects. Linguistic Inquiry 17:347-354.

Bittner, Maria, and Hale, Kenneth. 1996. The structural determination of Case and agreement. Linguistic Inquiry 27:1-68.

Bobaljik, Jonathan. to appear. Where's Phi? Agreement as a post-syntactic operation. In Phi Theory: Phi Features Across Interfaces and Modules, eds. David Adger, Daniel Harbour and Susanna Béjar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Burzio, Luigi. 1986. Italian syntax: A Government-Binding approach. Dordrecht: Reidel.Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: the framework. In Step by Step, eds. Roger

Martin, David Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Diesing, Molly. 1992. Indefinites. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Emonds, Joseph. 1985. A unified theory of syntactic categories. Dordrecht: Foris.Fox, Danny, and Pesetsky, David. 2004. Cyclic linearization of syntactic structure.

Theoretical Linguistics 31:1-46.Halle, Morris, and Marantz, Alec. 1993. Distributed morphology and the pieces of

inflection. In The View From Building 20, eds. Kenneth Hale and S.J. Keyser, 111-176. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Kornfilt, Jaklin. 1997. Turkish. New York: Routledge.Krueger, John. 1962. Yakut Manual. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Publications.Larson, Richard. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19:335-392.Legate, Julie. 2008. Morphological and abstract case. Linguisitic Inquiry 39:55-102.Marantz, Alec. 1991. Case and licensing. Paper presented at The 8th Eastern States

Conference on Linguistics, University of Maryland, Baltimore.McFadden, Thomas. 2004. The position of morphological case in the derivation,

University of Pennsylvania: Ph.D. dissertation.Ouhalla, Jamal. 1993. Subject extraction, negation and the anti-agreement effect. Natural

Language and Linguistic Theory 11:477-518.Rizzi, Luigi. 1990. Relativized minimality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Stachowski, Marek, and Menz, Astrid. 1998. Yakut. In The Turkic Languages, eds. Lars

Johanson and Eva Csató, 417-433. London: Routledge.Vinokurova, Nadezhda. 2005. Lexical categories and argument structure: a study with

reference to Sakha, University of Utrecht: Ph.D dissertation.

63