Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    1/22

    Middle-Range Theory in

    Archaeology

    Peter Kosso

    Historical

    1 Introduction: Conceptual Background

    EVIDEN E

    n archaeology, since it is an informational link between the unob-

    servable past and observable data in the present, must be accountable to

    justification that the link is secure and accurate. The same accountability is

    true of evidence in the natural sciences where epistemic responsibility requires

    an understanding of the connection between the manifest data (streaks in a

    bubble chamber, for example) and the theorized entities (alpha particles) of

    which the data are evidence. In the archaeological case, Lewis Binford has

    suggested that the informational link is understood, and hence the evidence is

    made meaningful and reliable, through middle-range theories which describe

    the formation process of the data. Applying this approach to the more specific

    case of historical archaeology, M. Leone and P. Potter suggest that the

    documentary record of the past and the material record could be used as

    independent sources of middle-range theories for each other.* They indicate

    though, that this epistemic opportunity in historical archaeology is rarely

    exploited.

    The purpose of this paper is to present an analysis of evidence in a particular

    case of historical archaeology to show the middle-range theories in action. By

    focusing on how the evidential link is made between observational data and

    the objects and events of theoretical interest it will be shown that middle-range

    theories are almost always implicit in the evidence, and that they can be

    articulated and evaluated for their independence from the theories their

    evidence is used to test. It is this independence that allows the theory-

    influenced evidence to be objective evidence nonetheless. Furthermore, the

    implicit status of the middle-range theories in the case at hand motivates the

    suggestion that documentary and material information participate more often

    *Department of Philosophy, Northern

    Arizona University, PO Box 6011, Flagstaff, AZ 8601 l-

    6011, U.S.A.

    Received 19 August 1992; n

    fin l

    form 21 October 1992.

    L.

    Binford, General Introduction,

    in L. Binford (ed.), For Theory Bui lding in Archaeology

    New

    York: Academic Press, 1977). p. 7.

    2M. Leone and P. Potter, Issues in Historical Archaeology, in M. Leone and P. Potter (eds),

    The Recovery of Meaning (Washington: Smithsonian Institute Press, 1988).

    Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci.

    Vol. 24, No. 2, pp. 163-184, 1993.

    Printed in Great Britain

    163

    003 3681/93 S6.00 + 0.00

    0 1993. Pergamon Press Ltd

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    2/22

    164 Studi es in Hi stor y and Phil osophy of Science

    in such a reciprocal relation than Leone and Potter indicate. The middle-range

    theorizing simply goes without saying.

    This is not to be a discussion of the structure of confirmation. It is not about

    the nature of the connection between the evidence, once youve got it, and a

    hypothesis. It is rather about the nature of the evidence itself and its relation to

    theoretical claims invoked to enhance the informational value of data.

    As a case study, this is an empirical contribution to a description of

    archaeological and scientific evidence, a description that requires a component

    of conceptual analysis as well. Like science itself, philosophy of science must

    offer both general theorizing and specific evidence. The specifics of this case

    will be more meaningful if presented in their theoretical context, that is, with a

    preliminary sketch of the conceptual analysis it is intended to complement. To

    this end, I now briefly outline the theorizing which will help structure the

    subsequent evidence.3

    The accomplishment of theorizing, in science as in our everyday knowledge

    about the world around us, is to make expansive claims about what is

    happening or has happened behind the scenes, beyond what is manifest in

    experience. Theories make claims about unobservable objects and events of all

    sorts, the tiny, the distant, the cumulative, the past. Evidential claims which

    function to test a theory must be relevant to these objects and events

    mentioned by the theory, and to the accessible, particular objects and events

    which are mid-sized, here and now. A complete picture of evidence then, must

    include claims, theoretical claims, which describe the link between accessible

    objects and the phenomena which make contact with theory. It is an appeal to

    theory, to revive a previous example, which allows the physicist to call these

    streaks in the bubble chamber indicators of alpha decay. These streaks mean

    alpha decay.

    The claims which add this kind of meaning and relevance to the data are

    often descriptions of how the data are formed. In describing the causal process

    which led from phenomenon of evidential interest (alpha decay) to the final

    observable event (streaks), the data are shown to be an image of the pheno-

    menon. Elsewhere4 I have referred to these claims which reveal the evidentially

    relevant information in observations as accounting theories, indicating that

    scientific evidence is not simply an episode of observation but an observation

    that is accountable in the sense that the scientist, or at least the scientific

    community at large, must know the circumstances of formation of the observa-

    tion to know both what it means - that is, in what sense it is relevant to the

    particular theory for which it is evidence - and to know that it is reliably

    The full treatment of this conceptual analysis can be found in P. Kosso, Science and

    Objectivity,

    The Journal of Phil osophy 86 1989), 245-257,

    and P. Kosso, Method in

    Archaeology: Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics,

    American An tiqui ty 56 621-627.

    KOSSO, Science and Objectivity,

    ibid.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    3/22

    M iddle-Range Theory i n H i st ori cal Archaeol ogy

    165

    linked to the phenomenon it describes. Evidential knowledge, like theoretical

    knowledge, must be accountable. The accounting claims could alternatively be

    thought of as imaging theories in the case of using an instrument such as a

    microscope to link a specimen of interest to an observable image. In the

    context of archaeology, Lewis Binford identifies the claims which give meaning

    to the static archaeological record as middle-range theories. As Binford puts it,

    middle-range theories describe the formation process of the archaeological

    record.5

    This informational link between present and past is a necessary

    component of archaeological evidence since only through an accurate under-

    standing of such processes can we reliably give meaning to the facts that

    appear, from the past, in the contemporary era.6

    Regardless of what you call them, the point here is that any accountable

    claims which go beyond the episodic data will require something like middle-

    range theories, accounting theories. These theories will not always, in fact not

    usually, be explicit in the presentation of evidence, but they must always be

    available and amenable to articulation. This is to say that while it may be too

    strict to insist that one must in fact give justification for all scientific claims, it

    is a basic responsibility that the scientific community must at least have

    justification available, even for evidential claims.

    This conclusion is based on principles of what theories do and what is

    required to make observations relevant to theory. We need to see now that in

    fact, not only in principle, this is the case and that middle-range theories can be

    seen in action and can be articulated. Since the conclusion in principle is very

    general, dealing with any activity of theorizing beyond the apparent data,

    accounting theories or middle-range theories (I use the terms interchangeably)

    should be discoverable in cases of evidence in natural sciences, social sciences,

    and even our day-to-day efforts to understand the world around us. The

    exposure of middle-range theories in the context of historical archaeology is

    the primary task of this paper, but it is done with the belief that similar

    analysis will be as fruitful in other archaeological and scientific cases.

    There is a secondary point I hope to make through the case study, a point

    that will help to fit the analysis of evidence into a bigger picture of the

    justification of scientific knowledge. Middle-range theories, the case will show,

    are not special kinds of theories with a special kind of content. They are not

    necessarily of middle-generality or of middling confirmation (nor particularly

    solid confirmation). They are just regular theories that are, in the particular

    circumstances that we find them here, used in a particular way.

    This fits into a coherence model of justification of scientific knowledge.

    Evidential claims require theories for justification, as theories require evidence

    Binford, op. cit ., note 1, p. I.

    Ibid.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    4/22

    166

    Studies i n H istory and Phi losophy of Science

    for justification, and the theories which justify evidence do not bring any

    epistemic privileges into the account. They must pass their own evidential and

    conceptual tests. There is a kind of hermeneutic circularity in all of this, in that

    the specific, particular reports of observation are guided by more general

    understanding of theories, while the theoretical claims are themselves shaped

    by the specifics of evidence. But it need not be a problematic circle insofar as

    we can insist on an independence between the theories which influence a

    particular observation and the theory for which that observation is evidence.

    All evidence is guided by theory, but not necessarily by the same theory it is

    used to test.

    But this is a big, conceptual issue, and the programme here is to consider

    some particular evidence. The bulk of the exposition is to be done through an

    example in historical Greek archaeology, where evidence is sought about the

    colonization by Classical Athens.

    Evidence and theory in archaeology do not make for a typical case study in

    the philosophy of science, but with the reciprocating relation between theory

    and evidence as will be shown here, it is wise to look for similarities between

    the status of evidence in archaeology and in natural science. Similarities in the

    nature of observation in archaeology and natural science were pointed out by

    John Fritz even before Binford introduced the concept of middle-range theory.

    Fritz classified prehistoric events and objects as being indirectly observed in the

    same sense as distant galaxies or atoms are indirectly observed. Much of what

    follows here will be built on Fritzs foundation.

    2. The Form of the Analysis

    Since the goal of this case study is to demonstrate the work done by middle-

    range theories and to assess the relationship between these and the object

    theory, the key to the analysis is to identify and articulate the participating

    claims in each presentation of scientific evidence. The example will begin with a

    statement of its hypothesis, the theoretical claim being tested by the evidence.

    A bit of background to the hypothesis, its importance to the science and the

    motivation for its proposal, will be provided to locate the example in its larger

    intellectual setting. Then the evidential claims will be presented. We will not

    uphold any significant epistemic distinction between particular claims which

    function as antecedent motivation for the hypothesis and those in the role of

    subsequent evidence. Whether an observation takes place before or after the

    actual proposal of a hypothesis, the observation can still function as evidential

    support.

    J. Fritz, Archaeological Systems for the Indirect Observation of the Past, in M. Leone (ed),

    Contemporary

    Archaeology

    (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1972), p. 136.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    5/22

    M iddle-Range Theory in H i st ori cal Ar chaeology 167

    The example analysed here is an on-going project. It is not a closed case, and

    so the evidence will be both actual, observations that have already been made,

    and potential, relevant observations proposed but yet to be carried out. In

    either case it is important to know of the theoretical influence which makes the

    observation relevant to the hypothesis. Of these evidential claims, care will be

    taken to identify two kinds: those which describe the manifest state of affairs,

    the data, and those which describe the phenomena which are not manifest.

    The final set of claims to be identified in the case will be those theoretical

    claims used to link the manifest data to the relevant phenomena. These will be

    the background information employed to tell us what the observations mean

    -that is, what they indicate about the hypothesis. These are the middle-range

    theories, or the accounting theories, which attest to the relevance and accuracy

    of the observations. These are what make observations into evidence.

    Once all these components of the evidence and testing have been identified,

    the analysis will continue by assessing the relation between the hypothesis, that

    is, the theory being tested, and the accounting theories. In particular, we will

    evaluate the independence between these two components to check for any

    covert circularity in the presentation of evidence. Finally, each case will end

    with a discussion of the negotiation between theory and evidence. When things

    go wrong and evidence does not match hypothetical expectation, something

    has to give. With the large cast of participants in each evidential claim there is

    apparently much work to be done in deciding which to revise or reject.

    Initially, none are immune to revision and the ensuing give-and-take between

    evidence and theory is a necessary concluding step in each case.

    3.

    The Cleruchy Hypothesis

    This is an example of using evidence to test a theory in the domain of

    historical archaeology. Historical archaeology, in contrast to prehistoric

    archaeology, is a study of places and people in times past for which there is a

    written record. Like all archaeology though, the technique of historical

    archaeology is to use the material remains, artifacts and lasting impact on the

    environment, as evidence for claims about past behaviour.

    The particular example to be analysed here deals with Classical Athens and,

    more specifically, with Athenian settlements outside of Attica. As understood

    from ancient inscriptions and from ancient authors, the traditional view

    classifies Athenian foreign settlements into three broad and somewhat flexible

    categories. The distinction is based on two things: the citizenship status

    (including military obligation) of the people in the settlement, and the political

    Much of what follows about these settlements I have learned with much help from corre-

    spondence with Mac Wallace.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    6/22

    168

    Studies in H istory and Phi losophy of Science

    autonomy of the settlers (including rights of ownership of land). Settlements

    differed, in other words, in terms of the occupants obligations and rights with

    respect to the homeland.

    One type of settlement was the

    garrison,

    essentially a military outpost.

    Residents of a garrison were given no land, either to work or to own. They had

    virtually no rights of self-rule and they were fully obliged of military service in

    the interests of Athens.

    At the other extreme was the Athenian colony. Colonists generally owned

    their own land in the settlement and were free to empower their own gover-

    nors. They did not owe military service to Athens, but interpretations differ as

    to whether they retained Athenian citizenship.

    The third sort of settlement, the cleruchy, was a kind of hybrid between

    garrison and colony. Cleruchs were given land to farm, though the land was

    not freely disposable. They retained their Athenian citizenship and were taxed

    accordingly. They were also obliged to Athens for military service. Cleruchies

    seem to have been a sort of paramilitary community, an Athenian presence on

    foreign soil, there to keep an eye on unwilling allies, a residential extinguisher

    of brushfires of discontent. It has been suggested9 that cleruchs were chosen

    from the lower classes of Athenian citizens. Service as a cleruch may have been

    marketed as an assistance to the poor - the use of land in exchange for

    minimal military service - but deployed in fact as a way to decrease the

    population of tiff-raff at home and to control unruly neighbours at the same

    time.

    Many of the details about cleruchies are unknown. There are questions

    about the specifics such as exactly where they were established and when. And

    there are more general questions such as whether the cleruchies were generally

    situated on good farm land or poor, and whether the group of cleruchs were

    grouped in a defensible, perhaps even fortified, community, or spread across

    the land of their hosts. The written record has so far been uninformative on

    these points.

    The issue of the Athenian cleruchy is relevant to studies by the Southern

    Euboea Exploration Project (SEEP), a group of archaeologists at work on a

    regional study of, not surprisingly, the southern third of the island of Euboea.

    (Map 1 shows the island of Euboea relative to the mainland and other Greek

    islands. Map 2 below shows southern Euboea, the area of study.) Several

    seasons of work have been focused on the cleruchy hypothesis which is, in its

    most basic presentation, the suggestion that there was a cleruchy on southern

    ee, for example, R. Meiggs,

    The

    Athenian Empire (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972).

    p. 121.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    7/22

    M iddle- Range Theory in H istori cal Archaeology

    169

    Map I.

    Euboea. It is a determinate claim about specific events in the past in the sense

    that the concept of a cleruchy is reasonably well distinguished and the region

    of southern Euboea is a distinctive region due to its isolation by mountains

    from the rest of the island. It is a theoretical claim in the sense that it describes

    unobservable objects and events.

    The motivation for proposing the cleruchy hypothesis and for spending time

    and money to test it is from two sources, written evidence (history) and

    material evidence (archaeology). Consider first the historical record.

    Herodotus and Thucydides both mention cleruchies but make only one

    reference each, and neither is in southern Euboea. Herodotus writes of a

    cleruchy at Chalkis in central Euboea, while Thucydides tells of a cleruchy at

    Mytilini on the island of Lesbos, near the coast of Asia Minor. Later historians

    add more accounts of cleruchies. Diodorus Siculus, a Sicilian writing four

    centuries after the fact, writes that Athens dispatched 1000 cleruchs to be

    divided into three cleruchy communities, one on Naxos, another on Andros,

    Much of this work was conducted under the title of the Canadian Karystia Project, work that

    was staffed and directed by SEEP personnel. Descriptions of the work and the cleruchy hypothesis

    can be found in D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project, Ectros

    Du Mona?

    Classique/Classicaf Views 30 1986). 155-I 59; D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian Karystia

    Project, 1986,

    Ethos Du Monde Classique/Classical Views 31 1987), 225227;

    D. Keller and

    M. Wallace, How to Catch a Cleruch,

    Canadian Archaeological Bull etin,

    Fall (1987), 6-7; and

    D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project: Two Classical Farmsteads, Ethos Du

    Mona e Classique/Classical Views 32 (1988), 151-l 57.

    Epistemological questions about the historical record, questions of accuracy and trustworthi-

    ness of the accounts, will be taken up later. I do not intend for any of these historical reports to be

    believed unequivocally, but it is helpful at this point to present who said what about cleruchies.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    8/22

    17 Studi es in H i stor y and Phil osophy of Science

    and a third on Euboea. Plutarch, in the

    Li fe of Peri cles,

    mentions the sending

    of 500 cleruchs to Naxos and 250 to Andros. Though no ancient author says

    explicitly how many cleruchs went to Euboea, we can put together the

    information from Diodorus and from Plutarch to conclude that the remaining

    250 cleruchs of the 1000 reported by Diodorus went to Euboea. Furthermore,

    while the northern two-thirds of Euboea were culturally and economically

    most closely associated with the mainland of Greece, the southern third of the

    island participated more with the Cycladic islands, like Andros and Naxos.

    This is reason to think that a dispatch of cleruchs to Andros, Naxos. and

    Euboea might well be a mission to the Cyclades, that is, to Andros, Naxos, and

    southern Euboea. Thus, the inference from the historical sources gives some

    reason to think that Athens sent 250 cleruchs to southern Euboea. There is

    some reason, that is, to entertain the cleruchy hypothesis.

    Interestingly, the evidence for southern Euboeas Cycladic connection is

    largely archaeological evidence. Much of the prehistoric pottery found in

    southern Euboea shows similarity to Cycladic pottery and can thereby be seen

    as indicative of interaction with Cycladic islands. The architecture of modern

    houses in southern Euboea also shows distinct similarities to Cycladic styles

    and dissimilarity from that of the northern two-thirds of Euboea.12 This is

    interesting for an analysis of the nature of the evidence because it is a case of

    archaeology helping to make sense of the historical evidence. Through an

    independent analysis of ceramic remains, the informational content of the

    textual data is enhanced. We see more fully what the text means in light of the

    background knowledge about pottery.

    These historical accounts might be thought of as direct references in that

    they mention cleruchies explicitly, but it would be misleading to regard them as

    direct information about events in the past. This is information that has been

    passed along by the historian, via his sources and with his writing, through

    time. There is work to be done in securing the credibility of these ancient

    writers on this particular subject. Diodorus and Plutarch, after all, were

    describing events that had taken place centuries earlier and their evidence is

    acceptable only insofar as we can keep track of how they would know about

    these things. Diodorus, in fact, is often inaccurate in his tales of ancient

    Greece, underscoring the need for justification of his particular claims about

    cleruchies. Pausanias, also writing centuries after cleruchs had come and gone,

    also makes explicit reference to the cleruchs sent to Euboea and Naxos, and

    Pausanias enjoys a good reputation for accuracy. This is due largely to his

    frequent description of landscapes and monuments, features of the land and

    x, for example, D. Keller, Archaeological Survey in Southern Euboea,

    Greece:

    A

    Reconstruction of Human Activity from Neolithic Times through the Byzantine Period, (unpub-

    lished Ph.D. Dissertation, Indiana University, 1983, pp. 64465.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    9/22

    M iddle-Range Theory i n H ist ori cal Ar chaeology

    171

    culture that are preserved today and can be checked against his account. Here

    again, archaeology, the study of the material record, is used in accounting for

    historical evidence.

    There is another complication in reading the written evidence for cleruchies,

    even when the writing is explicitly about that kind of settlement. The ancient

    authors did not always use the same word to refer to a cleruchy. Thucydides,

    for example, used the term apoikia (~UCOW~~U)ather than cleruchy (~S~pon~os)

    in his account of the settlement at Mytilini,n but scholars know from the

    context what he meant. He meant to describe a cleruchy.

    The point in mentioning these uncertainties in the written record is one that

    is obvious to historians. The historical text is not a direct access to the events

    of the past. Its not even close. Evidential claims about the past which come

    from a written record are always in need of accounting in the sense of requiring

    some verification of their accuracy and reliability, and of requiring an inter-

    pretation to pinpoint just what the text means, for as Kuhn points out, there

    are many ways to read a text.14

    Besides the ancient sources which explicitly refer to cleruchies, there is

    implicit textual evidence that can be finessed from accounts of other, related

    phenomena. For example, the Athenian Tribute Lists, inscriptions found in the

    Athenian Agora, listing the taxesI

    collected from the communities in the

    empire, can be used as a source of information about cleruchies. In the year

    450 B.C., Andros paid 12 talents in taxes to Athens. (One talent is equal to

    6000 drachmas, a drachma being a days wage.) The subsequent year, 449,

    Andros paid only 6 talents. This abrupt reduction can be explained by the

    establishment of a cleruchy on the island. If the cleruchs from Athens seize a

    large proportion of farmland, the commercial value of the island, as realized

    by the pre-settlement residents, is diminished and the locals, in all fairness, are

    assessed a lower tax. In this way, establishment of a cleruchy causes an abrupt

    decrease in payment of talents to Athens, allowing historians to use the

    Athenian Tribute Lists as a rough indicator of cleruchies.

    The Athenian Tribute Lists record for Karystos, the principle town in

    southern Euboea, a payment in 450 B.C. of 7+ talents, and in 449 a payment of

    5 talents. There is no corresponding drop in the assessment for Chalkis or

    Eretria, the major towns in the northern two-thirds of the island. This suggests

    a cleruchy in the domain of Karystos as a cleruchy would explain the reduced

    tax assessment and would fit nicely with the coincident reduction on Andros.

    There are no tax records for Naxos prior to 447 B.C., but the assessment in

    See A. Graham, Colony and Mother City in Ancient Greece (Manchester: Manchester

    University Press, 1983), p. 170.

    l4T. Kuhn

    The Essential Tension

    (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), p. xii.

    ISThe ATd actually lists the Quota, one sixteenth of the taxes paid. I am grateful to Mac Wallace

    for clarification of this point.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    10/22

    172

    Studies in H istory and Phi losophy of Science

    that year is quite minimal, an assessment that is compatible with the theory

    that Naxos, Andros, and southern Euboea were all saddled with cleruchies in

    the year 450/449 B.C.

    Further implicit written evidence of a cleruchy in southern Euboea is in the

    indication that Karystos did not participate in the Euboean revolts against

    Athens of 446 and 424 B.C. It is as if the Karystians were kept under control

    by resident Athenian loyalists. This, like the rest of the textual evidence

    presented so far, is surely not conclusive proof of a cleruchy in southern

    Euboea, but it is motivation for the hypothesis.

    There is also archaeological evidence which makes the hypothesis plausible.

    A recent archaeological survey by Don Keller of the Karystian Bay

    watershedI revealed an apparent network of Classical-period farms on the

    Paximadhi peninsula (see Map 2 below). The method of survey archaeology is

    to walk over large areas of land, noting artifactual remains that are visible on

    the surface. There is no excavation involved. From the surface deposits of

    ceramics, worked stones, and remains of walls, information about the habi-

    tation and use of the land can be reconstructed. Survey information is a

    valuable complement to excavation in that it allows for an account of patterns

    of land use and of behaviour spread over a large area.

    It is exactly this kind of pattern-of-habitation information that turned up on

    the Paximadhi. A network of sites emerged and the sites were dated as being of

    Classical period (500 B.C.-320 B.C.) on the basis of the pottery remains found

    on the surface at each site. (There will be more on how this is done and on the

    uncertainties involved when we discuss the relevant middle-range theories.)

    These sites were identified as farms on the basis of several features. Those with

    remaining identifiable groundplans resemble the groundplan of farm sites in

    Attica, the function of the Attic sites being known through inscriptional and

    other types of evidence. The pottery on the putative farm sites in Euboea is

    largely coarseware - the crude, functional stuff associated with domestic

    chores - and the relatively small amount of fineware tends to rule out any

    possible interpretation of the sites as being aristocratic domiciles. And finally,

    the sites are located in proximity to heavily terraced land, olive presses, and

    threshing floors, indicating a link between the sites of habitation and the

    activities of farming. Interestingly, the Paximadhi is no longer farmed. Today

    the land is marginal at best and the peninsula is barren. But the wealth of

    terraces and abundance of habitation sites indicates agricultural activity in the

    past, and the even spacing of the farm sites further indicates a planned

    community rather than a spontaneous growth over time. If the land was

    marginal in Classical times, this might explain why the tribute reduction for

    Euboea was only 7+ to 5 as compared to the more impressive reduction of 12

    l bKel l er p. cit.,

    note

    12.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    11/22

    M iddle-Range Theory in H istori cal Ar chaeology

    173

    to 6 for Andros. For this reason, it would be interesting to locate the Andros

    cleruchy and evaluate the quality of its land.i8

    The network of farmsites is exciting news for the cleruchy hypothesis, since

    the material remains are not only compatible with the hypothesis: they seem,

    with further attention to details, to indicate with greater precision where the

    cleruchy was located. What the initial survey calls for though is more material

    evidence and more precision. Since the written evidence indicates the presence

    of 250 cleruchs, further survey is called for to find the full complement of 250

    farmsites, assuming that each cleruch receives his own farm, along with a

    commensurate number of graves, altars, roads, and the other accoutrements of

    Classical Athenian life. More precise dating of the sites and the complex is also

    needed. The crux to establishing the existence of a cleruchy is the sudden

    appearance of the entire complex in roughly 450 B.C. and its equally sudden

    abandonment in roughly 400 B.C. at the demise of the Athenian empire. Thus

    a precision greater than Classical period would be helpful. It would also be

    informative to collect background data from the surrounding area. Only by

    knowing the patterns of sites and the style and fabric of pottery nearby can it

    be determined that the Paximadhi is unusually well-ordered in its pattern of

    settlement or unusually abrupt in the establishment and abandonment of a

    complex of sites. Thus the initial survey work, while encouraging, calls most

    immediately for more data.

    There is a third source of motivation for the cleruchy hypothesis: empathy

    with the Athenians. This is a risky technique, suitable at least in a context of

    discovery, if not as justification. The idea here is to think like an Athenian and

    see if it makes sense, in light of the fragmentary evidence so far, to put a

    cleruchy in southern Euboea on the Paximadhi peninsula. The land is

    marginal, and this might make it appropriate for a cleruchy for two reasons.

    For one, there is no reason to anger the locals by confiscating their best

    farmland. Better to keep the peace and get by if you can with the less desired

    land. And second, the Athenians can get by with the poor farmland since these

    are only lower class, poorer citizens who end up as cleruchs. If a cleruchy is a

    punishment, or at least no reward, for the lower class of society, it only makes

    sense to stick them with cheap land. I9 Furthermore, the Paximadhi peninsula is

    a strategic place to establish a military presence. Not only is it near the

    population centre of Karystos, but the peninsula juts into the important

    shipping lane between Andros and the mainland. From this one position,

    Paximadhi cleruchs could keep an eye on the local Karystians and the

    Mac Wallace points out (private communication) that the Karystian tribute was 12 talents in

    453. The reduction to 74 in 450 is unexplained.

    *This good idea came from Cynthia Kosso.

    Neither of these reasons for putting a cleruchy on marginal land is a considered conclusion or

    even a serious hypothesis of the SEEP archaeologists. Both were casual suggestions in the course

    of conversation.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    12/22

    174

    St udi es in H istor y and Phil osophy of Science

    Paximadhi Peninsula

    Map 2.

    important shipments of grain via Andros to Athens. Many of the Paximadhi

    farmsites have an excellent view of both the sea lands and the good Karystian

    farmlands.

    None of this proves that there was an Athenian cleruchy on the Paximadhi

    peninsula. But altogether the written and material remains make it reasonable

    to pursue the cleruchy hypothesis in its now more precise formulation. The

    Paximadhi supported at least part of a settlement of 250 cleruchs from the year

    450/449 B.C. until roughly 405 B.C. when the Athenian empire dissolved. This

    is the hypothesis to be tested.

    4. The Evidence

    The evidence for the testing was generated by further archaeological work as

    suggested by the initial survey and the predictions of the hypothesis.

    Confirmation of the hypothesis would be furthered by a linked community of

    roughly 250 farmsteads with coincident periods of occupation from roughly

    450 to 405 B.C., and perhaps with evidence of unusually close ties to Athens.

    To this end, other areas of southern Euboea, namely the vicinities of Geraistos,

    Marmari, and Kallianou, were surveyed in 1984, revealing that the pattern of

    finds in the Paximadhi was distinctive. Then the remainder of the Paximadhi

    peninsula was surveyed in 1986. (Only the eastern side, the Karystian bay

    watershed, was done in the initial survey by Keller.) The 1986 survey showed a

    continuation in the regular settlement pattern, finding more sites of roughly

    Classical period and apparently for use as farmsteads. The surface materials, in

    other words, seemed to bear out the prediction of an extensive community of

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    13/22

    M iddle-Range Theory i n Hi stori cal A rchaeology

    175

    coincident farmsteads. But the surface remains could not fix the dates of

    occupation of the sites with sufficient precision to count as clear evidence of a

    cleruchy. This precise dating could only come by excavation. By excavating

    one or two of the sites, hopefully determining the dates of the materials and

    looking for signs of Athenian material and stylistic influence, information

    would become available about the entire complex of sites. Survey shows that

    the sites are related; excavation refines the information on one or two.

    Together then, there is more precise information on the lot of them.

    This is something of an oversimplification about the ease and efficacy of

    survey archaeology. Nearly every concentration of artifacts, every findspot or

    site, shows material from many time periods. A typical survey report will list

    pottery finds of perhaps Archaic to Roman, or Classical to Byzantine. The

    demonstration that several sites are associated and were occupied at the same

    time is a complicated one which must cite relative numbers of potsherds and it

    is not without ambiguity. The ambiguity though is not caused by an inade-

    quacy in the middle-range theories. It is that the specimen itself is fuzzy, not

    that the image is out of focus. Excavation of a site can bring the information

    into even sharper focus, being in a sense a higher power microscope than

    survey, and with a narrower field of view, but it will still show a fuzzy image of

    a fuzzy specimen, fuzzy in the sense of having no sharp, distinct period of

    occupation. In any case, the survey data of surface material plays the role of

    finding evidence of community and of roughly dating the community.

    Excavation is used for more careful dating as well as to reveal groundplans

    of structures and to collect ceramic remains that might be diagnostic as to the

    origin of the clay or vessel. Two sites were excavated by SEEP in pursuit of

    evidence relevant to the cleruchy hypothesis. One was an abandoned cistern on

    cape Mnima (see Map 2), found during the survey to be filled with debris. The

    cistern is located within the network of farmsteads and is in a fortified and

    strategic location overlooking sheltered harbours. All indications are that the

    cistern was an important feature of the putative cleruchy, and dates of use of

    the cistern would be dates of use of the community. The idea was simply to

    excavate the cistern and determine the date of the oldest material inside. This

    would be the first debris that fell in or were thrown in and not cleared out, and

    would mark the end of use of the cistern as a cistern rather than a garbage pit

    or a shelter from the wind. Material in the cistern, in other words, would be

    evidence of the time of abandonment of an important site in the community.

    Confirmation of the cleruchy hypothesis would be a date of around 405 B.C.

    The other site of excavation was a putative farmsite at Palio Pithari (see

    Map 2). Excavation of this very typical site would provide more pottery, and

    importantly, more diagnostic pottery found in informative context with respect

    to the building structure and the strata. It would provide, that is, much more

    information on dating this characteristic site. It would also clarify the ground-

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    14/22

    176

    St udi es in H i stor y and Phil osophy of Science

    plan of the building and allow a comparison to excavated farmsteads in Attica.

    Again, if the hypothesis is true, one expects dates of occupation of the Palio

    Pithari site to run from 450 B.C. to roughly 405 B.C. That would be

    confirming evidence. Further confirmation would come from analysis of the

    ceramic fabrics, finding at least some of the Palio Pithari pottery to be of a

    fabric unlike that found at the local kiln and at sites away from the cleruchy. A

    greater amount of Attic fineware or coarseware of Attic clay would indicate a

    community with closer ties to Athens. In summary, the evidence for the

    cleruchy hypothesis, the predictions of the hypothesis, would be that Palio

    Pithari is indeed a farmsite with ties to Athens, in use during the second half of

    the fifth century B.C.

    The theory and predictions of the cleruchy hypothesis are clearly presented

    in a SEEP report of 1986. Subsequent reports get right to the experimental

    results.* The cistern was excavated in 1986, and the oldest debris were in fact

    dated to around 400 B.C.** The Palio Pithari farmsite was excavated in 1987

    with results that were not so unambiguously positive.23 The building was

    cleared down to a bedrock floor, revealing a distinct groundplan which was

    similar to several Classical farmsteads in Attica, having small rooms along the

    north wall and a courtyard on the south. The pottery remains were dated into

    the early fourth century, a bit later than would be expected of a cleruchs farm.

    Some of the ceramic materials are still in the process of petrographic analysis

    for comparison to Attic and to local Karystian clay.

    This is the evidence to date for the cleruchy hypothesis and there are two

    important points to note about the nature of the evidence and the role it plays

    in confirmation. The first is that, in citing as evidence a Classical farmsite or

    pottery from the fifth century, we are not citing things that we see. Thats not

    what is on the ground. Whether in survey or in excavation it is not at all

    apparent that a particular worn chip of ceramic is of late-fifth-century vessel or

    that a certain jumble of stones is a wall of a farm house. What is used as

    evidence is not what is seen, and that is exactly the nature of evidence that is of

    concern here. The picture must be filled in with an account linking what is seen

    to what functions as evidence. Thats the first point. The second involves the

    question of the extent to which the evidence presented so far in fact confirms or

    disconfirms the hypothesis. I will pursue these two points in order, spending

    more time on the first.

    What do the SEEP archaeologists see when they go looking for evidence to

    Keller and Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project,

    op ci r.,

    note 10.

    2Keller and Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project 1986, and The Canadian Karystia

    Project: Two Classical Farmsteads, op ci t ., note 10.

    zKeller and Wallace, How to Catch a Cleruch, op. ci t ., note 10.

    Z3Kellerand Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project: Two Classical Farmsteads, op ci t ., note

    10.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    15/22

    M iddle-Range Theory i n Hi stori cal Ar chaeology

    177

    test the cleruchy hypothesis? Mostly they find pieces of ceramic: potsherds,

    fragments of roof tiles and loom weights. They find these things and carefully

    record their spatial context whether on the surface in survey or in layers from

    excavation. Very few of the finds are whole pots, and a very few more are

    complete enough to make obvious, without any inferential reconstruction, the

    shape of the whole vessel. Mostly the data are small fragments of the body,

    rim, or base of a broken vessel. Unfortunately, these fragments are not

    stamped with their date or place of origin, nor are they or the places they are

    found marked for their use (as, for example, being a farm or a farm tool). This

    important information, the information that is relevant to claims about a

    cleruchy, must be somehow unnested from the more manifest. The data must

    be linked to the evidence.

    The first step in the archaeological case is to record all of the useful data by

    carefully describing the apparent physical features of the ceramics. This is the

    pottery inventory and anyone, regardless of their knowledge of archaeology or

    of the past, can do it. All it takes is average eyesight and maybe above-average

    patience. In the process of inventory, a sherd is described in a standardized

    language. Its colour, for example, is compared under controlled lighting to

    patches of colour on the standard Munsell colour chart so that an intersubjec-

    tive colour assessment is made. The ceramic fabric is inspected for inclusions

    and the relative number, size, and colour of the inclusions is noted. The sherd

    itself is measured for thickness and its shape is described using standardized

    terms such as rolled rim or strap handle. And finally the surface of the sherd

    is inspected for treatment such as glaze, slip, incisions or impressed design. All

    of these inventory features are readily apparent on the potsherds. The inven-

    tory reports are the data in this case of archaeological testing, but they are not

    the evidence because they make no contact with the objects and events

    described by theory. They are, as yet, not relevant to the phenomena predicted

    by the hypothesis.

    This requisite contact comes with the next step in the treatment of the finds,

    the preparation of a catalogue. This requires substantial background know-

    ledge on the part of the individual cataloguer and the archaeological commu-

    nity as a whole. A sherd which has been inventoried is now evaluated by the

    experts in an effort to determine the type of vessel it is from, the use of the

    vessel, and, most importantly, its date. The type of vessel is judged by

    comparing dimensions, fabric, and cross-sectional shape of the sherd to

    corresponding features of whole or nearly-whole vessels found elsewhere. The

    use of the vessel can then be inferred from its shape and from the context in

    which it and its comperanda are found.

    Dating the sherd is also dependent on the identification of the type of vessel

    (or in some cases on the physical features of the material or surface treatment).

    The sherd is distinguished by the vessel it is from, or by distinctive decoration

    SHI PS 24: 2-B

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    16/22

    178

    Studies in istory and Philosophy of Science

    or glaze, and can be then associated with similar pieces that have been found

    elsewhere in datable circumstances. Some excavations, notably in Athens at

    the Agora and the Kerameikos, and at Corinth, have uncovered specimens of

    pottery in context with dated inscriptions, with coins, or associated with

    buildings that are datable by historic reference. From these excavations come

    source-books of pottery types and their dates. This punctuated information

    can be filled out through studies of stylistic evolution and through seriation

    studies, attending to relative amounts of ceramic styles as a function of time.

    The accuracy of dating these reference materials is of course dependent on a

    thorough understanding of their context. An object kept for generations as an

    heirloom, for example, might eventually be discarded with a coin of much later

    period. A casual analysis of the tailings of an archaeological dig, for another

    example, might find a beer bottle next to an overlooked neolithic potsherd, but

    it would be a mistake to date one artifact by its association with the other.

    Thus, the datable circumstances of the Athenian Agora require an under-

    standing of the texts and buildings, including the intent and accuracy of the

    writing of the texts found with the pottery or of texts about the buildings, and

    the circumstances of deposition.

    By attending to the comparable features of the pottery found on the

    Paximadhi peninsula and by matching these features to pottery found in

    datable contexts, the catalogued sherds bear information of their own dates -

    information, that is, of activities in the past. Soft, powdery, orange fineware

    with black glaze, for example, is indicative of activities in the Classical period.

    This kind of pottery means occupation of the site during that time period. But

    it is so meaningful only with the support of the antecedent claims which make

    the general connections between the ceramic data and the evidential dates. In

    this case these are claims about the coincidence of pots and texts or pots and

    historic buildings in the Athenian Agora, the dating of coincident inscriptions

    or coins, and the accuracy of this dating as secured by knowing the circum-

    stances of deposition, the intent of the writing (that it is not itself a fiction) and

    the like. Its not that these claims are suspect or complicated. The reason for

    pointing them out is simply to show that they are being relied on and that they

    are, at least in part, claims about the past. They are, in the archaeological

    context, theoretical claims. And since they are being used to make the

    connection between the manifest archaeological record and the information it

    has to offer about the past, these are middle-range theories. They are used to

    tell the SEEP archaeologists what the sherds mean for the cleruchy hypothesis.

    These middle-range theories are all pretty simple claims, about the veracity

    of the dating material and the legitimacy of dating a particular pot by its

    association with a particular text, but simple accounting claims may be all that

    are needed in this case because it is pretty simple information that is being

    sought in the pottery from the Paximadhi. All we are getting by way of

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    17/22

    Middle-Range Theory in H istori cal Ar chaeology

    179

    evidence is a date. More complicated information, such as who made a

    particular pot or exactly what it contained, would demand more complicated

    middle-range theorizing. Dating a pot (and in turn the site where it is found) is

    not unlike sizing a microbe by positioning the little creature next to something

    else of otherwise known size. It is in the process of otherwise knowing the size

    of the comparanda where middle-range theories (accounting theories) are used

    in the case of the microbe. The relatively simple question of size may call for

    only simple middle-range theories, while more involved information, such as

    composition of the microbe, would involve more middle-range theorizing.

    Ascertaining the dates of occupation of the sites on the Paximadhi peninsula

    then makes use of some amount of middle-range theory. So too does another

    aspect of the evidence used to test the cleruchy hypothesis: the analysis of

    ceramic fabric to see if it is of Attic origin or from local Karystian kilns. This

    analysis is limited to coarseware pottery, the stuff with many large inclusions,

    because it is the inclusions themselves which are characteristic of the place of

    manufacture. The ceramic samples for this petrographic analysis are still at the

    lab, but there is no question that the cleruchy-relevant evidence as to whether

    the Palio Pithari coarseware is or is not from clay deposits in Attica will be

    heavily dependent on middle-range theories. The actual data in this case will be

    some sequence of chemical events in the Fitch lab of the British School in

    Athens and these must be made to speak of ancient pottery manufacture. A

    theoretical understanding will be needed to ensure that the petrochemical

    similarities or dissimilarities in the Euboean and Attic ceramics must be due to

    similar or dissimilar origin and not simply inevitable environmental processes

    that show their effects over time. Chemical analysis speaks of associations

    between ancient communities only with a lexicon linking chemical phenomena

    to mineralogical composition to deposits of clay and the manufacture of pots.

    The results of the fabric analysis are just coming in, and they are bound to

    be somewhat ambiguous when they are completed. If the results are negative in

    the sense of showing no greater proportion of Attic fabric at the purported

    cleruchy sites than at other sites around the Karystian bay, this will not

    necessarily tell against the cleruchy hypothesis. No one really knows that

    cleruchs tended to use nonlocal coarseware. In fact, fleshing out the under-

    standing of the cleruchs behaviour is part of the project. And if the evidence is

    of more Attic pottery, there remains the ambiguity as to whether this is pottery

    brought from home or pottery bought in trade by some group of residents on

    the Paximadhi. The problem here is that there is no middle-range theory to

    link the ceramic feature of being an Attic fabric and the feature of being

    brought over with Athenian citizens. Such a relation could only be established

    by studying what was already known to be a settlement of Athenians such as a

    cleruchy. But that would be begging the question in the Euboea case as it

    would breech the independence from theory for which the evidence is a test.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    18/22

    180

    tudies i n Hi story and Phil osophy of Science

    Such is the difficulty in trying to detect an object and at the same time

    determine its properties.

    There is a similar kind of ambiguity in the evidence of the groundplan of the

    Palio Pithari site. There is no disputing the observation that the plan resembles

    those of typical Classical farms in Attica. What is missing is the proof that this

    indicates any sort of influence of Attic farm design on the residents of the

    Paximadhi peninsula, or that the design identifies the Palio Pithari site as a

    farm. The similarity of design could be a result of Attic influence or it could be

    an independent development under the influence of similar environmental

    conditions in the two places. Persistent north winds lead to a predominance of

    residential sites with small rooms tucked against the north wall and courtyards

    on the sheltered south, and this shared design has nothing to do with

    communications between the residents. What is missing in the cleruchy hypo-

    thesis case is a middle-range theory linking groundplan to use and/or origin of

    design of a building.

    The point is that the data are informative evidence when there are indepen-

    dently justified middle-range theories to make the connection to the hypo-

    thesis, and not otherwise. Furthermore, where these theoretical links between

    data and phenomena are at work, they can be uncovered from their normally

    covert activities and made explicit. Thus in the dating of pottery there must be,

    and there are, claims linking descriptions of sherds to dates of pots, the step

    from inventory to catalogue. These simple middle-range theories are often

    presented as pictures with terse captions rather than as discursive theories, but

    they are nonetheless claims which connect the information in the present

    archaeological record with information about the unobservable past. And

    these claims which account for the evidence used to test the cleruchy hypo-

    thesis are accountable to their own evidential and theoretical support. The

    pottery dating catalogues are supported by evidence that is believable and

    meaningful in light of theoretical claims about the texts, and buildings that

    provide a datable context.

    The middle-range theories, in other words, are just like any other theories.

    They are nothing special when it comes to justification. They help and they

    need help. The pottery studied in its context in southern Euboea and dated

    under the influence of previous ceramic theorizing will itself be catalogued and

    published to serve in interpreting ceramic data found elsewhere. The theo-

    retical claims which are the accomplishment of the southern Euboea work will

    become the tools of evidential accounting in some other situation. They too

    can be used as middle-range theories.

    Note also that the accounting theories (the middle-range theories) used in

    the dating of pottery in this case are independent of the cleruchy hypothesis

    itself. There is no cleruchy information, no presumption of anything about the

    particular hypothesis in the dating of pottery from its context in the Athenian

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    19/22

    M iddle-Range Theory i n H ist ori cal Archaeology

    181

    Agora. So while there is a clear theoretical influence on the evidence used to

    test the theory about a cleruchy, it is not a case of circular, self-serving testing.

    The theory does not sponsor its own evidence. It is rather independent

    evidence and in this sense the testing is objective.

    The same is true in the potential evidence of analysing the ceramic fabric.

    The middle-range theories are amenable to articulation and they are normal

    theories which are the accomplishments of chemistry and geology, but they are

    in this case used to link singular properties of the present to general informa-

    tion of the cleruchy hypothesis. These theories are clearly independent of the

    cleruchy hypothesis, and thats important.

    Having presented the hypothesis, the evidence, and the middle-range theor-

    ies which give meaning to the evidence, the final question is of the status of the

    hypothesis in light of the testing. The evidence from the Palio Pithari excava-

    tion, in particular the dating of the abandonment of the site, tend to discon-

    firm the hypothesis. Put more symmetrically, there is tension in the network of

    claims which includes the hypothesis, evidence, data, and middle-range theor-

    ies. This incompatibility alone does not indicate which of the claims must be

    revised or rejected. Following Quine and Duhem, no claim is immune to

    revision or rejection, and the hypothesis is potentially retainable if there is

    reason to doubt some other parts of the network. For example, the auxiliary

    theories, claims that have not been discussed here but which are used to draw

    implications from the hypothesis, are part of the tension. Perhaps the proposed

    dates of the Karystian cleruchy are off. The start date is informed by relatively

    clear and secure textual evidence and is therefore well entrenched. But the

    termination date is more flexible. If, for example, the cleruchs did not farm

    their own land but only profited by renting it to locals, then it is not

    unreasonable to expect the farming activities to continue even after the

    cleruchs left for home. In this case, only the start date of the farmsite is

    definitive enough to be telling evidence for or against a cleruchy, and the start

    date matches expectation.

    The data claims, the pottery inventories for example, could also be ques-

    tioned. If the pottery is wrongly described it is likely to be wrongly dated. But

    this is a worry and a potential saving of the hypothesis that will last only as

    long as it takes to have another look and recheck the sherds.

    But the evidential claims, supported as they are by middle-range theorizing,

    are more vulnerable to lingering doubt. The date assessments of the standard

    comparanda pottery could be questioned, though this is unlikely because of

    the widescale upset this would cause in the larger web of beliefs about the

    ancient world. In other words, this would result in more tension rather than

    less. But perhaps the propriety of using Athenian or Corinthian stylistic dating

    in the context of Euboea could be questioned. Perhaps pottery styles change

    across social class as well as through time, and the class of people on the

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    20/22

    182

    Studies in H istory and Phi losophy of Science

    Paximadhi, these cleruchs, used each particular style at a slightly shifted time

    period than did the Athenians. Unfortunately, the most coherent of these

    pictures would have the lower class, displaced cleruchs getting the pottery

    styles

    later

    than the resident Athenians, thereby giving the Palio Pithari pottery

    even later dates and worsening the fit between evidence and hypothesis.

    The fate of the cleruchy hypothesis is still up in the air. The outcome though

    will have a relevance beyond writing the history of southern Euboea. The

    degree of certainty in our understanding of whether or not there is a cleruchy

    near Karystos will influence our understanding of the texts which originally

    motivated the hypothesis. It will add meaning to the figures of the Athenian

    Tribute Lists and assist in interpreting the ancient authors. In this way, a

    dialectic of assistance between textual and material records is established to

    take advantage of the independence of the two sources of information. As

    Leone and Potter suggest each source can be profitably used in the role of

    middle-range theory for the other. It is a back-and-forth sort of negotiation

    between the historical and archaeological claims. Reading the texts will suggest

    an interpretation of the material data (as the reading of Diodorus and Plutarch

    motivated the hypothesis that the Paximadhi sites were part of a cleruchy), and

    in turn the archaeological evidence may influence an interpretation of texts.

    (The dating of the Palio Pithari site makes it less likely that the Euboea

    described in the sending of cleruchs to Andros, Naxos, and Euboea was

    southern Euboea. Or perhaps Diodorus, Plutarch, and Pausanias got the whole

    thing wrong and there were no cleruchs at all.) Thus the theory of Euboean

    cleruchs can participate with middle-range theories in other circumstances. So

    too with the evidential claims discussed in this case, for example the pottery

    catalogue. What is an accomplishment on this project can be a tool on

    another.

    The point in presenting these details of evidence in the test of the cleruchy

    hypothesis is simply to show that in this test-case the middle-range theories,

    the accounting theories, are at work and can be identified and talked about.

    They are the required informational links between the archaeological record,

    the data, and the events and objects of the past which are relevant to the

    hypothesis and are the evidence. They are what you have to know to make the

    connection between what is on the ground and the objects and events of

    interest, that is, those things which make contact with the theory being tested.

    Furthermore the example shows that the middle-range theories are simply

    theoretical accomplishments from other concerns. They endure their own trial

    by evidence and must stand by their own justification.

    5. Summary and Generalizations

    This paper began with some predictions about the nature of archaeological

    and scientific evidence, predictions based on a conceptual argument. Claims

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    21/22

    M iddle-Range Theory in H istori cal Ar chaeology

    183

    about the unobserved require evidence of the unobserved, and this in turn calls

    for connections between the data of observation and these evidential claims

    about phenomena. Claims about these connections are theoretical claims in the

    sense of being descriptive of unobservable events and objects. To account for

    the formation of the observed data, to show what the data mean with respect

    to the hypothesis, requires some mention of what is going on behind the

    scenes. In this sense there must be middle-range theorizing. The prediction is

    that all evidence will be made meaningful and credible with the support of

    middle-range theories.

    This prediction has been put to the test by evidence from historical archaeo-

    logy. The analysis showed that middle-range theories are at work and can be

    articulated. Furthermore, they are not of a special kind of theory. Any theory

    could be used in the role of middle-range and in the examples we have caught

    the theoretical accomplishments of one context in the act of accounting for the

    evidence in another. And finally, these accounting theories are not, as the idea

    of middle-range is sometimes interpreted, of middling generality. Some

    accounting claims are very general, as about physical interactions, while others

    are specific as about a particular detector or a particular ancient author. This

    distinguishes Binfords use, and the use here, of the label middle-range theory

    from alternative applications by, for example, Schaffe34 who means exactly

    theories of mid-generality, regardless of their use.

    The philosophical point in all of this is not to show that archaeology makes

    hypotheses and tests them against the evidence as is the practice in natural

    sciences. The point is rather about the evidence used in this process and, for

    that matter, in any process of acquiring knowledge beyond the manifest. The

    evidence will be influenced by theory and the influencing theories can be

    articulated. And insofar as we can insist on independence between these

    influencing theories and the object theory, the hypothesis, the evidence will be

    objective and the testing will be meaningful. Thus it is not that we rely on only

    the best theories to account for the evidence, if by best is implied some

    dispensation from doubt. We rely on regular old theories, themselves part of

    the web of scientific beliefs. The examples show that beliefs which give

    meaning to the observations are themselves part of the network, and their

    epistemic contribution does not come from some epistemic priority but from

    an epistemic independence.

    Acknowledgements - I

    am

    pleased

    to be able to thank the archaeologists of the

    Southern Euboea Exploration Project, Don Keller, Cynthia Kosso, Roz Schneider and

    See K. Schaffer, Theory Structure in the Biochemical Sciences, The Journal of Medicine and

    Philosophy 5 1980), 57-95.

  • 8/10/2019 Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology

    22/22

    184

    St udies i n Hi story and Phil osophy

    of Science

    Mac Wallace, for their help toward my understanding and enjoying archaeology, and

    for letting me carry the zambilis.

    The conclusions expressed in this paper, such as the status of the cleruchy hypothesis

    in light of the current evidence or the ambiguity of certain evidence, are entirely my own

    and do not necessarily match the views of the archaeologists of the Southern Euboea

    Exploration Project.

    My work has been supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation,

    number DIR-8917989.