24
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Utilitarianism The greatest happiness principle: –Actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, –wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. Or: –Always do whatever will produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number.

Citation preview

Page 1: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Introduction to PhilosophyLecture 16

Ethics #2: Utilitarianism

By David Kelsey

Page 2: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Mill

• John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)• He was the greatest 19th century defender of Utilitarianism.• He was a child prodigy.• Defended women’s suffrage.• His text Utilitarianism was published in 1861.

Page 3: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Utilitarianism

• The greatest happiness principle:– Actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, – wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.

• Or:– Always do whatever will produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number.

Page 4: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Utilitarianism:it’s two parts

• Any version of Utilitarianism (including Mill’s version) is composed of two other views:

– Consequentialism:• We determine whether an act is right or wrong by looking at it’s consequences.

– Hedonism:• This tells us what makes for a better or worse consequence.

• Good: what promotes pleasure• Bad: what promotes pain.

Page 5: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Consequentialism

• Consequentialism: To determine whether or not an action is right: – weigh the good consequences of doing the action against the bad consequences of doing it. – And weigh the good consequences of not doing the action against the bad consequences of not

doing it. – Do whatever will have the best overall consequences.

• Sorting good from bad: Thus, to determine whether or not an action is right:– One must be able to sort the good consequences from the bad consequences.

• Defining the good then the Right: Thus, Consequentialist moral theories, like Utilitarianism, – Define the good, I.e. what they want to promote, then define what is right by simply calculating what

will best promote that good.

Page 6: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Consequentialism

• Other ways to define Consequentialism:– Between two actions, perform the one that has better consequences.

– One determines whether an act is right or wrong by looking solely at it’s consequences.

– The end justifies the means.• The consequences of an action can justify the action itself.• Thus, harming someone could be justified…

Page 7: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Hedonism

• Hedonism says that a good thing is one that adds to the sum total of human happiness.

– Happiness: pleasure and the absence of pain.– Unhappiness: pain and the absence of pleasure.

• Hedonism & Happiness: – What makes something, anything and not just life, good is the amount of happiness it

produces.

• Happiness is the only non-derivative good:– It is the only thing that is good as an end in itself.

• Derivative goods: money, knowledge, fulfilling personal relationships, etc.

Page 8: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Calculating Pleasures

• Jeremy Bentham, who with Mill created the Utilitarian theory, took it upon himself to provide a way to calculate pleasures and pains

– A calculus of pleasures and pains…

– He first lists the various pleasures and pains:• Those of sense, of wealth, of skill, of a good name, of piety, power, happy memories, etc.

– He then highlights the ways in which pleasures and pains can differ:• Intensity: • Duration:• Certainty or uncertainty:• Purity: • Extent:

– So Pleasures and Pains can be quantified.• We have a mathematical formula, a science, of pleasures and pains.

Page 9: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

A Side note:The two forms of

Utilitarianism

• Utilitarianism comes in two forms:– The first is called ‘Act Utilitarianism’:

• The view that you should determine whether any act is morally right by looking at the consequences of that act itself.

– The second is called ‘Rule Utilitarianism’.• The view that you should determine whether any act is morally right by looking at

the consequences of a rule which says that everyone should perform that act in like circumstances.

• You want a rule that would overall best serve to maximize happiness.

Page 10: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Objections toRule Utilitarianism

• Objection to Rule Utilitarianism: it collapses into act utilitarianism.– This is because no matter what the rule, there will be some circumstances in which it

is beneficial to break the rule, which means the rule would have to be modified to make an exception for those circumstances.

– But deciding whether a rule should be modified is tantamount to just being an act utilitarian…

Page 11: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Mill’s argument for Hedonism

• The non-derivative good is what people want non-derivatively:– Mill thinks that a non-derivatively good thing must be what all people want for itself, as

an end, not as a means to something else.

• But, Mill says, the production of pleasure and the absence of pain is what everyone wants for itself.

• His evidence for this: look around!!!– What people do desire is just the production of pleasure and the absence of pain.

Page 12: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

The form of Mill’s argument

• The form of Mill’s argument:– 1. A non-derivatively good thing is one that people want for itself.– 2. Happiness is the only thing that people want for itself.– 3. Thus, happiness is the only non-derivative good.

• Is this argument sound?– Premise 1:

– Premise 2?

– What about the move to the conclusion?

Page 13: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Objection to Hedonism:the life of the beasts

• Some people object that hedonism is degrading.– It makes the best life the ‘life of the beasts’.– If a pig can live a life completely satisfied, while a morally concerned and

thoughtful man like Socrates cannot ever be so satisfied, isn’t the life of the pig preferable?

• Mills reply:– Human beings have faculties more elevated than the animal appetites, and

when once made conscious of them, do not regard anything as happiness which does not include their gratification.

Page 14: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Mill’s reply

• The form of Mill’s reply:– 1-There are higher and lower pleasures.– 2-Any amount of higher pleasure is preferable to any amount of lower

pleasure.• His evidence: anyone who has experienced higher pleasures would prefer them,

on reflection, to lower pleasures.• Higher pleasures:

– any use of the mind including reflection or thought, • Lower pleasures:

– All pleasures not as a result of using the mind.

– 3-Since the life of the beast produces only lower pleasures, the life of the beast isn’t the best life at all.

– Questions

Page 15: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

The life of virtue

• Objection: wouldn’t you rather be virtuous than happy.– Selling out:

• Often we have the opportunity to ‘sell out’, to get something that will make us happy at the cost of doing bad.

• Many people would rather not do that.

• Mill’s reply:– The life of virtue is an important part of being happy.

• You wouldn’t really be happy if you sold out.

Page 16: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Who counts?

• Objection: it is difficult to determine just who we include in our calculation of utility?– Do we include all person’s whose interest may be affected?– Only those in our own state? Our own community? Our own family?

• What about non-human sentient beings? Should their pleasure or pain count?– Singer:

• argues that since animals can feel pleasure and pain just like humans, their interests must be taken into account when calculating the overall good an action produces.

• So it is morally wrong to eat animals, to experiment on them, or to imprison them in zoos.

• What about future generations?– Should we consider the interests of future persons?– Should we consider the environment?

Page 17: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Quantifying happiness?

• To determine how much pleasure vs. pain an act produces:– one must consider whether an act will lead to greater pleasure than pain – one must also consider the intensity of that pleasure (and the intensity of that pain).

• But it is extremely difficult to calculate the intensity of pleasure and pain.– Could you assign numeric values to your pleasures and pains? – Could you assign numeric values to your pleasures and pains vs. mine, or higher vs.

lower pleasure and pains.

• Mill’s reply:– Estimation is sufficient…

Page 18: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Calculation is based onmere prediction

• Isn’t it just impossible to weigh out the pleasure and pain that result from an action.

– Consider:• How can we even predict all of the consequences of our actions? • And how do we predict the pleasure and pain that will result from the

consequences of our actions?

• A plausible response:– We are only trying to maximize probable utility.

Page 19: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Demanding-ness

• Utilitarianism really asks us to leave our lives to go cure world hunger:– If everyone’s happiness is of equal value to our own, then it will be hard to justify doing

anything other than working to alleviate world hunger.• Justifying a steak dinner?

• The response:– We know what will produce our own happiness better than what will produce

happiness in other people.

• Counter-response:– Basic necessities…

Page 20: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Utilitarianism ignoresthe distinctness of person’s

• Utilitarianism could justify inflicting pain in some if others are afforded pleasure:

– Slavery example: • a utilitarian would have to weigh the suffering of those who would be slaves

against the benefits accruing to those who would be slave owners.

• Making the trade off:– It may be possible for a single individual to make this trade-off

• One could weigh the pain of having a tooth pulled against the benefit of getting rid of the toothache,

– But can you really justify inflicting pain on one person by pointing to the increased

pleasure this will bring to others?

Page 21: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

What about promises?

• Utilitarianism does not give sufficient weight to past acts:– Utilitarianism is forward looking

• Past events have relevance only to the extent that they affect future consequences.

– For the Utilitarian, the fact that I have promised to do something is not in itself a reason for doing it.

• As a Utilitarian, I will keep my promise only if keeping it will have the best consequences…

Page 22: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

Promises once again

• The Utilitarian will often talk of justifying keeping a promise because of the negative consequences brought if it is broken:

– I make it less likely that people will rely on my promises in the future– Undermining the institution of promise keeping

• But don’t we keep our promises for reasons other than that doing so produces pleasure?

• Isn’t there something valuable about keeping a promise in and of itself?

Page 23: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

What about Rights?

• For a Utilitarian there aren’t any absolute prohibitions– For anything can be justified if it produces the best consequences.– Thus, there are no absolute rights either.

• But aren’t there absolute rights?– These are rights that cannot be violated under any circumstances.

• The reply: – It would almost always maximize happiness to respect rights against such conduct.

• The counter:– But this still allows for individual violations of such rights…

Page 24: Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey

The fatal flaw of Utilitarianism

• The problem with Utilitarianism: – a Utilitarian would tell you to kill an innocent if it meant the production of more

pleasure than pain.

• The real problem: the Utilitarian puts the good before the right– Utilitarians first decide what is good and then decide what is right by looking at what

will produce the greatest amount of good.– As long as you do this, critics argue, no act is always morally wrong…

• Put the right before the good: – Some critics argue this is the only way to solve this problem…