[Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenomenology World-Wide Emmanuel Levinas- The Ethics of ВЂњFace to Face”The

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    1/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS:

    THE

    ETHICS

    OF

    "FACE

    TO

    FACE"(fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    409

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Primary Sources

    Ortega y Gasset, J. "Apuntes sobre el pensamiento, su teurgia y

    su demiurgia", in his Obras Completas, Vol. V.

    Ortega y Gas set, J. "Historia como sistema", Obras Completas,

    Vol. VI.

    Ortega y Gasset, J. "La idea de principia en Leibniz ... ", Obras

    Completas, Vol. VIII.

    Ortega y Gasset, J. Obras Completas. Madrid: Revista de

    Occidente.

    Ortega y Gasset, J. "Pro ogo para alemanes", Obras Completas,

    Vol. VIII.

    Ortega y Gas set,

    J.

    ~ Q u e es el conocimiento?, Madrid: Revista

    de Occidente/Alianza, 1984.

    Ortega y Gasset, J.

    ~ Q u e

    es filosoffa?", Obras Completas,

    Vol. VII.

    Ortega y Gasset,

    J.

    "Sobre el concepto de sensaci6n", Obras

    Completas, Vol.

    I.

    Zubiri,

    X.

    El Sol, March

    8,

    1936.

    Zubiri,

    X.

    Ensayo de una teona fenomenoldgica del juicio.

    Madrid: 1923, p.

    8.

    Zubiri,

    X.

    Inteligencia sentiente, Madrid: Alianza, 1980.

    Zubiri,

    X.

    Sobre Ia esencia. Madrid: Sociedad de Estudios y

    Publicaciones, 1972

    (4a

    ed.).

    Zubiri, X. Inteligencia y razon. Madrid: Alianza, 1983.

    Secondary Literature

    Benavides, M. De la ameba al monstruo propicio. Madrid:

    UNAM, 1988.

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF

    FACE TO FACE /THE RELIGIOUS TURN

    INTRODUCTION

    In

    the preface

    to

    The Phenomenological Movement: A

    Historical Introduction,

    Herbert Spiegelberg acknowl

    edges

    that the main

    innovation

    of the

    third edition to

    his

    work is the inclusion

    of

    a new chapter on

    Emmanuel

    Levinas. Spiegelberg

    states:

    Previously Levinas had been mentioned only in his

    historical role as one of the early links between French

    and German

    phenomenology and as a co-translator of

    Husserl's Cartesian Meditations into French. Only a brief

    note in the Supplement had hinted at his independent

    philosophical development. Now his academic rise and an

    additional major work have made it clear that his thought

    and especially his original type of phenomenology call for

    fuller treatment. (xliii)

    Cerezo, P. La voluntad de aventura. Barcelona: Ariel, 1984.

    Conill,

    J.

    El crepusculo de la metafzsica. Barcelona: Anthropos,

    1988.

    Conill,

    J

    El enigma del animal fantdstico. Madrid: Tecnos,

    1991.

    Conill,

    J.

    El poder de la mentira. Nietzsche y Ia pol{tica de

    la

    transvaloracion. Madrid: Tecnos, 1997.

    Fowler, Th. B. "Introduction to the Philosophy of X. Zubiri",

    The X. Zubiri Review

    1(1998), pp. 5-16.

    Garragorri, Paulino. "Nota preliminar" in

    J.

    Ortega y Gasset,

    Investigaciones psicoldgicas, Madrid: 1979.

    Gracia, D. Voluntad de verdad. Barcelona: Labor, 1986.

    Marias, J. Ortega. Circunstancia y vocaci6n. Madrid: Revista de

    Occidente, 1973.

    Orringer, N. Ortega y sus fuentes germdnicas. Madrid: Gredos,

    1979.

    Pintor,

    A.

    "El magisterio intelectual de Ortega y

    Ia

    filosoffa de

    Zubiri", Cuadernos salmantinos de filosofza 0 (1983), 55-78;

    Pintor, A. "Zubiri y Ia fenomenologfa", Realitas III-IV (1979),

    389-565.

    Pintor,

    A.

    "La 'maduraci6n' de Zubiri y

    Ia

    fenomenologfa",

    Naturaleza y Gracia XXVI/2-3 (1979), 299-353.

    Pintor,

    A.

    Realidad y verdad. Salamanca: Universidad Pontifica,

    1994.

    Regalado,

    A.

    El laberinto de Ia razon: Ortega y Heidegger.

    Madrid: Alianza, 1990.

    San Martin,

    J.

    (ed.). Ortega y

    la

    Fenomenologza. Madrid:

    UNED, 1992.

    Spiegelberg, H. The Phenomenological Movement. A Historical

    Introduction. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1969 (2. ed.).

    Levinas' rise

    to a position of eminence within the

    international philosophical world has been further con

    firmed

    since Spiegelberg

    wrote

    these

    words in 1982.

    The

    place Levinas now occupies within the history

    of

    the phe

    nomenological

    movement

    is

    unquestionably

    one of the

    highest importance. In his Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas,

    Jacques Derrida accurately gives us a sense

    of

    the enor

    mity

    ofLevinas's

    a?uvre: It is so large that one no longer

    glimpse

    its

    edges One can predict with confidence that

    centuries

    of

    readers

    will

    set

    this as their task"

    (3-4). One

    of

    the

    most

    lucid and coherent expositions

    of

    Levinas'

    thought can be found in Stephan

    Strasser's

    essay

    "Emmanuel

    Levinas:

    Phenomenological Philosophy,"

    excerpted and translated by Spiegelberg,

    and included in

    the

    third edition. However, Levinas continued to write

    and

    publish important

    work in

    the

    decade

    postdating the

    Spiegelberg

    volume.

    Although

    at

    times the reader will

    notice some factual corrections, the present essay is

    not

    an

    A. A. Bello et al., Phenomenology World-Wide

    Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2002

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    2/22

    410 EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE" THE RELIGIOUS TURN

    attempt to improve upon Strasser's piece, but rather to

    include material that postdates his publication and to offer

    an alternative reading

    of

    Levinas based in part upon his

    later writings. The more recent material published by and

    about Levinas indicates more clearly the way in which

    Levinas understood his own philosophical itinerary.

    Additionally, since the time

    of

    Strasser's publication,

    Levinas, through a series

    of

    interviews, revealed some

    of the elements of his biography that bear upon his phi

    losophy, and therefore are also included here. While his

    specifically Jewish writings are not considered as a

    separate subject, the path that he so often describes as

    "otherwise than Greek," including the relevance

    of

    his

    reflections on the Talmud for his ethics are here introduced.

    The originality

    of

    Levinas' s thinking, his use

    of

    language, and the richness

    of

    his phenomenological

    descriptions do not easily yield a summary of his research.

    Given the enormity

    of

    his philosophical task, his work has

    already been subjected to a variety

    of

    interpretations,

    responses, and applications. As Levinas' s thought con

    tinues to be recognized as one that challenges every stu

    dent

    of

    phenomenology, the secondary literature has

    grown exponentially in the past two decades. A selective

    bibliography of primary and secondary sources can be

    found appended to this article. A glossary

    of

    some

    of

    the

    key terms introduced by Levinas is also included.

    BIOGRAPHY

    The life of Emmanuel Levinas was affected and shaped

    by some of the epochal events of the twentieth century.

    His own thinking may be viewed in part as a response to

    the crises and catastrophes that produced so much suf

    fering in the world around him. Regarding his own phi

    losophic biography Levinas writes a single statement that

    is to remain permanently associated with his life and

    work:

    It

    is dominated by the presentiment and the

    memory of the Nazi horror" ("Signature" 291).

    Levinas was born in Kovno, Lithuania, on January 12th

    1906. Kovno had for centuries been recognized as one

    of

    the main centers

    of

    Talmudic scholarship, and Levinas's

    childhood was dominated by a traditional Jewish atmos

    phere that was itself a way of life. His father, Yechiel,

    owned a bookshop, and Levinas's relation to books was

    first nourished here. He learned to read the Jewish Bible

    in the Hebrew language in which he was tutored.

    Reflecting back on the Judaism of his childhood, Levinas

    describes it in the following way: "the spiritual

    essence

    and this remains a quite 'Lithuanian

    Judaism'-rested

    for

    me not in mystical modes but in a tremendous curiosity

    for books"

    (Elevations

    116).

    Levinas's family was forced to leave Lithuania in

    1915, along with the other Jews

    of

    the Kovno district, as a

    result

    of

    an edict from the Czarist government. The fol

    lowing year, the family settled in Karkhov, Ukraine,

    where Levinas attended public high school.

    It

    was from

    this distance that Levinas witnessed the disintegration

    of

    the Czarist regime and the beginning of the Soviet

    Revolution. In the aftermath

    of

    the Revolution, civil war

    ensued, accompanied by outbreaks of anti-Semitism that

    engulfed the Ukraine. These orchestrated pogroms, led by

    the Ukrainian nationalist Semeon Petlura, resulted in the

    murder

    of

    over 100,000 Jews. While the Levinas family

    survived this upheaval, they chose to return in 1920 to the

    familiarity and comparative safety of Lithuania.

    Levinas remained in Kovno for the next three years

    where he enrolled as a student in a Jewish Russian

    Language Gymnasium.

    It

    was during this time that he

    developed an abiding love for the Russian classics, from

    Pushkin to Dostoyevsky and Tolstoy, and also "the great

    writers

    of

    Western Europe, notably Shakespeare" whose

    descriptions of human existence prepared him for his

    encounter with philosophy

    (Ethics and Infinity

    22). These

    initial pre-philosophical experiences he would subse

    quently regard as a first contact with "the meaning of the

    human" (ibid). In 1923, Levinas left Kovno and enrolled

    at the University

    of

    Strasbourg. It was at this time that he

    absorbed the French language as his own, while also

    devoting himself to the study of German and Latin.

    During the same period, he met and was befriended by

    Maurice Blanc hot, who later emerged as one

    of

    France's

    eminent literary critics. Blanchot would remain a life

    long source

    of

    intellectual inspiration for Levinas, and

    Levinas in turn would leave his mark upon the writings

    of

    Blanchot.

    Levinas first became interested in Husserl's phenom

    enology in 1927. He traveled to the University of Freiburg

    for the academic year 1928-29, where he studied with

    Husserl, who was teaching his last public course, and with

    Heidegger, who was teaching his first courses at Freiburg,

    and "who was then the leading light in German phe

    nomenology and philosophy"

    (Face to Face with Levinas

    14). In 1929, Heidegger singled out Levinas to serve as

    his second in his famous debate at Davos with Ernst

    Cassirer, the eminent Kant scholar. At that time,

    as

    Levinas later remarked, "My admiration for Heidegger is

    above all an admiration for

    Sein und Zeit.

    I always try to

    relive the ambience

    of

    those readings when 1933 was still

    unthinkable"

    (Ethics and Infinity

    33). While Levinas

    would always retain his admiration for Heidegger as the

    author

    of Being and Time,

    he would later regret the

    assistance which he had given him in light

    of

    Heidegger's

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    3/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{I'HE RELIGIOUS TURN 411

    subsequent political

    act1v1ty.

    Heidegger' s involvement

    with the Nazi regime would force Levinas to reformulate

    the foundational importance

    of

    ethics to philosophy.

    In 1930, Levinas published his prizewinning doctoral

    dissertation:

    The Theory

    of

    Intuition in Husser ' s Phe

    nomenology.

    During this time, he married Raissa Levy, a

    childhood friend. He became a naturalized citizen of

    France and received a position in the French army.

    Throughout most

    of

    the 1930s, Levinas worked as a

    teacher and administrator at the Alliance Israelite

    Universelle, a French-Jewish organization dedicated to

    the education

    of

    Jews in countries under the influence

    of

    France, especially in North Africa.

    Levinas served in the French army as a translator

    of

    German and Russian. With the help

    of

    Maurice Blanchot,

    Levinas s wife and daughter escaped from Paris to

    Orleans, where they were given refuge in a monastery.

    Levinas's entire family

    of

    origin, including his mother, his

    father, and his brothers, were murdered by the Nazis and

    their collaborators in Lithuania. Levinas himself was

    captured and transported to a prisoner-of-war camp for

    French Jewish soldiers near Hanover, Germany, where he

    performed forced labor. In

    Difficult Freedom,

    Levinas

    comments on his incarceration, and acknowledges that the

    French uniform protected him and the seventy in his unit

    of

    Jewish prisoners-of-war from Hitlerian extermination.

    He recalls that "the other men, called free, who had

    dealings with us or gave us work or orders or even a

    smile-and the children and women who passed by and

    sometimes raised their eyes stripped us of our human

    skin." The only creature who recognized the prisoners as

    human beings was a dog. Levinas explains: "He would

    appear at morning assembly and was waiting for us upon

    return jumping

    up

    and down and barking with

    delight . . . For him, there was no doubt that we were

    men . . . This dog was the last Kantian in Nazi Germany,

    without the brain needed to universalize maxims and

    drives" (152-53). Levinas' subsequent philosophical

    reflections on the Holocaust are born

    of

    these searing

    personal experiences and observations.

    After his liberation, Levinas produced three important

    works in quick succession:

    Existence and Existents,

    begun

    in the stalag; Time and the Other; and Discovering Exis

    tence with Husser and Heidegger.

    These works represent

    the emergence

    of

    Levinas' s own philosophic path. In the

    late 1940s Levinas began to immerse himself in the study

    of

    the Talmudic texts in the presence

    of

    a master teacher,

    Mordechai Shoushani. This period marks the beginning of

    Levinas' philosophic recovery

    of

    the Hebraic tradition,

    and the alternative approach to philosophy that he would

    later inscribe in the phrase "Otherwise than Greek."

    Levinas is not indifferent to the rich phenomenological

    content

    of

    the Talmudic tradition which permitted him

    over the course

    of

    the next many years to reflect on a

    variety of subjects such as hunger and nourishment,

    injustice and forgiveness, suffering and

    redemption

    subjects too often submerged in the history

    of

    philosophy.

    However, Levinas tended to keep his philosophical and

    Talmudic reflections quite separate, at least in an overt

    sense, until after he had established himself as a philos

    opher of the first order through the publication

    of

    Totality

    and Infinity

    and

    Otherwise Than Being: Beyond Essence.

    In 1951, Levinas authored the important article "Is

    Ontology Fundamental?" representing his clearest break

    with Heidegger as a philosopher. In 1961 he received his

    first academic appointment at the University

    of

    Poitiers,

    followed in 1967 by a position at Nan erre, a branch

    of

    the

    University of Paris. In 1974, Levinas published Otherwise

    than Being

    which represents a radicalizing

    of

    his phe

    nomenological work and ensured the international repu

    tation that

    Totality and Infinity

    had already established.

    His teaching career culminated in a position as Professor

    of

    Philosophy at the Sorbonne in 1973, where he con

    tinued to teach and remained a Professor Emeritus until

    1979. In 1986, Levinas published Of God Who Comes to

    Mind,

    a work that would serve to provide a new model for

    the relation

    of

    philosophy to theology. In each of these

    works, Levinas continued to propel the human subject

    toward that which is beyond or outside

    of

    himself. By this

    time, Levinas had demonstrated that there is a third

    alternative between absolutism and the humanism

    of

    the

    enlightenment, a theism that is also a radical humanism:

    the humanism

    of

    the Other. During the last years

    of

    his

    life Levinas taught at the lnstitut Catholique in Paris.

    Levinas' s philosophic writings span over sixty years.

    The originality and rigor

    of

    his thinking secured for

    Levinas a position

    of

    eminence in Europe and continue

    gain him ever greater recognition throughout the philo

    sophic world. Levinas continued to write both new and

    important philosophic texts in the last years

    of

    his life. In

    addition, he produced a series

    of

    commentaries on the

    Talmud and the status of morality, especially in light of

    the Holocaust, and opened up new horizons for phe

    nomenological inquiry. Emmanuel Levinas died in Paris

    on the 25th

    of

    December 1995.

    EXPLORATIONS IN PHENOMENOLOGY

    When considering his philosophical influences, Levinas

    singles out the great masters Plato, Descartes, and Kant,

    and the twentieth-century luminaries Bergson, Husserl,

    and Heidegger. The philosophy of Henri Bergson made a

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    4/22

    412

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    strong impression on Levinas. In Face

    to

    Face with

    Levinas, he observes: "In 1925, in Strasbourg University,

    Bergson was being hailed as France's leading thinker."

    Levinas credits Bergson's theory of concrete duration (la

    duree concrete,

    as a contribution to philosophy of lasting

    importance. Levinas adds: "Indeed, it was this Bergsonian

    emphasis on temporality that prepared the soil for the

    subsequent implantation of Heideggerian phenomenology

    into France" (13).

    In Discovering Existence with Husser , Levinas gives a

    clear indication

    of

    the importance that he attributes to the

    work of Edmund Husserl. He refers to Husserl as the

    creator of phenomenology and then describes its project:

    Phenomenology means the science of phenomena.

    All

    things given, shown or revealed

    to

    our gaze are

    phenomena. But then

    is

    everything a phenomenon

    and every science a phenomenology? Not at

    all.

    What

    is given

    to

    consciousness only deserves the name

    phenomenon if one grasps it through the role it plays

    and the function it exercises in the individual and

    affective life of which it is the object.

    (33)

    Levinas makes it a point to place the philosophical

    revolution affected by Husserlian phenomenology in a

    historical perspective:

    [phenomenology] reverses the scientific attitude.

    Newton's physics precisely turns away from the subject

    for the greater glory of the object.

    t

    decrees the

    expulsion of every so-called subjective element from

    the object. For example, it

    wipes

    out from space every

    subjective heresy: "top" and "bottom: "righC and

    "left: far and "near Thus purified, objective space

    and the objective world

    see

    no limits to their ever-purer

    objectivity. (33)

    Here Levinas recognizes the existential importance of

    the attempt by phenomenology to recover the meaning of

    spatiality from its purified and overly reduced objectivism

    where there would be neither a sense of direction or dis

    tance or placement recognizable by and for the human

    subject.

    The immediate effect

    of

    the first phase

    of

    Levinas'

    encounter with phenomenology in the early 1930s

    resulted in the publication of translations and texts that

    made Levinas the recognized authority in France on the

    subject of phenomenology. These efforts include a col

    laborative translation

    of

    Husserl's

    Cartesian Meditations

    and The Theory of Intuition in Husser ' s Phenomenology,

    the first systematic examination

    of

    Husserl's thought in

    French. This latter work also served as Levinas' s doctoral

    dissertation. Levinas had already published a serious

    study

    of

    Heidegger in

    La Revue Philosophique

    in 1932,

    and it is clear that he was preparing to write a book-length

    study following Heidegger's adaptation

    of Husserl's phi

    losophy. However, this project was put to the side with

    Hitler' advent to power in 1933.

    While Levinas continued to publ ish articles on Husserl

    and Heidegger in the 1930s, he also authored "Some

    Reflections on the Philosophy of Hitlerism" in 1934.

    Levinas had already begun to rethink his relation to

    Heidegger, the philosopher whom one could not bypass in

    the twentieth century if one were to aspire to do serious

    work after the publication of

    Being and Time.

    In

    Ethics

    and Infinity, Levinas describes Heidegger's analysis in

    Being in Time of "anxiety, care and being-toward

    death... as a sovereign exercise of phenomenology"

    (39). For Levinas, Heidegger's methodological contribu

    tion consisted in

    verbalizing

    existence: "It aims at

    describing man's being or existing, not his nature." In this

    respect Levinas indicates that Heidegger expresses ele

    ments

    of

    a philosophical anthropology that awakens

    and delineates the awareness of the patterns of human

    existence.

    However convincing and brilliant Heidegger's analy

    sis, Levinas, by steps almost imperceptible in the early

    stages

    of

    his work in the thirties and forties, emerges as

    Heidegger's most serious philosophic critic. Levinas' own

    original thinking offers a radical alternative to Hei

    degger's ontology of power. The project of fundamental

    ontology becomes in Heidegger the consummate expres

    sion of

    a will-to-power unbounded by the other person's

    claims. Subsequently, with the 1951 publication of "Is

    Ontology Fundamental?" Levinas provides the first ser

    ious critique of Heidegger's insistence that ultimate or

    "first philosophy" is necessarily and inescapably ontol

    ogy. Here Levinas introduces a metaphysical critique

    of

    ontology which yields the ethical relation to the Other as

    irreducible and hence

    of

    unsurpassable importance. He

    elevates discourse to a place of special significance. And

    he criticizes the Hegelian notion

    of

    negation whose

    existential expression reveals itself

    as

    murder.

    Against Heidegger, Levinas argues that one's fear for

    the other, for his death and therefore his life, takes pre

    cedence even over concerns for one's own ultimate pos

    sibilities. Surely there is an undeniable interweaving

    of

    Levinas' thinking with his life and the climate under

    which his philosophy was nourished. Life is no longer to

    be modeled after an existential autobiography in which

    others merely make their appearances and recede. As

    Levinas writes in "Signature:"

    The fundamental experience which objective experi

    ence

    itself presupposes

    is

    the experience of the Other.

    It

    is experience par excellence. . . the disproportion

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    5/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"(fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    413

    between the Other

    and the

    self

    is

    precisely moral

    con-

    sciousness. Moral consciousness

    is

    not an experience of

    values but an access

    to

    external being: external being

    is

    par

    excellence,

    the Other. Moral consciousness is thus not

    a modality of psychological consciousness, but its

    condition.

    (293)

    For Levinas, the humanism

    of

    the other person is a

    precondition for the possibility of philosophy, which in

    tum forms a precondition for theory, and the responsi

    bility that grounds consciousness.

    LEVINAS' S PHILOSOPHICAL ITINERARY

    In the preface to Existence and Existents, Levinas notes:

    These studies begun before the war were continued and

    written down for the most part

    in

    captivity. The stalag

    is evoked here not

    as

    a guarantee of profundity nor

    as

    a claim to indulgence, but as an explanation for the

    absence of any consideration of those philosophical

    works published, with

    so

    much impact, between

    1940

    and

    1945. (15)

    In these revealing remarks, Levinas, in a sharp and

    pointed manner, indicates that he will be charting his own

    philosophic course. Muting his own personal reservations,

    here, about the role

    of

    Heidegger' s collaboration with the

    Nazis, Levinas is clearly announcing his own future

    philosophical itinerary, while at the same time expressing

    his recognition of the changing conditions under which

    philosophy must begin to think anew. As if

    to drive home

    this point, Levinas states:

    f

    in the beginning our considerations

    as

    far

    as

    the

    concept of ontology and the relation of man to Being

    are concerned are inspired in a high measure by Martin

    Heidegger's philosophy, they are [nevertheless] domi

    nated

    by

    the deeply felt need to relinquish the climate

    of this philosophy.

    (91)

    For Levinas, Heidegger's nihilism is situated ontically,

    between the insensibility toward the death of the Other

    and the totalitarian egocentrism inscribed in the arbi

    trariness

    of

    the resoluteness

    of

    the will. The future

    of

    phenomenology in part depends on the critique

    of

    Hei

    degger's presentation. The philosophic path which Levi

    nas takes from the time of

    the destruction

    of

    European

    Jewry focuses on a critique, and at times an enlightenment

    of the entire Western spiritual tradition.

    Preparing the reader for his work in Time and the

    Other, Levinas indicates the larger context within which

    his original reflection moves by first situating his phe

    nomenological exploration within the history of philoso

    phy: "Traditional philosophy, and Bergson and Heidegger

    too, remained with the conception of a time either taken to

    be purely exterior to the subject, a time-object, or taken to

    be entirely contained in the subject" (90). The path that

    Levinas is about to chart will diverge not only from

    Heidegger, but also from Greek philosophy:

    Classical philosophy left aside the freedom which

    consists not in negating oneself, but in having one's

    being pardoned by the very alterity of the other. It

    underestimated the alterity

    of

    the other in dialogue

    where the other frees us, because it

    is

    believed there

    existed a silent dialogue of the soul with itself. In the

    end the problem of time

    is

    subordinate to the task of

    bringing out the specific terms with which the dialogue

    has to

    be

    conceived.

    (90)

    In order to bring out these specific terms, Levinas

    introduces the phenomenon

    of

    the il

    y a.

    The il

    y

    a, or

    "there is," is an endless sequence

    of

    instants without

    direction, purpose or claiming power. The il

    y

    a is

    described as the consciousness of horror, the depersonal

    ization

    of

    the subject, and the experience

    of

    an inability to

    escape from existence. f there were no relation between

    the self and the other, the "the re is" would be completely

    senseless. However, from the relation between the self

    and the other arises the possibility of meaning, justice and

    goodness. In Existence and Existents, Levinas begins to

    explore a way

    of

    escaping the il

    y

    a through a description

    of time and alterity. He asks:

    How indeed could time arise in a solitary subject

    . . .

    if

    time is constituted by my relation to the other, it

    is

    exterior to my instinct, but is also something else than

    an object given to contemplation. The dialectic of time

    is the very dialectic of the relationship of the other,

    that

    is,

    a dialogue which in turn has to be studied in

    terms other than those of the dialectic of the solitary

    subject.

    (93)

    For Levinas, the diachronic nature of time makes time

    and alterity virtually synonymous. Here, the notion

    of

    a

    time that is not one, or "diachrony" emerges. In Time and

    the Other, Levinas states that "time is not the achievement

    of an isolated and lone subject, but that it is the very

    relation

    of

    the subject with the other"

    (39).

    In this text,

    Levinas lays claim to the originality

    of

    his presentation in

    a critique which reaches all the way back to Parmenides

    and Plato, and whose themes will dominate, in various

    ways, much of the rest

    of

    his philosophical writings:

    "There is a multiplicity and a transcendence in this verb

    'to exist,' a transcendence that is lacking in even the

    boldest, existential analysis" (91). Anticipating the more

    metaphysical grounding

    of

    these concrete descriptions in

    Totality and Infinity, Levinas emphasizes that "existing

    itself becomes double. The Eleatic notion

    of

    being

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    6/22

    414

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{THE RELIGIOUS TURN

    dominates Plato's philosophy, "where multiplicity was

    subordinated to the one, and where the role of the femi

    nine was thought within the categories

    of

    passivity and

    activity and was reduced to matter" (92-93). As part of

    his inquiry into the transcendence

    of

    being, Levinas refers

    the reader to the concrete situations

    of

    death, sexuality,

    paternity, femininity, and fecundity. He reminds the

    reader that the phenomenon

    of

    fecundity has not pre

    viously been treated in a philosophical manner, and that

    this omission leaves out one

    of

    the irreducible phenomena

    of

    human existence: "The fecundity

    of

    the ego must be

    appreciated at its correct ontological value, which until

    now has never been done." Levinas presents paternity,

    fecundity, femininity, and love as generative patterns of

    human existence that are open to phenomenological

    investigation. For example, the child is a paradox that

    formal logic cannot explain. The child both is and is not

    a continuation of the parent. In this respect the child repre

    sents an irreducible existent not completely reducible to

    genetics or biology with an identity to claim as its own.

    Just as Levinas raises birth to a philosophic category,

    so

    too does he register the death

    of

    the other as being

    phenomenologically irreducible. In this respect he challen

    ges Heidegger's understanding

    of

    human finitude and his

    notion that authenticity does not permit us to register the

    deaths of others as something outside of our own projects.

    In fact, for Levinas, the death

    of

    the other, and therefore

    the life

    of

    the other can take precedence over the possi

    bility of one's own death and at times one's own life?

    Totality and Infinity

    The publication

    of

    Totality and Infinity: An Essay on

    Exteriority in 1961 provided a vital new direction for

    phenomenology. Totality and Infinity represents the cul

    mination of Levinas' s independent philosophical positions

    and delineates his rethinking

    of

    the relation of time and

    alterity, ethics and ontology, self and other, justice and

    freedom. Levinas became the first phenomenological

    philosopher to offer a distinctly alternative approach to

    a field whose underpinnings remained dependent on

    Heidegger's fundamental ontology. Some

    of

    these origi

    nal departures are noted in John Wild 's Introduction to the

    English edition of Totality and Infinity. In Totality and

    Infinity, Levinas embarks upon what Wild characterizes

    as a "phenomenology of the other" (13). In so doing,

    Levinas, while building on the work

    of

    Husserl, recog

    nizes and responds to the egocentrism with which phe

    nomenology had been charged. He reaffirms the priority

    of

    the existent over existence. For Levinas, it is the Other

    as

    existent who now occupies a position of primacy.

    In this sense, Levinas could be interpreted as elevating the

    "ontic" over the ontological.

    I t

    is in the elaboration

    of

    the ethical character

    of

    Levinas' metaphysics that Totality and Infinity marks a

    new chapter in the history

    of

    the phenomenological

    movement. While Sartre and Merleau-Ponty had each

    contributed valuable and creative descriptions

    of

    human

    existence, metaphysics, as envisioned by Levinas, takes a

    position beyond and outside

    of

    Being.

    It

    begins with a

    relation to the Infinite that cannot be reabsorbed into

    Being. For Levinas, metaphysics arises and is maintained

    in desire, a desire that cannot be reduced to need. Need

    belongs within a system of ontological reference, where

    each being is the bearer

    of

    meaning. The preface to Tot

    ality and Infinity shows Levinas linking his metaphysical

    undertaking to the phenomenon of morality, describing

    its conditions for appearing, and attaching existential

    importance to the subject: "Everyone will readily agree

    that it is

    of

    the highest importance to know whether or not

    we are duped by morality" (21). Levinas appears to be

    asking whether or not morality is irreducible, despite war,

    which vitiates its application; despite commerce, in which

    subjects become commodities; or despite administration

    that would subsume all subjects, in advance, as objects or

    data exhausted in their quantification. An irreducible

    phenomenon

    of

    morality would mean that morality cannot

    be reduced to politics, or human beings reduced to bearers

    of historical meaning or sociological function. The other

    cannot be reducible to the self, nor can infinity be

    encapsulated within totality. Establishing this position is

    the work that Levinas undertakes in Totality and Infinity.

    Levinas begins his phenomenological investigation

    with an exposition and critique

    of

    totality, while posi

    tioning the sameness that dominates totality in relation to

    the otherness that derives from infinity. These formal

    categories

    of

    metaphysics, with their roots in the thought

    of Plato and Aristotle, are immediately endowed by

    Levinas with a concrete sense

    of

    urgency and existential

    importance. Levinas argues that an ontology of power is

    subsumed under totality:

    t

    establishes an order from which no one can keep his

    distance; nothing henceforth

    is

    exterior. War does not

    manifest exteriority and the other as other; it destroys

    the identity of the same. The visage of being that shows

    itself in war is fixed in the concept

    of

    totality, which

    dominates Western philosophy. (21)

    Levinas argues and affirms an alternative version of

    philosophy in which reason cannot be employed on behalf

    of injustice. He presents significant variations on the

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    7/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{rHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    415

    ontology presented by Heidegger in

    Being and Time

    and

    positions his thinking outside Heidegger's ontological

    paradigm altogether.

    The break with ontology makes it possible for Levinas

    to investigate a variety of phenomena in a new way.

    Levinas takes pains to describe phenomena such as the

    home, the face, and the welcome that have for the most

    part been previously overlooked. He also argues against

    Heidegger that such phenomena are not reducible to tools

    or implements, nor are they describable only within the

    realm

    of

    projects for the self. These new phenomen

    ological categories are essential to Levinas s critique

    of

    Heidegger and to his endeavor to situate ethics as first

    philosophy.

    The home, as described by Levinas, makes it possible

    for interior life to go on. "The privileged role

    of

    the home

    does not consist in being the end of human activity but in

    being its condition, and in this sense its commencement.

    The recollection necessary for nature to be able to be

    represented and worked over, for it to first take form as a

    world, is accomplished

    as

    the home" (152). The home

    appears to enjoy an irreducible ontological status for

    Levinas. The home does more than shelter the self from

    the elements.

    It

    secures for the separated self a sense

    of

    stability, and interiority, where one can recover one's

    sense

    of

    personal identity interrupted by sojourns through

    the world.

    The human face plays a central part in Levinas'

    depiction

    of

    ethics. He shows how the face is connected to

    ethics, reason, discourse, signification, and objectivity.

    Levinas's contribution to raising the phenomenon

    of

    the

    face to a philosophical category has both epistemic and

    ethical dimensions. Epistemically, it is impossible for

    one person to speak to another without making implied

    or tacit reference to the human face.

    It

    is impossible for

    anyone to understand anyone else, or for the speaker to

    know if the meaning

    of

    what he has said was understood

    without turning toward the face

    of

    the other. Here, the

    other may be absent or present, the face turned toward

    or away. Anonymous reason unattended by the human

    face is incapable

    of

    rendering itself into the personal, the

    singular, and the temporal dimensions

    of

    human exis

    tence. Prior to speech with the other is the face-to-face

    encounter.

    I t

    is here that original expression arises prior

    to any language. It is from the face

    of

    the other that an

    appeal prior to thematization appears. This appeal arises

    in "the uprightness

    of

    the face, its upright exposure

    without defense" (86). The face is the source

    of

    original

    expression mandating a relation that opens the realm

    of

    the ethical. The face is

    as

    necessary for meaning as

    the category

    of

    quantity is for counting. In Ethics and

    Infinity

    Levinas refers to the expression

    of

    the face as

    "signification without context" (86). In this respect

    Levinas begins to explore a distinctively non-intentional

    consciousness. This is to say that for Levinas there is a

    consciousness which exceeds the object

    of

    which it is

    aware, or to put it in more Husserlian language, a

    noesis

    which goes beyond the object to be known, the

    noema.

    Like the home and the face, Levinas elevates the

    phenomenon

    of

    hospitality to a metaphysical category

    with vital ethical implications for the relation

    of

    the self

    to the other. Hospitality arises as the welcoming

    of

    the

    other to the home without divesting the other

    of

    his or her

    alterity. The welcome is the first act of discourse where

    the "I" turns toward the other, thus making the self

    receptive to his speaking. The "welcome," then, is the

    invitation to language. For Levinas, the welcoming

    of

    the other, generosity and shame before the other, are no

    longer treated

    as

    pre-philosophic layers

    of

    human exis

    tence but as transcendental conditions necessary for the

    establishing

    of

    just discourse with the other. The welcome

    also suggests a dimension

    of

    moral height, the asymmetry

    that favors the other over the self, thereby wakening

    the self to a sense

    of

    responsibility for the other. For

    Levinas, the other has priority over the self, and through

    discourse the self is summoned to justify itself before

    the other.

    Here Levinas reveals the necessity of rethinking the

    unannounced premise that spontaneity is at the core of

    human freedom. He searches for an alternative description

    of

    human freedom that necessitates a critique

    of

    sponta

    neity, that is,

    of

    arbitrary self-assertion in relation to the

    other. Spontaneity is the absolutely free exercise of one's

    will, power, and self-assertion. Its unchecked expression

    may serve to menace, dominate, or subordinate the other.

    Levinas associates the phenomenon of spontaneity

    understood as absolute freedom with the ontology

    of

    power. "Political theory derives justice from the undis

    closed value

    of

    spontaneity; its problem is to ensure, by

    way of knowledge of the world, the most complete

    exercise of spontaneity by reconciling my freedom with

    the freedom of others"(83). The calling into question of

    spontaneity by the other is for Levinas the way that one

    first stumbles upon ethics. In a stunning reversal of

    modem philosophical thinking, Levinas argues that jus

    tice precedes freedom. This

    tum

    arises, in part, because

    only a just relation with the other makes discourse pos

    sible. Freedom, then, for Levinas, is understood as

    invested in justice, which delimits it and makes it possible

    and meaningful.

    Phenomenologically, justice has an epistemic as well

    as an ethical dimension. According to Levinas, the

    "I"

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    8/22

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    9/22

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    10/22

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    11/22

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    12/22

    420

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    the "for-the-other" emerges completely. This is a primary

    thesis

    of

    Otherwise than Being.

    For Levinas, subjectivity and alterity are spoken

    together. In his exploration

    of

    the diachronic relation with

    the other, Levinas moves beyond the reach

    of

    Rosenz

    weig's speaking-thinking and concerns himself with the

    origins

    of

    the phenomenon

    of

    speech before it is deposited

    in the lapidary language

    of

    the said.

    Levinas argues that it is proximity that binds sensibility

    to sense. As Levinas puts it, proximity "is to be described

    as extending the subject in its very subjectivity, which is

    both a relationship and a term

    of

    that relationship" (86).

    Here, Levinas introduces the phenomenon

    of

    obsession.

    It

    is only as proximity besieges the subject that the abso

    lutely exterior other is near to the point

    of

    obsession.

    Obsession for Levinas is a complete passivity, a rendering

    into the grammatical and existential mode

    of

    the accusa

    tive. Obsession renders the subject infinitely responsible,

    beyond its own intentions, even for what it does not

    will. In the concrete sense, this means, for Levinas, that I

    bear a responsibility for what others do, even against me,

    in the persecution I am forced to undergo. In

    Levinas, an

    Introduction,

    Colin Davis explains this succinctly in the

    following way: "I am persecuted because I cannot escape

    the dominance

    of

    the other person over me" (80).

    It

    is the

    recurring character of obsession that breaks open the limits

    of

    identity. Levinas writes, "This wound in the subject,

    that begins in sensibility, opens me to responsibility for

    the other" (120). Sensibility, rather than merely referring

    to the first registering

    of

    neutral sensory experience, is

    now reconceived in a more radical way as a susceptibility,

    a vulnerability, and an exposure to the Other.

    It

    is through

    this exposure that one begins to configure, perceive, and

    give sense to one's cognitive life.

    The phenomenon

    of

    responsibility does not displace

    the central role that justice plays in Totality and Infinity.

    Rather, responsibility occupies an ongoing, almost

    incessant place in language. Levinas argues that to speak,

    at its pre-original level, is to be responsible for others. The

    reestablishing

    of

    the saying in the said makes it possible

    to found economic, legal, and social justice. This, in turn,

    makes room for a kind

    of

    justice for the self as well as the

    other, the neighbor and the third party. The rationality of

    transcendence has been broached by Levinas through

    phenomenology.

    I t

    presents "the defection of identity . . .

    as a for-the-other in the midst

    of

    identity: it is the inver

    sion

    of

    being into time, the subversion

    of

    essence begins

    to signify before being, the disinterestedness

    of

    essence"

    (153). Before moving back to the conjuncture

    of

    respon

    sibility with justice from the saying to the said, the

    anarchic character of responsibility prior to commitment

    without a present, without an ongm, must be further

    exposed. This occurs through the "iteration of exposure

    . . .

    as expression, sincerity

    as

    saying

    . . .

    "

    (Otherwise than

    Being 153). In this saying the said begins to emerge

    through re-iteration always moving first to what is

    furthest, to the third party who is other to the neighbor

    and therefore makes justice for me also possible.

    Toward the close

    of Otherwise than Being,

    Levinas

    makes it clear what it means to speak as an ethical subject

    in the first person singular. He does so by interrupting his

    own philosophic discourse in the following statement:

    "And I still interrupt the ultimate discourse in which all

    the discourses are stated, in saying it to one that listens to

    it, and who is situated outside the said that the discourse

    says, outside all it includes. That

    is

    true

    of

    the discussion I

    am elaborating at this very moment" (170). Levinas, here,

    indicates that in Otherwise than Being he has been

    speaking philosophy to the reader and to the other.

    Levinas characterizes his phenomenology

    of

    transcend

    ence, that is, philosophy, as a "fine risk" (170).

    This does not mean that Levinas has absolved himself

    of

    the necessity for explaining keeping the relation

    between the self, the other, the neighbor, and the third

    person. The infinite responsibility of the saying must be

    reinstalled within the language

    of

    totality,

    of

    the said, if

    just institutions are to be possible in this world. However,

    the relation between the other and the third person is one

    of

    synchrony where coming together, reasoning together,

    and creating a peaceful and stable society is realized. The

    presence

    of

    the third person forces a common discourse.

    The third person preconditions the neighbor and the other,

    thus making room for me also, for my claims, for a

    symmetry in which democratic forms express themselves.

    However, it is in this sense that we may say that language

    arises posterior to expression with the appearance

    of

    the

    third person. Such synchrony is required to give just

    institutions continuity, stability, and coherence. This does

    not mean that Levinas reverts to the realm of totality in

    which the subject might free itself

    of

    the position

    of

    infinite responsibility. On the contrary, it is from the

    saying that the said can emerge and maintain itself. It is

    from the time

    of

    diachrony that the time

    of

    synchrony

    makes simultaneity and the time

    of

    sociality possible.

    Justice, in its turn, must be rendered finite in order to

    realize itself. However, in order for justice to appear, it

    must reflect the conjuncture

    of

    peace and reason that

    issues from the expression

    of

    the face

    of

    the other.

    Levinas describes the relation between responsibility and

    justice by reintroducing the phenomenon of the third

    person. Levinas calls the "illeity

    of

    the third person," the

    condition for the irreversibility

    of

    time.

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    13/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE" {THE RELIGIOUS TURN

    421

    PHENOMENOLOGY OF TRANSCENDENCE

    In the preface to the second edition

    of

    Of God Who Comes

    to Mind

    (1986) Levinas acknowledges that he has been

    reproached for not taking up questions

    of

    theology. He

    responds:

    We

    think, however, that theological recuperation

    comes after the glimpse of holiness, which

    is

    primary.

    This is all the more true that

    we

    belong to a

    generation-and to a century-for which

    was

    reserved

    the pitiless trials of ethics without consolation or

    promises; and because it

    is

    impossible-for us, the

    survivors-to witness against holiness,

    in

    seeking after

    its conditions. (ix-x)

    Here, Emmanuel Levinas appears to be searching for

    the conditions of holiness just as he previously sought to

    describe the conditions

    of

    knowledge and ethics. Is it

    possible, then, to speak in the language of transcendence

    without recourse to onto-theo-logy? Levinas does not, he

    insists, take leave completely from phenomenology. In

    fact, in Of God Who Comes to Mind, Levinas asserts that

    his inquiry into the holy may be understood as philosophy

    in the strict sense. How is this possible?

    It

    is through the approach

    of

    phenomenology that

    Levinas moves to metaphysics: the beyond

    of

    being. At

    the core

    of

    the argument in "God and Philosophy," the

    centerpiece

    of

    Of

    God Who Comes to Mind,

    Levinas takes

    issue with the position that the approach to the God of

    philosophy and to "the God

    of

    Abraham, Isaac, and

    Jacob" cannot be reconciled. He argues that such oppo

    sition is itself philosophically based upon ontological

    categories wherein the phenomenon of Transcendence

    cannot be approached. Levinas searches for a way that

    does not commit what we might call the ontological

    fallacy, a problem to overcome for theology as well

    as

    philosophy. As Levinas notes, this obstacle is

    inscribed within the history

    of

    philosophy: "the history

    of

    Western philosophy has been a destruction

    of

    trans

    cendence" (56).

    In philosophical discourse prior to Levinas, God can be

    thought

    of

    only as the exception to the categories gov

    erning an ontology of immanence and this Exception must

    itself be situated within the move or "gesture

    of

    Being."

    God, then, is reduced to a being within the unfolding

    gesture of Being. Rational theology depends upon the

    same kind of error that it originally sets out to rectify.

    If

    the intellection

    of

    the biblical God, theology, does not

    reach the level

    of

    philosophic thought, it is . . . because in

    thematizing God, theology has brought him into the

    course

    of

    being, while the God

    of

    the Bible signifies in an

    unlikely manner the beyond

    of

    being, or transcendence"

    (56). Here, Levinas concludes that the "faith" of rational

    theology-however unknowingly-has tied itself to the

    imperfect opinions

    of

    an uncritical, philosophical ontol

    ogy. In other words, Levinas rejects the opposition

    between the God

    of

    philosophy and the God

    of

    the Bible,

    thus putting the reader on notice that he is searching for an

    alternative approach to transcendence.

    For Levinas, rational theology reduces transcendence

    to complete intelligibility or dogma. While Levinas

    rejects such a reduction, he nonetheless proposes an

    ethical-religious stance that obligates the self in relation

    to the other. An extreme vigilance that expresses itself

    in what Levinas calls "insomnia" would be the "I" in a

    state of wakefulness resisting the fall into the impersonal

    matrix

    of

    being. This condition, not to be confused with

    the inability to sleep, is a readiness to be called by and

    made answerable to the other.

    "Insomnia," understood as vigilance for-the-other,

    permits otherness-in-sameness as a non-alienating con

    sciousness. Levinas insists that insomnia, understood as a

    primarily ethical meta-category, is irreducible. Trans

    muted into wakefulness it appears without intentionality.

    Levinas refers to this wakefulness as "a non-content"

    Infinity (59). Wakefulness without intentionality emerges

    as dis-interestedness. This breaks the simultaneity

    of

    consciousness resting within itself. In this way it differs

    dramatically from reminiscence. Here, Levinas intimates

    a critique

    of

    the Platonic doctrine

    of

    anamnesis. "Remi

    niscence is the extreme consciousness that is also uni

    versal presence and ontology " (60). This description

    of

    the hold that "universal presence and ontology" enjoys

    in the West extends, with variations, for Levinas from

    Plato to Husser . In order to explore Levinas's view fur

    ther, it necessary to consider being as pure act, i.e., "pure

    presence" for Aristotle, the sense

    of

    self-presence that

    accompanies the "I think" in Kant's transcendental unity

    of

    apperception, and the doctrine of intentionality in

    Husser where intelligibility or meaning is rediscovered

    completely in consciousness present to itself. Common to

    all these positions is the refusal to break with immanence,

    and therefore an absence of Transcendence.

    Levinas' s philosophic move toward transcendence calls

    not for the abandonment

    of

    phenomenology, but rather for

    pushing the phenomenological approach to its limits.

    Levinas achieves this end by beginning with what is

    already beyond the finite, thus making it possible to speak

    philosophy in terms

    of

    the criteria

    of

    measure, order and

    sense. This requires an ongoing "deformalization of time"

    as Levinas calls it. Only by beginning with the Infinite do

    the contours

    of

    the finite begin to emerge. How then does

    the Infinite appear? For Levinas, the infinite appears as a

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    14/22

    422

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    "trace" that has already pierced the simultaneity

    of

    self

    presence.

    It

    is the past, or more precisely the trace

    of

    the

    present in the past, that positions the "I" in the realm

    of

    the accusative. This means, therefore, that my responsi

    bility extends beyond my own intentions, beyond my

    own consciousness

    of

    the past. The "Infinite-in-me"

    as

    Levinas calls it, renders the "I" to a state

    of

    "pure pas

    sivity." Aware that the

    "I"

    is so severely conditioned as

    to be what Levinas calls "created," the awakening to this

    condition already positions the "I" as a "me." In awak

    ening the "I" to the accusative mode of subjectivity, what

    is exterior to consciousness, what consciousness can never

    quite contain, also makes responding to this exteriority

    possible. Here, the diachronic sense of time appears in the

    awareness that the other was there before me. I recognize

    myself as called upon to respond to the others who obsess

    me with their exigent appeals and demands. Understood

    as

    a respondent, the "I" can recognize itself as chosen,

    as

    singled out by a non-transferable responsibility. Sig

    nification appears now in order

    of

    exigency. In this way,

    Levinas begins to chart a way to understand meaning in

    terms

    of

    importance to some one.

    Levinas's philosophic moves, so original in their for

    mulation, have vital implications for reconfiguring the

    task

    of

    philosophy. Levinas charts a course which charges

    philosophy with responsibility for describing the condi

    tions that make ethical life possible. This has far-reaching

    practical, moral and political implications. Levinas argues

    philosophically for benevolent non-indifference toward

    the other and urges a philosophically inescapable position

    that must answer affirmatively to the question: "Am I my

    brother's keeper?"

    In Of God Who Comes to Mind Levinas discusses the

    philosophical error in the thinking

    of

    Cain that makes

    murder possible. The simple evocation

    of

    brotherhood is

    not sufficient to prevent murder:

    Biological human fraternity, considered with the

    sober coldness

    of

    Cain,

    is

    not sufficient reason that

    I be responsible for a separated being. Sober, Cain

    like coldness consists in reflecting on responsibility

    from the standpoint of freedom or according to a

    contract. (79).

    Levinas reaffirms his argument that one's responsi

    bility for the other comes prior to one's freedom. Levin as's

    description

    of

    ethical life forms the core

    of

    his phenom

    enology of transcendence. Levinas begins his quest for

    transcendence in a precisely philosophical manner. For

    Levinas, metaphysics arises as a desire for the Infinite.

    It

    is a desire that cannot be reduced to mere need.

    It

    is in

    this sense that the Infinite bestirs us, rips us out

    of

    our

    inertia, and moves us beyond the simultaneity of self

    presence. Levinas says that "love is only possible through

    the idea

    of

    the Infinite" (67). Such love, born

    of

    tran

    scendence, is beyond eroticism and interestedness for the

    beloved. Love (a term that Levinas uses with great dis

    cretion), even when it tries to grasp the other, always finds

    the other slipping away. For Levinas, what is unique in the

    beloved is that which is beyond the finite and therefore

    ungraspable. Levinas, then, begins his philosophy

    of

    the

    infinite with a registering of that which is unknowable.

    However, this does not nullify, but rather enables the

    inter-human drama that makes us responsible one for the

    other.

    Here Levinas approaches transcendence as love for the

    neighbor, the widow, the orphan, the stranger--even the

    beloved. The ultimate expression

    of

    love

    is

    in the "near,

    yet different" that Levinas calls Holy (68). With extra

    ordinary directness Levinas reformulates the "otherwise

    than being." In the language

    of

    a via eminentiae elevation

    to the good, even the holy is expressible in what Levinas

    calls "the humanism

    of

    the other man."

    The last two lecture courses

    of

    Emmanuel Levinas

    were edited and annotated by Jacques Rolland, and pub

    lished under the title God, Death, and Time. These lec

    tures are based upon student notes and therefore quite

    condensed. The first course on 'Death and Time' provides

    Levinas' distinctive view of these vital subjects within the

    context

    of

    some

    of

    modem philosophy's seminal thinkers,

    including Kant, Hegel, Bergson, Fink, Bloch and above

    all, Heidegger. Levinas crystallizes the main question

    of

    the course in the opening of the first lecture: "In question

    in this course is, above all, time. This is a course on the

    duration

    of

    time." As such, the text can be utilized to help

    the reader understand Otherwise than Being.

    Levinas argues in God, Death and Time that where the

    philosophic scandal

    of

    death has not been ignored alto

    gether, time has been thought on the basis

    of

    death. This is

    indeed the signature

    of

    the philosophy

    of

    finitude. Levinas

    sees in Bergson's duree, time as lived and irreducible.

    Bergson's presentation prepares the way for a phenom

    enological analysis of temporality. Here Levinas re

    encounters Heidegger's thinking. Whereas the ecstatic

    phases of human temporality would be authentically

    unified for Heidegger on the basis

    of

    resoluteness in the

    face

    of

    one's own death, Levinas refuses to regard the

    death

    of

    the other as inauthentic.

    Elevating the death

    of

    the other beyond the realm

    of

    the inauthentic, as Heidegger would have it, forces a

    re-thinking

    of

    the Heideggerian notion

    of

    authenticity.

    The other, for Heidegger, is merely a diversion from my

    facing the inevitability

    of

    my own being-towards-death.

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    15/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO

    FACE" IHE

    RELIGIOUS TURN 423

    Is not indifference toward the other, thereby, prescribed

    by Heidegger? What stops this indifference from a tum

    toward an interestedness accompanied by absorption into

    my own project, which can result ultimately in the

    negation or annihilation of the other?

    It

    is by emphasizing the diachronic nature

    of

    time that

    Levinas recognizes the death

    of

    the other as an event

    of

    irreducible importance. Describing time

    as

    diachrony

    makes it possible to think

    of

    death on the basis

    of

    time

    rather than time on the basis

    of

    death. When death is

    understood as the unknown, for both the Other and the

    self, it is possible to reinvestigate the ethical relation

    with the other on the basis of the infinite demands placed

    upon the self within the context

    of

    one's own finite

    temporal existence.

    Here meaning is understood in the context

    of

    the time

    left. Such time, deformalized, means that the death

    of

    the

    other can be elevated even beyond my own. This is one

    of

    the most essential differences between Levinas and

    Heidegger. For only by taking the death

    of

    other with utter

    philosophic seriousness is an ethical relation, one prior to

    the neutrality of Being, possible.

    The second set

    of

    lectures entitled "God and Onto

    Theo-Logy" clearly prefigures Levinas's last milestone

    text, Of God Who Comes to Mind. Here Levinas first

    reconstructs Heidegger's critique

    of

    theology by investi

    gating Heidegger's claim that philosophy prematurely

    becomes theology as soon

    as

    God is identified with

    ultimate being or reality. In this sense, Levinas sees in

    Heidegger's reading

    of

    Aristotle the beginning

    of

    "the

    European philosophy

    of

    being as being becomes theol

    ogy" (God, Death, and Time 123). According to

    Heidegger, Being, in its truth,

    is

    immediately vaporized as

    a question and instead becomes "the universal founda

    tions

    of

    being, by a supreme Being, a founder, by God"

    (123). Levinas clearly breaks with Heidegger on the most

    ultimate level by arguing on the contrary that God signifies

    the other of being.

    Heidegger' s thoughts still belong essentially to the

    ontology

    of

    power that has dominated the West. In

    opposition to Heidegger, Levinas posits that "to contrast

    God with onto-theo-logy

    is

    to conceive a new mode, a

    new notion

    of

    meaning. And it is from a certain ethical

    relationship that one may start out this new search" (125).

    To inquire after God on the basis

    of

    ethics does not reduce

    God to ethics, but rather, on the contrary, accounts for the

    possibility

    of

    religious life itself. In other words, to ask

    what makes totality possible

    is

    at the same time to ask

    what makes the possibility

    of

    intelligibility appear as

    well. According to Levinas, it is Infinity expressing

    itself through its trace in the finite-the metaphysical

    relationship par

    excellence-that

    makes it possible for us

    to speak in the common language

    of

    philosophy. Fur

    thermore, Levinas is explaining how God is other than

    and different from the neighbor. God is the alterity that is

    prior to the alterity

    of

    the other person-"prior to the

    ethical compulsion to the neighbor" (224). Levinas

    describes God as transcendence "to the point

    of

    absence,

    to the point

    of

    the possible confusion with the agitation of

    the

    there is"

    (224). The

    there is

    is pure immanence.

    Transcendence makes this immanence possible. This

    appears to be the philosophic basis

    of

    Levinas' s argument

    for identifying the infinite with pure transcendence and

    therefore as God. However, according to Levinas it is still

    possible to speak

    of

    bearing witness to and for the Glory

    of the Infinite. What does he mean by bearing witness?

    "Bearing witness does not thematize that

    of

    which it is

    the Infinite, and as such it can be a witness only

    of

    the

    Infinite" (196-97). Bearing witness has powerful ethical

    implications. We try to take refuge from responsibility by

    hiding in the concept. This represents Levinas' s very

    perplexing, but original refusal

    of

    the ethical as the

    universal: "Contrary to what Kierkegaard thought, the

    'ethical stage' is not universal; rather, it is the stage in

    which the

    'me'

    forgets its concept and no longer knows

    the limits

    of

    its obligation" (196). This more expands the

    realm

    of

    the ethical by contracting it. In other words, all

    obligations bear on me, personally.

    REITERATIONS: DISTILLATIONS, NEW DIRECTIONS:

    INTERVIEWS

    AND

    COLLECTED ESSAYS

    A number

    of

    interviews are found in collections of essays

    assembled by Levinas presenting diverse profiles on a

    variety

    of

    subjects toward the close of his philosophic

    career, in the late 1980s and early 1990s. These texts

    include Entre Nous: Thinking

    of

    the Other, Proper

    Names, Alterity and Transcendence, Outside the Subject,

    and

    In the Time of the Nations,

    a text devoted largely to

    issues in Jewish philosophy. Here we will introduce only

    some of the most salient subjects and themes explored by

    Levinas in some of his later works.

    For Levinas, speaking philosophy expresses an infinite

    conversation whose future does not announce itself in

    advance. It is extremely important to note that to

    re-iterate,

    to say again, is to keep these words saying what

    they still intend by taking continuing responsibility for the

    texts already authored. The interviews given by Levinas

    to serious interlocutors permit a greater mobility for the

    intention

    of

    saying to be addressed also to the third

    person, the reader. Levinas speaks with an unusual

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    16/22

    424

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO

    FACE"ffHE

    RELIGIOUS TURN

    mixture

    of

    patience for his questioner, and a sense

    of

    urgency regarding the existential necessity to respond to

    the suffering

    of

    the twentieth century, to which he was so

    often the witness. Despite his mastery

    of

    the Western

    philosophic tradition, or perhaps because of this mastery,

    he seldom strays from the junctures that shape the lives

    of

    human beings. The same tradition of philosophy in

    which he is so much at home, permits him to think beyond

    its self-defining limitations, and in so doing to open a

    vein

    of

    inquiry where the advance

    of

    philosophy

    implies the elevation

    of

    what he calls the humanism of

    the other.

    As is the case with the best

    of

    teachers, Levinas awak

    ens the other to a living encounter, pointing the student

    beyond himself toward the Infinite. However open the

    space

    of

    speech, Levinas goes beyond the level

    of

    encouraging questioning. Ethically, language is the other

    prior to a context, and is therefore devoid

    of

    presupposi

    tions. The continuing response I am called upon to give to

    the other constitutes "me"

    as

    an ethical subject answer

    able to and responsible for the other to an unimaginable

    degree. Levinas ' s reiterations are not mere repetitions,

    but the forward movement

    of

    an itinerary.

    What Levinas appears to be searching for is a language

    adequate to express the urgencies

    of

    human existence.

    The reiterations in dialogue, then, represent his continuing

    attempt to express again what has been said before; to

    make room for the reader to enter a temporal context

    along with the author where both can proceed together in

    the pursuit

    of

    wisdom. This is a way

    of

    reconceiving

    philosophy in terms of temporality, and phenomenology

    as a discourse open to transcendence. In Totality and

    Infinity

    Levinas puts it in the following way: "philosophy

    itself constitutes a moment

    of

    this temporal accomplish

    ment, a discourse always addressed to another. What

    we are now exposing is addressed to those who shall

    wish to read it. Transcendence is time and goes onto the

    Other" (269).

    Entre Nous

    In Entre Nous, Levinas speaks

    of

    exploring the inter

    subjective relation in the transcendence

    of

    the 'for-the

    other,' thus encapsulating what he calls the ethical

    subject.

    It

    is the ethical subject that initiates the entre

    nous.

    For Levinas, all thinking is

    of

    the other and for

    the other. This has technical and epistemological rele

    vance and serves as a kind

    of

    exhortation for the reader.

    Among the more original contributions in Entre Nous

    are "Useless Suffering," Levin as' meditation on human

    suffering; "Philosophy, Justice and Love," an interview

    that helps to clarify some of the salient social, ethical

    and political implications of Levinas' later thinking; and a

    succinct reflection on "Non-intentional Consciousness,"

    which deals with questions of phenomenological method.

    "From One to the Other: Transcendence and Time" pre

    sents the philosophic determination

    of

    the idea of culture

    and a critique of Eurocentrism. This critique originates

    from an invocation

    of

    metaphysical pluralism, founded

    upon the irreducibility of ethical life, where difference

    is argued to be a function of otherness, and uniqueness is

    discussed as non-transferable responsibility at the core of

    the singularity of the human subject. "Dying for" is a

    meditation on a non-egoistic form

    of

    self-sacrifice and

    the primacy of the death of the other. In two important

    dialogues, "Thinking of the Other," and "The Other,

    Utopia and Justice," Levinas invites a sustained inter

    rogation

    of

    some of the most fundamental complexities

    of

    his later thinking.

    In these essays, as elsewhere, Levinas, without

    preaching, speaks about the importance

    of

    philosophy

    guided by benevolence in the face

    of

    the legacy of the

    sufferings of the twentieth century and the burden that

    they impose upon the future

    of

    philosophy. Above all,

    Levinas is concerned with disconnecting philosophy from

    violence. In "Useless Suffering" Levinas argues against

    rationalizing the sufferings of others. He juxtaposes this to

    my own efforts to make sense out

    of

    my own suffering.

    The moral height

    of

    the other, however, prohibits me from

    superimposing a premature justification for the sufferings

    of

    others on whose behalf I may intercede, but in whose

    name I cannot speak. Therefore I can forgive, pardon, and

    absolve only the one who persecutes me. I am not per

    mitted to do so for the other without his or her consent. In

    this way, Levinas rejects as premature any recourse to

    systems based upon theodicy. Commenting on human

    suffering, Levinas asks the reader: "consider the outrage it

    would be for me to justify my neighbor's suffering" (98).

    For myself I can choose such a course. For the other, this

    is beyond the path

    of

    mere rationalization and shows an

    ultimate insensibility toward the other. Reckoning with

    human suffering requires no less than a reconfiguration

    of

    the essential nature

    of

    human intrigue

    as

    a social and

    political drama. For Levinas, the war

    of

    each against each

    and all against all must be viewed as subordinate to the

    relation he calls the "for-the-other".

    It

    is in this sense that

    it would be possible to justify the ways of God to the

    other as well as to myself. Refusal to justify the other's

    suffering marks Levinas's response to Nietzsche's "death

    of

    God" theology. There is no theodicy that I may impose

    upon the others who exceed my attempts to justify the

    ways

    of

    God. Levinas absorbs Nietzsche's warning

    of

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    17/22

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE"{fHE RELIGIOUS TURN

    425

    making a virtue into a necessity. However, he does so

    without abolishing the idea

    of

    the good as transcendent.

    Here again, the opening up

    of

    time proves to be decisive.

    As he states in "Philosophy, Justice and Love," "in

    my responsibility for the other, the past

    of

    the other,

    which has never been present 'concerns me:' it is not

    re-presentation for me" (115). Levinas goes on to explain

    the reason for this by again resorting to an unrelenting

    phenomenology

    of

    human time: "the past of the other

    and, in a sense, the history

    of

    humanity in which I have

    never participated, in which I have never been present,

    is my past" (115). The future, on the other hand, is dif

    ferent. "It is not my anticipation which is already and like

    the imperturbable order

    of

    being, as

    if

    it had already

    arrived, as if temporality were a synchrony" (115). Levinas

    links the future to the phenomenon

    of

    prophecy as a

    philosophical idea that can be articulated through phe

    nomenological inquiry: "the future is the time

    of

    pro

    phecy which is also an imperative, a moral "order, herald

    of

    an inspiration" (115). Levinas makes the ethical rela

    tionship with the other depend upon the diachronic rela

    tion between the past and the future in which each have

    their own sense of time, responsibility and signification.

    Proper Names

    Proper Names

    contains a collection

    of

    essays by Levinas

    on such thinkers as Buber, Derrida, Kierkegaard, Proust

    and Maurice Blanchot. There

    is

    also a touching essay

    devoted to Father Herman Leo Van Breda and the debt

    which future phenomenologists owe to his pains in

    creating, maintaining and disseminating the work of the

    Husserl Archives.

    Proper Names

    was first published in France in 1975

    and dates from the same time as

    God, Death and Time.

    Levinas begins

    Proper Names

    with a description

    of

    the

    breakdown of the human order in the catastrophes and

    crises haunting the twentieth century. He speaks more

    openly

    of

    the importance

    of

    formulating a response to the

    breakdown

    of

    language: "at no other time has historical

    experience weighed so heavily upon ideas, or at least

    never before have the members

    of

    one generation been

    more aware

    of

    that weight" (34). Showing a pronounced

    and keen awareness

    of

    the conditions leading to this cri

    tical time, Levinas offers his own characterization

    of

    the

    post-modem age:

    Now theories on the death of God, the contingency

    of

    humanness in philosophical reflection and the bank

    ruptcy of humanism-doctrines already voiced

    by

    the

    end of the last century-have taken on apocalyptic

    proportions. The new anxiety, that of language cast

    adrift, seems to announce without periphrases-which

    are henceforth impossible, which are henceforth

    impossible or deprived of all persuasive

    force-the

    end of the world.

    (4)

    As an alternative to the nihilism that follows from this

    condition, Levinas proposes the humanism

    of

    the other

    man. In

    Proper Names,

    Levinas diagnoses the disin

    tegration

    of

    contemporary life from some

    of

    its linguistic

    indications. As he states, "Time no longer conveys its

    meaning in the simultaneity

    of

    sentences. Statements no

    longer succeed in putting things together" (4). He refuses

    to believe that this signifies the death of philosophy, that

    is, its much-discussed inability to deal with the larger

    questions concerning the meaning

    of

    human life. He

    explains why each

    of

    the articles included in the volume is

    attached to a proper name. He urges the reader to keep in

    mind the irreducibility

    of

    a proper name that attaches to a

    human face. This is the someone with whom I can speak

    philosophy. As he says almost longingly, "Perhaps the

    names

    of

    persons whose

    saying

    signifies a face-proper

    names in the middle

    of

    all the common names and com

    monplaces--can resist the dissolution

    of

    meaning and

    help us to speak" (4). Levinas ties the importance

    of

    proper names to the recovery

    of

    the saying prior to the

    said where we are always speaking philosophy to some

    one. The said by itself can convey fields

    of

    knowledge,

    systems of thought, or being. However, it is necessary

    to join the said with the saying if we are to understand

    why it is that we are responsible for what we say. Only

    in this way is it possible to understand the meaning

    of

    what is most urgent, most important and therefore most

    meaningful.

    There

    is

    one essay that stands out

    as

    the exception

    that demonstrates what happens when proper names are

    effaced.

    It

    is an article entitled "Nameless."

    It

    refers to

    a time between 1940 and 1945 where all the institutions

    of justice had been suspended, and where proper names

    were reduced to an inhuman series

    of

    numbers branded

    on the arms

    of

    the concentration camp victims. In

    "Nameless," Levinas asks us to rethink the role

    of

    phi

    losophy in general, and phenomenology in particular in

    the aftermath

    of

    the Holocaust. He argues that when I

    express non-indifference toward the other, my uniqueness

    returns to me. I become aware of my irreplaceability

    rather than being alienated. It is in this sense that it is

    possible to again begin speaking philosophy. By elevating

    ethics to the rank

    of

    first philosophy, Levinas has

    embarked upon the task

    of

    restoring to philosophy its own

    good name.

  • 7/26/2019 [Doi 10.1007%2F978!94!007-0473-2_40] Bello, A. Ales; Antonelli, M.; Backhaus, G.; Balaban, O.; Baptis -- Phenom

    18/22

    426

    EMMANUEL LEVINAS: THE ETHICS OF "FACE TO FACE" {THE RELIGIOUS TURN

    ALTERITY AND

    TRANSCENDENCE

    Alterity and Transcendence

    includes twelve texts

    authored by Levinas from 1967 to 1989.

    It

    was first

    published in 1995, the last year of his life. The thrust

    of

    the work as a whole is in the direction of a philosophy of

    transcendence which absorbs but does not synthesize

    his previous work, and in which the social, political

    and religious implications of his philosophy are further

    delineated.

    In Alterity and Transcendence Levinas emphasizes

    that transcendence indicates both a crossing over (trans)

    and also an ascent (scando). As Pierre Hyatt notes in his

    preface, "Transcendence would appear to be the marker

    of

    the paradox

    of

    the relation of what is separate" (ix).

    This, for Levinas, represents ascent. What does "ascent"

    signify beyond the moral height

    of

    the other person? We

    may describe the ascent as a "surplus of morality." The

    phenomenology of transcendence, then, begins with the

    neighbor and my responsibility for this the "third" person

    who appears "before" and "after" the second or the you-

    to whom I am obliged completely. Here, Levinas ven

    tures toward the perfectly other. Earlier, in Totality and

    Infinity, Levinas had characterized religion as the refusal

    to engage in the reduction of the Other to the Same. The

    motive force behind these philosophical moves is to enact

    justice responsibly. Bleak times cannot compel us to give

    up on the phenomenon

    of

    transcendence.

    There

    is

    in Alterity and Transcendence a further dis

    tillation and reiteration of some of the signature themes

    of Levinas's later writings. For example, in "Philosopher

    and Death" he allows himself to be interrogated about

    questions on the importance of the way "we are answer

    able not only for the death of the other, but for his life

    as well" (167). Levinas remains very much concerned

    with taking responsibility not only for one's own life, but

    for the life and death of the other. This is not expiation by

    proxy for the other. This means that I am willing to

    substitute myself for the other even to the point of self

    sacrifice to preserve the humanity

    of

    the other.

    OUTSIDE THE SUBJECT

    In Outside the Subject, Levinas assembles a number

    of

    essays on important contemporary thinkers including

    Buber, Rosenzweig, Jean Wahl and Merleau-Ponty.

    Returning to the subject of the task of phenomenology,

    Levinas shows through his essays in this text that he has

    not left behind his original concerns to understand human

    subjectivity, and to rediscover