Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    1/7

    Simmel's Philosophy of History and Its Relation to Phenomenology: IntroductionAuthor(s): Gary BackhausSource: Human Studies, Vol. 26, No. 2 (2003), pp. 203-208Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20010328.

    Accessed: 22/10/2014 19:45

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Springeris collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toHuman Studies.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springerhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20010328?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20010328?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer
  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    2/7

    k.J

    Human Studies 26:

    203-208,

    2003.

    203

    f

    ?

    2003 Kluwer Academic

    Publishers. Printed

    in

    the

    Netherlands.

    Simmel's

    Philosophy

    of

    History

    and

    Its

    Relation

    to

    Phenomenology:

    Introduction

    GARY

    BACKHAUS

    Department

    of

    Philosophy

    and

    Religious

    Studies,

    Morgan

    State

    University,

    Baltimore,

    MD

    21251,

    USA

    This

    set

    of three

    papers

    presents

    an

    inaugural

    study

    of the

    relationship

    of

    Georg

    Simmel's

    philosophy

    of

    history

    to

    phenomenology.

    These

    studies function

    as

    provisional,

    yet

    trailblazing

    explorations

    in

    the

    sense

    that

    they

    lack

    corrobo

    ration with

    an

    established

    body

    of

    research.

    They

    are

    meant

    to

    motivate fur?

    ther

    historical

    research

    concerning,

    and

    creative

    use

    of,

    Simmel's

    philosophy

    of

    history

    towards the

    goal

    of

    developing

    a

    phenomenological

    approach

    to

    history.

    One

    task of this

    brief

    introduction

    is

    to

    demonstrate that this

    subject

    matter

    should

    be

    viewed

    as

    transcending

    the

    narrow

    interests

    of

    a

    circum?

    scribed

    group

    of Simmelian

    specialists.

    This new direction in Simmelian stud?

    ies

    should be

    recognized

    as

    potentially

    effecting

    important

    consequences

    in

    the

    fields of

    both the human

    sciences

    and

    philosophy.

    Any

    historical

    period

    of

    theoretical

    thought

    needs

    to

    be

    a

    living

    history,

    continually

    engaged

    so

    that it

    dynamically

    and

    continually

    unfolds

    through

    perspectival

    modifications.

    Otherwise,

    the

    historical

    relation

    (and

    history

    only

    exists

    as

    a

    relation)

    becomes

    reified:

    we

    forget

    that

    it

    is

    a

    human

    achievement

    and

    allow it

    to

    be

    packaged

    as

    positivistic

    facticities

    ( no

    assembly

    neces?

    sary ),

    rather

    than

    as

    a

    lived

    relation.

    Just

    as

    inauthenticity

    is

    a

    fundamental

    characteristic of

    Dasein,

    the

    reification of

    history

    is

    also

    a

    fundamental

    mo?

    dality

    of

    historical

    inauthenticity.

    Once

    the

    historicality

    of

    the

    lifeworld is

    objectivated

    as

    history,

    the

    hypostatization

    of

    the

    temporal

    process

    can

    be

    accepted

    without renewed

    and

    continued

    reflection. Another

    fundamental

    aspect

    of

    history

    is

    anachronistic

    thinking,

    which

    follows from

    its

    present-at

    hand

    objectivation.

    Anachronistic

    thinking

    reads

    an

    outcome

    back

    into

    its

    genesis.

    For

    example,

    we

    think

    of

    Husserl

    as

    the

    father of

    the

    phenomen?

    ological

    movement

    and from

    our

    temporally

    situated

    reflective

    glance

    may

    unthinkingly

    place

    the

    present

    meaning-context

    back

    into the

    horizons of his

    milieu.

    This

    anachronistic

    thinking

    is

    quite

    common

    without

    disciplined

    train?

    ing

    in

    historical

    thinking

    and

    method,

    but

    only

    a

    lived-historical

    reflection

    can

    counter

    this

    tendency

    of

    the

    natural

    attitude

    to

    de-historicize the

    genesis

    of

    its outcomes.

    This

    set

    of

    papers

    reopens

    to

    historical

    reflection

    a

    fertile

    moment

    in

    the

    history

    of

    theoretical

    thought

    that

    exhibited

    great

    intellectual

    transformation.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    3/7

    204

    GARY BACKHAUS

    Through relating

    ourselves

    to

    it

    we

    bear

    witness

    to

    the

    waning

    of neo-Kantianism

    and

    to

    the

    genesis

    of the

    phenomenological

    movement.

    It

    is

    a

    contemporary

    we,

    a

    succeeding generation

    that

    bears historical

    witness,

    for those within

    the historical milieu

    did

    not

    say

    to

    themselves:

    We

    are

    bearing

    historical

    witness

    to

    the

    waning

    of neo-Kantianism

    . .

    .

    They

    could

    not,

    unless

    they

    fantasized

    what their

    successors

    might

    say

    of them. We

    successors

    also bear

    historical

    witness

    to

    the

    arisings

    and

    developments

    of the human and social

    sciences that occurred

    during

    Simmers

    intellectual

    times.

    By raising

    the

    ques?

    tion of Simmel's

    philosophy

    of

    history

    in

    light

    of its

    possible

    relation

    to

    phe?

    nomenology,

    our

    three

    studies

    regenerate

    the

    lived-dynamics

    of historical

    perspective and open the potential for perspectival transformation. The pos?

    sible

    consequence

    will not

    merely

    concern a

    specific

    sub-text

    in

    this

    history,

    but rather there

    is the

    potential

    to

    set

    inmotion reverberations

    throughout

    the

    historical

    period

    in

    question,

    which

    engenders

    consequences

    for

    our

    living

    relation

    to

    it.

    Studies

    concerning

    the relation of Simmel's

    work

    to

    phenomenology

    are

    virtually

    non-existent.

    Even

    including

    the studies

    already accomplished by

    the

    authors

    of this

    set

    there

    simply

    exist

    scanty

    serious

    research

    exploring

    this

    relation.

    Some

    thinkers

    (Levine,

    1997;

    Psathas, 1973; Wolff,

    1991)

    have

    com?

    mented on Simmel's affinity to phenomenology's studies of essences and of

    the

    ontology

    of

    the

    lifeworld,

    so

    we

    must

    ask

    why

    such studies have been

    slow

    in

    materializing.

    One

    reason

    is

    that

    Simmel

    is

    read

    primarily

    by

    theoretical

    sociologists

    who have been

    trained

    in

    the

    history

    of

    German

    social

    theory,

    but

    not

    in

    phenomenology.

    The

    resulting

    reified

    historical

    perspective

    is

    that

    Simmel

    is

    an

    original,

    but

    neo-Kantian

    thinker.

    However,

    some

    recent

    histori?

    cal reflections

    (e.g.,

    Jaworski,

    1997)

    have

    linked Simmel with the

    postmodern

    perspective.

    Simmel

    has

    proven

    to

    be

    an

    enigmatic,

    ambiguous

    figure

    -

    a

    stat?

    ure

    that

    probably

    would have

    pleased

    him. Not

    only

    was

    he

    marginalized

    during his lifetime, his influence, although recognized, generally has been

    something

    woven

    inconspicuously

    into

    the

    social

    science

    tradition,

    which is

    quite

    ironic

    given

    his

    notable,

    intellectual

    flamboyance.

    New

    insights

    into

    Simmel

    are

    welcome,

    for

    they

    engender

    a

    living-exploration

    of

    his

    work.

    If

    Simmel's

    development

    as a

    thinker

    can

    be linked

    to

    a

    phenomenological

    ori?

    entation,

    his

    works

    appear

    within

    a

    whole

    new

    light,

    which

    effects

    a

    transfor?

    mation

    in

    our

    living

    history.

    Non-phenomenological

    sociologists

    may

    then be

    drawn

    into

    an

    exploration

    of

    phenomenology,

    for

    only

    then

    can

    they

    under?

    stand and

    critically

    remark

    on

    the

    Simmel-phenomenology

    thesis.

    The converse is also true:

    phenomenologists

    who have failed to

    recognize

    the

    phenomenological

    potential

    in

    Simmel

    will

    gain by viewing

    him

    as amem?

    ber of the

    fold

    who

    accomplished

    valuable

    applied/practitioner

    studies.

    It

    is

    ironic that the

    philosopher

    whose

    battlecry

    was

    back

    to

    the

    things

    themselves

    gave

    us

    no

    applied

    studies

    to

    speak

    of,

    unless

    one

    counts

    the

    things

    that

    were

    on

    Husserl's

    desk

    or

    things

    that

    he

    saw

    outside

    his

    window,

    which

    served

    as

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    4/7

  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    5/7

    206

    GARY

    BACKHAUS

    Another

    aspect

    of

    this

    set

    of

    papers

    concerns

    the

    specific

    theoretical

    area

    addressed,

    the

    philosophy

    of

    history.

    We

    hope

    that

    our

    studies

    stimulate

    sys?

    tematic

    comparative

    research of various

    philosophies

    of

    history by

    compar?

    ing

    Simmel's work with that of others who also

    sought

    to

    establish

    the scientific

    limits

    for the field of historical research.

    Moreover,

    our

    research

    promotes

    the

    viability

    of

    Simmel's

    work for continued theoretical

    development

    of

    phen?

    omenological

    approaches

    to

    history.

    If

    Simmel's

    approach

    to

    the

    philosophy

    of

    history

    can

    be

    shown

    to

    be

    phenomenologically

    oriented,

    then his

    work

    in

    this

    area can serve

    to

    promote

    further

    theoretical and

    applied study

    as

    well

    as

    to

    train the

    phenomenologically

    oriented historian.

    Some

    general points

    concerning

    the fundamental

    nature

    of

    phenomen?

    ological

    orientation

    in

    light

    of Husserl's

    goals

    and

    a

    few

    remarks

    concerning

    the

    sense

    of each of

    our

    three

    papers

    complete

    this

    introduction.

    These studies

    are

    based

    on

    the

    recognition

    that various

    strata

    of Simmel's

    thought developed gradually

    from

    a

    consciously

    oriented

    neo-Kantianism,

    through

    various revisions that weakened

    this

    affiliation,

    and

    finally

    to

    exhibit?

    ing

    amore

    phenomenological

    basis.

    Too much

    hair-splitting

    would

    be

    involved

    to

    decide whether Simmel's

    later work should be labeled

    quasi-phenomenol

    ogy,

    proto-phenomenology,

    a

    propaedeutic

    for

    phenomenology,

    or

    properly

    phenomenological.

    The first

    point

    is that the

    early major phenomenologists

    agree

    with

    Husserl's

    fundamental

    insight

    that

    non-constructive material

    a

    priori

    knowledge

    can

    be uncovered

    as

    the field

    of

    phenomenological

    inquiry.

    For

    example, Heidegger

    states:

    But

    to

    disclose

    the

    a

    priori

    is

    not

    to

    make

    an

    ''a-prioristic

    construction.

    Edmund

    Husserl

    has

    not

    only

    enabled

    us

    to

    understand

    once more

    the

    mean?

    ing

    of

    any

    genuine philosophical

    empiricism;

    he

    has also

    given

    us

    the

    nec?

    essary

    tools.

    'A-priorism'

    is the

    method

    of

    every

    scientific

    philosophy

    which

    understands itself.

    There

    is

    nothing

    constructivist about

    it.

    (1962,

    p.

    490)

    It

    is

    this

    specific

    character

    of

    non-constructivity

    that

    essentially

    separates

    the

    sense

    of

    phenomenology

    from neo-Kantian

    perspectives.

    Husserl's

    methodo?

    logical

    strategies

    for and

    theoretical constraint

    in

    apprehending phenomen?

    ological

    evidence

    become

    more

    understandable

    by

    keeping

    this

    single

    point

    in

    mind.

    Husserl

    clung

    to

    his

    Cartesianism,

    not

    because

    he did

    not

    recognize

    its

    limits and inherent

    problems,

    but because

    phenomenological

    evidence

    se?

    cured

    against

    neo-Kantian

    constructivism

    was

    his

    goal

    at

    all

    costs.

    Recent

    evidence shows that Husserl had already begun in the very early twenties to

    replace

    the

    egological

    standpoint

    of

    Cartesianism

    with

    intersubjectivity,

    to

    see

    the

    worldly

    horizon

    as

    co-constituting

    along

    with

    intersubjectivity,

    and

    to

    ground

    genetic

    phenomenology

    as a

    concrete

    deepening

    beyond

    the

    abstrac?

    tive

    nature

    of static

    phenomenology

    (Welton, 2000).

    Husserl

    already

    had

    begun

    phenomenological

    investigations

    that

    Heidegger

    was

    to

    take

    up

    and

    develop

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    6/7

    introduction:

    simmel's

    philosophy of history

    207

    in

    his

    own

    way.

    But he

    was

    concerned

    to

    avoid

    constructivisms

    that would

    corrupt phenomenological

    evidence

    in

    those

    non-egological investigations.

    It

    is

    not

    incompatible

    to

    have

    papers

    in

    this

    set

    that exhibit

    Simmel's

    relation

    to

    both

    Husserlian

    and

    Heideggerian

    phenomenology.

    In

    light

    of

    a

    broader

    understanding

    of

    Husserl's entire

    corpus,

    we

    believe

    that

    Husserl

    would

    not

    have

    been

    opposed

    to

    Simmel's

    starting

    points

    for

    study,

    but

    that he

    was

    at?

    tempting

    to

    find

    a

    way

    to

    rigorously

    ground

    such

    starting points.

    Simmel's

    intellectual

    flamboyance

    allows him

    to

    leap

    straightaway

    into

    areas

    in

    which

    Husserl

    was

    too

    cautious

    to

    venture.

    We

    claim

    that

    Simmel's

    development

    pushes

    him

    closer

    to

    a

    phenomenological

    viewpoint

    because he

    began to recognize structures present in the things themselves prior to any

    cognitive

    construction

    on

    the

    theoretical

    observer's

    part.

    It

    was

    this

    honest

    apprehension

    that led

    Simmel

    to

    modify

    his

    neo-Kantianism

    and

    then to

    aban?

    don

    much of

    it.

    He

    does

    this

    by starting

    from

    a

    standpoint

    of

    immersion ;

    from

    the

    empirical

    subject

    embedded

    in

    the

    socio-historical

    intersubjective

    world,

    which

    allows him

    to

    advance

    phenomenology

    without

    a

    conscious

    pre?

    figuring

    of

    its

    scope.

    In

    his

    philosophical

    anthropology

    Simmel

    strives

    to

    ground

    a

    fundamental

    a

    priori

    basis

    for human

    feelings,

    images,

    and

    narratives.

    He

    rejects

    both

    strictly

    empirical approaches and sheerly speculative accounts in favor of piecemeal

    advancements

    into

    a

    wide

    variety

    of

    human

    activities,

    attitudes,

    and

    world

    views.

    His

    panoramic

    compilation

    of

    human

    studies

    range

    through

    the

    descrip?

    tive

    study

    of

    adventure

    to

    the

    nature

    of

    the

    bridge, through

    ancient

    ruins

    to

    modern

    coquetry,

    and

    through

    the

    development

    of

    money

    to

    the

    need for

    tact.

    His

    work,

    in

    contrast

    to

    Husserl's,

    arrives

    at

    the

    parameters

    of

    phenomenol?

    ogy

    through

    discovery;

    that

    is,

    by

    concrete

    applications,

    rather

    than

    through

    a

    highly

    self-reflective

    stance

    of the

    principles

    of

    phenomenology

    prior

    to

    its

    practice.

    For Simmel, showing the legitimacy of history as a science

    appeared

    to be

    an

    important strategy.

    Human

    life

    unfolds in

    its

    history;

    thus

    without

    history

    having

    legitimacy,

    the other

    sciences,

    which deal

    with contents

    of

    an

    histori?

    cal

    nature,

    are

    inherently problematic

    sciences.

    History

    had

    to

    be

    wrested

    from

    metaphysical

    speculation

    as

    well

    as

    mere

    storytelling.

    Its

    interpretative

    meth?

    odologies

    had

    to

    be

    justified

    as an

    epistemologically

    sound

    component

    of

    historical

    science,

    otherwise

    the

    legitimizing

    course

    would be

    caught

    in

    the

    errors

    of

    realism.

    And

    finally,

    history

    had

    to

    contain

    a

    logical

    or

    existential

    component

    such

    that

    it could

    be

    wrested

    from

    historicism.

    The

    philosophy

    of

    history that followed this course for

    grounding

    the

    legitimacy

    of historical

    science

    would

    at

    least

    show

    itself

    to

    be

    not

    incompatible

    with

    phenomenol?

    ogy.

    The

    first of

    the

    papers

    that

    follows,

    by

    Gary

    Backhaus

    and

    Richard

    Owsley,

    presents

    a

    discussion of

    four

    components

    constitutive of

    Simmel's

    philoso?

    phy

    of

    history

    and shows

    the

    compatibility

    ofthat

    philosophy

    of

    history

    with

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Backhaus, Simmel's Philosophy of History and Phenomenology.pdf

    7/7

    208

    GARY

    BACKHAUS

    phenomenology.

    Comparisons

    could

    be made with

    Droysen,

    Dilthey,

    Humboldt,

    and others (Mueller-Vollmer, 1994). Such a task is modest in its claim, but if

    one were

    to

    carry

    this

    out

    systematically,

    certain

    thinkers,

    such

    as

    Rickert,

    put

    forth

    a

    philosophy

    of

    history quite

    incompatible

    with

    phenomenology.

    The

    paper

    discusses

    methodological

    and

    epistemological

    affinities that

    are

    absent

    from

    many

    thinkers who

    expounded

    a

    philosophy

    of

    history,

    and exhibits

    Simmel's

    phenomenological

    affinities.

    The

    second

    paper,

    by

    Backhaus,

    takes

    up

    the

    problem

    of evidence and in?

    terlaces Husserlian

    texts

    with Simmel's 1918

    essay

    on

    the

    philosophy

    of his?

    tory.

    My

    goal

    is

    to

    show that

    Simmel

    recognizes

    the intuitive

    apprehension

    of

    evidence,

    instead

    of

    cognitive

    constructions of the

    observer,

    as the basis

    for

    a

    science of

    history.

    I

    propose

    that Simmel

    explicates

    historical intuition

    in

    a

    way

    that

    is

    coherent

    with Husserl's

    categorial

    intuition,

    which

    is consid?

    ered

    the

    epistemological

    breakthrough

    that

    opens up

    the material

    apriori

    -

    the

    field of

    phenomenology.

    The third

    paper,

    by

    John

    Jalbert,

    addresses Simmel's

    philosophy

    of

    life

    and

    thus is oriented

    to

    ontological

    issues

    in which Simmel shares

    Heidegger's

    concerns.

    He

    assesses

    Simmel's

    struggles

    to

    account

    for the relation

    between

    the

    historicity

    of

    human

    existence

    as

    the

    uninterrupted

    flow

    of life and the

    problem

    of

    history

    as

    the

    product

    of

    historical

    reflection.

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    focus

    here is

    on

    the relation

    between

    the

    ontological

    and the

    ontic.

    References

    Backhaus,

    G.

    (1992).

    The Foundations

    of

    Husserl and

    Merleau-Ponty

    and

    the Phenomen?

    ological

    Critique

    of

    Science.

    Ph.D.

    diss.

    The American

    University.

    Heidegger,

    M.

    (1962).

    Being

    and

    Time,

    trans.

    John

    Macquarrie

    and

    Edward

    Robinson.

    New

    York:

    Harper

    and Row.

    Jaworski,

    G.D.

    (1997).

    Georg

    Simmel

    and

    the

    American

    Prospect.

    Albany:

    State

    University

    of

    New

    York Press.

    Levine,

    D.N.

    (1997).

    Simmel

    Reappraised:

    Old

    Images,

    New

    Scholarship.

    In C.

    Camic

    (Ed.),

    Reclaiming

    the

    Sociological

    Classics.

    Oxford:

    Blackwell

    Publishers

    Ltd.

    Mueller-Vollmer,

    K.

    (Ed.)

    (1994).

    The Hermeneutic

    Reader.

    New York: Continuum.

    Psathas,

    G.

    (Ed.)

    (1973).

    Phenomenological

    Sociology:

    Issues

    and

    Applications.

    New

    York:

    John

    Wiley

    &

    Sons.

    Welton,

    D.

    (2000).

    The

    Other

    Husserl:

    The

    Horizons

    of

    Transcendental

    Phenomenology.

    Bloomington:

    Indiana

    University

    Press.

    Wolff,

    K.H.

    (1991).

    Survival

    and

    Sociology:

    Vindicating

    the

    Human

    Subject.

    New

    Brunswick

    NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    This content downloaded from 137.99.31.134 on Wed, 22 Oct 2014 19:45:40 PM

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp