13
7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211 http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 1/13 Redeeming Xenophon: historiographical reception and the transhistorical Tim Rood* Redeem the time, redeem the dream . . . And after this our exile. T. S. Eliot 1 * * * The aim of this article is to explore some of the ramifications of Charles Martindale’s work for the study of the reception of classical historiography and to highlight some of the particular challenges facing researchers in this branch of reception studies. Historiography is a relatively undeveloped field within the area of classical reception studies, though there are signs that this is starting to change (notably through the large AHRC-funded project on the reception of Thucydides run by Neville Morley at Bristol University ).There is, however, a strong tradition of research on the influence of ancient historians on the modern conception and writing of history, associated above all with the work of Arnoldo Momigliano and more recently with that of Antony Grafton. The particular influence of reception studies themselves may be seen in the indirect light shed on the reception of Herodotus by recent work on cultural responses to the Persian Wars, including the growing scholarly literature on the film  300. I want to focus in this article on the main area of my own research in classical reception, Xenophon’s Anabasis (Rood 2004a, 2010), but I will start with some more general comments on the implications of Martindale’s approach for histori- ography. In explaining his resistance to traditional models of literary influence, *Correspondence: St Hugh’s College, Oxford OX2 6LE. [email protected] 1 Epigraph in Martindale (1993: p. viii) (from ‘Ash Wednesday’). I am grateful to Tom Phillips for proposing some helpful clarifications and suggestions. 2 See Harloe and Morley (2012); Morley (2012). Other recent work on Thucydidean reception includes Fromentin, Gotteland, and Payen (2010) and Iglesias-Zoido (2011). 3 See Momigliano (1990) for a summary; also e.g. the essays in Momigliano ( 1966). Grafton (2007) includes some detailed discussion of the reception of Curtius Rufus among others. 4 See Hall, Rhodes, and Bridges ( 2007) on the Persian Wars; on 300 and its reception, see e.g. Nisbet (2012) — a volume from the Nottingham AHRC-funded project ‘Sparta in Comparative Perspective, Ancient to Modern: history, historiography and classical tradition’. Classical Receptions Journal Vol 5. Iss. 2 (2013) pp. 199  – 211 ß The Author 2013. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] doi:10.1093/crj/clt003   b  y  g  u  e  s  t  o n  J  u  y  8  ,  0  3  t  t  p  :  /  /  c  j  .  o x  o  d  j  o  u n  a  s  .  o  g  / D  o  w n  o  a  d  e  d  o m  

Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 1/13

Redeeming Xenophon: historiographical

reception and the transhistorical

Tim Rood*

Redeem the time, redeem the dream

. . .

And after this our exile.

T. S. Eliot1

* * *

The aim of this article is to explore some of the ramifications of Charles Martindale’s 

work for the study of the reception of classical historiography and to highlight some of the particular challenges facing researchers in this branch of reception studies.

Historiography is a relatively undeveloped field within the area of classical reception 

studies, though there are signs that this is starting to change (notably through the 

large AHRC-funded project on the reception of Thucydides run by Neville Morley at 

Bristol University 2 

).There is, however, a strong tradition of research on the influence 

of ancient historians on the modern conception and writing of history, associated 

above all with the work of Arnoldo Momigliano and more recently with that of Antony 

Grafton.3 

The particular influence of reception studies themselves may be seen in 

the indirect light shed on the reception of Herodotus by recent work on cultural responses to the Persian Wars, including the growing scholarly literature on the film

 300.4 

I want to focus in this article on the main area of my own research in classicalreception, Xenophon’s Anabasis (Rood 2004a, 2010), but I will start with some

more general comments on the implications of Martindale’s approach for histori-ography. In explaining his resistance to traditional models of literary influence,

*Correspondence: St Hugh’s College, Oxford OX2 6LE. [email protected]

1 Epigraph in Martindale (1993: p. viii) (from ‘Ash Wednesday’). I am grateful to Tom

Phillips for proposing some helpful clarifications and suggestions.

2 See Harloe and Morley (2012); Morley (2012). Other recent work on Thucydidean

reception includes Fromentin, Gotteland, and Payen (2010) and Iglesias-Zoido (2011).

3 See Momigliano (1990) for a summary; also e.g. the essays in Momigliano (1966).

Grafton (2007) includes some detailed discussion of the reception of Curtius Rufus

among others.4 See Hall, Rhodes, and Bridges (2007) on the Persian Wars; on 300 and its reception, see

e.g. Nisbet (2012) — a volume from the Nottingham AHRC-funded project ‘Sparta in

Comparative Perspective, Ancient to Modern: history, historiography and classical

tradition’.

Classical Receptions Journal  Vol 5. Iss. 2 (2013) pp. 199 – 211

ß The Author 2013. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved.For Permissions, please email: [email protected]:10.1093/crj/clt003

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 2: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 2/13

Martindale suggests that when Jonson reworks a piece by Martial, we should not see

 Jonson as simply influenced by Martial, but rather as ‘trying to find out what sort of a

poet Martial is, constructing him and his tone of voice, so to say’ (2007: 209).

Welcome though this approach is, one problem with applying it to historiography

is that historians do not tend to respond in quite the same way as poets to their

source texts. We might well substitute Syme and Tacitus for Jonson and Martial,but it would probably be overambitious to view even, say, Grote’s reading of 

Thucydides in these terms.5

Two key terms for Martindale’s model of reception are dialogue and the trans-

historical. His preferred mode of transhistorical reception involves instances of 

reception that ‘initiate us into a serious or profound dialogue with antiquity’:

‘Dialogic reception energizes the classics, and illuminates antiquity; superficial re-

ception studies do not generate dialogue, do not tell us about the classical.’ And yet

in the pedagogical contexts with which Martindale is concerned, the question of what creates an energizing dialogue with antiquity depends on the way in which that

dialogue is taught as well as on the nature of the receiving text. More broadly, the

degree to which reception illuminates antiquity may depend on the way in which we

view antiquity. Martindale himself engages in a rich dialogue with great works of art

and literature as they have been received over the centuries. But too limited a

conception of the classical world may be as much of a threat to the status of 

Classics as the trends he deplores. A film that one might regard as in some ways

‘bad’ can still help one engage with antiquity: thusGladiator 

, likeSpartacus

before it,is part of a story about the reception both of gladiatorial combat and of ancient

representation of violence — a story that does offer a chance of an engaging dialogue

with writers such as Virgil or Lucan. Similarly 300 provides an interesting challenge

to canonical thinking of the classical in part because it takes place in a medium and

utilizes effects which were unforeseen until recently; as Susanne Turner has shown,

it is particularly effective in making us rethink classical conceptions of the male

nude.6

I would go further, however, and argue that studying 300 would be valuable even

if it did not meet Martindale’s criteria for the transhistorical — and that the reason itwould be valuable is that the film and its contemporary reception matter . The film

drew on a long tradition of representations of Greeks and Persians that have been

historically important; it has become itself a notably contested part of that tradition.

I have myself supervised an undergraduate thesis on 300 that focused in part on the

film’s reception in Iran and that was written by a student moved by his own

5 Grote himself suggested another way of thinking about reception when he wrote in a

letter after his narrative of the Peloponnesian War had reached the point whereThucydides stopped that it was ‘a terrible loss to be divorced from Thucydides, with

whom I had been so long in intimate communion’ (quoted by his wife in Grote 1873:

196).

6 Turner (2008).

T I M R O O D

200

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 3: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 3/13

experience of an audience disturbance at a showing of the film in Bradford. Studying

 300, then, is a valuable rather than dangerous part of reception studies if one views

the products of antiquity not just as sources of aesthetic pleasure and reflection but

as liable to political appropriation. The danger may rather be that ‘reception’ seems

too tame a word for the study of the political appropriation of antiquity.7

Not the least reason why studying the political appropriation of ancient histori-ography is integral to reception studies is that ancient historians were themselves

often concerned with the political appropriation of the past. They analyse the po-

tential for good or ill of the stories that societies tell themselves about their own

pasts: Herodotus and Thucydides were both in their different ways theorists of the

reception of the Persian Wars; Tacitus probed deeply into the reception history of 

the Roman republic. It follows from this thematic concern that ancient historiog-

raphy is itself part of the reception of antiquity: Herodotus is part of the reception of 

the Persian Wars, Tacitus part of the reception of the Roman republic. The ancienthistorian’s deep self-consciousness about the uses of the past — grounded in the

realization of its political potency — in turn imposes some moral responsibility on

the reader of ancient history as well as on scholars who explore how particular

readers have faced up to that responsibility.In the rest of this article I propose to practice some reception criticism, reading

some responses to the Anabasis through some of Martindale’s concerns — his notion

of the transhistorical; the ‘erotics of reception’ that Joshua Billings (2010) has

identified as fundamental to classical reception and that Martindale glosses as a

‘dialectic of resource and loss or absence or lack’; and, finally, the question of the

theorization of reception studies, especially the question of the reception of ancient

historiography as a mode of historical narrative in its own right. My examples will all

be drawn from the reception history of a famous section where Xenophon describes

the sanctuary he set up for Artemis of Ephesus at Scillus, near Olympia, following

his return to Greece (5.3.7-13). Xenophon looks ahead to his foundation of this

sanctuary after describing how the Greek army he had helped to lead back from

Mesopotamia sold some prisoners taken during the course of the retreat through

Asia. It was then decided to offer a tithe that was to be shared between Apollo andArtemis of Ephesus, and to distribute the money among the generals to offer to the

gods in due course. Xenophon then explains that he himself used his portion to buy

an estate for Artemis near Scillus, where he had been settled by the Spartans after

being exiled from Athens. He also set up an annual festival for the goddess to which

the young men of the neighbourhood would come to hunt while all feasted on game

7In a review of Krebs (

2011) — a study of the German nationalist appropriation of Tacitus’ Germania — Grafton warns that ‘dull, abstract terms’ like ‘reception’ or ‘clas-

sical tradition’ suggest that ‘the uses of ancient texts have a modest literary and peda-

gogical interest but are not of deep, existential importance to anyone, modern or early

modern’ (2011: 16).

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

201

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 4: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 4/13

and on fruit from the orchards that Xenophon had had planted. Xenophon does not

need to state outright the personal distinction that arranging the festival gave him.Even though Artemis’ estate at Scillus derived ultimately from (not redeeming

but) selling slaves, Xenophon’s account of the estate has been frequently idealized.

In another paper (Rood 2012), I have explored how it was appropriated in the

eighteenth and nineteenth centuries in the name of the picturesque, and viewedas a delightful retreat where Xenophon could find escape from the political turmoil

of contemporary Greece and devote himself to writing and philosophy. The two

stories that will form the largest part of this article will concern the earlier reception

of Scillus, but I will start by briefly giving one example of this picturesque reception

and exploring how it can be approached via Martindale’s concept of the

transhistorical.Emblematic of the view of Scillus as picturesque retreat is a sketch offered by the

conservative historian William Mitford in a volume of his History of Greece pub-lished in 1797, under the shadow of the threat posed by the French Revolution to

landed property and the personal freedom of the elite. There is room here only for

some excerpts (1789 – 1818: iii. 534):

According to antient accounts, (modern are yet wanting) all the various beauties of landscape

appear to have met in the neighbourhood of Scillus. Immediately above the town and the

adjacent temple, with their little river Selenus, inclosed between the hilly woodlands,

Diana’s property and the barren crags of Typæum, . . . we may conceive the finest classical

compositions of the Poussins. Up the course of the Alpheius and its tributary streams,toward Erymanthos and the other loftier Arcadian mountains, the sublimest wildness of 

Titian and Salvator could not fail to abound; while the Olympian hill . . . would offer the

various beauty, the rich grandeur, and the mind-filling expanse of Claud.

These excerpts are enough to show that Mitford — himself the owner of a country

estate — offers a strong aesthetic response to the landscape of Scillus, shaped in part

by the desire for plenitude (‘all the various beauties of landscape . . . ’), in part by a

sense of loss (modern accounts ‘are yet wanting’).8 The very aestheticism of 

Mitford’s description of the property makes it ripe for ideological criticism (foran attempt, see Rood 2012: 89 – 99, 113 – 14) at the same time as it caters to

Martindale’s preference for the transhistorical: we can read Mitford reading

Xenophon’s account, in line with the picturesque aesthetic of his own time, through

the eyes of seventeenth-century French and Italian painters — and perhaps even

doing so as a way of figuring out what sort of a man Xenophon was, and what sort of 

life he himself aspires to lead. Arguably, the type of reading of Xenophon that

8Tom Phillips further suggests to me that Mitford here presents the ancient landscape as aconstruct in need of a modern supplement and thereby points up the lack in Xenophon’s

own text that arouses the reader’s desire for fulfilment; at the same time, the very terms of 

Mitford’s supplementation (‘the sublime wildness . . . could not fail to abound’) enforce

that lack further.

T I M R O O D

202

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 5: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 5/13

Mitford offers has also had some impact on the way that Xenophon’s works have

come to be read, as the product of a country gentleman of some (but not vast) talent.I have started with a brief summary of this instance of reception because it shows

that Martindale’s aesthetic and transhistorical approach to reception can find some

echoes in the reception history of the Anabasis. I now want to tell two stories that

could be interpreted as fables about reception9 in general — at least if we followMartindale’s gloss on Billings’ ‘erotics of reception’. Together with the Mitford

passage, they will also lead to the question of how we theorize the narrativization of 

reception.

The first story starts in 1637, when Leone Allacci, librarian to Cardinal Francesco

Barberini, published a Greek manuscript that contained thirty-five letters, some

written by Socrates himself, some by his disciples. For Allacci, these newly dis-

covered letters, ‘reborn’ (‘renascentes’) through his own toils, afforded an extraor-

dinary insight into Socrates and his circle. As well as discussing the relative value of philosophy and the pursuit of money and political honours, the letters also had a

delightful informality, seemingly springing from the realia of day-to-day interaction

in the Socratic circle. Xenophon himself was prominent in the new texts as author of 

six letters and recipient of three, including one written by Socrates to Xenophon: ‘I

am told that you are in Thebes, and have caught up with Proxenus as he was setting

off to Cyrus in Asia. Whether this venture of yours will turn out well God knows, as

some people here are already trying to criticize it’ (Ep. 5, trans. Costa). Here, as

Allacci commented in his notes, was direct confirmation of Xenophon’s own account

of how Proxenus had summoned him to join Cyrus’ expedition and Socrates had

warned him of the danger of disapproval at Athens, since Cyrus had funded Sparta’s

victory in the recent war ( Anab. 3.1.4-7).10 In other letters, written after Socrates’

death, Xenophon spoke of the death of his son Gryllus at the battle of Mantinea and

invited Socrates’ disciples to join him for his festival at Scillus. He reported that two

of the disciples, Aristippus and Phaedo, had already visited him, ‘and they delighted

in the place and the construction of the buildings and the plants which I myself had

planted with my own hands’ (Ep. 18, my translation).11 Again Allacci’s notes cited

the relevant ancient evidence: Diogenes Laertius, he notes, attested to the pleasant-ness of Scillus (‘loci amoenitatem’) — but why, he adds, cite other sources, when

Xenophon himself offers an eloquent description? By way of commentary (‘loco

9 To use the term of Martindale (1993: 3).

10 And yet Allacci does not alert readers to two contradictions with the Anabasis: Socrates

gave Xenophon the precise warning about the political undesirability of joining Cyrus

when he was still in Athens (3.1.5); and Xenophon caught up with Proxenus in Sardis,

not in Thebes (3

.1

.8

). The epistolary form may explain the first change (Socrates was ableto speak to Xenophon directly without the need of a letter).

11 Again note the undetected addition: Xenophon does not mention doing any planting with

his own hands; contrast Cyrus’ revelation to the astonished Lysander in the paradise

scene at Sardis described at Oec. 4.22.

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

203

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 6: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 6/13

commentarii’), therefore, he does not shrink (‘non grauabor exscribere’) from repro-

ducing Xenophon’s account of Scillus in full. Rather than reading the Letters as part

of the reception of the Anabasis, that is, he uses the Anabasis to confirm the authen-

ticity of the Letters (1637: 211 – 12).Allacci’s claim that the Socratic letters were authentic did not survive a withering

attack from the great English scholar Richard Bentley. Bentley had engaged in alively dispute over his exposure of the inauthenticity of another set of ancient letters,

attributed to the tyrant Phalaris. In a later edition of his famous treatise, he demol-

ished the authenticity of other collections of ancient letters — including the letters

of Socrates and the Socratics. As well as pointing to historical errors, Bentley was

able to set the presentation of Xenophon against what was known from Xenophon’s

own writings.12 In a letter ‘Xenophon’ spoke of entertaining Aristippus at Scillus

and reading to him his memoirs of Socrates — and this alone, Bentley noted, is

‘sufficient to blast the reputation of our famous Epistles’ (1777: 406): Xenophon hadin fact attacked Aristippus’ views in his Memorabilia. Then again, an impoverished

Xenophon appears in a later letter at Megara — ‘whereas every body knows, that he

got great riches in the war; and lived in very great splendor and hospitality at Scillus’

(1777: 407).13 Bentley was similarly appalled by the disparity between Xenophon’s

polite reference to Socrates’ famously shrewish wife, Xanthippe, in one of the letters

and his disparaging reference to her in the Memorabilia: ‘what shall we say of 

Xenophon’s double-dealing? For my part; rather than I will harbour such a thought

of that great man, I will quit a whole cart-load of such Letters as these’ ( 1777: 411).

Though, as Martindale has written, ‘a reception history need not be part of a

narrative of progress’ (2007: 303), it seems hard not to read the shift from Allacci to

Bentley in those terms. Bentley’s philological acumen triumphs over Allacci’s naıve

willingness to believe in the authenticity of the letters. And yet Allacci’s reading of 

the letters also speaks to that longing for recovery that Billings identifies as funda-

mental to classical reception. If, then, ‘reception provides a way of compensating for

the loss of so much of the archive’ (Martindale 2007: 309), Allacci’s reading of the

letters shows how attempts to compensate for the loss of the archive can themselves

be part of its reception. More disturbingly, the erotics of reception — the desire torecapture the irrecoverable past in all its fullness — also appear to blind Allacci to

some parts of the evidence contained within the archive. As for Bentley, his reading

can be seen not just as a scholarly advance on Allacci, but also as part of a more

complex narrative about the shifts of scholarly fashion. When Bentley stridently

rejects the letters as presenting a picture unworthy of ‘that great man’ Xenophon

and as inferior products in their own right (‘I will quit a whole cart-load of such

Letters as these’), the personal tone of his response to Xenophon can in some ways

12 Though Bentley does not pick up the minor contradictions pointed out in the previous

two footnotes.

13 Yet Xenophon was generally thought to have left Scillus at some point (though Corinth,

not Megara, is the other home mentioned in the ancient biographical tradition).

T I M R O O D

204

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 7: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 7/13

still be aligned with Allacci’s acceptance of the letters’ authenticity: both are moves

towards the recapturing the past in its lost vitality. As for Bentley’s dismissal of the

Socratic letters, recent scholarship has started to paint this type of material in a

much more positive light. This sympathetic picture reflects two trends that are both

partly influenced by the growth of reception studies: a widening conception of the

canon and an increased interest in how the Greek literature of the Roman empirereceived the classical past.14

My second fable starts a few decades after Bentley’s discussion of the Socratic

letters. In 1758, Giacopo Nani, admiral of the Venetian navy, discovered (or at least

was shown) a small inscribed plaque of white marble in a church on one side of the

bay of Vathi on the island of Ithaca, then under Venetian control. Nani brought the

plaque — which measured a mere eight inches by six — back to Venice and gave it to

his brother Bernardo, a senator and the most prolific collector of antiquities in

Venice in the eighteenth century. Three years after its discovery, the inscriptionwas published by the antiquarian Paolo Paciaudi, a monk in the Theatine order, in

his two-volume Monumenta Peloponnesia ( 1761: 139 – 204), a treatise on some of the

antiquities in the Nani collection. Paciaudi subjected the thirty-one words of Greek

to a commentary of sixty-five pages of Latin. What made the inscription unusual was

that it was an exact replica of the inscription that Xenophon had set up in Artemis’

sanctuary and reproduced at the end of his account of Scillus ( Anab. 5.3.13):

I EQ OS O V WQ OS S G S AQSELI DOS . S OM EV OM S A J AI J AQ  POU LEM OM 

S G M L EM   DE J AS G M J AS AYU EI M EJ AS S OU  ES OUS . EJ  DE S OU P EQISS OU  S OM M AOM E P I S J E U AFEI M . AM  DE S I S  LG  POI GI 

S AU S A S GI  YE WI LE LG S EI .

(‘THIS PLACE IS SACRED TO ARTEMIS. HE WHO OWNS IT AND HARVESTS

ITS FRUITS MUST EVERY YEAR OFFER A TENTH OF THE PRODUCE TO THE

GODDESS, AND MUST USE SOME OF THE REMAINDER TO KEEP THE

TEMPLE IN GOOD REPAIR. NEGLECT OF THESE DUTIES WILL NOT GO

UNNOTICED BY THE GODDESS.’)

When Paciaudi published the inscription from Ithaca, he recognized that the word-ing was the same as Xenophon’s inscription. But he did not publish it as a mere copy

of Xenophon: he gave it a far grander title — ‘the sacred law of the Ithacans’. With

numerous citations from ancient Greek texts, he discussed a number of topics thathe claimed were relevant to understanding the inscription — in particular, rules on

working and renting sacred land. After an extensive discussion of shared laws on the

gods, he concluded that the Ithacans had borrowed the phrasing for their sacred law

from Xenophon. He even argued that the stone solved a question surprisingly left

open by the one poetic masterpiece set on Ithaca, Homer’s Odyssey — namely, the

question of who the major deity at Ithaca was.

14 For the letters as a novel, see Holzberg (1994: 38 – 47); see also Doring (1979: 114 – 28) for

the philosophical background.

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

205

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 8: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 8/13

The Ithaca inscription also attracted the attention of two early nineteenth-century

English travellers, William Gell and Edward Dodwell. Gell and Dodwell visited

Ithaca together in 1806; Dodwell was subsequently detained by the French, and it

was only in 1819 that he was able to publish his Classical and Topographical Tour 

through Greece, twelve years after Gell had produced a monograph on Ithaca. Noting

that the inscription did not even mention Ithaca, Dodwell argued that it was prob-ably brought to the island ‘from Patra, on the opposite coast of Achaia, where there

was formerly a temple of Diana Laphria’ (1819: i. 71). Small and hilly Ithaca, after

all, was no place to dedicate a sanctuary to the goddess of the hunt. Gell had in the

meantime endowed the inscription with a more striking degree of authenticity:

observing that Scillus itself was not far from the sea, he speculated that ‘the stone

or marble might possibly have been carried to the island either as ballast, or from

devotion to the church’ (1807: 38) — in other words, that the stone found on Ithaca

was the very inscription set up by Xenophon at Scillus. The erotics of reception atwork again . . .

15

As scholarship on Greek epigraphy developed in the course of the nineteenth

century with new collections of inscriptions, more sceptical views were advanced

about the copy of Xenophon’s inscription found on Ithaca. When August Boeckh

edited the text, he dismissed Paciaudi’s long discussion as ‘extraordinary and fruit-

less sedulousness’ (1828 – 77: ii. 41: ‘mira atque infructuosa sedulitate’), and claimed

that the very title ‘The Sacred Law of the Ithacans’ was a ruse to make the stone

more valuable (‘ut maioris videretur pretii’). Boeckh did think that the stone wasevidence of an actual foundation from the second century AD modelled on

Xenophon’s, but the rules of this sanctuary could not be taken as ‘the sacred law’

of the Ithacans as a whole.16 Other scholars, however, suggested that the stone was

not connected with an actual cult, but was a mere imitation set up by an admirer of 

Xenophon e.g. (Ziehen 1906: 246). As for Gell’s view that the inscription could have

been Xenophon’s actual stone, no reputable scholar even bothered to engage with

that fantasy.If we place the inscription in the second or third century AD, then it can become

part of a powerful story about the reception of Xenophon within antiquity. As Greekwriters under the Roman empire looked back to what they saw as the greatest period

of Greek history, Xenophon’s style, variously characterized as charming, graceful

and sweet, was upheld as a model for imitation in various critical works, including a

lost treatise by ‘Longinus’, the author of the famous treatise On the Sublime; Lucian

even claimed that other historians imitated Xenophon’s stylistic mannerisms right

15 Yet Gell added in an afternote (120) that ‘from the form of the letters in the original, it

may be presumed that the inscription is not of very remote antiquity’. He also slips whenhe writes (38) that ‘this is precisely similar to that inscription which Xenophon found in

Asia’; other aspects of the Scillus cult evoke Artemis’ sanctuary at Ephesus, but not the

inscription.

16 See also Boeckh (1842: 328).

T I M R O O D

206

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 9: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 9/13

down to the notorious stages and parasangs formula that maps out Cyrus’ march

upcountry (Hist. Conscr. 24). This was also the era when Arrian forged a whole

literary career for himself as the second Xenophon: writing an Anabasis, updating

Xenophon’s treatise on hunting, recording the day-to-day musings of Epictetus as

Xenophon had done with Socrates, even setting up an inscription of his own to

Artemis.17

While the second century AD seems to offer a satisfactory context for the Ithaca

inscription, its interpretation took a startling new turn after the Nani collection was

dispersed in the nineteenth century and the inscription given to the Musee du

Cinquantenaire in Brussels. The epigraphist Charles Michel (1913: 144) concluded

from an examination of the letter forms that they were of different dates and so the

product of an erudite — if fallible — Renaissance forger. In dismissing the stone as a

forgery, Michel was going to the other extreme from Gell. But he was also reopening

a possibility that Paciaudi (1761: 145 – 6) in his initial publication of the inscriptionhad raised — but rejected: why, Paciaudi had objected, would a forger set on making

a profit put the stone on the small and scarcely inhabited island of Ithaca? That

objection may not be enough in itself to overturn Michel’s scepticism; at any rate,

the question whether the stone is a second-century AD imitation or Renaissance

forgery is left open in its most recent manifestation (as IG i2.4.1700).To oppose ancient imitation to modern forgery is itself of course to beg an im-

portant question. How does second-century imitation differ from Renaissance for-

gery? We speak of imitation in the first case and forgery in the second because we

assume that the second-century carver was not trying to pass the stone off as ancient

while the Renaissance carver was. But this assumption only shows that if the mean-

ing of this inscription is realized at the moment(s) of reception, then the realization

of meaning itself depends on our reconstruction of other possible moments of re-

ception. The study of classical reception, that is, calls both for historical imagination

and for the detailed examination of often difficult pieces of historical evidence. At

the same time, all individual reconstructions of previous moments of reception will

themselves reflect their own specific historicities. The transhistorical, then, must

always remain in dialogue with the historical.Paciaudi’s defence of the inscription’s authenticity raises the further question of 

why Xenophon’s inscription came to be copied in Ithaca. Trying to answer this

question shows again how hard it is to interpret a text that is undated and divorced

from context. The stone’s alleged discovery place was first reported fifty years later

(Gell 1807: 36) — and even if it was found in a church it is still uncertain where it

had been before that. Whatever the stone’s origin, Ithaca may seem to modern

readers an eloquent place for it to be found: the island above all others associated

17 See Swain (1996), index, s.v. ‘Xenophon, atticist model’; Rutherford (1998: 64 – 79);

Tuplin (1993: 28), esp. nn. 59 (sweetness, grace, pleasantness), 60 (persuasiveness), 61

(thin style), 63 (purity) and 64 (books on Xenophon). For Arrian’s inscription, see

Stadter (1980: 52 – 3).

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

207

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 10: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 10/13

with the return of an epic hero had become home to an inscription associated with a

return from a long and dangerous journey that is itself figured as a new Odyssey.Does studying the reception of Xenophon’s Scillus inscription energize our dia-

logue with Xenophon’s original text? Let us return to the final phrase of Xenophon’s

inscription: AM  DE S I S  LG  POI G I S AU S A S G I   YE WI LE LG S EI 

(‘NEGLECT OF THESE DUTIES WILL NOT GO UNNOTICED BY THEGODDESS’). Xenophon here parades his concern for the goddess’ sanctuary for a

future audience — perhaps because he was writing at a time when he had himself 

been cast out of Scillus in the aftermath of the Spartan defeat at Leuctra. His

inscription, read in the light of the glowing account of the goddess’ festival thatprecedes it, conveys a sense of the ample resources of the goddess’ sanctuary and the

human dedication required to perpetuate the rich local identity that Xenophon has

created through the foundation of the festival. Yet his whole account of Scillus,

while suggesting redemption from the loss imposed on Xenophon by exile fromAthens, also, as John Ma has written (2004: 341), ‘already implies future absence.’

That is to say, Xenophon’s account speaks to that dialectic of resource and loss that

is central to classical reception. He prepares for his own reception history. At the

same time, the transhistoricity of Xenophon’s inscription may also be a dehistor-

icizing gesture that aims at redeeming Xenophon’s reputation: Xenophon could well

have been writing to defend himself from charges of deriving personal advantage

from his obligations to the goddess.The way Xenophon anticipates his own reception in the Anabasis is complicated

by an echo of another passage where he is overtly concerned with the question of hisown reception. The same verb used of the watchful goddess in the Scillus inscription

is used in the last sentence of the Hellenica: e’mo1 me ;n d1 mŒcri to0tou gra’ŒsqwÁ t1 de ;m"t1 taN ta 4 sw& 4llN m"l–s"i (7.5.27: ‘To this point, then, let it be written by me.

Perhaps someone else will be concerned with what happened after this’, trans.

Marincola). As has often been noted, Xenophon ends this work with an echo of 

its opening sentence: L"t1 de ; taN ta o2 polla8 &  3mŒrai&  4 st"ron . . . (‘And after

this, not many days later . . . ’).18 If that opening sets Xenophon up as a continuator

of Thucydides, then the closing sentence of the Hellenica gestures towards thefuture, expressing the hope that Xenophon himself will have continuators. If we

read the end of the Hellenica alongside the end of the Scillus inscription, then we can

see Xenophon as setting up an opposition between the human contingency of history

and the realm of the divine, untouched by uncertainty. In other words, we can view

Xenophon (like Herodotus and Thucydides before him) as a reception theorist.

The stories I have told about Scillus could be dismissed as antiquarianism rather

than transhistorical reception. But the advantages of a reception approach, if broadly

conceived, is that it questions such distinctions while also expanding the number of 

stories that can be told about antiquity. This expansion places a burden of respon-

sibility on the person telling reception stories, particularly in view of the

18 See Rood (2004b: 349), with further bibliography.

T I M R O O D

208

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 11: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 11/13

simultaneous expansion in the easy availability and accessibility of reception dataowing to electronic resources. The stories I have told evidently do not ‘matter’ in the

way that the German appropriation of Tacitus’ Germania matters — but the con-

struction of different sorts of Xenophon is of some historical importance all the

same. Methodologically, my stories could perhaps be dismissed as marked not by a

Pateresque receptivity but by the sort of naıve historical positivism that Martindalesees it as the task of reception to overcome — he has written elsewhere that his own

‘aesthetic turn’ might be seen as a move in his ‘war against the determination of 

classicists to ground their discipline in ‘‘history’’ ’: ‘I would like to see ‘‘history’’

giving place to ‘‘reception’’ ’ (2005: 29). I am not so disturbed by ‘history’, however,nor so convinced that its practitioners are guilty of the lack of theorizing that

Martindale suspects. It may be that they can be found guilty of occluding their

own theoretical reflections, but by the same token any reading that is open about its

own theoretical position must also at some point be guilty of occluding the politics of its own lack of occlusivity. Rather than opposing history and reception, I would

prefer to see the terms as mutually implicated: doing history is a type of reception;

doing reception is a type of history. Both history and reception are culturally sig-nificant and pedagogically useful ways of telling stories about the past.

Doing reception is also one of the types of story-telling that are most likely to

promote theoretical reflection about the constructedness of narrative — even if theprocess of reflection is not foregrounded in the way the narrative is told. I have

presented a number of stories in this short paper that can be seen as fragments of a

larger history of the reception of a particular description in Xenophon. This largerhistory is not in any real sense ‘out there’, ripe for verbal imitation. It is forged in the

very act of ordering the wild paradise that is the classical heritage. To acknowledge

this is not to demean reception studies: it is, rather, to foreground theirmeta-narratological potential. Reception, that is to say, fosters consciousness

about how we construct our historical narratives as we go about the process of 

redeeming the texts of antiquity in the ways that seem best to us, now, following,

however uncertainly, in the tracks of the unknown hands that created Socratic letters

or sculpted on a small piece of Ithacan stone the same words Xenophon had hadinscribed in Scillus.

And after this our exile . . .

References

L. Allacci, Socratis, Antisthenis, et aliorum Socraticorum Epistolae (Paris: S. Cramoisy, 1637).R. Bentley, A Dissertation Upon the Epistles of Phalaris: with an Answer to the Objections of the Hon.

Charles Boyle; To Which Are Added, Dr. Bentley’s Dissertation on the Epistles of Themistocles, Socrates,Euripides, and Others; and the Fables of Æsop (London: W. Bowyer and J. Nichols, 1777; orig. pub.1697).

 J. Billings, ‘Hyperion’s Symposium: An Erotics of Reception’, Classical Receptions Journal  2 (2010),pp. 4 – 24.

A. Boeckh (ed.), Corpus Inscriptionum Graecarum (Berlin, 1828 – 77). ——, Public Economy of Athens. G. C. Lewis, trans. (London: J. W. Parker, 1842; Germ. orig. 1817).C. D. N. Costa, (trans. and ed.), Greek Fictional Letters (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

209

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 12: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 12/13

F. V. M. Cumont, Catalogue des Sculptures et Inscriptions Antiques (Monuments Lapidaires) des Muse es

Royaux du Cinquantenaire (Brussels: Vromant, 1913).E. Dodwell, A Classical and Topographical Tour through Greece: During the Years 1801, 1805, and 1806,

2 vols (London: Rodwell and Martin, 1819).K. Doring, Exemplum Socratis: Studien zur Sokratesnachwirkung in der kynisch-stoischen

Popularphilosophie der fru hen Kaiserzeit und im fru hen Christentum (Hermes Einzelschriften 42

Wiesbaden: F. Steiner, 1979).V. Fromentin, S. Gotteland and P. Payen (eds), Ombres de Thucydide: la Re ception de l’historien Depuis

l’antiquite  Jusqu’au De but du XXe Sie cle (Pessac: Ausonius, 2010).W. Gell, The Geography and Antiquities of Ithaca (London: Longman, Hurst, Rees, and Orme, 1807).A. Grafton, What was History?: The Art of History in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 2007). ——, ‘Those Limbs We Admire’ (review of Krebs 2011), in London Review of Books 33 (2011),

pp. 15 – 16.H. Grote, The Personal Life of George Grote: Compiled from Family Documents, Private Memoranda, and 

Original Letters to and from Various Friends (London: J. Murray, 1873).E. Hall, P. J. Rhodes and E. Bridges (eds), Cultural Responses to the Persian Wars (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2007).K. Harloe and N. Morley (eds), Thucydides and the Modern World: Reception, Reinterpretation and 

Influence from the Renaissance to the Present  (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).N. Holzberg, Der griechische Briefroman: Gattungstypologie und Textanalyse (Tubingen: Gunter Narr,

1994). J. C. Iglesias-Zoido, El legado de Tucı dides en la cultura occidental: discursos e historia (Coimbra: Centro

de Estudos Classicos e Humanısticos da Universidade de Coimbra, 2011).C. B. Krebs, A Most Dangerous Book: Tacitus’ Germania from the Roman Empire to the Third Reich (New

York and London: W. W. Norton, 2011). J. Ma, ‘You Can’t Go Home Again: Displacement and Identity in Xenophon’s Anabasis’, in R. Lane

Fox (ed.), The Long March: Xenophon and the Ten Thousand  (New Haven: Yale University Press,

2004), pp. 330 – 45.C. Martindale, Redeeming the Text: Latin Poetry and the Hermeneutics of Reception (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1993).

 ——, Latin Poetry and the Judgement of Taste: An Essay in Aesthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press,2004).

 ——, ‘Reception’, in C. W. Kallendorf (ed.), A Companion to the Classical Tradition (Malden, Ma., andOxford: Blackwell, 2007), pp. 297 – 311.

W. Mitford, History of Greece, 5 vols (London: T. Cadell and W. Davies, 1789 – 1818).A. D. Momigliano, Studies in Historiography (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1966). ——, The Classical Foundations of Modern Historiography (Berkeley: University of California Press,

1990).

N. Morley, ‘Peter Handke’s Thucydides’, Classical Receptions Journal  4 (2012), pp. 20 – 47.G. Nisbet, ‘ ‘‘This is Cake-Town!’’: 300 (2006) and the death of allegory’, in S. Hodkinson andI. Macgregor Morris (eds), Sparta in Modern Thought: Politics, History and Culture (Swansea:Classical Press of Wales, 2012), pp. 428 – 59.

P. Paciaudi, Monumenta Peloponnesia: Commentariis Explicata (Rome: N. and M. Pagliarini, 1761).T. C. B. Rood, The Sea! The Sea! The Shout of the Ten Thousand in the Modern Imagination (London:

Duckworth Overlook, 2004a). ——, ‘Xenophon and Diodorus: Continuing Thucydides’, in C. J. Tuplin (ed.), Xenophon and his

World  (Historia Einzelschriften 172; Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 2004b), pp. 341 – 95. ——, American Anabasis: Xenophon and the Idea of America from the Mexican War to Iraq  (London:

Duckworth Overlook, 2010).

 ——, ‘A Delightful Retreat: Xenophon and the Picturesque’, in F. Hobden and C. J. Tuplin (eds), Xenophon: Ethical Principles and Historical Enquiry (Leiden: Brill, 2012), pp. 89 – 121.

I. Rutherford, Canons of Style in the Antonine Age: Idea-Theory in its Literary Context  (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 1998).

P. A. Stadter, Arrian of Nicomedia (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1980).

T I M R O O D

210

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om 

Page 13: Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

7/28/2019 Classical Receptions Journal 2013 Rood 199 211

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/classical-receptions-journal-2013-rood-199-211 13/13

S. Swain, Hellenism and Empire: Language, Classicism, and Power in the Greek World, AD 50-250(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).

C. J. Tuplin, The Failings of Empire: A Reading of Xenophon Hellenica 2. 3. 11 - 7. 5. 27 (HistoriaEinzelschriften 76; Stuttgart: F. Steiner, 1993).

S. Turner, ‘ ‘‘Only Spartan women give birth to real men’’: Zack Snyder’s 300 and the reception of themale nude’, in D. Lowe and K. Shahabudin (eds), Classics for All: Reworking Antiquity in Mass

Culture (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing,2008

), pp.128

 – 49

.L. Ziehen (ed.), Leges Graecorum Sacrae e Titulis Collectae, ii: Leges Graeciae et Insularum (Leipzig: B.G. Teubner, 1906).

R E D E E M I N G X E N O P H O N

211

  b  y g u e  s  t   on J   ul   y 8  ,2 

 0 1  3 

h  t   t   p :  /   /   c r  j   . oxf   or  d 

 j   o ur n a l   s  . or  g /  

D o wnl   o a  d  e  d f  r  om