542

Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    3

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 2: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

title: Charles S. Peirce On Norms &Ideals

author: Potter, Vincent G.publisher: Fordham University Press

isbn10 | asin: 0823217108print isbn13: 9780823217106

ebook isbn13: 9780585125855language: English

subject

Peirce, Charles S.--(CharlesSanders),--1839-1914, Norm(Philosophy)--History, Ideals(Philosophy)--History.

publication date: 1997

Page 3: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

lcc: B945.P44P6 1997ebddc: 191

subject:

Peirce, Charles S.--(CharlesSanders),--1839-1914, Norm(Philosophy)--History, Ideals(Philosophy)--History.

Page 4: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page iii

Charles S. Peirce On Norms & Ideals

By Vincent G. Potter, S.J.With a New Introductionby Stanley M. Harrison

FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PRESSNew York 1997

Page 5: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page iv

Copyright © 1997 by Fordham University PressAll rights reserved.LC 96-53944ISBN 0-8232-1709-4 (clothbound)ISBN 0-8232-1710-8 (paperback)ISSN 1073-2764American Philosophy Series No. 6Vincent M. Colapietro, EditorVincent G. Potter (1929-1994), Founding Editor

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Potter, Vincent G.Charles S. Peirce on norms & ideals/by Vincent G.Potter: witha new introduction by Stanley M. Harrison.p. cm.Originally published: [Amherst]: University ofMassachusettsPress, 1967.Includes bibliographical references and indexes.ISBN 0-8232-1709-4 (hard). ISBN 0-8232-1710-8(pbk.)1. Peirce, Charles S. (Charles Sanders), 1839-1914.2. Norm(Philosophy) History. 3. Ideals (Philosophy) History. I.

Page 6: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Title.B945.P44P6 1997191 dc21 96-53944

CIP

Printed in the United States of America

Page 7: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page v

In Memory of My Father

Page 8: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page vii

CONTENTS

Introduction to the 1997 Edition

Foreword xxv

Preface xxvii

Acknowledgments xxxiii

PART IPragmatism & the Normative Sciences

Introduction

1. The Categories & Normative Science

2. Analysis of Normative Science

3. Pragmatism & the Normative Sciences

PART IISynechism & Law

Introduction

1. Synechism & Metaphysical Realism

2. Law as Thirdness

3. Law as Living Power 110

Page 9: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

3. Law as Living Power 110

PART IIITychism & Evolusion

Introduction 151

1. Tychism versus Determinism 153

2. Evolutionary Love 171

3. The Beginning & the End 191

Appendices 207

Bibliography 215

Indices 223

Page 10: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page ix

INTRODUCTION TO THE 1997 EDITIONThe reissuing of Charles S. Peirce: On Norms andIdeals makes available once again one of the fineststudies of the thought of this challenging Americanphilosopher. Thirty years have elapsed since FatherPotter's volume was first published by the Universityof Massachusetts Press. Since that time Charles S.Peirce has become justly famous, a philosopher ofinternational repute whose influence continues togrow. Scholars in diverse fields in countries all overthe world find inspiration for their studies in his richyet unfinished work.1 Peirce believed that workingout a basic question in philosophy was not a task formerely one individual but would require the work ofgenerations. Many today believe that the same holdstrue with respect to clarifying and developing thethought of Peirce himself. This study is an excellentcontribution to that task.

Vincent Potter's serious work on Peirce began duringhis graduate studies in philosophy at Yale Universityin the early 1960s. His teaching, research, andwriting about Peirce were to continue for nearly thirtyyears, particularly during his distinguished career at

Page 11: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Fordham University. This volume, which is essentiallyhis doctoral dissertation of 1965, remains recognizedfor its admirable clarity, mature insight, andmeticulous scholarship. While the secondary literatureon Peirce has grown enormously during the past fourdecades, Father Potter's careful and penetratingstudy still ranks among the best and is regularly citedby scholars, particularly those who work on topicsrelated to Peirce's perspective on the normativesciences.

Few problems in philosophy seem more pressingtoday or more difficult than the job of legitimatingvalues and norms. Many

1 A recent example is Peirce and Value Theory, ed.Herman Parret (Amsterdam and Philadelphia: JohnBenjamins, 1994). This volume contains twenty-fouressays; seven deal with Peirce's Ethics, and seventeenwith aspects of his Esthetics.Other good examples appear in Frontiers in AmericanPhilosophy, ed. Robert W. Burch and Herman J.Saatkamp, Jr., 2 vols. (College Station: Texas A&MUniversity Press, 1992, 1996).

Page 12: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page x

reflective persons want to overcome the skepticalsuggestion that "values" are ultimately arbitrary, nomatter how ancient their pedigree, that they arefinally just imposed by human fiat without the claimor hope of a final sanction by critically informedexperience rooted in reality. Indeed, at least sincethe time of William James, the charge thatpragmatism has fatally relativized value claims hasfrequently been made. Moreover, there is widespreadrecognition of the problem presented by the pluralityof perspectives, whether these be cultural, gender-based, ethnic, or other, more local versions. Thesearch for a rich and compelling common perspectivevivified by shared judgments about important valuesis a complex and difficult affair. Yet unless it can beshown that inquiry into reality can disclose someultimate, universal, and compelling values and ideals,there seems to be no hope of escaping the morass ofserious and, too frequently, tragic human conflict.The implicit premise of Peirce's distinctive doctrine ofthe normative sciences is that the objective reality ofan ultimate ideal, and so of ultimate value(s), can bedefended. Most provocatively, perhaps, Peirce held tothis doctrine without compromising his lifelongcommitment to fallibilism.

Page 13: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Many points which Father Potter discusses meritattention and invite fuller discussion, but thisintroduction will be limited to a few which, it ishoped, will provide a useful orientation toward hisrich study. A superb expositor of Peirce's thought,Father Potter was a powerful and subtle thinkerwhose own philosophizing enabled him not only todiscern certain ambiguities, inconsistencies, andsome incompleteness in Peirce's work, but also tooffer suggestions both to clarify difficulties and,wherever possible, defend Peirce. In addition,because of his own impressive grasp of the history ofWestern philosophy, Father Potter was able to puthim in fruitful dialogue with classical figures such asAristotle, Aquinas, Kant, et al. Father Potter wasdeeply interested in what this great American thinkermight have to teach or learn from his mightypredecessors.

As the title indicates, the focus of this work is thebasic way in which Peirce understood the meaningand status of norms and ideals, topics belonging towhat he called the normative sciences of Logic,Ethics, and Esthetics. What may surprise the reader,especially if this is a first serious encounter withPeirce's discussion of these disciplines,

Page 14: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xi

is the way in which his view about norms and ideals isclosely integrated with other central ideas in histhought. Father Potter makes clear in his openingremarks that his book is indeed a study of Peirce'spragmatism. In fact, it is useful to know that the titleof his Yale dissertation was "Peirce's OntologicalPragmatism." This name clearly suggests theimportance of placing Peirce's pragmatism within theperspective of his metaphysical thought. But it doesnot indicate the central importance which thenormative sciences came to have for Peirce. It isprobably still true that too often Peirce is taught asthe originator of Pragmatism without adequateattention being given to this larger perspective. Thus,the book's title has a special import.

Father Potter was among those who believe thatPeirce's work, taken it its totality, achieves asignificant systematic unity, yet is not without flawsand is certainly incomplete. Nevertheless, he discernsa "remarkably interwoven and interdependent"character among key Peircean doctrines, several ofwhuch are necessary for understanding Peirce's viewsabout norms and ideals. This is why he begins with adiscussion of Peirce's distinctive categories (Firstness,Secondness, and Thirdness), notions "truly at the

Page 15: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

heart of all Peirce's thought" (p. xxx), and thenshows how the categories are related to thenormative sciences. With this background in place, hethen can consider how the normative disciplines arerelated to Peirce's pragmatism. The middle chapterspresent Peirce's metaphysical realism, with specialattention to the doctrine of synechism and the realityof law, ideas central to his cosmology. All thisprovides an important context for the presentation ofPeirce's religious conception of evolution in theclosing chapters.

Father Potter structures his study this way becausePeirce's view about man's summum bonum orgreatest good, the ultimate norm for all humanconduct, is rooted deeply in his theistic interpretationof the evolutionary process. What Peirce eventuallycame to see was that Logic, Ethics, and Estheticshave their foundation in the living character of thecosmos. Making this clear is a major achievement ofFather Potter's sympathetic but critical study.Readers may be surprised to discover that "Peirce'sappreciation of the connection between logic,practics, and esthetics came out of his cosmological

Page 16: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xii

studies" (p. 71). Ultimately, this was Peirce's way ofboth cutting through the commonly asserted dualismof fact and value and defending his view about theobjectivity of values. This connection betweencosmology and the normative sciences is integral tothe deeper unity which Peirce sought to bring forth inhis thought, and it likely accounts for the fact thatthe first of his 1903 Harvard Lectures on Pragmatismwas "Pragmatism: The Normative Sciences" (5.14-5.40).2 Peirce was intent to show how pragmatismwas inextricably linked with Logic, Ethics, andEsthetics. Indeed, wrote Peirce, here one gets "uponthe trail of the secret of pragmatism" (5.130).

Peirce stressed that pragmatism, as a logical doctrineor method for determining the meaning of concepts,pointed directly to the importance of Ethics. Here ishow he put it in that first Harvard lecture of 1903:"For if, as pragmatism teaches us, what we think is tobe interpreted in terms of what we are prepared todo, then surely logic, or the doctrine of what weought to think, must be an application of the doctrineof what we deliberately choose to do, which is Ethics"(5.35). Logic, then, is a special case of ethical action,because Logic deals with the inferences andarguments which we are prepared to approve and, as

Page 17: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

he notes later, "such self-approval supposes self-control" (5.130). The deliberate approval of anyvoluntary act is a moral approval. Ethics, as anormative science, studies those ends which we aredeliberately prepared to adopt. This sometimes ledPeirce to regard Ethics as the normative science parexcellence, because an end is relevant to a voluntaryact in such a fundamental way. Nevertheless, heconcluded that Ethics needs help from a more basicscience whose job is to discern what is ultimatelyadmirable in itself. This science he called Esthetics.

Before probing the nature and the hierarchicalrelation among the normative sciences, the readershould note that it is not Father Potter's task, nor wasit Peirce's intention, to discuss any but the mostgeneral sort of norms or ideals. Thus, there is noextended treatment

2 The numbers inside the parentheses refer in thestandard way to the corresponding volume andparagraph of Collected Papers of Charles SandersPeirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and PaulWeiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press ofHarvard University Press, 1931-1935); Vols VII-VIII, ed.Arthur W. Burks (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Pressof Harvard University Press, 1958).

Page 18: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xiii

in this book of particular human problems or disputesand, accordingly, no attempt to articulate particularrules for resolving them. Peirce's contribution has todo with prior issues such as the nature and numberof normative disciplines, their relation to one another,and whether one can speak plausibly of an ultimateuniversal ideal, a summum bonum relevant to humanaffairs. His focus is on the theory of such matters.

Let us note, also, something which initially maypuzzle or frustrate readers but is basic forunderstanding what is distinctive about Peirce'sentire approach to the normative sciences: namely,his unusual claim that the normative sciences aredisciplines whose purpose is purely theoretical.Indeed, as Father Potter notes (p. 26), quotingPeirce, they are "`the very most purely theoretical ofpurely theoretical sciences'" (1.282). This is a viewwhich sharply limits their task.3 A normative sciencestudies what ought to be (1.281) and establishesnorms or rules for reaching certain ends. For Peircethis means that it is not the business of logic, forexample, to teach one how to think, nor of ethics toteach one how to act. The theoretical knowledge oneseeks from a normative science helps one understandcertain kinds of conditions. Stated generally,

Page 19: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

normative sciences are about the laws of conformityof things to ends. The practical sciences, which haveto do with "reasoning and investigation, of theconduct of life, and of the production of works of art"(5.125), are linked to Logic, Ethics, and Esthetics but"are not integrant parts of these sciences" (5.125).As theoretical, the normative sciences analyze, clarify,and define basic notions and principles (1.575).Thus, the task of Ethics as a normative science is notto work on particular moral conflicts but, rather, todevelop and to justify the conceptions of `right' and`wrong.' As Father Potter writes, ''Ethics . . . is notconcerned directly with pronouncing this course ofaction right and that wrong, but with determiningwhat makes right right and wrong wrong. It has todo with norms or ideals in terms of which thesecategories have meaning'' (p. 32). Actionpresupposes having ends,

3 Not everyone has been pleased with Peirce'sconception of the normative sciences, particularly thisseparation of the theoretical from the practical. See,for example, John Stuhr's recent essay, "Rendering theWorld More Reasonable," in Peirce and Value Theory,ed. Parrett, pp. 3-15.

Page 20: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xiv

and the conformity of our actions to them is whatmakes an action right. Having knowledge of theseends and what counts as conformity is what Peirceregarded as theoretical. It makes it possible to judgerightly in particular cases about rightness andwrongness, but such judging is not part of the"science" of Ethics for Peirce. That task belongs towhat Peirce considered practical or applied ethics.

Moreover, as indicated above, Peirce came to seethat the theoretical knowledge sought by Ethicspresupposes something still more basic: namely, adoctrine which ". . . undertakes to define preciselywhat it is that constitutes the admirableness of anideal" (5.36). That doctrine is Esthetics. "Its problemis to determine by analysis what it is that one oughtdeliberately to admire per se in itself regardless ofwhat it may lead to and regardless of its bearingsupon human conduct" (5.36). This striking claim putsone on notice that the notion of the admirable or "thefine" is not synonymous with beauty. Beauty mustsubserve the admirable. Esthetics, therefore, is notdefined by Peirce in terms of `beautiful' and `ugly'because, as Father Potter aptly puts it, "the beautifuland the ugly are categories within esthetics. It isprecisely these categories which esthetics must

Page 21: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

establish and justify" (pp. 32-33). For example, thetask of esthetics as a theoretical discipline is not todecide whether the cathedral of Chartres is beautifulbut to determine ''what makes the beautiful beautiful,and the ugly ugly'' (p. 33). One needs knowledge ofthe relevant criteria by means of which one candefine and justify using `beauty' as a category.Factors such as proportion, contrast, harmony,integrity, etc., presumably would be relevant. Aspectssuch as depth or intensity also could be relevant toother objects and situations. Esthetics is the sciencewhereby one extends and deepens one'sunderstanding of all that is involved.

The intimate relation between ethics and esthetics isone of Peirce's most valuable insights. His claim wasunequivocal: "But we cannot get any clue to thesecret of Ethics . . . until we have first made up ourformula for what it is that we are prepared to admire.I do not care what doctrine of ethics be embraced, itwill always be so" (5.36). Ethics depends uponEsthetics, because the latter determines "what it isthat constitutes the admirableness of an ideal"(5.36). Such an ideal is "an absolute aim . . ., whatwould be pursued under all

Page 22: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xv

possible circumstances . . ." and ". . . capable ofbeing pursued in an indefinitely prolonged course ofaction" (5.134-5.135). Father Potter carefullyexplains how Peirce struggled to reach his matureconception of esthetics as the supreme normativescience which studies the admirable as such, theideal of ideals, the summum bonum. But Peirce didnot fully grasp the meaning of this ideal until he hadworked out his philosophical cosmology anddeveloped his evolutionary metaphysics. In fact, itseems evident that any such ideal will have to becomprehensive yet vague, one which gives meaningto and justifies all the more particular ends we pursuebut the demands of which require endless discovery.This is why Father Potter remarked that "Thesummum bonum ought not to be thought of assimply another member in a series of goods, not eventhe last member" (p. 33, note 6). Peirce came torefer to this ideal as the advance of concretereasonableness (1.615).

So stated, there is a beguiling simplicity to Peirce'sposition. Until one locates it within his "ontologicalpragmatism," as Father Potter termed it, one cannotappreciate adequately how Peirce's understanding ofhuman rationality is a function of a metaphysical

Page 23: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

doctrine which sees Reason as primordial and alwaysoperative in the cosmos. The human search for andfidelity to ideals is but a part, albeit crucial, of whatPeirce meant by the embodiment of Reason. One canhardly overstress that for Peirce this incarnation has acosmic dimension. Father Potter indicates this in hisown Preface: "In a proper conception of theevolutionary process, Peirce believed, was to befound the summum bonum, the ultimate norm forman's thinking and action" (p. xxx). Again, near theend of the book we find this cryptic conclusion:"Evolution is Reason progressively manifesting itself"(p. 201). The intervening chapters are largelydevoted to explaining the elements which form theclose alliance between Peirce's normative theory andhis philosophical cosmology. Indeed, one notes thatPeirce's conclusion is itself a thoroughly estheticjudgment. ''Peirce came to acknowledge theembodiment of Reason as the summum bonumthrough a contemplation of the universe's structure.The interplay of the modes of being bringing aboutthe cosmos's development struck him as somethingadmirable in itself" (p. 203, note 13). The reader, ofcourse, will do well to spend time studying the wealth

Page 24: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xvi

of exposition and discussion in Part II and III. Butthe basic ideas whereby Peirce linked the normativesciences with an evolutionary metaphysics deservesome brief treatment here because they help usappreciate the unified vision he struggled toarticulate.

Central to this effort was his defense of metaphysicalrealism, a realism implied, he argued, by bothcommon sense and scientific success. The key issue"was whether laws and general types are figments ofthe mind or are real" (1.16). That laws and typeswere real was for Peirce an unavoidable conclusion ofhonest science. Scientists are looking for and findinglaws of nature, articulating them mathematically assimply as possible, and using them as the basis forfurther experimentation and research. For Peirce, apivotal question concerned the sort of reality whichought to be ascribed to law. Is a law a mere quality(a First), a singular event (a Second), or that whichgoverns or mediates how qualities and events aregoing to be connected in the actual world (a Third)?Laws are Thirds. Their mode of being is that ofgovernance or mediation. This fact underlies Peirce'scommitment to "scholastic realism" and explains whyhe thinks of law as a mode of living power. To say

Page 25: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

that we can predict with confidence what is going tohappen when, for example, we drop a cube of sugarinto hot water is to admit that future events (thedissolving of the sugar, its dispersement in the water,etc.) really will take on a certain character. If so,those events must be under the sway of law. All theregularities of nature are evidence of this.

But Peirce was not content to insist on the reality oflaw as a distinctive mode of being. He asked whythere are laws of nature. "Law is par excellence thething that wants a reason" (6.12), that is, whatespecially needs to be explained. At the center ofPeirce's philosophical cosmology is his answer:namely, the idea of a primordial habit-takingtendency gradually bringing about intelligiblestructures in an evolving universe. Furthermore,Peirce argued for the reality of another basic factor,`chance,' an irreducible element of spontaneity orfreedom which, he said, was needed to explain theobvious variety of forms which exist in Nature. Thesetwo factors operating conjointly are integral toPeirce's powerful critique of the mechanistic andrigidly deterministic view of Nature, a critique givendue attention by Father Potter. Peirce arguesbrilliantly that the laws

Page 26: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xvii

of nature have gradually developed or grown up; thatthe vast and intricate pattern of multi-leveled andinterconnected orders of the cosmos are aconsequence of an evolutionary trajectory whichcombines uniformity, novelty, and complexity; aseminal habit-taking tendency, working inconjunction with a real spontaneity or chance, bestaccounts for the reality of our cosmos, with its vastregularities punctuated virtually everywhere bydifferent degrees of irregularity.

Moreover, Peirce saw these same two factorsirreducibly and prominently involved in the action of`mind.' "The one primary and fundamental law ofmental action consists in a tendency togeneralization" (6.21). Unlike mechanical laws,Peirce's laws are not absolutely rigid; despite theirreal sway, there is a certain degree of looseness,depending upon the particular situation or case.There is room for spontaneous developments.Sometimes quite novel forms emerge. Thus, life,simple awareness, complex animal and humanconsciousness, ideas, beliefs, self-control, etc., haveemerged and gradually become more determinate.

These skeletal remarks are intended only to help

Page 27: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

explain that the summum bonum, the advance ofconcrete reasonableness, is not a process that beginswith the human search for the good life. The wholeevolutionary development of the inorganic andorganic worlds is understood by Peirce as a livingembodiment and expression of Reason. Father Pottercites a passage (8.136) which makes this particularlyevident: "`The very being of law, general truth,reason, call it what you will consists in its expressingitself in a cosmos and in intellects which reflect it,and in doing this progressively; and that which makesprogressive creation worth doing so the researchercomes to feel is precisely the reason, the law, thegeneral truth for the sake of which it takes place'" (p.119, note 8). Here one can see as well that Peirce'smetaphysical realism involves a doctrine which makesfinal causality central. The intelligibility of the world isto be accepted neither as an inexplicable fact nor asmerely fortuitous (which comes to the same thing).Indeed, a prime virtue of Father Potter's book is theway it entices the reader into a sustainedconsideration of whether evolution can be understoodwithout final causation.

But the climax of Peirce's philosophical cosmology ishis

Page 28: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xviii

metaphysical claim that the cosmos reveals a processultimately governed by an overriding principle whichhe did not hesitate to call "creative love." This view,entailing not only ultimate final causation but Peirce'sChristian theism, is likely to be problematic for somereaders. As a matter of fidelity to Peirce's work,Father Potter devotes the last two chapters to hisevolutionary cosmology and explains why Peircethought agapasm, the doctrine that makes creativelove the central agency of evolution, was the onlysatisfactory view. What some may see asunsupported religious bias, Peirce defended asontologically true. This is why he named St. John(who says "God is love") the "ontological gospeller"(6.287). In his essay "Evolutionary Love" (6.287-6.317), one finds a striking formula: ''The movementof love is circular, at one and the same impulseprojecting creations into independence and drawingthem into harmony. This seems complicated whenstated so; but it is fully summed up in the formula wecall the Golden Rule'' (6.288).

Peirce's metaphysical realism and his cosmologicalspeculations come together in a striking way in hisevolutionary ideal. From the perspective of normativetheory, it is the connection of these with the idea of

Page 29: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

the summum bonum which furnishes a dramaticvision of how Peirce saw our ultimate situation ashuman beings informed by the living telos of reason.

So, then, the essence of Reason is such that its beingnever can have been completely perfected. It alwaysmust be in a state of incipiency, of growth. It is like thecharacter of a man which consists in the ideas that hewill conceive and in the efforts that he will make, andwhich only develops as the occasions actually arise. Yetin all his life no son of Adam has ever fully manifestedwhat there was in him. . . . [T]he development ofReason requires as a part of it the occurrence of moreindividual events than ever can occur. . . . I do not seehow one can have a more satisfying ideal of theadmirable than the development of Reason sounderstood. The one thing whose admirableness is notdue to an ulterior reason is Reason itselfcomprehended in all its fullness, so far as we cancomprehend it [1.615].

Page 30: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xix

This passage is at once provocative and, for some,perhaps problematic. Among the points that standout is a clear emphasis on growth. Always "in a stateof incipiency," the growth of Reason implies a kind ofinexhaustible eschatology. Our participation is madepossible by our power of self-control, our ability tomodify our habits of thinking, conduct, and feeling.These are the domains of the normative sciences. Inaddition, one must recall that Peirce had anindubitable belief in the pedagogical power ofexperience; indeed, "Experience is our only teacher"(5.50). For him the life and progress of science was acontinuing verification of this principle. But themethod of experiment, observation, and discovery ofexplanatory principles was not restricted to thespecial sciences. This method is demanded by lifeitself if we are to determine the more detailedmeaning of the summum bonum.

Many readers may endorse Peirce's view that aprinciple of creativity is at work in the cosmos and inus in a special way, and yet still harbor deepdisagreements about what the specific developmentof Reason calls for. The plurality of real differenceswhich divide not only cultures but also citizens withina given culture are not easily dissolved or reconciled,

Page 31: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

whether these be political, moral, religious, etc.Serious, indeed fatal, conflicts about the values offreedom, property, self-determination, communaltraditions, etc., occur daily in many parts of theworld. These often tragic results do not seem to bedue merely to human weakness. Peirce was not naïveabout the conflict, suffering, and human capacity forcruelty which plague human history. What is ofparticular interest, however, is whether his viewsoffer reason to hope for an eventual consensus onwhat would constitute the fully rational or ideal life, aconsensus about the greatest good.

To speak of the advance of concrete reasonablenessas something admirable in itself is obviously vague,perhaps intentionally so. Determining particularnorms and practices ingredient in the good life seemsnecessarily to be a process requiring the continuingcooperation of numberless individuals in actualcommunities over many generations. Peirce was fondof making this point with respect to the advance ofscientific truth. But Peirce offered no comprehensivetheory of community (unlike, for example, JosiahRoyce in The Problem

Page 32: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xx

of Christianity); nor did he write any treatise inEthics. More frustrating perhaps is the paucity of hiswork in Esthetics, the discipline he regarded assupreme among the normative sciences.

Peirce's original work, however, contains manyprovocative suggestions which others have taken aspoints of departure as they seek to develop a fullernormative theory.4 This is not the place to address allthese, but some show particular promise. One issue,for example, has to do with whether Peirce offers anyhelp for thinking about how consensus on moralmatters might be possible. In other words, are thereresources in his thought for avoiding the debilitatingmoral relativism that seems so common incontemporary thinking? It is well known that Peircedefined truth as that opinion which the competentunlimited community of inquirers would agree upon inthe long run. Does this mean that every significantcontroversy or conflict would be resolved someday?After all, empirical matters of fact can be settled bythe proper employment of the scientific methodwhereby opinions are shaped by the constrainingpower of experience. It is this power to constrainwhich makes experience our teacher. This is whyevery true empiricist takes experience seriously. In all

Page 33: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

the sciences, hypotheses are formed, experimentsconducted, careful observations made, so thatscientific theories can be gradually verified if theempirical data that would falsify them are neverfound. But many doubt whether anything like thiscan occur with respect to moral, esthetic, or religiousbeliefs, because these are said to be matters of valuerather than fact and so incapable of any authenticobjective grounding.5 At the basis of such a claim ofcourse is the fact/value distinction, somethingPeirce's philosophical cosmology denies. If thecosmos is the expression of a living Reason, a creativelove, then value is objective and authentic.

How one understands "experience" and itsdeliverances is surely

4 It is at least interesting that seventeen of thetwenty-four essays in the recent Parret volume aredevoted to a wide range of topics arising from aconsideration of remarks about esthetics made byPeirce. It is also notable that many authors apply ideasdrawn from Peirce's extensive work in semiotics totheir work in esthetic theory as it relates to the variousarts.5 Aspects of this problem are taken up in stimulating wayby Cheryl Misak in her "A Peircean Account of MoralJudgments," which also appears in Peirce and ValueTheory, ed. Parret, pp. 39-48.

Page 34: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 35: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxi

important. Here the discussion becomes more subtleand interesting, because Peirce has a view whichargues for a continuity between external and internalexperience. `Empirical' facts are normally thosematters taken to be subject to the force orcompulsion of external experience. But, for Peirce,the constraining power or force of experience alsooperates in the inner and more private world ofindividual consciousness, although not with the samedegree of brute compulsion as in the `outer' world ofconfrontations. For example, in his essay "Ideals ofConduct" (1.591-1.615), he presents a thoroughdescription of the process whereby a person canexercise imagination, resolve, and determination toamend his own conduct, to make it exhibit ideals(e.g., patience, honesty, etc.) that are esteemed. Itis a matter of common experience that people cantrain themselves to follow certain ideals. But whatmay be overlooked is the fact that these ideals musthave a power to attract. How this works is not wellunderstood, but there seems no denying that peopledo experience inwardly the efficacious power ofideals. Equally important, there is ample reason toacknowledge that we are affected by the perceivedworth of concrete realities. The varieties of this

Page 36: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

experience are exceedingly great. It is often said thatpeople become "more sensitive" as the result ofcultivating their powers of observation andreceptivity. One becomes more alive to what is beingpresented in experience. We may think of this kind ofsensitivity as something that is more pronounced in''artists," but the native ability seems to belong to allof us and is basic to being rational.

Peirce's view is that the "value" of being(s), the kindof worth or importance which belongs to something,is capable of being apprehended and working itseffect on the human agent. This is not to suggestthat serious moral disputes are going to be easilyresolved, or indeed that there may not be insolubledisputes. Many factors can mitigate against reachingconsensus. But the real issue is whether Peirce offersa theory which makes intelligible the view that truthand falsity are possible with respect to normativeclaims. Here the answer is affirmative. No one needsto suppose that consensus on such matters comeseasily; experience suggests quite the contrary.Particular features of the summum bonum may neverbe shared by all. Yet experience teaches us that thepossibility of important

Page 37: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxii

convergences on matters of deep concern is real, andwithout communal imperialism.

In addition, the great emphasis on cultivating "habitsof feeling," habits integral to human motivation and,thus, to human conduct, ought to be taken mostseriously. In 1898, several years before he came tohis conclusions about esthetics as the supremenormative science, Peirce was strongly defending thesupreme importance of feeling. "It is the instincts,the sentiments, that make the substance of the soul.Cognition is only its surface, its locus of contact withwhat is external to it" (1.628). This may seemremarkable coming from someone who devotedhimself so intensely to the intellectual rigors ofmathematics, logic, several sciences, philosophy,semiotics, etc. But the remarks on feeling are a keypart of his theory of human nature. Peirce was clearlyconvinced of "that department [of the soul] that isdeep and sure which is instinct" (1.647).Furthermore, and this is especially important here,"Instinct is capable of development and growth. . . .And just as reasoning springs from experience, so thedevelopment of sentiment arises from the soul'sInward and Outward Experiences" (1.648). Hereagain one sees his broad notion of experience as both

Page 38: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

"inner and outer.'' The development of appropriate''habits of feeling" is the outcome of one's estheticgrowth and the ground of moral conduct. Peirce'sdepth psychology sees human affectivity functioningunconsciously in the human psyche. He knew thategoism, selfishness, the motivations of what he calledthe "greed philosophy," were not ultimatelyintellectual problems, but affective or emotionaldeficiencies which could be overcome only by someprocess of conversion of one's "heart."

Peirce was clearly interested in the dynamic betweenintellectual cognition or reasoning and the morehidden structures of feeling which he associated with"the very core of one's being" (1.648). The phrase"habit of feeling" is instructive and intriguing preciselybecause it combines (in Peircean language) Thirdnesswith Firstness, generality with qualitative immediacy.It clearly suggests a form of affective or emotionalrationality which involves a form of knowing intimatelyconnected with our exquisite capacity to feel. Value issomehow primarily felt and known. This is why heregarded Esthetics as the supreme normativescience.

Page 39: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxiii

If Peirce is right, authentic human progress dependsupon our capacity for and commitment to cultivatingour affective life. This capacity to feel must benourished if we are to actualize our full rationalnature. The worth of something is integral to itsreality and as such it resonates in the "depths" of ourbeing, thus becoming habitual and enabling us to actin ways more appropriate or reasonable. The dynamicor dialectic between direct feeling, thought, andaction is real, complex, and ongoing. For Peirce theseexperiences are ultimately revelatory of the mysteryof the living cosmos. It is the human privilege to beable to catch a glimpse of this and, at leastsometimes, to be moved profoundly to mediate thetruth about this process through the continualdevelopment of our character and of all those culturalforms, including perhaps especially religion, whichseem to have the mark of reason on them. That wehave capacities to feel and can cultivate them isbeyond dispute; that we ought to cultivate thesecapacities in order to actualize our rational nature isat the heart of Peirce's understanding of what itmeans to live rationally, to pursue the summumbonum. Whether there is more than one defensibleview of what living rationally means is not likely to be

Page 40: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

settled anytime soon. It is up to us to help create anddiscern the lessons of future experience. FatherPotter has presented Peirce's bold and inspiringanswer in a way which leaves the reader with afeeling of hope and a debt of gratitude.

MARQUETTEUNIVERSITY

STANLEY M.HARRISON

Page 41: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxv

FOREWORDCharles Peirce is emerging, in the eyes ofphilosophers both here and abroad, as one ofAmerica's major thinkers. He is not likely, however, tobecome the founder of a philosophical tradition.Father Potter is correct in seeing that, unlike that ofAristotle, Aquinas, or Kant, Peirce's thought cannotbe understood through some one principle or thesisthat might be made into a "platform" for a school ofthought. Although Peirce's philosophy actuallypossesses a greater unity than many would admit,the peculiar language, the often cryptic style, and thenonsystematic form in which he presented many ofhis ideas, stood in the way, and few of hiscontemporaries caught the main drift of his thought.Fortunately, the situation has changed. The highquality of his thought has not escaped notice; recentyears have witnessed the efforts of philosophers andhistorical scholars alike to recover his works, toexpound, to criticize, and to evaluate their import. Inthe end it will be discovered that Peirce accomplishedsomething more important for the cause ofphilosophy than the founding of a tradition; through

Page 42: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

arresting questions and some most original answershe has forced us back to philosophical reflectionabout those basic issues that inevitably confront us ashuman beings, especially in an age of science.Peirce's concern for experience, for what is actuallyencountered, means that his philosophy, even in itsmost technical aspects, forms a reflectivecommentary on actual life and on the world in whichit is lived. To read Peirce is to philosophize, for tofollow his arguments it is necessary for the readerhimself to be wrestling with the very problems Peirceenvisaged.

Father Potter's fine study exhibits at one stroke boththe originality of Peirce's thought and the kind ofserious treatment now being given to his ideas. Nopart of Peirce's philosophy is bolder than his attemptto establish esthetics, ethics, and logic as the threenormative sciences and, even more, to argue for thepriority of esthetics among the trio. The author treatsthese ideas about the normative, the standards thatstructure and guide an activity, with clarity and goodjudgment, showing at the same time their connectionwith Peirce's

Page 43: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxvi

pragmatism and his realism. As Father Potter makesclear, Peirce expressed views on the same topic atdifferent times and he was not always consistent inthese utterances. The present study, however, showsthat Peirce did take seriously his trinity of normativesciences and that, at least on some occasions, he wasconvinced of the priority of the esthetic over theother two. Logic is said to be normative because itgoverns thought and aims at truth; ethics isnormative because it analyzes the ends to whichthought should be directed; esthetics is normativeand fundamental because it considers what it meansto be an end or something good in itself.

Father Potter brings to the accomplishment of histask two principal philosophical virtues; he combinessympathetic and informed exposition withstraightforward criticism and he deals in a sensibleway with the gaps and inconsistencies in Peirce'sthought. The author always prefaces his criticalcommentary with a sustained effort to discover, byattending to all the relevant passages, exactly whatPeirce was asserting on a given topic. Father Potterwisely stands with those who see in Peirce's manywritings not a mere mélange of ideas but an originaland generally consistent position which can survive

Page 44: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

some, if not all, of its incoherences. His study showsthat Peirce was above all a cosmological andontological thinker, one who combined science bothas method and as result with a conception ofreasonable action to form a comprehensive theory ofreality. Peirce's pragmatism, although it has to dowith "action" and the achievement of results, is not aglorification of action but rather a theory of thedynamic nature of things in which the "ideal"dimension of reality laws, thoughts, tendencies, andends has genuine power for directing the cosmicorder, including man, toward reasonable goals.

JOHN E. SMITH

Page 45: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxvii

PREFACEStudies in the philosophy of Charles Sanders Peircewhich have appeared in increasing numbers over thelast twenty-five or thirty years have won for him atlast the recognition which, for the most part, he wasdenied during his lifetime. Everyone is now agreedthat Peirce is one of America's truly original thinkers.1Indeed his contributions to logic alone would merithim that honor. Yet his writings cover such variedsubjects as physics, history, cosmology, mathematics,metaphysics, and religion. They are very fragmentaryand sometimes incomplete. Often they are merelyoutlines of projects to be undertaken. An importantquestion, therefore, in determining Peirce's place inthe history of philosophy is whether or not hesucceeded in constructing his philosophy"architectonicly" (5.5). Did he, like Aristotle and Kant,succeed in laying broad and deep foundations onwhich to build? Is Peirce's philosophy a philosophy ormerely a patchwork of incompatible tendencies?

Peircean scholars are divided on the issue. Not a fewclaim that there are two or more Peirces.2 Othersthink that the very undertaking which he set himself

Page 46: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

to construct a "scientific metaphysics" is doomedfrom the outset because of the basic antagonismbetween the aims of science and those ofmetaphysics.3 Still others argue that,

1 For the best biographical sketch of Peirce, see P.Weiss, "Charles Sanders Peirce," Dictionary ofAmerican Biography, 14 (1934), pp. 398-403.2 E.g. T.A. Goudge, The Thought of C.S. Peirce (Toronto:University of Toronto Press, 1950), Ch. 1; R.S. Robin,"Peirce's Doctrine of the Normative Sciences," Studies inthe Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, Second Series,ed. E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin (Amherst: University ofMassachusetts Press, 1964), p. 287; P.P. Wiener, "Peirce'sEvolutionary Interpretations of the History of Science,"ibid., p. 143.3 E.g. R. Wells, "The True Nature of Peirce'sEvolutionism," ibid., pp. 304-305; E. Freeman, TheCategories of Charles Peirce (Chicago: Open Court, 1934),pp. 4-6 (but Freeman thinks the major inconsistencies hehas found can be resolved, cf. p. 3); M.G. Murphey, TheDevelopment of Peirce's Philosophy (Cambridge: HarvardUniversity Press, 1961), p. 407 (Murphey thinks Peirce's"system" is an illusion).

Page 47: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxviii

despite the obviously fragmentary character of hispapers, Peirce has outlined a genuine philosophical"system."4 Yet another group feels that he hasachieved a partial synthesis with gaps andinconsistencies, some of which at least can beremedied.5

Our own view tends to be something like this last.Peirce will never turn out to be the founder of aphilosophical "school" as were Aristotle and Aquinasand Kant. He has left too much undone, too much inthe form of promissory notes for that. Nevertheless,there will be "Peirceans" in the sense that men will beinspired by his ideals of inquiry and guided by hisprinciples of logic. And perhaps one day some such''disciple" (or as Peirce himself might have thought,some such group of researchers) may achieve thesort of synthesis of which he dreamed. Peirce's workdoes show considerable unity and a good number ofthe alleged inconsistencies are only apparent. Largeblocks of his work are remarkably interwoven andinterdependent, so much so that one wonderswhether or not Peirce's claims to have worked outcertain problems, even though he never got aroundto putting the solutions on paper, are not worthy ofbelief. For example, the various formulations of the

Page 48: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

pragmatic maxim over the course of his career arebasically consistent. His categories are not onlyconsistent with his pragmatism but absolutelyessential to understanding it. Again Peirce's extremerealism is, as he always claimed, the bedrock ofpragmatism and synechism. A firm and definite line ofthought does emerge from the tangle of his paperseven though much of his work is incomplete andperhaps here and there inconsistent in details. It is

4 E.g. P. Weiss, "The Essence of Peirce's System,"Journal of Philosophy, 37 (1940), pp. 253-264; J.Feibleman, An Introduction to Peirce's Philosophy,Interpreted as a System (New York: Harper Bros.,1946), passim; W.D. Oliver, "The Final Cause andAgapasm in Peirce's Philosophy," Studies, Moore andRobin, pp. 289-290; R. Workman, "Pragmatism andRealism," ibid., p. 242; H. Wennerberg, ThePragmatism of C.S. Peirce: An Analytical Study (Lund:C.W.K. Gleerup, and Copenhagen: E. Wunksgaard,1962), pp. 25-28. Wennerberg's division of opinionconcerning Peirce's consistency is an oversimplification;I do not see that Murphey should be listed as holdingthe same position on this matter as Feibleman.5 J.E. Smith, The Spirit of American Philosophy (NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 5; T.S. Knight,Charles Peirce (New York: Washington Square Press,1965), pp. 180-183.

Page 49: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 50: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxix

simply too easy, therefore, to divide Peirce up neatlyinto "tendencies" which are incompatible.6

In the end perhaps we may disagree with Peirce, butfirst we must take him on his own terms, assympathetically as possible. In that way we are morelikely to understand him correctly and so our criticismwill be the stronger. It is possible to defend Peirce'sfundamental unity and coherence in large sectors ofhis writing and still not accept his position. Thequestion of understanding a position from the "inside"is of course distinct from the question of thatposition's truth, or adequacy. Clearly, however, if itcan be shown that a philosopher falls intocontradiction again and again, it is a decisive pointagainst him. On the other hand, to say that aphilosopher is basically consistent is not necessarily toclaim that his position is correct. We have a numberof serious reservations and criticisms of Peirce,despite the position we are here defending, and wehope to have the opportunity one day to air themthoroughly.7

Our presentation is developed in three parts. Part Ideals with the relation of the pragmatic maxim to thedoctrine of the normative sciences. The 1903 version

Page 51: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of that maxim was due in large measure to Peirce'srealization of these sciences' role in human inquiry.Since the doctrine of the normative sciences wasinfluenced by years of cosmological speculation, PartII takes up the doctrine of synechism. Peirce thoughtof his cosmology as proof of pragmatism.Pragmatism,

6 Some commentators use James' distinction betweenthe "tender-minded" and the "tough-minded" tocharacterize the "conflicting" elements of rationalismand empiricism in Peirce. They attach an evaluation tothis terminology, approving of toughness anddisapproving of tenderness. James did not mean toimply a value judgment. He merely meant to describetwo temperaments, equally good and necessary in thesearch for the "whole truth.'' See W. James,Pragmatism and Other Essays (New York: WashingtonSquare Press, 1963), pp. 5-21.7 For example, we have reservations about Peirce'sextreme realism. Again there are problems concerningthe status of the individual in Peirce's "system." We arenot entirely convinced either that metaphysics can becollapsed into logic. Further, questions might be asked asto the legitimacy of assuming that the movement ofhistory and evolution follows that of our reasoning. Theseare but some of the critical questions which might beaddressed to Peirce.

Page 52: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 53: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxx

he maintained, is a step in synechism. Yet there is nounderstanding of synechism without an appreciationof tychism and evolution. Indeed, there is nosynechism at all without them. Hence Part IIIconsiders the doctrine of "evolutionary love." In aproper conception of the evolutionary process, Peircebelieved, was to be found the summum bonum, theultimate norm for man's thinking and acting. The titlechosen by Philip Wiener for his edition of selectionsfrom Peirce, therefore, seems particularly appropriatesince it sums up so well what Peirce's philosophy triesto discover Values in a Universe of Chance.Throughout our presentation we have emphasizedthe key role habit is made to play in his thought. In atrue sense it is the unifying thread which tiestogether the strands of realism, idealism, andpragmatism.

This thesis does not propose the last word on thesubject of Peirce's "system." We think, however, thatwe have made a good case and that we haveresolved some of the "inconsistencies" in his writingsand have laid a foundation for the resolution ofothers. Perhaps more mature thought will lead us tomodify or even abandon altogether the position weare here defending. For the moment, nonetheless,

Page 54: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

this is how we read Peirce. One thing is certain; wehave begun to realize how much still remains to bedone. This study has convinced us that his categoriesare truly at the heart of all Peirce's thought. We feelthat an exhaustive study of them is very muchneeded, a study which will show them to be a greatdeal more complex than has generally been admitted.For example, a study should be made of the relationof the categories to the modes of being. Are they thesame? If they are not, how precisely are they related?This study should emphasize the interrelation andmutual dependence of the categories and not becontent with distinguishing them. Again, such a studyought to make clear how the application of thecategories shifts and adapts to the various levels ofanalysis. At the moment, we are inclined to think thatsuch a study in depth will support our general thesis.

We would like to point out that this work wasoriginally submitted to the Department of Philosophyof Yale University as a doctoral dissertation under thetitle "Peirce's Ontological Pragmatism." The presentversion is substantially the same as that dissertationwith the exception of some minor revisions and theaddition of a footnote

Page 55: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxxi

or two. The title has been changed at the suggestionof several associates as more appropriate to thework's central concern. The bibliography, of course,has also been brought up to date.

Finally, we wish to acknowledge our very great debtto Professor John E. Smith, who directed thedissertation at Yale, for the many hours he sogenerously gave us. Without his advice, suggestions,and encouragement we would have been utterly lost,and surely this book would never have appeared. Wewould also like to thank Mr. Richard Bernstein for hiscontinued interest in our project. It was he who firstintroduced us in a formal way to Peircean studies andoffered valuable criticism all along the way. Theinadequacies and/or errors which remain are all theauthor's. We thank, too, the Philosophy Departmentof Harvard University for permission to use the Peircemanuscripts on deposit in the Houghton Library, andthe library staff for their courtesy and assistance.

VINCENT G. POTTER, S.J.

Shrub Oak, New YorkJanuary, 1967

Page 56: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page xxxiii

ACKNOWLEDGMENTSPermissions have been received from the publishersto quote from the following works:

The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols.I-VI, eds. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss(Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University,1931-1935); vols. VII, VIII, ed. Arthur Burks(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958).References to these Collected Papers will be byvolume and paragraph number following theestablished convention. Thus (5.585) is to beinterpreted to mean Volume V, Paragraph 585.

The Peirce Papers in the Houghton Library of HarvardUniversity, the Philosophy Department of HarvardUniversity.

Charles S. Peirce's Letters to Lady Welby, ed. I.C.Lieb (New Haven: Whitlock's, 1953).

In full the author's article, "Peirce's Analysis ofNormative Science," Transactions of the Charles S.Peirce Society, II, 1, pp. 5-32 (as Part I, Chapter 2).

In full the author's article, "Pragmatism and the

Page 57: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Normative Sciences," Journal of the History ofPhilosophy, V, 1 (January 1967), pp. 41-53 (as PartI, Chapter 3).

Page 58: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 1

IPRAGMATISM & THE NORMATIVESCIENCES

Page 59: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 3

IntroductionIf one were asked to justify beginning a study ofPeirce's pragmatism with a consideration of thenormative sciences, perhaps the most simple andeffective reply would be to point out that this is theway Peirce himself chose to expound pragmatism inhis Harvard lectures of 1903. The first lecture wasentitled ''Pragmatism: The Normative Sciences." Butwhy did Peirce elect to begin thus? Was it merelythat he had to start somewhere, or did he think thatthe normative sciences in some way furnished the keyto all that was to follow?

Although Peirce came to recognize the nature androle of the normative sciences only late in his career,still he was convinced that his own account of thehierarchical dependence of logic on ethics and ofethics on esthetics was a discovery of fundamentalimportance for a correct understanding of his system,and one which distinguished his "pragmaticism" fromother less correct interpretations of his own famousmaxim. It would be a basic mistake to think thatbecause Peirce's exposition of that role was short andunsatisfactory, it is not an integral part of what he

Page 60: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

conceived to be his "architectonic" system. It wouldperhaps be more correct to say that Peirce'srealization of the place of these sciences put in hishands the capstone which unified all that he hadbeen trying to do more or less successfully for someforty years. At least Peirce himself seems to havelooked at it in this way.1

In a letter to William James, dated November 25,1902, Peirce remarks that many philosophers whocall themselves pragmatists "miss the very point ofit," and he tells us why:

But I seem to myself to be the sole depositary atpresent of the completely developed system, which allhangs together

1 Peirce was very conscious of his own development asa philosopher. He constantly refers to what he readand by whom he was influenced. He continuallyreturned to what he had written to annotate andcorrect his opinions. Therefore, the most reliable andfruitful source for an appreciation of what he is tryingto do is Peirce's remarks about himself.

Page 61: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 4

and cannot receive any proper presentation infragments. My own view in 1877 was crude. Even whenI gave my Cambridge lectures I had not really got tothe bottom of it or seen the unity of the whole thing. Itwas not until after that that I obtained the proof thatlogic must be founded on ethics, of which it is a higherdevelopment. Even then, I was for some time so stupidas not to see that ethics rests in the same manner on afoundation of esthetics by which, it is needless to say, Idon't mean milk and water and sugar. (8.255)

Other pragmatic positions, then, are onlyfragmentary.2 They lack the unity provided by atheory of the normative sciences, and this deficiencyhas led those positions into error the error of makingaction the be-all and the end-all of thought.3 If otherpragmatists had a correct view of the normativesciences, they would see how they are connectedwith Peirce's categories.

2 But cf. 5.494 (ca. 1906) where Peirce sketches thedifferences between himself and James, Schiller, andPapini in a less polemical way.3 "It [calculation of probabilities] goes to show that thepractical consequences are much, but not that they are allthe meaning of a concept. A new argument mustsupplement the above. All the more active functions ofanimals are adaptive characters calculated to insure the

Page 62: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

continuance of the stock. Can there be the slightesthesitation in saying, then, that the human intellect isimplanted in man, either by a creator or by a quasi-intentional effect of the struggle for existence, virtually inorder, and solely in order, to insure the continuance ofmankind? But how can it have such effect except byregulating human conduct? Shall we not conclude thenthat the conduct of men is the sole purpose and sense ofthinking, and that if it be asked why should the humanstock be continued, the only answer is that that is amongthe inscrutable purposes of God or the virtual purposes ofnature which for the present remain secrets to us?"So it would seem. But this conclusion is too vastly far-reaching to be admitted without further examination. Manseems to himself to have some glimmer of co-understanding with God, or with Nature. The fact that hehas been able in some degree to predict how Nature willact, to formulate general `laws' to which future eventsconform, seems to furnish inductive proof that man reallypenetrates in some measure the ideas that governcreation. Now man cannot believe that creation has notsome ideal purpose. If so, it is not mere action, but thedevelopment of an idea which is the purpose of thought;and so a doubt is cast upon the ultra pragmatic notionthat action is the sole end and purpose of thought."(8.211-212, letter to Mario Calderoni, ca. 1905.)

Page 63: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 5

These three normative sciences correspond to my threecategories, which in their psychological aspect, appearas Feeling, Reaction, Thought. I have advanced myunderstanding of these categories much sinceCambridge days; and can now put them in a muchclearer light and more convincingly. The true nature ofpragmatism cannot be understood without them. Itdoes not, as I seem to have thought at first, takeReaction as the be-all, but it takes the end-all as thebe-all, and the End is something that gives its sanctionto action. It is of the third category. (8.256)

Just how the normative sciences are connected withthe categories we will have to examine in some detail.For the present, however, let us just note the fact,and Peirce's insistence thereon.4 It was only whenPeirce became aware of the connection that he fullyrealized how crude his first presentation of thepragmatic maxim was. In the 1878 papers ("How toMake Our Ideas Clear" and "The Fixation of Belief")he seemed to identify meaning with action-reaction5because he had not yet seen that action-reaction isto be understood only in terms of purpose and thatpurpose is essentially thought. Thought may wellinvolve action, but it cannot be identical with it sinceSecondness and Thirdness are irreducible.6 Theacknowledgment of the role of ends in action is the

Page 64: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

insight into the role of the normative sciences, andthis acknowledgment brought about Peirce'ssuccessive attempts to formulate the pragmaticmaxim in a more sophisticated and adequate way.Meaning is the rational purport of a concept7

4 "Action is second, but conduct is third. Law as anactive force is second, but order and legislation arethird." (1.337, from an early fragment, ca. 1875,antedating the first published formulation of thepragmatic maxim. The distinction between action andconduct is essential to what follows.)5 Cf. 5.403 for the famous application of the maxim to theconcept "hard" where Peirce went so far as to say thatthere would be no falsity in saying of a diamond that itwas soft until someone tried to scratch it. But cf. 5.453and 457 where Peirce changed his view (1905).6 Cf. 1.322-323; Peirce takes up the objection that law isessential to the notion of one thing acting upon another.Tychism develops the distinction.7 "In general, we may say that meanings areinexhaustible. We are too apt to think that what onemeans to do and the meaning of a word are quiteunrelated meanings of the word `meaning,' or that theyare only connected

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 65: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 6

it is essentially a Third and not a Second even thougha Second may be involved in its recognition.

Peirce goes on to explain to James how the correctand systematic understanding of pragmatism involvessynechism, that is, the doctrine of law in the cosmos.

Only one must not take a nominalistic view of Thoughtas if it were something that a man had in hisconsciousness. Consciousness may mean any one ofthe three categories. But if it is to mean Thought it ismore without us than within. It is we that are in it,rather than it in any of us. . . .

This then leads to synechism, which is the keystone ofthe arch. (8.256, 257)

The line of thought begins to become clearer: allaction supposes ends, but ends are in the mode ofbeing of thought because they are general. Thought,however, is not merely in consciousness but pervadeseverything so that consciousness is rather in thought.Generals, then, are real and so authentic pragmatismis realistic. Elsewhere (in the Pragmatism Lectures of1903) Peirce explicitly suggests that the normativesciences get us "upon the trail of the secret ofpragmatism" (5.129). Consequently, we may say thatfor Peirce the categories, the normative sciences,

Page 66: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

pragmatism, synechism, and "scholastic realism" areof a piece.8

(footnote continued from previous page)

by both referring to some actual operation of the mind.Professor Royce especially in his great work The Worldand the Individual has done much to break up thismistake. In truth the only difference is that when aperson means to do anything he is in some state inconsequence of which the brute reactions betweenthings will be moulded [in] to conformity of the form towhich the man's mind is itself moulded, while themeaning of a word really lies in the way in which itmight, in a proper position in a proposition believed,tend to mould the conduct of a person into conformityto that to which it is itself moulded. Not only willmeaning always, more or less, in the long run, mouldreactions to itself, but it is only in doing so that its ownbeing consists. For this reason I call this element of thephenomenon or object of thought the element ofThirdness. It is that which is what it is by virtue ofimparting a quality to reactions in the future" (1.343).8 In a letter to Dewey, dated June 9, 1904, concerning areview of his Studies in Logic about to appear in theSeptember issue of The Nation, Peirce deplores the wayDewey turns logic into a "natural history," instead ofpursuing it as a normative science "which in my judgmentis the greatest need of our age" (8.239).

Page 67: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 7

The conclusion one must draw is that despite therelatively short time Peirce spent working out hisconception of normative science, despite his manyhesitations as to what ought to be included underthat rubric, and despite the promissory character ofthe development which he left us, he had seen whereand how the notion not only fitted into his view ofphilosophy, but he had also in some way united thewhole thing, moulding his earlier attempts atformulating the pragmatic maxim into acomprehensive and highly subtle analysis of meaning.

Page 68: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 8

1. The Categories & Normative ScienceFor Peirce, philosophy is a theoretical science ofdiscovery. Since it is scientific it deals with fact.Philosophy, in short, is a positive science differingfrom the more familiar positive sciences (physics,chemistry, etc.) only in this: that the facts with whichit deals do not require any special training orequipment in order to be observed. Philosophy dealswith ordinary facts of man's everyday existence, opento all at any time to observe. Peirce subdividesphilosophy into phenomenology, normative science,and metaphysics. Phenomenology takes inventory ofwhat appears without passing any judgment uponwhat it observes. It says neither ''true" or "false" nor"good" or "bad" about the phenomena.1 One mightsay that, for Peirce, phenomenology merely observesand catalogs the contents of experience. Normativescience evaluates and judges the data thus collected,while metaphysics tries to comprehend their reality. Itis clear, therefore, that in some sensephenomenology is the most basic of the philosophicaldisciplines the one without which the enterprise couldnot even begin. The categories which

Page 69: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

phenomenology provides will be the conceptual framein which the other parts of philosophy will make theiranalyses and explanations. It is not surprising,therefore, that Peirce should tell James that the truenature of pragmatism cannot be understood withoutthe categories (8.256), nor that Peirce himselfemploys them to elucidate his division of normativescience (8.256, 1.121-124, 5.129). Since we aretrying to understand the role of

1 An objection might be raised at the outset, namely,that the categories themselves are involved in thephenomenological analysis. Peirce would probablyreply that some categories are supposed in anyanalysis, but they need not be the universal ones.Peirce also distinguishes two stages in philosophy: theheuristic and the retrospective. The first he calls"coenoscopy," the second "synthetic philosophy."("Charles S. Peirce Papers," Houghton Library, HarvardUniversity, #283, pp. 13-15. These numbers are from R.S.Robin's Annotated Catalogue. Henceforth, references tothe Peirce manuscripts will be as follows: Peirce Papers,#283, pp. 13-15.)

Page 70: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 9

normative science in Peirce's pragmatism, we mustconsider briefly the relation of his categories toesthetics, ethics, and logic.2

To guide us in this rather intricate analysis, it wouldbe well perhaps to anticipate one result of Peirce'sphenomenological investigations, namely, his theoryof how ideas may be separated, or to put it in moretraditional terms, his theory of distinctions. Accordingto him there are three grades of separability of oneidea from another: (1) dissociation, (2) "prescission,"and (3) distinction. By "dissociation" he means thatone idea can be imagined without another, just as wecan imagine the color red without imagining the colorblue. By "prescission'' he means that even when twoideas are so closely connected that we cannotimagine one without the other, we can sometimessuppose one without the other. Thus, for example,while one can neither imagine nor suppose colorwithout space, one can suppose space without coloreven though our experience does not allow us toimagine uncolored space. In other words, althoughcolor and space are inseparable in our experientially-bound imagination, we can discern a logical priority ofone over the other in our example, that of the subjectof inherence of a quality over the quality itself. By

Page 71: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

"distinction," Peirce means simply the power todiscriminate between two ideas which cannot evenbe supposed one without the other, as for example,taller and shorter. The meanings here can bedistinguished although not separated because theyare strictly relative to one another. Peirce wouldprobably also allow the nonmutual relation of qualityto a subject of inherence as an example of what hemeans by "distinction'' (cf. 1.549 n. 1) even though itmight be argued that the foundation for thediscrimination is really in the fact that the subject canbe prescinded from the quality (1.353).3

In these terms, then, what is the relationship ofnormative science

2 Cf. 5.39: "This science of Phenomenology, then, mustbe taken as the basis upon which normative science isto be erected . . . ."3 Peirce sometimes refers to prescission as abstraction(1.549), but in a long note, he pinpoints "prescission" asone type of abstraction. He quotes Scotus as his authorityon this matter and yet nowhere takes up the much moresophisticated set of distinctions one mostly Thomistic, theother Scotistic current in the medieval schools. It turnsout that in the theory of distinctions lie the basicdifferences in the philosophies of these two schools; orperhaps more accurately, the differences in the theory ofdistinctions result from metaphysical differences.

Page 72: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 73: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 10

to phenomenology? They cannot be dissociatedbecause normative science intrinsically depends uponphenomenology for its categorial structure. On theother hand, there is more than just a distinctionbetween them, for phenomenology may beprescinded from normative science. The latter is astep beyond the former which perhaps need not betaken, but which cannot be taken without the former.Consequently, the categories precede normativescience. But once normative science is investigated, itof course becomes part of the phenomenainventoried by phenomenology and so the categoriesmust apply there too. In other words, while logicalpriority dictates that one begin with phenomenologyand subsequently move on to normative science (andthen to metaphysics), once normative science is born,there is a movement back again to phenomenology inorder to classify (and so more fully to understand) thenature of the normative. This will become clearer aswe proceed.

Let us begin then with a rapid description of Peirce'sphenomenology, in order to get at his newcategories. Peirce describes the role of this science asfollows:

Page 74: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

But before we can attack any normative science, anyscience which proposes to separate the sheep from thegoats, it is plain that there must be a preliminaryinquiry which shall justify the attempt to establish suchdualism. This must be a science that does not draw anydistinction of good and bad in any sense whatever, butjust contemplates phenomena as they are, simplyopens its eyes and describes what it sees; not what itsees in the real as distinguished from figment notregarding any such dichotomy but simply describing theobject, as a phenomenon, and stating what it finds inall phenomena alike. This is the science which Hegelmade his starting-point, under the name of thePhänomenologie des Geistes although he considered itin a fatally narrow spirit, since he restricted himself towhat actually forces itself on the mind and so coloredhis whole philosophy with the ignoration of thedistinction of essence and existence and so gave it thenominalistic and I might say in a certain sense thepragmatoidal character in which the worst of theHegelian errors have their origin. I will so far followHegel as to call

Page 75: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 11

this science Phenomenology although I will not restrictit to the observation and analysis of experience butextend it to describing all the features that arecommon to whatever is experienced or mightconceivably be experienced or become an object ofstudy in any way direct or indirect. (5.37)

Although Peirce's phenomenological studies beganunder Kant's and not Hegel's influence (cf. e.g. 4.3,4.4), he found that his conclusions and Hegel's werenot so very different, at least in comparison withthose of other philosophers. Hegel was right inmaking phenomenology bring out clearly thecategories of fundamental modes of reality. He wasagain right in distinguishing between universalcategories (all of which apply to everything) andlimited categories (limited to various phases ofevolution); it is with the former that we shall beengaged.

In regard to these [universal categories], it appears tome that Hegel is so nearly right that my own doctrinemight very well be taken for a variety of Hegelianism,although in point of fact it was determined in my mindby considerations entirely foreign to Hegel, at a timewhen my attitude toward Hegelianism was one ofcontempt. There was no influence upon me from Hegelunless it was of so occult a kind as to entirely escape

Page 76: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

my ken; and if there was such an occult influence, itstrikes me as about as good an argument for theessential truth of the doctrine, as is the coincidencethat Hegel and I arrived in quite independent wayssubstantially to the same result. (5.38)

These universal categories, according to Peirce, arethree in number, no more and no less, absolutelyirreducible one to another yet interdependent, anddirectly observable in elements of whatever is at anytime before the mind in any way. Firstness,Secondness, and Thirdness roughly correspond to themodes of being: possibility, actuality, and law(1.23).4

4 Cf. e.g., Peirce's letter to Lady Victoria Welby, Oct.12, 1904 where he defines and explains at lengthFirstness, Secondness, and Thirdness. Charles S.Peirce's Letters to Lady Welby, ed. Irwin C. Lieb (NewHaven: Whitlock's, 1953), pp. 7-14.

Page 77: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 12

The category most easily grasped is that ofSecondness or actuality. It is typified in theexperience of effort, of resistance, of struggle, ofopposition. Actuality consists in a then and there, in arelation to other existents. Briefly, actuality issomething brute brute fact which shocks. There is noreason in it.

I instance putting your shoulder against a door andtrying to force it open against an unseen, silent, andunknown resistance. We have a two-sidedconsciousness of effort and resistance, which seems tome to come tolerably near to a pure sense of actuality.(1.24)

Secondness is the category of experience. Thebreaking of the night's silence by a piercing whistlethe shock and surprise in it reveals a two-sidedconsciousness of an ego and a non-ego. This is whatexperience is what the course of life compels one tothink.5 Firstness is characteristic of the mode of beingwhich consists in its subject's being positively such asit is regardless of anything else (1.25).

For as long as things do not act upon one another thereis no sense or meaning in saying that they have anybeing, unless it be that they are such in themselvesthat they may perhaps come into relation with others.

Page 78: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

The mode of being a redness, before anything in theuniverse was yet red, was nevertheless a positivequalitative possibility. And redness in itself, even if itbe embodied, is something positive and sui generis.(1.25)

Thirdness, on the other hand, characterizes the modeof being of laws governing future events. It manifestsitself in experience through predictions which have adecided tendency to be fulfilled. If a prediction has adecided tendency to be fulfilled it must be that futureevents have a tendency to conform to a general rule.For Peirce, this can only mean that generals or lawsor Thirds are real.

"Oh," but say the nominalists, "this general rule isnothing but a mere word or couple of words!" I reply,"Nobody ever dreamed of denying that what is generalis of the nature of a general sign; but the question iswhether future events will

5Letters to Welby, p. 8-9.

Page 79: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 13

conform to it or not. If they will, your adjective `mere'seems to be ill-placed." (1.26)

Thirdness consists in the fact that future facts ofSecondness will take on a determinate generalcharacter. It is clear, then, that Thirdness ischaracterized by its mediating role. Law, governingevents, mediates between pure possibility (Firstness)and pure actuality (Secondness). Put in logical terms,Thirdness is always and exclusively a triadic relation.

Analyze for instance the relation involved in `A gives Bto C'. Now what is giving? It does not consist in A'sputting B away from him and C's subsequently taking Bup. It is not necessary that any material transfer shouldtake place. It consists in A's making C the possessoraccording to Law. . . . But now suppose that giving didconsist merely in A's laying down the B which Csubsequently picks up. That would be a degenerateform of thirdness in which the thirdness is externallyappended. In A's putting away B, there is no thirdness.In C's taking B, there is no thirdness. But if you say thatthese two acts constitute a single operation by virtue ofthe identity of B, you transcend the mere brute fact,you introduce a mental element. (Letter to LadyVictoria Welby, Lieb's ed., p. 8)

But to be (or at least to involve) a triadic relation is tobe "of the nature of a general sign."6 In psychological

Page 80: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

terms, then, we might express the mediating role ofThirdness this way: Thirdness is the category ofthought, mediating between the Firstness of feelingand the Secondness of reaction. Peirce gathers underThirdness the following: triadic relations, thought,generals, and laws. They all involve a mental elementand yet are real, not just figments of someone'smind. Therefore the mental or the realm of thoughtcannot be limited to a man's "consciousness" (see8.256). Thus it is that the category of Thirdness leadsPeirce to a form of objective idealism which he callssynechism.

The above treatment, of course, is but the barestoutline of

6 Cf. Letters to Welby, pp. 9-14 for an extendeddevelopment of the theory of signs.

Page 81: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 14

Peirce's categories. It will serve, however, to give ussome idea of the schema. Now we must consider fora moment how Peirce conceives Firstness,Secondness, and Thirdness to be related to eachother. On the one hand, it is clear that they areirreducible and omni-present. They describe allphenomena. On the other hand, Peirce tells usexplicitly that the categories are interdependent. Interms of the degrees of separability of ideas, Peirceexplains that the categories cannot be dissociated inthe imagination from each other, nor from otherideas. But one category can be prescinded fromanother in a definite order: Firstness can beprescinded from Secondness and Thirdness,Secondness can be prescinded from Thirdness, butSecondness cannot be prescinded from Firstness, norThirdness from Secondness. Of course, the categoriescan easily be distinguished, but still

. . . it is extremely difficult accurately and sharply todistinguish each from other conceptions so as to hold itin its purity and yet in its full meaning. (1.353)

Perhaps what Peirce has in mind is the fact that atrue appreciation of the categories would require athorough study of the logic of relatives. Peircedevelops his categories in two ways, from "without"

Page 82: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and from "within." The former is throughphenomenology, the latter through the logic ofrelations. The "logical" approach to the categories isthrough an analysis of what is necessarily involved inrepresentations and triadic relations. A thoroughappreciation of the categories requires bothexperience and logic. The categories themselves mustnot be confused with the elements in the categories:a First is not to be confused with Firstness, nor aSecond with Secondness, nor a Third with Thirdness.There can be various combinations of category withcategory, and of element with category. It becomesintricate indeed and requires no little logical skill.While it is not to our purpose to pursue this importantpoint at great length it might be well to discuss someof these combinations briefly.

Peirce tells us that Secondness and Thirdness areconceptions of complexity, although they are notcomplex conceptions (because they are ultimate andirreducible categories of being) (1.525). TakeSecondness for example. Secondness is the categoryof reaction and so naturally we think of two objectsinteracting, a First and a Second.

Page 83: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 15

But it would be a logical mistake to look upon thisdyadic relation as made up of three elements: theFirst, the Second, and their reaction. Secondness isnot built up out of pieces; rather Secondnesspervades the whole relationship. If an object is aSecond, it is a Second precisely because it is in adyadic relation to something else. It has an elementof being what another makes it to be. A fortiori thesame is true of the reaction itself. It is not anotherthing or object, but a fact about two objects (1.526).It follows, then, that one can talk about theSecondness of a Second and the Secondness of aFirst (where the First and Second are in a dyadicrelation), and that the Secondness of the First neednot be the same as the Secondness of the Second.Consider the Secondness of the relation of quality tothe matter in which it inheres (Peirce's ownillustration, 1.527). The quality in itself is a Firstness,a mere possibility. The relation of inherence does notchange the quality in itself, but merely imparts to itexistence. Its existence is nothing but the relation ofinherence in matter. But the situation with regard toits matter is quite different. Matter has no being at allexcept as subject of qualities, that is to say, itsrelation to qualities constitutes its existence. Void of

Page 84: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

all qualities, matter would not only not exist, but itwould have no definite possibility at all it would beunreal it would be nothing at all.

Thus we have a division of seconds into those whosevery being, or Firstness, it is to be seconds, and thosewhose Secondness is only an accretion. (1.528)

The reason is not difficult to find. Basically it is thesame reason which allows one to prescind Firstnessfrom Secondness and Thirdness, and Secondnessfrom Thirdness: the very essence of those categories.

This distinction springs out of the essential elements ofSecondness. For Secondness involves Firstness. Theconcepts of the two kinds of Secondness are mixedconcepts composed of Secondness and Firstness. Oneis the second whose very Firstness is Secondness. Theother is a second whose Secondness is second to aFirstness. (1.528)

Peirce remarks that this way of mingling Firstness andSecondness is distinct from the ideas of Firstness andSecondness which it combines, and so seems to forma different series of categories which, however,

Page 85: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 16

in turn, depend upon Firstness, Secondness, andThirdness as component parts.

The idea of mingling Firstness and Secondness in thisparticular way is an idea distinct from the ideas ofFirstness and Secondness which it combines. It appearsto be a conception of an entirely different series ofcategories. At the same time, it is an idea of whichFirstness, Secondness, and Thirdness are componentparts, since the distinction depends on whether the twoelements of Firstness and Secondness that are unitedare so united as to be one or whether they remain two.(1.528)

Thus arises Peirce's distinction between genuine anddegenerate grades of Secondness. GenuineSecondness is the Secondness of genuine Seconds,or matters; degenerate Secondness is theSecondness of a Second whose mode of being in se isFirstness (quality, in our example). A similar analysismight be made of Thirdness, with the exception thatit will be found to have two grades of degeneracy(1.529). Firstness, of course, cannot have such adistinction.

The categories themselves are capable of similarcombinations, and that because of their very nature.Whenever you have a triplet, you have three pairs;

Page 86: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

where you have a pair, you have two units (1.530).This is why the categories are subject to "prescission"in a certain order (see above). Thus, for example,because Secondness is an essential part of Thirdnessand Firstness is an essential part of both Secondnessand Thirdness, there is a Firstness of Secondness andof Thirdness, and a Secondness of Thirdness, butthere can be no Secondness of pure Firstness norThirdness of pure Firstness or Secondness.

When you strive to get the purest conceptions you canof Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness, thinking ofquality, reaction, and mediation what you are strivingto apprehend is pure Firstness, the Firstness ofSecondness that is what Secondness is, of itself andthe Firstness of Thirdness. When you contrast the blindcompulsion in an event of reaction considered assomething which happens and which of its nature cannever happen again . . . when, I say, you contrast

Page 87: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 17

this compulsion with the logical necessitation ofmeaning considered as something that has no being atall except so far as it actually gets embodied in anevent of thought, and you regard this logicalnecessitation as a sort of actual compulsion, since themeaning must actually be embodied, what you arethinking of is a Secondness involved in Thirdness.(1.530)

Thus we have the following combinations:

1) Firstness of Firstness quality in itself, or"possibility" (Primity)

2) Firstness of Secondness existence or actuality(Secundity)

3) Firstness of Thirdness mentality (Tertiality)

Taking Secondness we find:

1) Secondness of Secondness reaction

2) Secondness of Thirdness law as actualcompulsion

Finally Thirdness gives us:

1) Thirdness of Thirdness generality, lawfulness,reasonableness.7

Page 88: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Since Thirdness is the most important category for aphilosophical analysis and classification of sciences,let us consider it a little more closely. Wherever thereis Thirdness, according to Peirce, there is a First, aSecond and a Third (a triadic relation). The First is apositive qualitative possibility; the Second is anexistent thing determined by that First; and the Thirdis a law, or concept, which determines the relationbetween the First and Second (1.536). But Thirdnesshas a genuine and two degenerate forms. In genuinethirdness, the First, the Second, and the Third are allof the nature of Thirds, or thought. They are First,Second, and Third only relatively to each: the First isthought in its capacity as mere possibility (mindcapable of thinking);

7 Of course these same divisions could be ordered inanother way:

Firstness ofFirstness

Firstness ofSecondness

Firstness ofThirdness

Secondness ofSecondness

Secondness ofThirdnessThirdness ofThirdness

Page 89: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 18

the Second is thought as an event (actual thinkingexperience or information); the Third is thoughtinsofar as it brings information into the mind(informing thought or cognition) (1.537).

Peirce sees in this relationship between a First, aSecond and a Third, the operation of a sign, and interms of the elements in a sign he explains the twodegenerate grades of Thirdness. First of all, a signstands for something other than itself; but that otherfor which it stands can itself only be another sign.The reason is that if the sign is to be affected by theobject, "the object must be able to convey thought,that is, must be of the nature of thought or of a sign"(1.538). Every thought is a sign. In the first degreeof degeneracy, however, the Thirdness affects theobject, whereas in genuine Thirdness the sign is onlyaffected by the object. What happens is that theThird brings about a Secondness which it regards asnothing more than a fact. Peirce calls it the executionof an intention. In the last degree of degeneracythere is thought, "but no conveyance or embodimentof thought at all" (1.538). It is merely theapprehension of a fact according to a possible idea.Peirce calls it instigation without prompting.8 Hegives the example of one's saying "this object is red."

Page 90: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

If the speaker is asked to justify his judgment, hemight say, "I saw it was red." But that is notaccurate. What was seen was simply an image, withno subject or predicate in it, not in the least like aproposition. The image instigated the judgmentowing to the possibility of thought.9

Peirce applied his categorial scheme to philosophy ingeneral and to normative science in particular. Forhim, philosophy has a threefold division:phenomenology, which simply contemplates theuniversal phenomenon; normative science, whichinvestigates the universal and necessary laws of therelation of phenomena to ends; and metaphysics,which endeavors to comprehend the reality ofphenomena (cf. 5.121). Phenomenology is theFirstness of philosophy, since

8 This looks very much like the "simple apprehension"of the older logicians.9 It can now be seen how the two degenerate forms ofThirdness are related to Secondness and to Firstness,respectively. The first degree involves the execution of anintention and hence a will act; the second degree involvesonly the origin of perceptual judgment in a quality offeeling.

Page 91: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 19

it merely contemplates without judging; it merelylooks at and records phenomena as they appear inthemselves regardless of anything else. Normativescience is the Secondness of philosophy, because itstudies the dyadic relation of phenomena to ends andso enables one to form a basis for judging true andfalse, good and bad, beautiful and ugly. Metaphysicsis the Thirdness of philosophy, because it mediatesbetween phenomenology and normative science,between phenomena in themselves and in theirrelation to ends, by a study of the regularity, law, orefficient reasonableness therein involved.

Reality is an affair of Thirdness as Thirdness, that is, inits mediation between Secondness and Firstness. . . .Metaphysics is the science of Reality. Reality consists inregularity. Real regularity is active law. Active law isefficient reasonableness, or in other words is trulyreasonable reasonableness. Reasonablereasonableness is Thirdness as Thirdness. (5.121)

Peirce's division of philosophy, therefore, turns out tobe according to his universal categories (5.121-124).And he tells us that if ''Normative Science does notseem to be sufficiently described by saying that ittreats of phenomena in their secondness, this is anindication that our conception of Normative Science is

Page 92: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

too narrow . . .'' (5.125).

After a good deal of hesitation, Peirce's final opinionwas that there are three normative sciences:esthetics, ethics (practics), and logic (1.573). Thistrio relates to feeling, action, and thought, and assuch relates to the now familiar categories. Thusesthetics sets up norms concerning qualities offeeling or Firstnesses; ethics or practics sets upnorms for judging conduct or Secondnesses; logicsets up norms for deciding what thoughts we shouldentertain and what arguments we should accept,what procedures we should adopt, that is, norms forThirdnesses (1.574). Ethics or practics is what Peircecalls the mid-normative science. It is the normativescience par excellence, since the phenomena which itexamines are Secondnesses (action or conduct)considered in the dyadic relation they form with ends(another level of Secondness). Logic deals withThirdnesses considered in their dyadic relation toends (Secondnesses). Reasoning is but a special caseof controlled action controlled action dealing withThirdnesses and not just with Secondnesses and sologic is a special

Page 93: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 20

case of practics. Esthetics presented some difficulty,however, and caused Peirce to hesitate to include itamong the normative sciences. How can there be anyjudgment as to the goodness or badness of a qualityof feeling? A quality of feeling is just what it iswithout regard to anything else. In other words, howis it possible to get a Secondness from a Firstness?On the other hand, experience teaches that men domake evaluative judgments about qualities of feeling.A distinction is made between the esthetically goodand the esthetically bad. Is it merely a matter oftaste? When we consider in detail the development ofPeirce's thinking about esthetics we will be in a betterposition to know whether these difficulties areresolvable. For the moment, let us just point out thatPeirce's final position (and he claimed for it no morethan an opinion) was that ethics or practics is aspecial case or species of esthetics, becausesomehow or other esthetics deals with the deliberateformation of habits of feeling which ultimately governdeliberate conduct (doing or thinking). It will turn outthat while in one sense the phenomena with whichesthetics deals are ultimately qualities of feeling (andso esthetics truly relates to Firstness), in anothersense esthetics more proximately deals with the

Page 94: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

formation of habits of feeling (not just an isolatedquality) and as such has something of Thirdness orgenerality about it. Isolated qualities of feeling can bejudged good or bad precisely in terms of the habit,which in its turn can be altered, modified or rejectedin terms of experience's shock.10

What do we have so far in Peirce's architectonicpresentation of normative science? Philosophy as apositive science deals with facts facts gotten fromcommon, ordinary, everyday experience. These factsrequire no special apparatus to be observed; they areopen to any one who will take the time and the effortto become aware of them. On the level of what onedoes with this data, philosophy divides in three:taking an inventory (phenomenology Firstness ofphilosophy), evaluation (normative scienceSecondness of philosophy), and comprehension(metaphysics Thirdness of philosophy). Normativescience, of course, is not itself the evaluation ofphenomena, but more precisely the theory of suchevaluation. It subdivides on another

10 Cf. 5.113; see Part I, Chapter 2.

Page 95: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 21

level according to the predominant characteristic ofthe phenomenon studied: quality of feeling (estheticsFirstness of normative science), action (practicsSecondness of normative science), thought (logicThirdness of normative science).

Since, in Peirce's classification of the sciences, logic isagain subdivided into three parts and philosophyitself is a member of another trio, one would be led toexpect that his universal categories apply to thesedivisions too. Consider logic. In one place he tells us:

The term "logic" is unscientifically employed by me intwo distinct senses. In its narrower sense, it is thescience of the necessary conditions of the attainmentof truth. In its broader sense, it is the science of thenecessary laws of thought, or, still better (thoughtalways taking place by means of signs), it is generalsemeiotic, treating not merely of truth, but also of thegeneral conditions of signs being signs (which DunsScotus called grammatica speculativa), also of the lawsof the evolution of thought, which since it coincideswith the study of the necessary conditions of thetransmission of meaning by signs from mind to mind,and from one state of mind to another, ought, for thesake of taking advantage of an old association ofterms, be called rhetorica speculativa, but which Icontent myself with inaccurately calling objective logic,

Page 96: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

because that conveys the correct idea that it is likeHegel's logic. (1.444)

In another place he says:

We come, therefore, to this, that logic treats of thereference of symbols in general to their objects. In thisview it is one of a trivium of conceivable sciences. Thefirst would treat of the formal conditions of symbolshaving meaning, that is of the reference of symbols ingeneral to their grounds or imputed characters, andthis might be called formal grammar; the second, logic,would treat of the formal conditions of the truth ofsymbols; and the third would treat of the formalconditions of the force of symbols, or their power ofappealing to a mind, that is, of their reference ingeneral to interpretants, and this might be calledformal rhetoric. (1.559)

Page 97: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 22

Putting these two passages together, the division of"logic" might be sketched as follows:11

Speculative or formalgrammar, signs as signs

Logic in broadsense(normativelogic)

Logic (in narrow sense), orcritic, truth of signs

Speculative or formalrhetoric, or objective logic,communication of signs

Though Peirce himself never applies his categories tothis division (at least I found no such passage), itseems reasonably clear that he might have done sowith success. Speculative or formal grammar is theFirstness of normative logic, since it deals with signsas signs regardless of anything else. Logic or critic isa plausible candidate for Secondness because ittreats of signs as true or false, that is, in their relationto what they signify. Finally, speculative or formalrhetoric fits the category of Thirdness because ittreats of signs as communicated, that is, not merelyin their relation to what they signify, but for whom

Page 98: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

they signify.

Philosophy itself is one of the three theoreticalsciences of discovery. The other two are mathematicsand idioscopy. All three rest upon observation, butthey are observational in very different senses(1.239). Mathematics does not undertake toascertain any matter of fact, but simply positshypotheses, and traces out their consequences. Andyet it is observational

. . . in so far as it makes constructions in theimagination according to abstract precepts, and thenobserves these imaginary objects, finding in themrelations of parts not specified in the precept ofconstruction. (1.240)

Philosophy deals with "positive truth," but itsobservations are "such as come within the range ofevery man's normal experience, and for the most partin every waking hour of his life" (1.241). Idioscopy,too, deals with "positive truth,'' but the specialsciences which make it up depend upon specialobservation "which travel or other

11 Cf. also 3.430 ff.

Page 99: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 23

exploration, or some assistance to the senses, eitherinstrumental or given by training, together withunusual diligence, has put within the power of itsstudents" (1.242). On this basis, a reasonable casecan be made that the categories apply at this level ofclassification of the sciences, as they should, sincethey are universal. What is required for theobservations peculiar to mathematics? Nothing butthe "observer's" creative imagination. Mathematicsmakes no assertions about the actual, existing worldof experience, but rather explores the great world ofpossibility by means of hypothesis and deduction.Mathematics, then, does not logically requireanything beyond itself it is a First. Philosophy, on theother hand, makes categorical statements aboutreality which claim to be true or false. And accordingto Peirce its type of observation requires not onlyimagination, but also experience. Now experience isin the category of Secondness, and so one could saythat philosophy is a Second. The special sciences,too, make assertions about the world, and theycertainly depend upon experience for theirobservations. Yet their observations are alwaysmediated. It is not a question of common ordinaryexperience which is available to all; it is not, so to

Page 100: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

speak, merely a question of ego confronting non-ego,of observer confronting phenomena. Rather theobserver gets to his phenomena through somethingelse an instrument, a technique, etc. It may beargued, therefore, that the special sciences introducea Third in their observational procedures, and soqualify as a type of Thirdness, perhaps onlydegenerate.

This tentative application of the categories tomathematics, philosophy, and idioscopy is at leastplausible, and if it, or something like it, be admitted,there is a symmetry in Peirce's architectonic. We haveconsidered the application of the categories only tothose sciences with which we are dealing: tophilosophy (relative to mathematics and specialsciences), to normative science (relative tophenomenology and metaphysics), to the divisions ofnormative science, and finally to the subdivisions oflogic. No doubt, a similar analysis could be made forthe other triadic classifications in Peirce's alignmentof the sciences. What we notice is that the categoriesare extremely supple, as indeed they must be if theyare truly universal. They can bend or shift justenough to allow their application to different levels ofanalysis, and yet still keep their shape sufficiently tobe readily recognized. They remind one of the act-

Page 101: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

potency categories of Aristotle

Page 102: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 24

as used in the scholastic systems where they areapplied analogously to different levels of analysis.12

While no aspect of a phenomenon can be classifiedunder two categories at the same level of analysis,that same aspect may receive a different classificationat another level. Thus, for example, Peirce classifiesnormative science as Secondness (relative to theother divisions of philosophy); its own subdivisionsexhibit all three of the categories. Hence, if onealways keeps in mind the level of analysis, theperspective in which Peirce is viewing his subjectmatter, his use of the universal categories will befound to be more consistent than has sometimesbeen thought.

12 Take for example their application in Thomisticmetaphysics to the orders of existence, essence, andactivity, respectively. Basically act means "perfection;"potency "limitation." In the order of existence, esse isact, while essentia is potency. In the order of essence,form is act, while matter is potency. In the order ofactivity, accident is act, while substance is potency.Nothing can be both act and potency within the sameorder, but one may well be act in one order andpotency in another; e.g. substantial form is act in theorder of essence, while essence (and hence substantialform too) is potency in the order of existence.

Page 103: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

We are inclined to think that something like this is whatCharles Hartshorne has in mind when he distinguishes the"relatively absolute" from the "absolutely absolute." Firstsand Seconds of experience are only "relatively absolute,"relative to a context. Cf. ''The Relativity of Nonrelativity,"Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed.by Wiener and Young (Cambridge: Harvard UniversityPress, 1952), pp. 219 ff. and "Charles Peirce's `OneContribution to Philosophy' and His Most Serious Mistake,"Studies, Moore and Robin, pp. 459 ff.

Page 104: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 25

2. Analysis of Normative ScienceNormative Science is the study of what ought to be(1.281), that is, it sets up norms or rules which neednot but ought to be followed (2.156). "Ought" thenexcludes compulsion, coercion, and determinism. It isalways possible to act contrary to the "ought." The"ought" rather implies ideals, ends, purposes whichattract and guide (1.575) deliberate conduct. Peircesometimes refers to normative science as the science''which investigates the universal and necessary lawsof the relation of phenomena to Ends . . ." (5.121).Still, Peirce looks upon normative science as positivescience, that is, as an inquiry which seeks for positiveknowledge expressible in categorical propositions.

By a positive science I mean an inquiry which seeks forpositive knowledge; that is, for such knowledge as mayconveniently be expressed in a categorical proposition.Logic and the other normative sciences, although theyask, not what is but what ought to be, nevertheless arepositive sciences since it is by asserting positive,categorical truth that they are able to show that whatthey call good really is so; and the right reason, righteffort, and right being, of which they treat, derive thatcharacter from positive categorical fact. (5.39)

Page 105: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

The statements of normative science, then, make atruth claim. They are founded in experience thatsame experience upon which philosophy in general isfounded, namely, "which presses in upon every oneof us daily and hourly" (5.120).1

It is understandable, therefore, why Peircesometimes describes normative science as that whichtreats of phenomena in their Secondness (cf. 5.123,125, 110, 111). As a positive science, it deals withfact,

1 Yet in "Minute Logic" written shortly before the 1903Harvard Lectures (that is, ca. 1902), Peirce seems tohave held a different, and perhaps incompatible view.See Appendix I for discussion of this passage.

Page 106: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 26

and fact is in the category of Secondness. Again, itsproper and peculiar appreciations of the facts relateto the conformity of phenomena to ends (themselvesnot immanent in those phenomena) and this isanother dyadic relation or Secondness (5.126). Interms of the relation of phenomena to ends,normative science enables one deliberately toapprove or disapprove certain lines of conduct. Thusit is the science which separates the sheep from thegoats, makes the dichotomy of good and bad (cf.5.37, 110, 111). From every viewpoint normativescience involves an "emphatic dualism" (cf. 5.551).

Since normative science deals with "ought," that is,with deliberate conduct, and since it allows one tomake value judgments concerning such conduct, onemight be tempted to look upon it as an art or apractical science. We have seen that for many yearsPeirce himself so considered ethics (cf. 5.111). YetPeirce insists again and again that normative scienceis purely theoretical, indeed, "the very most purelytheoretical of purely theoretical sciences" (1.282; cf.1.575, 5.125). To say that knowledge of normativescience would directly and in itself either help one tothink more correctly or to live more decently or tocreate more artistically, would be like saying that a

Page 107: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

knowledge of the mechanics involved in a game ofbilliards would allow us to become a master player(cf. e.g. 2.3). A vast knowledge of physics does notmake a good mechanic, nor is it so intended.Normative science looks primarily to an understandingof certain sets of conditions. Of course Peirce seesand explicitly says that normative science is closelyrelated to art (1.575) and that there are "practicalsciences of reasoning and investigation, of theconduct of life, and of the production of works of art''(5.125) which correspond to the normative sciences,"and may be probably expected to receive aid fromthem" (5.125).

But they are not integrant parts of these sciences; andthe reason that they are not so, thank you, is no mereformalism, but is this, that it will be in general quitedifferent men two knots of men not apt to consort theone with the other who will conduct the two kinds ofinquiry. (5.125)

Normative science, then, is theoretical, and accordingto Peirce that is precisely why it is called and must becalled "normative" (1.281). Its business is analysis ordefinition (1.575).

Page 108: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 27

Peirce feels obliged to emphasize that normativescience is not a special science. It is a subdivision ofphilosophy and as such relies on data available toanyone at any time by reflection upon experience. Itdoes not require specialized techniques or apparatusfor its observations as do physics or chemistry orpsychology. Furthermore, he insists that while nowand then philosophy may make use of such specialdata it is not significantly aided thereby not even bythe results of psychology (5.125, 3.428). Thus, Peircefrequently argues, the science of logic, contrary tothe opinion of the German school,2 cannot bereduced to a matter of feeling. Ultimately, anargument cannot be judged valid because of someinstinctive feeling that it is so, nor by any compulsionso to judge, nor by appeal to an intuition (cf. 2.155ff., 2.19, 2.39-51, 3.432). In general, thepsychological fact that men for the most part show anatural tendency to approve the same argumentswhich logic approves, the same acts which ethicsapproves, and the same works of art which estheticsapproves is insufficient support for the conclusions ofthose sciences. And if one were to urge in a particularcase, let us say, that something is logically sound,simply because men have a strong and imperious

Page 109: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

tendency to think so, one would be arguingfallaciously (5.125). It would be much like arguing forthe truth of a proposition from the certitude whichone has about it, instead of justifying one's certitudeby establishing the truth of the proposition. Or to putthe difficulty (and its solution) quite clearly in Peirce'sown terms:

By the theory of cognition is usually meant anexplanation of the possibility of knowledge drawn fromprinciples of psychology. Now, the only soundpsychology being a special science, which ought itselfto be based upon a well-grounded logic, it is indeed avicious circle to make logic rest upon a theory ofcognition so understood. But there is a much moregeneral doctrine to which the name theory of cognitionmight be applied. Namely, it is that speculativegrammar, or analysis of the nature of assertion, whichrests upon

2 E.g. Schröder, Sigwart, Wundt, Schuppe, Erdmann,Bergmann, Glogau, Husserl. Peirce opposes to thisgroup the "English logicians," Boole, De Morgan, J.S.Mill, Venn (cf. "Why Study Logic"). And yet Peirce isvery critical of J.S. Mill for "psychologizing" (cf. 2.39-51).

Page 110: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 28

observations, indeed, but upon observations of therudest kind, open to the eye of every attentive personwho is familiar with the use of language, and which, wemay be sure, no rational being, able to converse at allwith his fellows, and so to express a doubt of anything,will ever have any doubt. (3.432)

In a later paper (written ca. 1906) Peirce makesexactly the same observations and adds a distinctionwhich is quite to the purpose. He says that thoselogicians who make logic rest on psychology confoundpsychical truths with psychological truths (5.485). Ofcourse, logic rests upon the former since they areobservational data ("of the rudest kind") with whichspeculative grammar deals. It is such psychical truthswhich Peirce has in mind when he explicitly admitsthat there is in a sense a compulsion at the base oflogic, a compulsion arising from positive observationof a factual situation, not a compulsion of merefeeling, nor a compulsion based on the principles ofanother theoretical science.

But logic begins to be a positive science; since thereare some things in regard to which the logician is notfree to suppose that they are or are not; butacknowledges a compulsion upon him to assert the oneand deny the other. Thus, the logician is forced bypositive observation to admit that there is such a thing

Page 111: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

as doubt, that some propositions are false, etc. Butwith this compulsion comes a correspondingresponsibility upon him not to admit anything which heis not forced to admit. (3.428)

The mistake of the psychologizing logicians is not somuch to recognize the presence of compulsion ofsome sort, but to make logical consequentialityconsist in "compulsion of thought" (3.432).3

Peirce warned his reader that if he did not see thatnormative science deals with phenomena in theirSecondness, the reason lay in a too narrowconception of that branch of philosophy (5.123). He

3 See also 2.47-48 and cf. Richard J. Bernstein,"Peirce's Theory of Perception" in Studies, Moore andRobin, pp. 165-189, for a thorough analysis of role of"compulsion" in authenticating perceptual judgments.Certitude is not a sign of nor a guarantee of truth.

Page 112: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 29

takes care to point out two ways in which modernphilosophy generally misconstrues the nature ofnormative science. In the passages we are about toconsider his references to these errors areexceedingly brief and so are enigmatic. A certainamount of explanation is necessary to understandwhy Peirce considers them so important and torealize in what ways they differ radically from his ownviews. The first mistake, according to Peirce, is tothink that normative science's chief and only concernis to differentiate goodness and badness and to sayto what degree a given phenomenon is good or bad.The error here is to think of normative sciencemathematically or quantitatively, instead ofqualitatively. The distinctions which are of interest innormative science are those of kind, not of degree.Thus Peirce says that logic, in classifying arguments,recognizes different kinds of truth; ethics admits ofqualities of good; and esthetics is so concerned withqualitative differences ''that, [when they are]abstracted from, it is impossible to say that there isany appearance which is not esthetically good"(5.127). Briefly, the important question for normativescience is not how good something is, but whether itis good at all. Peirce calls this "negative goodness" or

Page 113: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

"freedom from fault."

I hardly need remind you that goodness, whetheresthetic, moral, or logical, may either be negativeconsisting in freedom from fault or quantitativeconsisting in the degree to which it attains. But in aninquiry, such as we are now engaged upon, thenegative goodness is the important thing. (5.127).

Perhaps the reader is asking this question: why doesPeirce consider it so important to mention a pointwhich seems almost obvious? What is back of it? Atentative suggestion comes to mind: the doctrine ofcontinuity. A quantitative treatment of goodness (orbadness) would suppose that it comes in discretepackages, whereas in reality goodness is acontinuum. In a certain sense goodness (or badness)does not admit of degrees. It is of the nature of aquality of a Firstness and is what it is withoutreference to anything else. To be sure, goodnessinvolves a complex relation (e.g. between ends,means, intention, and circumstances), but thegoodness qua goodness is an undifferentiated quality.Thus the old scholastic maxim: bonum ex integracausa; malum ex quocumque defectu. Nor does thisinsight

Page 114: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 30

into the continuity of goodness conflict with our useof comparative and the superlative degrees of theadjective "good," because they refer to a concretesubject participating or sharing in goodness and notto the quality itself. Again, Peirce would not deny thatone might be able to set up a quantitative scale ofmeasurement to indicate the degree in which acertain set of concrete subjects share in goodness,but he would insist that such a scale is alwayssomewhat arbitrary and can never claim exactitude.

The second mistake of modern philosophy in thismatter is to think that normative science relatesexclusively to the human mind.

The beautiful is conceived to be relative to humantaste, right and wrong concern human conduct alone,logic deals with human reasoning. (5.128)

Peirce tells us that in the truest sense these sciencesare sciences of mind, but that the mistake is to thinkof mind in the narrow Cartesian way as somethingwhich "resides" in the pineal gland.

Everybody laughs at this nowadays, and yet everybodycontinues to think of mind in this same general way, assomething within this person or that, belonging to himand correlative to the real world. A whole course of

Page 115: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

lectures would be required to expose this error. I canonly hint that if you reflect upon it, without beingdominated by preconceived ideas, you will soon beginto perceive that it is a very narrow view of mind. Ishould think it must appear so to anybody who wassufficiently soaked in the Critic of the Pure Reason.(5.128)

Indeed it would take "a whole course of lectures" topresent Peirce's theory of mind. Clearly, however,Peirce is here making the same point he made in hisletter to James (8.256) where he labeled asnominalistic (and hence erroneous) the notion thatthought is in consciousness rather thanconsciousness in thought. Mind is thought, andthought is Thirdness, and Thirdness is ubiquitous.The human mind is only one manifestation of Mind,perhaps the highest because it has the greatestcapacity for self-control, but not unique. Here againPeirce is insisting upon the continuity of reality. Ifmind is anywhere,

Page 116: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 31

it is everywhere in one form or another. It is true,however, that in his own usage of the term he is notalways so careful as not to fall into the Cartesianusage.

Peirce accepted the traditional division of normativescience into three disciplines: esthetics, ethics, andlogic, but added his own meanings to them. Thisdivision was in his eyes by no means arbitrary. It hadan inner logic dictated by the very process ofreasoning itself. To appreciate fully the greatimportance Peirce attached to these three disciplinesit is necessary to examine their close interrelation. Itwill become evident, too, that what Peirce means byesthetics, ethics, and logic is not exactly what hadbeen traditionally meant. He tended to keep theterminology because it was close enough to his ownconception to introduce the reader and direct hisattention toward the general area he was to discuss.4It should become clear as we proceed that Peirce'searly hesitation to call ethics a theoretical science andhis persistent doubts about the nature of estheticscan be traced to a confusion in his own mind and inthe literature he read as to what these subjects treat.

Let us begin, then, by examining at length one of

Page 117: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Peirce's earliest presentations of the divisions ofnormative science and their interrelation. In hismanuscript, "Minute Logic" (ca. 1902), he explainsthat after a study of phenomenology one mustundertake "the logic of the normative sciences, ofwhich logic itself is only the third, being preceded byEsthetics and Ethics" (2.197). He tells us that he hadonly recently come to realize the importance ofesthetics in logical theory and that he is notcompletely clear about the matter yet himself (seeabove). He goes on to say, as we have seen, that fora long time he had looked upon ethics as an art andagain that only recently had he come to appreciateits role as a theoretical science and its connectionwith logic (2.198). He had up till then not clearlydistinguished ethics from morality. His mistake was tothink ethics was correctly defined as the science ofright and wrong. Only when he realized that theseare themselves ethical conceptions did he see thatthey could not be used to define ethics.

4 We have already remarked that Peirce did ultimatelysubstitute the term "practics" for "ethics" and warnedthe reader repeatedly that his use of the terms "logic"and "esthetics'' was peculiar. Evidently, he just couldnot think of better designations.

Page 118: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 32

We are too apt to define ethics to ourselves as thescience of right and wrong. That cannot be correct, forthe reason that right and wrong are ethical conceptionswhich it is the business of that science to develope andto justify. A science cannot have for its fundamentalproblem to distribute objects among categories of itsown creation; for underlying that problem must be thetask of establishing those categories. (2.198)

Ethics, then, is not concerned directly withpronouncing this course of action right and thatwrong, but with determining what makes right rightand wrong wrong. It has to do with norms or ideals interms of which those categories have meaning. Peircetherefore came to see ethics as the science of ends.

The fundamental problem of ethics is not, therefore,What is right, but, What am I prepared deliberately toaccept as the statement of what I want to do, what amI to aim at, what am I after? . . . It is Ethics whichdefines that end. (2.198)

Now it becomes clear just what is the relation ofethics to logic. Logic deals with thinking and thinkingis a kind of deliberate activity. It, therefore, has anend. But if ethics is the science which defines the endof any deliberate activity, it also defines the end ofthinking. Logic is a study of the means of attaining

Page 119: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

that end, that is, the study of sound and validreasoning.5 The dependence of logic on ethics,therefore, is apparent. Thus Peirce concludes, "It is,therefore, impossible to be thoroughly and rationallylogical except upon an ethical basis" (2.198).

A similar line of reasoning holds good for esthetics.Peirce began to appreciate its importance as atheoretical science and the foundation of ethics onlywhen he began to realize that it should no more bedefined in terms of beauty than ethics in terms ofright. The reason is the same: the beautiful and theugly are categories within esthetics. It is preciselythese categories which esthetics must establish and

5 Peirce later defines normative science as science ofends. Here he says logic is a science of means. Means,however, are themselves subordinate or partial ends.Thus reasoning has its own end, attaining truth, yetrelative to action it is a means.

Page 120: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 33

justify. Again esthetics, as a theoretical discipline,does not judge this or that to be beautiful or ugly,but tries to decide what makes the beautifulbeautiful, and the ugly ugly. It has to do with normsand ideals in terms of which we can define andultimately apply those categories. And so it is closelyallied with ethics. Peirce reasons this way:

Ethics asks to what end all effort shall be directed. Thatquestion obviously depends upon the question what itwould be that, independently of the effort, we shouldlike to experience. But in order to state the question ofesthetics in its purity, we should eliminate from it, notmerely all consideration of effort, but all considerationof action and reaction, including all consideration of ourreceiving pleasure, everything in short, belonging tothe opposition of the ego and the non-ego. (2.199)

Esthetics, then, deals with ends (or more properly theend) in themselves. It studies the admirable per se,regardless of any other consideration. This is the idealof ideals, the summum bonum.6 As such it needs nojustification, it is what it is and gives meaning to therest. As such it belongs to the category of Firstness.English has no suitable word for it, Peirce observes,but the Greek kalos comes close. "Beautiful" will notdo because kalos must include the unbeautiful as

Page 121: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

well. Whatever term may be chosen to express it, thequestion of esthetics is to determine what isadmirable, and so desirable, in and for itself (2.199).

Upon this question ethics must depend, just as logicmust depend upon ethics. Esthetics, therefore,although I have terribly neglected it, appears to bepossibly the first indispensable propedeutic to logic . . .. (2.199)

Peirce's position in this section of the "Minute Logic"is clear enough and makes good sense in terms of hisrevised notions of ethics

6 The summum bonum ought not to be thought of assimply another member in a series of goods, not eventhe last member. Peirce is not always as clear as mightbe desired in the way he uses the term, but as we shallsee as we continue our analysis he did not fall into thatmistake. Cf. H.W. Schneider, "Fourthness," Studies,Wiener and Young, p. 211.

Page 122: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 34

and esthetics. Human action is reasoned action; butreasoned action is deliberate and controlled.Deliberate and controlled action is action governed byends; but ends themselves may be chosen and thatchoice, in order to be rational, must be deliberate andcontrolled. This ultimately requires the recognition ofsomething admirable in itself. Logic, as the study ofcorrect reasoning, is the science of the means ofacting reasonably. Ethics aids and guides logic byanalyzing the ends to which those means should bedirected. Finally, esthetics guides ethics by definingwhat is an end in itself, and so admirable anddesirable in any and all circumstances regardless ofany other consideration whatsoever. As we shall see,Peirce concludes that this summum bonum is nothingelse than reasoned and reasonable conduct. Ethicsand logic are specifications of esthetics. Ethicsproposes what goals man may reasonably choose invarious circumstances, while logic proposes whatmeans are available to pursue those ends.

A problem arises, however, as we read on in the"Minute Logic." Chapter 4 deals specifically withnormative science and in it Peirce seems to contradictwhat he had said previously. There he seems to denythat pure ethics or esthetics are normative sciences

Page 123: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

at all. He seems to say that only logic is trulynormative. Is there any way around the apparentinconsistency?

Peirce begins this chapter by enumerating variousgeneral positions concerning the number and natureof divisions of normative science. Everyone is agreedthat logic is normative. The majority of writers alsoinclude esthetics and ethics, so that the divisioncorresponds to the ancient triad of ideals: the true,the beautiful, and the good. Others, however, admitonly two normative sciences, namely, logic andethics. The former would consider the conformity ofthought to being; the latter the conformity of beingto thought. According to this position logic and ethicsare normative precisely because nothing can belogically true or morally good without a purpose to beso. Thus the conformity therein involved is controlledand deliberate. But such control seems to beconspicuously lacking when it is a question ofsomething being beautiful or ugly. It simply isbeautiful or is ugly without any purpose so to be.Consequently, on this sort of analysis esthetics isexcluded from the trio (1.575).

Finally, there seems to be some doubt as to whetherethics is truly normative. The subject matter of pureethics is not "right and

Page 124: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 125: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 35

wrong" nor "duties and rights." These are practicalmatters which make "heavy drafts upon wisdom"(1.577). No, these questions are a superstructureraised upon the foundations of pure ethics. Thequestion at the center of pure ethics is, "What isgood?'' and this is not normative, but pre-normative.The reason is, Peirce explains, that

It does not ask for the conditions of fulfillment of adefinitely accepted purpose, but asks what is to besought, not for a reason, but back of every reason.Logic, as a true normative science, supposes thequestion of what is to be aimed at to be alreadyanswered before it could itself have been called intobeing. Pure ethics, philosophical ethics, is notnormative, but pre-normative. (1.577)

It certainly seems that here Peirce makes logic theonly true normative science. This is not to deny,however, that it depends on the answer which ethicsgives to the pre-normative question, "What is good?"And there is no use objecting that logic already hasits own object, truth, because in the final analysislogic must face the question "What is truth?" In otherwords, just what is it that logic seeks? And, of course,this involves the question of ethics in a particularcontext: truth is a good (1.578-579). Truth is nothing

Page 126: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

but a phase of the summum bonum, the subject ofpure ethics (1.575).

There is a real difficulty in reconciling this chapterwith the earlier one. The problem stems from Peirce'sinability to decide clearly, once and for all, just whatis to be included in the discipline called "ethics." He issearching in this work and will continue to searchuntil near the very end of his career when he willdiscard that terminology altogether. The same is trueof his presentation of esthetics, but his difficulty ismore acute. The reader will have perhaps alreadyremarked that in the passages just discussed whatPeirce deems pure, pre-normative, ethics in Chapter4 sounds very much like the esthetics he discussed inan earlier chapter. Nevertheless, the inconsistencieswhich one would expect to find in an original theory(at least in the first stages of articulation) are notdestructive of the essential insight which Peirce istrying to express. Certain clear gains have been madeand the line of thought is beginning to emerge.Furthermore, some remarks can be made whichdiminish somewhat the confusion theseinconsistencies may cause.

Page 127: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 36

In the first place, in reading the ''Minute Logic," onemust remember that it is a book on logic.Consequently, logic will be the center of attentionand the main perspective from which the entire workwill be developed. Thus, for example, in the sectionentitled "Why Study Logic?" Peirce says that he is totreat, not precisely the normative sciences, but "thelogic of the normative sciences" (2.198, emphasisadded). So too, when he points out the importance ofesthetics as "propedeutic to logic'' he concludes that"the logic of esthetics" ought not be omitted from thescience of logic (2.199, emphasis added). This factmight help us to understand in part why Peirce, inChapter 4, makes esthetics and ethics pre-normative.His main interest is logical; logic for certain is a "truenormative science;" esthetics and ethics arenecessary "propedeutics;" hence from that point ofview one could think of them as in a sense pre-normative that is, pre-logical. There is some textualevidence that Peirce was thinking of the topic in thisway. Thus, after he reviewed the current opinions asto the number of normative sciences, he remarks:

Those writers, however, who stand out for the trinity ofnormative sciences do so upon the ground that theycorrespond to three fundamental categories of objects

Page 128: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of desire. As to that, the logician may be exemptedfrom inquiring whether the beautiful is a distinct idealor not; but he is bound to say how it may be with thetrue . . . . (1.575)

Peirce, then, writing as a logician, explicitly disclaimsany responsibility for settling the question of thenumber of normative sciences. The only point he feelsobliged to make is that the true is an aspect of thegood and that therefore logic can be studiedsatisfactorily only once it has taken into considerationits purpose and end.

In the second place, Peirce identifies the usualtripartite division of normative science in his chapteron ethics with positions he had criticized earlier. Thisis clearly the case in his discussion of esthetics, and acase, less strong perhaps, might also be made forwhat he says about ethics. Remember that he saidthat the usual division of the normative sciences intologic, ethics, and esthetics makes their objects thetrue, the good, and the beautiful. Yet earlier he hadsaid that esthetics had been seriously handicappedby its definition as the science of the beautiful. Nowthe apparent inconsistency with respect

Page 129: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 37

to what Peirce says about esthetics might bediminished if we look at it this way: those who (likeSchleiermacher) would exclude esthetics from thenormative sciences are correct if esthetics is taken tobe concerned with the doctrine of the beautiful. Thereason would be simply this: if the beautiful is thesubject about which esthetics concerns itself and notmerely a category within that science, it must be anultimate, self-justifying category, and as such couldbe known only through intuition. There could be noargument about it; it could not be subjected to anycriticism; there could be no legitimate and resolvabledifference of opinion. One would see that X isbeautiful or he would not. In other words, estheticscould not be a science which would allow one todecide and to judge that something is beautiful ornot. It would not be normative at all; it would be onlyphenomenological. The beautiful would be a "non-natural quality" and any attempt to analyze it wouldbe to fall into the "naturalistic fallacy." On this view,then, it would be correct to say that esthetics is notnormative, but perhaps pre-normative. On the otherhand, if, as Peirce did in the earlier section of the''Minute Logic," one defined esthetics as the scienceof the admirable per se, it could be considered

Page 130: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

normative precisely because it investigates the ideal,in terms of which one could separate the sheep fromthe goats, the beautiful from the ugly, and defendand justify that discriminatory judgment in terms of anorm. It is doubtful whether Peirce saw thisdistinction clearly here because in a later discussionhe will still be struggling with the question of whetherthere can be such a thing as esthetic goodness andbadness. Yet if it is admitted that this analysis couldhave been lurking just behind the clarity ofconsciousness, then all that would have beennecessary for Peirce to avoid his apparentinconsistency would have been to state that he wasdiscussing two different conceptions of esthetics.

A similar, although perhaps a less convincing, casemight be made out for what he says about ethics.The difficulty here, however, is that the formermistake to which he objected was not in definingethics as concerned with the good, but as concernedwith right and wrong, duties and rights. Still,although he is not as explicit about it as in the caseof esthetics, we think that his thinking is the same.For if one takes the good as the object of ethicalstudy and not as a category within the science, againit becomes an ultimate, which cannot

Page 131: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 38

be judged but merely recognized. Such a studycannot be normative, but only pre-normative. Itcannot justify the distinction of good and bad, it canonly intuit it as a primitive given. Again we have thefamiliar notion of G.E. Moore. If Peirce had this inmind as the paradigm of theoretical ethics when hewrote the fourth chapter of the "Minute Logic," it isunderstandable why he looked upon ethics as pre-normative. On the other hand, if in the earlier sectionhe was objecting to the indescribability of goodness,and rejecting at least implicitly the "naturalisticfallacy" as no fallacy at all, then he would be justifiedin making ethics a theoretical, normative science, ascience of ends, in terms of which one might judgegoodness and badness, in so far as goodness andbadness were not "non-natural" properties butrelations of conformity and disconformity to ends.7

In any case Peirce has made this significant gain: hehas seen that truth and goodness are intimatelyconnected. He will exploit this insight in hisPragmatism Lectures of 1903. There he will strive toshow that logic, ethics, and esthetics deal with threekinds of goodness, and that this goodness isultimately reasonableness manifesting

Page 132: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

7 We suspect that what Peirce is trying to express issomething akin to the scholastic distinction betweentranscendental and predicamental categories.Traditionally the scholastics looked upon Oneness,Truth, and Goodness (some included Beauty) as theabsolutely universal categories which attached to beingas being independently of and thus cutting across allgenera and species. These transcendental categoriesare not really distinct from being itself, but are merelythree aspects of it, three ways in which man canconsider it. When these transcendentals are predicatedof this or that being they are so by analogy. Becausethese categories are transcendental, they can only bediscovered by phenomenological analysis. Thescholastics distinguished between these ultimate,absolutely universal categories and particularcategories affine to the former. Thus, for example, theydistinguished logical and moral truth from one anotherand from the universal category, ontological truth.Again they distinguished moral or ethical goodnessfrom ontological goodness. The normative sciences oflogic and ethics, in terms of the transcendentalcategories of truth and goodness, set up norms fordeciding the logical truth or falsity of propositions andarguments, and for deciding the moral goodness orbadness of such and such deliberate conduct. PerhapsPeirce was unconsciously sliding from one type ofcategory to the other, and thus at one time saw ethicsas prenormative and at another as normative.

Page 133: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 134: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 39

itself in three different ways. Let us consider in somedetail what he had to say in those famous lectures.

In the first lecture, "Pragmatism: The NormativeSciences," Peirce again tells us that traditionally thenormative sciences have been numbered as three,logic, ethics, and esthetics, and that he will continueto employ those terms. He characterizes thesesciences as those which distinguish good and bad inthe representations of truth, in the efforts of the will,and in objects regarded simply in their presentation,respectively (5.36). Thus he begins to developexplicitly the notion that the sciences in question alldeal with kinds of goodness.

The purpose of this first lecture was to sketch theconnection between his form of pragmatism and thenormative sciences. Although we will examine thisessential point in detail later in this chapter, it isnecessary for our understanding of the doctrine ofnormative science to consider how Peirce laid out histhought in this matter. After having expounded hismaxim, he makes this important inference:

For if, as pragmatism teaches us, what we think is tobe interpreted in terms of what we are prepared to do,then surely logic, or the doctrine of what we ought to

Page 135: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

think, must be an application of the doctrine of whatwe deliberately choose to do, which is Ethics. (5.35)

Pragmatism is a doctrine of logic. It is a logicalmethod helping us to know just what we think, justwhat we believe. Our thought's meaning is to beinterpreted in terms of our willingness to act uponthat thought it is to be interpreted in terms of itsconceived consequences. Peirce, then, sees aconnection between thinking and doing, and so aconnection between good thinking and good doing.What we are prepared to accept as proper conduct,good conduct, approvable conduct, as theinterpretant of our thinking, must be the measure ofproper, good, acceptable, logical thinking. Thus logicdepends upon ethics. But in its turn ethics mustdepend upon something else. Conduct is approved ordisapproved to the degree that it conforms or fails toconform to some purpose, but the question remainsas to what purposes are to be adopted in the firstplace.

Page 136: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 40

But we cannot get any clue to the secret of Ethics . . .until we have first made up our formula for what it isthat we are prepared to admire. I do not care whatdoctrine of ethics be embraced, it will always be so.(5.36)

To determine what we are prepared to admire, whatis admirable per se, is the task of esthetics.

It [Ethics] supposes that there is some ideal state ofthings which, regardless of how it should be broughtabout and independently of any ulterior reasonwhatsoever, is held to be good or fine. In short, ethicsmust rest upon a doctrine which, without at allconsidering what our conduct is to be, divides ideallypossible states of things into two classes, those thatwould be admirable and those that would beunadmirable, and undertakes to define what it is thatconstitutes the admirableness of an ideal. (5.36)

Esthetics, then, attempts to analyze the summumbonum, the absolutely ideal state of things which isdesirable in and for itself regardless of any otherconsideration whatsoever. Esthetics studies the idealin itself, ethics the relation of conduct to the ideal,and logic the relation of thinking to approvedconduct.8

In the following lectures in the series Peirce continues

Page 137: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

to hammer home the key insight into the normativesciences: they all have to do with goodness andbadness, with approval and disapproval. Thus theessence of logic is to criticize arguments, that is, topronounce them acceptable or not, good or bad(5.108). But to say that certain arguments are goodor bad implies that they are subject to control. It

8 It must not be imagined that esthetics and ethics donot involve logic. They do because they are theoreticalsciences. Therefore, it would be incorrect to think thatPeirce held for a purely emotive conception of ethics,or a purely subjective conception of esthetics (not tobe confused with mere taste). All three normativesciences involve deliberate approval, and hence arebased on reasoning. The distinction to be kept in mindis that between logica utens and logica docens whichPeirce himself never tires of making. Logic as anormative science is docens a thinking about thinkingwherever it may occur. That Peirce was aware of thepossibility of confusion on this point is evidenced by hisconstant rebuttal of any type of hedonism as illogicaland hence unreasonable.

Page 138: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 41

supposes that in the future we can avoid using badarguments and strive to use good ones. Indeed, thevery notion of criticism implies the ability to controland to correct.

Any operation which cannot be controlled, anyconclusion which is not abandoned, not merely as soonas criticism has pronounced against it, but in the veryact of pronouncing that decree, is not the nature ofrational inference is not reasoning. Reasoning asdeliberate is essentially critical, and it is idle to criticizeas good or bad that which cannot be controlled.Reasoning essentially involves self-control; so that thelogica utens is a particular species of morality. (5.108)

The distinction between logical truth and falsity,then, is nothing but the distinction between logicalgoodness and badness, which in turn is only a specialcase of moral goodness and badness.

This is the very heart of the matter. It is the veryheart of Peirce's logic and of his entire philosophicaloutlook. To make a normative judgment is to criticize;to criticize is to attempt to correct; to attempt tocorrect supposes a measure of control over what iscriticized in the first place. Any other kind of criticism,any other conception of goodness and badness is idle(cf. 2.26). In this Peirce was directly opposed to

Page 139: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

almost all other schools of thought of his day.9 Two ofthese positions Peirce considered to be of particularimportance because their objections to his ownposition are serious and not easily answered. The firstobjection says that Peirce's position makes logic aquestion of psychology (5.110). This is J.S. Mill's viewand one which Peirce criticized at length again andagain (see e.g. 2.47-51). The principle on which Millbased his opinion is that to say how a man ought tothink has to be based ultimately on how he mustthink. In the passage we are now examining Peircedoes not take up a detailed reply. In like manner, wewill content ourselves with Peirce's simple denial ofthe allegation.

The first [objection] is that this [Peirce's position] ismaking logic a question of psychology. But this I deny.Logic does

9 For Peirce's survey of opinions, 13 in all, see 2.19-78.

Page 140: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 42

rest on certain facts of experience among which arefacts about men, but not upon any theory about thehuman mind or any theory to explain facts. (5.110)

Psychology, like any science, theorizes about facts. InPeirce's view, logic itself theorizes about facts and notabout another theory. The second objection is moreserious and on Peirce's own admission deceived himfor many years (5.111). It argues that by makinglogic dependent upon ethics, and ethics dependentupon esthetics, Peirce in effect has fallen into theerror of hedonism. What is more, such an hierarchicalarrangement of the normative sciences involves abasic confusion of the categories of Firstness andSecondness (5.110). Clearly this objection is adifficulty which Peirce proposed to himself and whichprevented him for a long time from seeing theimportance of normative science for his own thought.On the one hand, he had been convinced from earlyin his career of the error of hedonism, and on theother hand, he did not clearly see how to avoid aninconsistency in his doctrine of the categories if heaccepted the traditional triple division of normativescience.10 Let us consider in some detail, then, howPeirce resolved this problem.

The answer came to him through a more penetrating

Page 141: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

analysis of his categories. He began to realize thatone can and does have a representation of a Secondor a First as well as of a Third. With this new light itwas clear to him that

To say that morality, in the last resort, comes to anesthetic judgment is not hedonism but is directlyopposed to hedonism. (5.111)

How is this so? Consider the phenomena of pleasureand pain to which the hedonist appeals as theultimate factors in a man's choice. They are notmainly phenomena of feeling at all (5.112). Peircesays that, despite his special training in recognizingqualities of feeling, he cannot discover any suchquality common to all pains (5.112). All that carefulobservation reveals is that "there are certain states ofmind, especially among states of mind in whichFeeling has a large share,

10 The difficulty he felt was something like this: thethree universal categories are irreducible; but logicclearly deals with Thirds, ethics with Seconds, andesthetics with Firsts. How then can one consistentlyseek the source of a Third in a Second and the sourceof a Second in a First?

Page 142: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 43

which we have an impulse to get rid of" (5.112). Toadd that such an impulse is excited by a commonquality of feeling is a theory, not a fact. Hedonism,therefore, cannot claim to be a datum of experiencealthough, like any other theory, it appeals toexperience for confirmation. Furthermore, grantingthat the phenomena of pleasure and of pain areprominent only in those states of mind in whichfeeling is predominant, they do not consist in anycommon feeling-quality of pleasure or of pain (evensupposing that there are such qualities) (5.113). Ifone analyzes the phenomenon of pain, he will seethat it consists in "a Struggle to give a state of mindits quietus" (5.113). It is therefore, in essence, anevent, an actuality, and not just a mere quality offeeling, or, in terms of the categories, pain isessentially a Second and not a First, althoughundoubtedly it is accompanied by a First. A similaranalysis of pleasure will reveal that it consists in "apeculiar mode of consciousness allied to theconsciousness of making a generalization, in whichnot Feeling, but rather Cognition is the principleconstituent" (5.113). In other words, Peirce analyzespleasure as a sort of Third an affair of mind and notof mere conscious feeling.11

Page 143: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

. . . and it seems to me that while in estheticenjoyment we attend to the totality of Feeling andespecially to the total resultant Quality of Feelingpresented in the work of art we are contemplating yetit is a sort of intellectual sympathy, a sense that here isa Feeling that one can comprehend, a reasonableFeeling. I do not succeed in saying exactly what it is,but it is a consciousness belonging to the category ofRepresentation, though representing something in theCategory of Quality of Feeling. (5.113)

Thus, to make esthetics the science upon which theother two normative

11 For Peirce consciousness is merely a collection ofqualities of feeling, or rather, qualities of feeling arethe contents of consciousness."My taste must doubtless be excessively crude, because Ihave no esthetic education; but as I am at presentadvised the esthetic Quality appears to me to be the totalunanalyzable impression of a reasonableness that hasexpressed itself in a creation. It is a pure Feeling but afeeling that is the impress of a Reasonableness thatCreates. It is the Firstness that truly belongs to aThirdness in its achievement of Secondness" (from thefirst draft of Lecture V of the Lectures on Pragmatism.Peirce Papers, #310).

Page 144: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 44

sciences depend is not to subscribe to hedonism andis not to confuse the categories. The categories arenot confused because esthetics deals with therepresentation (a Third) of a quality of feeling (aFirst), just as ethics deals with a representation (aThird) of an action (a Second) and logic with arepresentation of thought (a Third). Again hedonismis avoided because in this view pleasure consists insomething intellectual; it is not the case thatsomething is deliberately approved because it ispleasurable, but something is pleasurable(esthetically pleasing) because it is approved.Perhaps it would be more accurate to say that Peirceis saying that something is pleasurable because it isreasonable, and not vice versa.12

In the lectures on pragmatism, therefore, Peirce hasonce and for all linked logical truth and falsity tomoral goodness and badness. He is still not absolutelysure that there is a science of esthetics (so that moralgoodness and badness would be a species of estheticgoodness and badness), but he is inclined so to thinkand assumes that there is for the sake of developinghis line of thought (5.129). It is essential to noticethat Peirce at this point has made an importantconnection between goodness and badness and

Page 145: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

conformity or disconformity to an end or ideal.Normative science in general is the science of thelaws of conformity of things to ends; normativesciences in particular are distinguished in terms ofwhat sort of "things" one is considering in relation totheir ends.

. . . esthetics considers those things whose ends are toembody qualities of feeling, ethics those things whoseends lie in action, and logic those things whose end isto represent something. (5.129)13

The "things" he is talking about are more preciselyaspects or modes of things corresponding to thesethree universal categories of Firstness, Secondness,and Thirdness. In scholastic terms we might say thatPeirce distinguishes these sciences by their "formalobjects." Qua

12 Perhaps the reader sees in what direction this lineof thinking will take Peirce: the admirable in itself isthe growth of reasonableness in the world. Peircedevelops this theme at length in a paper called "Idealsof Conduct" part of his Lowell Lectures of 1903 (1.591-615). We will have occasion to take it up in detail inanother place.13 Cf. also 3.430 ff.

Page 146: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 45

sciences, however, each normative science employsrepresentations of its formal object, and theserepresentations are of course Thirds. Qua normativeeach of these sciences treats its object in itsSecondness, precisely because it is engaged injudging good and bad within the phenomenaconsidered.

In the remainder of the section we have beenconsidering (5.130) Peirce argues in much the sameway as he did before. Logic criticizes and classifiesarguments. This criticism and classification impliesqualitative approval (or disapproval) of the argumentsso analyzed. In turn approval supposes control ofwhat we approve. Hence inference is a voluntary act.But approval of a voluntary act is a moral approval.Hence logic is a kind of moral conduct and so issubject to ethical norms. At this point, however,Peirce again mentions some lingering doubts aboutesthetics.

Ethics the genuine science of normative ethics, ascontradistinguished from the branch of anthropologywhich in our day often passes under the name of ethicsthis genuine ethics is the normative science parexcellence, because an end the essential object ofnormative science is germane to a voluntary act in a

Page 147: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

primary way in which it is germane to nothing else. Forthat reason I have some lingering doubt as to therebeing any true normative science of the beautiful.(5.130)

The emphasis has shifted from that of the "MinuteLogic." We have seen that there logic upstaged everyother consideration to the point that Peirce calledpure ethics "pre-normative." Here Peirce stresses thedependence of logic on ethics and he has come tosee that ethics, not logic, is the normative sciencebecause reasoning in the last analysis is a voluntaryact. But precisely because of this insight he findsdifficulty in fitting esthetics into the scheme. Theproblem is always the same: things seem to bebeautiful or ugly independently of any purpose (cf.above and our remarks about "the beautiful" beingthe object of esthetics). Still, if by the "beautiful" wemean what is kalos, what is admirable in itself, Peircefeels that the only kind of goodness such an ideal canhave is esthetic, and so the morally good is a speciesof the esthetically good after all.

On the other hand, an ultimate end of actiondeliberately

Page 148: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 46

adopted that is to say, reasonably adopted must be astate of things that reasonably recommends itself initself aside from any ulterior consideration. It must bean admirable ideal, having the only kind of goodnessthat such an ideal can have; namely, estheticgoodness. From this point of view the morally goodappears as a particular species of the esthetically good.(5.130)

But just what is the esthetically good? What is theadmirable in itself? In the first place, according to thedoctrine of the categories, it must be of the nature ofa First. It must be some positive, simple, immediatequality pervading a multitude of parts. It makes nodifference what subjective effect that quality mayproduce in us; it is esthetically good.

In the light of the doctrine of categories I should saythat an object, to be esthetically good, must have amultitude of parts so related to one another as toimpart a positive simple immediate quality to theirtotality; and whatever does this is, in so far,esthetically good, no matter what the particular qualityof the total may be. If that quality be such as tonauseate us, to scare us, or otherwise disturb us to thepoint of throwing us out of the mood of estheticenjoyment . . . then the object remains none the lessesthetically good, although people in our condition areincapacitated from a calm esthetic contemplation of it.

Page 149: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(5.132)

But from this account follow a number of startlingand paradoxical conclusions. In the first place, thereis no such thing as positive esthetic badness.Everything is what it is, and as such has some qualitypervading its totality. Everything, then, to this extentis esthetically good. (The scholastics called thisontological goodness.) In the second place, if oneconsiders goodness and badness as relative terms,then one might also correctly say that there is nosuch thing as esthetic goodness. This is the veryconclusion that Peirce draws (5.132). All that one hasis various esthetic qualities, which are what they are.

All there will be will be various esthetic qualities; thatis, simple qualities of totalities not capable of fullembodiment in the parts, which qualities may be moredecided and strong

Page 150: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 47

in one case than in another. But the very reduction ofthe intensity may be an esthetic quality; nay, it will beso; and I am seriously inclined to doubt there beingany distinction of pure esthetic betterness andworseness. My notion would be that there areinnumerable varieties of esthetic quality, but no purelyesthetic grade of excellence. (5.132)

What is back of Peirce's continual hesitation aboutesthetics is perhaps becoming clearer. It seems to bethis: normative science supposes criticism andcontrol; but esthetic qualities seem to be just whatthey are regardless of anything else and so arebeyond criticism and beyond control. The distinctionof good and bad implies approval and disapproval.But in what sense can one approve or disapprove ofsomething which is ultimate? In a way one can onlyrecognize it for what it is, unless one's approval of anaim makes it ultimate. Peirce, however, cannotsubscribe to that without reservation since it wouldmake the ultimate subjective and arbitrary.

Thus Peirce, in the following paragraph, considersanother moment in the process of adopting ideals,namely, the instant when an esthetic ideal isproposed as an ultimate end of action. Now it is nolonger simply a question of considering the ideal in

Page 151: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

itself, but a question of one's adopting or rejectingthat ideal. Peirce talks in terms of Kant's categoricalimperative pronouncing for or against it with thisimportant difference, namely, that while for Kant thatimperative is itself beyond our control, for Peirce it isnot. The imperative itself is open to criticism and thisis what makes it rational (5.133). At this point, then,there is room for a distinction between good and badaims: a good aim is one that can be consistentlypursued; a bad aim is one that cannot. It follows,then, that a bad aim could not be ultimate.14 A goodaim, Peirce tells us, becomes ultimate once it isunfalteringly adopted because then it is beyondcriticism (5.133).

The question, therefore, is to ascertain what end orends are possible, that is, what end or ends can beconsistently pursued under all possiblecircumstances. This is the problem of the summumbonum. The difficulty, however, is that here Peircemakes this inquiry a

14 An ultimate aim is what would be pursued under allpossible circumstances (5.134) and hence would not bedisturbed by one's subsequent experiences (5.136).

Page 152: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 48

problem of ethics and not of esthetics as he had donein an earlier paper. Again, the general line of Peirce'sthinking in this matter is clear enough, but he ishaving a great deal of trouble classifying the stepsaccording to the traditional triad of normativesciences. Perhaps at this point it would be well toconsider Peirce's final formulation of the normativesciences and see how he recognized and met thesedifficulties.

In the ''Basis of Pragmatism'' (1905-06), Peirce in hisusual way shows that "the control of thinking with aview to its conformity to a standard or ideal is aspecial case of the control of action" (1.573). Thusthe theory of controlled thinking, "logic," must be aspecial determination of the theory of controlledaction what he has up to now called "ethics." Thetheory of the control of conduct and action in generalis the second of the trio of normative sciences andthe one "in which the distinctive characters ofnormative science are most strongly marked." Whatshould this science be called?

Since the normative sciences are usually held to bethree, Logic, Ethics, and [Esthetics], and since he[Peirce], too, makes them three, he would term themid-normative science ethics if this did not seem to be

Page 153: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

forbidden by the received acception of that term.(1.573)

At last Peirce seems to have become aware of one ofthe obstacles in his earlier attempts to classify the"mid-portion of coenoscopy" the usual way in whichthe term "ethics" had been used. Traditional treatiseson ethics included much more than Peirce wanted toinclude in the mid-normative science. Thus, forinstance, they included analyses of the ideal orsummum bonum to which action was to conform.Peirce, however, wishes to make the mid-normativescience only a theory of the conformity of action to anideal, reserving the study of the ideal itself foranother science, esthetics. This throws a good deal oflight on the apparent confusion in Peirce's lectures onpragmatism discussed in the preceding paragraphs.There he was using the term "ethics" in its traditionalsense and applying it to the mid-normative science.Hence what he included under "ethics" and"esthetics" overlapped. To make the distinctionsharper he proposes new terminology.

He [Peirce] accordingly proposes to name the mid-normative science, as such (whatever its content maybe) antethics,

Page 154: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 49

that is, that which is put in place of ethics, the usualsecond member of the trio. It is the writer's opinionthat this antethics should be the theory of theconformity of action to an ideal. Its name, as such, willnaturally be practics. Ethics is not practics . . . . (1.573)

Peirce's problem with esthetics had always been tomake sense of goodness and badness applied toesthetic qualities since they seemed to be entirelybeyond criticism and control. By the time he wrotethe "Basis of Pragmatism" a number of considerationshad helped him come to a satisfactory solution. Theline of reasoning which would offer an answer seemsevident. What is required is a distinction betweenesthetic qualities in themselves, that is, in their ownintrinsic reality, and the conscious adoption of themas ideals to be pursued. Similarly, in the case of theultimate aim, the summum bonum, a distinctionneeds to be made between its own objective realityand its conscious acceptance and approval. Armedwith this sort of distinction one could argue that thebusiness of esthetics is to seek out through reflectiveanalysis (see 1.580) what end is ultimate (can beconsistently pursued in any and all circumstances)and to use this as a norm in adopting any particularesthetic quality as an ideal. According to this account

Page 155: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of esthetics there would be the necessary element ofcriticism and control even with respect to thesummum bonum, not in the sense that the objectivereality of that bonum would be affected, but in thesense that one would accept it and conform to itwillingly and deliberately.15 The only question iswhether or not Peirce had such an explanation inmind.

There can be little real doubt that Peirce did come tothis sort of solution, although a detailed proof wouldrequire many more pages of analysis than areavailable.16 There is sufficient evidence for our

15 One might refuse to recognize or to accept theultimare good, but then that would be to actunreasonably and so to act without true liberty. Cf.1.602: "My account of the facts, you will observe,leaves a man at full liberty, no matter if we grant allthat the necessitarians ask. That is, the man can, or ifyou please is compelled, to make his life morereasonable. What other distinct idea than that, I shouldbe glad to know, can be attached to the word liberty?"Cf. also 5.339 n.16 We think that such a proof would have to consider atleast the following: (1) Peirce's distinction betweenmotive and ideal, (2) his realization

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 156: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 157: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 50

immediate purpose in the following section from the1906 paper, "Basis of Pragmatism":

Every action has a motive; but an ideal only belongs toa line [of] conduct which is deliberate. To say thatconduct is deliberate implies that each action, or eachimportant action, is reviewed by the actor and that hisjudgment is passed upon it, as to whether he wisheshis future conduct to be like that or not. His ideal is thekind of conduct which attracts him upon review. Hisself-criticism, followed by a more or less consciousresolution that in its turn excites a determination of hishabit, will, with the aid of the sequelae, modify a futureaction; but it will not generally be a moving cause toaction. It is an almost purely passive liking for a way ofdoing whatever he may be moved to do. Although itaffects his own conduct, and nobody else's, yet thequality of feeling (for it is merely a quality of feeling) isjust the same, whether his own conduct or that ofanother person, real or imaginary, is the object of thefeeling; or whether it be connected with the thought ofany action or not. If conduct is to be thoroughlydeliberate, the ideal must be a habit of feeling whichhas grown up under the influence of a course of self-criticisms and of hetero-criticisms; and the theory ofthe deliberate formation of such habits of feeling iswhat ought to be meant by esthetics. (1.574)

The first thing to notice is that in this passage it is

Page 158: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

not a question of the ideal in itself, but rather theideal as the agent's. It is a question of what attractshim upon review. Thus Peirce has shifted theemphasis from the admirable per se to aconsideration of the habit of feeling in the agent inthe presence of certain ends proposed as ideals. Anend is made the agent's ideal through the mediationof habit, and in its turn habit, by its aspect ofefficacious determination, will modify action in termsof the ideal so adopted. The second thing to remarkis that the habits of feeling through which one makesan ideal one's own are subject to criticism andcontrol. They develop; they are

(footnote continued from previous page)

that ideals can influence man's actions in differentways and in different degrees of awareness, and (3)the role of habit in deliberate conduct. We will havesomething to say about (3) in the course of this study.

Page 159: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 51

modified; they are corrected. Consequently, theideals which one adopts are subject to criticism andcontrol or, more precisely, the adoption of this or thatideal is subject to control. In the case of the ultimateideal or summum bonum, of course, its deliberateadoption is conditioned only by its recognition, sincerefusal to make it one's own would involve the livingcontradiction of a rational man using his reason inorder to be irrational. To put it another way, rejectionof an ideal recognized as ultimate would be to refuseto accept the inevitable finality of human activity.17The recognition of the summum bonum is a questionof comparing experience with the transcendentalcondition of such an ultimate, namely, that it is suchthat it can be pursued in any and everycircumstance. Thus when the pursuit of an ideal isrendered impossible it cannot be ultimate (cf. 1.599ff.). According to Peirce, then, habits of feeling andthe adoption of ideals are subject to criticism andcontrol, and indeed must be if they are to be calledreasonable. Thus esthetics is truly a normativescience if it be thought of as the science of thedeliberate formation of such habits of feeling.

17 This is perhaps possible for more or less longperiods of time, but it seems to us that unless one

Page 160: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

abandon all thinking about the problem, he wouldsooner or later have to capitulate.

Page 161: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 52

3. Pragmatism & the Normative SciencesEven as a boy Peirce was interested in the normativesciences. He recounts how he picked up his elderbrother's textbook in logic and worked right throughit on his own. Undoubtedly his mathematician fatherencouraged and directed this interest. Logic,however, was not the only normative science towhich he early applied himself. He tells us that as anundergraduate at Harvard (ca. 1855) he expoundedas best he could Schiller's Aesthetische Briefe to hisfriend Horatio Paine (2.197). Almost fifty years laterhe expressed regret that he had not seriouslyfollowed up this study, because he then saw howfundamental it was to a theory of knowledge (2.120,2.197, 5.129 ff.).

Although logic received most of Peirce's attentionthroughout his long career, still he tells us that hehad always been interested in ethical systems(2.198). Until the '80's, however, he consideredethics to be nothing more than an art or practicalscience which relied little upon theoretical principles.It should be remembered that the first formulation ofthe pragmatic maxim (which he later called "a rough

Page 162: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

approximation" 5.16) and his analysis of belief interms of what one is willing to act upon appeared inthe '70's. Peirce says that he first began to see theimportance of ethical theory around 1882 (2.198). Atthat time he started to distinguish morality from"pure" ethics. As a result of this illumination he tookup a serious study of the great moralists (5.111,5.129) and began to suspect that there was someimportant connection between ethics and logic(5.111). It was only some ten years later (ca. 1894)that this suspicion became a firm conviction (2.198)and only in about 1899 was he ready to say thatethics is truly a normative science (5.129). Peirce'sjudgment in this matter, therefore, was certainly nothasty. Rather it was the result of long reflectionduring the height of his intellectual powers (in 1899Peirce was only 58 years old). Finally in 1903 Peircemade public for the first time his conclusions in theLowell Lectures (5.533). Yet even then he was notprepared to say apodictically that esthetics is anormative science and indeed the science uponwhich both ethics and

Page 163: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 53

logic ultimately rest. He is content with the modestproposal of an opinion and an hypothesis (5.129,2.197).

In the Cambridge lectures of 1903 Peirce explicitlyrelated his doctrine about the normative sciences tothe correct understanding of pragmatism as he firstused the term. He tells us that once one sees thatthe normative sciences in general examine the lawsof conformity of things to ends, one begins "to getupon the trail of the secret of pragmatism" (5.130).What then was the development of the "pragmaticmaxim" from about 1893 onward? Just how didPeirce's speculation concerning the normativesciences modify his thinking about the meaning of his1878 statement (5.402)?

Peirce considered the first formulation of the maxim"crude" (8.255) and only approximate (5.16). His firstemendation (5.402, n. 2) was made in 1893 atapproximately the time he began to see a connectionbetween logic and ethics. This note was meant tomeet the objection that the maxim is "skeptical andmaterialistic."1 Peirce defends himself by an appeal toa collective finality governing the ''realization of ideasin man's consciousness and in his works.'' We must

Page 164: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

be on our guard, he warns us, against understandingthe maxim in a too individualistic sense. The fruitborne by an individual's endeavors is not limited justto what he aims at; whether he knows it or not hisefforts contribute to a collective result a growth ofreasonableness in the world.

Individual action is a means and not our end. Individualpleasure is not our end; we are all putting ourshoulders to the wheel for an end that none of us cancatch more than a glimpse at that which thegenerations are working out. But we can see that thedevelopment of embodied ideas is what it will consistin. (5.402, n. 2)

Three years later William James' Will to Believepushed the pragmatic maxim "to such extremes asmust tend to give us pause." Peirce interpreted hisold friend's position to be that man's end is actionand in an article2 for Baldwin's Dictionary ofPhilosophy and

1 Peirce has in mind those who would make his maxim"stoical." Cf. 5.3. For his analysis of classical Stoicismcf. 6.36.2 Under "Pragmatic and Pragmatism."

Page 165: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 54

Psychology (1902) criticized James for not seeingthat far from action being man's end, action itselfsupposes an end.3

If it be admitted, on the contrary, that action wants anend, and that that end must be something of a generaldescription, then the spirit of the maxim itself, which isthat we must look to the upshot of our concepts inorder rightly to apprehend them, would direct ustowards something different from practical facts,namely, to general ideas, as the true interpreters ofour thought. (5.3)

Action, then, cannot be the final logical interpretantof thought because it is not general while thoughtis.4 Thought can only be interpreted in terms ofThirds; the general can only be understood in termsof the general. The meaning of a conception cannotbe found in action, but in the end for which theaction (resulting from the conception) is done.5 Ofcourse, the practical facts must not be overlooked orignored. And if one chooses to call this necessaryreference to the practical the "pragmatic maxim,"then it should be applied in a thoroughgoing wayindeed, but

. . . when that has been done, and not before, a stillhigher grade of clearness of thought can be attained by

Page 166: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

remembering that the only ultimate good which thepractical facts to which it directs attention can subserveis to further the development of concretereasonableness; so that the meaning of the conceptdoes not lie in any individual reactions at all, but in themanner in which those reactions contribute to thatdevelopment. (5.3)

The meaning of a concept, therefore, is judged interms of the contribution which the reactions itevokes make toward the realization of thought'sultimate end. In other words, Peirce introduces in thepragmatic maxim itself a normative function. Thepragmatic maxim is a way of recognizing the reality ofthe objects of general ideas in their generality. Butgeneral ideas "govern" action; they are really

3 Cf. letter to Calderoni (8.211-213).4 Peirce discusses interpretants at length in 5.475-493and again in 4.536. See Appendix II for a summary ofthese texts.5 Cf. 1.343-344.

Page 167: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 55

laws of growth; they are really final causes; they arereally normative.

In this Dictionary article Peirce himself admits that hisearly formulation of the maxim did lend itself to thesort of interpretation given it by James and others,but he implies that he never meant it to be the"stoical maxim" that man's end is action. He explains:

Indeed, in the article of 1878, above referred to, thewriter practised better than he preached; for he appliedthe stoical maxim most unstoically, in such a sense asto insist upon the reality of the objects of general ideasin their generality. (5.3)

Now if one carefully rereads "How to Make Our IdeasClear" in the light of subsequent clarification byPeirce, it will become clear that in truth he did notmake action man's end, nor did he make action theend of man's thinking. Action, no doubt, is involved inthinking both in the sense that thinking is a form ofaction and that thinking normally results in action.Action is, therefore, certainly a criterion of thought.But he does not say that action is the purpose ofthinking. Its purpose is the establishment of "a belief,a rule of action, a habit of thought."6 A habit is notan action. It is in an entirely different category. A

Page 168: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

habit is general, an action is singular; a habit is aThird, and action is a Second. Still, although this iswhat Peirce meant and what he strictly said, asuperficial reading of the paper could lead tomisunderstanding especially if one were notacquainted with Peirce's subsequent development ofthe nature of habit as a general. Then, too, Peirce'sexamples of how the maxim is to be applied aremisleading and betray perhaps a certain hesitationand lack of clarity in the new doctrine he was tryingto work out for the first time. For example, he appliesthe maxim to elucidate the meaning of the term"hard":

Suppose, then, that a diamond could be crystalized inthe midst of a cushion of soft cotton, and shouldremain there until it was finally burned up. Would it befalse to say that that diamond was soft? . . . We may,in the present case,

6 Elsewhere, e.g. in a paper on the classification of thesciences (ca. 1902), Peirce distinguishes "purpose"from "final cause." Purpose is one kind of final cause,the one "most familiar to our experience." (1.211) Buthe is not always careful to observe the distinction. Thepoint he is making is that final cause does not alwaysrequire consciousness. (1.216)

Page 169: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 56

modify our question, and ask what prevents us fromsaying that all hard bodies remain perfectly soft untilthey are touched, when their hardness increases withthe pressure until they are scratched . . . there wouldbe no falsity in such modes of speech. They wouldinvolve a modification of our present usage of speechwith regard to the word "hard" and "soft," but not theirmeanings. (5.403)

This certainly seems to be a rather strong expressionof the very sort of operationalism which Peircebranded nominalistic and hence erroneous because itreduces potentiality to actuality.7 In another placeand at a later date (ca. 1905) he criticized andmodified the misleading character of his illustration.8He regretted the infelicitous example because ittended to obscure rather than to clarify what he hadintended to say.

In any case, in 1903, Peirce decided to makepragmatism the subject of a series of lectures atHarvard. This gave him the opportunity of comparinghis doctrines with others of the same name but of adifferent spirit. In those lectures he tells us that hehas no particular fault to find with the numerousdefinitions of pragmatism he had lately come across,but "to say exactly what pragmatism is describes

Page 170: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

pretty well what you and I have to puzzle outtogether" (5.16). Then in a playfully ironic passage,he teases the "new pragmatists" for notacknowledging their debt to him.

To speak plainly, a considerable number ofphilosophers have lately written as they might havewritten in case they had been reading either what Iwrote but were ashamed to confess it, or had beenreading something that some reader of mine had read.For they seem quite disposed to adopt my termpragmatism. I shouldn't wonder if they were ashamedof me. What could be more humiliating than to confessthat one had learned anything of a logician? (5.17)

Peirce is delighted to share the opinions of such abrilliant company and has no complaint to makeagainst them except that they are "lively."

7 But see 7.340, written in 1873, for a realisticinterpretation of "hardness."8 Cf. 5.403, n. 3; 1.615; 8.208.

Page 171: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 57

The new pragmatists seem to be distinguished for theirterse, vivid and concrete style of expression togetherwith a certain buoyancy of tone as if they wereconscious of carrying about them the master key to allthe secrets of metaphysics. (5.17)

No doubt, Peirce has in mind "cocksureness" and notmerely qualities of literary style when he chides thisliveliness. One thing Peirce could not tolerate was acocksure attitude. For him this was the very antithesisof the scientific attitude, humble "fallibilism" orwillingness to learn.9 Peirce clearly has in mind thosewho enthusiastically pushed the pragmatic maxim "toextremes." The maxim was not intended to be anopen-sesame to all metaphysical problems nor apanacea for all intellectual ills. It was not proposed asa principle of speculative philosophy, but as a logical,or perhaps better, a semantic maxim which wouldguide all types of investigation.10 Indeed Peircerecognized that

. . . one of the faults that I think they [the newpragmatists] might find with me is that I makepragmatism to be a mere maxim of logic instead of asublime principle of speculative philosophy. (5.18)

And, with tongue in cheek, he continues:

In order to be admitted to better philosophical standing

Page 172: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

I have endeavored to put pragmatism as I understandit into the same form of a philosophical theorem. Ihave not succeeded any better than this:

Pragmatism is the principle that every theoreticaljudgment expressible in a sentence in the indicativemood is a confused form of thought whose onlymeaning, if it has any, lies in its tendency to enforce acorresponding practical maxim expressible as aconditional sentence having its apodosis in theimperative mood. (5.18)

9 Cf. 1.9 ff.; 1.55; 1.141.10 "I also want to say that after all pragmatism solves noreal problem. It only shows that supposed problems arenot real problems. . . . The effect of pragmatism here issimply to open our minds to receiving any evidence, notto furnish evidence." From a letter to James, March 7,1904 (8.259); see also 5.13, n. 1.

Page 173: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 58

Peirce managed to get his logical principle into theform of a philosophical theorem, but he immediatelyappends his original statement of the maxim therebyleaving his audience to judge whether the new formis really an improvement. In any case, he never usedthat form again. Still, there is one important pointmade in it: the pragmatic maxim must be interpretedin terms of conditionals. Indeed the burden of theHarvard lectures is to show that meaning is intimatelybound up with real laws of nature, that is, with realpotentialities in things expressible in conditionalsentences. The conditional necessity of law isexpressed not only by a "will-be" but also by a"would-be," because law deals with the realm of thepossible what would be the case whenever certainconditions are fulfilled. What the conditionalexpresses is not merely the juxtaposition of anantecedent and a consequent, but the consequenceor connection between them. "If such and such werethe case (or were done), then such and such wouldfollow." When Peirce came to see this more clearly,he corrected what he had said about the relationshipbetween the hardness of a diamond and scratchingwith carborundum. A diamond never scratched isnevertheless hard because if it were brought into

Page 174: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

contact with carborundum it would be scratched.Thus the meaning of hardness is not in an action butin an intention or "intellectual purport.''

During this whole period (ca. 1896-1903), then, dueto the sudden popularity of "pragmatism," Peirce wasvery much preoccupied with disassociating his viewsfrom those circulating. Again, in 1905, he felt that heought to try once more to explain what his notion ofpragmatism entailed and even went so far as to coina new word for it, "pragmaticism," which was "uglyenough to be safe from kidnappers" (5.414). So hepublished a series of three articles in the Monist,which contain perhaps the clearest presentation ofhis case that he ever wrote.

In the first of these essays ("What Pragmatism Is")he re-expressed the maxim thus:

Endeavoring, as a man of that type [a "laboratory-man"] naturally would, to formulate what he soapproved, he framed the theory that a conception, thatis, the rational purport of a word or other expression,lies exclusively in its conceivable bearing upon theconduct of life; so that, since

Page 175: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 59

obviously nothing that might not result fromexperiment can have any direct bearing upon conduct,if one can define accurately all the conceivableexperimental phenomena which the affirmation ordenial of a concept would imply, one will have thereina complete definition of the concept, and there isabsolutely nothing more in it. (5.412)

This formulation makes it clear that the maxim hasvery little indeed to do with the practical.11 AndPeirce explains that his awareness of this factdetermined his choice of the name "pragmatism" or"pragmaticism" rather than "practicism" or''practicalism."

But for one who had learned philosophy out of Kant, asthe writer, along with nineteen out of every twentyexperimentalists who have turned to philosophy, haddone, and who still thought in Kantian terms mostreadily, praktisch and pragmatisch were as far apart asthe two poles, the former belonging in a region ofthought where no mind of the experimentalist type canever make sure of solid ground under his feet, thelatter expressing relation to some definite humanpurpose. Now quite the most striking feature of thenew theory was its recognition of an inseparableconnection between rational cognition and rationalpurpose; and that consideration it was whichdetermined the preference for the name pragmatism.

Page 176: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(5.412)12

It is not, therefore, the practical consequences of aconception which make it true and meaningful. Theyare, of course, criteria of its truth and meaningfulness(since one might expect a true and meaningfulconcept to have consequences), but do not in somecrude sense constitute truth and meaning. This is butanother way of repudiating the notion that action isman's end and the purpose of man's thinking. The

11 Cf. 5.197 where Peirce expounds pragmatism as thelogic of abduction. He remarks that if pragmatismteaches that every conception is a conception ofconceivably practical effects it makes conception reachfar beyond the practical, since it allows any flight ofimagination which will ultimately alight upon a possiblepractical effect. Cf. also 5.538-545.12 Cf. Kant, Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht(Leipzig: Modes und Baumann, 1839), Vorrede. SeeSmith, op. cit., pp. 13-16, for an excellent discussion ofPeirce's use of the term "practical."

Page 177: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 60

key to meaning and to truth is the relation of aconception "to some definite human purpose," tosome end which governs actions in the same wayThirds govern Seconds. Rational cognition is in thecategory of Thirdness and must be interpreted interms of some other Third. For Peirce this is nothingother than rational purpose. The pragmatic maxim,then, is but a way of expressing this relation. Onceagain we see that Peirce intends meaning to beidentical with rational purport and not with actionalone. Of course, Peirce realizes that a proof that thisis so would require a sustained exposition of his entirephilosophy of logic, cosmology, and metaphysics, or,in his words, "the establishment of the truth ofsynechism" (5.415).

In the same article Peirce tries to answer certainobjections to his positions in the form of a littledialog. It is particularly enlightening because itindicates as clearly as anyone could wish theconnection he saw, or at least thought he saw,between pragmaticism and the normative sciences. Itis objected, first, that according to the pragmaticposition nothing enters into the meaning of a conceptbut an experiment; yet an experiment in itself cannotreveal anything more than a constant conjunction of

Page 178: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

antecedent and consequent (5.424). This typicallyHumean objection, Peirce observes, betrays amisunderstanding of pragmaticism's fundamentalpoint. In the first place, the objection raisedmisrepresents what is involved in an experiment. Anexperiment is not an isolated, "atomic" event, butalways forms a part of connected series or system. Anexperiment essentially requires the followingingredients: 1) an experimenter, 2) a verifiablehypothesis concerning the experimenter'senvironment, and 3) a sincere doubt in theexperimenter's mind about the hypothesis' truth. Theexperimenter, by an act of choice, must single outcertain identifiable objects on which to operate. Thenby an external (or quasi-external) act he modifiesthose objects. Next comes a reaction of the worldupon the experimenter through perception. Finally,he must recognize what the experiment teaches him.While the chief elements in the event of theexperiment are action and reaction, the unity ofessence of the experiment, what makes theexperiment an experiment, lies in its purpose andplan (5.424).

In the second place, this sort of objection fails tocatch the pragmaticist's attitude of mind. Rationalmeaning does not consist in an experiment, but in

Page 179: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

experimental phenomena. These phenomena, to

Page 180: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 61

which the pragmaticist refers, are not particularevents that have already happened to someone or tosomething in the dead past, but are "what surely willhappen to everybody in the living future who shallfulfill certain conditions" (5.425). Essential toexperimental phenomena is that they have beenpredicted.

The phenomenon consists in the fact that when anexperimentalist shall come to act according to a certainscheme that he has in mind, then will something elsehappen, and shatter the doubts of sceptics, like thecelestial fire upon the altar of Elijah. (5.425)

In the third place, this objection that an experimentcan only show constant conjunction of antecedentand consequent overlooks in a very nominalistic waythe fact that the experimenter is not interested in thissingle experiment or in that single experimentalphenomenon. He is interested in general kinds ofexperimental phenomena, for what is conditionallytrue in futuro can only be general. In other words,experimental method implicitly at least affirms thereality of generals (5.426).

It is just at this point that the connection betweenpragmaticism and the normative sciences becomes

Page 181: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

unmistakable. Peirce asks how it is that the relationalmeaning of a proposition lies in the future. Thereason is that according to his theory the meaning ofa proposition is precisely that form in which itbecomes applicable to human conduct, "not in theseor those special circumstances, nor when oneentertains this or that special design, but that formwhich is most directly applicable to self-control underevery situation, and to every purpose" (5.427).Future conduct is the only kind that is subject to self-control, and, in order that the form of the propositionmight apply to every situation and purpose uponwhich it has any bearing, "it must be simply thegeneral description of all the experimentalphenomena which the assertion of the propositionvirtually predicts" (5.427). Therefore, according topragmaticism, the meaning of a proposition isattained when it is grasped as capable of governingfuture action through the exercise of self-control.That is its "rational purport."

The next objection which Peirce raises against hisown theory is that pragmaticism is a thoroughgoingphenomenalism. He answers it briefly by denying theallegation in the light of what had just been

Page 182: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 62

said about "rational purport." The following objection,however, is the really crucial one in Peirce's view andthe one involving James' fundamental mistake.

QUESTIONER: Well, if you choose so to make Doing theBe-all and the End-all of human life, why do you notmake meaning to consist simply in doing? Doing has tobe done at a certain time upon a certain object.Individual objects and single events cover all reality, aseverybody knows, and as a practicalist ought to be thefirst to insist. Yet, your meaning, as you have describedit, is general. Thus, it is of the nature of a mere wordand not a reality. (5.429)

The objection is just about as clearly and as forciblyput as it can be. And for Peirce it touches the veryheart of the matter because it points out the basicchoice that all philosophers must make betweennominalism and realism. The objection is powerfulbecause it involves so many things that must beadmitted, and Peirce clears away the groundimmediately by conceding what he must.

It must be admitted, in the first place, that ifpragmaticism really made Doing to be the Be-all andthe End-all of life, that would be its death. For to saythat we live for the sake of action, as action, regardlessof the thought it carries out, would be to say that thereis no such thing as rational purport. Secondly, it must

Page 183: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

be admitted that every proposition professes to be trueof a certain real individual object, often the environinguniverse. Thirdly, it must be admitted thatpragmaticism fails to furnish any translation ormeaning of a proper name, or other designation of anindividual object. Fourthly, the pragmaticistic meaningis undoubtedly general; and it is equally indisputablethat the general is of the nature of the word or sign.Fifthly, it must be admitted that individuals alone exist;and sixthly, it may be admitted that the very meaningof a word or significant object ought to be the veryessence of reality of what it signifies. (5.429)

These admissions come down to this: pragmaticismholds that meaning or rational purport, since it isnecessarily general, can only belong to the categoryof Thirdness, and consequently, cannot be reducedto

Page 184: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 63

action-reaction or to individual existence whichbelong to the category of Secondness. Of course, ageneral is of the nature of a word or sign preciselybecause it cannot be exhausted by any singularindividual instance. While it is true that generals donot exist, it does not follow that they are not real.They have the reality of types or forms to whichobjects conform but which none of them can exactlybe (5.429). The type or form abstractly considered isan ideal which the instances embody to a greater orless degree, and as an ideal the type or form plays anormative role with respect to its concrete instances,to our knowledge of them (by natural classification),and to expression of that knowledge in terms ofabstract definition.13

It would take us too far afield to discuss in detailPeirce's notion of reality and his adaptation of''scholastic realism." Yet from what we have seenthus far their connection with pragmaticism isevident. A brief word, however, may not be out ofplace. For the pragmaticist, "that is real which hassuch and such characters, whether anybody thinks itto have those characters or not" (5.430). Thusanything is real which is not a mental fiction. On theother hand, reality is that ultimate state of things

Page 185: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

which will be believed in the ultimate opinion of thecommunity of inquirers. The ultimate opinion,however, seems to be for Peirce a theoretical limittoward which the community of inquirers convergebut which is never quite attained, for no opinion isultimate in the sense that no further questions maybe asked about the subject matter of that opinion.There will always be more to learn. There isconvergence in the sense that independent inquirerswill tend to accept as established certain propositionsabout their subject matter. Peirce's view seems to bethat both the external world and man's knowledge ofthat world are evolving. On the one hand, sinceman's knowledge of the world is dependent uponexperience, since he does not create the objects ofknowledge, and since the world he experiences isconstantly growing, there will always be a lag in hisknowledge of the world. Man's knowledge of theworld is constantly corrected by experience and so,given an indefinitely long time, man's opinion aboutthe world will tend to become uniform. Taught by

13 Cf. 1.222. An abstract definition does not constitutenecessarily a "natural" or "real" class. What constitutessuch a class is a common final cause. An abstractdefinition expresses, or attempts to express, the classalready constituted.

Page 186: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 187: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 64

nature herself, man would come to know throughexperience what to expect from nature. This does notmean that he would ever have finished his lessons,for nature will always exhibit "sporting," but he wouldhave come to understand the process in terms of itsgeneral direction and purpose the growth of concretereasonableness.

Now, just as conduct controlled by ethical reason tendstoward fixing certain habits of conduct, the nature ofwhich . . . does not depend upon any accidentalcircumstances, and in that sense may be said to bedestined; so, thought, controlled by a rationalexperimental logic, tends to the fixation of certainopinions, equally destined, the nature of which will bethe same in the end, however the perversity of thoughtof whole generations may cause the postponement ofthe ultimate fixation. If this be so, as every man of usvirtually assumes that it is, in regard to each matterthe truth of which he seriously discusses, then,according to the adopted definition of "real," the stateof things which will be believed in that ultimate opinionis real. But, for the most part, such opinions will begeneral. Consequently, some general obects are real.(Of course, nobody ever thought that all generals werereal. . .) (5.430)

Some generals, then, are real and have a real efficacy

Page 188: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

in just the way common sense acknowledges anefficacy in human purposes. Human actions arecontrolled in terms of human purposes; they arespecified and determined by certain ends and goals.So, too, real generals specify and determine humanknowledge. Real generals are what constitute thecosmos as ordered and intelligible. They are both thecondition of possibility of any rationality whatsoeverand the normative principles of that sort of rationality(human) which is continually dependent upon theshock of experience. "Individual existence or actualitywithout any regularity whatever is a nullity. Chaos ispure nothing" (5.431).

According to Peirce, if this "scholastic realism" is putin the form of a general conditional proposition aboutthe future such that it is calculated to influencehuman conduct, one has the pragmatic maxim. Truepragmatism, therefore, does not make action thesummum bonum. The growth of concretereasonableness in the world of

Page 189: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 65

existents is that ultimate good. As evolutionprogresses, human intelligence plays a greater andgreater role in that development through itscharacteristic power of self-control. There is aninteraction between human rationality and theevolutionary process.14 In the beginning the humanmind emerged from that process, according toPeirce's view, but once emerged it can and doesinfluence the course of evolution through deliberateconduct. In effect human rationality becomes one ofnature's agents in the process. Nature's objectiveregularity specifies man's knowledge, and man guideshis own activity toward and in nature accordingly.Even if, through some perversity, some men, evenover long periods of time, should choose tocounteract nature's directives, to swim against thetide, in the long run man will be forced by experienceto recognize her as growing in rationality despite himand as guiding him in his own quest for reason.15

Peirce concludes this informative Monist article byinsisting upon the utter inadequacy of action(Secondness) to account for the generality(Thirdness) of meaning (5.436). To understand allthat is involved in this contention one would have toundertake a serious study of continuity which "is

Page 190: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

simply what generality becomes in the logic ofrelatives, and thus, like generality, is an affair ofthought, and is the essence of thought." Peirce tellsus why he alludes to the theory of continuity here: toemphasize what is absolutely essential topragmaticism, namely, that

. . . the third category the category of thought,representation, triadic relation, mediation, genuinethirdness, thirdness as such is an essential ingredientof reality, yet does not by itself constitute reality, sincethis category. . . can have no concrete being withoutaction, as a separate object on which to work itsgovernment, just as action cannot

14 Cf. W.D. Oliver, "The Final Cause and Agapasm inPeirce's Philosophy," Studies, Moore and Robin, pp.294-295.15 "Accordingly, the pragmaticist does not make thesummum bonum to consist in action, but makes it toconsist in that process of evolution whereby the existentcomes more and more to embody those generals whichwere just now said to be destined, which is what westrive to express in calling them reasonable. In its higherstages, evolution takes place more and more largelythrough self-control, and this gives the pragmaticist a sortof justification for making the rational purport to begeneral." (5.433)

Page 191: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 66

exist without the immediate being of feeling on whichto act. (5.436)

Almost fifteen years earlier (ca. 1892) Peirce hadsaid, "My philosophy resuscitates Hegel . . . in astrange costume" (1.42). Hegel too had seen theimportance of continuity and indeed the "Secret ofHegel" was just that he discovered that the universeis everywhere permeated with continuous growth(1.40-41). Peirce's pragmaticism, then, is "closelyallied to Hegelian absolute idealism" with thisimportant difference: Thirdness alone is not enoughto make the world. Hegel's fundamental mistake wasto dismiss Firstness and Secondness (5.436).16

The second article of this Monist series also appearedin 1905 under the title "Issues of Pragmaticism."Peirce remarks that in the 1878 formulation of thepragmatic maxim, contrary to his wont, he used fivederivates of the same word, concipere. He did so fortwo reasons: 1) to show that he was speaking ofmeaning "in no other sense than that of intellectualpurport," and 2) "to avoid all danger of beingunderstood as attempting to explain a concept bypercepts, images, schemata, or by anything butconcepts." The point is, of course, that onlysomething in the category of Thirdness can constitute

Page 192: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

meaning. Action is like the finale of a symphony, butnobody would say that the finale was the purpose ofthe symphony; it is rather its upshot (5.430, n. 3). Ofcourse, pragmaticism recognizes a connectionbetween thought and action.17 Ultimately it makesthought apply to action, and indeed it is thoughtwhich distinguishes conduct from mere activity. Yetthis is quite different from saying either that thoughtconsists in action or that thought's ultimate purposeis action.

Pragmaticism makes thinking to consist in the livinginferential metaboly of symbols whose purport lies inconditional general resolutions to act. As for theultimate purpose of thought, which must be thepurpose of everything, it is beyond humancomprehension; but according to the

16 Cf. also 5.79, 5.37 ff.17 Cf. 5.491. Peirce's way of looking at this connectionhas marked similarity to the scholastic maxim "ageresequitur esse." J. Boler points this out too in CharlesPeirce and Scholastic Realism (Seattle: University ofWashington Press, 1963), p. 102.

Page 193: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 67

stage or approach my thought has made of it . . . it isby the indefinite replication of self-control upon self-control that the vir is begotten, and by action,through thought, he grows an esthetic ideal . . . asthe share which God permits him to have in the workof creation. (5.403, n. 3)

Page 194: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 69

IISYNECHISM & LAW

Page 195: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 71

IntroductionPeirce frequently remarked that his pragmaticism wasintimately related to synechism or the doctrine ofcontinuity. In a letter to William James he says thathis own version of pragmatism leads to synechism(8.257). In another place Peirce remarks that athorough-going proof of pragmaticism's truth ''wouldessentially involve the establishment of the truth ofsynechism" (5.415). In still another place he saysthat synechism "is not opposed to pragmatism in themanner in which C.S. Peirce applied it, but includesthat procedure as a step" (5.4).1 Peirce spent thebetter part of twenty years working out hissynechistic cosmology. This period (from about 1880to 1900), it will be noticed, fills in the gap betweenPeirce's first formulation of the pragmatic maxim andthe later reworking of it. It should also be pointed outthat this period coincides with his awakening to theplace of the normative sciences in philosophy. Thiswas not all by accident. Peirce's appreciation of theconnection between logic, practics, and estheticscame out of his cosmological studies. He undertookand pursued the inquiry into the nature of the

Page 196: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

cosmos under the guidance of his pragmaticprinciple. As this inquiry progressed he gainedgreater insight into the meaning of this principleitself. In a very real sense Peirce drew out what wasimplicit in his early essay by putting the maxim towork. In other words, Peirce's cosmologicalspeculations form the bridge between the 1878 and1903 versions of pragmaticism.

Just what, then, is this synechism which Peirceconsiders so essential to this thought? His popularpresentation of the notion in Baldwin's Dictionary ofPhilosophy and Psychology will serve our presentpurposes. In the first place, it is not "an ultimate andabsolute

1 The main features of synechism were developedafter the first formulation of the pragmatic maxim in1877 and its subsequent revision in the light of thedoctrine of normative science (ca. 1903). No doubt itwas Peirce's work with synechism which led him to seethe relevance of normative science for pragmatism. Cf.M. Thompson, The Pragmatic Philosophy of C.S. Peirce(Chicago: Phoenix Books, 1963), p. 103.

Page 197: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 72

metaphysical doctrine," but like the pragmatic maximitself "is a regulative principle of logic" (6.173). Whilethis renowned maxim deals with the meaning ofconcepts, the synechistic principle prescribes "whatsort of hypothesis is fit to be entertained andexamined" (6.173).2 In general, it seeks to excludeany hypothesis which would block the road of inquiry.

The general motive is to avoid the hypothesis that thisor that is inexplicable. For the synechist maintains thatthe only possible justification for so much asentertaining a hypothesis is that it affords anexplanation of the phenomena. Now, to suppose athing inexplicable is not only to fail to explain it, and soto make an unjustifiable hypothesis, but, much worse,it is to set up a barrier across the road of science, andto forbid all attempt to understand the phenomenon.(6.171)

Thus, Peirce tells us, synechism as a logical principleforbids one to consider any inexplicability as apossible explanation, and this is nothing more or lessthan the assumption behind the scientific enterpriseas such, namely, that the world is knowable.

The synechistic principle does not deny that there isan element of the inexplicable and of the ultimateand brute in the world. That would be to deny that

Page 198: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

there is such a thing as experience. Experience iswhat is forced upon one will he, nill he. It is theelement of shock and surprise which countersexpectation, engenders doubt, and so stimulatesfurther inquiry. In short, there is a sort of compulsionwhich in the very act is inexplicable and so ultimate.There is brute fact, or Secondness. This does notblock the road of inquiry, but rather stimulates one togeneralize from the experience, to form newhypotheses, because he is convinced that the factscan be understood that they manifest another modeof being other than brutishness, namely, obedienceto rationality and to law.

It would, therefore, be most contrary to his ownprinciple for the synechist not to generalize from thatwhich

2 In his Harvard Lectures of 1903, Peirce says thatpragmatism is nothing but the logic of abduction, thatis, it proposes a rule for the admissibility of hypothesesto rank as hypotheses (5.196). It must be, then, anexpression or summary of synechism.

Page 199: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 73

experience forces upon him, especially since it is onlyso far as facts can be generalized that they can beunderstood; and the very reality, in his way of lookingat the matter, is nothing else than the way in whichfacts must ultimately come to be understood. (6.173)

It is clear, then, that an understanding of synechismas a principle of inquiry is closely bound up with anunderstanding of the interdependence of thecategories of Secondness and Thirdness. What Peircehas in mind is much like Aristotle's distinctionbetween the fact and the reasoned fact. Everyphenomenon insofar as it is an event has somethingbrute about it. If that event happens contrary to ourexpectations, that bruteness manifests itself asstruggle and shock. But insofar as that event is a kindof phenomenon, it can be understood, and ourexpectations can be altered to include its like in thefuture. Therefore, the ultimacy of fact is not the lastword it is not something to be looked upon asabsolutely realized.

For science, therefore, and so for synechism, factscannot be looked upon as being, in the last analysis,atomic and unrelated. They cannot be consideredincapable of generalization. They must be seen in asystem (cf. e.g. 1.424) where they are related and

Page 200: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

grouped according to general laws. Peirce thinks ofthis relatedness of facts as a continuum.

A true continuum is something whose possibilities ofdetermination no multitude of individuals can exhaust .. . (6.170). True generality is, in fact, nothing but arudimentary form of true continuity. Continuity isnothing but perfect generality of a law of relationship.(6.172)

Atomic, isolated facts would be ultimate in theobjectionable sense of being inexplicable andunintelligible. They would be examples of pureSecondness uninterpretable and so unknowable.They would be Kantian "things-in-themselves." Inshort, they would not have any reality at any rate notfor us.

In short, synechism amounts to the principle thatinexplicabilities are not to be considered as possibleexplanations; that whatever is supposed to be ultimateis supposed to be inexplicable; that continuity is theabsence

Page 201: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 74

of ultimate parts in that which is divisible; and that theform under which alone anything can be understood isthe form of generality, which is the same thing ascontinuity. (6.173)3

By now the reader undoubtedly suspects that,despite Peirce's apparent disclaimer concerningsynechism's metaphysical pretensions, this regulativelogical principle does indeed involve an ontology anda metaphysics. And these suspicions are justified, forPeirce himself in several places tells us thatmetaphysics consists in the acceptance of logicalprinciples as principles of being (1.487; 1.624-625).4But if any doubt remains, Peirce dispels it when hewrites:

Synechism is founded on the notion that thecoalescence, the becoming continuous, the becominggoverned by laws, the becoming instinct with generalideas, are but phases of one and the same process ofthe growth of reasonableness. This is first shown to betrue with mathematical exactitude

3 Peirce, of course, was much influenced by Kant. Hecut his philosophical teeth on the Critique of PureReason and had it almost by heart. A passing remarkmade in his famous rejoinder to Prof. Carus indicatesthat the doctrine of synechism was fashioned with Kantin mind that is, to bridge the gap between the inner

Page 202: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and outer worlds. Discussing the view that Kant's apriori is a universal objective, as opposed to subjective,condition of cognition, Peirce declares: "It is a weakconception, unless the whole distinction between theinward and the outward world be reformed in the lightof agapastic and synechistic ontology. For to deny thatthe a priori is subjective is to remove its essentialcharacter; and to make it both subjective and objective(otherwise than in the sense in which Kant himselfmakes it objective) is uncalled for, and is cut off byOckham's razor. But when synechism has united thetwo worlds, this view gains new life" (6.590).4 Here again Kant's influence is apparent. The Critique ofPure Reason concluded that metaphysics as an empiricalscience was impossible because the a priori source ofnecessity and universality is a subjective condition ofknowledge only. Knowledge itself, or in any case,empirical knowledge requires a synthesis of the manifoldof sense. In other words, for Kant, empirical knowledge islimited by experience. When Peirce says that hissynechism unites Kant's "two worlds," he means that thetranscendental conditions of knowledge should not beconfined merely to the subject, but must also be in theobject. In other words, the object of knowledge itself isintelligible, has a rational structure.

Page 203: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 75

in the field of logic, and is thence inferred to hold goodmetaphysically. (5.4)

In the second place, then, synechism is ametaphysical position (even though not ''ultimate andabsolute") precisely because it is a regulative logicalprinciple.5 Although one cannot separate logical frommetaphysical considerations in Peirce (for the reasonsjust adduced), insofar as they can be distinguishedour interest will be confined to the metaphysical.Thus we must undertake a close examination of"becoming governed by law" as a phase in the"process of the growth of reasonableness."

5 It may be well to reproduce this Peircean descriptionof metaphysics: "Metaphysics consists in the results ofthe absolute acceptance of logical principles not merelyas regulatively valid, but as truths of being.Accordingly, it is to be assumed that the universe hasan explanation, the function of which, like that of everylogical explanation, is to unify its observed variety. Itfollows that the root of all being is One; and so far asdifferent subjects have a common character theypartake of an identical being. This, or something likethis, is the monadic clause of the law. Second, drawinga general induction from all observed facts, we find allrealization of existence lies in opposition, such asattractions, repulsions, visibilities, and centres of

Page 204: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

potentiality generally. . . . This is, or is a part of, adyadic clause of the law. Under the third clause, wehave, as a deduction from the principle that thought isthe mirror of being, the law that the end of being andhighest reality is the living impersonation of the ideathat evolution generates" (1.487). As always Peirceuses his universal categories to characterize whateverdiscipline he wishes to describe.

Page 205: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 76

1. Synechism & Metaphysical RealismPragmatism is a step in the general procedure ofsynechism because the correct formation ofhypotheses supposes a correct understanding of theconcepts so employed. Both pragmatism andsynechism are built upon the bedrock of realism,1that position which Peirce tells us he espoused sovery early in his career and to which he everremained faithful through all the vagaries of hisspeculations.2 In Part I of this essay we indicatedhow "scholastic realism" is essentially involved inPeirce's understanding of the pragmatic maxim. Sincethe truth of pragmatism essentially requires the truthof synechism, we must consider in some detail therelation between synechism and realism, and to dothat we must present a more careful analysis of theissue under debate in the realism-nominalismcontroversy.

Let us begin by eliminating what is not at stake. It isnot a question of just epistemological realism, that is,a question of the existence of a real "external" world.Peirce never considered that to be a genuineproblem. It is rather a fact of everyday experience,

Page 206: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

doubts about which could be easily dispelled unlessone is blinded by some irrational scruple about thekind of evidence required or prejudiced by apreconceived theory. In this sort of realism allmedieval thinkers were agreed, even the nominalists.It is little more than what common sense requires torecognize that we cannot

1 "Now whoever cares to know what pragmaticism isshould understand that on its metaphysical side it is anattempt to solve the problem: In what way can ageneral be unaffected by any thought about it? Hencebefore we treat of the evidences of pragmaticism, itwill be needful to weigh the pros and cons of scholasticrealism. For pragmaticism could hardly have entered ahead that was not already convinced that there arereal generals" (5.503).2 See, e.g. 6.605. Writing in 1891 he says, "Yet be itknown that never, during the thirty years in which I havebeen writing on philosophical questions, have I failed inmy allegiance to realistic opinions and to certain Scotisticideas . . . ."

Page 207: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 77

think whatever we want and that wishing will notnecessarily make it so. Still there are some passagesin which Peirce addresses himself to this question,usually when he is expounding his "Critical Common-sensism" (e.g. 5.439) or elucidating the meaning oftruth (e.g. 2.1533). Thus, for example, in the "Logicof 1873" Peirce writes this very curious passage:

The question is, "Whether corresponding to ourthoughts and sensations, and represented in somesense by them, there are realities, which are not onlyindependent of the thought of you, and me, and anynumber of men, but which are absolutely independentof thought altogether." The objective final opinion isindependent of thoughts of any particular men, but isnot independent of thought in general. (7.336)

The passage is curious because on the one hand itdeclares for epistemological realism, and on the otherfor objective idealism (cf. 2.153). To understand howthe two are compatible we must examine theproblem of metaphysical realism and the solutionPeirce adopted.

Peirce continually insisted that he held "scholasticrealism" as against nominalism in all its forms.Further, he insisted that he opted for one particularstyle of that realism, namely, that of John Duns

Page 208: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Scotus. Exceptionally well acquainted with medievalphilosophy, he knew that the great issue of the dayconcerned the ontological status of "universals" andthat even among the realists there were a variety ofopinions.

In the days of which I am speaking, the age of Robertof Lincoln, Roger Bacon, St. Thomas Aquinas, and DunsScotus, the question of nominalism and realism wasregarded as definitively and conclusively settled infavor of realism. You know what the question was. Itwas whether laws and general types are figments ofthe mind or are real. If this be understood to meanwhether there really are any laws and types, it isstrictly speaking a question of metaphysics and not oflogic. (1.16)

3 Yet cf. 8.218 ff. where he criticizes Royce for failingto understand the realist position.

Page 209: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 78

But in accord with his general conviction that logicand metaphysics are intimately related, nay, thatmetaphysics is objectified logic, he says immediately:

But as a first step toward its solution, it is proper to askwhether, granting that our common-sense beliefs aretrue, the analysis of the meaning of those beliefsshows that, according to those beliefs, laws and typesare objective or subjective. This is a question of logicrather than of metaphysics and as soon as this isanswered the reply to the other question immediatelyfollows after. (1.16)

Peirce wrote this in 1903. A few years earlier, in1898, he formulated the same question in a waywhich emphasizes its relevance to Peirce's synechisttheory of law.

Now what was the question of realism and nominalism?I see no objection to defining it as the question ofwhich is the best, the laws or the facts under thoselaws. It is true that it was not stated in this way. Asstated, the question was whether universals, such asthe Horse, the Ass, the Zebra, and so forth, were in reor in rerum natura. . . . in using the word law, orregularity, we bring into prominence the kind ofuniversals to which modern science pays mostattention. Roughly speaking, the nominalists conceivedthe general element of cognition to be merely a

Page 210: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

convenience for understanding this and that fact and toamount to nothing except for cognition, while therealists, still more roughly speaking, looked upon thegeneral, not only as the end and aim of knowledge, butalso as the most important element of being. Such wasand is the question. (4.1)4

4 "The facts which the abstract nouns such ashardness, sweetness, etc. are used to express arereally and truly so. But there are in the physicaluniverse no existing, that is reacting, things hardness,sweetness. They have their being only in the discourseof our minds with themselves and in our speech toothers. Hence they are called entia rationis, or beingsof Reason. Some men say they are real, meaning thatthey serve to express what is really so. Others say thatthey are not `real,' meaning that there are no suchreacting things called hardness, sweetness, etc. Theformer writers use the word `real' in the precise sensewhich it was invented to signify; and remember

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 211: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 79

The question, then, was not whether there is anexternal world which we can know to some degree,but what is included in that world's reality whichenables us to understand it to some degree. Isgenerality, rationality, lawfulness, Thirdness a realmode of the world's being? If it is not, then the worldis not in itself intelligible and does not exhibit anystructure. It does not reveal itself to man upondiligent investigation, but rather presents itself as amad puzzle into which man must introduce orderfrom without, as it were. If it is a real mode, thenscientific inquiry seeks to discover the world's orderand rationality by careful attention to correctreasoning and by docility to experience, the world'sown great revealer and teacher. If the nominalists areright, then we do not strictly speaking know theworld or anything about it. We may encounter it inbrutal shock, but that encounter does not revealanything about what is encountered. It might bethought that on the nominalistic view one might beable to say that he knows that there is an externalworld "out there" but it would remain opaque as towhat it is. It would be unknown and unknowable inthis sense, and it would be a short step indeed todenying even knowledge of the that. Whatever is

Page 212: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

known is categorized and generalized. It is set inrelation to other things, objects, and experiences.And if it is known, it must warrant suchgeneralization. To do that, Peirce argues, it musthave a real mode of generality as part of its structureand being. To be actually known implies to beknowable, while to be does not in any way imply tobe actually known. In another place, discussing theweak evasive tactics of the conceptualists (thefainthearted nominalists), Peirce formulates the issueonce again in a way which clearly brings out thepoint.

The question was whether all properties, laws ofnature, and predicates of more than an actuallyexistent subject are, without exception, mere figmentsor not. The conceptualists seek to wedge in a thirdposition. . . . They say, "Those universals are real,indeed; but they are only real thoughts."

(footnote continued from previous page)

this: To use a precise word in a wrong sense is a sin,because it tends to make human thought, which is theonly really valuable ingredient of human nature, to beconfused. The latter writers are apt to think that it isonly what actually has happened that is true, while infact what would surely happen under describedcircumstances is as true and more important, becauseit guides our conduct more directly" (Peirce Papers,

Page 213: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

#48, p. 11).

Page 214: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 80

. . . The great realists had brought out all the truththere is in that much more distinctly long beforemodern conceptualism appeared in the world. Theyshowed that the general is not capable of fullactualization in the world of action and reaction but isof the nature of what is thought, but that our thinkingonly apprehends and does not create thought, and thatthat thought may and does as much govern outwardthings as it does our thinking. . . . The conceptualistdoctrine is an undisputed truism about thinking, whilethe question between nominalists and realists relatesto thoughts, that is, to the objects which thinkingenables us to know. (1.27)

Peirce was not content merely to declare for"scholastic realism" in general. He is very careful tospecify the particular brand he chose. Peirce claimsScotus as his inspiration, and this insistence is notwithout great significance in understanding hissynechistic version of metaphysical realism (cf. e.g.1.6, 4.50, 5.77, n. 1, 5.312, etc.). Thomism andScotism are the two great rivals among the scholasticrealisms. Both schools were equally antagonistic tonominalism on the one hand and to platonizing or"extreme" realism on the other. In common they heldthat all concrete existents are singular, while ourknowledge of them is in terms of universal concepts.

Page 215: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

But since our knowledge is objective, there must besome sort of ground in the singular for the universal.Both schools agreed in a general way that thefundamentum universalitatis had to be somethingreally and objectively common (natura communis) toall individuals of which the universal is predicable.This was the logical aspect of the problem. Thedistinction often used to express this position isbetween that which a universal concept represents(id quod conceptus representat) that is, the commonnature, and the way in which (modus quo) thatcontent is real in the concrete singular of which it isobjectively predicated and in the intelligence whichso predicates it. Thus far, Scotists and Thomistsagree. But as to the question of the ontological statusof that natura communis and to that of how such anature is individuated, they part company.5 WhileAquinas held for a unique

5 Cf. 5.107; Peirce recognized that the relation of lawto "a blind reacting thing" (of Thirdness to Secondness)involved "the great problem of

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 216: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 81

substantial form accounting for the unity of thespecies and for signate matter (materia quantitatesignata) as its individuating principle, Scotus thoughtthat there were a plurality of forms ingredient in anyindividual (one to account for each essential propertyof the species to which it belonged, as, for example,in a man, a form of bodiness, a form of life, a form ofmixture, etc.) and that these forms were madeconcrete, singular and actual by haecceity or''thisness," itself not another form, but an entitativeperfection effecting the passage from specific unity toindividual unity.6 Thus in Scotus' view the concreteindividual in a species is made up of a commonnature in virtue of which it is a member of the speciesand haecceity in virtue of which it is this individual.The common nature itself is made up of a plurality offorms, each corresponding to a note (essential oraccidental) in that nature's description. These formsare not really distinct from one another, nor are theymerely rationally distinct in the sense of being merefictions, but rather between them is a formaldistinction. The same is true of the relation betweencommon nature and haecceity. As Scotus sometimesputs it, the formal distinction is between realitas etrealitas, but not between res et res.

Page 217: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

It is instructive to notice that the most frequentcriticism of Scotism by Thomists is that it tendstoward, if it is not really, a form of extreme realism.The Thomists criticize haecceitas as a mere deus exmachina to escape making the individual a merebundle of concrete universals (platonizing), not tomention the fact that despite the Scotists'protestations it looks very much like anotherformality, if not the airiest of abstractions. Again theformalities, according to the

(footnote continued from previous page)

the principle of individuation which the scholasticdoctors after a century of the closest possible analysiswere obliged to confess was quite incomprehensible tothem."6 E. Bettoni, O.F.M., Duns Scotus: The Basic Principles ofhis Philosophy, trans. by B. Bonansea, O.F.M.(Washington, D.C.: Cath. U. of Amer. Press, 1961), p. 61,sums up the notion of haecceity as follows: "In otherwords, the haecceity is not just a perfection added to theform and within the form, but a new mode of being thataffects matter, form, and the composite, i.e., the wholecommon nature, which is thereby contracted and forcedto come out of that sort of indetermination which isproper to the specific nature. It is on the plane of act, andtherefore a real principle, without being a formalelement."

Page 218: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 219: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 82

Thomists, are either really or only rationally distinct.They do not see that any halfway house is possible. Ifthey are only rationally distinct then Scotism has notanswered the nominalist position, while if they arereally distinct, then the realism is extreme. And yet,Peirce criticizes Scotus for not having been anextreme enough realist and, therefore, accuses himof having to a degree fallen into nominalism (cf. e.g.1.560, 6.175, 8.11). Thus he says of himself, "Ishould call myself an Aristotelian of the scholasticwing, approaching Scotism, but going much fartherin the direction of scholastic realism" (5.77, n. 1) and"I am myself a scholastic realist of a somewhatextreme stripe" (5.470). Peirce, therefore, opts forextreme realism that type of realism which Scotismwould be without the theory of individuation. AndPeirce does in places insist that such a theory mustbe abandoned.7 Nor does Peirce seem to think thatthis extreme realism would leave him open to thecharge of reifying universals. He feels that his newlogic of relatives allows him to escape this sort oferror.8 Thus, he prefers to phrase his realism in termsof the objective reality of laws rather than in terms ofuniversals (see 4.1). Laws are formulations ofrelations, not "things."9 So all properties are in the

Page 220: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

end laws expressed in subjunctive conditionals (seee.g. 5.545). It is hardly necessary to point out thatthis sort of position is not without very seriousdifficulties especially in regard to the status of theconcrete, singular individual. And while a logic ofrelatives may escape the charge of platonizing in thegrand old style, it may not be so successful inescaping latter-day platonizing à la Hegel (despitePeirce's many protests to the contrary).

The extreme metaphysical realism which putsuniversality formally

7 "Even Duns Scotus is too nominalistic when he saysthat universals are contracted to the mode ofindividuality in singulars, meaning, as he does, bysingulars, ordinary existing things. The pragmaticistcannot admit that. I myself went too far in thedirection of nominalism when I said that it was a merequestion of convenience of speech whether we say thata diamond is hard when it is not pressed upon. I nowsay that experiment will prove that the diamond ishard, as a positive fact. That is, it is a real fact that itwould resist pressure, which amounts to extremescholastic realism." (8.208, from a letter to MarioCalderoni, Italian pragmatist, ca. 1905)8 Cf. Peirce's paper "The Logic of Relatives," Monist, 7(1897) 3.456 ff. esp. 3.458-463.9 Cf. Boler, op. cit., pp. 102-103 and W.B. Gallie, Peirce

Page 221: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and Pragmatism (Penguin Books, 1952), pp. 153-156.

Page 222: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 83

(not just radicaliter) in things themselves and not inthe mind of the knower, avoided by Scotus throughhis doctrine of formal distinction and haecceity, isdefended by Peirce. That is why he can call hisdoctrine objective idealism.10 It is a form of idealismbecause of the close affinity he posits betweenknower and object known; it is objective because herecognizes that it is the object known which governsour knowledge and not vice versa, that is, the objectknown has such and such characteristicsindependent of any particular person's knowledge,though not independent of thought in general. Butobjective idealism, interpreted in terms of thesynechistic principle of investigation, leads to a formof monism or what Peirce preferred to call neutralism(6.24). Synechism requires that reality be lookedupon as continuous, or as Leibniz says "natura nonfacit saltus." The only differences in nature, therefore,are those of degree and not of kind. As we shall seemore clearly in our discussion of law anddeterminism, Peirce rejects mechanistic monism as afalse theory. Accordingly, "the one intelligible theoryof the universe is that of objective idealism, thatmatter is effete mind, inveterate habits becomingphysical laws" (6.25).

Page 223: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

It is not unusual, then, that Peirce should criticize thescholastics for their "matter-of-fact" dualism. It wasbecause of this dualistic position that theirformulation of the realist-nominalist controversy interms of universals rather than in terms of laws is notaltogether satisfactory. It was their dualisticassumption which led to a variety of answers to theproblem (rather than a simple yes or no) and to itsdivision into various parts (4.1). The belief that mindand matter are two ultimate and irreducibleingredients of reality caused the scholastics toexaggerate, in Peirce's view, the opposition betweenuniversals and individuals and so for some of them toregard the one or the other as "more real." Again,this belief raised the perplexing question of howmatter can act on mind and of how the concrete canbe transformed into the universal. To answer this sortof problem required a breaking down of the questioninto logical, psychological, and metaphysicalquestions, the first dealing with predication, thesecond with the origin of ideas, and the third with theground of objectivity. The scholastic theory ofabstraction as a psychological process by which the

10 Cf. e.g. 6.25, 6.158, 6.339, 5.310, 8.151. In 5.121Peirce identifies "reality" with regularity or active lawwhich is Thirdness.

Page 224: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 225: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 84

mind sorted out the intelligible structure of sensedata through the action of the agent intellect wasdesigned especially to bridge the gap between mindand matter. This, of course, Peirce's idealism coulddispense with. Thus, when he talks of precisiveabstraction, he is not concerned with a psychologicalprocess but with a type of logical distinction betweenconcepts. We have already remarked thatmetaphysics is for him only objectified logic. And sothe problems which were distinct for the scholasticsare for Peirce really only one because in virtue of hisextreme realism he applied without qualification theprinciple: whatever is needed to explicate reality mustbe granted a place within reality11 (1.351).

It is not possible here to present in any complete waythe arguments which Peirce adduces for hismetaphysical realism. Such a presentation wouldrequire a detailed study of his theory of inquiry,philosophy of logic, and entire metaphysics. Ofcourse, as we proceed, certain of Peirce's reasons willbe analyzed, but for the moment we would contentourselves with a brief sketch of some of the moreimportant arguments, positive and negative. Thestrongest positive argument in favor of realism is thatthe very enterprise of science requires it (cf. e.g.

Page 226: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

1.351, 7.186). Thus, Peirce more than once refers tothe work of his friend Dr. F.E. Abbot, ScientificTheism, as having convinced him that "science hasalways been at heart realistic, and always must beso" (1.20, 5.12, 5.423). Basically this is so becausescience necessarily makes predictions which in themajority of cases are fulfilled in the event (cf. e.g.1.26, 1.343, 5.96, 8.212, etc.). A prediction isessentially general and as such can never becompletely fulfilled. It says what would be the casewhenever certain conditions are fulfilled. No series ofactual cases, however long, will exhaust theprediction. But when a prediction shows a definitetendency to be fulfilled, that decided tendency canonly be due to the fact that the future events aregoverned by a law, not by sheer chance.

If a pair of dice turns up sixes five times running, thatis a

11 Cf. W. Reese, "Philosophic Realism: A Study in theModality of Being," Studies, Wiener and Young, p. 225.One such qualification which scholastics would certainlymake is a distinction between cause and sufficientreason.

Page 227: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 85

mere uniformity. The dice might happen fortuitously toturn up sixes a thousand times running. But that wouldnot afford the slightest security for a prediction thatthey would turn up sixes the next time. (1.26)

The case of the pair of dice is not at all the same asthe case of a stone in my hand of which I predict thatit will fall if I let it go. In that case, says Peirce, Iknow that it will act according to the law ofgravitation (5.96). What affords us a safe basis forprediction must be the fact that the future eventsconform to a general rule.

''Oh," but say the nominalists, "this general rule isnothing but a mere word or couple of words!" I reply,"Nobody ever dreamed of denying that what is generalis of the nature of a general sign; but the question iswhether future events will conform to it or not. If theywill, your adjective `mere' seems to be ill-placed."(1.26)

A rule to which future events show a decidedtendency to conform is an important element in thehappening of those events.

. . . the fact that I know that this stone will fall to thefloor when I let it go, as you all must confess, if you arenot blinded by theory, that I do know . . . is the proofthat the formula, or uniformity, as furnishing a safe

Page 228: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

basis for prediction, is, or if you like it better,corresponds to, a reality. (5.96)

Peirce also offers a number of negative arguments insupport of realism, that is, he reduces certainnominalistic positions to absurdity or exposes certainerrors to which they lead. Thus, for example, heshows the absurd inconsistency of the followingnominalistic positions: that qualities are not realexcept insofar as they are actually perceived (1.422);that percepts are not subject to certain general laws(2.149); that possibles are not real but only afunction of our ignorance as to whether a givensupposition can be made (6.367-368); that there areno real connections between individual things (5.48-49). Again, by way of example, Peirce argues thatnominalism is responsible for that widespreadmisunderstanding of inductive argumentation whichmakes it impossible to justify, and ought to lead to anoutright denial

Page 229: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 86

of its validity (6.99-100).12 A nominalistic view gaverise to the mechanistic error (6.93, 6.274) andcontinues to set up roadblocks in the path of inquiry(6.273). Peirce could hardly have been more severein his condemnation of what he considered to be thesource of just about every philosophical mistake evermade. There is no doubt but that he was convincedthat any sound philosophy must adopt metaphysicalrealism, and indeed of an extreme type.13

If Peirce made synechism the metaphysical basis forpragmaticism, he also made realism the basis forsynechism. Synechism assured that his metaphysicsmust be monistic; extreme metaphysical realismassured that it must be idealistic; epistemologicalrealism assured that it must be objective. There is stilla fourth element to be explored, tychism, whichassures that it must be evolutionist. But now we mustconsider in a more systematic way precisely whatPeirce understood by "law."

12 Peirce is criticizing John Stuart Mill's claim (Systemof Logic) that the validity of induction depends upon"uniformity." According to Peirce, Mill uses the word inorder to avoid talking about "law" which would implythe reality of a general. Mill could not admit this, Peircesays, because of his strong nominalistic prejudice. The

Page 230: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

substitution of "uniformity" for "law," therefore, implies''that the facts are, in themselves, entirelydisconnected, and that it is the mind alone whichunites them" (6.99). In Peirce's view this positionraises insuperable obstacles to showing the validity ofinductive reasoning. Mill seems to have recognized thedifficulty and so had recourse to the notion of''uniformity of nature" which he says means that if allthe circumstances attending two phenomena are thesame, they will be alike. Peirce argues that thisstatement taken literally is meaningless "since no twophenomena ever can happen in circumstances preciselyalike, nor are two phenomena precisely alike" (6.100).If the statement is modified to give it some meaning,then (1) either it becomes grossly false, (2) or a purelygratuitous assertion, (3) or "a quasi subjective truth,not lending any colour of validity to induction proper."Peirce goes on to develop each of these alternatives.Finally, in 6.101 Peirce lists several senses in whichnature may reasonably be said to be uniform andoutlines his own position.13 See 8.145 ff., for a strong criticism of Karl Pearson'sGrammar of Science.

Page 231: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 87

2. Law as ThirdnessBy now, the reader ought not be surprised to learnthat Peirce's theory of "law" is intimately connectedwith his universal categories. It has already becomeclear that he situates law in the category of Thirdnessand that Thirdness involves generality or continuity.We propose to examine in detail the characteristics ofthis category as Peirce applied them to "real laws ofnature." Again, however, we must realize that we canhardly expect to find absolute consistency in theformulations employed over so many years in suchprolific writing for such varied occasions. At best, wecan hope to find a clear and firm line of thought auniform direction in which Peirce's whole philosophicthinking is developing. With these cautions in mindlet us begin by examining the chief characteristicsascribed to Thirdness and hence to law in order tosee how they are interrelated.

Fundamentally Thirdness is mediation. It is a mediumbetween Firstness and Secondness. In terms ofPeirce's modes of being, then, law mediates betweenpure possibility and actual fact. But in order so tomediate it must be general; it must be neither of the

Page 232: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

extremes and yet partake of aspects of both. Finally,because of its generality Thirdness must essentiallyrefer to the future.

First, Thirdness is mediation.1 Consider Peirce'shomely but apt illustration of the cook who desires tomake an apple pie for her master. The apple pie shedesires is no particular one, but only one of a certainkind, of a certain general description. She has an ideaof the sort of pie she desires and this idea taken initself, independently of the deliberate decision to takethe necessary steps to produce a concrete singularinstance of that type of pie, is a pure possible the airyobject of a dream. Between the dream and thefinished product is the efficacious desire. Again, tomake the pie she has to pick out some

1 "By the third, I mean the medium or connecting bondbetween the absolute first and last . . . . Continuityrepresents Thirdness almost to perfection" (1.337 froma fragment, "Third," ca. 1875). Peirce came to thisnotion early in his career.

Page 233: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 88

apples. Any good apples will do although she cannotpick out "any apple" but this one or that. It is herdesire to select apples of a certain type whichmediates between the given quality and the concretecase.

What she desires is something of a given quality; whatshe has to take is this or that particular apple. Fromthe nature of things, she cannot take the quality butmust take the particular thing. Sensation and volitionbeing affairs of action and reaction relate to particularthings. She has seen only particular apples. But thedesire has nothing to do with particulars; it relates toqualities. Desire is not a reaction with reference to aparticular thing; it is an idea about an idea, namely,the idea of how delightful it would be for me, thecook's master, to eat an apple pie. (1.341)

The object of the desire is not an unattached quality.

She [the cook] has no particular apple pie sheparticularly prefers to serve; but she does desire andintend to serve an apple pie to a particular person. . . .Throughout her whole proceedings she pursues an ideaor dream without any particular thisness or thatness or,as we say, hecceity to it, but this dream she wishes torealize in connection with an object of experience,which as such, does possess hecceity; and since shehas to act, and action only relates to this and that, she

Page 234: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

has to be perpetually making random selections, thatis, taking whatever comes handiest. (1.341)

Peirce explicitly spells out the moral of the story.

The dream itself has no prominent thirdness; it is, onthe contrary, utterly irresponsible; it is whatever itpleases. The object of experience as a reality is asecond. But the desire in seeking to attach the one tothe other is a third, or medium. (1.342)

It illustrates what Peirce understands by mediationand why mediation always involves a Third. Yet itmust not be taken as a rigorous analysis, because itturns out that, more strictly speaking,

Page 235: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 89

representation and not desire is the prime analogueof mediation.2 All that interests us for the moment isPeirce's generalization of the principle involved and itsdirect application to laws of nature.

So it is with any law of nature. Were it but a mere ideaunrealized and it is of the nature of an idea it would bea pure first. The cases to which it applies, are seconds.(1.342)

But that condition is contrary to fact. Preciselybecause it applies to Seconds, a law of nature is not apure First. It is then a Third or medium, andconsequently belongs to the category of Thirdnesssince "Thirdness is nothing but the character of anobject which embodies Betweenness or Mediation inits simplest and most rudimentary form . . ." (5.104).

Second, mediation supposes generality. In theillustration of the cook and the pie we have seen thatgenerality is involved in her desire. She desired tomake some particular instance of a general kind.Furthermore all her actions in the actual process ofbaking, for example selecting the apples, weregoverned by general rules of conduct. But let us seeif we can go a little deeper into the reason whymediation necessarily involves generality. Just what is

Page 236: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

required that anything at all be a medium? It mustbe distinct from what it mediates, although notnecessarily separable. It is a Third, not a First nor aSecond. Yet it must partake of the natures of what itbrings together. It must be like a First and like aSecond, that is, it must be both a First and not aFirst, and both a Second and not a Second.3 In otherwords, a

2 See Appendix II concerning the final logicalinterpretant.3 For Peirce vagueness and generality are two kinds ofindeterminacy. The former is the antithetical analogue ofthe latter. A sign is objectively general, if it leaves it tothe interpreter to supply further determinations. A sign isobjectively vague, if it reserves for some other possiblesign and not for the interpreter, the function ofcompleting the determination. Thus, in the sentence "Manis mortal" the term "man" is objectively general becausethe answer to the question "What man?" is "Any one atall whom you may choose." But in the sentence, "Thismonth a great event will happen,'' the term ''a greatevent" is objectively vague because the answer to thequestion "What event?" is not "Any one you like," butrather "Let us wait and see." Thus it is that the principleof excluded middle does not apply to the

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 237: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 90

medium is essentially indeterminate (5.447-449,5.505). It is both vague and general, although not inthe same respect (5.506). It is vague because in onesense the principle of contradiction does not apply toit and it is general because in another sense theprinciple of excluded middle does not apply to it(5.505).4 Thus the cook's desire is indeterminate withrespect to her dream on the one hand and theproduct of her industry on the other. In terms of logicher desire is of the nature of a sign. Indeed Peircesometimes says that mediation "reaches its fullness inRepresentation" (5.104), or that law is a matter ofthought or meaning in things (1.343), or that law isof the nature of a general sign (1.27, 1.27 n. 1, 1.26,5.107). In terms of mathematics, the essentialindeterminateness of a medium, its vagueness andgenerality, is nothing but continuity. Hence he tellsus that "true generality is . . . nothing but arudimentary form of true continuity" (6.172). A pointon a line, for example, could not connect the portionsof that line if it were truly discrete and atomic. In thatcase it would be a break in the line. It can bethought of as joining the parts of the line only if it iscontinuous with its immediate predecessor andimmediate

Page 238: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(footnote continued from previous page)general, while the principle of contradiction does notapply to the vague (5.505). No sign can be both vagueand general at one and the same time and in one andthe same respect, "since insofar as the right ofdetermination is not distinctly extended to theinterpreter it remains the right of the utterer" (5.506).The only way a sign can escape being either general orvague is by not being indeterminate, that is, by beingboth singular and definite. While a general predicaterenders the singular subject of which it is predicateddeterminate with respect to itself, it leaves that subjectindeterminate with regard to other predicates andremains itself indeterminate with regard to othersubjects. A vague predicate does not determine itssingular subject with regard to itself and a fortiori isnot itself determined to that subject. A vague predicateremains indefinite with respect to the subject. ForPeirce, no communication between persons can beentirely definite. Wherever degree or any otherpossible continuous variation subsists no absoluteprecision is possible. And since no man's experience isexactly the same as another's, his interpretation of aword must be to some degree imprecise (5.506).4 Cf. M. Thompson, op. cit., pp. 213-218, for discussion ofPeirce's analysis of vagueness. In two unpublished papers(1903 and 1909 respectively) Peirce explains that theprinciple of contradiction does not apply to "may-be's" orpossibility and that the principle of excluded middle doesnot apply to "would-be's" or laws (Peirce Papers, #641,

Page 239: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

pp. 24 4/5-24 5/6; # 642, pp. 20-22).

Page 240: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 91

successor. This is the idea one tries to express bysaying that a point has no length or breadth but onlyposition. Or again, colors in a spectrum arecontinuous. There are no sharp gaps. The borderlinesare assigned arbitrarily because in themselves thecolors gradually blend one into the other so that atplaces on the scale it is impossible to say objectivelywhether the color is orange or red; perhaps it is bothor neither.

Mediation, then, implies on Peirce's analysis bothvagueness and generality. The continuous involvesboth these sorts of indeterminateness. Therefore, byapplying the ultrarealistic principle that all logicaldistinctions are also metaphysical, it follows that realmediation implies real vagueness and real generality.Continuity is ingredient in reality.

Third, and finally, generality necessarily refers to thefuture. To understand what this assertion means wewill have to consider in some detail the kind ofgenerality Peirce ascribes to quality and the kind heascribes to law. At first sight it may seem strangethat Peirce should ascribe any generality at all toquality since he usually puts quality in the firstcategory and not in the third. Indeed, it might be

Page 241: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

argued that here Peirce collapses Firstness intoThirdness. We think, however, that such an objectionis based on a misunderstanding of theinterdependence of Peirce's categories and a failureto distinguish between at least two ways in which heuses the term "quality."

Peirce does ascribe a certain generality to quality aswell as to law. Thus in the "Logic of Mathematics"(ca. 1896) he says that qualities "merge into oneanother" (1.418) and thus exhibit a certaincontinuity. Again he says that qualities are somewhatvague and potential in contrast to occurrences whichare perfectly individual. And that is why qualities donot make up facts although they are "concerned in"them (1.419). Or again, explaining what a generalfact might be, he attributes its generality to itsconnection with the potential world of quality(1.420). The thing to note here is that quality is a"mere abstract potentiality" or possibility (1.422).Some have taken the position that Peirce is talkingabout logical possibility instead of real power.5 This iscertainly a mistake. In the text Peirce criticizes those

5 E.g. Thomas A. Goudge, "The Views of Charles Peirceon the Given in Experience," Journal of Philosophy,XXXII (1935), 533-544. Cf. John Dewey's refutation,"Peirce's Theory of Quality," ibid., 701-708, reprinted in

Page 242: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 243: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 92

who claim that a thing does not have the quality ofred in the dark, or that a piece of iron is not hardexcept when actually resisting pressure. Of coursethe quality of hardness or of redness is actualizedonly when the thing that has it interacts withsomething else, but before that interaction the thingreally has that quality potentially, as a real power andnot just as a logical possibility. Peirce describesquality as what "might happen" given the suitableconditions. It is a way of behaving and consequentlyit is understandable why Peirce sees it as general. Itwould be a nominalistic error to deny that thingsreally have ways of behaving, that is, to deny thatthey have real potentialities. Yet this is the position towhich one is forced who would make qualities merelylogical possibilities.

Now the question is whether Peirce thought thatquality, in the sense of potentiality, fits the categoryof Firstness. The answer is no. We have already citedin the previous section the text which makes thisconclusion inescapable. It will be well to repeat ithere.

A Firstness is exemplified in every quality of a totalfeeling. It is perfectly simple and without parts; andeverything has its quality. Thus the tragedy of King

Page 244: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Lear has its Firstness, its flavor sui generis. Thatwherein all such qualities agree is universal Firstness,the very being of Firstness. The word possibility fits it,except that possibility implies a relation to what exists,while universal Firstness is the mode of being of itself.That is why a new word was required for it. Otherwise,"possibility" would have answered the purpose. (1.531)

Possibility or potentiality, therefore, almost fitsFirstness as such, but not quite. Consequently qualityconsidered as potentiality does not quite fit Firstnesseither, because as potentiality quality implies arelation to Secondness or existence. Still, it is clearthat Peirce does use quality to exemplify Firstness.Firstness is the "sheer totality and pervading unity ofquality in everything experienced, whether it be odor,the drama of King Lear, or philosophic or scientificsystems."6 Peirce,

(footnote continued from previous page)

R. Bernstein's John Dewey on Experience, Nature andFreedom (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1960), pp. 199-210. I am much indebted to Dewey's article for thissection.6 Dewey, art. cit., p. 200, in Bernstein's edition.

Page 245: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 93

however, uses the term "quality" in two senses: as itis in itself, sheer totality and pervading unity, and inits relation to other aspects of a phenomenon, and inparticular, to Secondness or existence. In this secondsense, quality is not pure Firstness, precisely becauseit involves a relation to Secondness. More exactly,quality here is the Firstness of Secondness, and theco-presence of these two categories yields thegenerality necessary for potentiality or Thirdness.Quality per se, that is, in the first sense distinguishedabove, is pure Firstness, but as such is neithergeneral nor individual. It is something like thescholastic natura communis, an abstract naturewhich is neither formally universal nor individuated.Or again it is like the comprehension of a term takenwithout any reference to its extension. In this sense,then, quality does not signify potentiality or possibilityand there is some question in Peirce's mind whetherquality per se can be conceived at all. He seems tosay, as we shall see in the next paragraph, that it canonly be pointed to by an indexical sign. Secondnessper se is not general either. It is individual and evenantigeneral (7.132)7 in that it resists generalization tothe point where it would lose its character asSecondness if it were generalized. In this,

Page 246: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Secondness per se differs from quality per se or pureFirstness. Quality per se does not resistgeneralization. In fact, it is what makes generalitypossible at all. Hence, strictly speaking, Secondnessestaken in themselves have no common quality (1.532).Each Secondness is unique. NeverthelessSecondnesses as we experience them do havecommon qualities precisely because, as weexperience them, they are inseparably bound up withFirstnesses. It follows, too, of course, that we cannever experience pure Firstnesses or qualities per seeither. We can experience them only in relation toSecondnesses, that is to say, only as realpotentialities. Our human experience always involvesthis Thirdness, mediation, lawfulness. Indeed, Peircedefines Thirdness as

. . . that mode of being which consists, mind my word ifyou please, the mode of being which consists in thefact that future facts of Secondness will take on adeterminate general character [Firstness]. (1.26)

7 By "anti-general" is meant that Secondness cannotbe generalized after the manner of a law without losingits character of Secondness. Firstness may be sogeneralized without destruction of its character.

Page 247: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 94

It is no wonder, then, that Peirce finds no difficulty inassimilating qualities considered as potentialities tolaw expressible in conditionals.

The point to remember here is that Peirce'scategories are never experienced in their purity. Andwe saw in our discussion of the categories inconnection with the normative sciences, Firstness,Secondness, and Thirdness are distinguished aselements in every experience by precisive abstraction.Certainly, they are irreducible elements into which anexperience must be analysed, but they arenonetheless inseparable. Thus, it will be recalled,Peirce warned us that it is very difficult so todistinguish them as to hold them each in their purityand yet in their full meaning (1.353). In the sameparagraph he says that the categories are sointangible that they are tints or tones uponconceptions rather than conceptions. In yet anotherplace, Peirce points out that the categories, "beingenormously large, very promiscuous, and known butin small part, cannot be satisfactorily defined, andtherefore can only be denoted by Indices" (4.544).The categorial structure which Peirce uses istherefore highly subtle and complex, admitting ofvarious combinations. The more familiar terms which

Page 248: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Peirce applies to his categories, therefore, must beapproached with caution. They do not always fitexactly (e.g. "quality" and "possibility" for Firstness).8Indeed no term describing our experience couldexactly capture just one of the categories since ourexperience will always involve all three categories. Atleast this will be true of any experience which we areconsciously examining. By examining it, we areknowing it. By knowing it we are judging andinterpreting it. Whatever is known, insofar as it isknown, has a share of Thirdness. But Thirdness islogically dependent upon Firstness and Secondness.

Thus Peirce himself distinguishes qualities inthemselves and qualities as reflected upon.

When we say that qualities are general, are partialdeterminations, are mere potentialities, etc., all that istrue

8 Peirce distinguished the matter of phenomena fromthe forms of experience. The categories of the formerare quality, fact, and law, while the categories of thelatter are the monad, the dyad, and the polyad. Bothsets of categories are under Firstness, Secondness, andThirdness as universal categories (see 1.452).

Page 249: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 95

of qualities reflected upon; but these things do notbelong to the quality-element of experience. (1.425)

A quality reflected upon is one asserted of a subjectin a judgment. It is referred to some other aspect ofa phenomenon and so takes on generality. But initself, taken in abstraction, "the quality is whatpresents itself in the monadic aspect" of experience(1.424).

The phenomenon may be ever so complex andheterogeneous. That circumstance will make noparticular difference in the quality. It will make it moregeneral. But one quality is in itself, in its monadicaspect, no more general than another. The resultanteffect has no parts. The quality in itself isindecomposable and sui generis. (1.425)

Notice that the monadic aspect of experience is notitself experienced. It is gotten from experiencethrough precisive abstraction. This is the "quality-element" of experience.

In a later fragment (ca. 1904) Peirce characterizedthese qualities in themselves as mere "may-be's"which are not necessarily realized. Their beingconsists in the fact that there might be such apeculiar, positive, suchness in a "phaneron." And to

Page 250: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

emphasize that these qualities in themselves do notimply any relation to Secondness or existence, headds that they are merely a question of what one canimagine (e.g. a being whose whole life "shouldconsist in nothing at all but a violet color or a stink ofcabbage") and not of what psychological laws permit.This very fact

. . . shows that such a feeling is not general, in thesense in which the law of gravitation is general. Fornobody can imagine that law to have any being of anykind if it were impossible that there should exist twomasses of matter, or if there were no such thing asmotion. A true general cannot have any being unlessthere is to be some prospect of its sometime havingoccasion to be embodied in a fact, which is itself not alaw or anything like a law. A quality of feeling can beimagined to be without any occurrence, as it seems tome. Its mere may-being gets along without anyrealization at all. (1.304, emphasis added)

Potentiality, or quality as reflected upon, and law,therefore, are "true

Page 251: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 96

generals" in Peirce's sense. Now since the very notionof potentiality refers to the future (what can or couldbe) and since only something which is or involvespotentiality is a true general, we have established theproposition that generality necessarily refers to thefuture.

And yet we are not quite finished. It remains todiscuss the relation between potentiality and law, forPeirce explicitly distinguishes the sort of "truegenerality" proper to each. In the Logic ofMathematics, explaining what must be excluded fromthe category of fact or Secondness, Peirce writes,

This is the general, and with it the permanent oreternal (for permanence is a species of generality), andthe conditional (which equally involves generality).Generality is either of that negative sort which belongsto the merely potential, as such, and this is peculiar tothe category of quality; or it is of that positive kindwhich belongs to conditional necessity, and this ispeculiar to the category of law. (1.427)

Peirce never explains in so many words what hemeans by negative and positive generality. He onlygives us hints and leaves us to puzzle it out. The cluehe gives us is a set of contrasts: (1) the permanentor eternal as opposed to the conditional, (2) the

Page 252: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

potential in contrast to the conditionally necessary,(3) quality compared with law. Presumably, then,negative generality is that generality whichcharacterizes quality as potentiality, and potentialityhas something permanent or eternal about it. Thepermanent or eternal is what is time-independent. Itholds good always, under any circumstances. Itwould seem, therefore, to be an a priori condition orformal law. Did we not just say, however, that thepotential necessarily refers to the future? Is it not,therefore, time-dependent and mutable? The way outof this dilemma can be found by examining moreclosely how we express potentiality. Consider Peirce'sown famous example of "hardness." The test of amaterial's hardness is scratching. But no one wouldwant to say that the testing constituted thehardness. The material was hard antecedent to thetest (even though perhaps we did not know it untilthe test was made). Furthermore, a differentspecimen of the same sort of material would still bejudged hard even if no test were ever made upon it.Therefore, we express real potentiality in terms

Page 253: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 97

of subjunctive conditionals: "If such and such wererubbed with this material, it would resist marking."This conditional might be a contrary-to-fact, yet itwould still be true. In one sense then it is permanent,eternal, time-independent. The conditional does notspecify any particular time or time-interval t. And yetthe conditional does in a general way refer to thefuture. It says that would happen, if a certain set ofconditions were fulfilled. This sort of conditionalproposition does not assert the antecedent or theconsequent (neither as contingent nor as necessary);it asserts the connection between them or theconsequence as necessary. The Universe of this sortof proposition is that of possibility. It is thereforeindependent of the actual time-order, but notindependent of a possible time-order.9 It should beclear, however, that what the subjunctive conditionalasserts as true gives no direct information concerninghow one knows that it is true, nor does the assertionqua assertion need to furnish the evidence for itstruth. The point is that while the assertion of realpotentiality concerns the Universe of Possibility, theevidence for the truth of that assertion must beobtained in and through the Universe of Actuality bymeans of induction.10

Page 254: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Thus potentiality is in a sense permanent or eternal inthat it expresses a necessary relationship. Thenecessity, however, is not unconditional.Unconditional necessity would attach to theantecedent or to the consequent either as brute factwhich happened once and for all in the irretrievablepast, or as brute force force without law or reason(1.427). The necessity is conditional or relational, andhas permanence or eternality as a relationship. Ofcourse, if the conditions of the relation are alteredone has another and different relation. The formerdoes not ipso facto cease to be a real possibility (atthe very

9 In "Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism"(Monist, 16 [1906]), Peirce identifies the modes ofbeing (actuality, possibility, destiny) with theuniverses, not with his categories. "On the contrary,"he says, "the succession of Predicates of Predicates isdifferent in the different Modes of Being" (4.549). Eachof the three universes must be divided into "realms" forthe different predicaments or categories. Potentialitythen would turn out to be the Thirdness of the universeof possibility.10 For Peirce, what distinguishes a "true law" from mere"regularities" or summations of past experience is theway in which they are discovered (7.84).

Page 255: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 98

least a logical possibility). We see no objection to norinconsistency in Peirce's regarding potentiality as akind of law.

Still Peirce distinguished the sort of generality properto law, positive generality, from that proper topotentiality, negative generality. Consequently, hedoes not simply identify "law" and "potentiality."Indeed, Peirce's usual formulation of what a law is, isnot in terms of the "would-be" of potentiality but inthose of the "will-be" of actuality. To be sure, law inthis more usual sense is expressed in a conditional,but that conditional is usually in the indicative mood.It takes the form of a prediction. ''If such and suchmaterial is rubbed, it will resist marking."

A law of nature, then, will be regarded as having a sortof esse in futuro. That is to say they will have a presentreality which consists in the fact that events willhappen according to the formulation of those laws.(5.48)

Again, enumerating the three modes of being, Peircedescribes the being of law as that which "will governfacts in the future" (1.23). In another place, hewrites:

When an experimentalist speaks of phenomenon . . .

Page 256: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

he does not mean any particular event that did happento somebody in the dead past, but what surely willhappen to everybody in the living future who shall fulfillcertain conditions. (5.425)

In yet another context, Peirce describes law as "howan endless future must continue to be" (1.534),stressing the necessity, albeit conditional, of a truelaw.

In the light of these clear statements it is perhaps fairto say that the distinction between negative andpositive generality is the same (or almost the same)as that which exists between "would-be" and "will-be," between the subjunctive and the indicative. Thedifference which the speaker intends to convey by hischoice of mood is one of emphasis. The mood signalsa point of view or point of interest to be taken intoconsideration in determining the sentence's meaning.It signals what we called before a Universe.11 Peirce'sUniverses are

11 A shift in the modal auxiliary indicates anotherchange of emphasis, namely, a change of category. Forexample, a shift to "may-be" and "mightbe"

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 257: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 99

those which correspond to what he takes to be thebasic modes of being. Both ''would-be" and "will-be"are forms employed in future conditional sentences.The "would-be" emphasizes the necessary connectionor the consequence, leaving out of consideration thefactual status of antecedent and consequent. Itstresses the relationship between kinds ofantecedents and consequents, and only implies arelation to actual instances (as the basis for thegeneralization, let us say, in past experience). The"will-be" formulation, while including the necessaryconnection or consequence of the "would-be'' as thevery basis for the prediction, emphasizes the factualstatus of antecedent and consequent as about to berealized, probably to be realized, surely to be realizedin the long run, etc. While it deals with kinds of factsand their relations, it adds an explicit reference to theactual instances in the order of our actual experience.

1) If X were rubbed with Z, X would resist marking byZ.

2) If X is rubbed with Z, X will resist marking by Z.

For Peirce, Sentence 2 is a confident prediction as tothe actual occurrence of an actual fact in ourexperience on the condition that another actual

Page 258: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

occurrence of an actual fact be realized. Theconfidence of this prediction is based on thenecessary connection or consequence expressed inSentence 1, even though Sentence 1 gives noindication, expectation, or hope that Z will ever, as amatter of fact, touch X. We suggest, therefore, thatthe distinction between negative and positivegenerality has to do with the absence or the presencein the formulation of explicit reference to the actualworld of our experience. Potentiality, expressed inwould-be's, the foundation of and necessarycondition for law, expressed in will-be's (and,therefore, capable of being called a "law" byanalogy), is only negatively general for Peircebecause it consciously refrains from explicit referenceto the factual status of its antecedent andconsequent, while law is positively general because itconsciously makes such a reference. From one pointof view, then, "would-be" conditionals are strongerclaims than "will-be's" since they are the basis for theprediction in the first place. Yet from another point ofview they say less because they prescind from theactual occurrences in our world of experiences.

(footnote continued from previous page)

seems to indicate in Peirce a shift to Firstness as such,to quality in itself (1.304).

Page 259: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 260: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 100

We have indeed gone far afield in attempting tounderstand why Peirce conceived generality asnecessarily implying a reference to the future.Whether we understand generality as negative or aspositive our discussion has clearly shown that bothindeed do so refer. Both potentiality and conditionalnecessity by definition imply such a reference, and soboth are characterized by Thirdness.12 There areseveral other problems which must be explored (e.g.the distinction between formal and material laws, andthe notion of destiny), but at this point a summary ofwhat we have seen may be useful. So far in searchingfor an understanding of Peirce's use of the term"law," we have found that as essentially Thirdness orthought (1) it mediates between qualities inthemselves (Firstnesses) and facts or actualities(Secondnesses), (2) it is therefore indeterminate,that is, vague and general, and so is a special case ofcontinuity, and finally (3) its

12 "We may say that the bulk of what is actually doneconsists of Secondness or better, Secondness is thepredominant character of what has been done. Theimmediate present, could we seize it, would have nocharacter but its Firstness. Nor that I mean to say thatimmediate consciousness (a pure fiction, by the way),would be Firstness, but that the quality of what we are

Page 261: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

immediately conscious of, which is no fiction, isFirstness. . . . [W]hat is to be, according to ourconception of it, can never be wholly past. . . . I callthis element of the phenomenon or object of thoughtthe element of Thirdness. It is that which is what it isby virtue of imparting a quality to reactions in thefuture" (1.343).Past as past is over and done with. It can never beretrieved. It is frozen as it were with all the singularityand concreteness of its happening. To this extent, then,Secondness is its specific characteristic. Still, this does notmean that there is nothing of Firstness and Thirdness inpast events. Since everything and every event is what itis, past events have Firstness about them but not insofaras they are past. Again, since we can and do generalizeabout past events and since every concrete, singularevent is also an instance of a type, past events haveThirdness about them, but not qua past. Similarly, thepresent as present, the indivisible nunc, is only what it iswith no reference to anything else. Its specific characteris Firstness. Yet it manifests Secondness and Thirdness:secondness because any quality to be experienced mustbe embodied in an actual event; Thirdness because thepresent is embedded in a continuum. The future quafuture is characterized by Thirdness, because it isindeterminate. It has reality only as potentiality really inactual things capable of future determination. But ofcourse, future events will manifest Firstness andSecondness insofar as they are events, not insofar as theyare future.

Page 262: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 263: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 101

specific sort of generality ("true generality") refers tothe future. In short, law is founded in real potentialityin things, and can be best formulated in a conditionalproposition. Here are some of the ways in whichPeirce describes law. (Bracketed words have beeninserted to indicate the presence of the threeelements just enumerated.)

A law of nature, then, will be regarded . . . as having asort of esse in futuro. That is to say they will have apresent reality [real potentiality] which consists in thefact that events [Secondnesses] will happen accordingto the formulation [a symbolic representation to whichFirstnesses are essential] of those laws. (5.48)

In another place, and perhaps more clearly, he says:

[Thirdness is that mode of being] which consists, mindmy word if you please, the mode of being whichconsists in the fact that future facts of Secondness willtake on a determinate general character [Firstness]. . .. (1.26)

Or again,

My view is that there are three modes of being. I holdthat we can directly observe them in elements ofwhatever is at any time before the mind in any way.They are the being of positive qualitative possibility,the being of actual fact, and the being of law that will

Page 264: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

govern [hence mediate] facts [of a certain positivequality] in the future. (1.23)

In another place, Peirce underlines the conditionalelement in law.

When an experimentalist speaks of phenomenon . . .he does not mean any particular event that did happento somebody in the dead past [Secondness], but whatsurely will happen to every body in the living futurewho shall fulfill certain conditions. (5.425)

Again, in answering the objection that one cannotconsistently hold both that to be and to berepresented are not identical and that the nature ofreal law is to be represented (if the laws are real,they are

Page 265: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 102

not of the nature of representation; if they are of thenature of representation, they are not real), hewrites,

My answer to this would be that it rests upon anambiguity. When I say that the general proposition asto what will happen, whenever a certain condition maybe fulfilled, is of the nature of a representation, I meanthat it refers to experiences in futuro, which I do notknow are all of them experienced and never can knowhave been all experienced. But when I say that reallyto be is different from being represented, I mean thatwhat really is, ultimately consists in what shall beforced upon us in experience, that there is an elementof brute compulsion in fact, and that fact is not a merequestion of reasonableness. (5.97)

It is this reference to the future which distinguisheslawfulness from mere uniformity exhibited in pastevents. Rolling six straight passes with honest dice isa mere uniformity serving no basis for predictionconcerning the seventh throw. Thus in a review ofHerbert Nichol's A Treatise on Cosmology (ca. 1904)he criticizes John Stuart Mill for not having seenprecisely this difference.

We all know that John Mill banished the word `law' andsubstituted `uniformity' for it, as more preciselyexpressing what it meant. But pragmatism discovers a

Page 266: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

serious error here. For while uniformity is a characterwhich might be realized, in all its fulness, in a shortseries of past events, law, on the other hand, isessentially a character of an indefinite future; andwhile uniformity involves a regularity exact andexceptionless, law only requires an approach touniformity in a decided majority of cases. (8.192)

Peirce explains that law could reasonably affecthuman conduct only through the knowledge of sucha law creating and warranting anticipations of futureexperience. And what this requires is

. . . that the law should be a truth expressible as aconditional proposition whose antecedent andconsequent express experiences in a future tense, andfurther, that, as long as the law retains the character ofa law, there should be

Page 267: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 103

possible occasions in an indefinite future when eventsof the kind described in the antecedent may come topass. (8.192)

Such, then, Peirce declares, ought to be ourconception of law.

In a very early paper (ca. 1866) Peirce discussed thequestion whether in a world of chance all law wouldbe abrogated. His opinion was that they would not,because there are two kinds of law, formal andmaterial.

Suppose that in throwing the die other numbers hadturned up from those which actually turned up, so thatthe row of numbers would have been somewhatdifferent; still the laws would have held; they wouldhold with one set of numbers as well as with another.Whereas if we were to give a whale legs or a womanwings, the laws of the animal kingdom would beinterfered with. So that there are two kinds of laws,those which in a different state of things wouldcontinue to hold good and those which in a differentstate of things would not hold good. The former we callformal laws, the latter material laws. (7.137)

Peirce gives the principle of induction as an exampleof a formal law, namely, as is the sample so is thewhole and the sameness of a number of characters

Page 268: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

manifests identity of objects (7.137, cf. 7.131).

But so long as there are any laws whatsoever, theselaws . . . must exist. . . . Now all law may, in onesense, be contingent. But that there should beknowledge without the existence of law, that thereshould be intelligence without anything beingintelligible, all admit to be impossible. These lawstherefore cannot be abrogated without abrogatingknowledge; and thus are the formal conditions of allknowledge. (7.138)

The laws of logic, therefore, including the laws ofprobability, are universal laws that do not depend fortheir validity upon the peculiarities of the world inwhich we happen to live. They would hold good inany world whatsoever that was knowable. Even aworld of pure chance, if it were at all knowable,would be subject to these

Page 269: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 104

laws of reason. This notion of formal law, law ofreason, plays an important role in Peirce's theory oftychism. The world in which we live is not a world ofpure chance nor is it a world of absolute determinism.As a matter of fact the material laws of our worldadmit of variation, exception, and growth, which canbe accounted for only by admitting that chance is areal principle in its constitution. Nevertheless, in aworld of chance and of law Peirce will hold that thereis a destiny something to be fulfilled: the growth ofconcrete reasonableness. This growth requires formallaws of reason which give it direction and stabilityamid the variation and vagaries of particular materiallaws.

Forty years later, Peirce described the third mode ofreality as that which was destined or sure to cometrue (4.547), and he explained that "destined" meantthat which is sure to come "although there is nonecessitating reason for it" (4.547, n. 1). Theexample he uses is that if a pair of dice are thrownoften enough, they will be sure to turn up sixes sometime, although there is no necessity that they should.What assures us that they will surely turn up sixessometime or other is the law of probability. Indeed,the probability that they will so behave in the long

Page 270: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

run is one. And yet there is no necessitating causethat they should. The throw of the dice follow theformal law of probability, although there is no givenset of circumstances which determine just when thesixes will appear. Still as a matter of fact there are noformal laws really at work except in some sort ofuniverse with its material laws. Indeed we believethat Peirce held that it is the formal laws that notonly allow us to discover the material laws of ouruniverse at any particular time but also make thoselaws to be laws. It is the formal laws of reason thatcreate in the world regularities, potentialities, habitsof uniform activity (subject, of course, to modificationand growth through the operation of chancevariations which may tend to establish newregularities).13 There is evidence for such aninterpretation in the following portion of theparagraph under consideration.

I do not see by what confusion of thought anybody can

13 Hence Peirce's remark to Calderoni thatclassification of the elements of thought andconsciousness according to their formal structure iswhat is important. This he tried to do in his categories(8.213).

Page 271: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 105

persuade himself that he does not believe thattomorrow is destined to come. The point is that it istoday really true that tomorrow the sun will rise; orthat, even if it does not, the clocks or something, willgo on. For if it be not real it can only be fiction: aProposition is either True or False. But we are too aptto confound destiny with the impossibility of theopposite. I see no impossibility in the sudden stoppageof everything. In order to show the difference, I remindyou that "impossibility" is that which, for example,describes the mode of falsity of the idea that thereshould be a collection of objects so multitudinous thatthere would not be characters enough in the universeof characters to distinguish all those things from oneanother. Is there anything of that sort about thestoppage of all motion? There is, perhaps, a law ofnature against it; but that is all. (4.547)

Clearly Peirce is trying to distinguish "destiny" from"the impossibility of the opposite." He asks us toconsider two cases: (1) the sudden stoppage of allmotion, and (2) a greatest multitude of actualobjects. These cases cannot be called "impossible'' inprecisely the same sense. Case 2 is logicallyimpossible because it involves a contradiction.14 Inother words, it is strictly unthinkable because itviolates a formal law of intelligibility. Case 1 may bephysically impossible given the structure of our world,

Page 272: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

that is, there may be a "law of nature'' against it, butit is not strictly unthinkable since it does not seem toinvolve any contradiction in terms.

14 At least this is how we interpret that rather obscuresentence, "In order to show the difference . . . ." Fromthe context it seems certain that he is talking aboutlogical "impossibility" because he is referring to a modeof falsity. But something is logically impossible only if itviolates the principle of contradiction. The obscurityarises from the example which Peirce proposes. It hasto do with the thorny issue of whether there can be agreatest multitude. Is the notion contradictory? AsMurphey points out, the term "multitude" is usedambiguously for both series and collection (op. cit., p.274). It is clear, however, that, regardless of whetherPeirce's proof of his paradox is correct or not, he meantto show a contradiction and hence an example of thestrictly "impossible." See ibid., 238-288, for anexcellent discussion of the issue involved.

Page 273: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 106

Now, Peirce wants to say that the indefinitecontinuation of motion may be destined even thoughits opposite does not involve a contradiction. Neitherthe continuation of motion indefinitely, nor thesudden stoppage of everything is unthinkable. Eithermight serve as an hypothesis which must besupported by observation and analysis of experience.Neither can be ruled out a priori. On the other hand,we can infer that a "greatest multitude" of actualobjects could not be destined since it is contradictory.Whatever be the constitution of our world, a prioriknowledge indicates at least one characteristic itcould not have.

Regardless of how apt one might judge Peirce'sexamples to be, the point he is making is clearenough and bears out our discussion concerningformal and material laws. To summarize what can bededuced from this passage: (1) for Peirce the"impossibility of the opposite" means "what involves acontradiction;" (2) since the principle of contradictionis a logical law, the sort of possibility Peirce here hasin mind is ''logical'' (logical possibility is a necessary,but not sufficient, condition for real potentiality); (3)the formal or logical law of contradiction does notafford us any positive evidence of what the real

Page 274: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

potentialities of our world are, but rather sets anegative boundary to them; (4) therefore, the laws ofnature or material laws must be discovered byinductive inference; (5) these alone are the basis forour beliefs about future occurrences; (6) the logicalpossibility of these laws being contravened does notalter the fact that the evidence on hand that they willnot be so contravened may give us a probability ofone. The formal laws of logic therefore are theunchanging conditions necessary for our knowledgeof changeable material laws. But since, as has beenshown, Peirce's synechism requires that the laws oflogic also be laws of being, the formal laws of thoughtare not simply laws of "our mind," but laws of theintelligibility of things. They furnish, therefore, theformal principle of regularity to the world of changingfact. At any given moment our knowledge of the lawsof nature (material laws) is a union of the knownfacts and the laws of scientific inference governingthe facts. The facts might change and so the materiallaws, but not the laws of rationality. The change inthe facts, if and when it occurs, is to be set down toreal chance. Peirce's tychism will put it this way: nomaterial law is exact, not merely because we have

Page 275: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 107

imperfect knowledge of it, but also because of thevery nature of our world. Destiny, therefore, is theinevitable working out in the world of the laws ofreason without absolute determination of the facts.Destiny seems to be for Peirce something like anobjectified probability theory.15 Thus the summumbonum is the growth of concrete reasonableness thecontinual process of the embodiment of laws ofreason in fact.16

We have remarked that Peirce frequently likens lawto a general sign. Indeed, Thirdness or mediation, hesays, "reaches its fullness in Representation" (5.104).Perhaps this lead will throw more light on our inquiryinto the nature of law as Thirdness.

In a paper entitled, "The Regenerated Logic,"published in the Monist (1896) Peirce analyses whatis involved in making an assertion. Every assertionsupposes a sign-maker who delivers it and someinterpreter or other who will receive it. Some of thesigns employed are supposed to excite in the mind ofthe receiver familiar images ("we might almost say,dreams"), that is, ''reminiscences of sights, sounds,feelings, tastes, smells, or other sensations, nowquite detached from the original circumstances of

Page 276: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

their first occurrence, so that they are free to beattached to new occasions" (3.433, emphasisadded). These images themselves are signs signs byresemblance, or icons of the real quality (Firstness) ofthe thing referred to. This is the assertion's predicate(3.433). But the assertion which the deliverer seeksto convey to the receiver relates to some object orobjects forced on his attention in the course ofexperience, and if he is to communicate he must alsosucceed in forcing those same objects on thereceiver's attention. The icon, however, cannot dothe job because it does not relate to any particularthing. Some sign like ''this" or "that" or "hullo" mustbe used. This sort of sign is called an

15 ". . . thought, controlled by a rational experimentallogic, tends to the fixation of certain opinions, equallydestined, the nature of which will be the same in theend, however the perversity of thought of wholegenerations may cause the postponement of theultimate fixation" (5.430).16 Since "generals" are not only real, but active forces inthe world, Peirce could write: "Accordingly, thepragmaticist . . . makes it [the summum bonum] toconsist in that process of evolution whereby the existentcomes more and more to embody those generals whichwere just now said to be destined, which is what westrive to express in calling them reasonable" (5.433).

Page 277: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 278: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 108

index. An index does not describe the quality of itsobject; it merely points to it (Secondness, or"hecceity"). This is the assertion's subject(s) (3.434).But Peirce observed, "Neither the predicate, nor thesubjects, nor both together, can make an assertion"(3.435). The assertion represents a compulsion whichexperience brings upon the deliverer or sign-maker toattach the predicate to the subjects in a particularway. Once this compulsion is felt, it attains a certainpermanence.

This compulsion strikes him at a certain instant; and heremains under it forever after. It is, therefore, differentfrom the temporary force which the hecceities exertupon his attention. This new compulsion may pass outof mind for the time being; but it continues just thesame, and will act whenever the occasion arises, thatis, whenever those particular hecceities and that firstintention are called to mind together. (3.435)

As Peirce observes, this is merely the description of apermanent conditional force, or law. Therefore, tomake an assertion the deliverer requires a new kindof sign distinct from the icon and the index whichshall signify a law to the effect that "to objects ofindices an icon appertains as a sign of them in agiven way." That sort of sign is a symbol, and is the

Page 279: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

copula of the assertion (Thirdness).17

The following year (1897) in the same journal Peirceexpounded the same ideas in "The Logic ofRelatives." Arguing that class names should bedispensed with in favor of verbs, he writes:

A verb by itself signifies a mere dream, an imaginationunattached to any particular occasion. It calls up in themind an icon. A relative is just that, an icon, or image,without attachments to experience, without "a localhabitation and a name," but with indications of theneed of such attachments. (3.459)

This, of course, is unattached quality or Firstness.

An indexical word, such as a proper noun ordemonstrative or selective pronoun, has force to drawthe attention of the

17 Cf. also 2.249 ff., 2.293.

Page 280: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 109

listener to some hecceity common to the experience ofthe speaker and listener. (3.460)

This is the concrete individual or Secondness to whichthe quality is attached or in which it is embodied inexperience.

Contrast this [the "hecceity"] with the signification ofthe verb, which is sometimes in my thought,sometimes in yours, and which has no other identitythan the agreement between its severalmanifestations. That is what we call an abstraction oridea. (3.460)

This is what the nominalist would call a mere nameand what the platonizing realist would say is real.According to Peirce the correct opinion requires thatwe strike out the nominalist's "mere" and replace thePlatonist's "is" by ''may be.'' The force of the "may-be" is this: An idea is or exists

provided experience and reason shall, as their finalupshot, uphold the truth of the particular predicate,and the natural existence of the law it expresses, andthis is likewise true. (3.460, emphasis added)

In other words, to go from "may be" to "is" requiresthe mediation of some law or conditional necessity. Itis only real law which allows one to assert that such

Page 281: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and such an icon belongs to such and such an indexor, if one prefers, that such and such a quality isembodied in such and such a "hecceity." It is thesentence or proposition which makes the assertion. Itsignifies or expresses a law.

The proposition, or sentence, signifies that an eternalfitness, or truth, a permanent conditional force, or law,attaches certain hecceities to certain parts of an idea.(3.461)

Ideas or abstractions, therefore, escape from being"lifeless things" by being embodied in concreteinstances through real laws of nature (4.447-448).

Page 282: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 110

3. Law as Living PowerIt would not be inappropriate to say that for Peircethe notion of thought as a living force in the worldsums up his notion of law, and that thought as livingforce in the world is nothing other than realpotentiality or power, the ground for laws of nature.In more than one place he explicitly says just that.For example, in working out a detailed classificationof the sciences (ca. 1902), he argues that "the ideaof right and wrong is" (like Truth) the "greatestpower on earth, to which every knee must sooner orlater bow or be broken down" (1.217). Nor do thesemaster ideas get their life and power from powerfulmen who are disposed to make them so, rather ''it isthe idea which will create its defenders and renderthem powerful'' (1.217).1 In yet another place, hesays:

Whatever one's theory may be as to the invalidity ofhuman reason, there are certain cases where the forceof conviction practically cannot be resisted; and one ofthese is the experience that one opinion is so far frombeing as strong as another in the long run, though itreceives equally warm support, that on the contrary,ideas utterly despised and frowned upon have an

Page 283: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

inherent power of working their way to the governanceof the world, at last. True, they cannot do this withoutmachinery, without supporters, without facts; but theideas somehow manage to grow their machinery, andtheir supporters, and their facts, and to render themachinery, the supporters, and the facts strong. Asintellectual development proceeds, we all come tobelieve this more or less. Most of us, such is thedepravity of the human heart, look askance at thenotion that ideas have any power; although that somepower they have we cannot but admit. (2.149)

1 See letter to James, June 12, 1902, in R.B. Perry'sThe Thought and Character of William James, vol. II(Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1935), pp. 424-425.

Page 284: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 111

Peirce argues that even if one does not accept thisopinion, one must see that it is perfectly intelligible(1.217). Not only does he himself subscribe to thisbelief (1.219), but is willing to defend "the extremeposition that every general idea has more or lesspower of working itself out into fact . . ." (2.149).Whether or not he be correct in this "extremeposition"

. . . it must at any rate be admitted by every candidman that he does believe firmly and without doubt thatto some extent phenomena are regular, that is, aregoverned by general ideas; and so far as they are so,they are capable of prediction by reasoning. (2.149)

Ideas, then, have "generative life" (1.219); they arereal laws governing events.

That something like this is so, Peirce maintains, is amatter of experiential fact. But it is not the sort offactual claim that can be verified "by producing amicroscope or telescope or any reconditeobservations of any kind" (1.219). Its evidence, hesays, stares us all in the face every hour of our lives.It is, then, the type of factual question with whichphilosophy, not physical science, deals. The fact isthere in front of us, but we must open our eyes to

Page 285: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

see it and then try to understand it.

If one does not see it, it is for the same reason thatsome men have not a sense of sin; and there is nothingfor it but to be born again and become as a little child.If you do not see it, you have to look upon the worldwith new eyes. (1.219)

Indeed, if anyone were to deny that ideas havepower to work out physical and psychical results, itwould be a sufficient refutation to point out that thedenial involves a belief in that very same proposition.After all, any controversy, or more generally anycommunication, involves an interchange of ideas andthese ideas produce effects on the parties, in theirthinking or acting.

Words then do produce physical effects. It is madnessto deny it. The very denial of it involves a belief in it;and nobody can consistently fail to acknowledge it untilhe sinks to a complete mental paresis. (5.106)

Page 286: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 112

The fact is beyond any doubt; the question to beanswered is "how?" Peirce will offer his own "guess"(5.106).

Peirce felt obliged to explain in detail his unusual andcontroversial position. The main question to beanswered was the nature of thought's efficacy orpower to work itself out in the world and thus"transform the face of the earth" (1.217). In moretraditional terms, the question was what sort ofcausality do ideas exercise. Peirce turns to traditionfor the answer to Aristotle's distinction between finaland efficient causation (cf. 1.211 ff.). Peirce hadbeen arguing that a "natural" or "real'' class (anefficacious idea or law) is one ''the existence of whosemembers is due to a common and peculiar finalcause" (1.211). Ideas have their power by exercisingfinal causality. Now the term "final cause" must notbe limited to purpose. Rather, purpose is but onetype of final cause more familiar in our humanexperience because human purpose is conscious andcontrolled. But an idea a thought as opposed tothinking is not necessarily confined to aconsciousness, to a brain, to a soul (1.216, cf.1.211). Final causation, therefore, means simply

Page 287: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

. . . that mode of bringing facts about according towhich a general description of result is made to comeabout, quite irrespective of any compulsion for it tocome about in this or that particular way; although themeans may be adapted to the end. The general resultmay be brought about at one time in one way, and atanother in another way. Final causation does notdetermine in what particular way it is to be broughtabout, but only that the result shall have a certaingeneral character. (1.211)

In scholastic terminology, the final cause specifies theeffect an agent or efficient cause produces, that is,determines it to be of a certain kind.2 Again, sincethe means must be adapted to the end, the endspecifies what means are appropriate in a general,not necessarily in a particular, way. Efficientcausation, on the other hand,

. . . is a compulsion determined by the particularcondition of things, and is a compulsion acting to makethat situation

2 See e.g. Summa Theologica I-II, q. 1, a. 2; SummaContra Gentiles, III, 2, Item 2.

Page 288: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 113

begin to change in a perfectly determinate way; andwhat the general character of the result may be in noway concerns the efficient causation. (1.212)

The efficient cause, then, is what produces the effectby its own activity or action, hic et nunc, in theseparticular and determinate circumstances. Theefficiency as such has nothing general about it. It isbrute force, or compulsion. Thus in terms of Peirce'scategories, what characterizes final causation isThirdness and what characterizes efficient causationis Secondness.

To say that efficient and final causation are distinctand indeed irreducible is not to say that they areseparable.3 Peirce tells us explicitly:

Final causality cannot be imagined without efficientcausality; but no whit the less on that account are theirmodes of action polar contraries. (1.213)

We are beginning to get some insight into whatPeirce means when he continually insists that therecan be no law without cases under the law there canbe no true generals without instances, and so on. Hisfavorite illustration of the intimate connectionbetween final and efficient causality, between lawand force, between Thirdness and Secondness

Page 289: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

generally, is the relation between the court and thesheriff.

Law, without force to carry it out, would be a courtwithout a sheriff; and all its dicta would be vaporings.(1.212)

The court cannot be imagined without a sheriff. . . .The sheriff would still have his fist, even if there wereno court; but an efficient cause, detached from a finalcause in the form of a law, would not even possessefficiency: it might exert itself, and something mightfollow post hoc, but not propter hoc; for propter impliespotential regularity. (1.213)

. . . a law of nature left to itself would be quiteanalogous to a court without a sheriff. A court in thatpredicament might probably be able to induce somecitizen to act as sheriff; but until it had so provideditself with an officer who, unlike itself, could notdiscourse authoritatively but who could put

3 See the discussion of Peirce's theory of distinctions inPart I.

Page 290: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 114

forth the strong arm, its law might be the perfection ofhuman reason but would remain mere fireworks,brutum fulmen. (5.48)

A reaction cannot be generalized without entirely losingits character as a reaction. A generalized reaction is alaw. But a law, by itself without the addition of a livingreaction to carry it out on each separate occasion, is asimpotent as a judge without a sheriff. It is an idleformula entirely different from a reaction. A reactionmay be ever so conformable to law or reason, that is, itmay occur when law or reason calls for it. But in itself,as reaction it is arbitrary, blind, and brute exertion offorce. (7.532)

Generally speaking genuine secondness consists in onething acting upon another, brute action. I say brute,because so far as the idea of any law or reason comesin, Thirdness comes in. When a stone falls to theground, the law of gravitation does not act to make itfall. The law of gravitation is the judge upon the benchwho may pronounce the law until doomsday, but unlessthe strong arm of the law, the brutal sheriff, giveseffect to the law, it amounts to nothing. True, thejudge can create a sheriff if need be; but he must haveone. The stone's falling is purely the affair of the stoneand the earth at the time. (8.330)

The Court takes authoritative decisions; the sheriffcarries them out. The Court guides and directs; the

Page 291: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

sheriff does and acts. Together they achieve orderand maintain the peace; separated, the one isimpotent, the other brutal. Indeed neither Court norsheriff are imaginable except in reference one toanother and yet they and their activity ever remainclearly distinct. So it is with efficient and finalcausation (cf. 1.213).4

4 Every analogy limps. So does this one and Peirce ofcourse knew it. The weak point is this: a court mustmake practical judgments of conscience with thetheoretical judgments of rationality. "Conscience is likeour Supreme Court, which intends to frame itsdecisions according to the principles of law. But when ithas decided a point, its decision becomes law, whetherthe wisest counsels would have maintained it or not.For the actual law consists in that which the court'sofficers will sustain. But according to

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 292: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 115

To put the relation between final and efficientcausality in another way, we might say that

Efficient causation is that kind of causation wherebythe parts compose the whole; final causation is thatkind of causation whereby the whole calls out its parts.(1.220)

Peirce gives this illustration. If you took a corpse anddissected it very carefully, separated all the varioussystems of the anatomy and hung them in a cabinet,one superimposed over the other, so that eachappeared to be in its proper place, this would be avery instructive specimen, but nobody would dreamof calling it a man (1.220). What is missing is thefinal causation, the unity of parts, "which is whatcharacterizes the definitum" (1.220). Final causationis what organizes the parts in a particular way, whatgives them life and direction. Final causation is morethan the mere sum of the parts merely putting backall the dissected members of the corpse does notyield the man, (nor the corpse for that matter!).Thus, while final causation without efficient causationis helpless,

Efficient causation without final causation . . . is worsethan helpless, by far; it is mere chaos; and chaos is noteven so much as chaos, without final causation; it is

Page 293: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

blank nothing. (1.220)

Thus an idea (a natural class) is a vera causa, apower conferring existence upon its instances, not inthe sense that it creates new matter (for "blind forceis an element of experience distinct from rationality,or logical force" 1.220) but in the sense that itconfers upon the instances a direction, anintelligibility, a power of working out results in theworld, an organic existence, life (1.220).

(footnote continued from previous page)

the English logicians it is otherwise with rationality"(2.153). For Peirce, then, making a practical decisionhas an element of the arbitrary about it which is out ofplace in theoretical inquiry. There is a "fiat" involvedwhich enters into the legislation itself. Thus consciencemust decide how we are to act here and now, grantedall the limitations here and now of our knowledge ofprinciple and of fact. It must say "yes" or "no''; it mustdecide and that decision is final. This sense of ''law,"the decision of conscience, is characterized chiefly bySecondness. This is not the same as "law of nature"since nature's laws do not depend upon our fiat; wediscover them and submit to them; we do not makethem. Cf. 1.55.

Page 294: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 116

The doctrine that natural or "real" classes areconstituted by their members all having the samefinal cause is closely connected with Peirce'sconception of pragmatism. We saw that thepragmatic maxim is in the first instance a logical orsemantical maxim. It tells us how to make our ideasclear. It is a way to get at meaning. But meaning isan idea's "intellectual purport" and intellectualpurport has to do with ''purpose," ''intention," finalcause. Thus the pragmatic maxim has to do with thenormative with what our ideas ought to mean (orperhaps more accurately, with how we ought todetermine what they do mean). In this connection itis important to point out the connection Peirce seesbetween definition and the discovery of naturalclasses. The question is whether it is the definitionwhich determines what the class shall be or whethersomething else (final cause) determines what thedefinition shall be. The first alternative is that takenby nominalists; according to it any one class is as"natural" or "real" as another, because every classhas a defining character, and of course everymember of that class must have that character.Furthermore, any collection of objects whatsoever hassome characteristic in common, and so any collection

Page 295: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of objects, no matter how heterogeneous, could bemade members of a natural or real class. This positionis the denial of real or natural classes altogether,since absolutely every class would be real or natural.Peirce adopts the second alternative: find the naturalclasses first through an investigation into theirrespective common final causes and then definethem. The pragmatic maxim will aid in this sort ofinvestigation by directing our attention to the sort ofconsequences that might conceivably result from anidea, and those results reveal its finality. Strictlyspeaking the maxim does not yield an abstractdefinition but "intellectual purport."

So then, a natural class being a family whose membersare the sole offspring and vehicles of one idea, fromwhich they derive their peculiar faculty, to classify byabstract definitions is simply a sure means of avoidinga natural classification. I am not decrying definitions. . .. I only say that it should not be by means ofdefinitions that one should seek to find natural classes.When the classes have been found, then it is proper totry to define them; and one may even, with greatcaution and reserve, allow the definitions to lead us to

Page 296: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 117

turn back and see whether our classes ought not tohave their boundaries differently drawn. After all,boundary lines in some cases can only be artificial,although the classes were natural. . . . When one canlay one's finger upon the purpose to which a class owesits origin, then indeed abstract definition mayformulate that purpose. But when one cannot do that,but one can trace the genesis of a class and ascertainhow several have been derived by different lines ofdescent from one less specialized form, this is the bestroute toward an understanding of what the naturalclasses are. This is true even in biology; it is muchmore clearly so when the objects generated are, likesciences, themselves of the nature of ideas. (1.222)

Commentators5 have pointed out that the pragmaticmaxim so understood is very similar to the scholasticmaxim, agere sequitur esse. This principle wasunderstood to have a double thrust. As a maxim ofinvestigation it meant that the way to know what athing is, how it is structured, is to observe how itacts. The real potentialities of a thing are manifestedin its activity. On the basis of this principle thescholastics, too, specified "real" or "natural" classes or"natures." As an ontological theorem it meant that athing can act only in accordance with its structure ornature. Its being specifies its activity. Peirce's only

Page 297: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

objection to this principle is that the scholastics, dueto their limited logic, thought of the dispositionalstructure of a being in terms of substantial formsinstead of in terms of relations.6

The type of causation, therefore, exercised by laws asopposed to "forces," is final and not efficient. But finalcausation is logical causation, the causation of mind(1.250).

Mind has its universal mode of action, namely, by finalcausation. The microscopist looks to see whether themotions of a little creature show any purpose. If so,there is mind there. Passing from the little to the large,natural selection is the theory of how forms come to beadaptive, that is, to be governed by a quasi purpose. Itsuggests a machinery of

5 E.g. Boler, op. cit., p. 102.6 Cf. Gallie, op. cit., pp. 124 ff.

Page 298: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 118

efficiency to bring about the end a machineryinadequate perhaps yet which must contribute somehelp toward the result. But the being governed by apurpose or other final cause is the very essence of thepsychical phenomenon, in general. (1.269)

Thus in the concluding paragraph of an undatedfragment in which Peirce was striving to classify ends,he writes:

. . . there have been three grand classes of rationalisticmoralists who have differed from one another upon themuch more important question of the mode of being ofthe end. Namely, there have been those who havemade the end purely subjective, a feeling of pleasure;there have been those who have made the end purelyobjective and material, the multiplication of the race;and finally there have been those who have attributedto the end the same kind of being that a law of naturehas, making it lie in the rationalization of the universe.(1.590, emphasis added)

Peirce, of course, identifies himself with the lastgroup, but what is of immediate interest is that heidentifies the nature of law with the nature of end orfinal cause. Therefore, wherever there is law,regularity, real potentiality, there is mind, reason,rationality. And once again, for Peirce, mind, reason,rationality, do not necessarily suppose consciousness.

Page 299: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

So he can say that logic need not suppose that thereis consciousness (2.66). All it is obliged to suppose isthat there is knowledge embodied in some form (athought thought) and inference, in the sense thatone embodiment of knowledge affects another(2.66). Under these conditions all its rules hold good.Thus

the essence of rationality lies in the fact that therational being will act so as to attain certain ends.Prevent his doing so in one way, and he will act insome utterly different way which will produce the sameresult. Rationality is being governed by final causes.(2.66)

Indeed, for Peirce, since consciousness is in itself onlya quality of feeling, it has no room for rationality. Andthe notion that logic is in

Page 300: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 119

any way concerned with it "is a fallacy closely allied tohedonism in ethics."7

True laws of nature, we have seen, belong to thecategory of Thirdness and as such are manifestationsof the presence of mind or reason in the world of ourexperience. Laws are living ideas which have forceand power to work themselves out in the cosmos. Itis this conviction which as a matter of fact motivatesmen of science in their arduous research.8 Peirce hasexplained that the type of causation proper to reasonand law is final that of a type or form or ideal which,of course, to be effective needs some mechanism ofefficient causation, and therefore the very being oflaw is to govern actual

7 See the discussion of hedonism in Part I. The point ofthe comparison is this: just as it is a mistake to thinkthat the feeling of pleasure or pain which accompaniessome moral act constitutes that act's rightness orwrongness, so too it is a mistake to think that theawareness we have of an argument's validity orinvalidity constitutes that validity or invalidity. Thepoint is directed against those logicians who wouldmake logic rest upon a feeling or instinct for what issound and what is unsound reasoning. Of course, inanother sense of "reasoning" Peirce will admit thatcontrol is an essential ingredient and that

Page 301: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

consciousness is required for such control. Cf. 2.148,2.169 ff., 2.179 ff. for discussion of "expectation" inreasoning. Thus man is the "reasoner" par excellencesince his power of critical review and of self-control ismore highly developed than in any other animal weknow. Cf. 5.85-87.8 "The man of science has received a deep impression ofthe majesty of truth, as that to which, sooner or later,every knee must bow. He has further found that his ownmind is sufficiently akin to that truth, to enable him, oncondition of submissive observation, to interpret it insome measure. As he gradually becomes better andbetter acquainted with the character of cosmical truth,and learns that human reason is its issue and can bebrought step by step into accord with it, he conceives apassion for its fuller revelation. He is keenly aware of hisown ignorance, and knows that personally he can makebut small steps in discovery. Yet, small as they are, hedeems them precious; and he hopes that byconscientiously pursuing the method of science he mayerect a foundation upon which his successors may climbhigher. This, for him, is what makes life worth living andwhat makes the human race worth perpetuation. Thevery being of law, general truth, reason call it what youwill consists in its expressing itself in a cosmos and inintellects which reflect it, and in doing this progressively;and that which makes progressive creation worth doingso the researcher comes to feel is precisely the reason,the law, the general truth for the sake of which it takesplace" (8.136).

Page 302: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 303: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 120

events. The question now arises: just how, in detail,does this final causation work; how does it governactual cases; how is it ingredient in events? Peircefaced this question in a brilliant essay, "Ideals ofConduct," read as part of the 1903 Lowell Lectures.

Directly, this paper examines only deliberate humanaction or conduct and so only analyzes one kind offinal cause, the one "most familiar in our experience,"human purpose. In particular, then, the question ishow human purpose enters into human activity insuch a way as to make it controlled or reasonedaction. In virtue of the doctrine of continuity,however, Peirce will try to extend the results of hisanalysis to other levels of reality where mind orreason is embodied in other forms. Peirce was awarethat this sort of analysis is open to the criticism ofbeing anthropomorphic. He knew that objectorswould allege that he was reading things into the datawhich are proper only to his own experience as aman. Peirce considers this objection explicitly inseveral places. He says that to say an hypothesis isunscientific because it is "anthropomorphic" is anobjection "of a very shallow kind, that arises fromprejudices based upon much too narrowconsiderations" (5.47). In fact, he maintains, almost

Page 304: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

all human conceptions are at bottomanthropomorphic. What else would we or could weexpect them to be? All man's knowledge is basedupon his experience. How else could he elaborate atheory or an hypothesis except in those terms? Thereis no way for man to peek outside of his ownexperiencing-apparatus to get a look at "things-in-themselves.''

I hold . . . that man is so completely hemmed in by thebounds of his possible practical experience, his mind isso restricted to being the instrument of his needs, thathe cannot, in the least, mean anything that transcendsthose limits. (5.536)

The limits of his possible practical experience insurethat all his conceptions will be "anthropomorphic" insome sense. As he says, one might just as well pass alaw forbidding man to jump over the moon. Such alaw, however, would not prevent him from jumpingas high as he could. So too man cannot have an ideaof any cause or agency so stupendous that therewould be any more adequate way of conceiving itthan as vaguely like a man. Furthermore, Peircerecalls that the only satisfactory explanation of man'sability to form any hypothesis

Page 305: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 121

and so make any scientific discovery is man's affinityto the universe.

And in regard to any preference for one kind of theoryover another, it is well to remember that every singletruth of science is due to the affinity of the human soulto the soul of the universe, imperfect as that affinity nodoubt is. To say, therefore, that a conception is onenatural to man, which comes to just about the samething as to say that it is anthropomorphic, is as high arecommendation as one could give to it in the eyes ofan Exact Logician. (5.47)

Let us, then, begin with what might be called theprime analogue of mind's embodiments, conscioushuman reason, governing, controlling, and guidingconduct.

Peirce begins his analysis with the matter-of-factclaim that all men have some idea about the sort ofconduct which befits a rational animal in his particularcircumstances. Men have some vague notion at leastof "what most accords with his total nature andrelations" (1.591). Natura humana completespectata, as the scholastics following Aristotle wouldsay, is for Peirce too in some sense the material normof human conduct. Again, by inductive generalization,Peirce remarks that the ideals of conduct culled from

Page 306: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

this sort of reflection upon one's nature and conditionusually and rightly recommend themselves in threeways: (1) they have a certain esthetic quality aboutthem, a certain fittingness and proportion, whichmakes us judge them "fine"; (2) they must beconsistent with each other; and (3) they must beseen to lead to consequences which, if fully carriedout, are desirable (1.591). Ideals of conduct, then,must submit to a triple criterion: esthetic, logical, andpragmatic. Failure to live up to any of them indicatesthat the ideals do not in fact conform to man's totalnature and relations.

These ideals, final causes, laws of conduct, however,are not innate ideas9 nor intuitions nor even, in thebeginning anyway, conclusions based on experience.In the beginning they are learned from parents

9 They are not innate in respect to their particularcontent, although, as we shall see, there are innatecognitive powers or potentialities which must beinformed and developed by habits acquired throughexperience. In other words, what is innate is astructure or natural disposition to take habits and, inconscious beings, to control those taken. Cf. 5.504.

Page 307: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 122

or guardians. As the child develops his ownpersonality, through growing awareness of himselfand his environment, he gradually begins tointeriorize these ideals, to make them his own and toshape them to his own situation. In other words, hebegins to reflect upon the ideals he has learned andto intend to conform his conduct to at least part ofthem. He makes this intention articulate and explicitby formulating rules of conduct. Since his reflection isnot external to himself but rather the exercise of hisnatural powers and dispositions, that activity has inturn an effect upon his dispositions. They aremodified and moulded by the ideals upon which hereflects. In the course of these reflections he willconsider possible future situations in which he willhave to act and in which he ought to act inaccordance with the disposition such as it has beenformed in him through his reflections. Thus hegathers his inner forces and resolves so to act whenthe occasion arises. He makes his plan. Still, resolve,in this sense of a plan, is not enough in itself toassure that he will as a matter of fact act upon it. Hehas to work the resolve into his muscles, as it were.He has to convert it into determination or realefficient agency "such that if one knows what its

Page 308: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

special character is, one can forecast the man'sconduct on the special occasion" (1.592). Thus theideal of conduct through reflection is made into a realpower or potentiality which could be the ground forprediction. It has become the "would-be" which is thebasis for a "will-be." The ideal has become a law ofconduct. And we readily recognize Peirce'spsychological description as that of what we ordinarilycall a habit.

Peirce admits that we do not know with certitudewhat the machinery is which converts resolution intodetermination (1.593). It is "something hidden in thedepths of our nature." Peirce is interested for themoment only in a phenomenological analysis of whatdoes happen. He adds that while we are conscious offorming our habits, later we are not necessarily awareof them. One of the ways in which we ordinarilyrecognize them on the appropriate occasion is by afeeling of need or desire. Peirce offers the followingcase as illustrative of the process he has beendescribing. Upon reflection I decide that I should talkto a certain person in a certain way. I plan or resolveto do so when I meet him. And to be sure that I willnot be carried away in the heat of conversation Iimpress the resolution upon my mind so that when Ido get into animated conversation with this person,

Page 309: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

although

Page 310: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 123

my mind is completely occupied with the topic ofconversation and I never advert to my resolution, stillit influences my conduct (1.594). After I have left myfriend, I begin reviewing what transpired and askmyself whether I lived up to my resolution. If theanswer is affirmative, I am in the very formulation ofthe answer aware of a feeling of satisfaction (1.596).

In his illustration Peirce introduces the notion ofcritical review of conduct. It is this review whichallows for control of conduct in the future in terms ofideals. Conformity produces satisfaction andconsequently a pleasurable feeling; disconformityproduces dissatisfaction and a painful feeling whichindicates that our resolve is not yet fully adetermination and this may lead us to resolve again,thus strengthening the determination.

This sort of process, Peirce proceeds to say, can bebrought to bear on the question of whether myconduct conforms to my general as well as to myparticular intentions. It can be applied still further tothe question of the conformity of my conduct to themost general ideal of conduct befitting a man like me.

In any and all these ways a man may criticize his ownconduct; and it is essential to remark that it is not

Page 311: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

mere idle praise or blame such as writers who are notof the wisest often distribute among the personages ofhistory. No indeed! It is approval or disapproval of theonly respectable kind, that which will bear fruit in thefuture. Whether the man is satisfied with himself ordissatisfied, his nature will absorb the lesson like asponge; and the next time he will tend to do betterthan he did before. (1.598)

A man must frequently review his ideals; he mustcriticize them; he must control them. The job is neverdone once and for all time, because experience iscontinually contributing more cases, more situations,which throw more or less light on those ideals.According to Peirce the new data of experience arefirst digested in the depths of man's reasonable beingand then brought to consciousness. "But meditationseems to agitate a mass of tendencies and allowthem more quickly to settle down so as to be reallymore conformed to what is fit for the man" (1.599).

All these cases are practical. They deal with a man'sreview of his

Page 312: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 124

conduct and ideals with a view to improvement.Peirce now points out that critical reflection can alsobe brought to bear on the theoretical questionconcerning in what the fitness of an ideal of conductconsists, and from that deduce what conduct oughtto be. His concern is to remark once more that suchtheoretical inquiry is quite distinct from the practicalbusiness of forming conduct, while at the same timehe admits that if one does not lose sight of thedifference, such theoretical study "is more or lessfavorable to right living" (1.600).10 Peirce, then,admits a certain interplay between practical affairsand theoretical reasoning, but he is careful to offer awarning based on theoretical grounds and advicebased on practical experience: do not rashly andprecipitously abandon practical maxims and rules ofconduct gleaned from ages of experience becausesome theoretical consideration or speculation casts ashadow of a doubt thereon, precisely because reasonis notoriously fallible and so very slow to accept newprinciples as indubitable (2.177). Patience andprudence are the watchwords in translating thetheoretical opinions into everyday rules of thumb. Thetheoretical search for truth must ever be pressedforward if man is to be true to his nature, but

Page 313: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

experience and nature are the final teachers

10 See Part I of this book for a discussion of theoreticaland practical science. Peirce was forever pointing outthe advisability of following instinct and traditionalmores in practical issues of moral conduct. He thoughtof reasoning theoretical reasoning as very unreliable inthese matters and instinct as practically infallible. Andhe thought that there was theoretical evidence for thisposition. His thoughts come through in a striking wayin the ironic and satirical papers, "Detached Ideas onVitally Important Topics." He told his Harvard audiencethat if by vitally important topics they understoodmatters of everyday moral decisions, how to succeed inbusiness, or practical matters in general, they would bebetter off not to get involved in logic and philosophy.They just had to follow common sense and theaccumulated wisdom of the ages. But these "vitallyimportant topics" are not for Peirce so "vitallyimportant." The most important, because specificallyhuman, enterprise is the search for truth. And this canonly be accomplished by reasoning and by engaging intheoretical investigation. To be sure, progress ishalting and conclusions are fallible, but success isassured if men as a community persevere. Being a partof the community of researchers is what sets man offfrom the beast and what makes life worth living. Thatis why in another essay he could say that we arefortunate not to be tied to the infallible instincts of theanimal kingdom. (See 2.178.)

Page 314: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 315: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 125

and correctors of theory. Gamaliel once told theSanhedrin that if this work was not of God it wouldpass away, while if it was, nothing they could dowould destroy it (Acts 5, 34-37). This is much likePeirce's attitude toward practical principles of action.If they are true, theory will not change them; if theyare false, experience will sooner or later destroythem. Man's search for truth according to the canonsof right reason and in the spirit of humility can be,and indeed is, one of Nature's most powerful meansof making the truth appear because right reasonrequires respect for facts of experience and at thesame time is itself a fact of experience which must betaken into account.

Thus Peirce has described what he takes to be thephenomenon of controlled action. He has found inman at least five grades of self-control which he listedin another place as follows: (1) inhibitions andcoordinations that entirely escape consciousness; (2)instinctive modes of self-control; (3) self-controlwhich results from training; (4) the power to controlself-control (as when one becomes his own trainingmaster) in terms of some moral rule; (5) the power tocontrol one's control of control, that is, when oneundertakes to improve his rules of conduct through a

Page 316: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

study of the normative sciences (5.533). Peirce, then,has tried to show how human purposes are bothnormative and capable of modification by criticalreview. Human purpose, the arche-type of finalcauses, involves habits acquired and/or modified byreflection on experience. It is this capacity for criticalreview and control of actions and of habits of actionwhich for Peirce defines reason. It is this capacitywhich defines man as a rational animal and therefore,while it supposes freedom on man's part, freedom ofchoice, man is not free to accept or reject his natureand its freedom. Man is a rational animal whether helikes it or not; he has a final cause which even hisperversity cannot completely frustrate; he iscompelled to make his life more reasonable and inthis lies his true dignity and liberty (1.602).

Thus Peirce discovers that man himself belongs to anatural or real class quite independent of his owndoing or willing or wishing. While specific humanpurposes are subject to man's control and so to hiswill, the purpose of his purposes, the final cause orend of man, is found not to be subject to control inthe same sense. Man cannot completely vote himselfout of the human race, because even the mostdrastic step of suicide would be a deliberate choiceand so

Page 317: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 318: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 126

paradoxically reaffirm that man is man unto the end.The only sort of control to which man's end issubjected in the hands of man himself is the extentto which it is fulfilled and developed in individualcases. Thus while human purposes are the ''mostfamiliar in our experience" and therefore the mosteasily analyzed, they are not the most basic finalcauses even for man. Even though man is in aprocess of evolution, rather because man is in aprocess of evolution, he cannot abandon the deep-seated drive toward more and more rational behavior.That would be to turn back the clock; it would be theend of his evolution or growth; it would be devolutionor decay. Man's destiny in this process of growth is tocontribute more and more by his own decisions andchoices to the process itself.

Out of these considerations we are able to draw adistinction between acquired habit and naturaldisposition often overlooked by the commentatorsand yet one which throws considerable light onPeirce's doctrine. It is true that Peirce sometimesuses the word "habit" to cover both what iscongenital and what is acquired (5.367, 2.711), butwhen he does so it is with full knowledge that strictlyspeaking habits are only acquired (5.538).

Page 319: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Furthermore, at least once he explicitly warns hisreader that he is about to use habit in a loose senseto cover any sort of disposition at all. What isimportant to notice is that for Peirce, while a givenindividual man can and does control his acquiredhabits he cannot control his natural disposition (his"nature," what he came into the world with, what heis), at least not in the same sense.11 It may beindeed that his nature is a habit or bundle of habitsof something else Nature, matter, mind or what haveyou and Peirce sometimes talks this way (1.416). Aswe shall have occasion to see, his evolutionary theoryof the emergence of conscious human mind fromnature is in terms of habit-taking and grouping ofhabits.

Man, then, finds himself in the world with the powerto reason, and the power to reason is none otherthan the power to submit actions, purposes, andideals to critical review and control. Reasoning, then,is a type of moral or ethical conduct. If it is notsubjected to any check or control, it is notdeliberately approved and so is not reasoning. Alldeliberate conduct is conduct according to a rule,norm, or

11 Is Peirce here groping toward a notion of"substance," a principle of unity for the "habits"? See

Page 320: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Boler, op. cit., pp. 160-165, for a criticism of Peirce forholding a realism without substance.

Page 321: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 127

general pattern of what is appropriate under thecircumstances. These rules, norms or generalpatterns are habits, that is, acquired dispositions toact in a certain way rather than in another. Thesehabits are themselves capable of critical review andcontrol. This type of examination is what isundertaken in the normative sciences. Thus, if we askin what does right reasoning consist, what habits ofreasoning ought we to follow and to develop, theanswer is that right reasoning consists in suchreasoning as is conducive to our ultimate aim. Whatis or ought to be our ultimate aim? It cannot besomething narrow or selfish. It must be the highest,broadest and most general possible aim; it must besomething admirable in itself (1.611). We recognizethe hierarchy of logic, ethics, and esthetics scienceswhich investigate, respectively, what habits ofthought, of conduct, and of feeling man ought todeliberately cultivate in order to fulfill himself.12

Laws of nature, therefore, are in Peirce's viewfounded upon real active powers or potentialities inthings. The type of causality proper to "would-be's" isfinal, that is, specifying kinds of activity, specifyingkinds of objects by imparting such a unity to thewhole that the whole

Page 322: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

12 In the following paragraphs (1.612-1.614) Peirce iscareful to reject any semblance of hedonism. InPeirce's hierarchical arrangement of the normativesciences, aesthetics turns out to be what commandsthe rest and what is least satisfactorily developed. Notonly is Peirce's elaboration slight, but also appears tobe confused and inconsistent. On the one hand, heseems to assimilate aesthetics to questions of taste, tofeeling, to the subjective. And on the other hand, herejects mere qualities of feeling as admirable inthemselves without any reason and at least once talksof an intellectual side to aesthetic appreciation. Thedifficulties can be met satisfactorily, we believe, if wekeep in mind that (1) Peirce's final opinion aboutaesthetics was that it dealt with the formation of righthabits of feeling and not with qualities of feeling, and(2) Peirce's categories can never be separated or foundin their isolated purity anywhere in experience. Thesummum bonum itself, therefore, could not be just apure Firstness, at least not insofar as it is operative inour world of experience. Again a habit of feeling is aThirdness while a quality of feeling, in itself andunreflected upon, is a Firstness. The error of thehedonist is to confound the admirable in itself with theperfectly self-satisfied, the stationary, the self-contained. Peirce, in other words, challenges thecontention that the admirable in itself must be pureFirstness. His counterproposal is to make it consist inthe concrete growth of reasonableness an evolutionaryprocess of growth which needs all the categories to be

Page 323: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

understood but which is identified absolutely with noone of them (1.615).

Page 324: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 128

calls out its parts. Final causality is the causality ofnorms, rules, or general patterns in terms of whichdeviations are recognized and thought to be not onlyexceptions but also in some sense aberrations. Themost familiar and therefore most readily analyzed sortof final causality is that exercised by human beings intheir purposive, deliberate conduct. Upon analysis itbecomes clear that human purposes are, or at leastultimately involve, developed habits developed withinthe context of man's natural dispositions or naturewhich allow man to criticize and control his activityand which themselves are subject to review andmodification in terms of other habits and ofexperience. The critical review and control of habits isthe object studied by the normative sciences. When,therefore, man is called a rational animal, it meansthat he is capable of consciously taking habits, andthis itself is a habit (not precisely of man, since ratherit defines him, but of nature in whatever that may befound ultimately to consist).

The similarity between the role which habit plays inPeirce's scheme and the role of form in Aristotle's istoo striking to go unmentioned (cf. 6.347, for Peirce'sstudy of "matter" and "form" in Aristotle and in Kant).Of course for Aristotle form has a variety of meanings.

Page 325: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

It can be the sensible shape (morphé) of a materialobject, the intelligible structure (eidos) of a thingexpressed in a definition, or the final cause. The lattertwo meanings will concern us here. In effect Aristotletook Plato's transcendent forms and made themcompletely immanent. The Aristotelian form functionslike the Platonic in that it accounts for theintelligibility of the object informed, arms it withpower to act, and guides that activity along certainlines rather than along others. Thus for Aristotle athing's nature is the norm for its activity. Form putsfinality into the object and allows that finality to betruly active. A final cause which remained in everysense extrinsic to an object could not produce anyeffect at all on the object. At best it might be aterminus de facto reached. Briefly, for Aristotle formaland final cause in natural objects tend to becomeidentified. But this formal-final cause is also evident inthe principle by which an agent acts as an efficientcause since it is what sets the agent to work and isthe source of its activity. It is what the scholasticscalled causa causae.13 Peirce's "habit" plays just thesame roles. He undoubtedly

13An. Post. 71 b9-12, 94 a20; Phys. 184 a10-14; DeCoelo, 311

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 326: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 327: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 129

preferred "habit" to "form" because the latter was toostatic a notion. Habit was much more flexible andallowed for changes, modifications, growth anddevelopment, and at the same time preserved theimportant Aristotelian insight into real potencies orpowers in things.

In order to generalize the results of his analysis ofhuman conduct, Peirce must show thatconsciousness does not always entail the power ofself-control. Although Peirce holds that there can beno self-control without consciousness he is notcommitted to the proposition that all consciousnessexercise self-control. To appreciate this point ascholastic distinction may help, namely, that betweenconscientia directa and conscientia reflexiva. For self-control, reflexive consciousness is required, and ofcourse that sort of consciousness supposes directconsciousness. The distinction between first andsecond intentions is based on this distinction of typesof consciousness. The exercise of self-controlsupposes some sort of reflexive consciousness overand above direct consciousness.

We have seen that Peirce's analysis of man revealedthat there are some elements of his mind over which

Page 328: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

he has control and others over which he has none,but which are nevertheless necessary for the controlwhich he does exercise.

Our logically controlled thoughts compose a small partof the mind, the mere blossom of a vast complexus,which we may call the instinctive mind, in which thisman will not say that he has faith, because that impliesthe conceivability of distrust, but upon which he buildsas the very fact to which it is the whole business of hislogic to be true. (5.212)

One of the mind's elements over which man has nocontrol is the perceptual judgment, and yet it isthrough such judgment that he has experience ofand contact with his environment. It is through theperceptual judgment that he has data to think about.One of Peirce's most imaginative formulations of thepragmatic maxim incorporates this very idea:

The elements of every concept enter into logicalthought at the gate of perception and make their exitat the gate of

(footnote continued from previous page)

al-6; i.e. Meta., Book Z, passim. Cf. D. Ross, Aristotle(New York: Barnes & Noble, University Paperbacks,1964), pp. 71-75; 172-173.

Page 329: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 130

purposive action; and whatever cannot show itspassports at both those two gates is to be arrested asunauthorized by reason. (5.212)14

This ''instinctive mind" through which every conceptenters into logical thought Peirce elsewhere calls"Insight . . . into the Thirdnesses, the generalelements, of Nature." Again he refers to it as a"faculty" which man must have because otherwisethere would be no accounting for his undeniableability to guess right among the millions of possiblehypotheses which might explain a fact often enoughto allow him to make genuine discoveries (5.171 ff.).Man, in other words, manifests an affinity to naturehe is in it, is part of it, and finally it is this affinitywhich gives him "il lume naturale" for choosingappropriate hypotheses at all (cf. e.g. 1.80, 2.750,5.47, 5.603-604, 6.10). Instinctive mind, then, ispart of the natural disposition with which man comesinto the world, and must ultimately be constituted of''in posse innate cognitive habits, which is all thatanybody but John Locke ever meant by innate ideas"(5.504).

Peirce finds that the gamut of self-control in man(from control of one's control of control down to nocontrol) is reflected in the higher forms of animal life

Page 330: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

lower than man, with the exception, of course, ofthat highest type of control which distinguishes manfrom the brute.

The brutes are certainly capable of more than onegrade of control; but it seems to me that oursuperiority to them is more due to our greater numberof grades of self-control than it is to our versatility.(5.533)

The brutes, for example, use some sort of language(a phenomenon of self-control) and seem to exercisesome little control over it (5.534). They are, ofcourse, conscious beings, and the grade of theirconsciousness is judged precisely by the sort of self-control they manifest. For Peirce, what sets manapart from even the highest brute is the power tocriticize his thought logically the power to think about

14 When Peirce claimed that pragmatism is only a stepin synechism (5.4), he was thinking of the latter as ageneralization of the elements of mind or reasondiscovered in the analysis of reasoning which yieldedhis famous maxim.

Page 331: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 131

thought. One form of this distinctive feature of man'sconsciousness is the power of hypostatic abstraction.The brutes do not show any tendency towardactivities which require this sort of reflection (forexample, they are not engaged in mathematicalresearch or in the logic of mathematics) (5.534). Thesame sort of reasoning which led to the affirmation ofuncontrolled elements in the human mind would leadto the same conclusion in the case of the mind ofbrutes.

Clearly for Peirce man is directly aware of at leastsome of those uncontrolled elements. For example,man is directly aware of his perceptual judgments,even though he is not conscious of the psychologicaland physiological processes involved. In so far as thebrute too must have some kind of perceptualjudgment (vis aestimativa, in scholastic terminology),the same holds for him. This consciousness ofelements over which no control can be exercised isdirect, not reflexive. Besides, Peirce argues for threedegrees of consciousness: (1) consciousness offeeling, (2) consciousness of an interruption ofconsciousness, and (3) consciousness of learning(1.377-382). The first two degrees are certainlybeyond the control of those beings which have them.

Page 332: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Even the third type, consciousness of learning, mightbe in certain cases simply the result of randomreinforcement of reflex responses to external stimuli,and be, therefore, only direct and not reflexiveconsciousness. Indeed Peirce proposes as anhypothesis that the physiological basis of any sort ofconsciousness is tied up with the activity of nervecells discharging over different possible paths atrandom and slowly taking on an habitual response,that is, manifesting a tendency to reinforce thatresponse which removed the stimulus (1.390 and6.259 ff.). In the case of a frog whose brain has beenremoved and yet whose leg muscles respond tostimulation (say, by a drop of acid), there is somefeeling or awareness of the stimulus, and so somesort of consciousness present. But the random kickingand rubbing of the leg does not show control over themovements, but rather that the movements arecontrolled by the stimulus. The "learning" that takesplace is merely a conditioning of the reflex responseby "reward" (removal of stimulation). Peirce goeseven further and proposes that these properties ofthe nervous system (to feel, to discharge, to "learn")are rooted in the very stuff out of which all livingtissue is made, protoplasm. He suggests that all theproperties of protoplasm can be grouped under theheadings sensibility, motion,

Page 333: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 334: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 132

and growth (again corresponding to his threecategories) and that this "life-slime" is in some sense"aware" of its environment and that it acquires habits(e.g., in regard to its feeding) (1.393 ff., and 6.246ff., 6.278 ff.).

Not every conscious being, therefore, is capable ofself-control, although every being which is capable ofself-control is necessarily conscious.15 Indeed, interms of a doctrine of continuity and evolution Peircemust say that self-control developed out of a morerudimentary form of consciousness in which thepower of self-control was present only virtually. Andnow that Peirce has succeeded in generalizing therole of habit in giving direction to all living beingsfrom man to cells, he proceeds to extend the notionstill further to include what the man in the street calls"nonliving" beings. Again, Peirce's commitment tocontinuity does not allow him to admit a sharp line ofdemarcation between "living" and "nonliving,"between "mind'' and "matter.'' The fact that Peircethought of his system as an objective idealismindicates what direction his analysis must take.Perhaps his remarks about the classification of thesciences will help us to see the point. Peirce classifiedthe special sciences under two general headings,

Page 335: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

physical and psychical, the former dealing with theworkings of efficient causation, the latter with theworking of final causation (1.242). Just as efficientand final causation cannot be separated, so physicaland psychical sciences are interdependent to someslight degree at least (1.252 ff.) and both aredependent upon philosophy (1.249-250). Philosophy,however, cannot be divided into an efficient and finalwing. "For . . . to philosophy must fall the task ofcomparing the

15 Peirce tells us in one place that man lives in twoworlds, an inner and an outer, and that these worldsare bridged by his acquired habits and his naturaldispositions (5.487). He defines consciousness ingeneral as a congeries of nonrelative predicates(feelings), symptomatic of the interaction of the outerworld and of the inner world, and amenable to directeffort of various kinds with feeble reactions. The outerworld seems to act directly on the inner, while theinner only indirectly, through habits, on the outer. Thusconsciousness is necessary for self-control sincewithout it or at least without that of which it issymptomatic, "the resolves and exercises of the innerworld could not affect the real determinations andhabits of the outer world" (5.493). Peirce's "inner" and"outer" worlds bear a remarkable similarity to Teilhardde Chardin's "within" and "without."

Page 336: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 337: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 133

two stems of causation and of exhuming theircommon root" (1.273). Given a choice betweenCartesian dualism and some variety of monism,philosophy must adopt the latter. Peirce sees threepossible directions in which monism can bedeveloped: (1) neutralism, which would take physicaland psychical laws as independent of each other andstemming from some third Urstoff, (2) materialism,which would take the psychical laws as derived fromthe physical, and (3) idealism, which would take thephysical laws as derived from the psychical. Peircedisposes of neutralism by Ockham's razor and ofmaterialism by the first principle of scientific logic,that is, do not resort to the ultimate and inexplicableas an explanation (6.24). Objective idealism is theonly rational alternative: matter is effete mind.

Leaving aside for the moment Peirce's objections tomaterialistic monism which he identifies with theabsolute determinism of mechanistic philosophies, letus consider the strategy of argumentation dictated bythe espousal of objective idealism. If matter is effetemind, and if physical laws are derived from psychical,the great law of the universe is that of mind. What isthe law of mind?

Page 338: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Logical analysis applied to mental phenomena [forexample, the analysis in "Ideals of Conduct"] showsthat there is but one law of mind, namely, that ideastend to spread continuously and to affect certain otherswhich stand to them in a peculiar relation ofaffectability. In this spreading they lose intensity, andespecially the power of affecting others, but gaingenerality and become welded with other ideas.(6.104)16

This is recognizable as the tendency to generalizeand to form associations (6.21). This tendency isnothing other than the tendency to form habits, itselfa habit (6.612). Yet a habit, as a tendency togeneralize, cannot become wooden and fixed withoutceasing to be a habit. The generalizing of habit onlymakes it more likely that something will react in oneway rather than in another because it has already soreacted (6.148, 13.90 ff., 1.409). As Peirce remarks,did habits establish an absolute necessity,

16 See 6.102-163 for a lengthy development of the lawof mind.

Page 339: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 134

. . . habits would become wooden and ineradicableand, no room being left for the formation of newhabits, intellectual life would come to a speedy close.(6.148)

In other words, the law of mind would destroy itself.The uncertainty of its action, therefore, is no defect inthis law but rather its very essence. Mind is notsubject to law in the absolute sense of thedeterminists, nor indeed is matter. Mind onlyexperiences "gentle forces" which make it more likelyto act one way rather than in another. And now wecome to the key sentence: "There always remains acertain amount of arbitrary spontaneity in its action,without which it would be dead" (6.148, emphasisadded). The action of mind, then, requiresspontaneity, and spontaneity is characteristic of life.

The relationship between law, evolution, andchance17 in Peirce's cosmology is beginning to takedefinite shape. We will discuss this in detail later on,but for the moment we want to see how theseconsiderations enter into Peirce's extension of habitdown to the world of physics and chemistry, down tothe world of "physical laws." The strategy of the moveis clear enough. Peirce must claim that even atomsmanifest a certain spontaneity in their activity and are

Page 340: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

not, therefore, contrary to the unsophisticatedjudgment of the man in the street, completely dead.To accomplish that, Peirce must show that no laws ofnature whatsoever are completely exact andunvariable, not merely in the sense that ourexpression of those laws is inexact nor merely thatthere are errors in observation, but that the observedobjects themselves do not conform precisely to thegeneral ideal governing them. In turn, this willrequire an analysis of the laws of conservative andnonconservative action.

Peirce is explicit in siding with the ancient atomistswho made the atoms swerve as they whirled in thevoid (6.36, 6.201). Atoms are not completely dead.By swerving they manifest a certain spontaneity,"immanent action" in scholastic terms, and in sodoing reveal themselves as conscious in somerudimentary way.18 Consciousness, for

17 See 6.201, "chance" is a mathematical term for"spontaneity."18 Peirce seems to imply that any activity subject to anylaw of reason whatsoever, even only the law of statisticsin the case of the chance swerving of atoms, is really asort of conduct, and so ultimately subject to control. Tothe control of what or whom? Who or What is theObjective Mind? In

Page 341: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 342: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 135

Peirce, is, we have seen, in the category of Firstness.So is spontaneity. Peirce feels he can conclude,therefore, that

. . . whatever is First is ipso facto sentient. If I makeatoms swerve as I do I make them swerve but veryvery little, because I conceive they are not absolutelydead. And by that I do not mean exactly that I holdthem to be physically such as the materialists holdthem to be, only with a small dose of sentiencysuperadded. For that, I grant, would be feeble enough.But what I mean is, that all that there is, is First,Feelings; Second, Efforts; Third, Habits all of which aremore familiar to us on their psychical side than on theirphysical side; and that dead matter would be merelythe final result of the complete induration of habitreducing the free play of feeling and the bruteirrationality of effort to complete death. (6.201)

Thus by introducing spontaneity, chance,rudimentary consciousness into the physical world,Peirce feels that he can break the vise-like grip ofmechanism which not only does not explain any ofthe phenomena but so chokes the life out ofeverything that any movement at all, even purely"mechanical" would be impossible. What Peirce isgetting at is that there is no such thing as purelymechanical movement. All movement requires some

Page 343: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

degree of spontaneity, and indeed, paradoxically, sodoes the observed regularity of the movement. AsPeirce himself puts it,

I make use of chance chiefly to make room for aprinciple of generalization, or tendency to form habits,which I hold has produced all regularities. Themechanical philosopher leaves the whole specificationof the world utterly unaccounted for, which is prettynearly as bad as to baldly attribute it to chance. Iattribute it altogether to chance, it is true, but tochance in the form of spontaneity which is in somedegree regular. [That is, governed by laws ofprobability.] (6.63)19

(footnote continued from previous page)

places, Peirce seems to tend toward identifying it withGod and in other places seems to consider the questionunnecessary.19 ". . . the existence of absolute chance, as well as manyof its characters,

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 344: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 136

To put it in another way, for Peirce there is nophysical without the psychical, just as there is nopure efficient causation without final. Whilespontaneity, chance, or rudimentary consciousness isnot identical with mind or reason and its fundamentallaw of habit-taking, it breaks the bonds of pureefficient causation and allows Mind and its lawentrance, making the physical intelligible.20

Peirce centers his analysis of physical laws on thequestion of causation. He is considering the relationbetween efficient and final cause, which wediscussed above, from another side. There are, hetells us, many examples of "empirical laws" in bookson physics which, although they are satisfied byobservation of the facts under limited circumstances,do not "go down to the roots of existence" exhibitingthe general form of all phenomena (7.468). The lawof centrifugal force is a good example. It applies tothe force exerted on railroad tracks by the wheels ofa train negotiating a curve. The force is real and iteven leaves its mark on the tracks and on the wheels.But what happens when the formula for centrifugalforce is extended to cases where the motion inquestion is not restrained and guided by somethingrigid like railroad tracks? What happens when it is

Page 345: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

applied to the revolution of the planets?

In this case, centrifugal force is a mere formula, aformula

(footnote continued from previous page)

are not themselves absolute chances, or sporadicevents, unsubject to general law. On the contrary,these things are general laws. Everybody is familiarwith the fact that chance has laws, and that statisticalresults follow therefrom. Very well: I do not propose toexplain anything as due to the action of chance, that is,as being lawless. I do not countenance the idea thatBible stories, for instance, show that nature's lawswere violated; though they may help to show thatnature's laws are not so mechanical as we areaccustomed to think. But I only propose to explain theregularities of nature as consequences of the onlyuniformity, or general fact, there was in the chaos,namely, the general absence of any determinate law.In fact, after the first step is taken, I only use chanceto give room for the development of law by means ofthe law of habits" (6.606, rejoinder to Dr. Carus).20 As has been pointed out elsewhere, in virtue of thegeneral doctrine of the categories, consciousness andhabit are distinct as Firstness and Thirdness. In manypassages Peirce makes the point even more explicitly: ageneral idea is the mark of a habit (7.498); consciousnessof a habit constitutes a general idea (6.21); habitsthemselves are unconscious, but feelings are

Page 346: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

symptomatic of their presence (5.492); etc.

Page 347: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 137

which is undoubtedly quite correct as far as the effectgoes, while yet the centrifugal force is a merely formalaffair with nothing at all corresponding to it in nature.(7.468)

Peirce likens this sort of extension to a bookkeepingfiction.21

It is very much as if between two men, A and B, therehad been a single transaction consisting in A lending B$5. Now if B were to keep his books in such a mannerthat the state of the account as entered on those booksmade A owe him $100 with $105 on the opposite sideof the account, the entries would in effect be correct;but yet that hundred dollars would be a fiction of book-keeping. In like manner the centrifugal force of aplanet is a fiction due to using polar coordinates inplace of rectangular coordinates. (7.468)

Certainly, if the sun's gravitation were suddenlydestroyed, "there would be at the first instant anacceleration of the plant away from the circular orbitequal to the centrifugal force," but, Peirce argues,this acceleration away from the circular orbit is simplythe entry we have to make on one side of ouraccounts to balance the first fictitious entry wevirtually made on the other side by taking the planet'scircular motion as the standard from which to reckon

Page 348: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

accelerations (7.468).22 The question Peirce wishesto raise, therefore, is whether

21 The technique of "balancing the books" is nowcalled by physicists "renormalization." It consists incertain adjustments that must be made betweentheoretical computation and observation. Fermi usedprecisely the analogy of bookkeeping.22 The concept of centrifugal force comes from suchphenomena as wheels following a curved track or themotion of a sling whirled in the air. Once we generalizethe idea in such a way that we remove the string whichkeeps the object in a circular path or the rigid trackforcing the wheels to turn, we have a mathematicalformula only, useful perhaps for explaining thephenomena but no longer a "real force" or real entity.Peirce was not alone in realizing this. Indeed, as MaxJammer has shown, physicists were already well on theirway to making the notion of force as applied togravitation operational, and were inclined to jettison thenotion that force is some sort of entity in its own right.See Concepts of Force (New York: Harper Torchbooks,1962), Ch. 10 and 11, pp. 188-240. Peirce would bewilling to go along with this interpretation within physics,but would not be willing to admit there are no forces atwork in the cosmos with which philosophy

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 349: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 138

or not there is any way to tell that any "empirical law"is not just a bookkeeping fiction but a "real and aliving action in nature" (7.469). Peirce realizes thatnominalistic logicians will not admit any suchdistinction in virtue of their "preconceivedmetaphysical opinions'' and that ''of absoluteknowledge there can be no question" (7.469). Whathe is after is the hypothesis sanctioned by synechismthe hypothesis which does not block the road toinquiry.

Peirce immediately formulates his hypothesis, and it isnot hard to recognize the notion of habit thereinimplied.

But if we see that as soon as circumstances aresomewhat varied, the form of the law is lost, theinference would seem to be that it is not a universal orliving mode of action. If on the other hand, we find thatas soon as the form is prevented from manifestation inone shape it immediately reappears in another shape,and especially if it shows a power of spreading and ofreproducing itself, these phenomena may beconsidered as evidence of genuine vitality andfundamental reality in the form of the law. (7.469)23

What he intends to prove is that causation, asdistinct from the action of conservative force, "is a

Page 350: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

real, fundamental, and vital element both in the outerand in the inner world" (7.469). In another placePeirce

(footnote continued from previous page)

must reckon. One of his main theses is precisely thatpotentialities are real and living forces in nature.23 Here Peirce seems to be groping toward a formulationof the second basic principle of special relativity theory:the covariance of basic physical laws. (See A. Einstein andL. Infeld, The Evolution of Physics [New York: Simon andSchuster, 1961], pp. 177-178.) Of course, he never put itquite that way since he was not dealing with exactly thesame sort of problems as Einstein. This is not surprisingwhen we remember that relativity was in the air aboutthis time. Physicists were beginning to run into problemswhich Newtonian space, time and laws of motion couldnot handle satisfactorily. The time was fast becoming ripefor a fresh look at the whole structure of that science. Asearly as 1904 Poincaré formulated a theory of relativityvery much like Einstein's. (See Sir Edmund Whittake, AHistory of the Theories of Aether and Electricity [NewYork: Harper Torchbooks, 1960], pp. 30 ff.) Peirce knewof these developments and could not have been surprisedwhen, in 1905, Einstein's paper amplifying and modifyingthe relativity theory of Poincaré and Lorentz appeared.

Page 351: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 139

examines just what is meant by the principle ofcausation and finds that it means many differentthings to different people at different times (6.66).For the sake of the argument, however, he assumesthat the principle involves three propositions to whichmost thinkers of his day would subscribe, namely, (1)that the state of things at any one instant iscompletely and exactly determined by the state ofthings at one other instant; (2) the cause, ordetermining state of things, precedes the effect ordetermined state of things in time; and (3) no factdetermines a fact preceding it in time in the samesense in which it determines a fact following it in time(6.68). Although Peirce himself does not admit theabsolute determinism implied in this formulation, itwill serve his purposes, namely, to show that all threeof these propositions are in flat contradiction to thelaws of mechanics, and that causation is notreducible to any such law even though it has itsorigin in the very same thing as those laws. If thelaws of dynamics contradict the principle of causationin its most deterministic form, it follows that adeterminist cannot appeal to those laws to supporthis metaphysical position. If, on the other hand,causation in some sense of the term can be shown to

Page 352: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

be different from conservative force and irreducible toit, there is then room for end-directed activity even inthe physical world.24 If, finally, both conservativeaction and nonconservative action (causation) can beshown to arise from a common root, it follows thatneither alone provides a satisfactory understanding ofthe universe.

There is no point in examining the details of howPeirce shows that the laws of dynamics contradict thethree propositions belonging to the mechanisticversion of the principle of causation cited above (cf.6.68-69). Let us simply point out that since, in termsof the laws of dynamics, the future determines thepast in exactly the same way in which the pastdetermines the future, he can define the essentialcharacteristic of conservative action as reversibility.The classic example of reversibility is a ball falling andstriking a perfectly elastic horizontal surface. Itsvelocities before and after striking the surface will beexactly the same except in reverse order, and thereason

24 Peirce remarks that if the word "teleological" is toostrong, then we might invent the word "finious" todescribe the end-directed nature of nonconservativeaction (7.471). Modern biologists have inventedanother word for the same idea, "teleonomic."

Page 353: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 354: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 140

obviously is because velocity is a function of thesquare of the time. Since even powers admit bothpositive and negative values without affecting theresult, every law of dynamics in which an even powerappears is conservative. As we would expect, then,nonconservative action is characterized byirreversibility of phenomena and a tendency toward afinal state (finiosity) (7.472). While it is clear thatpsychical phenomena show nonconservative action,what is more interesting is that even phenomena inthe physical world which are of psychical interestseem at least to be under the governance of thesame kind of action. For example, birth, growth, life,friction, viscosity, combustion, conduction of heat,capillarity, diffusion of liquids, to mention but a few,all seem to be nonconservative.

Physicists generally explain those actions which seemto violate the law of the conservation of energy(nonconservative actions) in terms of the action ofchance. Thus, for example, the phenomenon of gasescaping through a hole in a cylinder can be analyzedinto the change of movement of millions of molecules.Again, friction can be looked on as the chanceinterlacing and rupturing of molecules forming thesurfaces in contact (7.472). Peirce is in complete

Page 355: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

accord with this sort of explanation (cf. 7.470, 6.73).

As to those explanations which the physicists proposefor irreversible phenomena by means of the doctrine ofchances as applied to trillions of molecules, I acceptthem fully as one of the finest achievements of science.. . . This explanation demonstrates that the agency ofenergy is disseminated through every department ofphysical phenomena. But in one thing it fails; namely,it fails to show the absence of a very different kind ofagency; and it not only fails to show its absence, buteven supplies the means of proving its presence.(7.470)

The agency to which Peirce refers is spontaneity orrudimentary consciousness.25

25 When Peirce comes to work out his evolutionaryhypothesis, he will refer to this rudimentaryconsciousness as quale-consciousness. Strictly speakingit is the first emergence from the "Nothing of boundlessfreedom" and is not a waking consciousness. It is apotential consciousness (6.219-221, 6.198).

Page 356: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 141

We will not attempt to go into the mathematico-logical analysis of chance and probability worked outso carefully by Peirce. It is sufficient for anunderstanding of what he is up to simply to remarkthat he does not put chance down to our ignorance.

Surely, I need not waste breath in refuting thatfeeblest of attempts at analysis which makes chance toconsist in our ignorance. For that has already beensufficiently done in the Logic of Chance of John Venn. .. . It is the operation of chance which produces theretardation of the upper layer of air [an example offriction which Peirce had just considered] . . .; butsurely it is no ignorance of ours that has that effect.Chance, then, as an objective phenomenon, is aproperty of a distribution. (6.74)

In one place, Peirce tells us clearly that chance is"that diversity and variety of things and events whichlaw does not prevent" (6.612). This is the real chanceupon which kinetic theory, for example, depends. Itcan be shown, Peirce declares, that this chance mustbe absolute, that is, not derivable from law, by thevery logic of explanation (cf. Part III, Chapter 1) andat the same time it is not totally lawless since itexhibits at least the uniformity of the absence of anydeterminate law (6.606). This is the only sort of

Page 357: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

regularity chaos could manifest, but because of itchaos can be reasoned about statistically and couldallow for the development of determinate law bymeans of the law of habit (6.606). And if it beobjected that Peirce does not escape making lawabsolute, since the tendency to take habits is itself alaw, the reply is that while the word "law" isconvenient to describe that tendency, it is not used inthe sense of inviolable, mechanical law but in thesense of mental law the violation of which is soincluded in its essence that unless it were violated itwould cease to exist (6.612).

If chance is a property of a distribution, a distributionis a property of a collection. Since, however, there aredifferent kinds of collections, the sorts of distributionof which each is capable are different and so eachmust be considered in turn to determine whether ornot it can have a chance or fortuitous distribution.Peirce examines in turn denumeral, enumerable, andmore than denumeral (continuous) collections (6.75-78). His conclusion is that chance is governed by the

Page 358: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 142

laws of probabilities, formal laws of mind or reason,present in any world that is knowable. They are notthemselves material laws of nature, but are the verycondition for there being any such laws since theseformal laws permit the gradual formation of materiallaws through habit.

A fortuitous distribution of, let us say, colored andwhite objects, is the highest pitch of irregularity. Anydeparture from this irregularity, that is to say, anyregularity, may tend in either of two directions: (1)the colored things and the white things may becomemore perfectly and uniformly mixed as when theywould become arranged alternately, or (2) thecolored things and the white things may tend tobecome grouped together. Both these tendenciesmay be called a process of sifting (6.80). Can aconservative force bring about sifting? Peirceanswers, yes and quite inevitably (6.80). He gives theexample of a ray of white light striking a prism. Thedifferent wave lengths of light, fortuitously distributedin that ray, are sifted out to form the spectrum.Another might be the case of gas escaping from onecontainer into a larger. Because the pressure islowered, the molecules' state of equilibrium incontainer A is disturbed and so the particles rush out

Page 359: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

into container B, but they will re-establish a state ofequilibrium again in the new container.

Conservative action, however, is characterized by itsreversibility. Consequently, if each wave of lightdiffracted by the prism, and each molecule ofescaping gas, were to strike a perfectly elastic surfaceat right angles to its path, it would reverse itsdirection and the original state of the system wouldbe restored white light and gas in container A. Peircepoints out that this does not happen, except perhapsin a laboratory, and then only imperfectly, due to theelaborate contrivance of the experimenter (6.80).

Conservative force, left to itself, can produce no suchresult, because it depends on the purposeful exactadjustment of each pencil of light. Now one of the firstthings that the mechanical philosophy discovered wasthat there are no final causes in pure mechanicalaction. (6.80)

Still, it is true to say that the experimenter could notintervene in this purposeful way unless he weredealing with a conservative force. He could not sointervene, for example, in the process of organicgrowth.

Page 360: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 143

Can conservative forces bring about a fortuitousdistribution? Peirce answers in the negative. Thereason is that a fortuitous distribution in aphenomenon can only be brought about by anotherfortuitous distribution in the conditions of thephenomenon. Take a jar containing some hotnitrogen and then add some cold oxygen. At first thenitrogen molecules will be moving with various viresvivae fortuitously distributed, and so will the oxygenmolecules. On the average, however, the oxygenmolecules will be moving more slowly than thenitrogen molecules. In this state of things thedistribution of the vires vivae of nitrogen and oxygenmolecules taken as one collection will not befortuitious. Now in the course of time there will becontinual fortuitous encounters of the two sorts ofmolecules and consequently there will be a continualinterchange of vis viva with the result that graduallythere will be an approximation to one fortuitousdistribution of vis viva among all the molecules.

That which happens, happens entirely under thegovernance of conservative forces; but the character offortuitous distribution toward which there is a tendencyis entirely due to the various fortuitous distributionsexisting in the different initial conditions of the motion,with which conservatve forces never have anything to

Page 361: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

do. (6.81)

This is more remarkable, Peirce observes, becausealthough the initial distribution of vires vivae tendsgradually to die out, the subsequent fortuitousdistributions dependent upon the initial conditionsnot only hold their ground, but mark their effectwherever the conservative forces act. "Hence, it isthat we find ourselves forced to speak of the `actionof chance'" (6.81).

So far, then, Peirce has shown that from a fortuitousdistribution of objects acting under conservativeforces can arise a uniform distribution (state ofequilibrium). Now this is very much like one of thecharacteristics of nonconservative force, namely,finiosity. He also maintains that this phenomenoncannot be reversed except by the purposefulintervention of an experimenter, either by introducingnew energy into the system to disturb the equilibriumor by introducing perfectly elastic reflectors to makethe molecules reverse their direction. Perhaps suchintervention could happen by the chance interferenceof one dynamical system by another, but the point isthat the

Page 362: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 144

conservative forces within a system, left tothemselves, cannot bring about such a reversal.Thus, the tendency of an inertial system to movefrom a completely fortuitous distribution to a uniformdistribution manifests the other characteristic ofnonconservative force, irreversibility. Now Peircedraws attention to two other important facts aboutuniform distributions: (1) not all of them seem to bethe result of fortuitous distributions, and (2) eventhose which are, also involve some regularity in theconditions. Chemical reaction and electricity, forexample, seem to involve a uniformity not due tofortuitous interaction, but to a definite relationshipbetween the particles interacting a fixed relation ofattraction and repulsion in one case, fixed valences inthe other. In the case of Boyle's law (illustrating fact2 above), the density of a gas varies directly as thepressure, because more molecules confined to asmaller space will strike the walls of the container perunit time. But Peirce observes that this is not due tothe fortuitous distributions of the molecules alone; italso requires that the paths of the molecules be allnearly rectilinear. But what is true of all the moleculesis a regularity (7.519). Boyle's law, therefore, is dueto fortuitous distribution plus a regularity. Peirce

Page 363: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

concludes that regularity in a phenomenon supposessome regularity in its initial conditions; irregularitysupposes a fortuitous distribution in these conditions.

It would seem, therefore, that Peirce has effectivelydone away with monism altogether. He appears tohave painted himself into a corner, hemmed in bytwo ultimate principles: law and chance (7.521). If itwere only a question of some formal law at the baseof every uniform distribution, there would be somehope of a rational explanation (7.511).26 But it is notmerely that, because in many cases constants areinvolved.

The explanation of the laws of nature must be of sucha nature that it shall explain why these quantitiesshould have the particular values they have. But theseparticular values have nothing rational about them.They are mere arbitrary

26 Peirce means by "rational" in this context"rationalistic" or "a priori." In his day a number ofphysicists, influenced by Kant, were trying to deduce allthe laws of dynamics a priori. For example, HeinrichHertz's The Principles of Mechanics (1894) brings in therole of experience in a single paragraph. See Doveredition, 1956, p. 145.

Page 364: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 145

Secondnesses. The explanation cannot then be apurely rational one. (7.511)

The way out of the difficulty, then, is to look for anexplanation which is not "purely rational," that is notpurely rationalistic. In other words, Peirce does notgive up immediately in face of a serious difficulty. Todo so would be to violate his fundamental law ofscientific logic: do not block the road to inquiry. Thefact that on extreme rationalistic principles he wouldhave to admit law and chance as two ultimates, twoinexplicables, as the explanation of the cosmos is anargument against the adequacy of those principles.Deductive logic is not the only kind of logic, nor isdeduction the only kind of valid argumentation, nor isnecessary reasoning the only kind of reasoning. Thereare also probable reasoning, abductive inference, andevolutionary logic in Peirce's "weapons-system."Indeed as soon as he stated this difficulty he added:

Or if we are to escape this duality at all, urged to do soby the principle of retroduction, according to which weought to begin by pressing the hypothesis of unity asfar as we can, the only possible way of doing so is tosuppose that the first germ of law was an entity, whichitself arose by chance, that is as a First. (7.521)

Chance, then, after all, can explain law if it is

Page 365: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

integrated into a process of evolution (7.512 ff.). Thisprocess, however, must proceed according to someprinciple, itself of the nature of a law, but such a lawas is capable of developing itself, not perhaps suchthat if it were entirely absent it would create itself,but such that, when present, would strengthen itself.Thus we are led to the hypothesis of a universaltendency in all things toward generalization andhabit-taking (7.515).

Peirce, then, believed that he had driven life,spontaneity, chance, and rudimentary consciousness,all the way down to the atomic world, and thus hadloosened the bonds of mechanistic determinism toallow the entrance of mind into the world. He alsothought that this kind of reasoning would allow himto pivot and so to explain the development of highergrades of consciousness through a philosophicaltheory of evolution or emergence. The logicalprinciples of pragmatism, he was convinced, wouldpermit no other sort of explanation, for the

Page 366: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 146

alternative, absolute determinism, would block theroad of further inquiry in science and in philosophy,leaving an increasing number of questionsunanswered supposedly because they wereunanswerable. Logic requires that any meaningfulquestion have an answer and that before one toohastily declares a question meaningless because it isyet to be answered, he explore as many alternativehypotheses as he can or as there are.

Peirce always insisted that his tychism was merely acorollary to his synechism.27 He objected to havinghis philosophy as a whole called tychism because thatwould be to misrepresent and to distort his views.Synechism is the very heart of Peirce's thought.Fidelity to the pragmatic maxim, he considered to bea step leading to that view. Tychism enters into thepicture only because synechism requires it.Synechism requires it because there is no other wayto account for the world except in terms of anevolutionary hypothesis, and without spontaneitythere could be no growth or development of any kind.It is no wonder, then, that the synechistic theory oflaw which we have been analyzing makes law to befounded in living potentiality manifesting itself in thetendency toward habit-taking and generalization.

Page 367: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

This habit is a generalizing tendency, and as such ageneralization, and as such a general, and as such acontinuum or continuity. It must have its origin in theoriginal continuity which is inherent in potentiality.Continuity, as generality, is inherent in potentiality,which is essentially general. (6.204)

It only remains for us now to examine in some closerdetail Peirce's philosophical theory of evolution. Butbefore leaving this section on synechism, it might behelpful to reproduce here Peirce's own summarywhich appeared as the conclusion to his paper "TheLaw of Mind." Although he was very dissatisfied withthis article as a whole, its conclusion does make clearthose elements Peirce meant synechism to include.

I have thus developed as well as I could in a littlespace the synechistic philosophy, as applied to mind. Ithink that

27 Cf. e.g. letters to James, March 13, and December26, 1897; Perry, op. cit., p. 222 and 419.

Page 368: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 147

I have succeeded in making it clear that this doctrinegives room for explanations of many facts whichwithout it are absolutely and hopelessly inexplicable;and further that it carries along with it the followingdoctrines: first, a logical realism of the mostpronounced type; second, objective idealism; third,tychism, with its consequent thoroughgoingevolutionism. We also notice that the doctrine presentsno hindrances to spiritual influences, such as somephilosophies are felt to do. (6.163)

Page 369: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 149

IIITYCHISM & EVOLUTION

Page 370: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 151

IntroductionIn one of his lectures on pragmatism at Harvard,Peirce recounted this anecdote about himself andChauncey Wright. When Darwin's great bookappeared in 1859, Peirce, engaged in surveying inthe ''wilds of Louisiana,'' knew of the sensation itcaused only through letters. Upon his return toCambridge, Peirce heard that Wright was veryenthusiastic about Darwin's theory, and decided tosound him out on the subject. In the course of theconversation Peirce remarked that Darwin's ideasmust inevitably kill mechanical philosophy. AlthoughWright, of course, did not agree, he was perplexedenough by the statement to inquire why Peircethought so. Peirce answered that Darwin's theory,nourished by positive observation, must be deadly toa merely "metaphysical" opinion (5.64).

The story sums up the views Peirce was to developover the next forty years and indicates succinctly thegeneral intellectual climate in which he would have toair them. Wright was a devotee of Mill's positivismand thoroughly convinced of mechanicaldeterminism.1 Yet he was one of the staunchest

Page 371: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

defenders of evolutionism and of Darwinism inparticular. Peirce contended that mechanicaldeterminism and evolutionism are basicallyincompatible. Mechanical philosophy, an a priori("metaphysical") position, is not only unsupported byobservational evidence such as Darwin's but positivelycontradicted by it. Wright's inability to see thatmechanical determinism precluded the possibility ofgrowth and development was typical of theintellectual condition of most of Peirce'scontemporaries.

The preceding section has shown Peirce's insistenceupon the reality of law and regularity in the universeand has indicated in passing that he could not admitthat laws of nature were absolutely rigid. That line ofthought must be pursued farther. A synechistictheory of

1 See E.H. Madden, Chauncey Wright and theFoundations of Pragmatism (Seattle: University ofWashington Press, 1963), Ch. 1 and Ch. 4. See alsoP.P. Wiener, Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1949), Ch. III.

Page 372: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 152

law requires that chance be operative in the universe,for otherwise there would be no room for mind. Toadmit tychism is to admit growth and development asfundamental to the entire cosmos. Conversely, tohold a thoroughgoing and consistent evolutionaryaccount of the universe, one must admit real chance.

Page 373: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 153

1. Tychism versus DeterminismAlthough Peirce sometimes calls his philosophicalposition "Critical Common-sensism," he knew that notall "common-sense" opinions are helpful in the task offinding out the truth. Hence he uses the word"critical.'' Sound philosophy must take "common-sense" convictions seriously, but must not be leddown the garden path by a naive trust in what seemsobvious. Those common-sense positions which canstand up under scrutiny are philosophy's pure gold;those which cannot are its dross. The dross not onlycontributes nothing positive to the enterprise but canseriously hinder any further progress by blocking theroad to inquiry. One such uncritical common-senseopinion prevalent in Peirce's day was the conviction''which makes the real things in this world blindunconscious objects working by mechanical lawstogether with consciousness as idle spectator"(7.559). This position takes for granted, even as self-evident, "that every event is precisely determined bygeneral laws" (1.132, emphasis added). Peirceproposed to submit this "necessitarian" dogma to thetest of criticism.

Page 374: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Necessitarianism has taken many forms throughoutthe history of philosophy and it would be well to statemore exactly what brand Peirce's attack was aimedat. It is what he calls "mechanical philosophy" ormaterialism.

Whoever holds that every act of the will as well asevery idea of the mind is under the rigid governance ofa necessity coordinated with that of the physical worldwill logically be carried to the proposition that mindsare part of the physical world in such a sense that thelaws of mechanics determine anything that happensaccording to immutable attractions and repulsions.(6.38)

Peirce calls this "the usual and most logical form ofnecessitarianism."1

1 Alternate forms of necessitarianism, less usual inPeirce's day because they involve so many logicaldifficulties, are the numerous versions of Descartes'dualism.

Page 375: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 154

Peirce claims that the necessitarian viewpoint arose inthe first place because so many of the greatmetaphysicians had been mathematicians, and so,understandably enough, made mathematics themodel of metaphysics. The Ionians, Pythagoreans,and Platonists, in early times, the Cartesians andNewtonians, in modern times, all explicitly looked tothe ideal of rigid demonstration from first principles asnormative in any and every scientific undertaking,physical and philosophical (1.130, 1.400). Since thediscovery of non-Euclidean geometry, however, thestatus of mathematic's first principles has beensomewhat revised, namely, from what was self-evidently true to postulates of a logical system. It hadalways been recognized, of course, that mathematicalfirst principles were never strictly and exactlyconfirmed by observation (1.30, 1.400 ff.) but thathad been put down simply to faulty measurement. If,however, the first principles of Euclidean geometryare only postulates of a system, and if differentassumptions will yield different but equally validgeometries, there is no a priori reason to expect thatfirst principles are true of the world at all, much lessexactly true of it. That is a question to be decided byobservation, and all experimental evidence points to

Page 376: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

the conclusion that all such mathematical principlesare only approximated in the physical world, notsimply because methods of measurement are crudebut because the world itself does not quite fit themathematical mold.2 The more refined the means ofmeasurement become, the more evident it becomesthat there will always be some inexactitude becausewhat is being measured is continuous while exactmeasurement supposes discrete units (cf. 1.130,1.400, 6.45).

Peirce argues, therefore, that since exactitude isdespaired of even by mathematicians, it can nolonger be hoped for in metaphysics. That is to say, nometaphysical first principle can be expected to bemore than an approximation of how things are in theworld. Consequently, common sense has no longerany right to assume that every

2 In a rejoinder to Dr. Paul Carus' defense ofnecessitarianism, Peirce distinguishes betweenmathematics' ideal constructions and physical laws.The former are exact only insofar as they are analytic;the latter, because they come from experience throughampliative inference, can only be approximative. If,and insofar as, ideal mathematical constructions can beinterpreted in a physical system, their application tothe real world can only be approximate (6.595).

Page 377: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 378: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 155

event is precisely determined by law. Rather,common sense ought to expect just the opposite. Acritical examination into the arguments usually givenby philosophers in support of the necessitarian thesismust be undertaken.

Peirce classifies the arguments under three generalheadings: (1) absolute determinism is a postulate ofscientific reasoning; (2) it is supported byobservational evidence; and (3) it is supported byvarious a priori reasons. The first class of argumentsis based upon a faulty analysis of the logic ofscientific reasoning; the second is simply gratuitouslyasserted; and the third does not take into accountvarious theories of chance forcefully argued fromAristotle down to Peirce.

What are we to think of the contention that absolutedeterminism is a postulate of scientific reasoning?3 Inthe first place, even if it were a postulate of scientificreasoning that would not make it true, nor would itafford any solid reason for thinking that it may betrue. It would merely be the expression of a hopethat it may be the case (6.39). In practical matters,of course, in cases where a decision to act must betaken, it is legitimate to assume certain things to be

Page 379: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

true, because if they are not true there would be noreason to act in one way rather than in another. But,Peirce contends, in these cases what is assumed astrue is always some individual fact, never anabsolutely universal principle:

. . . it is manifest that no universal principle can in itsuniversality be comprised in a special case or can berequisite for the validity of any ordinary inference.(6.39)

In other words, what is at issue here is thejustification of valid induction and a judgment as towhat can be expected of such argumentation. On theone hand, Peirce seems to be saying, no particularinstance of a general ever exhausts that general norcontains in it the general's generality. How, then,from a limited sample could one ever hope to draw anabsolutely exact general principle? An approximation,yes, but that is not what is at stake. On the otherhand, if some postulate were required for the mostsimple and ordinary type of inference, how would webe able to begin reasoning in the first place?

3 See 3.632-635 for Peirce's discussion of the terms"postulate" and "presupposition" which appeared inBaldwin's Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology.

Page 380: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 156

Would we have to wait until someone supplied uswith the latent major premise?4 Is that premiseinnately known? Is it unknown but operative in ourreasoning anyway? But then in what sense could itbe said to be reasoning at all, since reasoningsupposes control over the process and henceawareness of the premises? Or perhaps what ismeant by the defenders of the postulate theory isthat the postulate is not strictly speaking a hiddenpremise of our reasoning but a condition for ourreasoning discovered when we make a reflexiveanalysis of reasoning (logica utens). This lastpossibility makes sense, but then the question isreduced to what is the correct analysis of scientificreasoning.

Peirce thinks of inference as divided into two majortypes, explicative and ampliative, a distinctioninspired by Kant's synthetic-analytic dichotomy.Deduction is explicative, that is, it does not extendour knowledge of the world but rather enriches ourknowledge of the relations among ideas. Induction,hypothesis, and analogy do extend our knowledge ofthe world. This difference is so fundamental that itdooms to failure any attempt to make induction (andother forms of ampliative reasoning) merely a special

Page 381: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

kind of deduction.5 No doubt the influence of themathematical model of reasoning is back of this faultyanalysis of induction. For Peirce, all nondeductive orampliative reasoning is based on the same principleand procedure, namely, sampling (6.40). Theexample he gives is this: from samples of a shipmentof wheat (mixed and stirred up with greatthoroughness) we find that 4/5 of the samplecontains quality A wheat; therefore, we inferexperientially and provisionally, that about 4/5 of allthe grain in the shipment is of the same quality.

By saying that we infer it experientially, I mean thatour conclusion makes no pretension to knowledge ofwheat-in-itself, our aletheia, as the derivation of theword implies, has nothing to do with latent wheat. Weare dealing only with the matter of possible experienceexperience in the full

4 This is the position which those who would reduceinduction to a form of deduction must hold.5 Mill's theory of induction takes "uniformity of nature" asthe hidden major premise. See 2.761-767 for Peirce'scriticism of Mill.

Page 382: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 157

acceptation of the term as something not merelyaffecting the senses but also as the subject of thought.(6.40)

In other words, Peirce is saying that our argument isbased only on what we have experienced or canexperience of the wheat in future samplings. Itexcludes from consideration: (a) wheat hidden on theship that will never turn up, (b) wheat half-hidden insuch a way that it may turn up but is less likely to doso than the rest (this situation would alter therandomness of the sampling since it would be falsethat any grain of wheat has as much chance as anyother of turning up in the sample), (c) wheat whichcan affect our senses or pockets but which cannot bereasoned about (is unknown and unknowable).6Because our reasoning about the wheat is soconditioned by our actual and possible experience ofit, our conclusion concerning the true proportion ofquality A is drawn only provisionally.

By saying that we draw the inference provisionally, Imean that we do not hold that we have reached anyassigned degree of approximation as yet, but only holdthat if our experience be indefinitely extended, and ifevery fact of whatever nature, as fast as it presentsitself, be duly applied, according to the inductive

Page 383: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

method, in correcting the inferred ratio, then ourapproximation will become indefinitely close in the longrun . . . . (6.40)7

At any given time, then, the inferred ratio is only anapproximation of what we will find in futureexperiences of sampling. That ratio becomes anhypothesis to be verified and/or modified byexperience. If experience fluctuates irregularly so thatthe ratio cannot be assigned any definite value, wecan find out approximately within what limits

6 In another paper written a year or so later (1893)Peirce attributed the errors of mechanical philosophy tothe "incautious assumption" that there is a differencebetween "to look red" and "to see red," the assumptionof a Ding an sich (7.561).7 Goudge points out that there is a certain ambiguity inPeirce's use of the term "probable deduction." Itsometimes seems to mean necessary reasoning aboutprobabilities; sometimes it seems to mean that theconclusion drawn is only probable, that is, approximatelytrue. Op. cit., p. 172 ff.

Page 384: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 158

it fluctuates. If experience changes from one definiteratio to another, we will be able to find that out andmodify our approximation.

. . . and in short, whatever may be the variations ofthis ratio in experience, experience indefinitelyextended will enable us to detect them, so as topredict rightly, at last, what its ultimate value may be,if it have any ultimate value, or what the ultimate lawof succession of values may be, if there be any suchultimate law, or that it fluctuates irregularly withincertain limits, if it does so ultimately fluctuate. (6.40)

Peirce's contention, therefore, is that what ultimatelyjustifies ampliative reasoning is its self-correctivepower (cf. 2.769, 5.575 ff.),8 and that for this reasonthe inference, claiming to be no more thanexperiential and provisional, involves no postulatewhatever.9

On Peirce's analysis every postulate of scientificreasoning is cut off either by the provisionality or bythe experientiality of such inference. Any fact whichmight be supposed postulated, must either be

8 Cf. Goudge, op. cit., pp. 189-190; J.W. Lenz,"Induction as Self-Corrective," Studies, Moore andRobin, pp. 151-162.

Page 385: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

9 See Goudge, op. cit., pp. 191-193 for a lengthydiscussion of whether or not Peirce's account of inductiondoes not presuppose something like Mill's uniformity ofnature after all. He rightly concludes that it does not, andmakes a good distinction between Mill's positiveassumption about uniformity and Peirce's negativeassumption about the intervention of "supernal powers."Undoubtedly it is true that any existential subject mattermust be ordered in some way, and no doubt Peirce heldthis view. Again it is undoubtedly the case that Peirce wasconvinced that random sampling will find out that order.But would it be accurate to say that the validity ofinduction depends upon those assumptions, no matterhow analytic one would make them? Would it not beenough to say that if there is any order, random samplingwill find that out in the long run, and alternately, if thereis no definite order, sampling will find that out too? Peircemakes a great deal of the fact that for an induction to bevalid the character for which we sample must bepredesignated. This means, it seems to us, that we firstform an hypothesis as to what regularity we are likely tofind or are interested in verifying, and the inductionmerely confirms or disconfirms it in some ratio. Theinduction does not suppose antecedently that there isnecessarily the order we have assumed in the subjectmatter. The induction is precisely the method of findingout whether or not the order is there at all and to whatdegree.

Page 386: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 159

such that it would ultimately present itself inexperience, or would not (6.41). If it will show up inexperience, there is no need to postulate it; if it willnot show up in experience, it is irrelevant to thevalidity of our conclusion since the only pretensionthat conclusion makes is to say what is valid as far aspossible experience goes. By linking induction toexperience in such a way that experience is allowedto modify the ratio provisionally assigned, inductionbecomes self-corrective and dependent upon nopostulate whatsoever, but only upon futureexperience.

Peirce sees one important objection to his position,namely, that it does not give induction the full forcethat it in fact does have. For, on his view, no matterhow thoroughly the mixing had been, theexamination of a sample would not give anyinsurance that the next sample would not greatlymodify the value of the ratio under inquiry (6.43). Yetas a matter of fact the assurance is very high that theerror is not great. Peirce admits that ideally theassurance would be high, but that in most cases wefall somewhat short of perfect conditions. The idealinduction requires that the sampling had been trulyrandom and that the character sampled for had been

Page 387: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

determined before the sample was examined. Theseideals should always be striven for, but when theycannot be perfectly satisfied, provided the inductionis carried out honestly, the inference still has somevalue. Peirce's account was meant to show what thatminimum value is, namely, that the process is self-corrective and so will lead to the truth of the matter ifpersevered in.

Now what about the observational evidence insupport of necessitarianism (cf. 6.609)? Peirce doesnot see how anyone acquainted with scientificresearch on the inside could take any such claimseriously. Every scientist knows that no observationdetermines the value of a continuous quantity with aprobable error of zero (6.45). But it is objected thatthis is true only of continuous quantities. What aboutthose continuous quantities that are discontinuous atone or at two limits? Take a line, for instance. Weknow that it cannot have a length less than zero.Peirce proposes a case where it is a question ofdetermining the length of a line that a certain personhad drawn from a marked point on a piece of paper.If we can see no line at all, the observed length iszero;

Page 388: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 160

. . . and the only conclusion this observation warrants isthat the length of the line is less than the smallestlength visible with the optical power employed. (6.45)

To conclude that probably no line had been drawn atall the experimenter would need to have recourse tosome indirect evidence such as that the person inquestion was never near enough to the paper todraw any such line. The general point that Peircewants to make is that to conclude that some quantityor other is absent from a certain subject matter theremust be some experiential evidence, direct or remote,to that effect. It is not enough simply to say that weare unable to detect it. All that we can do in strictestlogic in cases where there is no such evidenceavailable is to abstain from any opinion as to thepresence of the substance in question (6.45).

Consequently, in Peirce's opinion, not only is there noobservational evidence to support the necessitarianview, but all the observational evidence on hand isdirectly contrary to it. All that the evidence shows isthat there is some regularity in nature, a regularityindeed which is anything but exact.

Try to verify any law of nature, and you will find thatthe more precise your observations, the more certainthey will be to show irregular departures from the law.

Page 389: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(6.46)

Heisenberg did not enunciate his indeterminacyprinciple until more than a quarter of a century later(1927), but Peirce would not have been surprised ifhe had lived to see science so conclude. He certainlywould have sided with those who have interpretedthe principle to mean that atoms are endowed with acertain spontaneity in their movement against otherswho attribute the apparent indeterminacy to theintrinsic limitations of measurement techniques.

What most clearly characterizes the universe aroundus is its enormous variety and diversity (1.159 ff.).But the regularity of law cannot produce irregularityof itself (1.161, 1.174 ff.). Even a rather gross,common-sense sort of observation, therefore,supports the thesis that the universe is not the meremechanical result of blind law (1.162). Only the trulyscientific attitude of humble fallibilism allows one tosee that this is the case. Synechism is nothing morethan fallibilism objectified (1.171 ff.); in other words,a correct logical analysis

Page 390: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 161

will lead one inevitably to a doctrine of continuity anda doctrine of continuity precludes the possibility oflaw ever being absolutely precise and exact.

The defenders of rigid determinism, therefore, aredriven to a priori reasons to support their case (6.48).They usually argue either that the human mindcannot help thinking that everything is preciselydetermined by law (6.49), or that this is a naturalbelief and natural beliefs usually are borne out byexperience (6.50), or that absolute chance isinconceivable (6.51), or that, although it may beconceivable, it is unintelligible in the sense that itdoes not explain the how or why of things, the onlyjustification for any hypothesis (6.52). Peirce doesnot consider arguments from conceivability orinconceivability to be serious enough to warrant anygreat attention. The history of ideas and of sciencehas shown all too vividly how precarious a positionthat is. He thinks that an appeal to "natural belief" issomewhat stronger but still not convincing since theobvious rejoinder is that natural beliefs must bepurged through criticism of natural illusions. Thegenuine natural belief at the bottom ofnecessitarianism is that there is some regularity innature. The natural illusion is to think that this

Page 391: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

regularity is absolutely universal and absolutely exact.The only argument, then, that deserves a closer lookis the one which claims absolute chance is not anexplanation. The issue to be settled is what is anexplanation and when is one required.10

Now the paragraphs we have been considering herecome from one of a series of five articles which Peircepublished in the Monist between 1891 and 1892.This article, entitled "The Doctrine of NecessityExamined," was in fact the second of that series. Inthe very first article, called "The Architecture ofTheories," Peirce briefly took up the question of whatrequired an explanation and concluded:

10 "One of the architectonic and, therefore, I suppose,by Dr. Carus considered as highly reprehensiblefeatures of my theory, is that, instead of saying off-hand what elements strike me as requiring explanationand what as not doing so, which seems to be his way, Ihave devoted a long time to the study of the wholelogical doctrine of explanation, and of the history ofexplanations, and have based upon the generalprinciples so ascertained my conclusions as to whatthings do and what do not require to be explained"(6.612).

Page 392: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 162

Uniformities are precisely the sort of facts that need tobe accounted for. That a pitched coin shouldsometimes turn up heads and sometimes tails calls forno particular explanation; but if it shows heads everytime, we wish to know how this result has beenbrought about. Law is par excellence the thing thatwants a reason. (6.12)

In his detailed reply to Dr. Carus' criticism of Peirce'srefutation of necessitarianism, Peirce chides theMonist's editor for saying "off-hand" what requires anexplanation rather than carefully studying the logicalproblems involved. If he had, Peirce says, he wouldnot have claimed that absolute chance requires anexplanation in terms of law (6.611-612).

First, then, let us see how Peirce defines"explanation" and second, how he arrived at thatdefinition. Something can be called an "explanation"in a strict or in a loose sense. In the loose sense an"explanation" is a "reason.'' Restricting the term''explanation" to the strict sense, Peirce defines it as

. . . the replacement of a complex predicate, or onewhich seems improbable or extraordinary, by a simplepredicate from which the complex predicate follows onknown principles. (6.612)

A reason, or "explanation" in the loose sense, he

Page 393: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

defines as

. . . the replacement of a multiple subject of anobservational proposition by a general subject, whichby the very conditions of the special experience ispredicable of the multiple subject. (6.612)11

If these definitions are justified, it follows immediatelythat only co-incidences

11 Dr. Carus defined "explanation" as a description of aspecial process of nature in such a way that theprocess is recognized as a transformation (6.612). Tothis, Peirce has four major objections: (1) it is not truethat special processes of nature are the only things tobe explained; (2) an explanation cannot simply be adescription of the fact to be explained; (3) not everyrecognition of a transformation is an explanation, butmay indeed itself call for an explanation; and (4) notevery explanation as a matter of fact involves therecognition of a transformation, e.g. in certainastronomical explanations.

Page 394: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 163

or regularities need an explanation and hence law isthe thing, par excellence, to be explained.

The analysis which led Peirce to these definitions willbe taken from a paper he wrote a few years later (ca.1901) concerning the logic of history, because it isworked out there in some detail. To begin, he askswhat is the psychological sign that an explanation isneeded. What spurs us to ask further questions? It issurprise, the emotion we experience when we runinto the unexpected (7.189). Is it regularity orirregularity which causes us surprise?

Nobody is surprised that the trees in a forest do notform a regular pattern, or asks for any explanation ofsuch a fact. So, irregularity does not prompt us to askfor an explanation. Nor can it be said that it is becausethe explanation is obvious; for there is, on the contrary,no explanation to be given, except that there is noparticular reason why there should be a regular pattern. . . . (7.189)

On the other hand, if we were to meet some equallyunexpected regularity during our forest stroll, wewould start wondering about the explanation.Perhaps this forest is a government conservationproject and the trees were planted deliberately in acertain order. The reason for the difference in our

Page 395: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

reaction to equally unexpected regularity andirregularity is simply this: we are surprised at theregularity because irregularity is "the overwhelmingpreponderant rule of experience" (7.189). Nature'smost obvious characteristic is variety and almostinfinite diversity (1.159). Irregularity, then, is notsurprising. But, Peirce continues, a breach of anexisting regularity does call for explanation. Notice, itis not enough merely to have expected antecedentlyto investigation some regularity and then to havefound only irregularity. In this case we do notdemand an explanation of the irregularity which wefound but rather revise our reasons for havingexpected regularity in the first place (7.191).

Let us look at the matter in another way. The wholepurpose of science is to find out truth aboutphenomena, to work out their rationale. The acid testof whether a scientific proposition is true orapproaches the truth about phenomena is verificationof prediction. Scientific method then looks to makingpredictions, thus letting us know more or less what toexpect. A scientific explanation of a phenomenon

Page 396: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 164

supplies a proposition which, if it had been knownbefore the phenomenon presented itself, would havemade it predictable. In other words, a scientificexplanation makes the phenomenon a logicalconsequence, necessary or probable, and so rendersit rational. Suppose a die is thrown and it turns upsix. Does this fact call for any particular explanation?Not unless there is reason to believe that there arepeculiar and pertinent features about that particularthrow in which the six turned up. The reason issimply because antecedently to any trial we knewthat over the long run it will turn up six about once insix throws (7.192). The case would be very different,however, if a certain die continually turned up sixdespite the law of probability. We would immediatelysuspect that it was loaded. In other words, we wouldimmediately seek an explanation because theunexpected had happened. Or again, suppose thaton the day of the Lisbon earthquake a new starappeared in the heavens. Does this require a specialexplanation? The answer again is no. Although it ispossible that there is some explanation of thecoincidence, it would be foolish to adopt this as aworking hypothesis since there is no evidence thatthere is any connection, this is, antecedently to the

Page 397: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

event there was no more reason to expect it than notto expect it (7.193). Peirce's conclusion, therefore, isthat the only case in which an explanation is calledfor is when the phenomenon, without some specialexplanation, would be expected not to present itself(7.194).

In summary, according to Peirce's analysis thefollowing cases require no explanation: (1) sheerirregularity, because it engenders no expectation asto what is likely to turn up, and (2) purely formalregularities (e.g., law of probability), according towhich a certain phenomenon is bound to turn upsometime or other in the chance medley of thingsbecause these are simply part of the a prioriconditions of our knowing randomness at all. Thefollowing cases do require an explanation: (1)empirically observed regularities in nature, becausethey are the exception to the preponderance ofexperience, (2) breaches in empirically observedregularities, since the regularity has led one to expectcertain phenomena to happen and when they do notcome to pass, questions must be asked, and (3)failure to discover empirical confirmation of apostulated regularity, and in this case the explanationsought is not precisely why there was no observedregularity but why we were led to postulate it.

Page 398: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Explanation,

Page 399: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 165

then, has to do with the rationality of things and so isin the category of Thirdness. Sheer Firstness andbrutal Secondness as such require no explanationsbecause in themselves they are not reasonable. Onlywhen Firstness and Secondness are brought togetherthrough the mediation of Thirdness or law are weforced to reason, to ask questions, to inquire, to seekexplanations.

The general conclusion to be drawn in the context ofPeirce's criticism of necessitarianism is this: law andlaw alone requires an explanation; consequently, itcannot be posited as the ultimate explanation of thecosmos. Such a position leads to this rather curioussort of reasoning: on the one hand, since law andregularity cannot explain irregularity and growingdiversity, the latter are to be set down asinexplicable; on the other hand, since he holds thatlaws cannot have evolved out of irregularity becausethey are immutable and ultimate facts, noexplanation can be given of them. In short both theregularity and the irregularity of the world areinexplicable (6.60). This is hardly a doctrine soundlogic would sanction since it blocks the road toinquiry. The rejection of the hypothesis of absolutechance as a real factor in the universe for a priori

Page 400: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

reasons leads to a blind alley (see also 1.405 ff.).

Necessitarianism, then, stands on no firm ground. Itis not a postulate of scientific reason, is notsupported by observational data, and leads to ahopeless logical position on a priori arguments. Allthat remains is for Peirce to give positive reasons foradopting his position. Briefly, they are four: (1) thegeneral prevalence of growth which seems to beopposed to the conservation of energy, (2) theimmense variety of the universe, which is chance,and needs no explanation, (3) law, which since itrequires an explanation must be explained in terms ofsomething else, namely, chance, and (4) the realityof feeling and consciousness, for which there is noroom in a mechanical universe (6.58-61, 6.613).

In regard to the first argument, Peirce simply invitesthe reader to examine any science which deals withthe course of time: history, geology, paleontology,astronomy. All testify to growth and increasingcomplexity.12 Death and corruption are merelysecondary and accidental phenomena.

12 This is one of the major points made by Teilhard deChardin in The Phenomenon of Man.

Page 401: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 166

From these broad and ubiquitous facts we may fairlyinfer, by the most unexceptionable logic, that there isprobably in nature some agency by which thecomplexity and diversity of things can be increased;and that consequently the rule of mechanical necessitymeets in some way with interference. (6.58)

Peirce tells Dr. Carus that a real understanding of theforce of this argument requires a thorough familiaritywith the way in which physicists explainnonconservative action in terms of conservativeaction.13 We have already seen how they take refugein the laws of probability "as preventive of thevelocities ever getting reversed" (6.613). Consideragain the example of white light refracted through aprism. It is possible for the colored light to bereversed through the prism so as to reconstitute theoriginal white light. But as a matter of fact, withoutspecial intervention on the part of the experimenter,this rarely happens because the probabilities are soover-whelmingly against just the right combinationsof circumstances being present to bring about theeffect. The nonconservative effect of friction andviscosity are similarly explained in terms ofprobabilities. Peirce's point is that the physicists arecalling upon the action of chance to explain these

Page 402: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

phenomena.

I do no more, then, than follow the usual method ofthe physicists, in calling in chance to explain theapparent violation of the law of energy which ispresented by the phenomena of growth: only instead ofchance, as they understand it, I call in absolute chance.(6.613)

The difference between Peirce's interpretation ofchance and the usual one of the physicist is thatPeirce's makes chance something in nature and notmerely a function of our ignorance of an extremelycomplex causal system. The general principle behindthis view is that

. . . in a broad view of the universe a simulation of agiven elementary mode of action can hardly beexplained except by supposing the genuine mode ofaction somewhere has place. (6.613)

13 See the treatment in Part II, Ch. 3.

Page 403: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 167

Of course, there is no question of strict and absoluteproof but merely of which hypothesis is betterwarranted by logic. The pragmatic maxim and thesynechistic rule of logic, based as they are on realism,indicate that we should assume that a simulatedviolation of the law of energy has a real violation ofthe same law as its ultimate explanation (6.613).

Now, growth appears to violate the law of energy. Toexplain it, we must, at least, suppose a simulated, orquasi, chance, such as Darwin calls in to produce hisfortuitous variations from strict heredity. (6.613)

Even if it be argued that there is no real violation ofthe law and no real chance in the immediatephenomenon, must not the conditions upon whichthe phenomenon depends require real chance? Or itmight be argued that the law of conservation ofenergy is not strictly accurate while the other laws ofdynamics are and that therefore there is no absolutechance. But Peirce thinks that physicists would notallow such a distinction and that if the exactitude ofthe law of energy were called into question all theother laws' exactitude would be questioned too. Inthat case, mechanical philosophy would have yieldedits position.14 Add to this the fact that mostpsychologists

Page 404: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

14 Peirce thinks of the laws of dynamics as formal lawsor regulative principles used to account for phenomenagoverned by real forces or material laws. The formallaws are ways of thinking about the phenomena but donot exhaust their reality, and hence the formal lawsare never exactly verified. They are reallymathematical constructions giving us a way ofinterpreting observed regularities. These formal lawsare not laws of the phenomena, nor do they make thereal regularities or material laws any the less real andobjective. Thus writing in 1905, Peirce declares: "As tothe common aversion to recognizing thought as anactive factor in the real world, some of its causes areeasily traced. In the first place, people are persuadedthat everything that happens in the material universeis a motion completely determined by inviolable lawsof dynamics; and that, they think, leaves no room forany other influence. But the laws of dynamics stand onquite a different footing from the laws of gravitation,elasticity, electricity, and the like. The laws ofdynamics are very much like logical principles, if theyare not precisely that. They say only how bodies willmove after you have said what the forces are. Theypermit any forces, and therefore any motions. . . .Setting dynamical laws to one side, then, as hardlybeing positive laws, but rather mere formal principles,we have only the laws of gravitation, elasticity,

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 405: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 406: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 168

will admit the intimate connection between the law ofgrowth and the law of habit, which would bedestroyed if it were rigidly obeyed, the phenomenonof growth surely seems to indicate a positive violationof energy's law (6.613).

Peirce invites us next to consider the third argumentsince it fortifies the first. We have already seen howand why the logic of explanation requires that law orregularity be explained. What Peirce wants toconsider here is that among the physical laws whichappear to be so different there are analogies whichalso have to be explained. He gives as examplesgravitation, electricity, and radiation, all of which,despite the differences in the forces involved, obey aninverse square law. This calls for an explanation andas we have seen, if the laws are fundamentallyoriginal and absolute, there can be no explanation.The only way out is to suppose that law is not soabsolute and that there is real absolute chance(6.613).

As regards the second argument, variety in theuniverse, insofar as it consists in the unlikenessesbetween things, calls for no explanation. Still varietyis a general characteristic of the world, and its

Page 407: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

generality needs some explanation. Peirce sees thisas the question to be answered:

. . . whether this manifold specificalness was put intothe universe at the outset, whether God created theuniverse in the infinitely distant past and has left it toits own machinery ever since, or whether there is anincessant influx of specificalness. (6.613)

Peirce sees two alternatives: one can argue that thephenomenon of growth in the universe is limited tocertain intervals and to certain parts of the universe,but that the universe as a whole is not growing; orone can argue that the pervasiveness of growththrough the cosmos as far as science can tell seemsto argue that the whole is constantly growing andconstantly has new diversity and variety introduced.This is the position of the evolutionist and, for Peirce,the hypothesis recommended by all sound logic(6.613). The reason is always the

(footnote continued from previous page)

electricity, and chemistry. Now who will deliberatelysay that our knowledge of these laws is sufficient tomake us reasonably confident that they are absolutelyeternal and immutable, and that they escape the greatlaw of evolution?" (1.348).

Page 408: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 169

same: the anti-evolutionist hypothesis rendersphenomena ultimately inexplicable and so blocks theroad to inquiry.

. . . to say no process of diversification takes place innature leaves the infinite diversity of natureunaccounted for; while to say the diversity is the resultof a general tendency to diversification is a perfectlylogical probable inference. (6.613)

Sound logic prescribes that we may not legitimatelyconclude to what goes beyond what we observe,except insofar as it explains or accounts for what weobserve. The evolutionistic hypothesis does just that.It is no explanation to say that there is diversity inthe world because God made it so. This is simply tostate the fact that there is diversity in the world, notto give an explanation of how it got there, whether allat once in the beginning or continually throughouttime by an evolution.15

As to the fourth argument, Peirce contends thatnecessitarians are embarrassed by the fact ofconsciousness and must do their best to make upaccounts with a reality which by all rights accordingto their theory should not be real at all. Indeed, theydo try to reduce it to some sort of illusion, an illusion

Page 409: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of a material system. Colors are

15 Peirce goes on to remark that we do not know God'ssecret counsels. We only know what He does do, andnothing more. Then he says, "For the same reason onecannot logically infer the existence of God; one canonly know Him by direct perception" (6.613). It seemsthat what Peirce is rejecting is "God as hypothesis" or"the God of the gaps." We agree that one may not callupon the existence of God as a substitute for scientificexplanation, but we would have some reservations asto the illegitimacy of inferring the existence of God asground and goal of phenomena as such. Might not oneargue that God is the necessary condition of possibilityfor there being anything at all? At least we do not seethat it is logically impossible. Even Peirce admits thatwe can legitimately conclude to something beyondwhat we have observed if it accounts for or explainswhat we have observed. This would not be necessarilysimply to fall back into the "God-of-the-gaps" trap,because the sort of question it seeks to answer isdifferent. It is not a scientific question and so does notrequire a scientific explanation. It is properlyphilosophical and addresses itself not merely to thequestion of understanding a given structure, but to thequestion of why and how there should be anything atall, even bits of matter swirling at random throughspace.

Page 410: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 170

reduced to rates of vibrations; brain matter is nothingmore than protoplasm, itself merely an arrangementof mechanical particles, of a certain degree ofcomplexity. All feeling is reduced to some "inwardaspect" of matter, to a phantom. Peirce's hypothesisis not so encumbered by observed psychical facts, asempirical as any physical facts, as to be forced toexplain them away.

On the other hand, by supposing the rigid exactitude ofcausation to yield, I care not how little be it but by astrictly infinitesimal amount we gain room to insertmind into our scheme, and to put it into the placewhere it is needed, into the position which, as the soleself-intelligible thing, it is entitled to occupy, that of thefountain of existence; and in so doing we resolve theproblem of the connection of soul and body. (6.61)

Now that Peirce has attacked the great redoubtblocking the road to further progress in science andin philosophy, he must sketch in some detail theposition he proposes to erect in its place, a positionwhich will help traffic move smoothly andcontinuously over the road to be travelled by inquirersafter the truth. We must, therefore, now follow Peircein working out his philosophical account of thecosmos as it arises out of absolute chance.

Page 411: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 412: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 171

2. Evolutionary LovePeirce once remarked that in philosophy one musthave a thoroughgoing evolutionism or none at all(6.14). In our day perhaps it would seem very oddfor a thoroughgoing evolutionist to have reservationsabout Darwin's theory of natural selection. And yetPeirce had them. He was never very enthusiasticabout the Origin of Species and to appreciate his own"thoroughgoing" evolutionism we must try tounderstand why. Peirce's reluctance to endorseDarwin wholeheartedly might simply have been dueto the theory's novelty and lack of sufficientconfirmation. No doubt, this is part of the reason, butit certainly is not the whole.

In reading what Peirce has to say about Darwinismwe note that one thing stands out: Peirce wasabashed that the new theory should receive suchwidespread, enthusiastic, and comparatively uncriticalacceptance among scientists and philosophers. It wasnot that Peirce did not recognize in Darwin's work atruly great and significant scientific advance. He didand said so in many places. He could not understand,nor approve, the sweeping generalizations in fields as

Page 413: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

far removed from biology as political economy, ethics,and religion which followed almost immediatelyDarwin's book (published late in the year 1859). Nosober mind, guided in its speculations by sound logic,could honestly and in good conscience indulge insuch irresponsible declarations. Even from a purelyscientific viewpoint, Darwin's work was not beyondcriticism. Peirce was genuinely disturbed at thesedevelopments.

On the other hand, there were reactions, equallyviolent, in the opposite direction, which must haveequally disturbed Peirce. There were philosophersand religious leaders who vigorously condemnedDarwin's hypothesis on various a priori grounds. Butevolution was not a new idea with Darwin. Why,then, did his account of it make such a sensation?Why was it that men could hardly discuss itdispassionately?1

1 Lamarck's theory was formulated between the years1801 and 1809.

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 414: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 172

To understand Peirce's position, it will be helpful tokeep in mind the distinction between evolution as ascientific hypothesis aimed at explaining thedevelopment of organic species and evolution as aphilosophical hypothesis aimed at explaining theentire cosmos. Though Peirce was primarily interestedin the latter, he always modeled it on the former. Herealized that philosophical adaptation of scientifictheories is always a risky business and so he insistedthat it be based upon a sound and sane logic whichwould enable one to judge accurately exactly whatscience had established (and to what degree ofprobability) and what it had not. Only sound logicalmethod enables one to see clearly where scienceends and philosophical speculation begins, and so toavoid confusing the claims of each. The mistake ofphilosophers and scientists who thought that scienceconfirms necessitarianism is of this kind faulty analysisof the logical weight of the evidence. Peirce'sreservations about Darwinism are both scientific andphilosophical.

Why, then, was Darwin's theory so enthusiasticallyreceived by most of the scientific world even thoughit was far from being proved?

Page 415: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

(footnote continued from previous page)Darwin himself in the Origin of Species accepted theinheritance of acquired characteristics as playing a rolein evolution. It was only after Weismann's work thatLamarck's principle was seriously challenged andcontroversy split the biologist's camp. Furthermore,evolutionism had always been a part of westernthought since the Ionians. Anaximander, Empedoclesand Anaxagoras proposed versions of natural selectionand the survival of the fittest on observational andphilosophic grounds. The Stoics advocated a theory of''logoi spermatikoi'' for philosophical reasons. St.Augustine adapted the Stoic cosmology for theologicalreasons. His followers throughout the Middle Ages sawno conflict between "rationes seminales" and theChristian doctrine of creation. Indeed Augustine'stheological reason for proposing a version of that Stoicdoctrine was to reconcile certain passages in Scriptureconcerning creation (cf. De. Gen. ad litt. 6, 5, 8; DeTrinit. 3, 8, 13). It was the influence of Aristotle whichinclined most medieval thinkers to hold to fixity ofspecies, and so to interpret creation in that light. Itmight be that the opposition to Darwinism amongnineteenth century philosophers was due to theinfluence of a prioristic dogmatism prevalent in manyGerman Schools, and the reaction among religiousleaders was due to a loss of contact with a part of theChristian tradition and to fundamentalism. On the otherhand, the over-enthusiastic reception of Darwinismmight be due to smouldering rebellion against both a

Page 416: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

prioristic metaphysics and fundamentalist religionwhich needed only the slightest fanning from science toburst into new flames.

Page 417: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 173

Peirce finds the answer in the intellectual climate ofthe scientific world at the time, dominated as it wasby mechanical philosophy and the "statisticalmethod." Addressing himself to this very question,Peirce briefly surveyed the state of science from 1846to 1859. He called this period the most productiveperiod of equal length in the entire history of science(6.297). The big breakthrough came with therealization that chance begets order. According toPeirce it was put into its clearest light in 1847 byQuetelet's paper on the application of probabilitytheory to moral and political sciences. In the sameyear, Herapath, an English chemist, outlined kinetictheory and Helmholtz formulated the conservation ofenergy principle. In 1850 Clausius and Rankine,independently, worked out the mechanical theory ofheat. Buckle's History of Civilization (1857) met withgreat success because he had made use of Quetelet'ssuggestion. In the very summer preceding Darwin'spublication of the Origin of Species Maxwell read themost important paper to date on the dynamicaltheory of gases before the British Association. Peirceobserves:

The consequence was that the idea that fortuitousevents may result in a physical law, and further that

Page 418: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

this is the way in which those laws which appear toconflict with the principle of the conservation of energyare to be explained, had taken a strong hold upon theminds of all those who were abreast of the leaders ofthought. (6.297)

It was inevitable that Darwin's work should bewelcomed by minds thinking along these lines. TheOrigin of Species was simply the application of thesame principle to another "nonconservative" action,organic development. They looked on Darwinism asanother confirmation of mechanical philosophy, a veryspecial and a most welcome one, since it applied tolife and growth, the two phenomena which fitted inleast well with their philosophical view of the world.In other words, Peirce maintains that philosophicalprejudice more than the intrinsic scientific worth(great though that was) of Darwin's theory insured itswarm and uncritical acceptance by a large part of thescientific community.

Nor was mechanism the only intellectual prejudice ofthe nineteenth century which provided a favorableenvironment in which Darwinism

Page 419: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 174

could rapidly take root in popular as well as inscientific thought. The dominant ethical theory of theday was utilitarianism. The strong family resemblanceis unmistakable. The greatest good for the greatestnumber was merely the ethical counterpart of thesurvival of the fittest.

All this time, utilitarianism that improved substitute forthe Gospel was in its fullest feather; and was a naturalally of an individualistic theory. Dean Mansell'sinjudicious advocacy had led to mutiny among thebondsmen of Sir William Hamilton, and the nominalismof Mill had profited accordingly; and although the realscience that Darwin was leading men to was sure someday to give a death blow to the sham-science of Mill,yet there were several elements of the Darwiniantheory which were sure to charm the followers of Mill.(6.297)

Add to the various interpretations of utilitarian ethics,the economic theory and policy which dominated thenineteenth century, laissez-faire, and the picture iscomplete. All the sciences, physical and social, wereusing probability theory. Darwinism fitted right in.

Peirce's explanation of why the Origin of Species wasan immediate success in certain quarters also tells uswhy he was opposed to it as a philosophical account

Page 420: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of the development of the universe. He had boththeoretical and practical reasons against it. For him,Darwinism generalized into a philosophical thesis wasnothing more than another form of mechanism andso labored under all the same theoretical difficultieswhich beset mechanical philosophy in general.Besides, if it is only a faulty logical analysis of chance(viz. merely ignorance of the causes at work) whichled some philosophers to conclude that reduction ofnonconservative physical forces to probability curvesfinally vindicated absolute determinism, it is the verysame error to think that Darwinism added any forceto that position. Statistical analysis as applied inkinetic theory or in natural selection, when properlyanalyzed, does not support philosophical mechanism.As we have seen, Peirce contends that just theopposite is the case. These scientific theories have aplace in our understanding of the world, but they arenot in themselves answers to philosophical questionsabout the nature of the cosmos. They may serve asdata for

Page 421: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 175

philosophical speculation but that speculation is onlyas good as its logic. It is simply a mistake, a verynaive one at that, to appeal to a scientific theory asthe justification of a philosophical theory designed toexplain the scientific one. Mechanical philosophy isdesigned to explain scientific laws and laws of nature.No scientific theory will or can justify that doctrine.Peirce's theory of tychism is a philosophical theorydesigned to explain scientific laws and laws of nature.The laws of nature cannot establish that theory.2

It must be thoroughly understood that Peirce is notcriticizing the use of probabilities in scientific method.On the contrary, he advocates it wholeheartedly.Peirce is not saying that kinetic theory is a poorphysical theory, nor even that Darwinism isscientifically unacceptable. The point he is makinghas to do with philosophical interpretations giventhose theories and the implications they are supposedto support.

The practical motive for Peirce's opposition to ageneralized Darwinism is that it encourages abasically unsound and immoral social order. Thenineteenth century, according to Peirce, was the"Economical Century" in which political economy had

Page 422: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

been reduced to "a philosophy of greed" (6.290). Ofcourse Peirce did not think for a minute that this wasa legitimate conclusion of political economy, any morethan he thought necessitarianism was a legitimate

2 Cf. R. Wells, "The True Nature of Peirce'sEvolutionism," Studies, Moore and Robin, pp. 304-322.Wells is very hard on Peirce. Peirce's wholeundertaking, he feels, is so misguided that it cannot berepaired, only replaced. The basic reason is that thescientific ideal of testability is incompatible with themetaphysical ideal of all-comprehensiveness (p. 305).Any attempt to write them into a "scientificmetaphysics" is doomed from the start. All that Peirceachieves in metaphysics, it seems, is to make someanalytical statements which are true but irrelevant (p.322). We disagree with this position, but, of course, wecannot enter into details here. We think, perhaps,there is some misunderstanding as to what Peircemeans by ''scientific metaphysics." It does not meansubstituting scientific hypotheses for philosophicalones. Indeed, according to us, Peirce condemns "SocialDarwinists" for doing just that. It seems to us to be adifferent thing to use scientific theories as models orguides for specifically philosophical explanations. Todistinguish natural science from metaphysics is notnecessarily to "drive them apart''; it may be that onedistinguishes in order to unite. This, of course, makesno sense if one is already committed to the propositionthat natural science is the only source of knowledge

Page 423: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

about the world.

Page 424: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 176

conclusion of physics. The injustice and exploitationwhich the greed philosophy not only condoned butraised to the rank of virtue could not, in Peirce's view,produce anything but the direst consequences.

Soon a flash and quick peal will shake economists quiteout of their complacency, too late. The twentiethcentury, in its latter half, shall surely see the deluge-tempest burst upon the social order to clear upon aworld as deep in ruin as that greed-philosophy has longplunged it into guilt. (6.292)

The only inaccuracy about this apocalyptic predictionis that the deluge twice engulfed the world in the firsthalf of the twentieth century. And it is not over yet byany means. By raising Darwin's limited scientifichypothesis to the status of a philosophical and moraldogma, Peirce saw aid and comfort going tomankind's mortal enemy. According to the crudestversion of the pragmatic maxim, this sort ofphilosophy meant disaster and it could not beaccepted as true without absolutely compellingevidence.3 Peirce did not think, however, nor did hemean to imply, that Darwin's researches weremotivated particularly by any political or ethicalconsiderations, least of all by any conscious desire tofurther greed-philosophy. The only point is that as a

Page 425: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

matter of fact it played right into the hands of thosewho did desire to justify such a philosophy (6.297).4

3 "The Origin of Species . . . merely extends politico-economical views of progress to the entire realm ofanimal and vegetable life. The vast majority of ourcontemporary naturalists hold the opinion that the truecause of those exquisite and marvelous adaptations ofnature . . . is that creatures are so crowded togetherthat those of them that happen to have the slightestadvantage force those less pushing into situationsunfavorable to multiplication or even kill them beforethey reach the age of reproduction. Among animals,the mere mechanical individualism is vastly reenforcedas a power making for good by the animal's ruthlessgreed. As Darwin puts it on his title-page, it is thestruggle for existence; and he should have added forhis motto: Every individual for himself, and the Deviltake the hindmost!" (6.293). In an unpublishedfragment Peirce speculates whether Darwin wasinfluenced by Malthus and political economy. Thisfragment also contains a summary of his evolutionarytheory. (Peirce Papers, #954)4 Karl Pearson in Grammar of Science, Chap. I, arguedthat in accordance with Darwinian theory the summumbonum is social happiness, and social stability. Peirceargues that this does not follow from Darwinism.

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 426: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 177

There is no need to enter into details concerningPeirce's reservation about Darwinism as a strictlyscientific hypothesis designed to explain the originand development of organic species. At the time, thehypothesis was simply not sufficiently confirmed towarrant making it the sole factor in evolution. Peirceremarks that it had not been proved by the evidenceas Darwin first presented it and that more thantwenty years after the publication of the Origin ofSpecies a sober mind must judge the case even lesslikely of ever being established (6.297). Peircethought, however, that Darwin showed beyondserious doubt that natural selection played some rolein the process but just how great was not yet clear.When we remember that Lamarckism was stillbiologically respectable, Peirce's doubts aboutDarwinism are not hard to understand. Indeed,further developments in genetics have shown Peirce'slogic to be correct in that Darwinism has had to berevised. This scientific prudence and sobriety wasmerely an application of "humble fallibilism": do notbe "cocksure" of anything in science (cf. 1.366 n. 1).

Peirce's own theory of evolution was philosophical,designed to account for the origin and developmentof the cosmos. He meant to model his philosophical

Page 427: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

theory on the best scientific information and theoriesavailable. There were three main theories of theevolution of organic species current in his day:Darwinism, Lamarckism, and cataclysmal evolution(1.104; 6.14-17).

First, the theory of Darwin, according to which theentire interval from Moner to Man has been traversedby successive purely fortuitous and insensiblevariations in reproduction. The changes on the wholefollow a determinate course simply because a certainamount of change in certain directions destroys thespecies altogether, as the final result

(footnote continued from previous page)

Rather if natural selection is generalized into aphilosophical thesis man's summum bonum can only bethe continuance of the stock regardless of thehappiness of individual men. The individual is of noaccount except insofar as he can reproduce. And sincethere is no happiness except that of individuals,Darwinism has nothing to do with happiness at all(8.133-136). The only thing that motivates scientificinquiry is desire to know the truth. Furthermore, Peircedoes not think that there is the slightest reason tobelieve that man's highest good consists in procreating,and consequently it is just absurd to extend Darwinisminto ethics.

Page 428: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 178

of successive weakenings of its reproductive power.Second, the theory of Lamarck, according to which thewhole interval has been traversed by a succession ofvery minute changes. But these have not taken place inreproduction, which has absolutely nothing to do withthe business, except to keep the average individualsplastic by their youth. The changes have not beenfortuitous but wholly the result of strivings of theindividuals. Third, the theory of cataclysmal evolution,according to which the changes have not been smalland have not been fortuitous; but they have takenplace chiefly in reproduction. According to this view,sudden changes of the environment have taken placefrom time to time. These changes have put certainorgans at a disadvantage, and there has been an effortto use them in new ways. Such organs are particularlyapt to sport in reproduction and to change in the waywhich adapts them better to their recent mode ofexercise. (1.104)

Peirce is convinced, despite Weismann's attack onLamarck, that most probably all three modes ofevolution have acted to produce species, and further,he thinks it probable that the third mode has beenmost efficient (1.105).5

5 The controversy concerning the inheritance ofacquired characteristics went on until much afterPeirce's death. With the great strides made in genetics

Page 429: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

the importance of the controversy gradually subsidedbecause most biologists considered the questionmisplaced. Gene mutation was the real mechanism atwork in the transformation of species. Peirce's instinct,then, seems to have been correct, namely, that thereis much more to organic evolution than Darwin'shypothesis provided. Furthermore, since Peirce'sphilosophical evolutionism meant to account for allsorts of development of ideas, of mind, of institutions,of history there was no reason why he should restricthis speculation to one scientific model even if only onemodel should turn out to be correct for biologicaldevelopment. He was interested in the biologicaltheories for their structures, that is, insofar as theywere suggestive of how things might have developed.He then considered various phenomena to see whichmechanism was more likely to be the sort of thingneeded. Thus he tried a Darwinian and a Lamarckianmodel to explain the historical development of weightsand measures (1.106). He did the same with regard tothe development of our opinions and beliefs (1.107).He thought that the cataclysmal model was moreappropriate for an understanding of the developmentof science (science

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 430: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 179

On Peirce's view these theories of evolution arecomplementary. Lamarckian theory only explains thedevelopments of characters for which individualsstrive, while the Darwinian theory only explains theproduction of characters really beneficial to the race,though these may be fatal to the individuals (6.16).Geological and paleontological evidence seems torequire cataclysmal evolution. The data seems toindicate that species are not very greatly modifiedunder normal circumstances, but are rapidly alteredafter cataclysms or rapid geological changes (6.17).On this assumption, then, Darwin and Lamarck wouldaccount for the insensible variation of species duringthe millenia between the geological ages when somedrastic alteration of environment broke up establishedpatterns of life abruptly, thereby bringing aboutdrastic and rapid adaptive changes in the specieswhich survived (6.17). Considered morephilosophically, these sorts of evolution may beinterpreted respectively as evolution by chance,evolution by habit and effort, and evolution bybreaking up of habits and formation of new ones. Andwith this foreshadowing of Peirce's own developedphilosophical position, let us turn to consider hisanalysis of various philosophical theories of evolution

Page 431: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and their interrelations.

Peirce's classification of philosophical evolutionism israther complex, and, as is his wont, he has devised avery unusual vocabulary to designate the divisions.6The main divisions of Peirce's classifications are (1)elements of evolution, (2) modes of evolution, (3)doctrines of evolution. Each of these divisions issubdivided into three parts.

(footnote continued from previous page)

grows by leaps) (1.109). His own general theory ofevolution, however, must also explain these variousmechanisms themselves how they developed and howthe laws which govern them came about. Cf. T.A.Goudge, "Peirce's Evolutionism After Half a Century,"Studies, Moore and Robin, pp. 323-341.6 Peirce coined unusual technical terms deliberately inaccordance with the principles of his "Ethics ofTerminology." New ideas should have new words toexpress them. If old words are made do, he thought, onlyconfusion results. Since the old, familiar words retainsome of their old meaning, a person seeing them quicklyassumes that he knows how they are being used in thenew context. Hence he runs the risk of missing the newmeaning. Peirce would prefer to use obscure andunfamiliar words in such a case than familiar butambiguous ones. It forces the reader's attention on thenovelty of the idea expressed and makes him work to

Page 432: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

grasp it.

Page 433: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 180

The terms for these subdivisions are ingeniouslycontrived out of the stems of three Greek words withappropriate suffixes indicating the main division inquestion. The Greek words are tyché (chance),anangké (necessity), and agapé (love of friendship).The classification is as follows (6.302):

1. PROPOSITIONS ABOUT THE MODES:

a) tychism affirms that as a matter of fact chanceplays a role;

b) anancism affirms that as a matter of factnecessity plays a role;

c) agapism affirms that as a matter of fact creativelove plays a role.

2. MODES OF EVOLUTION:

a) tychastic evolution (tychasm) designates anyevolutionary process which involves the action offortuitous variation;

b) anancastic evolution (anancasm) designates anyevolutionary process which takes place bymechanical necessity;

c) agapastic evolution (agapasm) designates any

Page 434: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

evolutionary process which takes place by creativelove.

3. DOCTRINES OF EVOLUTION:

a) tychasticism, according to which fortuitousvariation plays the principal if not the only role inevolution;

b) anancasticism, according to which mechanicalnecessity plays the principal if not the only role inevolution;

c) agapasticism, according to which creative loveplays the principal if not the only role in evolution.

The point of this rather elaborate scheme is to helpthe reader understand the dialectical synthesis Peircesketches. As one might suspect there is a connectionbetween Peirce's evolutionary scheme and hiscategorial scheme. The structure of both analyses istoo strikingly similar to be merely coincidental.Certainly it is not when we recall that he explicitlyapplied the "triad" to Darwinian evolution in his paper"A Guess at the Riddle" (1.395). The first divisioncited above corresponds to a phenomenologicalaffirmation. At this point the only claim made is thatthese elements are to be accounted for in anyscheme. The second division, on the other hand,

Page 435: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

introduces

Page 436: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 181

the notion of discrimination and ordering. Modes lookto the interrelation of the elements at work inevolution. One could not hold just one mode ofevolution to the exclusion of the others, just as onecould not hold one category only. Furthermore, theinterdependence of the modes of evolution follows adefinite order which cannot be altered, just as theinterrelation of the categories does. Finally, the thirddivision introduces the synthetic doctrines resultingfrom the ordering of the modes. One could notconsistently be a tychasticist, an anancasticist, andan agapasticist.

It is clear that Peirce has Darwinism in mind as anexample of tychastic evolution (6.298; 6.304).Evidently, the Darwinism to which Peirce is willing togive a place in the development of the universe is notthat of the mechanists who tried to make it shore upa collapsing a priori principle.7 Authentic Darwinismaccounts for evolution in terms of two factors:heredity and natural selection. These factors arecapable of great generalization (6.15).

Wherever there are large numbers of objects having atendency to retain certain characters unaltered, thistendency, however, not being absolute but giving roomfor chance variations [thus a mechanistic interpretation

Page 437: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

is not legitimate], then, if the amount of variation isabsolutely limited in certain directions by thedestruction of everything which reaches those limits,there will be a gradual tendency to change in directionsof departure from them. (6.15)

The clearest illustration of this sort of evolution is thatof gamblers betting at an even game. As one afterthe other is ruined, the average wealth of those leftin the game continually increases (6.15; 1.396 ff.).

Here is indubitably a genuine formula of possibleevolution, whether its operation accounts for much orlittle in the development of animal and vegetablespecies. (6.15)

Diametrically opposed to tychastic evolution isanancastic. Peirce has in mind such men as Hegel,Spencer, and others (6.298, 6.14, 6.305). Evolutionby mechanical necessity, whether that necessity isexternal or internal, is plainly absurd on Peirce's viewfor reasons

7 Peirce has in mind among others Chauncey Wrightand Herbert Spencer. Cf. 6.14 and E.H. Madden, op.cit., Ch. 1 and Ch. 4 passim.

Page 438: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 182

already sufficiently considered. Absolute mechanicalnecessity would be the death of evolution. It wouldbe hell freezing over. There simply is no reign ofabsolute and exact law in the universe. Such a frozenstate of things might be posited as a theoretical limittoward which the growth of law and order tends, justas absolute chaos might be posited as the oppositelimit. But neither limit is ever reached. Speculationapproaches them only asymptotically. The kernel oftruth in back of mechanism is simply the presence oflaw in the cosmos, but mechanism itself is anexaggeration. The kernel of truth present in tychasticevolution is that chance is really ingredient in things,but a denial of law amid the chance is equally anexaggeration.

Tychasm and anancasm, therefore, are conceptionsat odds with one another. They are at opposite poles,as it were, and the only hope of reconciliation isthrough a third party, a mediator. If the kernels oftruth in them both are to be preserved, a syntheticview must be taken. Obviously Peirce is using thesame strategy he did in the analysis of thecategories: Firstness and Secondness can bereconciled only through Thirdness. Agapasm, ofcourse, fills the bill.

Page 439: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Among the scientific theories, Lamarckism mostclosely resembles agapasm. Peirce believed thatenwrapped in Lamarck's theory was a third positionwhich supersedes the strife between the other two(6.299). What attracted him to a theory ofdevelopment through effort and striving was itslikeness to habit-taking, the great law of mind.

Such a transmission of acquired characters is of thegeneral nature of habit-taking, and this is therepresentative and derivative within the physiologicaldomain of the law of mind. (6.299)

Furthermore the very notion of striving and endeavormeans end-directed activity and consequently isessentially psychical, even though not necessarilyconscious. New forms are created by spontaneity("energetic projaculation") and habit forces them totake practical shapes compatible with the structureswhich the new forms affect; further, habit graduallyreplaces the spontaneous energy which sustainsthose forms.

Thus, habit plays a double part; it serves to establishthe new features, and also to bring them into harmonywith the

Page 440: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 183

general morphology and function of the animals andplants to which they belong. (6.300)

Peirce sees in this account of evolution what he callsthe "action of love."

The movement of love is circular, at one and the sameimpulse projecting creations into independency anddrawing them into harmony. This seems complicatedwhen stated so; but it is fully summed up in the simpleformula we call the Golden Rule. (6.288)

And he attributes these views to St. John, "theontological gospeller," who made "the One SupremeBeing, by whom all things have been made out ofnothing, to be cherishing-love" (6.287). Be itunderstood, however, that for all the religiousovertones in this conception, Peirce looked upon it asstrictly philosophical.

The philosophy we draw from John's gospel is that thisis the way [i.e. by creative love] mind develops; and asfor the cosmos, only so far as it yet is mind, and so haslife, is it capable of further evolution. Love, recognizinggerms of loveliness in the hateful, gradually warms itinto life, and makes it lovely. That is the sort ofevolution which every careful student of my essay "TheLaw of Mind" must see that synechism calls for.(6.289)8

Page 441: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

So far Peirce has said very little about the place ofcataclysmal evolution, the third scientific hypothesis,as a model for his philosophical interpretation. Wherewould it fit in the tripartite division: tychasm,anancasm, and agapasm? In one place he groups thedefenders of cataclysmal evolution with those whomake mechanical necessity the chief factor in theprocess (6.298). But he seems to think that this ismerely an erroneous interpretation of scientific datain the same way that a necessitarian interpretation ofDarwinism is a mistake.

8 Peirce seems to have been very much impressed withthe doctrines of Swedenborg just becoming widelyknown in his day. Henry James, Sr. did much to makethem known in this country through his book Substanceand Shadow. For the influence of Swedenborg andJames on Peirce see M.G. Murphey, op. cit., pp. 350-352, and W.P. Krolikowski, "The Peircean Vir," Studies,Moore and Robin, pp. 257-270.

Page 442: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 184

Thus, naming Nägeli, Kölliker, and Weismann asmechanists, he remarks:

It is very noticeable that all these different sectariesseek to import into their science a mechanicalnecessity to which the facts that come under theirobservation do not point. (6.298)

He adds in the very next sentence:

Those geologists who think that the variation ofspecies is due to cataclysmic alterations of climate orof the chemical constitution of the air and water arealso making mechanical necessity chief factor ofevolution.

The mistakes are always the same: (1) cocksurenesswhich closes the mind to other possibilities and otherfacets of the evidence, resulting in sweepinggeneralization and exclusivity; (2) failure to realizethat the mechanism (efficient cause) proposed as the"explanation" of evolution is efficient only because itsforce is under the guidance and control of law (finalcause), and that it is precisely law which needs anexplanation.

We suggest that the counterpart to cataclysmicevolution in Peirce's theory is the sometimes violentbreakup of habits. Strictly speaking Lamarckian

Page 443: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

theory only accounts for the acquisition of habitsthrough effort. It does not account for change ofhabit. Surprise and shock bring about the destructionof certain habits of thought in a manner very muchlike the sudden changes in environment whichproduced, according to some scientists, the rapidadaptation of species, say at the beginning of theglacial period. Something brute takes place whichupsets established patterns. Either those patterns aregiven up or extinction ensues. Only those thingsdevelop which remain plastic enough in their habitsto change them in the face of experience. In thedevelopment of science, for instance, it is true that itadvances through cooperation and common effort ofa community of inquirers (e.g. 2.157), and that thereis continuity in scientific results even when thoseresults come out of a theory later found deficient(2.150). But that does not necessarily deny thatscience makes its great strides forward by leaps(1.109). Today we would say that scientific advancesdepend upon the ability of men to look at the dataafresh and so conceive a whole new framework

Page 444: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 185

in which to theorize. Once the new framework isestablished scientists cooperate in working out itsimplications and in testing its results. Furthermore,what has been verified in the whole framework is notabandoned. It remains a true acquisition within thesystem and many times has its counterpart in thenew framework, although perhaps couched in verydifferent terms and/or formulas. When Peirce thoughtof the community of inquirers, he had in mindprimarily an ideal group of dedicated men pursuing acorrect method of research. Now precisely the pointof fallibilism in men of science is to expect and towelcome new conceptual frameworks. The newframeworks, of course, rarely come out of the blue.Usually they are ''in the air'' when someoneformulates them. The very fact that scientists areworking on a certain set of problems withunsatisfactory results paves the way for a new look.Evolution, or development, along Lamarckian lines,therefore, is not so incompatible with development byleaps and bounds.9

Peirce, then, believed that agapasm incorporated thebest in tychasm and anancasm. These latter are onlydegenerate types of the former (6.303). Tychasticevolution alone could not handle the notion of

Page 445: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

positive sympathy among created things springingfrom continuity of mind (6.304). Anancastic evolutionalone might do if it worked, but Peirce was convincedthat without a good dash of tychism to relieve theatrophy of necessitarianism it was all a Hegeliandream (6.305). Only agapasticism satisfactorilyaccounts for all the various sorts of developmentgoing on in the universe by admitting both chanceand law, but uniting them in and through habit.

Peirce was very much aware of the difficulty inkeeping the lines of demarcation between thesemodes of evolution as sharp as is desired. Indeedsuch sharp delineation is impossible due to the natureof things reality is continuous, not discrete. If allthree modes are operative in the process of growth,they will be found to a greater or lesser degree in allsuch processes (6.306). Of course, this observationdoes not take anything away from the fact that thethree are different. This way of looking at thingsreflects Peirce's thinking about the universalcategories. Peirce saw that things may bedistinguished

9 Contrary to P.P. Wiener, "Peirce's EvolutionaryInterpretations of the History of Science," Studies,Wiener and Young, pp. 144-145.

Page 446: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 447: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 186

although not in fact separable. The modes ofevolution can indeed be distinguished but cannot beseparated in any adequate account of the realevolutionary process. Before bringing this chapter toa close therefore, let us consider these modes ofevolutionary development in relation to thecategories.

Peirce definitely thought of the three evolutionarymodes and their interrelations along the lines of thethree categories and their interrelations. This is justwhat one would expect, since the categories areuniversal. We would also expect that Peirce's peculiarcontribution will have to do with what corresponds tothe category of Thirdness since he was convincedthat practically all philosophers of his day excepthimself had fallen into the nominalistic error ofdenying the reality of that category. We have alreadyseen that Peirce refuses to do away with any of theevolutionary modes, just as he refused to do awaywith any of the categories.

Tychastic evolution corresponds to Firstness. It ispure spontaneity. It is lawless and aboriginal,therefore requiring no explanation. It is what it iswithout reference to anything else. For that very

Page 448: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

reason, it cannot be the only factor at work in thisworld of existents. Anything that exists requiresinteraction with an environment and henceSecondness. Anancastic evolution corresponds toSecondness. It is the brute element in development.It is the blind interaction of objects supplying theforce after the manner of the sheriff. Finally,agapastic evolution corresponds to Thirdness,mediating between chance and brute force and soproducing order, law and the reasonableness of thecourt.

If there could be any doubt about Peirce's mind inthis matter a long passage in the paper "EvolutionaryLove" removes it. He remarks that there is only onevariety of tychastic evolution, but two of anancasticand three of agapastic. This is exactly the way inwhich the categories are analyzed: Firstness can haveno degenerate form, Secondness can have two,Thirdness three (6.307).10

Here is how Peirce works out the variety of modes inthe evolution of human thought:

1) tychastic development (Firstness): new ideas arisethrough

10 Cf. Part I, Ch. 1.

Page 449: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 450: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 187

purposeless and purely spontaneous departuresfrom habitual ideas;

2) anancastic development (Secondness): new ideasare adopted without seeing whither they tend butwhose character is determined either

a) by external causes such as environmentalchanges (genuine), or

b) by internal causes such as logical development(degenerate);

3) agapastic development (Thirdness): new ideas areadopted neither heedlessly nor blindly, but by animmediate attraction for the idea itself, divined evenbefore the mind consciously possesses the idea bythe power of sympathy or affinity (continuity of mind)either

a) by the community possessing the idea in itscollective personality and then passing it on toindividuals otherwise incapable of attaining it, or

b) by an individual discovering the idea for himselfbut only because he is in sympathy with acommunity and this sympathy allowed him toexperience the idea's attractiveness, or

Page 451: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

c) by an individual discovering the idea for himselfindependently of his human affections simply byvirtue of the attractiveness of the idea itself.

These subdivisions of agapasm seem to correspond tothe genuine (c) and two degenerate (a, b) forms ofThirdness. When Peirce talks of the "attractiveness"of the idea one is reminded of what we saw in Part Iabout the normative sciences. Indeed it was justabout the time when he wrote "Evolutionary Love"(ca. 1893) that he became convinced that ethics isconnected in some important way with logic. He hadnot yet taken up a serious study of the relationbetween logic, practics, and esthetics, but it is clearthat his cosmological speculations prepared the wayfor the investigation. Certainly the work he did onevolutionary theory foreshadowed what he finally saidabout man's ultimate good.

A paragraph from the paper "The Architecture ofTheories" is

Page 452: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 188

worth reproducing here because in it Peirce explicitlyapplies the notions of First, Second and Third to whatwe have been considering.

The origin of things, considered not as leading toanything, but in itself, contains the idea of First, theend of things that of Second, the process mediatingbetween them that of Third. A philosophy whichemphasizes the idea of the One is generally a dualisticphilosophy in which the conception of Second receivesexaggerated attention; for this One (thought of courseinvolving the idea of First) is always the other of amanifold which is not one. The idea of the Many,because variety is arbitrariness and arbitrariness isrepudiation of any Secondness, has for its principalcomponent the conception of First. . . . In biology, theidea of arbitrary sporting is First, heredity is Second,the process whereby the accidental characters becomefixed is Third. Chance is first, Law is Second, thetendency to take habits is Third. Mind is First, Matter isSecond, Evolution is Third. (6.32)

In another place, he developed the same idea in aslightly different way, relating the notions of absolutefirst and absolute last to the Christian conception ofGod as Alpha and Omega.

The starting-point of the universe, God the Creator, isthe Absolute First; the terminus of the universe, God

Page 453: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

completely revealed, is the Absolute Second; everystate of the universe at a measureable point of time isthe third. (1.362)

If one holds that all there is to the universe is what ismeasureable with no absolute first or last, with nodefinite tendency whence or whither, he is anEpicurean; if one holds that the definite drift ofnature's course is cyclic so that the absolute end isonly a return to the nothingness of the absolutebeginning, he is a pessimist (6.363). On Peirce'sview, the only conception of the universe compatiblewith Christian theology is an evolutionism whichadmits that the absolute First is distinct from theabsolute Second, and that the state of things in theend has a general character different from the stateof things in the beginning (1.362, n. 1).11

11 Although Peirce was a deeply religious man, he didnot give religious conceptions much philosophicstanding. Religion for him was not the speculations

(footnote continued on next page)

Page 454: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 189

In summary, then, Peirce's evolutionary cosmology isbest characterized as "hyperbolic" (8.317). It beginsin the world as it is a world in which there is life andgrowth everywhere. Spontaneity and variety aboundamid regularity and order. His world view looks inboth directions: backward toward the origins of thisgrowing cosmos, and forward toward thedevelopment yet to be realized. As man looks in eachof these directions he only approaches the limitsindefinitely. To have reached the limits in eitherdirection, even in thought, would be to transcend thespace-time order to which man is bound. At best mancan only speculate as to the how of the origins and ofthe outcome. Peirce's idea of evolution, then, can bethought of as an hyperbolic curve indefinitelyapproaching the x-axis of origin and the y-axis of end.

In a letter to Christine Ladd-Franklin (August 29,1891) Peirce described these axes like this:

The state of things in the infinite past is chaos, tohubohu, the nothingness of which consists in the totalabsence of regularity. The state of things in the infinitefuture is death,

(footnote continued from previous page)

of theologians and philosophers. It was a personal

Page 455: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

conviction based on one's direct (if mediate)experience of God. God was not to enter intometaphysics as an explanatory hypothesis. Still, he isnot willing to condemn all philosophers who have usedthe term God to designate some part of their system.Thus he thinks that those philosophers who speak of"ideas in God's mind" are on the right track, but areusing figures of speech which are more ludicrous thanfalse (6.199). In another place, in a more indulgenttone, he concedes that those who must think of theuniverse as having an adequate cause are justified inthinking of that cause as God (5.536). We must remarkin passing that the greatest weakness in Peirce'streatment of religion is his studied neglect of itscognitive or interpretative element. In particular if hehad been more aware of the cognitive claims ofChristian theology he would have better understoodthe gigantic intellectual efforts put into the problems ofanalogous predication by the great scholastics. To ourknowledge, Peirce, despite his familiarity with thescholastic tradition, never takes up the question ofwhether there are any distinctions to be made betweensorts of analogy. He lumps them all together under theheading of anthropomorphisms. Cf. J.E. Smith,"Religion and Theology in Peirce," Studies, Wiener andYoung, pp. 266-267. For a representative presentationof the problems of analogy taken up by the greatscholastics, cf. G.P. Klubertanz, Introduction to thePhilosophy of Being, 2nd ed. (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1963), passim.

Page 456: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 457: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 190

the nothingness of which consists in the completetriumph of law and absence of all spontaneity. (8.317)

Between these two different sorts of nothingness

. . . we have on our side a state of things in whichthere is some absolute spontaneity counter to all law,and some degree of conformity to law, which isconstantly on the increase owing to the growth ofhabit. (8.317)

The tendency to form habits, to generalize, grows byits own action.

Its first germs arose from pure chance. There wereslight tendencies to obey rules that had been followed,and these tendencies were rules which were more andmore obeyed by their own action. There were alsoslight tendencies to do otherwise than previously, andthese destroyed themselves. (8.317)

Finally, the law of habit is the law of mind and hencethe growing cosmos is "alive." Matter is merely minddeadened by the development of habit to the pointwhere the breaking up of those habits is very difficult.Consequently, the universe is not as the mechanisticphilosophers would have it. It is not governed solelynor principally by the laws of dynamics. It is governedby reasonableness working itself out in the concrete.

Page 458: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

It has an intrinsic and immanent finality which cannotbe reduced to the interaction of blind forces. All thatremains for us to consider is Peirce's speculationsabout the universe's beginning and end.

Page 459: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 191

3. The Beginning & the EndAn Hyperbola determines two limits, its asymptotes,which are indefinitely approached but never reached.Since Peirce uses this analogy to characterize theevolutionary process, one is not surprised that hegives an account of its limits, that is, of the universe'sbeginning and end. Man, of course, cannotexperience these limits, and yet they are logicallyrequired if evolution takes an hyperbolic course. Sincethis is speculation about the infinite, although heused all the logic and mathematics at his disposal,Peirce himself had to admit his account of universe'sorigin must seem to his reader "wildly confused"(6.203).1 For all the obscurity, however, we mustconsider the limiting cases for completeness.

Peirce says relatively little about the universe's endand a good deal about its origin. This is not to implythat the cosmos' outcome is any less important thanits beginning. In some respects the outcome is moreimportant for Peirce since so much of his logicaltheory depends upon the "long run" and since hefrequently defines reality in terms of the ultimateagreement of the community of researchers. But

Page 460: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

since there are two papers which deal with thebeginnings in some detail, it is best to start there andconsider the universe's end later.

The two papers we are about to consider werewritten about 1898. By this time Peirce's cosmologyhad taken definite shape and he was seriouslyengaged in thought about the normative sciences.One paper is called "The Logic of Continuity" and theother "The Logic of Events." The editors of theCollected Papers have given the sections consideredhere the titles "The Logic of the Universe" and"Objective Logic,'' respectively. Since the paperscomplement each other we will discuss themtogether.

1 See 6.419 ff. for an early expression of theimportance of determining whether the universe isfinite or infinite in age and extent. See 1.273 ff. for amuch more developed mathematical approach to thesame sort of question.

Page 461: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 192

The question of origins is metaphysical rather thancosmological because it deals with the universe as awhole.

Metaphysics has to account for the whole universe ofbeing. It has, therefore, to do something like supposinga state of things in which that universe did not exist,and consider how it could have arisen. (6.214)

But because the question of the universe's origin ismetaphysical, it is logical since, for Peirce, logicalprinciples are principles of being. Such aninvestigation, then, must consider the objectivelogical sequence of the world's origin. There can beno question of temporal sequence since time itself, asan organized something, only began with thecosmos.2

With this fundamental distinction in mind, let usconsider the strategy of Peirce's reasoning. He statesthat the basic supposition back of every attempt tounderstand something is "that the very objects ofstudy themselves are subject to a logic more or lessidentical with that which we employ" (6.189). Inother words, science is realistic and not nominalistic.3The "logic of the universe," therefore, governs ours.Our logic aspires to the universe's and not the other

Page 462: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

way round. Thus, the universe's own intelligibility isnormative of our thinking. Whatever theory weentertain must submit itself to our experience of howthings are and not dictate how things must be.

Consequently, with the modesty befitting a scientificman, Peirce begins by ascertaining as nearly aspossible how things are in the world of ourexperience. According to him, logic shows thatcontinuity is simply a higher type of generality. It is infact relational generality (6.190). Our experience tellsus that there is at least some

2 This is an answer to Kant's fourth antinomy (A452-B480; A453-B481). To think of the cosmos asbeginning in time leads to an absurdity, but to think ofthe beginning of the cosmos as the beginning of timedoes not.3 Peirce says that science "supposes" or "at least hopes"that the world is intelligible. It would be hasty to concludefrom this reservation that Peirce thought any less of thearguments he gave elsewhere in support of realism. Allhe needs for the passage under consideration is thelesser claim. Besides, humble fallibilism requires theelimination of ''cocksureness" even where one isconvinced that one holds the best hypothesis so faroffered. It could and should be altered if the evidencewarrants a change.

Page 463: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 464: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 193

continuity and generality in the world, since there arereal laws of nature. As a matter of fact, we know theworld only to the extent that we discover these laws.According to the logic of explanation (see Part III,Chapter 1), it is precisely the regularity of theuniverse which must be accounted for. Our world isone of variety and uniformity4 in which, as far as wecan tell, there is a definite movement from lesser togreater organization. Variety and diversity cannot beexplained in terms of uniformity, but uniformity canbe explained in terms of variety and diversity throughthe mediation of habit. So the universe is evolvingfrom chaos to order.5

Granted, then, that the uniformity of our universe isthe thing to be explained, the question Peirce puts tohimself is whether one ought to look upon that orderas the result of welding together discrete entities ornot (6.191). On the one hand, Peirce's logic ofexplanation seems to demand something like that,since it must account for order rising out of chaos. Onthe other hand, our logic, as the reflected image ofthe universe's, seems to indicate that humanreasoning always moves from the vague to thedefinite, from the homogeneous to theheterogeneous (6.191). Apparently, then, the

Page 465: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

uniformity of our universe ought to be explained interms of something still more homogeneous andvague, or, in Peirce's words, in terms of a still highersort of continuum. But in that case, how can weclaim to be explaining uniformity in terms of variety?

The inconsistency is only apparent, but before weshow why it is, let us try to understand what ledPeirce to argue for an original and primordialcontinuum of pure indeterminacy as the beginning-limit of our world's evolution. There were tworeasons: (1) since he took seriously the propositionthat our logic reflects the universe's, he was forced toadmit "in Spencer's phrase [that] the undifferentiateddifferentiates itself" (6.191), that is, evolutionproceeds from

4 See 6.88-101. Peirce analyzes four or five positionsconcerning how much variety and uniformity we are toadmit.5 Peirce was convinced that the hypothesis most in linewith science is the one which supposes that there is someprogress and development in the universe, that is, whichholds that the cosmos goes from somewhere tosomewhere. He could not admit either the "Epicurean" orthe "cyclic" conceptions of time (1.363). It is not that hethinks them foolish or inconceivable but simply thatexperience favors evolution (1.273).

Page 466: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 467: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 194

the vague to the definite; (2) if all continua are madeup of discrete units (individuals or collections orentities in one-to-one correspondence with either),Peirce thought that he could deduce a contradiction(Cantor's paradox of the greatest cardinal)6 and toresolve the paradox he denied that the greatestmultitude has any discrete or actual parts at all. Thisgreatest multitude which has no parts Peirce called apotential aggregate (6.185 ff).

When I say that the series of abnumeral multitudes hasno limit, I mean that it has no limit among multitudesof distinct individuals. It will have a limit if there isproperly speaking, any meaning in saying thatsomething that is not a multitude of distinct individualsis more than every multitude of distinct individuals. . . .That which is possible is in so far general, and, asgeneral, it ceases to be individual. Hence,remembering that the word "potential" meansindeterminate yet capable of determination in anyspecial case, there may be a potential aggregate of allthe possibilities that are consistent with certain generalconditions; and this may be such that given anycollection of distinct individuals whatsoever, out of thatpotential aggregate there may be actualized a moremultitudinous collection than the given collection. Thusthe potential aggregate is, with the strictestexactitude, greater in multitude than any possible

Page 468: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

multitude of individuals. But being a potentialaggregate only, it does not contain any individuals atall. It only contains general conditions which permit thedetermination of individuals. (6.185)

Peirce might have tried to resolve the paradox of thegreatest

6 Cf. M.G. Murphey, op. cit., pp. 263 ff. Murphey'scareful analysis shows that in fact Peirce failed to provehis paradox because he failed to produce a genuinecase in which 2n = n. Still Peirce's formulation of theparadox is correct and Cantor himself proved it in 1899.Cantor showed that the power-set of any set is alwaysgreater than that set (2n > n). He also showed thatthe set of all sets, M, must include, or be equal to 2M,since 2M is the set of sub-sets of M. Peirce's solution tothe paradox, therefore, is of genuine interest.

Page 469: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 195

cardinal after the manner of Russell's theory oftypes.7 We are inclined to think that he did notbecause of his ultrarealistic contention that all logicalprocesses reflect nature's. The vague and indefiniteare real for Peirce. So he had no difficulty inadmitting a pure and absolute indeterminacy at thebeginning of everything and out of which everythingarose. His solution did escape the contradiction of thegreatest cardinal and at the same time avoidedRussell's conclusion that there can be no meaningfulself-referential propositions.8

Just how does Peirce characterize the initial conditionof the universe?

The initial condition, before the universe existed, wasnot a state of pure abstract being. On the contrary itwas a state of just nothing at all, not even a state ofemptiness, for even emptiness is something.

If we are to proceed in a logical and scientific manner,we must, in order to account for the whole universe,suppose an initial condition in which the whole universewas non-existent, and therefore a state of absolutenothing. (6.215)9

But there are two sorts of nothingness, that ofnegation and that of complete indeterminacy. The

Page 470: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

nothingness of negation is really otherness and ''otherthan" is a relation which can be applied only wherethere is some degree of definiteness anddiscreteness. The nothing of negation is only asynonym for the ordinal number second and as suchimplies a First (6.217). The nothingness of the "purezero," or indeterminacy, is prior to any First. Pushedto its extreme, the nothingness of negation would bethe nothingness of death; it would be the state ofabsolute Secondness in which everything would be

7 Cf. Murphey, op. cit., p. 274; S. Körner, ThePhilosophy of Mathematics (London: HutchinsonUniversity Press, 1960), pp. 45-47; 62-66.8 Russell's solution is not entirely satisfactory either. Itdeclares meaningless any statement which refers to itself.F.B. Fitch, for one, argues forcefully for the need of self-reference in philosophy. Cf. Symbolic Logic: AnIntroduction (New York: Ronald Press Co., 1952), pp. 217-225.9 W. Wallace (transl.), The Logic of Hegel (London:Oxford University Press, 1959), nos. 86-87, pp. 158-163.

Page 471: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 196

frozen solid. The nothingness of "pure zero" is thenothingness of not having been born.

There is no individual thing, no compulsion, outwardnor inward, no law. It is the germinal nothing, in whichthe whole universe is involved or foreshadowed. Assuch, it is absolutely undefined and unlimited possibilityboundless possibility. There is no compulsion and nolaw. It is boundless freedom. (6.217)

Peirce likened this initial state to Aristotle's primematter (6.206). Prime matter is nec quid nec qualenec quantum. Peirce's potential aggregate, however,has one property, spontaneity. For Aristotle, primematter functioned as an individuating and limitingprinciple which has no reality at all apart from arelation to some form. It has no spontaneity apartfrom act. Peirce, then, seems to endow Aristotle'sprime matter with a little energeia or act.10

From pure indeterminacy nothing in particularnecessarily results. Here Peirce departs from Hegel.

In this proposition lies the prime difference betweenmy objective logic and that of Hegel. He says, if thereis any sense in philosophy at all, the whole universeand every feature of it, however minute, is rational,and was constrained to be as it is by the logic ofevents, so that there is no principle of action in the

Page 472: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

universe but reason. But I reply, this line of thought,though it begins rightly, is not exact. A logical slip iscommitted; and the conclusion reached is manifestly atvariance with observation. (6.218)

Hegel's slip was to think that because the universe isrational it is constrained to be as it is. According toPeirce, then, Hegel fell into the error of allnecessitarians. He supposed the logic of evolution to

10 The schoolmen disputed over how prime mattershould be conceived. Thomists generally held that itcould not have any act whatsoever not even an actproper to itself. Suarezians generally held that primematter has its own act. The difference is not a merequibble. It determines to a large extent how theseschools analyzed the notion of being and so affectstheir metaphysics at almost every point. Although theterms "act" and "potency" appear in both they do nothave precisely the same meaning.

Page 473: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 197

be "of that wooden kind that absolutely constrains agiven conclusion" (6.218). Peirce points out that theuniverse's logic of development may be that ofinductive or hypothetic inference. Hegel's mistakeforced him to deny "the fundamental character of twoelements of experience which cannot result fromdeductive logic" spontaneity (Firstness) andarbitrariness (Secondness).

Although nothing in particular necessarily resultedfrom the "tohu bohu," something or other had to,simply because it is boundless spontaneity andfreedom.

I say that nothing necessarily resulted from the Nothingof boundless freedom. That is, nothing according todeductive logic. But such is not the logic of freedom orpossibility. The logic of freedom, or possibility, is that itshall annul itself. For if it does not annul itself, itremains a completely idle and do-nothing potentiality;and a completely idle potentiality is annulled by itscomplete idleness. (6.219)

There can be no potentiality which would never,somewhere and sometime, have the occasion to beactualized. To say that there were such a do-nothingpotentiality would be to confuse potentiality withmere logical possibility. It would be to deprive

Page 474: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

potentiality of all its power and dynamism.11 There is,then, a kind of necessity in the first step in evolutionbut not that sort of necessity required by thedeterminists. For Peirce there must be some move orother (necessitas quoad exercitium), but no one inparticular (necessitas quoad specificationem). Strictnecessitarians would require that the specification bealso determined.12

Something or other, then, had to come from theoriginal pure spontaneity just because it is purespontaneity. But again, because

11 Aristotle and Thomas would agree, but they wouldsay that the power and dynamism of real potentialitycomes from some act with which it is associated. If thisis what Peirce means, he is not very clear about it.12 See T.A. Goudge, op. cit., pp. 172 ff., for a discussionof an ambiguity in Peirce's use of the term "probablededuction." Sometimes it refers to necessary inferencesabout probabilities; sometimes to conclusions which areonly probable. Our distinction between kinds of necessitymight throw some light on this ambiguity.

Page 475: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 198

pure spontaneity has no order, nothing in particularhad to appear neither this, nor that, nor the other.Whatever did appear, appeared by pure chance. Weare beginning to see that Peirce saw no inconsistencyin saying that uniformity resulted from variety andthat the original chaos had a certain uniformity aboutit. Clearly Peirce has in mind two quite different sortsof uniformity. The uniformity which requiresexplanation is that manifested in laws of nature. Thatsort of uniformity is manifested amid an actualmultiplicity of instances. The uniformity of the originalvague potentiality is a unity without any actualmultiplicity at all. It is not the sort of thing whichwould lead us to expect from it anything in particular.Therefore, it would not cause any surprises and sowould not lead us to ask questions. The sort of unitywhich raises questions is that which we find inmultiplicity. The original continuum has only thatunity which comes from lacking every determination.It has a unity, as it were, by default. As Peircepointed out to Dr. Carus, this sort of "law" is entirelydifferent from the rigid law of the determinists. It isthe "law of freedom" and the basis of the law ofmind.

When we think of chance we are apt to think of a

Page 476: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

random distribution of discrete units governed only bythe laws of probability. Peirce once remarked that aworld of chance in this sense would not be totallylawless. A random distribution of discrete entities,then, would not be entirely without order. Of coursethat order would only be accidental to the collection.The units in the collection could have beendistributed some other way without affecting thecollection. Nevertheless, Peirce seems to havethought the collection would have some order. Nowas far as we can tell, the random distribution of adiscrete collection is what Peirce meant by "quasi-chance." The limit case of "randomness" is whatPeirce calls "absolute chance" and it has no orderwhatsoever because it has no discrete parts. Quasi-chance simulates the indeterminacy of absolutechance and

. . . in a broad view of the universe a simulation of agiven elementary mode of action can hardly beexplained except by supposing the genuine mode ofaction somewhere has place. (6.613)

Peirce, then, takes the potential aggregate as thelimit from which the evolutionary process began backin the infinitely distant

Page 477: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 199

past. Once we have grasped this difficult notion, therest of Peirce's logical account is not too hard tofollow. We must not forget, however, that it is aquestion of logical, not temporal, sequence. All ourthinking is bounded by temporal conditions and so wemust ever be correcting the tendency to transposethe temporality of our mental processes into theatemporal ordering of logical relations.

Peirce's logical studies, of course, provided him with aset of ordered logical relations: Firstness,Secondness, and Thirdness. And, as we have seen, tothese categories roughly correspond the modes ofbeing: qualitative possibility, actuality, and law.Peirce can make use of these notions in his accountof the origin of our existing universe. The spontaneityof the original vague potentiality assured thatsomething or other would be actualized. Logicassures that the first articulation of that vaguepotentiality must be "Firstnesses" or qualitativepossibilities.

Thus the zero of bare possibility, by evolutionary logic,leapt into the unit of some quality. This was hypotheticinference. Its form was: something is possible; red issomething; therefore, red is possible. (6.220; cf. 6.194ff.)

Page 478: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

The first evolutionary move away from completeindeterminacy, therefore, was the emergence of the"World of Platonic Forms" by their inherent Firstness(6.198). Potentiality in general became particularpotentialities.

It would be a mistake, Peirce insists, to think thatthese qualitative possibilities arose separately andonly afterwards came into relation (6.199). If theyhad appeared on the scene in complete isolationthere would be no way in which they could ever berelated, since in themselves they are what they areindependently of anything else. Once in isolation theywould forever remain so, and then the "PlatonicWorld" would be atomic and static. No furtherdevelopment would be possible (cf. 6.222-237).Consequently, we must assume that they sprang upalready reacting upon one another. In that case,Peirce can say that they have a sort of existence(6.199), something like the existence our ideas havein our minds.

Logic further requires that every potentiality haveactual instances at some time or other, somewhere orother. Peirce can argue, therefore, that a necessarycondition for the move from vague

Page 479: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 200

potentiality to definite potentialities is that thesedefinite potentialities have at some time actualinstances. Our existing world is one locus of theactual instances of some of the "Platonic forms."Concrete actuals, however, in our world at least,never exhibit only one quality. Each is an actualinstance of several potentialities. The instances, then,can be thought of as at the intersection, or points ofinteraction, of the forms. We may conclude that thespringing up of potentialities in reaction one toanother is a condition for there being concreteinstances, just as concrete instances are a necessarycondition for real potentiality. The universes ofpotentiality and of actuality, therefore, areinterdependent although distinct in the same way asFirstness and Secondness.

If we recall what Peirce had to say about law, we seethat the relationship between potentialities and theiractual cases defines law. Brute interaction can beconceived as taking place between individuals, butnot between individual and type. The only way inwhich an individual can come under a type is by alaw. Thus the universe of law is a logical condition forthe other two. All the universes, then, are inseparablybound up although distinct, just as are the

Page 480: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

categories. They can be prescinded one from anotherin a definite logical sequence. Notice, however, thatthe order of involution and that of evolution are justthe opposite. Thirdness or law involves Secondness oractuality and Firstness or potentiality; but potentialityevolves actuality and these two together evolve law.As far as temporal sequence is concerned all threeuniverses appeared at once since time itself arosewith them.

We must now say something about the limit towardwhich our universe is evolving. It must be a state inwhich the reign of law is at a maximum. This doesnot mean that the universe will ever grind to a halt orbecome frozen in a "heat-death." When Peirce doesdescribe the limit in these terms (cf. e.g. 8.317), heknows it will never be reached. In one place hecharacterizes this ultimate condition as the AbsoluteSecond and likens it to "God completely revealed"(1.362), thinking perhaps of Hegel's Absolute Spiritabsolutely articulated. At this limit, there would be nospontaneity and so no mind. The Absolute Second isthe antithesis of the Absolute First.

There are several reasons why the Absolute Secondwill never be reached. First, since the primordialpotentiality can never be exhausted,

Page 481: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press
Page 482: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 201

all spontaneity cannot cease (1.615). Second, nogeneral can ever be completely embodied by actuals.Third, perhaps not entirely distinct from the other tworeasons, the law of mind cannot be self-destructive(6.148), for if it were, the very growth of concretereasonableness would be its undoing. Reason woulddestroy itself in and through the very process of itsdevelopment. Reason would, then, be acting in amost unreasonable way.

Peirce's criticism of absolute determinism really comesdown to saying that such a view admits that theAbsolute Second will be reached. More accuratelyperhaps, it says that the universe is always in a stateof absolute Secondness. According to Peirce, theabsolute determinist cannot, consistently with hisown principles, admit growth, variety, and diversity,and so he charges that observational data not only donot support such a position but are against it.

As we have seen in an earlier chapter, Peirce doesnot claim that a sudden end of everything isinconceivable, but again there is no positive evidenceto support such an hypothesis (4.547). He told usthat there might be material laws of nature againsteverything coming to a halt tomorrow, but that the

Page 483: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

notion itself is not self-contradictory. It is conceivable,for instance, that some force transcending our worldmight destroy it. Still, mere logical possibility is not asufficient ground upon which to base an hypothesis.Consequently, Peirce is convinced that tomorrow isdestined to come and another tomorrow and anotherinto the indefinite future.

Between the limits of vague potentiality and absolutefixity evolution goes on. Through the tendency togeneralize, the universe is growing and developing. Itis becoming more and more organized and subject tothe law of mind. Evolution is Reason progressivelymanifesting itself. Reason, for Peirce, consists in itsgoverning individual events and without those actualfacts it would have no reality at all. It consists inbeing continually embodied in fact. It follows, then,that Reason can never be fully embodied since nonumber of events of actual facts can ever fulfill itspotentiality.

So, then, the essence of Reason is such that its beingnever can have been completely perfected. It alwaysmust be in a state of incipiency, of growth. It is like thecharacter of a man which consists in the ideas that hewill conceive

Page 484: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 202

and in the efforts that he will make, and which onlydevelops as the occasions actually arise. Yet in all hislife no son of Adam has ever fully manifested whatthere was in him. So, then, the development of Reasonrequires as a part of it the occurrence of moreindividual events than ever can occur. It requires, too,all the coloring of all qualities of feeling, includingpleasure, in its proper place among the rest. (1.615)

Reason, then, is the working out of ideas in theworld. And for Peirce the growth of concretereasonableness is the admirable in itself.

Peirce's cosmological speculations and hispragmaticism come together in a striking way in hisevolutionary ideal. The course of evolution itself, thegrowth of concrete reasonableness, becomes thesummum bonum, the highest norm. He has foundthe object of esthetics, and through contemplation ofit, he feels that man can deliberately form habits offeeling in accord with it. In terms of this highestgood, man can determine what are to be his ideals ofconduct, for he has found his place in the universe.

Man, then, holds a privileged and unique place in thisevolving world. Although he himself is a product ofthat process of development and still is in greatmeasure subject to it, he has reached a stage where

Page 485: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

he is capable of a very high degree of self-control. Itis this superior degree of control which sets him apartfrom other animals;

. . . it is by the indefinite replication of self-control uponself-control that the vir is begotten, and by action,through thought, he grows an esthetic ideal . . . as theshare which God permits him to have in the work ofcreation. (5.403, n. 3)

Man has evolved to a point where he now cancooperate in the process of evolution itself, since hecan deliberately control his own actions and influencethe community of which he is a member. He maychoose to further as best he can the growth ofconcrete reasonableness in the world and so fulfillhimself, or he may decide to act perversely and sosucceed in destroying himself. He cannot completelyfrustrate Nature for he is still subject to her. Reasonwill continue to embody itself with or without him,but he is privileged to cooperate in that

Page 486: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 203

process consciously and willingly. Man needs normsto guide his deliberate conduct and those norms hefinds in and through the universe which he knowsand experiences the universe which he knows andexperiences because he arose out of it and is a partof it.

I do not see how one can have a more satisfying idealof the admirable than the development of Reason sounderstood. The one thing whose admirableness is notdue to an ulterior reason is Reason itselfcomprehended in all its fulness, so far as we cancomprehend it. Under this conception, the ideal ofconduct will be to execute our little function in theoperation of the creation by giving a hand towardrendering the world more reasonable whenever, as theslang is, it is ''up to us" to do so. (1.615)13

13 Peirce came to acknowledge the embodiment ofReason as the summum bonum through acontemplation of the universe's structure. The interplayof the modes of being bringing about the cosmos'development struck him as something admirable initself. We wonder whether or not this is the sort ofthing he had in mind when he spoke of "musement"through which, he thought, one would be convinced ofGod's reality. In any case, he certainly held that"musement" on the interrelation of the "threeUniverses" would bring one to that hypothesis, which ".

Page 487: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

. . the more he ponders it, the more it will findresponse in every part of his mind, for its beauty, for itssupplying an ideal of life, and for its thoroughlysatisfactory explanation of his whole threefoldenvironment" (6.465; cf. 6.452-493).

Page 488: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 205

APPENDICES

Page 489: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 207

Appendix IIn the ''Minute Logic" written shortly before the 1903Harvard lectures, that is, about 1902, Peirce writes:

The science which Berkeley, Kant, and others havedeveloped, and which goes by the name of the theoryof cognition, is an experiential, or positive science. Itlearns and teaches that certain things exist. It evenmakes special observations. But the experientialelement in logic is all but nil. No doubt it is anobservational science, in some sense; every science isthat. Even pure mathematics observes its diagrams.But logic contents itself almost entirely, likemathematics, with considering what would be the casein hypothetical states of things. Unlike the specialsciences, it is not obliged to resort to experience forthe support of the laws it discovers and enunciates, forthe reason that those laws are merely conditional, notcategorical. The normative character of the scienceconsists, precisely, in that condition attached to itslaws. (2.65, emphasis added)

It certainly seems that here Peirce contradicts whathe said about normative science in 5.39 (quoted inPart I, Chapter 2), namely, that its truth iscategorical. In any case it is difficult to reconcile

Page 490: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

these passages. In conversations with colleagues,however, a number of things have been suggested todiminish the conflict. (1) In the passage quoted inthis note Peirce is interested in distinguishing logicfrom any Erkenntnislehre which makes psychology itsbasis. Psychology might tell us how we must thinkwhat are the uncontrollable processes thereininvolved, but logic as a normative science must dealwith reasoning precisely from the point where it canbe controlled. Logic, then, is not a positive science inthe same way that psychology is, and in this respectis closer to mathematics. (2) When Peirce says thatthe conditional character of logic's laws is preciselywhat makes logic normative, he means to stress thatlogic lays down rules for right thinking, and

Page 491: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 208

rules, since they refer to ends to be achieved, aremost appropriately expressed in conditional, notcategorical, propositions. He certainly has in mindformal rules of thinking which would be valid in anyuniverse of rational creatures, but does notnecessarily restrict normative logic to formalconsiderations. Thus he admits that logic does needat least that experience necessary to motivate itsresearch, and in another place tells us that all truelaws, true generals, formal as well as material, arecharacterized by conditional necessity only. Whilelogic is like mathematics, it is still distinguished fromit in that it also must take into consideration theprocesses of thinking and the nature of the objectthought as they actually are, not just as they mightbe. (3) Peirce makes the laws of logic the laws ofbeing. Normative logic looked at in this way mightconceivably be thought of as making categoricalstatements of positive fact about reality, and still onecould hold that the norms, rules, or laws which itenunciates are to be put in the form of conditional,not categorical propositions. Considered precisely asnorms or laws for right thinking they ought to takethe form, "If you want X, do Y." Considered as laws ofbeing, general facts about reality, they might be

Page 492: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

expressed in categorical form, perhaps something likethis: "It is a general fact or law of nature that if youwant X, do Y." These suggestions are offered forwhat they are worth. At least we are working on theprinciple that before a man's thinking is pronouncedinconsistent every effort to save it ought to be made.Cf. R.S. Robin, "Peirce's Doctrine of the NormativeSciences," Studies in the Philosophy of CharlesSanders Peirce, ed., by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin(Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964),pp. 275 ff. for a perceptive discussion of thisdifficulty.

Page 493: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 209

Appendix IiIN A LONG FRAGMENT (ca. 1906) Peirce expounds insome detail his doctrine of "interpretants" (5.475-493). He tells us that the "meaning" of an intellectualconcept requires a study of interpretants, that is, ofthe "proper significate effects" of signs. There arethree general classes of interpretants (correspondingto the three universal categories): (1) the emotionalinterpretant, or feeling produced by a sign, (2) theenergetic interpretant, or effort, physical or mental,elicited by a sign, and (3) the logical interpretant, orrational purport of a sign (5.475-476). Peirce setshimself the difficult task of explicating the logicalinterpretant. The first logical interpretant is aconjecture or hypothesis suggested by involuntaryexperience (5.480). Such a conjecture stimulatesvoluntary performances or "experiments'' in the "innerworld," that is, one considers the consequences ofthe conjecture and weighs alternatives. The logicalinterpretant, then, is seen to refer to the future, notto the future which as a matter of fact ''will be," butto what "would be" on certain assumptions. Thelogical interpretant, therefore, has the character of a

Page 494: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

general (5.481-483). But what categories of mentalfacts are of general reference? Peirce lists only fourpossibilities: (1) conceptions, (2) desires, (3)expectations, and (4) habits.

Now it is no explanation of the nature of the logicalinterpretant (which, we already know, is a concept) tosay that it is a concept. This objection applies also todesire and expectation . . . since neither of these isgeneral otherwise than through connection with aconcept. Besides, as to desire, it would be easy toshow . . ., that the logical interpretant is an effect ofthe energetic interpretant, in the sense in which thelatter is an effect of the emotional interpretant. Desire,however, is cause, not effect, of effort. As toexpectation, it is excluded by the fact that it is notconditional. For that which might be mistaken for aconditional expectation is nothing but a judgment that,under certain conditions, there

Page 495: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 210

would be an expectation: there is no conditionality inthe expectation itself, such as there is in the logicalinterpretant after it is actually produced. (5.486)

By elimination, therefore, Peirce concludes that theessence of the logical interpretant is habit.

In every case, after some preliminaries, the activitytakes the form of experimentation in the inner world;and the conclusion (if it comes to a definiteconclusion), is that under given conditions, theinterpreter will have formed the habit of acting in agiven way whenever he may desire a given kind ofresult. The real and living logical conclusion is thathabit; the verbal formulation merely expresses it.(5.491)

Peirce, of course, admits that another concept, orproposition, or argument can be a logical interpretantof a concept, but it cannot be the final logicalinterpretant, "for the reason that it is itself a sign ofthat very kind that has itself a logical interpretant."Only the habit can be the final logical interpretantbecause, although it too is a sign, it is not a sign likethe concept of which it is the logical interpretant is asign. What interprets habit considered as a sign(together with motive and circumstances) is action.But action is an energetic not a logical interpretant

Page 496: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

precisely because it lacks generality.

The deliberately formed, self-analyzing habit self-analyzing because formed by the aid of analysis of theexercises that nourished it is the living definition, theveritable and final logical interpretant. Consequently,the most perfect account of a concept that words canconvey will consist in a description of the habit whichthat concept is calculated to produce. (5.491)

Peirce concluded this important paragraph with arhetorical question.

But how otherwise can a habit be described than by adescription of the kind of action to which it gives rise,with the specification of the conditions and of themotive?

This is but another expression of the scholastic maxim"agere sequitur esse," the medieval counterpart ofthe pragmatic maxim. To know

Page 497: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 211

what a thing is, you must see what it does! Cf. J.E.Smith, The Spirit of American Philosophy (New York:Oxford University Press, 1963), pp. 8-9. Yet cf. 4.536for a slightly different arrangement:

Immediateinterpretant

= the interpretant as revealed in theright understanding of the signitself, and it is ordinarily called sign'smeaning.

Dynamicalinterpretant

= actual effect which signdetermines.

Finalinterpretant

= refers to the manner in which signtends to represent itself to berelated to its object.

Page 498: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 213

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Page 499: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 215

Bibliography

Works by Peirce

Charles S. Peirce's Letters to Lady Welby. Edited I.C.Lieb. New Haven: Whitlock's, 1953.

Charles S. Peirce Papers. Houghton Library, HarvardUniversity (Manuscripts).

Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI. Edited by C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss.Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931-1935.Vols. VII-VIII. Edited by A.W. Burks. Cambridge:Harvard University Press, 1958.

Values in a Universe of Change: Selected Writings ofCharles S. Peirce. Edited with introduction and notesby P.P. Wiener. New York: Doubleday Anchor Books,1958. Reprinted, New York: Dover Publications, Inc.,1966.

Works About Peirce

Burks, Arthur W. "Peirce's Conception of Logic as aNormative Science," Philosophical Review, 2 (March1943), 187-192.

Page 500: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Bernstein, R.J. "Peirce's Theory of Perception,"Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce,Second Series. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 165-189.

. Perspectives on Peirce: Critical Essays on CharlesSanders Peirce. Edited by R.J. Bernstein. New Haven:Yale University Press, 1965.

Boler, J.F. Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism.Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1963.

Dewey, J. "Peirce's Theory of Quality," John Deweyon Experience, Nature, and Freedom. Edited by R.J.Bernstein. New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1960. Pp.199-210.

Feibleman, J. An Introduction to Peirce's Philosophy,Intrepreted as a System. New York: Harper andBros., 1946.

Page 501: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 216

Fitzgerald, J.J. Peirce's Theory of Signs as Foundationfor Pragmatism. (Studies in Philosophy, XIL.) TheHague: Mouton and Co., 1966.

Freeman, E. The Categories of Charles Peirce.Chicago: Open Court, 1934.

Gallie, W.B. Peirce and Pragmatism. Harmondworth,Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1952.

Goudge, T.A. The Thought of C.S. Peirce. Toronto:University of Toronto Press, 1950.

. "Peirce's Evolutionism After Half a Century." Studiesin the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, SecondSeries. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 323-341.

Haas, W.P. The Conception of Law and the Unity ofPeirce's Philosophy. Studia Friburgensia, New Series,No. 38. Fribourg: University Press, and Notre Dame:University of Notre Dame Press, 1964.

Hartshorne, C. "The Relativity of Nonrelativity,"Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce.Edited by P.P. Wiener and F.H. Young. Cambridge:Harvard University Press, 1952. Pp. 215-224.

Page 502: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

. "Charles Peirce's `One Contribution to Philosophy'and His Most Serious Mistake." Studies in thePhilosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, Second Series.Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin. Amherst:University of Massachusetts Press, 1964. Pp. 455-474.

Hickman, Larry. "Why Peirce Didn't Like Dewey'sLogic," South Western Philosophical Review, 3(1986), 178-189.

Kemp-Pritchard, Ilona. "Peirce on Philosophical Hopeand Logical Sentiment." Philosophic PhenomenolResearch, 42, 75-90.

Kent, Beverley. "Peirce's Esthetics: A New Look."Transactions of C.S. Peirce Society, 12 (1976), 262-283.

Knight, T.S. Charles Peirce. New York: WashingtonSquare Press, 1965.

Krolikowski, W.P. "The Peircean Vir," Studies in thePhilosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, Second Series.Edited by E.C. Moore

Page 503: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 217

and R.S. Robin. Amherst: University ofMassachusetts Press, 1964. Pp. 257-270.

Lenz, J.W. "Induction as Self-Corrective," Studies inthe Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, SecondSeries. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 151-162.

Madden, E.H. Chauncey Wright and the Foundationsof Pragmatism. Seattle: University of WashingtonPress, 1961.

Moore, Edward C. and Richard S. Robin, eds. Studiesin the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, SecondSeries. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press,1964.

Murphey, M.G. The Development of Peirce'sPhilosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,1961.

Oliver, W.D. "The Final Cause and Agapasm inPeirce's Philosophy." Studies in the Philosophy ofCharles Sanders Peirce, Second Series. Edited by E.C.Moore and R.S. Robin. Amherst: University ofMassachusetts Press, 1964. Pp. 289-303.

Page 504: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Potter, Vincent G. "Normative Science and thePragmatic Maxim." Journal of the Hisory ofPhilosophy, 5 (January 1967), 41-53.

. "Peirce's Analysis of Normative Science."Transaction of C.S. Peirce Society, 2 (Spring 1966),pp. 5-32.

Reese, W. "Philosophic Realism: A Study in theModality of Being," Studies in the Philosophy ofCharles Sanders Peirce. Edited by P.P. Wiener andF.H. Young. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,1952. Pp. 225-237.

Reiser, Oliver L. "The Role of Symbols in HumanExistence." Main Currents, 25 (May-June 1969), 134-142.

Robin, R.S. Annotated Catalogue of the Papers ofCharles S. Peirce. Amherst: University ofMassachusetts Press, 1967.

. "Peirce's Doctrine of the Normative Sciences,"Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce,Second Series. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 271-288.

Salabert, Pere. "Aesthetic Experience in Charles S.Peirce: The Threshhold," Peirce and Value Theory.

Page 505: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Ed. Herman Parret. Amsterdam: J. Benjamins, 1994.

Schneider, H.W. "Fourthness." Studies in thePhilosophy of Charles

Page 506: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 218

Sanders Peirce. Edited by P.P. Wiener and F.H.Young. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1952.Pp. 251-267.

Smith, C.M. "The Aesthetics of Charles S. Peirce,"Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 31 (1972), 21-29.

Smith, J.E. The Spirit of American Philosophy. NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1963.

. "Religion and Theology in Peirce," Studies in thePhilosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce. Edited by P.P.Wiener and F.H. Young. Cambridge: HarvardUniversity Press, 1952. Pp. 251-267.

Thompson, M. The Pragmatic Philosophy of C.S.Peirce. Chicago: Phoenix Books, 1963.

Weiss, P. "Charles Sanders Peirce." Dictionary ofAmerican Biography, 14 (1934), 398-403.

. "The Essence of Peirce's System." Journal ofPhilosophy, 37 (1940), 253-264.

Wells, R. "The True Nature of Peirce's Evolutionism,"Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce,Second Series. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 304-322.

Page 507: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Wennerberg, H. The Pragmatism of C.S. Peirce: AnAnalytical Study. Library of Theoria, No. 9. Lund:C.W.K. Gleerup, and Copenhagen: E. Munksgaard,1962.

Wiener, P.P. Evolution and the Founders ofPragmatism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press,1949.

. "Peirce's Evolutionary Interpretations of the Historyof Science," Studies in the Philosophy of CharlesSanders Peirce. Edited by P.P. Wiener and F.H.Young. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1952.Pp. 143-152.

. Values in a Universe of Chance: Selected Writings ofCharles S. Peirce. Edited with introduction and notesby Philip P. Wiener. New York: Doubleday AnchorBooks, 1958. Reprinted, New York: DoverPublications, Inc., 1966.

Workman, R. "Pragmatism and Realism," Studies inthe Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, SecondSeries. Edited by E.C. Moore and R.S. Robin.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1964.Pp. 242-253.

Page 508: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 219

Miscellaneous Works Cited In the Text

Abbot, F.E. Scientific Theism; or, The Philosophy ofFree Religion. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1885.

Bettoni, E. Duns Scotus: The Basic Principles of HisPhilosophy. Translated by B. Bonansea, O.F.M.Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America,1961.

Einstein, A., and Infeld, L. The Evolution of Physics.New York: Simon and Schuster, 1961.

Fitch, F.B. Symbolic Logic: An Introduction. NewYork: The Ronald Press Co., 1952.

Hegel, G.F.W. The Logic. Translated by W. Wallace.Second edition. London: Oxford University Press,1892.

Hertz, H. The Principles of Mechanics. New York:Dover Books, 1956.

James, W. Pragmatism and Other Essays.Introduction by J.L. Blau. New York: WashingtonSquare Press, 1963.

Jammer, M. Concepts of Force. New York: HarperTorchbooks, 1962.

Page 509: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Kant, I. Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht. InVol. 10 of Immanuel Kant's Werke. Leipzig: Modesund Baumann, 1839. Pp. 113-377.

. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by N.K. Smith.New York: St. Martin's Press, 1961.

Klubertanz, G.P. Introduction to the Philosophy ofBeing. Second edition. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1963.

Körner, S. The Philosophy of Mathematics. London:Hutchinson University Press, 1960.

Pearson, K. The Grammar of Science. Everyman'sLibrary, edited by E. Rhys. London: J.M. Dent & Sons,1937. (First published in 1892, then in 1900, andagain in 1911, each with modifications. Peircereviewed both the first and second editions.)

Perry, R.B. The Thought and Character of WilliamJames, Vol. II. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1935.

Ross, Sir David. Aristotle. New York: Barnes andNoble (University Paperback), 1964.

Teilhard de Chardin, P. The Phenomenon of Man.New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1961.

Page 510: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 220

Weiss, P. Modes of Being. Carbondale: SouthernIllinois University Press, 1958.

Whittaker, Sir Edmund. A History of the Theories ofAether and Electricity. New York: Harper Torchbooks,1960.

Page 511: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 221

INDICES

Page 512: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 223

Index of Names*

A

ABBOT, F.E., 84

ANAXAGORAS, 172n

ANAXIMANDER, 172n

AQUINAS, ST. THOMAS, vii, x, 77, 80, 197n

ARISTOTLE, vii, ix, x, 23, 73, 112, 121, 128, 172n,196, 197n

AUGUSTINE, ST., 172n

B

BACON, R., 77

BALDWIN, J.M., 53, 71, 155n

BERGMANN, J., 27n

BERKELEY, G., 207

BERNSTEIN, R. 28, 92nn

BETTONI, E., 81n

Page 513: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

BOLER, J., 66n, 82, 117n, 126nBONANSEA, B., 81n

BOOLE, G., 27n

BOYLE, R., 144

BUCKLE, H.T., 173

C

CALDERONI, M., 4n, 54n, 82, 104

CANTOR, G., 194

CARUS, P., 74n, 136n, 154n, 161n, 162, 166, 198

CLAUSIUS, 173

D

DARWIN, C., 151, 167, 171, 172, 173, 174, 176,177, 179

DE MORGAN, C., 27n

DESCARTES, R., 153n

DEWEY, J., 6n, 91n, 92n

E

EINSTEIN, A., 138n

EMPEDOCLES, 172n

Page 514: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

ERDMANN, B., 27n

F

FEIBLEMAN, J., x n

FITCH, F.B., 195n

FREEMAN, E., ix n

G

GALLIE, W.B., 82, 117n

GAMALIEL, 125

GLOGAU, G., 27n

GOUDGE, T.A., ix n, 91n, 157n, 158nn, 179n, 197n

H

HAMILTON, SIR W., 174

HARTSHORNE, C., 24n

HEGEL, G.W.F., 10, 11, 21, 66, 82, 181, 196, 197,200

HEISENBERG, W., 160

HELMHOLTZ, H., 173

HERAPATH, SIR J., 173

Page 515: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

HERTZ, H.R., 144n

HUSSERL., E., 27n

I

INFELD, I., 138n

J

JAMES, H. (the elder), 183

JAMES, W., xi

JAMMER, M., 137n

K

KANT, I., vii, ix, x, 11, n, 3, 4n, 6, 8, 30, 53-55, 57n,62, 71, 110, 146n, 183

KANT, I., vii, ix, x, 11, 47, 59, 74nn, 128, 144n, 156,192n, 207

KLUBERTANZ, G.P., 189n

KNIGHT, T.S., x n

KÖLLIKER, A., 184

KÖRNER, S., 195n

KROLIKOWSKI, W.P., 183

Page 516: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

LLADD-FRANKLIN, Mrs. (Christine), 189

LAMARCK, J., 171n, 178, 179, 182

LEIBNIZ, W., 83

LENZ, J.W., 158n

LIEB, I.C., 11n, 13

LOCKE, J., 130

LORENTZ, H.A., 138n

* The author wishes to thank his students at LoyolaSeminary for their invaluable help in compiling theseindices.

Page 517: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 224

M

MADDEN, E.H., 151n, 181

MALTHUS, T., 176n

MANSELL, H.L., 174

MAXWELL, J.C., 173

MILL, J.S., 27n, 86n, 102, 151, 156n, 158n, 174

MOORE, E.C., ix n

MOORE, G.E., 38

MURPHEY, M.G., ix n, 105, 183, 194n, 195n

N

NÄGELI, K.W., 184

NICHOL, H., 102

O

OCKHAM, WILLIAM OF, 74n

OLIVER, W.D., x n, 65n

P

PAINE, H., 52

Page 518: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

PAPINI, G., 4n

PEARSON, K., 86, 176n

PERRY, R.B., 110, 146n

PLATO, 128

POINCARÉ, H., 138n

Q

QUETELET, L.A.J., 173

R

RANKINE, W., 173

REESE, W., 84n

ROBERT OF LINCOLN, 77

ROBIN, R.S., ix n, 8n, 208

ROSS, SIR D., 129n

ROYCE, J., 6n, 77n

RUSSELL, B., 195

S

ST. JOHN THE EVANGELIST, 183

SCHILLER, F.C.S., 4n

Page 519: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

SCHILLER, J.C.F. VON, 53

SCHLEIERMACHER, F.D.E., 37

SCHNEIDER, H., 33n

SCHRÖDER, E., 27n

SCHUPPE, W., 27n

SCOTUS, DUNS, 9n, 21, 77, 80, 81, 82

SIGWART, C. VON, 27n

SMITH, J.E., x n, 59n, 189n, 211

SPENCER, H., 181, 193

SWEDENBORG, E., 183

T

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN, P., 132n, 165n

THOMPSON, M., 71n, 90n

V

VENN, J., 27n, 141

W

WALLACE, W., 195n

WEISS, P., ix n, x n

Page 520: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

WEISMANN, A., 172n, 178, 184

WELBY, LADY V., 11, 12n, 13

WELLS, R., ix n, 175n

WENNERBERG, H., x n

WHITTAKER, E., 138n

WIENER, P., ix n, 151n, 185

WUNDT, W.M., 27n

Y

YOUNG, F.H., 24n, 33n

Page 521: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 225

Index Of Subjects

A

ABSTRACTION, 9n, 83, 84, 94, 131

ACT-POTENCY, 23, 196n

ACTION, viii, 4, 5, 6, 19, 21, 33, 45, 48, 50, 53-55,59-61, 63, 64, 65, 66, 80, 114, 125, 130, 134, 138,140, 166, 190, 196, 198, 210;

chance, 136n, 140, 143;

conservative, 134, 139, 142, 166 (see also force);

controlled, 19, 34, 48, 125 (see also control);

and habit, 55;

human, 34, 120;

of love, 183;

mechanical, 142;

nonconservative, 139, 140, 166, 173;

and thought, 39, 53ff., 62, 66, 67;

ultimate end of, 47

Page 522: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

ACTUALITY, 11, 12, 17, 56, 64, 97, 98, 100, 199,200;

and Secondness, 12, 13

ADMIRABLE IN ITSELF (per se), 33, 34, 37, 40, 44n,46, 50, 127, 202, 203n. See also summum bonum

AFFINITY OF MIND TO NATURE, 121, 130, 187

AGAPASM, 180, 182, 183, 185, 187

AGAPASTICISM, 180, 185

AGAPISM, 180

AGGREGATE, POTENTIAL, 194, 196, 198

ANANCASM, 180, 182, 183, 185

ANANCASTICISM, 180

ANANCISM, 180

ANTHROPOMORPHISM, 120, 121, 189n

ARCHITECTONIC, ix, 3, 20, 23, 161n

C

CATEGORIES, x, xii, 4-12, 23, 32, 36, 38n, 42-44,75n, 87, 97n, 104, 113, 127n, 136, 181, 182, 185,186, 199, 200, 209;

Page 523: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and act-potency, 23, 196n;and division of philosophy, 18-22;

and evolution, 180-189;

genuine degenerate grades, 16;

interdependence of, 14-18, 91, 94;

and normative science, 8-24, 94;

transcendental and predicamental, 38n. See alsoFirstness, Secondness, and Thirdness

CAUSATION, 138, 139, 170;

efficient, 112-117, 119, 128, 132, 136, 184;

final, 55, 63n, 112-121, 126, 128, 132, 136, 140,142, 184, 190

CHANCE, 84, 103, 104, 106, 134-136, 140-145,152, 157, 164, 166, 167, 174, 179, 185, 186, 188,190, 198;

absolute, 135, 136, 141, 161, 162, 165, 166, 168,170, 198. See also spontaneity

CLASSES, NATURAL OR REAL, 116, 117, 125

''COCKSURENESS,'' 57, 177, 184, 192n

"COMMON NATURE" (natura communis), 80, 81, 93

Page 524: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

COMMUNITY OF INQUIRERS, 63, 184, 185, 187,191, 202

COMPULSION, 16, 17, 25, 27, 28, 72, 102, 108,112, 113, 196

CONDITIONALS, 57, 58, 64, 66, 82, 94, 96-98, 101,102, 108, 109, 207-209

CONDUCT, 4n, 5n, 6n, 19, 20, 25, 26, 30, 32, 34,38n, 39, 40, 48, 50, 58, 59, 61, 64, 65, 66, 89, 102,120-124, 126, 128, 129, 134n, 203;

habits of, 127;

ideals of, 121, 122, 124, 202, 203;

rules of, 122

CONSCIOUSNESS, 6, 12, 13, 30, 43, 55n, 100n,104, 112, 118, 119n, 123, 125, 129-136, 153, 165,169;

direct, 129, 131;

grades of, 145;

physiological basis of, 131;

reflexive, 129, 131;

rudimentary, 140, 145;

Page 525: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

three degrees of, 131CONSEQUENCES, 59, 97, 99, 121, 136n, 164, 209

CONSISTENCY OF PEIRCE'S PHILOSOPHY, viii-ix, 24,34ff., 87

Page 526: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 226

CONTINUITY, 29, 30, 65, 66, 71, 73, 74, 87, 90, 91,100, 120, 132, 146, 161, 184, 185, 187, 192, 193

CONTROL, 41, 45, 47, 48, 49, 51, 119n, 121n, 125-130, 134n, 156, 202;

problem in Peirce's analysis of normative science,34ff.

CREATION, 4n, 64, 119n, 202, 203

CRITICISM, 41, 45, 47, 49, 51, 120, 128, 130, 153,161;

and critical review, 123-127

D

DARWINISM, 151, 171-177, 181, 183

DEDUCTION, 23, 145, 156, 156n

DESTINY, 97n, 100, 104, 105, 107, 126

DETERMINISM, 25, 83, 161;

absolute, 104, 133, 139, 146, 155, 174, 201;

mechanistic, 145, 151;

Peirce's refutation of, 155-165

Page 527: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

DISSOCIATION, 9, 14DISTINCTION, 9, 14, 15;

formal, 81, 83;

Peirce's theory of, 9

E

ENDS, viii, 5, 6, 25, 34, 36, 50, 54, 59, 64, 118;

science of, see ethics;

in themselves, see summum bonum

ESTHETICS, vii, viii, 3, 4, 9, 19-21, 27, 31-42, 47-51,71, 127, 187

ETHICS, vii, viii, 3, 4, 9, 19, 20, 27, 31-42, 52, 119,127, 174, 177n, 187

EVOLUTION, xi n, xii, 65, 107, 126, 132, 134, 145,146, 168n, 169, 171, 177, 179, 181-189, 191, 193,197, 200-202;

agapastic, 180, 186;

anancastic, 180, 185, 186;

cataclysmal, 177, 178, 183, 184;

and categories, 180-189;

doctrines of, 179;

Page 528: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

elements of, 179;

logic of, 196;

modes of, 178, 179, 185, 186;

tychastic, 180, 185, 186

"EVOLUTIONARY LOVE," xii, 171-190

EVOLUTIONISM, 147, 151, 179, 188

EXISTENCE, 15, 17, 63, 64, 92, 93, 95, 199

EXPERIENCE, vii, 8, 11, 12, 14, 20, 22, 23, 25, 33,42, 43, 51, 63-65, 72, 73, 74n, 79, 88, 93-95, 97n,99, 102, 106-109, 119-129, 154, 156-159, 161,164, 184, 192, 193n, 197, 203, 207-209

EXPLANATION, 140, 144, 147, 161-169, 175n, 184,186, 198, 203n, 209;

logic of, 141, 161-169, 193;

in strict sense, 162

F

FALLIBILISM, 57, 160, 177, 185, 192n

FEELING, 19, 27, 28, 42, 43, 66, 95, 123, 131,132n, 135, 136n, 170;

Firstness of, 13;

Page 529: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

habits of, 20, 51, 127, 202;

of pleasure, 118;

quality of, 19-21, 42, 43, 50, 95, 118, 127n

FINALITY see causation

FIRST, 14, 15, 17, 42

FIRSTNESS, 11-16, 20, 29, 33, 42, 44, 66, 87, 91-94, 99n, 100, 101, 108, 127n, 136n, 165, 182, 186,197, 199, 200;

of feeling, 13;

of Firstness, 17;

of normative science, 21;

of philosophy, 18, 20;

of Secondness, 17, 93;

of spontaneity, 135;

of Thirdness, 17. See also possibility, potentiality

FORCE, 186, 190, 201;

centrifugal, 136, 137;

conservative, 138, 139, 142, 143, 144;

nonconservative, 143, 144, 174

Page 530: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

FORM, 128, 129, 200

FUTURE, 6n, 12, 13, 61, 64, 84, 85, 87, 91, 93, 96-98, 100-103, 106, 122, 123, 139, 165, 189, 201,209

G

GENERALS, 6, 12, 13, 54, 55, 61-65, 74, 76n, 80,87, 107, 155, 208, 209. See also ideas, realism

GENERALITY, 17, 20, 65, 73, 74, 79, 87, 89n, 90-101, 133, 146, 168, 192, 193, 210;

and mediation, 89;

negative, 96-100;

positive, 96-100;

refers to future, 91

GOD, 4n, 67, 125, 135n, 168, 169, 188, 189n, 200,202, 203n

GOODNESS, 29, 30, 38, 39, 40, 41, 44, 49;

esthetic, 29, 37, 46;

kinds of, 44;

logical, 29;

moral, 29;

Page 531: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

negative, 29;

onthological, 38n, 46;

and reasonableness, 38;

and truth, 38

Page 532: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 227

H

HABIT, xii, 50, 55, 64, 104, 121n, 122, 125-130,132-136, 138, 142, 179, 182, 184, 185, 188, 190,193, 209, 210;

acquired, 126;

of conduct, 127;

of feeling, 20, 50, 51, 127, 202;

and law, 83, 136n;

law of, 141, 168, 190;

of thought, 127

haecceity, 81, 83, 88, 108, 109

HEDONISM, 40n, 42-44, 119, 127n

HYPOTHESIS, 23, 72, 76, 106, 120, 130, 138, 140n,145, 146, 156, 157, 158n, 161, 164-171, 175n, 176,177, 183, 189n, 192, 193n, 201, 203n, 209

I

IDEA, 4n, 53, 109-112, 115, 119, 136n, 186, 187,199;

innate, 121, 130;

Page 533: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

separability of, 9, 14

IDEAL, viii, 25, 32, 33, 36, 37, 46-51, 63, 67, 119,121-124, 126, 134, 175n, 203;

of conduct, 121, 124, 202, 203;

esthetic, 45, 47;

evolutionary, 202;

in itself, 40

IDEALISM, xii, 13, 66, 77, 83, 84, 132, 133, 147

INDETERMINACY, 89n, 160, 193, 195, 198, 199

INDETERMINATENESS, 90, 91

INDIVIDUATION, 81n, 82

INDUCTION, 86, 97, 103, 155-159

INFERENCE, 45, 118, 138, 155, 157, 158, 169, 197;

abductive, 145;

ampliative and explicative, 154n, 156;

deductive, see deduction;

hypothetic, 199;

inductive, 4n, 106, 121, see also induction

Page 534: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

INQUIRY, xi, 26, 79, 124, 177n;and experience, 72, 73;

roadblock to, 72, 86, 138, 145, 146, 153, 165,169

INTERPRETANT, 209, 210;

final logical, 53, 89n;

three classes of, 209

K

KALOS, 33, 45

L

LAMARCKISM, 177, 182

LAW, viii, 4n, 5n, 6, 11-13, 17, 55, 58, 72-74, 77-80,82-84, 86, 87, 89-91, 93-96, 98-103, 105-111, 114,115n, 117-119, 121, 122, 134, 136, 138, 141, 144,145, 151, 153, 154n, 155, 161, 165, 168, 182, 184,186, 188, 190, 192, 196, 199, 200, 207, 208;

as actual compulsion, 17;

and chance, 185;

of conservation of energy, 140, 167;

conservative, 134;

Page 535: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of dynamics, 139, 140, 144n, 167, 190;and explanation, 163-165;

formal, 103-106, 142, 144, 167n;

and habit, 83, 136n;

of habit, 141, 168, 190;

material, 103, 104, 106, 142, 167n, 201;

mechanical, 141, 153;

of mechanics, 139, 153;

of mind, 133, 134, 141, 182, 190, 198, 201;

of nature, 127, 134, 136n, 160, 175, 193, 198;

physical, 136, 173;

potentiality, 96-98;

as Thirdness, 87 ff.

LOGIC, vii, viii, xi, 3, 4, 6n, 9, 14, 19, 21, 22, 27-33,34, 35, 36, 39-42, 45, 52, 59n, 64, 71, 72n, 75,103, 106, 107, 118, 119n, 127, 129, 131, 145, 146,168, 169, 171, 172, 175, 187, 191, 193, 197, 199,207, 208;

division of, 21, 22;

docens, 40n;

Page 536: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of evolution, 196;

of explanation, 141, 193;

and metaphysics, 77, 78, 84;

of relatives, 14, 65, 82;

utens, 40n, 41, 156

M

MATERIALISM, 133, 153

MATHEMATICS, 22, 23, 90, 131, 154, 191, 207

MATTER, 15, 126, 132, 134, 135, 170, 188, 190;

and mind, 83, 84, 133;

prime, 196

"MAY-BE'S," 90n, 95, 98n, 109

MEANING, 4n, 5, 6n, 7, 12, 17, 21, 32, 33, 39, 53,56-62, 65, 67, 77, 90, 98, 116, 209, 211

MECHANISM, 135, 173, 174, 182, 184

MEDIATION, 87, 89, 91, 93, 107, 109, 165, 193.See also Thirdness

METAPHYSICS, ix, xi n, 8, 10, 19, 20, 24n, 57, 74n,86, 154, 172n, 175n, 189n, 192, 196n;

Page 537: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

and logic, 74, 75, 77, 78, 84;

Peirce's description of, 75n

Page 538: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

Page 228

MIND, 42, 65, 83, 118-120, 126, 130n, 131, 132,134, 136, 146, 170, 183, 185, 187, 188, 200, 201;

causation of, 117;

instinctive, 129, 130;

law of, 133, 134, 142, 182, 190, 198, 200;

and matter, 83, 84, 123

MODES OF BEING, xii, 6, 11, 12, 16, 79, 87, 93,97n, 98, 99, 101, 118, 199, 203n

MONISM, 83, 133, 144

N

NATURE, 4n, 64, 65, 124, 125, 126, 130, 137, 163,202;

common, 80, 81, 93

NECESSITARIANISM, 153, 154n, 159, 161, 162,165, 172, 175, 185

NOMINALISM, 12, 62, 75-85, 116

NORMATIVE SCIENCE, vii, viii, xi, 3-9, 18-20, 25, 26,30, 34, 36, 39, 40, 48, 52, 71, 125, 127, 128, 187,191, 207;

Page 539: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

analysis of, 25-49;and categories, 8-24, 94;

division of, 8, 20, 31-36;

interrelation of, 31ff.;

modern errors concerning, 29-31;

and phenomenology, 9, 10;

and pragmatism, 8, 9, 52-67

NORMS, 19, 25, 32, 33, 37, 38n, 45, 49, 126-128,202, 203, 208

NOTHINGNESS, 189, 190;

two sorts of, 190, 195

P

PAIN, 42, 43, 119n

PHENOMENOLOGY, 8, 9n, 11, 14, 19, 20, 31;

division of, 18;

and normative science, 9, 10;

Peirce's description of, 10

PHILOSOPHY, ix, 8, 18, 20, 23;

division of, 8, 18, 20, 132;

Page 540: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

of greed, 175, 176;

mechanical, 151, 153, 157n, 167, 173-175;

unity of Peirce's, vii. See also consistency

PLEASURE, 33, 43, 44, 53, 119n;

feeling of, 118;

and pain, 42, 43;

as a Third, 43

POSSIBILITY, 1, 12, 13, 15, 17, 23, 87, 90n, 91-93,97, 98, 101, 106, 196, 197, 199, 201

POTENTIALITY, 58, 91-101, 104, 106, 110, 117,118, 121n, 122, 127, 129, 138n, 146, 197-201;

and law, 96ff.

PRACTICS, 20, 21, 31, 49, 71, 187. See also ethics

PRAGMATIC MAXIM, x, xi, 5, 7, 39, 52-54, 57, 58,60, 64, 66, 71, 72, 76, 116, 117, 146, 167, 176, 210

PRAGMATICISM, 3, 58, 59, 60, 62, 63, 65, 66, 71,76n, 86

PRAGMATISM, viii, x, xi, xii, 3, 5, 6, 8, 39, 56, 57,58, 71, 72n, 76, 102, 116, 130n, 145, 151, 202;

and normative science, 8, 9, 52-67

Page 541: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

"PRESCISSION," 9, 14-16

PREDICTION, 4n, 12, 61, 84, 85, 99, 111, 122, 163,176

PRE-NORMATIVE, 35-38, 45

PROBABILITY, 103, 104, 106, 107, 135, 141, 142,157n, 164, 166, 173, 174, 175, 197, 198

PSYCHOLOGY, 27, 28, 41, 42, 207

PURPORT, 58, 60-62, 65, 66, 116, 209 See alsomeaning

PURPOSE, 4n, 5, 25, 35, 36, 39, 55, 59, 60, 61, 64,66, 112, 117, 120, 125, 126, 128

Q

QUALITY, 9, 15-17, 29, 30, 37, 46, 88, 91-96, 100n,107, 108, 109, 199;

esthetic, 43n, 46, 47, 49, 121;

of feeling, 19, 20, 21, 42, 43, 50, 95, 118, 127n;

in itself, 15, 93, 94, 95, 99n, 100;

as reflected upon, 94, 95

R

Page 542: Charles S. Peirce. On Norms and Ideals...paragraph of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. I-VI, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press

REALISM, viii, x, xi n, xii, 6, 62-64, 76-86, 126n, 147,167, 192n

REALITY, viii, 23, 63, 65, 73, 79, 82, 83n, 91, 138,191, 203n, 208

REASONABLENESS, 17, 19, 38, 43n, 44n, 53, 54, 64,74, 75, 102, 104, 107, 127n, 186, 190, 201, 202.See also summum bonum

RELATION, 29, 117, 199;

dyadic, 15, 19, 26;

triadic, 13, 14, 17, 65

RULES, 12, 25, 55, 72n, 85, 89, 118, 122, 124-128,190, 207, 208