16
". building designing thinking STANFORD ANDERSON THINKING IN ARCHITECTURE A bbe Laugier's claim that "in those arts which are not purely mechanical it is not sufficient to know how to work; it is above all important to learn to think" But how should one think about architecture, or rather, think in architecture? Is there a specific architectural way of thinking? .., Can a design be a form of thinking? Or does it all boil down to subjective taste? "Not subjective taste!" - we had better say, if we think there is a discipline of architecture, a profession of architecture; if we can honourably have schools of architecture or be professors or crtucs of architecture. Abbe Laugier put his question with reference to "arts which are not purely mechanical," among which he counted architecture. The obverse of that characterisation is, then, that these arts are also 'mechanical.' Architecture does have to answer to many instrumental demands of function and making. It is not surprising then, nor wrong, that much thought in architecture is addressed to instrumentalities. Nor is it surprising that we have had programmes called "functionalism," claiming not only to address the necessary instrumentalities of architecture, but also to be theoretically adequate. In later discussions of the theory of architecture, functionalism is generally rejected; but functionalism remains a default position in much of architectural practice, and even in pedagogy. Is there a specific, architectural way of thinking? I think there is a logically necessary condition if that question is to be answered. If we are to think, to design, to build architecturally, then these activities cannot simply be reduced to information supplied by other diectplines, as [unctionalism at least appeared to do. ALVAR AALTO worked at a time when there were architects of consequence who strongly advocated the theory and practice of Functionalism. Aalto did not buy into a narrow functionalism. Repeatedly he made the case for a deeper functionalism that would give adequate ptah.08 THINKING I N ARCHITECTURE Stanford Anduson is a registered architect and Professor of HIstory and Architecture in the Department of Architecture at the Massachusetts Institute Df Technology, Cambridge, MaSsachusetts, where he has taught since 1963 Hew-founded and directed MIT's pioneering PhD program In History, Theory and Criticism of Ar~ Archite(;ture, and Urban Form from 1974 to 1991 He served as Head of the Department of Architecture from 1991 to 1005. Anderson was educated in architecture at the Universities of Minnesota and California, and holdsa PhD in historyof art from Columbia University in New York City He was the 2004 AlAI ACSA Topaz laureate, the highest American award in arctutecturat education. Anderson's research and writing concern architectural theory, modern architecture in Europe and America, American urbenbmand epistemology and historiography Anderson translated and wrote the lruroduc- tory essay for Hermann Muthesius: Style-Architecture and BUilding-Art: Transformations of Architecture in the Nineteenth Century and its Present Condition (Santa Monica, CAThe reuycemer, 1~1. He is the authorof Peter eenrens.x New Architecture for the Twentieth Century lcambridge, MAThe MIT Press, <000; ltal ian ed non Milan Electa, 1002) He is the entrepreneur and editor of On Streets (MIT Press, 1978)and Eladiu Dieste: Innovation in Structural Art (New vork Princeton Ar(;h,tectural Press, 1004). His MIT traveling exhibition on meste has been seen in North and South Amenca.and a European edition opened in Rome in April <007 He is now co-eomng a volume titled Alvar Aaltoand emerfca.ccrreruresearcj is on mid-rise mghdenstty housing, conducted with coueagoes ar Tongji University in Shanghai ~ Aloar Aalto. v,ll" Mairea Chimney detail

building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    5

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

". buildingdesigning

thinking

STANFORD ANDERSON

THINKING IN ARCHITECTURE

Abbe Laugier's claim that "in those arts which are not purely mechanicalit is not sufficient to know how to work; it is above all important to learnto think" But how should one think about architecture, or rather, think in

architecture? Is there a specific architectural way of thinking? .., Can a design be aform of thinking? Or does it all boil down to subjective taste?

"Not subjective taste!" - we had better say, if we think there is a disciplineof architecture, a profession of architecture; if we can honourably haveschools of architecture or be professors or crtucs of architecture.

Abbe Laugier put his question with reference to "arts which are notpurely mechanical," among which he counted architecture. The obverseof that characterisation is, then, that these arts are also 'mechanical.'Architecture does have to answer to many instrumental demands offunction and making. It is not surprising then, nor wrong, that muchthought in architecture is addressed to instrumentalities. Nor is itsurprising that we have had programmes called "functionalism,"claiming not only to address the necessary instrumentalities ofarchitecture, but also to be theoretically adequate. In later discussionsof the theory of architecture, functionalism is generally rejected; butfunctionalism remains a default position in much of architecturalpractice, and even in pedagogy.

Is there a specific, architectural way of thinking? I think there is alogically necessary condition if that question is to be answered.

If we are to think, to design, to build architecturally, then these activitiescannot simply be reduced to information supplied by other diectplines, as[unctionalism at least appeared to do.

ALVAR AALTO worked at a time when there were architects ofconsequence who strongly advocated the theory and practice ofFunctionalism. Aalto did not buy into a narrow functionalism. Repeatedlyhe made the case for a deeper functionalism that would give adequate

ptah.08THINKING IN ARCHITECTURE

Stanford Anduson is a registeredarchitect and Professor ofHIstory and Architecture in theDepartment of Architecture atthe Massachusetts InstituteDf Technology, Cambridge,MaSsachusetts, where he hastaught since 1963 Hew-foundedand directed MIT's pioneering PhDprogram In History, Theory andCriticism of Ar~ Archite(;ture, andUrban Form from 1974 to 1991 Heserved as Head of the Departmentof Architecture from 1991 to1005. Anderson was educated inarchitecture at the Universitiesof Minnesota and California,and holdsa PhD in historyof artfrom Columbia University in NewYork City He was the 2004 AlAIACSA Topaz laureate, the highestAmerican award in arctutecturateducation. Anderson's researchand writing concern architecturaltheory, modern architecture inEurope and America, Americanurbenbmand epistemologyand historiography Andersontranslated and wrote the lruroduc-tory essay for Hermann Muthesius:Style-Architecture and BUilding-Art:Transformations of Architecturein the Nineteenth Century and itsPresent Condition (Santa Monica,CAThe reuycemer, 1~1. He isthe authorof Peter eenrens.x NewArchitecture for the TwentiethCentury lcambridge, MATheMIT Press, <000; ltal ian ed nonMilan Electa, 1002) He is theentrepreneur and editor of OnStreets (MIT Press, 1978)and EladiuDieste: Innovation in Structural Art(New vork Princeton Ar(;h,tecturalPress, 1004). His MIT travelingexhibition on meste has been seenin North and South Amenca.and aEuropean edition opened in Romein April <007 He is now co-eomnga volume titled Alvar Aaltoandemerfca.ccrreruresearcj is onmid-rise mghdenstty housing,conducted with coueagoes arTongji University in Shanghai

~ Aloar Aalto. v,ll" MaireaChimney detail

Page 2: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world
Page 3: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

.,; buildingdesigning

thinking

" Claude-Nicolas Ledoux. City ofel1"U'. First and Nnal schemes

attention to the humanistic dimensions of architecture. But would thatsimply yield a functionalism that considers more variables, proposed bymore disciplines? Psychology and sociology would join anthropometriesand Taylorism and materials science and structural and mechanicalengineering? These additional variables might enhance the performanceof functionalism, but architecture would remain a mechanical techniquefor the agglomeration of information from other disciplines.

If Aalta's advocacy of a more informed functionalism does not answerto the problem of architectural thinking, are we merely left with the viewthat architectural design possesses a certain je ne sais quai, as in thisfamous detail from the Villa Mairea, that leads us to set some architectsor buildings apart from the norms of professional practice?Idon't want to settle for architecture _ or for an interpretation of

Aalto's work - as either merely a more sensitive functionalism or aprogramme for the sophisticated design of details of elusive significance.Further, despite the way it sounds, Idon't want completely to reject eitherfunctionalism or the je ne sots quoLl Nonetheless, these are not the routesby which to address the question of what it is to think architecturally.

In this article, Iwill review earlier attempts to discover anarchitectural way of thinking through the concept of architecturalautonomy. Not satisfied with these proposals for autonomy, but stillseeking to "think in architecture," Iwill give renewed attention to mynotion of "quasi-autonomy."

Thlnkin. architecturally: Autonomy with Emil Kaufmann's Ledoux What isit to think architecturally? The question is not new. We are led back toattempts to claim, and then discern, the autonomy of architecture. Theconcept of autonomy in architecture has been proposed from differentpositions that I will sample here. At the outset, we can take 'architecturalautonomy' to be a proposition that in some way recognises 'a specificarchitectural way of thinking', and traces the constitution of that way ofthinking within the discipline of architecture itself.

One of the most noted of such endeavours was by the historianEMILKAUFMANNin the early 1930s, in the time of high modernism.Kaufmann was an advocate of LECORBUSIER,but his theoretical position

ptah ...THINKING IN ARCHITECTURE

Page 4: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

relied on French architecture ofthe late 18'h century. There he found theorigins and nature of autonomy in architecture.'

The architect CLAUDENtCOLASLEDOUXis Kaufmann's key figure.Ledoux embodied in his life and work a crucial change that Kaufmannsees as epochal for society and its cultural forms. Ledoux's key workis the royal saltworks at Chaux, conceived as an ideal city. Kaufmanninterpreted Ledoux's first project for Chaux as a hierarchical, compact,and strictly organised design. These traits he perceived as counterpartsto an earlier, then receding, authoritarian political and culturalorganisation that Kaufmann subsumed under the term 'baroque'.

In contrast, the final, only partially realised, scheme for Chaux,although clearly ordered, exemplified an unprecedented openness withindividual buildings conceived quite differently from one anotherdepending on their intended use. This form of organisation Kaufmanntermed the "pavilion system" and traced it in works of the late 18'hcentury by Ledoux and other architects whom he collectively termed'Revolutionary Architects'.

These architects worked almost wholly before the French revolution,so the 'revolution' of the 'Revolutionary Architects' was a revolutionthat had been underway for some time and reached beyond France - therevolution of the Enlightenment. Kaufmann cited especially JEAN-JACQUESROUSSEAU'Sconcerns for the rights of the individual, drawinga rather literal connection between an emphasis on individual rights andthe conceptual opening and particularity of arch itecture ordered within

the pavilion system.Kaufmann conflates at least two concepts of autonomy. There is a

'conceptual autonomy' as just referenced: an intellectual and politicalshift from a traditional, hierarchical society to the origins of modernsociety with relative autonomy in thought and action. Formally, theauthoritarian baroque society displayed itself in hierarchical spatialorganisations, intended for perspectival viewing from an idealisedposition. With this concern for a hierarchical image, architectural formcould be twisted and ornamented till both individuality and materiallogic were subverted to the holistic image. In contrast, Ledoux designed

THINKING IN ARCHITECTUREptah.OB

buildingdesigning

thinking

'J Fran,oisMansart. cMleau d.Maison"16;1-5).

'n

Page 5: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

IIIi:1

:1",:,

ilI

buildingdesigning

thinking

• £\"nn.·Lou" 80ull;eCenotaph of Newton

his dispersed pavilions according to particular programmes andsensibilities.

As concerns materiality, Kaufmann argued that Ledoux's severesurfaces, in planes or geometrical forms, allowed the realisation ofLedoux's own claim that "stone could again be stone," There is anarchitectural autonomy that is to be found in the proper use of materialsand constructional logic. In Kaufmann, there is also an autonomy, or anautonomy conflated with the material claims, based on function.

ETIENNE BOlJLLEE is a notable figure among Kaufmann's'Revolutionary Architects', and here we may sense that sheer scale,as much as simple forms, contributed to the claim for architecturalautonomy in this body of work.

Kaufmann's long essay appeared in a volume of works by colleaguesin the so-cal lad 'new Viennese School of art history'. In a review of thisViennese work, the noted New York scholar MEYER SCHAPIRO criticisedthe group's reliance on the concept of autonomy in the arts ~ being soblunt as to say that one of the articles, as others in the collection, "suffersfrom the dogma of autonomous principles." 3 Consequently, it comes assomething of a surprise that Schapiro found Kaufmann's essay to be"excellent." Admittedly there could be an underlying sympathy betweenSchapiro's left politics and Kaufmann's claims for the individual vsauthority. Yet it comes as a surprise that Schapiro seems readily to buyinto Kaufmann's finding that "the essential contribution of Ledoux is hisdiscovery of an autonomous principle of architecture." Kaufmann furthercharacterises this autonomy as deriving "its aesthetic from the internaldemands of construction and use, and is independent of any foreign,imposed artistic conception:' Toward the end of his review article,Schapiro again becomes critical of claims for autonomy, relating it "tothat idea of a 'pure art' which arises constantly among artists" to justifythe "absolute independence of their activity as artists:'

ptah.OBnfIN~ING IN ARCHITECTURE

Page 6: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

Schapiro concludes this thought with a remarkable passage that soundsas ifhe anticipated the early work of PETER EISENMAN. Here is Schapiro,in 1933, thirty years before Eisenman's House I;

They [the self-justifying artists} know only the 'laws of art,' and submit tono others. In the name of a similar purity, an architectural aesthete mightdeduce an crt which conceals or suppresses the tectonic, constructiveelements as non-artistic, and which constructs independently of thesefactors its own effects of mass and space and light.4

Almost surely Eisenman has read Kaufmann and the review essay ofSchapiro. In any case, Eisenman notably resumes the quest for autonomyin architecture.

Thinking architecturally: Autonomy with Peter Eisenman's Le Corbusler IfKaufmann relied on Rousseau and individual liberty, Eisenman relied onIMMANUEL KANT, as read (not uniquely) by the noted New York formalistart critic CLEMENT GREENBERG. Greenberg relied on his interpretationof metacriticism in Kant to formulate his own position that what setsmodern art apart is its exploration of its own production. Claiming Kantas the first modernist, Greenberg made self-referentiality the central tenetof modernism, most clearly demonstreted in New York painting of thepost-war yeers.t

Eisenman's early work, his 'Cardboard Architecture' houses, madecommitments remarkably similar to what Schapiro had anticipated: "anart which conceals or suppresses the tectonic, constructive elements asnon-artistic, and which constructs independently of these factors its owneffects of mass and space and light:'

Eisenman's cardboard architecture already involved the ambition tobring modernist self-referentiality to architecture, and thus claim for

THINKING IN ARCHITECTUREptah.OB

buildingdesigning

thinking

• Peter Eisenman. Cardboardar(h;tectur. House VI

... Peter Eisenman, House IV,

detail

'"

Page 7: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

buildingdesigning

thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world of New York andbeyond,

In 1979,in his journal Oppositions, Eisenman sought an earlyprecedent for 'self-referential' architecture in the modern movement-

and thus to give his thesis of self-referentiality a firmer theoretical base,6In his essay, titled Aspects of Modernism: Maison Dam-ina and the

Self-Referential Sign, Eisenman made a new claim for the significance ofthe Maison Dam-ina. He proposed a theoretical interpretation internalto the Dom-ino image itself. In so doing, he sets aside the reigninginterpretation ofthat work, stemming largely from the writings of hismentor COLIN ROWE. Eisenman sees Rowe's claim for the innovativemodernity of the Maison Dam-ina, revealed fully in Le Corbu sier's greatvillas of the late 1920s, as marking no more than one more instance ofhistorical change in an established mode of representation.

Rather than establishing a historical continuity, as Eisenman foundin Rowe, Eisenman recognises features of the Maison Dom-ino that heposes as a radical break with tradition. Relying solely on the famedperspective drawing of the Maison Dam-ina, Eisenman enters upon aclose description entailing such observations as the different lengths,A and S, of the slabs, the alignment ofthe slabs and the equal spacingof their vertical stacking. The possibility of many variations of thosefactors is noted, and also that such variations entail little more thangeometrical distinctions. However, in Le Corbusier's project drawing,Eisenman notes, these features are what they are; Eisenman's respectfor Le Corbusier and the renown of the Maison Dom-ina diagram is suchthat he unquestioniogly makes the assumption that there must be formalintentionality in the given configuration ofthe Maison Dom-ino.

What then is that intentionality? Eisenman finds it to be cruciallyrevealed in the relation of the columns to the slabs. The columns areset back from the long side of the slabs, but are close to the edge of thenarrow ends of the slabs. Here Iquote Eisenman: [As the difference,A versus S, of] "the column locations acts to reinforce the originalgeometric A B relationship which in itself is so clear as not to needreinforcement [Eisenman's emphasis], one interprets this as an intentionto underscore a condition of being, that is as a significant redundancy .... The redundancy ofthe mark thereby signals that there is somethingpresent other than either the geometry or the function of the column andslab."?

Eisenman concludes: "Thus, the fact itself - the slab _ plus the spatialmarking - the location of the columns _ suggest an idea about sides Aand 8 which is an idea only about itself, a self-referential statement. Thisthen may be a primitive though truly Modernist phenomenon, one thatspeaks about its mere existence and its own condition of being.v''

Self-referentiality as a "truly Modernist phenomenon" was not,of course, a new idea. Aside from its appearance in innovative art,including cinematography, from the late nineteenth century onward, ithad also been theorised. As noted, the major art theorist of mid-twentieth~entury New York,Clement Greenberg, built his theory, criticism, andIlldeed his history on the concept. Greenberg was directly influential

ptah.OBTHINKING IN ARCHITECTURE

Page 8: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

bUildin~ 0",

designinthinking

00•

~----

• ~

$•

on the circles in which Eisenman moved, though that influence wasthen on the wane. Eisenman notes that architecture bad been slow toadopt a modernist stance, though here he finds early intimations in theMaison Dom-ina. In his theoretical essay, as in his 'cardboard' houses,Eisenman seeks a self-referential autonomy that relies heavily on theatectonic emphasis OIl redundancy and the gratuitous introduction ofonly seemingly tectonic elements.

With Rowe, Eisenman, and others, I share in the conviction of theimportance of the Maison Dom-ino. I see it as a major contribution towhat I term the quasi-autonomy of architecture - a claim that will needdevelopment following some other remarks on autonomy.

We might say that Eisenman sought autonomy through negationof Building, negation of functional and material conditions. Thedistinctiveness of architecture, its autonomy, lay in self-referentialityembedded in abstract systems of markings and relationships. Hisrejection of the material conditions of architecture is explicit.

Emil Kaufmann had seen the autonomy of his Revolutionary architectsas establishing a new tradition. Despite the interval of the nineteenthcentury, with its many competing architectural positions, Kaufmann,looking to his own time, was strongly attracted to the work of LeCorbusier as a brilliant manifestation of that tradition.

With Eisenman looking back to the early period of Le Corbusier asthe root of his still more abstract position, we have a proposition of atradition of architectural autonomy established in the late eighteenth

THINKING IN ARCHITECTUREptoh.08

l> Ledoux - Le corbusier- Eisen·man,

" IOrawingslMaiSon Dom·lno,Eisenman's analytic diagramsof LeCorbosier'S Malson Oom-ino, relations of columns 10sides of the slabs, 1979_

Page 9: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

buildingdesigning

thinking century. allegedly rarified and advanced in an early work of Le Corbusier,and finally set out, in theory and practice. by Eisenman.

I am not satisfied with that story and so will return to it. But first Iwanl to touch on the other architect of recent times whose work is closelyassociated with the concept of autonomy: ALDO ROSSI.

Thinking architecturally: Aida Rossi's autonomy through precedentContemporaneously with Eisenman, Aida Rossi too sought autonomyby negation of functional and material conditions. There is, however, agulf between Rossi and Eisenman. Eisenman rejected precedent. Rossi,conversely, sought the autonomy of architecture precisely in the history ofthe discipline, as manifested in the rigours of the architectural disciplineand in the historical city.

Rossi and his circle speak of the craft of architecture - the architect'smetier. With this, the Rossi group comes to their admiration for thework of HEINRICH TESSENOW, We are being returned to a classicaltradition, a stripped classicism that represents a strict discipline withinarchitecture."

Is the notion of autonomy a stalking horse for classicism? With theRossi circle, one might think so. Kaufmann, looking back to eighteenth-century France, may seem to embrace classicism, but one must rememberhis favoured attention to Le Corbusier. Stripped classicism is the world ofthe Rossi group, and no doubt one possible, but not the necessary, end ofthe quest for autonomy in architecture.

Architectural autonomy must neglect "BUilding"? But the big question:Where is the B, where is BUilding, within thought about autonomy inarchitecture?

It was present in Kaufmann, He spoke of autonomy as deriving "itsaesthetic from the internal demands of construction and use, and isindependent of any foreign, imposed artistic conception." Just as he spokeofthe formal and representational autonomy of the pavilion system.

Schapiro wrote with a slightly diffident acceptance of these twoaspects of Kaufmann's autonomy: disciplined affirmation of materialconstraints on the one hand (a position that both Rossi and Eisenmanfind anathema to any claim for autnnomv]: and an abstract, moraland philosophical, idealism on the other. However, I find, neither inKaufmann's writings, nor in Schapiro's commentary, any attempt to domore than juxtapose these two grounds of autonomy.

Once more, Is there a specific architectural way of thinking? Inexploring the attempts to answer this question through the concept ofautonomy, I come to a sense of aridity. With Eisenman a slighting ofprecedent. With the Rossi group, a return to a reduced classicism. Andin both cases, not just a neglect, but a refusal to deal with tectonics, withBuilding. The material conditions of building are seen as inherentlynegaIing architectural thinking.

Thinking architecturally: Quasi-autonomy with Anderson's Le CorbusierSo, where is Building in the search for "a specific architectural way of

ptah.08THINKING IN A.RCHIIECTURE

Page 10: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

thinking"? Le Corbusier's Maison Dam-ina is recurrently a test case inarchitecture, as it was for Eisenman. Let us give it another look.

Unlike Eisenman, I am unwilling to assume that the Maison Dam-inadiagram of 1914 revealed a sophisticated proposition such as self-referentiality. My doubt is borne out through a broader examination ofthe Maison Dam-ina project and its afterlife in Le Corbusier's career.

The Maison Dam-ina project was distinctly pragmatic in its origins; itspremises are more fully revealed by attention to other Dom-ino projectdrawings: plans, detail drawings, and perspectives of possible houses Ihousing based on the project. The project grew out of Le Corbusier'sinterest to develop a system using the relatively new technology of thereinforced concrete frame, calculated to meet the severe housing needsin Flanders, devastated by the locally sustained battles of World War I.Le Corbueier sought to form an industrialised company for production ofthe rationalised frame system that could be deployed and then in-filledlocally. Under the exigencies of the time that infill might includerubble from destroyed buildings, though Le Corbusier also envisionedindustrialised in-fill systems. Attention to structure is integral to theproject, but we will see that Le Corbusier's structural concern is far froma structural determinism.

The reflected ceiling plan of the Maison Dam-ina shows that it did notinvolve 'slabs' in the usual sense of that word as monolithic concretefloors. Rather it is a framework of girders and beams formed by smallrepetitive cement or tile units, destined to have a plaster ceiling. Infillwalls would then have preferred locations on the structural lines. In LeCorbusier's Maison Dam-ina plans, we find no innovative exploitationof structure or space. Whenever possible, columns are buried in walls.Where an interior wall is of lesser dimension than a column, the exposedpart of the column is boxed-in or projected into the less significant space.Neither is structure emphasised nor is planning free from the structure.The cantilevered space beyond the columns on the long sides of thebuilding merely sets the dimensions of insignificant spaces. Where aprincipal room is projected through that space, there is no recognitionof space within or beyond the column line. In brief, examination of theMaison Dam-ina project as a whole reveals nothing of Le Corbusier'sfamous propositions often associated with the Maison Dam-ina, the FivePoints, the free plan. Eisenman's self_referentiality also appears foreign

to the issues at hand.Le Corbusier first published the Maison Dam-ina project in the early

1920s in the journal L'Esprit nouveau, and again in his most importantbook, Vers une Architecture.10 In both these publications, Le Corbusieruses large illustrations of interior and exterior perspectives of individualand collective "moisons 'Domino'." The now famous perspectivaldiagram appears only as a thumbnail reproduction near each afthe largeexterior perspective drawings. It is mentioned as a concrete framework,but the discussion turns on the process of fitting out the house and laying

out an agreeable site.Nonetheless, my purpose is not to be dismissive of the Moisan Dom-ino-

In the past, I have referred to it as a 'non-ccnservattve model' - that is, it

THINKING IN ARCHITECTUREptah.08

buildingdesigning

thinking0",

Page 11: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

". buildingdesigning

thinking

.. L~Corbu,ie'· Stuttgart,Oou ble house at theOeutS(her Werkbund 's

Weissenhur housing

exhi bitioo, 19'1

-

is not a rigid model with a defined, singular purpose. It is a model thatcan be revisited, and has been, with great profit. When Le Co-buster,more than a decade later, in 1926,was designing the Villa Stein and histwo houses for the wetssenhof exhibition in Stuttgart, he introduced hisrenowned "Five Points": pilotis. free plan, roof garden, free facade, andstrip window, a New ground was broken both in building and polemics.Pilatis and the Five Points had not been foreseen in the Maison Dom-ino nor even in the extensive housing design documented in his 1923publications. A potential of the Maison Dam-ina could only be realisedafter concerted (and 'patient'] effort, as manifested at Stuttgart, atGarches, and in the other brilliant villas of the late 1920s. The 'non.conservative' Maison Dam-ina diagram had been revisited till it becamea provocation for the inventive Five Points and the villas.

In 1937,Le Corbusier published his early architectural work, includingthe great villas, in the first volume of his Oeuvre camplete.l' For the firsttime his presentation of the Maison Dam-ina project emphasised not thehousing, villa, or urban designs, but the perspective diagram.

The Five Points were not possible without the innovation ofmodern frame construction, but such technological capacity awaitedthe architectural innovation of Le Corbusier. The Five Points are anarchitectural innovation. We no longer assign to them the imperative

ptah.08THINKING IN ARCHITECTURE

Page 12: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

sense of Le Corbusier circa 1930, but they are a fundamental partof architectural knowledge. In design, it is a conscious, and almostinescapable, act to employ them - or not. Facilitated by, but not partof, structural technology, the Five Points are an important moderncontribution to the discipline of architecture, to the quasi-autonomy ofarchitecture. Or, to return to the question raised in the beginning: "Howone should think in architecture."

I want to return to the matter ofthe 'non-conservative model.' To theextent Eisenman's essay purports (or seems to purport) to be a historicalinquiry, Iargue that he is quite wrong. But if the Maison DOIIJ"inoisa 'non-conservative model: then it is open to new readings, just as LeCorbusier did through his villas of the 1920s. t believe the master didso again with the Carpenter Center at Harvard in 1960. Le Corbusierconducted a long-extended research programme, a programme thatadopted and adjusted increasingly rewarding auxiliary hypotheses, butthat traced back to a common core, the Maison Dom-ino diagram [fig.1)whose capacity was only revealed with concerted effort over nme."

So it is completely appropriate that another architect, still later,should propose yet another way to learn from this model. Conceivably,what Eisenman proposed is an extension of Le Corbusier's research.Alternatively, his new auxiliary hypotheses may be so radical as toreposition the old core and generate a new research programme.

Eisenman's essay can be understood then not as a history, butas a 'rational reconstruction' of what may have been latent in thediagrammatic Maison Dam-ina perspective!" Whether the MaisonDam-ina provoked Eisenman's self-referentiality, or his self-referentialityled him to 'mis-read' the Moisan Dam-ina, there is a new impetusfor the discipline of architecture. To seek such reconstructions is achallenging and potentially fruitful exercise. A rational reconstructioncan elude conventional historical criticism, but it must achieve a logicalconstruction and hopefully one that is both empirically sound andfruitful. Ifind some of the details of Eisenman's argument for a self-referential Maison Dom-ino to be in question. Nonetheless, IapplaudEisenman's effort and where it finally took him (or where Ipresume tosay it took him) in the closing lines of the last quotation: to "anotherprimitive condition for an architecture."

Quasi-autonomy; Aalto, form, and accommodation of circumstance Inthis setung, I do not want to conclude without recognising the architectwhose achievement brings us together. Aalta emphasises other lessons for"thinking in architecture."If one attends carefully to an Aalto building and its details, it is

difficult not to embrace a thought that lance borrowed from Aalto:"the methodical accommodation of circumstance."'s With Aalto.'accommodation' rarely means the submission of one circumstance toanother, but rather the informing presence of contrasting formal moveseach making its own accommodation to varying circumstances. Thereare formal propositions, but accommodation is not forced under someunifying system, whether structural or decorative. The results of such

THINKING INARCKITECTUREptah.08

buildingdesigning

thinking."

Page 13: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

buildingdesigningthinking a method appear throughout Aalto'a work, as I sought to demonstratein my paper for the centennial publication by the Museum of FinnishArchitecture.

Conviction in Aalto's attention to human need. even to its finer effectsin particular circumstances, is only reinforced by differences among hisbuildings. Baker House at MIT won international critical acclaim andpositive reception by its residents from the outset (and so it continues).Yet Aalto did not again create a building with serpentine curves or adramatic hanging stairway. Forms were invented for a purpose, not assomething to be visited upon other circumstances.

Methodical accommodation of circumstance is fundamental to otherarchitects for whom form, building, and use are intrinsic to architecture.If we were to attend to Louis Kahn when he says, "It is the role of designto adjust to the circumstantial," we must remember that Kahn usedthe word "design" to name the process of fulfilling the "form" that wasenvisioned. With Kahn too, accommodation demands reciprocity." Aaltawould not have spoken in the manner of Kahn, but with Aalto, no morethan with Kahn, should we think that concern for the circumstantial wasa matter of minor problem-solving.

For the Finland Pavilion at the 1939 New York World's Fair, Aaltowas given an anonymous box within which to create a representationof Finland. There were no disparate elements to unite. Formally, in theapparent absence of circumstance, or to probe the depths of his attitude,it was necessary to invent the circumstances to be reconciled _ necessaryto invent a form that sets both opportunities and constraints. Withhis minimal, wavy sketch, Aalto constructed the dichotomy and thenworked to harmonise it. Aalto wrote: "architecture is thus a kind ofsuper-technical creation, and the harmonisation of many disparate formsof activity is central to it." I?

We may also invoke Le Corbusier. In his famous analytic drawing ofThe four compositions, he assesses his villa Savoye favourably for itssatisfaction of functional needs (largely invented) in a work formed byarchitectural will."

Formal invention reconciled with circumstances is partially a matter ofpractical considerations, a resolution that satisfies by its accommodationwithout suppression of competing factors. I have argued for its deepersignificance in architectural design. There is, however, a still deepersignificance: an ethical and philosophical commitment and satisfactionin this responsibility to the complexities ofthought and action. SANDY

WILSON probed these concerns and mOVingly observed that as anarchitect, bound by the abstractness of the discipline, "the sale metaphoryou had for dealing with every emotion, frustration or fantasy, fearor joy [and which] owes its emotional charge to its reconciliation ofcontradictory material. It is one of the most marked characteristics ofAalto's work that it so dangerously engages with contradictory elementswhich it yet manages to control." 19

'Methodical accommodation' is not to indicate humble and randomsolVing of small problems. There is a large framework; in everydesign effort there is not only potential, but also conflict among the

ptah.08THI NKI NG IN ARCH IHCTU RE

Page 14: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

form commitments and the multitude of conditions that apply. Somearchitects ruthlessly suppress the difficult but compelling condition.Some allow one to intrude on another. Aalto was exceptional in bringingcircumstances into positive association with one another.

Conclusion By way of summary, I would like to repeat and emphasisemy three examples of 'thinking in architecture" inherently architecturalthought beyond technological potentials, 'rational reconstruction,' andmethodical engagement of form and accommodation,

t am asserting that the Five Points are "a specific architectural wayof thinking." They are a distinctive contribution to the discipline ofarchitecture. They could not have been conceived without the potentialthat lay in modern frame construction, but it took an architecturalinvention, 'an architectural way of thinking,' to change that materialpotential into a new architecture. That surplus in the potential isexemplary of the autonomy of architecture. Yet, materiality is part of thisphenomenon and therefore I prefer to speak of 'quasi-autonomy.'

'Rational reconstruction" is a means of re-visiting and re-inventingpotentials that may lie dormant within the discipline of architecture. Ioffer as an example what Eisenman did theoretically with the MoisonDom-ine. and he would claim to have made effective in his work.

'Methodical accommodation of circumstance,' if in somewhat differentwords, has been both pronounced and practiced by such exceptionalarchitects as Le Corbusier, Aalta and KAHN. This practice requiresformal invention, knowledge of and sensitivity to material conditions,and methodical resolution of their potentials and conflicts. Here toothere is profound probing of both abstraction and materiality - thus, forme, another example of the quasi-autonomy of thinking in architecture,

STANFORD ANDERSON

THINKING IN ARCHITECTUREptah.08

buildingdesigning

thinking

• tcursKahnKtmbeuMuseumand Salk In,titute

... routs Kahn: Rochester, NY.unitarian Church.

Page 15: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world

buildingdesigning

thinking Stanford Andersoo,"l'icfion of Function,"A .. embloge 2 (February 19871. pp. 18_31.

2 Emil Kaufmann, "Die Stndt des ArcMtektenLedoux: Zur Erkenntni< der aUMnamefl

A,chitektur," KunSlwisseIl.<chaftlicheFOfschungefl, J[ (1931), 131-160: Von

Ledoux bis to Corba.ier. Ursprung undEn/wick/ang der aulanomen Arch/rekta{Vienna and Leipzig: Holf Pas.er, lIJJJ;ropeint, Stu!lgarr: Hatin, 1965}; Thre"Revo!utlol1o,y Architects: Boalle", Ledoux.and Lequeu (PhUndnJphin. PA: AmericanPhilosophical Society. 1952); Architectu,ein fhe Age of Reason. Buroque and POSf-

Baroque in England, Italy, France (195.,]

(New York: Dover, 1968).3 Meyer Sohapiro. "The New Viennese

School," Art Bulle/in. XV/lJ (1936), PI'2511_266.

4 Schapiro. p. 2665 Ciement Grnenberg, Art and Cuhure'

Critical Essays (Boston: Beacon Press.196/): a .rudy of Greenberg and histhought: Caroline lones. Eyesighl Aione,Clement Greenberg's Modernism and lhoBureaucratization of the Senses (Chicago:University of Chicago Press, 2005).

6 Peler Eisenman. "Aspects of Modernism:Maison Dam-ina ond tho Solf-ReferenlialSign," OpposWons 15!l6{WinlerISpring1979). 118_128: reprinted pp, 188-198 inK, Michael Hays, ed .. Oppo.ilions Reader(New York: Princeton Arrhitecruroi Pro«,1998).

7 idem .. p. 1948 ibid.

9 Giorgio Grass;, La costruzione logicadeJJa architeltura (Padaa: MarsWo. 1967):L'orchiletlum COme mesUere e altri scrilli(Milan: Franco Aogoli. 1980),

W Le Corbusier_Saugnier. "Maisons en '''rie,''L'Espra nouveau, 13 {undared. Co, 1922-23},{15251_1542:Le Corbusier, Vers unoarctvitecture (Paris: Vincent, Freai. 1923),pp, 189_224.

11 ILe Corbusier], "Colendrier d'orchitecturo"in his Almonach d'architecture moderne{Paris: G. Cres. 19261.Here. Le Corbu.iormake. on e~tended presontarion Withinwhich, with hind,ight, one Can discernlhe Five Points. The Fivo POints am.howel-.r. stated succincrly, as poinls.in two publications o.. ociated wUh theW.issenhof exhibition: Le Corbusierand Pierre Jefmnerel. "Funf Punkte woiner neuon Archilektur," in DeutscherlVerkbund. Bou und IVohnung: Die Bauteader Wei.. enhofsiedlung (Stuttgart: F.

Wedekind. ln7), pp, 27-28; and inAifred ROlh. Zwei Wahnh""ser VOnLe Corbusier und Pierre 'oallneret(StWlgan: 1', Wedekind. t927). In "Ouen est J'archi/ecture?", illrchUecturedvante (AWumnflVinter 1927). pp. 7-29,Le Carbusier lists si~ point., adding One

on lhe "suppre.sion of the cornice,' Hisdiscussion is lleavily weighted to iss"esof snow on flat roofs and 10 his .ixlhpoillt - nol to ",hat one \\'Duld de~m thomore important archHeclllrol issues.Since IMs i' a publication of late 1927. th~concern 10 defend flar roofs in norlherllwimer conditions is probably empha.lsedbecause of the heavy criticism of Ihe flalroofs of the lVei"senhof exhibition.

12 Le Corbu.ier and Pierre 'ealllleret. OeuvrecamplMe 1910_1929 (Zurich: EditionGirsberger. t937), pp, 23-25,

1,1 It is time to acknowledge that mytheorericol opparotu. af research project.,cores, and auxiliary hypalheses nreowing to my long-held intere.t in Iheepistemological sludies af Imre Lakatos,See esperioJly Lakalos, The Methodologyof Scienlific Ileseorch Progromme.(Cambridge: Cambridge University Pross.1978). Myadaptation of Lakatos' thougiltto archilecture appears in Anderson,"Architectllroi Design as u System afResearch Programmes," Design Studie.(London), V (Jllly 1984), 146-150, alld

"Architeclumi Re.earch Programmes inthe Work of La Corbusier," De.ign Stlldies(London), V (juiy 1984), pp. 151_15B.

14 "Rational reconslructiall" relies on ahi,·toriagraphic!theoretical extension ofLakatos' tlleory. See "History of Scienceand il. RaUanal £teconstructioIr." pp, 102-138 in the book cited in the last footnote.

15 Stanford Andarson. ''Aaito olld'Methodicai Accommodation toCircllmslonce· ... ~nd ''A01l0 und'die melhodi.che Anpassung anGegebenheiten'," in Hmo Thoml at 01"eds., Alvar Aalta in Seven BuiJdings/AlmrAalto in .ioben Bouwerken (Helsinki:Museum of Finnish Architecture. 1998).pp. 142-149, In. Also in editiOn>' withI'inllish. Swedish and Portuguesetranslations,

16 Kahn's wards are from Robert Venturi.Campiexity and ContradictiOJ1 (Now York:Museum of Modern Art, 1966), p. 54,

17 AallO, '''rhe Reconstruction of ErJrope i,'

tha Key Problem for tho Architecture of ourTimes" (1941). mprillied iJl A~ko Salokorpi.ed" Abacus,.l (Helsinki: Finnish Mu"eumof Architeclure, 1983), t21-142, SarahMeoin introduces the "wavy line" diagramin her axceJ1ent paper for a book saJl inpracess: Stanford AnderSOIl, Gail Fenske,and David Fixler, ods" Aalta und America

16 IV. Boesiger and 0, Stonoraw, Lo Carbusier:l'he Complete Archilecturoi Works(London Thomes and Hlldson, 1964). I:p.189.

19 Cohn St,John lVi/son, "Slole ofModernism,· ill hi. ArchitecturalllejiecUons (Manchester: MoncheslerUn!<-er.ity Press. 2000), p, 90.

THI N KING IN ARCH ITECTURE

Page 16: building designing thinking - MITweb.mit.edu/soa/www/downloads/2000-09/TH_Ptah08_Nov2008_08.pdf · building designing thinking himself a significant position in the cultural world