Anthropological Psychologizing

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    1/12

    Whitehead, C. (2000) Anthropological psychologizing and what we need to do about it

    20th Annual Conference of the Society for the Anthropology of Consciousness: Tucson,

    Arizona, 5-9 April

    Anthropological psychologizing

    and what we need to do about it

    Charles Whitehead

    15 minute presentation

    Affiliations and research:

    Department of Anthropology, University College London

    Wellcome Department of Imaging Neuroscience, University College London

    Harrow School of Computer Science, University of Westminster

    Correspondence:

    Email: [email protected]

    Website: www.socialmirrors.org

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    2/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    Anthropological psychologizing and what we need to do about it

    Title = Slide 1.

    1. Core problem

    For over a hundred years field anthropologists have been confronted with people who do not

    seem to think the way we do. Some have inferred that, if other people represent the world

    differently, their representationalprocesses must be different. That's a bit like explaining a

    photograph of a UFO by arguing there must be something wrong with the camera. In fact, if

    you think of all the ways anyone might react to a photograph of a UFO, what you get is a

    synchronic metaphor for 150 years of anthropological thought.

    THE CAMERA THE REAL WORLD OTHERWORLDS

    Faulty Political Platonic world

    Normal Theatrical Denial

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    3/12

    CHARLES WHITEHEAD

    Slide 2.

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    4/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    So, we have a suitably unidentifiable object in the middle, lots of people can see it, and there

    are no clues to what it might be.

    1. Some people will blame the camera.

    2. Others will think it's something real - maybe something sinister concealing vested

    political interests, or just people fabricating an illusion.

    3. Others will say its from another world, inaccessible to science; or deny that anyone

    can ever explain anything - the terminal Kantian position.

    1. `Faulty-camera' theorists, from Boas and Lvy-Bruhl, to J.V. Taylor and Hallpike, variously

    describe the non-literate mind as primitive, emotional, childlike, or pre-logical, so dividing

    humanity into two ideal types - `primitive' and `modern'.

    Well we can't talk like that any more, so we have to assume the camera is normal:

    that's the approach taken by the intellectualists in the 19th century; and the structuralists and

    cognitive anthropologists in the 20th. The traditional approach in cognitive anthropology has

    been to say `Let's ignore the UFO, and explain all the ordinary photographs instead.'

    Pascal Boyer tackles the UFO head on. He accuses us all ofad hoc psychologizing.

    There have been major advances in the cognitive sciences: it's time we took note of that

    instead of continually reinventing psychology ex vacuo just to suit ourselves. But he ends up

    arguing that animism is natural precisely because it's not natural. All cameras take photos of

    UFOs precisely because they are designed not to.

    You cannotexplain cultural difference on the grounds that people are all the same,

    without reference to real-world experience, history, and so on. And the reason Boyer attempts

    the impossible is because the cognitivist paradigm itself ignores real world experience. We

    need to export anthropology into cognitive science so they will know what it is we all need to

    explain. Simply importing cognitive science into anthropology is not good enough. We need

    cross-fertilization between disciplines, not a one-way transfusion.

    2. Let's look at real-world explanations. Real-world theorists tell us the UFO is not what it

    appears to be it's false consciousness, society projected onto the sky, or an anti-structural

    inversion of society. Marx made an interesting observation when he said: We become

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    5/12

    CHARLES WHITEHEAD

    conscious by acting on the world. But he inferred therefore we create ourselves through

    labour. Acting on the world, however, does not begin with labour it begins with childhood

    play. Marxist anthropologists focus on the world of work; the collective-representation/

    liminal anti-structure schools focus on play. If you ignore childhood, like the forces-and-

    relations-of-production theorists, you ignore everything that makes us human. And if you

    ignore competition, like pantomime-and-performance theorists, you ignore everything that

    makes us monsters. We are both at the same time, so we need to combine these two

    approaches.

    3. Hermeneutic anthropology takes the Otherworldapproach - assuming a Platonic world of

    self-sufficient closure that can be understood without reference to the real world. They deny

    explanation the world of meaning can only be understood by interpretation and more

    recently, they denied psychology as well. Clifford Geertz said:

    culture...is no more a psychological phenomenon...

    than the progressive form of the verb (1973: 13).

    This is the Saussurian paradigm, and culture as communication, which led to the collapse of

    structuralism, and the failure of cognitive anthropology to deal with religious belief.

    The denial of psychology is always hypocritical: Geertz goes straight into ad hoc

    psychologizing. The Problem of Meaning, he says, is all about human awe, fear, helplessness

    and need, in the face of uncontrollable natural forces: the same simplistic psychology that

    Malinowski imposed on the Trobrianders.

    The denial of explanation is equally false. You cannot observe anything, let alone

    describe it, without assumptions of significance which are covert theories. Secondly, it

    leads to absolute relativism, which also rests on self-contradiction. You can't write an emic

    account unless there are etic universals that allow you to understand your informants. Gellner

    described relativism as a revolving signpost, pointing everywhere and nowhere, except

    towards postmodernism. Everything becomes subjective; knowledge is impossible; science is

    mythology; it's all too much; let's push that final button labelled `self-destruct'.

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    6/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    So, I've been unforgivably negative, and presented a range of anthropological views as a

    series of denials:

    1. There are camera-based theories, which are reductionist, ignore real-world experience, and

    explain difference in terms of sameness because they have:

    a disembodied view of culture as communication a disembodied Saussurian linguistic metaphor a disembodied cognitivist paradigm

    3. At the opposite pole we have anti-reductionists who deny psychology, deny explanation, and

    emphasize

    a disembodied Platonic view of meaning

    But meanings are always grounded in real world experience. A baby is learning what wet and

    dry mean every time it has its nappy changed. It doesn't need to read Mythologiques to

    understand binary oppositions. We don't invent symbols then look around for something to

    attach them to. Meanings are there first, rooted in experiences which are real because they

    cause pleasure and pain.

    We need to ground human meaning in embodied experience; we need to know the

    universal substrates of symbolic behaviour, biological and psychological, as an antidote to

    relativism - a universal basis for etic accounts of cultural difference.

    2. In the middle we have real-world theories which do acknowledge embodied experience, and

    allow both reductionist and expansionist accounts to coexist. What Marxist anthropology

    lacks is an account of childhood, of how we become conscious through childhood play. What

    `performance' theorists need is an operational account of liminality, which is the same thing,

    because childhood is the major liminal stage in human development.

    So all these denials reflect a common problem and require a common solution: we need to

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    7/12

    CHARLES WHITEHEAD

    know the universal cognitive and biological underpinnings of enculturated behaviour.

    2. What needs to be explained

    What cognitive science can tell us right now is that three-year-old children, in all societies

    studied to date, have ontological intuitions, such as the difference between appearance and

    reality, make-believe and reality, or dreams and reality, which appear to be innate or

    universal in our species.

    Ethnographic data suggests that human adults reify representations, which means that,

    somehow, the real-world intuitions of childhood have been turned on their heads. Somewhere

    between childhood and adulthood we are manufacturing a blindness to reality: our

    representations become so powerful that they blot out the world.

    Children are realists, and adults are representationalists. What we need cognitive

    science to explain is the power of collective representations to turn make-believe into make-

    belief, and the place to begin is with social mirror theory.

    3. Where we need to start

    Social mirror theory, deriving from Dilthey, Baldwin, Cooley, and Mead, says: Without

    mirrors in society, there cannot be mirrors in the mind. Performative behaviours such as song,

    dance, and role-play, are signs of an explosive proliferation of social mirroring behaviours in

    our species.

    Communication Play Performance

    Implicit Gesture calls Embodied Song-and-dance

    Mimetic Iconic signals Role-play Ritual

    Conventional Approval and

    disapproval

    Games with

    rules

    Economic

    exchange

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    8/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    Slide 3.Social mirrors

    The table above is an attempt to sort human social-mirroring abilities in a heuristically useful

    way. I have only put one example in each box. The point I want to make is that, if we begin

    with real-world social mirroring behaviours, we can develop a scheme which:

    1. avoids creating an artificial discontinuity between nature and culture which is

    itself a reified representation

    2. avoids fabricating Platonic or Saussurian worlds of disembodied meanings and

    symbols

    Social mirrors make us conscious. It is ironic that collective representations, which exploit

    social mirroring behaviour, should turn us into representationalists, more or less blinded to

    the real-world orientation of our childhood.

    4. Mapping role-play in the brain

    I propose a collaborative approach between anthropology and cognitive science, which aims

    to investigate and understand human social mirroring abilities and social adaptations of the

    brain.

    My own programme has begun with a brain-mapping study of role-play, with Robert

    Turner at the Wellcome Department of Cognitive Neurology* in London. The main findings

    were:

    1. Switching from role-play to a non-role task involved significant areas of brain

    activity, indicated in this slide [Slide 4].

    2. Maintaining the non-role state also involved significant activity in contrast to role-

    play states [Slide 5].

    3. Role-play itself, however, and switching role-play on, did not show robust activations

    relative to controls [Slide 6].

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    9/12

    CHARLES WHITEHEAD

    *Now the Wellcome Department of Imaging Neuroscience

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    10/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    Slide 4: Switching off role-play

    Slide 5: Maintaining the non-role state

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    11/12

    CHARLES WHITEHEAD

    Slide 6:Role-play minus control

    The two areas you see here [this refers to Slide 4: in the side view of the brain I am indicating

    the dark oblong area at the front (i.e. on the right), and the triangular area at the back (top

    left)] are areas you would expect to be involved in role-play. But our study did not reveal

    that. Instead we find increased activity here only when role-play is being `switched off'. How

    do we explain these `wrong way round' findings? One possible interpretation might be that

    role-play is a default state for the human mind. Cognitive effort is needed to suppress or

    ignore social imagination when we are engaged in non-social tasks. `Theatre of mind'

    continues through the control tasks, but unconsciously, and we only see one brief flash at themoment of dissociation.

    I will be presenting a fuller account of this study at next week's conference, `Towards

    a Science of Consciousness', on Tuesday 11th April at 4.30 pm.

  • 8/6/2019 Anthropological Psychologizing

    12/12

    ANTHROPOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGIZING

    Summary and conclusion (Slide 7)

    1. Cognitive research has a role to play in anthropology

    2. Cognitive science is not yet sufficient to help answer

    core anthropological questions

    3. Social-mirror theory offers a useful basis for

    theoretical development and research.

    Research into the social brain seems likely to provide insights with theoretical relevance in

    anthropology.

    Charles Whitehead, Department of Anthropology, UCL