43
Seven Myths of Randomisation in Clinical Trials Stephen Senn 1 (c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Seven myths of randomisation

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Seven myths of randomisation

Seven Myths of Randomisationin Clinical Trials

Stephen Senn

1(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 2: Seven myths of randomisation

Why this talk

• I had begun to notice that there were a number of published criticisms of randomisation in the methodology of science literature of randomisation

• These seemed to be accepted as valid by others

• I felt a refutation was called for

2(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 3: Seven myths of randomisation

The Magnificent Seven

• Patients are treated simultaneously• Balance is necessary for valid inference• Observed covariates can be ignored• Randomisation is not necessary for blinding• Randomisation is inefficient• Randomisation precludes balancing• Large trials have better balance

3(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 4: Seven myths of randomisation

Outline

• A game of chance• The seven myths• My philosophy of randomisation and analysis

4(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 5: Seven myths of randomisation

Game of Chance• Two dice are rolled

– Red die– Black die

• You have to call correctly the odds of a total score of 10• Three variants

– Game 1 You call the odds and the dice are rolled together– Game 2 the red die is rolled first, you are shown the score

and then must call the odds– Game 3 the Game 2 the red die is rolled first, you are not

shown the score and then must call the odds

5(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 6: Seven myths of randomisation

Total Score when Rolling Two Dice

Variant 1. Three of 36 equally likely results give a 10. The probability is 3/36=1/12.

6(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 7: Seven myths of randomisation

Variant 2: If the red die score is 1,2 or 3, probability of a total of10 is 0. If the red die score is 4,5 or 6 the probability of a total of10 is 1/6.

Variant 3: The probability = (½ x 0) + (½ x 1/6) = 1/12

Total Score when Rolling Two Dice

7(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 8: Seven myths of randomisation

The Morals• You can’t treat game 2 like game 1.

– You must condition on the information you receive in order to act wisely

– You must use the actual data from the red die• You can treat game 3 like game 1.

– You can use the distribution in probability that the red die has• You can’t ignore an observed prognostic covariate in analysing

a clinical trial just because you randomised– That would be to treat game 2 like game 1

• You can ignore an unobserved covariate precisely because you did randomise– Because you are entitled to treat game 3 like game 1

8(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 9: Seven myths of randomisation

Trialists continue to use their randomization as an excuse for ignoring prognostic information (myth 3), and they continue to worry about the effect of factors they have not measured (myth 2). Neither practice is logical.

The Reality

9(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 10: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 1: Patients are treated simultaneously

If, having created groups matched with respect to those ‘known’ factors, one then goes on to decide which will be the experimental and which the control group by some random process—in the simplest case by tossing a fair coin—then one can do no epistemic harm, though one also does no further epistemic good. Worrall 2007, p463.

For example, one could arrange for the matching to be performed by a panel of doctors representing a spectrum of opinion on the likely value of the drugs and whose criteria of selection have been made explicit. Urbach, 1985, p272

10(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 11: Seven myths of randomisation

All this is pretty obvious

• The point is that it is obvious to us• It is not obvious to them

– Critics of randomisation writing on clinical trials• You need to tell them to abandon the deep-

freeze microwave theory of clinical trials• You can’t thaw patients out just when it suits

you

11(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 12: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 2: Balance is necessary for validity

• It is generally held as being self evident that a trial which is not balanced is not valid.

• Trials are examined at baseline to establish their validity.

• In fact the matter is not so simple...........

12(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 13: Seven myths of randomisation

A Tale of Two TablesTrial 1 TreatmentSex Verum Placeb

oTotal

Male 34 26 60Female

15 25 40

Total 49 51 100Trial 2 TreatmentSex Verum Placeb

oMale 26 26 52Female

15 15 30

Total 41 41 82

• Trial two balanced but trial one not

• Surely trial two must be more reliable

• Things are not so simple

13(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 14: Seven myths of randomisation

A Tale of Two TablesTrial 1 TreatmentSex Verum Placeb

oTotal

Male 26+8 26 60Female

15 15+10

40

Total 49 51 100Trial 2 TreatmentSex Verum Placeb

oMale 26 26 52Female

15 15 30

Total 41 41 82

• Trial two contains trial one

• How can more information be worse than less

• If statistical theory could not deal with Trial 1 there would be something wrong with it

14(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 15: Seven myths of randomisation

StratificationAll we need to do is compare like with like.

If we compare males with males and females with females we shall obtain two unbiased estimators of the treatment effects. These can then be combined in some appropriate way. This technique is called stratification.

A similar approach called analysis of covariance is available to deal with continuous covariates such as height, age or a baseline measurement.

15(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 16: Seven myths of randomisation

What you learn in your first regression course

1 11 1 0 1

2 12 2 1 2

1

11 ...

1 ...

k

k

n n kn k n

Y X XY X X

Y X X

X β ε

Y = Xβ +ε

Y

ˆ -1β = XX XY 1 2ˆ ˆ( ) , ( ) .E V β β β XX

16(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 17: Seven myths of randomisation

1 2

11 12 1

12 22 2

1

22

ˆvar( ) ( )

2 /

k

k kk

X X

a a aa a

a a

a n

The value of 2 depends on the model.

For a given model, the value of

a22 depends on the design and this only achieves its lower bound when covariates are balanced.

The Value of BalanceVariance multiplier for the treatment effect

17(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 18: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 3Observed covariates can be ignored

• This is wrong whether or not covariates are imbalanced• Nobody would analyse a matched pairs design like a

completely randomised design• However two classes of statisticians are implicitly signing up

to this– Those who minimise– Those who use the propensity score

18(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 19: Seven myths of randomisation

The Problem with Minimisation

• Many public sector trials are minimised but not strictly randomised– That is to say a dynamic form of balancing is

employed• Often the covariates used for balancing are

not fitted in the model

19(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 20: Seven myths of randomisation

Typical MRC Stuff‘The central telephone randomisation system used a minimisation algorithm to balance the treatment groups with respect to eligibility criteria and other major prognostic factors.’ (p24)

‘All comparisons involved logrank analyses of the first occurrence of particular events during the scheduled treatment period after randomisation among all those allocated the vitamins versus all those allocated matching placebo capsules (ie, they were “intention-to treat” analyses).’ (p24)

1. (2002) MRC/BHF Heart Protection Study of cholesterol lowering with simvastatin in 20,536 high-risk individuals: a randomised placebo-controlled trial. Lancet 360:7-22

20(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 21: Seven myths of randomisation

Corollary – unobserved covariates can be ignored if you have randomised• The error is to assume that because you can’t use

randomisation as a justification for ignoring information it is useless

• It is useful for what you don’t see• Knowing that the two-dice game is fairly run is important

even though the average probability is not relevant to game two

• Average probabilities are important for calibrating your inferenceso Your conditional probabilities must be coherent with your

marginal ones See the relationship between the games

(C) Stephen Senn 2014 21

Page 22: Seven myths of randomisation

A Red Herring• One sometimes hears that the fact that there are

indefinitely many covariates means that randomisation is useless

• This is quite wrong • It is based on a misunderstanding that variant 3 of our

game should not be analysed like variant 1• I showed you that it should

(c)Stephen Senn 2013 22

Page 23: Seven myths of randomisation

You are not free to imagine anything at all• Imagine that you are in

control of all the thousands and thousands of covariates that patients will have

• You are now going to allocate the covariates and their effects to patientso As in a simulation

• If you respect the actual variation in human health that there can be you will find that the net total effect of these covariates is bounded

Where Z is a treatment indicator and the X are covariates. You are not free to arbitrarily assume any values you like for the Xs and the because the variance of Y must be respected.

(c)Stephen Senn 2013 23

Page 24: Seven myths of randomisation

The importance of ratios

• In fact from one point of view there is only one covariate that matters o potential outcome

If you know this, all other covariates are irrelevant

• And just as this can vary between groups in can vary within• The t-statistic is based on the ratio of differences between to

variation within• Randomisation guarantees (to a good approximation) the

unconditional behaviour of this ratio and that is all that matters for what you can’t see (game 3)

• An example follows

(c)Stephen Senn 2013 24

Page 25: Seven myths of randomisation

Hills and Armitage Eneuresis Data

10

8

14

2

12

6 1210

6

4

2

0

40 8

Dry nights placebo

Dry nights drug

Line of equality

Sequence Drug PlaceboSequence placebo drug

Cross-over trial in Eneuresis

Two treatment periods of 14 days each

1. Hills, M, Armitage, P. The two-period cross-over clinical trial, British Journal of Clinical Pharmacology 1979; 8: 7-20.

25(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 26: Seven myths of randomisation

0.7

4

0.5

2

0.3

0

0.1

-2-4

0.6

0.2

0.4

0.0

Density

Permutated treatment effect

Blue diamond shows treatment effect whether or not we condition on patient as a factor.

It is identical because the trial is balanced by patient.

However the permutation distribution is quite different and our inferences are different whether we condition (red) or not (black) and clearly balancing the randomisation by patient and not conditioning the analysis by patient is wrong

26(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 27: Seven myths of randomisation

The two permutation* distributions summarised

Summary statistics for Permuted difference no blocking Number of observations = 10000

Mean = 0.00561

Median = 0.0345

Minimum = -3.828

Maximum = 3.621

Lower quartile = -0.655

Upper quartile = 0.655

P-value for observed difference 0.0340

*Strictly speaking randomisation distributions

Summary statistics for Permuted difference blocking

Number of observations = 10000

Mean = 0.00330

Median = 0.0345

Minimum = -2.379

Maximum = 2.517

Lower quartile = -0.517

Upper quartile = 0.517

P-value for observed difference 0.0014

27(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 28: Seven myths of randomisation

Two Parametric ApproachesNot fitting patient effect

Estimate s.e. t(56) t pr.

2.172 0.964 2.25 0.0282

(P-value for permutation is 0.034)

Fitting patient effect

Estimate s.e. t(28) t pr.2.172 0.616 3.53 0.00147

(P-value for Permutation is 0.0014)

28(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 29: Seven myths of randomisation

What happens if you balance but don’t condition?

Approach Variance of estimated treatment effect over all randomisations*

Mean of variance of estimated treatment effect over all randomisations*

Completely randomised Analysed as such

0.987 0.996

Randomised within-patientAnalysed as such

0.534 0.529

Randomised within-patient Analysed as completely randomised

0.534 1.005

*Based on 10000 random permutations

(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015 29

That is to say, permute values respecting the fact that they come from a cross-over but analysing them as if they came from a parallel group trial

Page 30: Seven myths of randomisation

In terms of t-statisticsApproach Observed variance

of t-statistic over all randomisations*

Predicted theoretical variance

Completely randomised Analysed as such

1.027 1.037

Randomised within-patientAnalysed as such

1.085 1.077

Randomised within-patient Analysed as completely randomised

0.534 1.037@

*Based on 10000 random permutations@ Using the common falsely assumed theory

(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015 30

Page 31: Seven myths of randomisation

The Shocking Truth• The validity of conventional analysis of randomised

trials does not depend on covariate balance• It is valid because they are not perfectly balanced• If they were balanced the standard analysis would

be wrong

(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015 31

Page 32: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 4Randomisation is Not Necessary for Blinding

Fisher, in a letter to Jeffreys, explained the dangers of using a haphazard method thus

… if I want to test the capacity of the human race for telepathically perceiving a playing card, I might choose the Queen of Diamonds, and get thousands of radio listeners to send in guesses. I should then find that considerably more than one in 52 guessed the card right... Experimentally this sort of thing arises because we are in the habit of making tacit hypotheses, e.g. ‘Good guesses are at random except for a possible telepathic influence.’ But in reality it appears that red cards are always guessed more frequently than black(Bennett, 1990).(pp268-269)

…if the trial was, and remained, double-blind then randomization could play no further role in this respect. (Worrall, 2007)(P454)

32(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 33: Seven myths of randomisation

Avoiding Double Guessing

• If you don’t randomise you have to assume that your strategy has not been guessed by the investigator

• You are using ‘the argument from the stupidity of others’

• Not publishing the block size in your protocol is a classic example

33(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 34: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 5Randomisation is Inefficient

• There is a sense in which this is no myth• Randomisation is not fully efficient• Theory shows that there is a loss of about one

patient per factor fitted compared to a completely balanced design– Such completely balanced designs are not usually

possible, however• In any case, the loss is small

34(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 35: Seven myths of randomisation

An ExampleLinear Trend in Prognosis

The figures refer to the difference in position between B and A. Of course alternation means that the Bs are on average one place beyond the As. The other schemes are ‘unbiased’. Since alternation and the double sandwich are deterministic the have no variance.

It is assumed that there are 2n patients in total and that n is an even number.

35(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 36: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 6Randomisation precludes balancing

• Of course we know this is not true

• We can build strata and randomise within them

• ‘Balance what you can and randomise what you can’t’ was Fisher’s recipe

36(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 37: Seven myths of randomisation

Myth 7Large trials are more balanced than small ones

Measure of balance

Comparison large v small (on average)

Mean difference at baseline

Large trial is more balanced

Total difference at baseline

Small trial is more balanced

Standardised difference at baseline

Large and small trial equally balanced

• Large trials have narrower confidence intervals for the treatment effect

• The advantage of increased mean balance in covariates has already been consumed in the form of narrower limits

• There is no further insurance to be given by size– Only increase in validity is

because closer to asymptotic limit that guarantees Normality

37(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 38: Seven myths of randomisation

My Philosophy of Clinical Trials• Your (reasonable) beliefs dictate the model• You should try measure what you think is important• You should try fit what you have measured

– Caveat : random regressors and the Gauss-Markov theorem• If you can balance what is important so much the better

– But fitting is more important than balancing• Randomisation deals with unmeasured covariates

– You can use the distribution in probability of unmeasured covariates– For measured covariates you must use the actual observed distribution

• Claiming to do ‘conservative inference’ is just a convenient way of hiding bad practice– Who thinks that analysing a matched pairs t as a two sample t is acceptable?

38(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 39: Seven myths of randomisation

What’s out and What’s inOut In

• Log-rank test• T-test on change scores• Chi-square tests on 2 x 2

tables• Responder analysis and

dichotomies• Balancing as an excuse for

not conditioning

• Proportional hazards• Analysis of covariance fitting

baseline• Logistic regression fitting

covariates• Analysis of original values• Modelling as a guide for

designs

39(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 40: Seven myths of randomisation

Unresolved Issue

• In principle you should never be worse off by having more information

• The ordinary least squares approach has two potential losses in fitting covariates– Loss of orthogonality– Losses of degrees of freedom

• This means that eventually we lose by fitting more covariates

40(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 41: Seven myths of randomisation

Resolution?

• The Gauss-Markov theorem does not apply to stochastic regressors

• In theory we can do better by having random effect models

• However there are severe practical difficulties• Possible Bayesian resolution in theory• A pragmatic compromise of a limited number of

prognostic factors may be reasonable

41(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 42: Seven myths of randomisation

To sum up

• There are a lot of people out there who fail to understand what randomisation can and cannot do for you

• We need to tell them firmly and clearly what they need to understand

42(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015

Page 43: Seven myths of randomisation

Finally

I leave you with this thought

Statisticians are always tossing coins but do not own many

43(c)Stephen Senn 2011-2015