102
FREDERICK J. NEWMEYER UNIVERSITY OF WASHINGTON, UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA, AND SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY Class 3: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics 1

The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

The Edge of Linguistics lecture series from Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer During Oct 7 to Oct 17, Prof. Newmeyer offered a lecture series on a wide range of linguistic topics in Beijing Language and Culture University. Lecture 1: The Chomskyan Revolution Lecture 2: Constraining the Theory Lecture 3: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics Lecture 4: The Boundary between Competence and Performance Lecture 5: Can One Language Be ‘More Complex’ Than Another? Background: Fredreck J. Newmeyer is Professor Emeritus of Linguistics at the University of Washington and adjunct professor in the University Of British Columbia Department Of Linguistics and the Simon Fraser University Department of Linguistics. He has published widely in theoretical and English syntax.

Citation preview

Page 1: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

1

FREDERICK J. NEWMEYER

UNIVERSITY OF WASHINGTON, UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA,

AND SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY

Class 3:The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics

Page 2: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

2

THE NATURE OF MEANING

This class will deal with meaning/semantics and its treatment within generative grammar.

Many debates both within generative grammar and between generativists and those in other frameworks have centred around questions of semantics.

To make things more complicated, there has always been debate about what meaning ‘means’.

Page 3: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

3

THE NATURE OF MEANING

Three approaches to meaning, each of which is at root incompatible with the other two.

Nevertheless, each has found its place in current theoretical work:

Page 4: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

4

THE NATURE OF MEANING

FIRST: Meanings are ‘ideas’ or in current terminology, ‘cognitive representations’.

This has its roots in continental philosophy and was developed by European structuralism.

For Saussure the basic unit of linguistics was the ‘sign’: the relationship between a ‘mental image’ and an ‘acoustic image’.

Page 5: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

5

THE NATURE OF MEANING

Ray Jackendoff’s Conceptual Semantics is a variant of this idea.

In Cognitive Linguistics, this is the approach to meaning taken.

Today in generative grammar, we see it in such notions as ‘thematic roles’, ‘interpretable features’, and so on.

Page 6: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

6

THE NATURE OF MEANING

SECOND: Meanings are ‘uses’.

This has its roots in behaviourism, ordinary language philosophy, and British structuralism.

“If you want to know what a word/sentence, etc. means, then see how it is used.”

The use-theory of meaning manifests itself today in pragmatic theory (based on work by such philosophers as Grice, Austin, and Searle).

Page 7: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

7

THE NATURE OF MEANING

THIRD: Meanings are conditions for establishing the truth of propositions.

This has its roots in the logical tradition, in particular in logical positivist philosophy.

Today we see it in mainstream semantic theory.

Interestingly, Chomsky has always rejected this approach.

Page 8: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

8

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

Most of the debates in the past 50 years have focused on the boundary between form and meaning.

That is, questions like ‘Is it productive to study form independently of meaning?’

‘To what extent does syntax have its own patterning that does not reflect meaning?’

One can go a long way to answering these questions without knowing a lot about the nature of meaning.

Page 9: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

9

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

Chomsky in Syntactic Structures took a very clear position on the form-meaning relationship:

“I think that we are forced to conclude that grammar is autonomous and independent of meaning.” (Chomsky 1957: 17)

In other words, you can and should study form without studying meaning at the same time.

Page 10: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

10

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

Chomsky gave empirical arguments for the independence of form and meaning:

Something can be formally grammatical, but have no meaning: Colourless green ideas sleep furiously.

Two sentences can be related by a transformational rule, yet differ in meaning:

Everyone in the room speaks two languages.Two languages are spoken by everyone in the room.

Page 11: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

11

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

Chomsky also argued that we can use form to get at meaning:

‘In general, as syntactic description becomes deeper, what appear to be semantic questions fall increasingly within its scope...’ (Chomsky 1964: 936).

For example, Chomsky motivated the passive transformation purely on its formal properties (the occurrence of the morpheme be+en, its limitation to transitive verbs, and so on).

The rough paraphrase relation between actives and passives was not one of Chomsky’s motivations.

Page 12: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

12

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

There was no semantic component in Syntactic Structures.

Incorporating semantics into the model was the work of the next decade.

It was carried out by Jerrold Katz, Jerry Fodor, and Paul Postal.

Page 13: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

13

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

Katz and Postal (1964): An Integrated Theory of Linguistic Descriptions.

The Katz-Postal Hypothesis: Transformations do not change meaning.

Another way to put that is to say that everything that you need for semantic interpretation is at the level of Deep Structure.

Page 14: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

14

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

But what about?:

Everyone in the room speaks two languages.

Two languages are spoken by everyone in the room.

Isn’t this an example of Passive changing meaning?

Katz and Postal argued that both sentences are ambiguous!

Page 15: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

15

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

In the earliest work, John saw Mary, John did not see Mary, and Did John see Mary? were all derived from the same underlying structure.

So transformations were certainly changing meaning!

Katz and Postal agued that negatives and questions had abstract NEG and Q morphemes in Deep Structure.

So meaning was not changed under transformation.

Page 16: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

16

THE BOUNDARY BETWEEN FORM AND MEANING

All of these changes laid the basis for Chomsky’s 1965 book Aspects of the Theory of Syntax.

This book proposed what came to be called the ‘Standard Theory’.

Page 17: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

17

THE 1965 ASPECTS OF THE THEORY OF SYNTAX MODEL, THE ‘STANDARD

THEORY’

Page 18: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

18

TOWARDS GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

But in the late 1960s, generative syntacticians split off in two directions:

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

INTERPRETIVE SEMANTICS

Page 19: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

19

TOWARDS GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

For almost 10 years, the battles between the two were so vitriolic, the period has been called the time of the ‘linguistic wars’.

Page 20: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

20

SOME LEADING GENERATIVE SEMANTICISTS

GEORGE LAKOFF

HAJ ROSS

JAMES MCCAWLEY 1938-1999

PAUL POSTAL

Page 21: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

21

TOWARDS GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

By 1965-1967, Postal, Ross, and Lakoff were arguing that deep structure was much more ‘abstract’ than in the standard theory.

In this sense, ‘abstract’ means farther from surface structure and closer to semantic representation.

Page 22: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

22

‘Floyd broke the glass’ in the Standard Theory

Now look at the same sentence in a generative semantics treatment.

Page 23: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

23

Page 24: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

24

TOWARDS GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

Notice the lexical decomposition in the tree:

The verb break is derived from (roughly) 'cause + come about + be + broken'.

Page 25: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

25

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

By 1970 Generative Semantics was born.

Deep Structure had been ‘pushed back’ so closely to semantic representation that Lakoff, Ross, Postal, and McCawley came to the conclusion that there was no independent level of Deep Structure at all.

Page 26: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

26

TOWARDS GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

Page 27: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

27

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

Generative Semantics did not at first seem like a big departure from the standard theory.

Their arguments were arrived at almost entirely by recourse to the assumptions of Katz and Postal's Integrated Theory of Linguistic Descriptions and Chomsky's Aspects of the Theory of Syntax.

Page 28: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

28

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

The Katz-Postal Hypothesis:

Transformations do not change meaning = everything you need for meaning is at the level of Deep Structure.

That hypothesis invited a syntactic solution to every semantic problem.

Page 29: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

29

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

James McCawley pointed out that words can have the same meaning as phrases:

kill = cause to die

McCawley reasoned that if they have the same meaning, they should have the same syntactic structure. So:

Page 30: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

30

GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

Page 31: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

31

LATE GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

By 1970 Generative Semantics was at its peak.

If it had stabilized there, it might exist today.

But it did not stabilize. It kept adding more and more new types of data to account for and more complex devices to handle them.

Page 32: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

32

LATE GENERATIVE SEMANTICS

Needless to say, generative semanticists gave up on formalism very quickly.

By the mid 1970s, the program of Generative Semantics held very little appeal for most linguists.

The great majority went over to a more ‘Chomskyan’ way of looking at grammar.

Page 33: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

33

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

• During the interpretive-generative semantics debate more and more evidence was put forward for the autonomy of syntax.

• Let’s look at some of this and then turn to mainstream developments.

• Virtually every linguist in the world agrees that the relationship between form and meaning is highly systematic.

Page 34: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

34

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

Almost all linguists agree that the match up between form and meaning is far from one-to-one.

Ambiguity (The chickens are ready to eat).

Paraphrase (Mary looked up the answer / Mary looked the answer up)

Page 35: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

35

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

Lexical peculiarities: a. He is likely to be late.

b. *He is probable to be late. (likely, but not probable, allows raising)

a. He allowed the rope to go slack.b. *He let the rope to go slack. (let doesn’t take infinitive

marker)

a. He isn’t sufficiently tall.b. *He isn’t enough tall. / He isn’t tall enough. (enough is only

degree modifier that occurs post-adjectivally)

Page 36: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

36

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

One grammatical relation encoding more than one semantic role:

a. Mary threw the ball [‘Mary’ is the Agent of the action]b. Mary saw the play [‘Mary’ is the Experiencer of an event]c. Mary received a letter [‘Mary’ is the goal/recipient of

transfer]d. Mary went from Vancouver to Montréal [‘Mary’ is an

object undergoing transfer of position]

In each case Mary is the grammatical subject.

Page 37: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

37

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

Categorial mismatches — where the same concept is encoded by different grammatical categories:

Quantificational nouns and quantifiers:Bill has [a lot of] friends.Bill has [many] friends.

Page 38: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

38

FORM-MEANING MISMATCHES

Displacements — frontings and extrapositions — that break up what are clearly semantic units:

  a. [Many objections to the new work rules] were raised.

b. [Many objections] were raised [to the new work rules].

Page 39: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

39

WHY DO FORM AND MEANING DIVERGE?

Pure historical accident: Most disyllabic adjectives in English beginning with unstressed a- do not occur prenominally:*the asleep baby, *the aslant window, *the ajar door, *the atilt picture, etc.

There is no semantic generalization at work:the sleeping baby, the slanted window, the open door, the titled picture

The generalization is not phonological either:the abrupt remark, the acerb comment, the astute recommendation

Page 40: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

40

WHY DO FORM AND MEANING DIVERGE?

The story: Most of the adjectives that don’t occur prenominally are historically grammaticalizations of PPs:asleep < on sleep; awake < on wake; ajar < at jar

They don’t occur prenominally because PPs don’t occur prenominally.

Abrupt, acerb, and astute, on the other hand, have different histories:abrupt (< Lat. abruptus); acerb (< acerbity < Fr. acerbité); astute (< Lat. astutus)

Given their history, there was never an impediment to abrupt, acerb, and astute occurring prenominally.

Page 41: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

41

WHY DO FORM AND MEANING DIVERGE?

Real-time constraints imposed by the vocal channel (Chafe 1967)

  Conflicting pressures (Martinet 1962) 

Fronting an object highlights the fronted element, but breaks up a semantic unit:a. What did you eat?b. Raw potatoes, I would never eat. Pressure from the parser: a. [Many objections to the new work rules] were raised.b. [Many objections] were raised [to the new work rules].

Page 42: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

42

THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

What kinds of facts bear on whether syntax is autonomous?

An answer from some formalists: ‘Just show a mismatch between form and meaning/function’.

But if that’s all there were to it, then every linguist would believe in autonomous syntax.

Page 43: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

43

THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

We’ve just seen examples of mismatches.

Some functionalists say that to refute the autonommy of syntax, all that you need to do is to show that there is a rule-governed relationship between form and meaning.

Page 44: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

44

THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

DORIS PAYNE

“Crucial evidence for choosing a functionalist over a Chomskyan formalist approach would minimally be any language in which there is a rule-governed relationship between discourse/cognitive functions and linear order, where the relationship between form and function is rule-like. Such languages clearly exist.”

Page 45: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

45

THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Parts of speech: a. Nouns tend to denote persons, places, things, or concepts.b. Verbs tend to denote actions, processes, etc.c. And so on for other syntactic categories.

Page 46: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

46

THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

All formal theories posit a rule-governed relation between syntactic and semantic structure.

There would be no ‘autonomous syntacticians’ if, in order to qualify as one, you had to reject regular rules linking form and meaning.

Page 47: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

47

SUPPORT FOR THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

What does support the autonomy of syntax, then?

Autonomy of Syntax: The rules (principles, constraints, etc.) that determine the combinatorial possibilities of the formal elements of a language make no reference to constructs from meaning, discourse, or language use.

Page 48: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

48

SUPPORT FOR THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

To establish the correctness of the autonomy of syntax, one must demonstrate that:

a. there exists an extensive set of purely formal generalizations orthogonal to generalizations governing meaning or discourse.

FoG1 FoG2 FoG3 FoG4 FoG5 etc. (FoG = Formal Generalization)

Page 49: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

49

SUPPORT FOR THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

b. these generalizations ‘interlock’ in a system.

Page 50: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

50

THE AUTONOMY OF GRAMMATICAL COMPONENTS

The adjective with infinitival complement structure in English Noun – Copula – Adjective -- Infinitive There are six logically possible ways that the NP subject can relate (in terms of understood grammatical relations ) to the Adjective and the Verb. All six occur:  Relation of NP subject to A to Va. Mary is eager to please subject subjectb. Mary is easy to please none objectc. Mary is liable to dance none subjectd Guns are cheap to buy subject objecte. It is useless to try none nonef. It is (too) dark to seesubject none 

Page 51: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

51

THE AUTONOMY OF GRAMMATICAL COMPONENTS

 Clearly there is something ‘real’ about that pattern itself, whatever meanings or uses it might manifest.

In other words, the formal patterns themselves have an autonomy, not derivable from meaning or use.

Page 52: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

52

STRUCTURAL-SYSTEMIC PRESSURE ON CHANGE

Preposition-stranding:

a. Who did you talk to?b. Mary was talked to.

Page 53: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

53

STRUCTURAL-SYSTEMIC PRESSURE ON CHANGE

Despite its typological rarity, P-stranding in English has expanded its domain consistently in the last 1000 years.

Chronology of the expansion of P-stranding in English: a. Old English period (all wh-movement type

operations without an overt wh-pronoun; topicalization) b. Early Middle English (overt wh-movement) c. Later Middle English (passives) d. Modern English (over a direct object; e.g.

Who did they take advantage of?; Mary was taken advantage of.)

Page 54: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

54

STRUCTURAL-SYSTEMIC PRESSURE ON CHANGE

What is going on here?

An existing grammatical structure has steadily expanded its domain.

Speakers have the pattern and seem to love it.

They use it in more and more contexts.

Page 55: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

55

STRUCTURAL-SYSTEMIC PRESSURE ON CHANGE

Perhaps the expansion is due to the model of other P-final structures in English:

a. Phrasal verbs with postposed particles:i. I looked the answer up.ii. Let’s check it out.

b. Final P-like directional particles:i. I found this lying around.ii. She’s coming up (e.g. the

stairs)

Page 56: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

56

STRUCTURAL-SYSTEMIC PRESSURE ON CHANGE

In other words — P-stranding has been reinforced by the existence of similar — but analytically independent — structures in the language.

This ‘sensitivity to pure structure’ is predicted by the autonomy of syntax.

Page 57: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

57

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The autonomy of syntax has become progressive weakened over the years in mainstream ‘Chomskyan’ syntax.

The result is that syntax has been pushed back to semantics — similar to what happened with Generative Semantics!

Page 58: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

58

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The Theta-Criterion from Chomsky’s Lectures on Government and Binding (Chomsky 1981).

Page 59: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

59

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The Theta-Criterion:

Each argument bears one and only one Q-role and each Q-role is assigned to one and only one argument. (Chomsky 1981: 36)

Page 60: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

60

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The Theta-Criterion demands abstract PRO subjects where they do not occur on the surface:

a) Mary yearns [PRO to convince John that she is qualified]. b) John left the room [PRO angry].

Page 61: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

61

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Next step: The idea that ‘c-selection (essentially subcategorization) is derivable from ‘s-selection’ (essentially, the thematic properties of the items involved) (Chomsky 1986).

Page 62: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

62

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

C-selection (subcategorization): the categories that an verb takes at the level of D(eep)-structure:

persuade ___ NP CP

S-selection: the semantic roles that a verb takes:

persuade Agent ___ Patient Proposition

Page 63: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

63

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Getting rid of subcategorization is tantamount to removing one piece of motivation for an independent level of D(eep)-Structure.

Page 64: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

64

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

It is not obviously correct to try to derive c-selection from s-selection:

Eat ___ (NP)Dine ___ (on NP)Devour ___ NP

Page 65: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

65

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The next step: Uniformity of Theta Assignment Hypothesis (UTAH) (Baker 1988).

Identical thematic relationships between items are represented by identical structural relationships between those items at the level of D-structure. MARK

BAKER

Page 66: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

66

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

UTAH is another step in the direction of Generative Semantics. Notice how the subjects of each of these sentences have different thematic roles:

Mary threw the ball [‘Mary’ is the Agent of the action]Mary saw the play [‘Mary’is the Experiencer of an event]Mary received a letter [‘Mary’is the recipient of an object]Mary went from Chicago to Detroit [‘Mary’ is an object undergoing

transfer of position]Mary underwent torture [‘Mary’ is a Patient]

Page 67: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

67

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Under one interpretation of UTAH, in each of these sentences Mary would have to be in a different structural position.

Page 68: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

68

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Next: Lexical decomposition, which derives semantically complex predicates via syntactic movement operations.

KEN HALE, 1934-2001 JAY KEYSER HAGIT BORER

Page 69: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

69

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Next: The cartography program (Rizzi 1997; Cinque 1999), which appeals in part to semantic motivation for syntactic projections:

 

LUIGI RIZZI GUGLIELMO CINQUE

Page 70: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

70

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

“In fact, a restrictive theory should force a one-to-one relation between position and interpretation (p. 20) … each projection has a specific semantic interpretation.” (p. 132) (Cinque 1999)

Page 71: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

71

Page 72: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

72

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Next: The triggering of movement (and/or the licensing of configurations) by semantic properties of heads (Rizzi 1991/1996; Haegeman 1995):

 

LUIGI RIZZI LILIANE HAEGEMAN

Page 73: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

73

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

“Syntactic movement … must be triggered by the satisfaction of certain quasi-morphological requirements of heads. … [S]uch features have an interpretive import (Wh, Neg, Top, Foc, …): they determine the interpretation of the category bearing them and of its immediate constituents …, function as scope markers for phrases with the relevant quantificational force in a local configuration, etc.” (Rizzi 1997: 282; emphasis added)

 “[The Negative Criterion appeals to] the semantic-syntactic feature NEG.” (Haegeman 1997: 116)

Page 74: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

74

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

g. The principle of Full Interpretation: Every element of Phonological Form and Logical Form must receive an appropriate interpretation.

h. Phases, which are defined as full propositional structures.

Page 75: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

75

THE WEAKENING OF THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

These do not illustrate syntax becoming deeper and incorporating semantics.

They illustrate grafting semantic notions directly into the syntax.

There are negative consequences — I’ll just give one example.

Page 76: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

76

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

Crosslinguistically we also find the positing of semantically-based projections that render purely formal generalization all but impossible to capture.

Take the Neg Phrase projection. The default assumption now is that where we have semantic negation we have NegP.

Page 77: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

77

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

Two possibilities:

Negative markers cross-linguistically have their own distinct syntax, i. e., as part of Neg Phrase.

Negative markers cross-linguistically pattern with elements that have nothing to do with negation.

It’s the second possibility — the one supporting autonomy — that is correct.

Page 78: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

78

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

Negation is almost never overtly phrasal.

Even worse, NegP obscures the formal similarities between negatives in a particular language and other categories with the same formal properties (different for different languages).

Page 79: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

79

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

1. Complement-taking verbTongan  

a. Na’e ‘alu ‘a SialeASP go ABSOLUTE Charlie‘Charlie went’

 b. Na’e ‘ikai [S ke ‘alu ‘a Siale]

ASP NEG ASP go ABSOLUTE Charlie‘Charlie did not go’

 ‘ikai behaves like a verb in the seem class (we know there is a complement because ke occurs only in embedded clauses)

Page 80: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

80

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

2. AuxiliaryEstonian Negative forms pattern with perfects, which are based on a form of the copula OLEMA

Page 81: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

81

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

3. Derivational affixTurkish  V + Refl + Recip + Cause + Pass + Neg + Possible + Tense/Mood + Person/Number

Page 82: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

82

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

4. NounEvenki (Tungus) 

a. nuan a:cin ‘he is not here’b. nuartin a:cir ‘they are not here’

(a:cin has a plural form and takes case endings like ordinary nouns)

Page 83: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

83

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

5. Adverb

EnglishNot is an adverb in the same class as never, always, just, barely.

We need the filter *not before a finite verb

to block *Mary not left, etc.

Page 84: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

84

NEGATION AND AUTONOMY

In other words, negation supports the autonomy of syntax.

Page 85: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

85

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Why has the autonomy of syntax come to be so weakened?

Page 86: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

86

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Partly the Minimalist Program is to blame.

Three hypothesis central to the MP have pushed syntax back towards semantics.

Page 87: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

87

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The three hypotheses: a. There is no optionality in grammar; hence

elements move only when they are ‘required to’. (Chomsky 1995)

b. Movement must be triggered by a feature on a functional head. (Chomsky 1995)

c. “In a perfectly designed language, each feature would be semantic or phonetic, not merely a device to create a position or to facilitate computation.” (Chomsky 2000: 109)

Page 88: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

88

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

(a) There is no optionality in grammar; hence elements move only when they are ‘required to’. (Chomsky 1995)

This hypothesis requires that seemingly optional variants have different underlying structures.

But few if any structural variants have the same semantic properties.

So structural differences came to be located in projections with direct semantic relevance.

Page 89: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

89

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

(b) Movement must be triggered by a feature on a functional head. (Chomsky 1995)

If projections are semantically defined and, as in (b), movement is triggered by features of projections, then we are a step closer to the idea that movement is semantically motivated.

Page 90: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

90

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The quote in (c) is the icing on the cake:

“In a perfectly designed language, each feature would be semantic or phonetic, not merely a device to create a position or to facilitate computation.” (Chomsky 2000: 109)

We can disagree with each other profoundly about what a ‘perfectly designed language’ might look like. But if we do happen to agree with (c) — then we can say good-bye to the autonomy of syntax.

Page 91: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

91

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

Well before 1995 mainstream syntax was headed in an anti-autonomist position.

So we can’t ‘blame’ (or ‘thank’) minimalism for that.

Page 92: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

92

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

The most popular formal semantic theories haven’t meshed comfortably with mainstream generative syntax.

And the main reason for that is that Chomsky, has never shown any interest in formal semantics.

Page 93: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

93

THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM AND THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX

So the tendency has been to ‘go with what we know’ — to expand syntax to encompass what is naturally the domain of semantic theory.

Page 94: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

94

DOES THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM MAKE THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX A NON-ISSUE?

“We hypothesize that FLN only includes recursion and is the only uniquely human component of the faculty of language.” (Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch 2002: 1569)

If the quote were correct, then syntax would be autonomous by definition.

Page 95: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

95

DOES THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM MAKE THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX A NON-ISSUE?

In addition to recursion, at least the following are needed in a minimalist theory:

a. Economy principles such as Last Resort, Relativized Minimality (or Minimize Chain Links), and Anti-Locality. These don’t fall out from recursion per se, but rather represent conditions that need to be imposed on it.

b. The entire set of mechanisms pertaining to phases, including what nodes count for phasehood and the various conditions that need to be imposed on their functioning, like the Phase Impenetrability Condition.

Page 96: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

96

DOES THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM MAKE THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX A NON-ISSUE?

c. The categorial inventory (lexical and functional) needs to be specified, as well as the formal features they manifest.

d. The set of parameters (there might be hundreds), their possible settings, and the implicational relations among them, need to be specified.

Page 97: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

97

DOES THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM MAKE THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX A NON-ISSUE?

e. “PF-syntax.” Some syntactic phenomena that have been attributed to PF:

i. extraposition and scrambling ii. object shiftiii. head movements iv. the movement deriving V2 orderv. linearization (i.e. VO vs. OV) vi. Wh-movement

Page 98: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

98

DOES THE MINIMALIST PROGRAM MAKE THE AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX A NON-ISSUE?

Economy principles, phases, categories, parameter settings, and PF syntax clearly differ from language to language.

So the MP doesn’t make the question of autonomy irrelevant.

Page 99: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

99

THE ANTI-AUTONOMIST TREND THREATENS THE FOUNDATIONS OF GENERATIVE GRAMMAR

To stress again: the one feature that has made generative grammar distinctively different from every other contemporary approach is the claim that there is something ‘special’ about syntax.

And furthermore that this ‘specialness’ of syntax is at the root of the theory of Universal Grammar.

Page 100: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

100

THE ANTI-AUTONOMIST TREND THREATENS THE FOUNDATIONS OF GENERATIVE GRAMMAR

If you give up the Autonomy of Syntax, then the arguments for innate structural principles disappear.

Opponents of generative grammar claim that the arguments for UG fall through because Chomsky and his associates don’t realize how isomorphic syntax is to semantics (see, for example, Van Valin 1998).

Page 101: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

101

THE ANTI-AUTONOMIST TREND THREATENS THE FOUNDATIONS OF GENERATIVE GRAMMAR

The blurring of the distinction between form and meaning gives a huge opening wedge to opponents of generative grammar.

“In a perfectly designed language, each feature would be semantic or phonetic, not merely a device to create a position or to facilitate computation.” (Chomsky 2000: 109)

“The core similarities across languages have their origin in two sources: physiological constraints on the sound system and conceptual constraints on the semantics.” (Evans and Levinson 2007: np)

Page 102: The Boundary between Syntax and Semantics - Prof. Fredreck J. Newmeyer

102

THE ANTI-AUTONOMIST TREND THREATENS THE FOUNDATIONS OF GENERATIVE GRAMMAR

Peace, harmony, and convergence are good things, if you don’t have to give up too much to achieve them.

Giving up the Autonomy of Syntax is giving up too much!