7
William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic Stephen Read Published online: 12 July 2007 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007 William of Ockham’s Summa Logicae is a classic of ana- lytical metaphysics, using a typical fourteenth century lo- gic treatise to defend a reductionist ontology. 1 For Ockham, everything is an individual, and this is to be shown by the correct logical analysis of language, rein- terpreting Aristotle’s Categories as a taxonomy of the many ways in which terms can be predicated. The ultimate basis is the attribution of an individual quality to an indi- vidual substance. This theory of the signification of terms is then extended to an account of the truth-conditions of propositions and the truth-preservation of arguments, but always with the reduction to individuals as the key. This classic work in the logical analysis of language still con- tains lively insights for contemporary scholars. Much of Part I of the Summa Logicae is taken up with the notion of the signification of words. Indeed, like Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, it opens with a quotation from Augustine, in this case coupled to another from Boethius reporting Aristotle’s three-fold division of language from the start of his De Interpretatione. Terms and the propositions of which they are composed are of three types, written, spoken and mental: and ‘‘these con- ceptual terms and the propositions composed from them are those mental words which St Augustine in De Trinitate XV said are of no language, because they remain only in the mind and cannot be carried forth from it, whereas the sounds subordinate to them as signs can be uttered pub- licly.’’ 2 Two iconoclastic ideas are contained in germ in this passage: first, the Augustinian conceit that concepts form a mental language in parallel to spoken and written language; secondly, the consequential insight that this language cannot be signified by spoken and written language since it is itself a language and so open to interpretation. Rather, Ockham described spoken language, and written language in turn, as subordinated to mental language, deriving its signification from the signification of that language of thought. Mental language too, as a language, needs to obtain its interpretation and signification in some way. But how? By being common to all men, as Aristotle said (De Interpretatione 16a7)—but contrary to his observation that all signs signify by convention (16a26)—mental terms signify naturally, not by convention as do spoken and written terms in different languages. But what do they signify? Here the London school of Ockham and his sympathizer Wodeham, opposed by the realist Chatton, takes inspiration from Avicenna’s commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Everything which is one and not many is a singular and individual thing. Nothing is common to other things except by signification. The only universals are names. Avicenna expresses this nominalist credo in a passage cited by Ockham: ‘‘One form in the mind is related to many and in this respect is a universal, since it is a concept in the mind This form, although universal in its relation to indi- viduals, is individual in its relation to the particular mind in 1 See Ockham (1974) for the full critical edition of the Latin text. Parts I and II, and a small part of Part III (which itself comprises more than half the work), have been translated into English. For details, see Spade (1999), 8. S. Read (&) Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, St Andrews, Fife, Scotland, UK e-mail: [email protected] 2 Ockham (1974), I 1: 7. All references to the Summa Logicae will be to Ockham (1974), citing Part, chapter and page number. 123 Topoi (2007) 26:271–277 DOI 10.1007/s11245-007-9024-x

William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

Stephen Read

Published online: 12 July 2007

� Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

William of Ockham’s Summa Logicae is a classic of ana-

lytical metaphysics, using a typical fourteenth century lo-

gic treatise to defend a reductionist ontology.1 For

Ockham, everything is an individual, and this is to be

shown by the correct logical analysis of language, rein-

terpreting Aristotle’s Categories as a taxonomy of the

many ways in which terms can be predicated. The ultimate

basis is the attribution of an individual quality to an indi-

vidual substance. This theory of the signification of terms is

then extended to an account of the truth-conditions of

propositions and the truth-preservation of arguments, but

always with the reduction to individuals as the key. This

classic work in the logical analysis of language still con-

tains lively insights for contemporary scholars.

Much of Part I of the Summa Logicae is taken up with

the notion of the signification of words. Indeed, like

Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, it opens with a

quotation from Augustine, in this case coupled to another

from Boethius reporting Aristotle’s three-fold division of

language from the start of his De Interpretatione. Terms

and the propositions of which they are composed are of

three types, written, spoken and mental: and ‘‘these con-

ceptual terms and the propositions composed from them

are those mental words which St Augustine in De Trinitate

XV said are of no language, because they remain only in

the mind and cannot be carried forth from it, whereas the

sounds subordinate to them as signs can be uttered pub-

licly.’’2

Two iconoclastic ideas are contained in germ in this

passage: first, the Augustinian conceit that concepts form a

mental language in parallel to spoken and written language;

secondly, the consequential insight that this language

cannot be signified by spoken and written language since it

is itself a language and so open to interpretation. Rather,

Ockham described spoken language, and written language

in turn, as subordinated to mental language, deriving its

signification from the signification of that language of

thought. Mental language too, as a language, needs to

obtain its interpretation and signification in some way. But

how? By being common to all men, as Aristotle said (De

Interpretatione 16a7)—but contrary to his observation that

all signs signify by convention (16a26)—mental terms

signify naturally, not by convention as do spoken and

written terms in different languages. But what do they

signify?

Here the London school of Ockham and his sympathizer

Wodeham, opposed by the realist Chatton, takes inspiration

from Avicenna’s commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics.

Everything which is one and not many is a singular and

individual thing. Nothing is common to other things except

by signification. The only universals are names. Avicenna

expresses this nominalist credo in a passage cited by

Ockham: ‘‘One form in the mind is related to many and in

this respect is a universal, since it is a concept in the mind

… This form, although universal in its relation to indi-

viduals, is individual in its relation to the particular mind in

1 See Ockham (1974) for the full critical edition of the Latin text.

Parts I and II, and a small part of Part III (which itself comprises more

than half the work), have been translated into English. For details, see

Spade (1999), 8.

S. Read (&)

Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, St

Andrews, Fife, Scotland, UK

e-mail: [email protected]

2 Ockham (1974), I 1: 7. All references to the Summa Logicae will be

to Ockham (1974), citing Part, chapter and page number.

123

Topoi (2007) 26:271–277

DOI 10.1007/s11245-007-9024-x

Page 2: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

which it is imprinted.’’ (I 14: 48) The idea is this: uni-

versals are words, whether spoken, written or mental.

Spoken and written words derive their signification from

being subordinated to mental words. Mental words are acts

of the mind, acts of cognition of, in general, extra-mental

things, all of which are individual. Some of these acts,

however, embrace many things—they are universal to

them, and unite them in a single mental act. These acts are

thereby universal.

Ockham did not always hold this view. He was per-

suaded of it by his Franciscan colleague Walter Chatton.

His earlier thought was this: everything is individual, but

we can think of universals. Hence universals must be

without real existence, but existing only as an object of

thought (tantum obiective—existing only ‘‘objectively’’).3

This is his notorious fictum theory: universals are fictive

entities existing only in thought. Chatton criticized the

theory presented in Ockham’s lectures on the Sentences in

his own lectures: either each fictum depends essentially on

the corresponding act of thought for its existence—in

which case we multiply ficta unacceptably for each and

every act—or it does not, in which case we could have a

fictum existing ‘‘objectively’’ (i.e., as the object of an act of

thought) without any act of thought—which is a plain

contradiction. The argument is invalid,4 but was so per-

suasive with Ockham that he repeated it verbatim in his

Quodlibetal Disputations presented shortly before com-

posing the Summa Logicae, and revised shortly afterwards,

possibly in Avignon.

What, then, is the object of an act of thought concerning

universals, for example, that Socrates is a man? It needs no

object other than men; indeed, that is what makes the act a

universal, its being common, by natural signification, to all

men. Ockham had already eliminated the intermediary

species (or form) in so-called ‘‘intuitive’’ cognition of

individuals—in thinking of Socrates I think of him, not of

or by means of any representative image; now in abstrac-

tive cognition, in abstracting the universal from a range of

individuals, what is formed is not the object of an

abstractive act, but the act itself which embraces, directly,

those individuals.

This reductive philosophy has dramatic, possibly

heretical, implications. For it occasions Ockham to rethink

entirely Aristotle’s project in his Categories. The bulk of

Part I of Summa Logicae is taken up with consideration of

the meaning of terms, which Ockham claims was Aris-

totle’s real project. But if nothing is universal except by

signification, then what fall into the categories are words,

not things. It is a classification of types of expression. But

names are of essentially two types, not ten. Either they

describe something absolutely and simply, like ‘man’ and

‘animal’; or they describe something indirectly, by con-

noting some accident of it, like ‘white’ or ‘cause’: ‘‘[con-

notative names] have what is, in the strict sense, called a

nominal definition. In the nominal definition of a conno-

tative term it is frequently necessary to put one expression

in the nominative case and another in one of the oblique

cases. The term ‘white’ provides an example … if someone

should ask for the nominal definition of ‘white’ the answer

would be … ‘something having a whiteness’.’’5

Ockham proceeds to show that all the divisions of

Aristotle’s non-substance categories are misleading and

unnecessary. Take privations, for example, like blindness.

This isn’t any real quality existing in the blind person, but

its lack or absence. It’s no more than a function of the way

words signify. Ockham cites Anselm in support of his

view. Language can mislead: ‘‘‘to fear’ is grammatically in

the active voice; in actual fact it is something passive.

Similarly, according to the form of speech blindness is said

to be something; in actual fact it is not anything at all.’’ (I

36: 119) Passions don’t inhere in subjects, but are only in

the mind (or loosely, in speech or in writing), for passions

are predicated of things, and only elements of propositions,

that is, words, are predicated. Indeed, substance is only a

word: first substance is a proper name, and second sub-

stance a common name: for example, ‘‘when Aristotle says

that if first substance was destroyed it would be impossible

for any of the other things to remain [2b4-6], he is not

talking of real distinction and real existence. He means,

rather, destructive by way of a negative proposition. Thus,

he is saying that when ‘to be’ is not predicated of anything

contained under a common term, it is only denied of the

common term itself as well as of the properties and acci-

dents proper to that common term.’’ (I 42: 134)

The most radical application of Ockham’s reduction of

the categories is elaborated in chs. 44–52 of Part I of the

Summa Logicae, where he denies the distinct reality of

quantity and relation. For the central doctrine of the Aris-

totelian categories is not only that they are exhaustive and

exclusive (distinct things belong to distinct categories) but

they are essential in that what is, for example, an animal (a

substance) is essentially an animal, and cannot cease to be

an animal without ceasing to be; a weight of five kilos (a

quantity) is essentially five kilos, distinct from a quantity of

six kilos; similarity (a relation) between two things is

essentially similarity, and cannot become a different rela-

tion; and so on. Ockham rejects this orthodox interpreta-

tion: the only essences are substance and quality. This

3 On the origin of the notions of objective and subjective existence,

and the almost total switch in their usage during the eighteenth cen-

tury, see Hamilton (1846), §I, especially the footnote to Proposition 6,

pp. 806–808.4 See, e.g., Adams (1987), 105 and Read (1977), 28. 5 Ockham (1974), I 10: 36.

272 S. Read

123

Page 3: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

claim is heretical,6 and Ockham realises it, so he attributes

the view to Aristotle, saying he will ‘‘outline the account

without committing myself to it.’’ (I 44: 145) Take quan-

tity, for example. The quantity of air in a container can

change, when it condenses or is rarefied. If quantity were a

real accident, this would be impossible unless the original

quantity were destroyed and replaced by an entirely new

quantity. Since condensation and rarefaction are continu-

ous, this would entail an actual infinity of quantities, which

all Aristotelians believe is impossible. The correct expla-

nation is that quantity is a connotative term, naming some

quantity of something. Quantity is not distinct from that

substance of which it is some quantity.

Ockham likewise denies the reality of points, lines and

surfaces distinct from the lines, surfaces and solids which

they delimit. For example, if lines were real parts of a

surface, there would be an actual infinity of them, which is

impossible. Rather, a surface is indefinitely divisible, and

each division creates a line, but only as the limit and so as

an attribute of the surface of the body. Again, time and

place are not real things; rather something has a quality at

some time at some place, so time and place connote attri-

butes of something real, but are not real separable entities

themselves.

In ch. 49, Ockham proceeds to argue that (for Aristotle,

at least) relations are not really distinct from their relata.

‘Relation’ is, he says, a term of second intention, that is,

relations are terms, not things, for they are, Aristotle says,

qualified by some expression in an oblique case (genitive,

dative or ablative): a father is father of someone, a cause is

a cause of something, something similar is similar to

something, a slave is someone’s slave. Relations are con-

notative names, naming one relatum and connoting the

other(s). So this is not to deny the division of the ten cat-

egories. There are indeed ten different types of terms, and

types of question one can ask. But underlying these lin-

guistic categories there are only two types of thing, sub-

stance and quality.

Why does Ockham maintain this dualism? He writes:

‘‘to determine when a quality should be posited as a thing

distinct from substance and when not, one can employ the

following test: predicables which, while incapable of being

truly applied to one thing at the same time, can succes-

sively hold true of an object merely as a result of a local

motion [motum localem], need not be construed as signi-

fying distinct things.’’ (I 55: 180) For example, something

straight becomes curved simply by the movement of its

parts, so curvature (curvitas) and straightness (rectitudo)

are not real qualities distinct from the curved and straight

substances; but this is not true of, for example, whiteness

and blackness or heat and cold, so these are real qualities.

This might seem to be an application of Ockham’s

Razor, but a closer look shows matters are more subtle. It’s

well known that the famous phrase, ‘‘Entia non sunt mul-

tiplicanda praeter necessitatem’’, occurs in many other

medieval authors besides Ockham. In fact, it is not found in

Ockham at all. The ontological principle which does guide

Ockham is cited by Adams (1987), 269: ‘‘It is impossible

for contraries to be successively true about the same thing

unless because of the locomotion of something or because

of the passage of time, or because of the production or

destruction of something.’’7 The closest Ockham comes to

the Razor, she says, is: ‘‘No plurality should be assumed

unless it can be proved by reason, or experience, or by

some infallible authority.’’8 This hardly says that entities

must not be multiplied beyond necessity, if necessity

means reason or experience: it defers to revelation—the

Bible and the sayings of the saints.9

Despite these qualifications, however, Ockham’s ap-

proach is reductive, at least as far as the denial of real

universals outside the mind is concerned. This comes out

strikingly in his theory of truth, detailed in Part II of the

Summa Logicae. In a notorious passage in ch. 2, he says

that a singular proposition like ‘Socrates is a man’ is not

true because Socrates has humanity, or because humanity is

in Socrates, or man is in Socrates, or that man is part of the

quidditative concept of Socrates. Rather, it is true simply

because ‘Socrates’ and ‘man’ are both names of Socrates,

the first a proper name, the second a common name. He

generalizes this to all atomic propositions using the tech-

nical notion of supposition. As he explains in I 63, strictly

speaking supposition is the relation of the subject-term to

what it stands for, whereas appellation is the corresponding

relation for predicates. But given that universals are no

more than names, predicates do not differ enough seman-

tically from subjects to justify two concepts, so broadly, he

says, both subject and predicate have supposition. Taken

significatively (that is, in the jargon, ‘‘personally’’), what

terms in a proposition supposit for depends on the tense

and mood of the copula. With a present-tense copula, a

term ‘/’ supposits for just those things which it signifies,

that is, of which it can be truly predicated in a singular

6 On the question whether Ockham’s ontological doctrines were in-

deed heretical, see e.g., Adams (1987), 979 ff.

7 Cited from Ockham (1979), 369. See also Adams (1987), 155, 176,

251 and 279.8 Adams (1987), 1008, citing his Treatise on Quantity, which is

probably a surviving fragment of the Reportatio of Book I of his

Sentences corresponding to the revised Ordinatio at Ockham (1979),

290.9 Ockham did not believe the Pope or the Church were included

among the infallible, as dramatically demonstrated by the fact that, on

examining the question of apostolic poverty, Ockham accused Pope

John XXII himself of heresy.

William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic 273

123

Page 4: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

proposition, ‘This is / ’. Now take an indefinite or par-

ticular proposition of the form ‘Some / is w’. This is true

just when ‘/’ and ‘w’ supposit for the same, that is, are

truly predicable of the same thing. Its contradictory, the

universal negative, ‘No / is w’, is true if ‘/’ and ‘w’ do not

supposit for anything in common. Its contrary in turn,

‘Every / is w’, is true, following standard medieval prac-

tice in preserving the square of opposition, if ‘/’ supposits

for something and ‘w’ supposits for everything for which

‘/’ supposits. Finally, the contradictory of the universal

affirmative, namely, the particular negative, ‘Some / is not

w’, or perhaps better, ‘Not every / is w’, is true if ‘/’ does

not supposit for something for which ‘w’ supposits—so in

particular, it is true if ‘/’ supposits for nothing.

Geach (1972) deplored Ockham’s introduction of this

‘‘two-name theory’’ (as Geach called it) as compounding

by a further ‘‘corruption of logic’’ Aristotle’s initial fall

from grace in introducing the ‘‘two-term theory’’ inherent

in the theory of the syllogism. To read Geach, one would

think Ockham had jettisoned the linguistic dualism of

subject and predicate to proclaim a monism of substance

and name. But that is not the doctrine. Terms name indi-

viduals either by signifying their essential natures (sub-

stance) or connoting their accidents (quality). Without the

dualism of substance and quality, Ockham would find

himself drawn into a Leibnizian necessity where each

predication was essential. Connotation of accidents main-

tains the contingency of accidental predication. What he

avoids in all this is any regress of instantiation, as we saw

in the passage from Summa Logicae II 2: ‘‘for all propo-

sitions such as these are false: ‘Man is of the quiddity of

Socrates’, ‘Man is of the essence of Socrates’, ‘Humanity

is in Socrates’, ‘Socrates has humanity’, ‘Socrates is a man

in virtue of humanity’,’’ and so on. All that is required is

that there be Socrates, the individual, and his individual

qualities, whiteness, snub-nosedness and so on, what are

nowadays called ‘‘tropes’’.10 The world is a collocation of

substance and quality.

This sounds very like Humean supervenience. To be

sure, as stated by David Lewis, that doctrine incorporates

physicalism; he writes: ‘‘Humean supervenience … is the

doctrine that all there is to the world is a vast mosaic of

local matters of particular fact … maybe point-sized bits of

matter … [a]nd at those points, we have local qualities.’’11

But Lewis concedes that materialism is included in the

doctrine only to endorse ‘‘our best physics’’. Indeed,

Ockham goes further: not only does everything supervene

on local matters of fact; it is reducible to them. At least,

that is his project.

At the heart of the theory is the singular predication,

‘This is /’. It is also used to define the modes of common

personal supposition needed to frame the non-syllogistic

modes of inference. Take determinate supposition, for

example, which some 70 years earlier, Lambert of Lagny

(1988, 111) had described vaguely as ‘‘what a common

term has when it can be taken equally well for one or for

more than one, as when one says ‘A man is running’.’’

Ockham makes this idea precise by the doctrine of ascent

and descent, whereby he can relate the modes of supposi-

tion of common terms to that of discrete terms like ‘this’.

‘‘Determinate supposition occurs when it is possible to

descend to singulars by way of a disjunctive proposition.

Thus, the following is a good inference: a man runs,

therefore this man runs or that man and so on for singu-

lars.’’ (I 70: 210) Ockham is not the first to exploit descent

and ascent in the definition of the modes of common per-

sonal supposition. Walter Burley did so 20 years earlier, at

least if we correct the reading in Brown’s edition of Bur-

ley’s early treatise De Suppositionibus (which otherwise is

nonsense): ‘‘Determinate supposition occurs when a com-

mon term supposits disjunctively [reading disiunctive for

Brown’s distributive] for supposita as here ‘Some man

runs’. Whence by determinate supposition and disjunctive

[reading disiunctive with MS C] supposition I understand

the same.’’12 Burley goes on to characterize merely con-

fused supposition (e.g., in the predicate of A-propositions)

when one can ascend from any singular (‘Every / is this

w’) but cannot descend conjunctively or disjunctively;

confused and distributive supposition (e.g., the subject of

A-propositions) when one can descend conjunctively.

Ockham follows him in this, adding that in the case of

merely confused supposition, one can descend by way of a

disjunct predicate: from ‘Every / is w’ infer ‘Every / is

this w or that w and so on’. Though not original to Ockham,

the doctrine of ascent and descent suits his reductive pur-

poses perfectly, in taking every case back to the singular

predication, ‘This is / ’. For example, from ‘Every / is w’

we can first infer ‘Every / is this w or that w and so on’,

then infer ‘This / is this w or that w … and that / is this wor that w … and …’, and finally infer a conjunction of

disjunctions of the form ‘This / is that w’, true just when

subject and predicate co-supposit.

Thus the truth-conditions of non-modal present-tense

propositions can be reduced to that of singulars. What,

however, of past-tense, future-tense, modal and intensional

propositions? Here Ockham is radical and original, but

alone. Other authors deal with such cases by invoking the

doctrine of ampliation. Ampliation is that property of terms

which extends (‘‘ampliates’’) the supposition of terms to

past, future and possible (or even impossible) supposita.10 See, e.g., Campbell (1990).11 Lewis (1986), ix–x. 12 Brown (1972), 38.

274 S. Read

123

Page 5: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

However, the way ampliation works on them is different.

Moreover, there is a significant difference between the

treatment in Britain and in Paris. In Paris, past- and future-

tense propositions are given a disjunctive interpretation.

For example, ‘Some / was w’ is said to be true if and only

if something which either is or was / (at some time) was w(at some time—not necessarily the same time). Burley and

Ockham, however, treat it as ambiguous, either as saying

that what is / was w or as saying that what was / was w.

Even if something that is / was w, the proposition is

accordingly false on one reading, whereas on the Parisian

account it will come out unequivocally true. For modal

propositions, both groups treat them as ambiguous, but

differently from tensed propositions. ‘Some / must be w’,

for example, has both a compounded sense, that ‘Some / is

w’ is necessarily true, and a divided sense, saying of

something which is / that it must be w. It’s easy to miss

this dissimilarity between tensed and modal propositions,

and indeed, Ockham’s remarks in Part III-4 encourage it,

where he sets out the analysis of tensed propositions side

by side in a way that at first glance looks analogous. But in

fact it is not. He writes: a modal ‘‘proposition should be

distinguished because the subject-term can stand for those

that are or for those that can be or for those that can be and

can not be.’’ (III-4 4: 763). It’s that final ‘‘can be and can

not be’’ (contingit esse) which shows up the difference. In

the composite sense, ‘Some / must be w’ is true if ‘Some

/ is w’ is necessarily true, i.e., true for all time and in all

possibilities, and in those possibilities, ‘This is / and w’

can be true where ‘this’ refers to contingent existents which

do not actually exist. Nonetheless, the truth-condition is

radically different in structure from that of ‘Some / were

w’.

Although there is no unequivocal statement of his po-

sition, it seems clear that Ockham is both a presentist and

an actualist. What exists is what actually exists now. A

presentist thinks belief to the contrary arises only from

sloppy use of tensed expressions. Neither the past nor the

future exists,13 but are what did or will exist. Similarly, no

mere possibilia exist—rather, they might or might have

existed. Thus the truth-condition of tensed and modal

propositions is repeatedly given in terms of the past, future

or possible truth of present-tense propositions. Take modal

propositions in the divided sense, for example. Ockham

reduces their truth to that of ‘‘a non-modal proposition in

which the very same predicate is predicated of a pronoun

indicating that for which the subject supposits’’ (II 10:

276), effecting a recursive reduction of the truth-conditions

of all propositions to that of singulars.

Much of Ockham’s account of consequence in Part III is

framed in terms of the syllogism, non-modal and modal. To

a modern logician, the treatment is frustratingly particular

and unsystematic, treating every possible combination of

premise-pair and conclusion in the three figures separately.

Once modal syllogisms are introduced, with mixed pre-

mises where the mode of either can be ‘necessary’, ‘pos-

sible’, ‘contingent’ or ‘impossible’, or one can be non-

modal, or from another mode such as ‘known’ or ‘be-

lieved’, the sheer variety is overwhelming. After 68

chapters of Part III-1, and a further 41 on the demonstrative

syllogism in III-2, treatise III-3 appears to promise some

relief: a general account of consequence. But what we find

in fact is an addendum to the theory of two-premise

inference in the syllogism, namely, one-premise inference,

again treated piecemeal with little systematic generaliza-

tion.

This is unfortunate, because there is an underlying

systematization available. Aristotle himself showed this for

the non-modal syllogism: the dictum de omni et nullo

grounds first-figure syllogisms, and simple and per acci-

dens conversion and reduction per impossibile reduce

validity in the second and third figures to the first. But such

systematization was not the medievals’ forte, and it has its

costs, for it encourages concentration on cases that fit the

chosen Procrustean bed, overlooking others (e.g., first-or-

der predicate logic is very powerful, but it does not prop-

erly represent arguments containing demonstratives,

common nouns, mass terms and many others). The medi-

evals revelled in diversity, and it is part of Ockham’s

contribution to the theory of the modal syllogism that he

extends the treatment to cases Aristotle had overlooked,

resolving the so-called problem of the ‘‘two Barbaras’’.14

Aristotle accepts modal Barbara where major premise and

conclusion have the mode of necessity (and the minor is

non-modal) but not when the minor is a necessity propo-

sition and the major is non-modal. This suggests that he

reads ‘w necessarily applies to all /’ de re (or in the di-

vided sense). But so read, it does not convert per accidens,

as Aristotle says it should (25a29), and as it would if read

de dicto.15

Ockham diagnoses the ambiguity and works out the

detail of what follows for each combination of premises

(III-1 31). In fact, there is a double ambiguity, for not only

may the modal premise be taken in a compounded or a

divided sense, but the non-modal premise may be true

absolutely (simpliciter) or only as-of-now (ut nunc, at

13 See, e.g., Ockham (1978) ch. 10, p. 211: ‘‘Moreover, no part of

time exists because neither the past nor the future do; so time is not

something really existing totally distinct from other things.’’

14 See, e.g., Thom (2003), 27–30.15 Of course, the compounded/divided distinction is broader than, but

includes the de dicto/de re distinction. For example, any proposition

of the form ‘You believe p and not-p’ has compounded and divided

senses, but is not ambiguous de dicto/de re.

William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic 275

123

Page 6: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

present but not always). Given that all propositions true

absolutely are necessarily true, then whether the modal

minor is taken in the divided or compounded senses, the

syllogism is valid provided the non-modal major premise is

true absolutely. But if the major is only true at present, and

not necessarily or absolutely, the syllogism is invalid.

Karger (1976, 185–90) infers that Ockham adopts the

Diodorean account of necessity and equates necessary truth

with truth at all times, by reference to Summa Logicae II 9:

275. But this passage merely claims that a necessarily true

proposition is only true when it exists. In fact, Ockham

nowhere defines what it is for a proposition to be true

‘‘simpliciter’’ or ‘‘ut nunc’’ as such. However, if we turn to

Part III-3 ch. 1, where he defines inference ut nunc et

simpliciter, we find him conclude in ch. 2: ‘‘for when a

predication of a superior of an inferior is necessary, then

the inference is absolute; but when the predication of a

superior of an inferior is contingent, then the inference is

only ut nunc.’’ (III-3 2: 591) All becomes clear when we

turn to the definitions in ch. 1: ‘‘Inference ut nunc is when

the premise can be true at some time without the conclu-

sion but not at this time … Absolute inference is when at

no time could the premise be true without the conclusion.’’

(III-3 1: 587–8) So rather than equate necessary truth with

truth at all times, Ockham equates absolute truth with

necessary truth. Absolute truth is already a modal notion.

Ockham’s treatment of intensional propositions other

than modals, e.g., ‘I promise you a horse’ or ‘I know the

one approaching’, is again reductionist. These proposi-

tions open the door to sophistical reasoning: consider, for

example, the crooked horse-dealer who points to each

horse in turn, asking rhetorically: ‘Did I promise you this

horse?’. He claims there is no (particular) horse he

promised you, and so no particular horse he need give

you. There’s obviously a fallacy here, and in Part III-4

Ockham proceeds to discuss and illustrate Aristotle’s 13

types of misleading constructions. He diagnoses this

example as falling under the third type of equivocation,

diversity of supposition (III-4 4): ‘horse’ doesn’t exhibit

a lexical ambiguity (the first type), where a word has

different meanings; nor is there any extended or meta-

phorical meaning (the second type) to ‘horse’ in this

example. De Rijk argued persuasively in the 1960s that

the spur to the development of the medieval theory of

supposition was a desire to create a technical tool for

diagnosing fallacies like this, and Ockham applies it here

in what seems a novel way. Burley argued that ‘horse’ in

this example had simple supposition, for the universal

horse.16 The promise is fulfilled by giving the universal

in the only way possible, in a particular horse. Ockham

has to reject this: if universals are just acts of mind,

then what was promised was certainly not an act of

mind. Rather, what was promised was a horse. So how

does ‘horse’ supposit in ‘I promise you a horse’? It can

supposit either determinately, or merely confusedly.

Taken the first way, the proposition is false—there was

no particular horse he promised you; taken the second

way, it is true, for ‘horse’ is equivalent to ‘this horse

or that horse and so on’, provided the disjunction

ranges over horses which may be given you, namely,

present and future horses (again, Ockham does not

speak of ampliation). So ‘I promise you a horse’ is

equivalent to ‘I promise you this horse or that horse

and so on’, but not to ‘I promise you this horse or I

promise you that horse and so on’, so ‘horse’ supposits

merely confusedly and not determinately. (See I 72:

219) Accordingly, the rule forbidding the move from

merely confused to determinate supposition explains

the fallacy.

The puzzle of the hooded man cannot be solved in this

way. If I know Coriscus and Coriscus is the one

approaching, then it seems I must know the one

approaching. Ockham agrees—that argument is valid. The

puzzle arises, he says, because we confuse this argument

with a different one, for example, Coriscus is the man and

Coriscus is the one approaching, so the one approaching is

the man—a valid expository syllogism. However, if we

know the major premise, it does not follow that we know

the conclusion. It is a fallacy of accident, for it does not

always follow that ‘‘when some things are conjoined in

predication with a third, they are mutually conjoined in a

valid conclusion.’’ (III-4 11: 819) To know the one

approaching I would have to know that Coriscus was the

one approaching, that is, know both premises and not just

one of them.

To conclude: how does Ockham’s Summa Logicae

fare as a classic? Can it still provide inspiration for

contemporary scholars, as a source of fresh ideas and

insights? The opening words of Adams (1987) are crucial

to this evaluation; she writes: ‘‘Ockham’s philosophical

focus, whether he is doing logic, natural science, or

theology, is on the branch of metaphysics commonly

called ‘ontology’.’’ (p. 3) The Summa Logicae is a classic

of philosophy, more narrowly of metaphysics, not of

logic. Ockham uses the context of a work on logic, in the

broader sense of the philosophy of logic and language, to

defend his central reductive ontological theme. As a work

of logic, it is embedded in its own cultural milieu; as a

work of reductionist metaphysics, it is timely and time-

less. The Summa Logicae is a model of analytical

metaphysics whose reductive metaphysics is as arresting

now as it was in 1324.16 Burley (2000), 96.

276 S. Read

123

Page 7: William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic

References

Adams MM (1987) William Ockham. University of Notre Dame

Press, Notre Dame

Brown SF (1972) Walter Burleigh’s treatise De suppositionibus and

its influence on William of Ockham. Fran Stud 32:15–64

Burley W (2000) On the purity of the art of logic, tr. P.V. Spade. Yale

University Press, New Haven and London

Campbell K (1990) Abstract particulars. Blackwell, Oxford

Geach PT (1972) ‘History of the corruptions of logic’, in his Logic

matters. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 44–61

Hamilton W (1846) Of presentative and representative knowledge. In:

Hamilton W (ed) The works of Thomas Reid DD. Maclachlan

Stewart, Edinburgh, pp 804–815

Karger E (1976) A study in William of Ockham’s modal logic, Ph.D.

thesis. University of California, Berkeley

Lambert of Lagny (Lambert of Auxerre) (1988) Properties of terms.

In: Kretzmann N, Stump E (eds) The Cambridge translations of

medieval philosophical texts, vol I. Cambridge University Press,

Cambridge, pp 102–162

Lewis DK (1986) Introduction. In: Lewis DK Philosophical papers,

vol II. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp ix–xvii

Spade PV (1999) Introduction. In: Spade PV (ed) The Cambridge

companion to Ockham. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,

pp 1–16

Ockham William of (G. de Ockham) (1978) Expositio in librum

praedicamentorum Aristotelis. In: Gal G (ed) Opera philosoph-

ica, vol II. Franciscan Institute Publications, St Bonaventure

Ockham William of (G. de Ockham) (1979) Scriptum in librum

primum sententiarum ordinatio, distinctiones XIX–XLVIII, In:

Etzkorn G, Kelley F (eds) Opera theologica, vol IV. Franciscan

Institute Publications: St Bonaventure

Ockham William of (G. de Ockham) (1974) Summa logicae. In:

Boehner P, Gal G, Brown S (eds) Opera philosophica, vol I. St

Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute Publications

Read S (1977) The objective being of Ockham’s ficta. Philos Quart

27:14–31

Thom P (2003) Medieval modal systems. Ashgate, Aldershot/

Burlington

William of Ockham’s The Sum of Logic 277

123