5
What's So Great about Feeling Good? Author(s): Laura A. King and James W. Pennebaker Source: Psychological Inquiry, Vol. 9, No. 1 (1998), pp. 53-56 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1449612 . Accessed: 14/06/2014 20:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Psychological Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

What's So Great about Feeling Good?

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

What's So Great about Feeling Good?Author(s): Laura A. King and James W. PennebakerSource: Psychological Inquiry, Vol. 9, No. 1 (1998), pp. 53-56Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1449612 .

Accessed: 14/06/2014 20:53

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PsychologicalInquiry.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

COMMENTARIES

Note

Kelli A. Keough, Department of Psychology, Uni- versity of Texas, Austin, TX 78712.

References

Brown, J. D., & Dutton, K. A. (1995). The thrill of victory, the complexity of defeat: Self-esteem and people's emotional reac- tions to success and failure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68, 712-722.

Crocker, J., & Major, B. (1989). Social stigma and self-esteem: The self-protective properties of stigma. Psychological Review, 96, 608-630.

Fiske, A. P., Kitayama, S., Markus, H. R., & Nisbett, R. E. (1998). The cultural matrix of social psychology. In D. Gilbert, S. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (4th ed).

Franks, M. M., Herzog, A. R., & Markus, H. R. (1994, November). Self-making and well-being. Paper presented at the 47th meeting of the Gerontological Society of America, Atlanta, GA.

Harber, K. D., & Pennebaker, J. W. (1992). Overcoming traumatic memories. In S. Christianson (Ed.), The handbook of emotion and memory research and theory (pp. 359-387). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

Hobfoll, S. E. (1989). Conservation of resources: A new attempt at conceptualizing stress. American Psychologist, 44, 513-524.

Keough, K. A., Garcia, J., & Steele, C. M. (1997). Reducing stress and illness by affirming the self Unpublished manuscript, Stan- ford University, Stanford, CA.

Kitayama, S., & Markus, H. R. (Eds.). (1994). Emotion and culture: Empirical studies of mutual influence. Washington, DC: Ameri- can Psychological Association.

Linville, P. W. (1987). Self-complexity as a cognitive buffer against stress-related illness and depression. Journal of Personality and

Social Psychology, 52, 663-676. Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implica-

tions for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Review, 98, 224-253.

Markus, H., & Wurf, E. (1987). The dynamic self-concept: A social psychological perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 38, 299-337.

Pennebaker, J. W., & Francis, M. E. (1996). Cognitive, emotional, and language processes in disclosure. Cognition and Emotion, 10, 601-626.

Rowe, J. W., & Kahn, R. L. (1987). Human aging: Usual and successful. Science, 237, 143-149.

Sacks, 0. W. (1995). Anthropologist on Mars: Seven paradoxical tales. New York: Knopf.

Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (in press). The big three of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the big three explanations of suffering. Morality & Health.

Spencer, S. J., Josephs, R. A., & Steele, C. M. (1993). Low self-es- teem: The uphill struggle for self-integrity. In R. Baumeister (Ed.), Self-esteem: The puzzle of low self-regard (pp. 21-36). New York: Plenum.

Steele, C. M. (1988). The psychology of self-affirmation: Sustaining the integrity of the self. Advances in Experimental Social Psy- chology, 21, 261-302.

Steele, C. M. (1990, August). Protecting the self. Implications for social psychological theory and minority achievement. Paper presented at the 98th meeting of the American Psychological Association, Boston.

Taylor, S. E. (1983). Adjustment to threatening events: A theory of cognitive adaption. American Psychologist, 38, 1161-1173.

Taylor, S. E., Neter, E., & Wayment, H. A. (1995). Self-evaluation processes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 21, 1278-1287.

Tesser, A. (1988). Toward a self-evaluation maintenance model of social behavior. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 21, 181-227.

What's So Great About Feeling Good?

Laura A. King and James W. Pennebaker Department of Psychology

Southern Methodist University

It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied. Better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.

John Stuart Mill

Ryff and Singer present a breathtakingly compre- hensive analysis of what it is that constitutes a life well- lived. In so doing, they bring up an important and often-ignored dilemma presented in most empirical research on subjective well-being: that typically, hap- piness is equated with a good life. It is difficult to argue against the importance of happiness to the good life.

Aristotle argued that all goals were valued only to the extent that they related ultimately to happiness. All other goals are essentially sought in the service of the happiness they promise. Research on life goals and wishes confirms that the pursuit of happiness is a com- mon desire. Richards (1966) found that happiness was a common goal among college students. Schwartz and Bilsky (1987) identified enjoyment as a central dimen- sion of human values. The wish for happiness was among the top three wishes among participants in a study by King and Broyles (1997). Clearly, people want to be happy. Yet, as Ryff and Singer acknowledge,

53

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

COMMENTARIES

history is filled with examples of individuals whose lives were by no means good but who were nevertheless happy, as well as people whose lives were by most accounts good ones, but who were by no means happy. Considering psychological well-being in this light is an enormous challenge: How do we separate the good life from considerations of personal happiness?

Ryff and Singer attempt to confront this issue by focusing not on feelings of happiness, but instead on a sense of purpose or meaning in life. The distinction between meaning in life and happiness is an impor- tant one. Unfortunately the distinction is difficult to make and maintain; for the most part such a differ- ence is lost throughout Ryff and Singer's discussion. One reason for this difficulty is that meaning in life and happiness are interwoven constructs, conceptu- ally and empirically.

Separating meaning in life and happiness presents quite an empirical challenge. Certainly, meaning in human life may contribute to the good life, independent of happiness. A person may suffer greatly and still possess a strong sense of purpose (Frankl, 1985). How- ever, and importantly, meaning in life is not only a characteristic of a good life; it is also a correlate of happiness (e.g., Zika & Chamberlain, 1992). Research on generativity-the sense that one has left a meaning- ful legacy for the future-also supports the notion that experiencing a sense of purpose is a vital part of feeling happy (McAdams & de St. Aubin, 1992; McAdams, de St. Aubin, & Logan, 1993).

Self-report measures of meaning in life are likely to tap into positive affect and feelings of satisfaction. Indeed, such relations are presented as evidence for the construct validity of these measures. For example, the Sense of Coherence Scale (Antonovsky, 1988) corre- lates positively with measures of happiness, well-being, and so forth. It is not surprising that measures including items like, "There is always a solution to the painful things in life," and "Most of the things I do in the future will probably be interesting and fascinating" (An- tonovsky, 1988) should tap into positive affect. This conflation of happiness and meaning is not only a characteristic of self-report questionnaires, but is also typical of many theories of human development. The more developed individual is also the one who is more psychologically adjusted-living happily ever after (with the exception of Loevinger's conception; Loev- inger & Hy, 1996).

Ryff and Singer have highlighted this issue dramati- cally. Their call for the use of multiple methods of measurement is laudable. Triangulating quantitative and qualitative measures certainly will be necessary to bring clarity to this very complex but important issue.

54

In the remainder of this commentary, we seek to expli- cate how focus on negative experiences and suffering provides a means out of the happiness-meaning in life conundrum. We agree that the positive aspects of life have not held the prominence in research that they should, yet we hope to demonstrate that it may be in difficult times that the goods of life truly come to the fore. The tendency of previous research to focus on negative life events is not necessarily a negative bias; rather, we propose that it is in the context of negative life events that the human capacity for positive func- tioning, for experiencing realistic joy, and for develop- ment are most dramatically manifested.

Defensive Processes: Health or Happiness?

Ryff and Singer focus on the essential connections between the mind and body but do not fully grapple with those times when the mind and body disagree. Defensive processes provide a fine example of the ways that mind-body asynchronies may enter into the experience of "the good life" for some individuals. Certainly a great deal of research has shown that some individuals who report a great deal of well-being are actually engaged in psychological defense. We may view such individuals as engaged in "healthy" positive illusion (a la Taylor & Brown, 1988) or more poten- tially destructive repression or denial (e.g., Shedler, Mayman, & Manis, 1993; Weinberger, 1990). In any case, researchers from a variety of areas have acknow- ledged that reality may play a minimal role in the lives of seemingly happy people. Setting aside for the tiimie being the idea that some of this defensiveness is symp- tomatic of psychological health, research examining more destructive defensive processes tends to show that the appearance (and experience) of psychological well-being may take its toll on the body through auto- nomic and cardiovascular activity. This line of re- search tends to indicate that, for individuals who en- gage in such defenses, the mind says one thing and the body another.

Considering the issue of defense mechanisms leads to another set of issues suggested by Ryff and Singer's ideas. We concur with Ryff and Singer's call for the inclusion of psychological and physiological measures whenever possible, in research on well-being. How- ever, such multiple measurements will inevitably lead to a line of questioning that has not really been ad- dressed: Which outcome measures are paramount? In a sense, if the mind and body always agreed, this question would not need asking. But psychological well-being

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

COMMENTARIES

may exist amidst physical illness and psychological distress may certainly exist in the absence of physical illness. When these important variables disagree, where does the psychologist stand? Is happiness, meaning, or survival the outcome variable of choice?

Ryff and Singer call for research that focuses on positive functioning, but the possibility of confounding positive functioning with psychological defense may be another reason for focus on negative states in past research. If individuals are dealing directly with nega- tive life experience, then the issues of defensiveness become less problematic.

The Implicit Quality of the Wonderful Life

Even without considering the issues of awareness and defenses, we are left with a dilemma in terms of measuring the good life. That is, most of the time the wonderful life is being lived not thought about (cf., Csikszentmihalyi, 1990). George Bailey didn't recog- nize that he was, in fact, living "a wonderful life," until circumstances forced him to realize it. Why is it that we "don't know what we've got 'til it's gone?"

Emotion theorists have discussed at some length the informative character of negative emotion (e.g., Mar- tin, Tesser, & McIntosh, 1993). Feeling bad tells us that we need to take action to reduce the negative feeling. The informative aspect of positive emotions is another story; if we are feeling good we want to con- tinue feeling good. This sort of framework acknow- ledges that the default setting for most of us is to try to be happy-as happy or happier than we were just a moment ago.

Ryff and Singer rightly acknowledge that negative life events are often opportunities for positive change. It may be that negative experience provides the appro- priate context through which to study and understand positive functioning. The challenge, in teasing apart meaning in life and happiness, is to find people who have forsaken the implicit search for happiness (at least temporarily) to explicitly seek some other end (King, 1997). One possible answer to these questions involves focusing on individuals who have experienced extreme circumstances (i.e., traumatic events or other life- changing experiences).

The ability to appreciate and enjoy the good things in life almost demands the ability to get beyond the painful parts of existence. When a friend dies or we are faced with failure, we often have great difficulty com- ing to terms with the events. Depression, rumination, and illness are all hallmarks of dealing with traumatic events. To return to the good life, then, we must under-

stand why the trauma occurred (to help us avoid facing a similar one in the future) and see its impact on the various facets of our lives.

Talking or writing about traumas is one way by which to move past them. In our earlier work, we discovered that having people write about their deepest thoughts and feelings about traumas resulted in initial feelings of distress. But, within weeks, those who had disclosed their traumas reported greater happiness and well-being than controls who had written about super- ficial topics (e.g., Pennebaker, 1989). More detailed analyses of these studies indicates that the ways people write makes a tremendous difference. Linguistically, for example, the more that people use positive emotion words and, to a moderate degree, negative emotion words, the better their subsequent health. Getting past a trauma, then, demands a certain acknowledgment of all of the emotional consequences of an event. When a friend dies, for example, it may be important to recall the positive times during his or her life as well as the emotional support one felt in the wake of the death (King & Miner, 1997; Pennebaker, Mayne, & Francis, 1997).

Although acknowledging the emotional domains of a trauma is beneficial, it is perhaps more important that the person organizes the event cognitively. Our data suggest that it is critical for individuals to construct a story or narrative to explain the traumatic experience. Constructing a story, rather than having a story per se, may be one of the keys to moving from reliving a trauma to returning to the good life. Thus, finding and experi- encing meaning serves as a stepping stone to the good life. Looking at individuals confronting a traumatic life event allows us to examine the search for meaning in the absence of the search for happiness. That is, con- fronting traumas is likely to be an upsetting experience but in allowing oneself to be upset, the individual is free to seek meaning. Research on negative life circum- stances isn't necessarily "biased" as much as it is a reflection of human life-"if it ain't broke, we don't fix it." Importantly, difficult life experiences also can serve to promote personal growth (Helson & Roberts, 1994). Negative events provide individuals with invaluable opportunities for self-discovery and provide us as re- searchers invaluable opportunities to observe human capacities for redemption and to examine the search for meaning apart from happiness.

On certain points we agree wholeheartedly with Ryff and Singer. Feeling good and having many or- gasms is unquestionably great. But these lofty states cannot be reached unless one's emotional life is in order. When we begin to look beyond feeling good to issues of gaining insight and wisdom, to the lessons of

55

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

COMMENTARIES

illness and health, then we might be getting into truly uncharted territory.

Notes

Preparation of this commentary was supported by National Institute of Mental Health/FIRST Award 54142 to Laura A. King.

Laura A. King and James W. Pennebaker, Psychol- ogy Department, Southern Methodist University, Dal- las, TX 75275-0442. E-mail: [email protected]

References

Antonovsky, A. (1988). Unraveling the mystery of health. San Fran- cisco: Jossey-Bass.

Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow. New York: Harper & Row. Frankl, V. E. (1985). Man's search for meaning. New York: Simon

& Schuster. Helson, R., & Roberts, B. (1994). Ego development and personality

change in adulthood. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- ogy, 66, 911-920.

King, L. A. (1997, May). What makes life worth living? Paper presented at the Midwestern Psychological Association Con- vention, Chicago.

King, L. A., & Broyles, S. (1997). Wishes, gender, personality, and well-being. Journal of Personality, 65, 50-75.

King, L. A., & Miner, K. N. (1997). Writingabout the perceived benefits of trauma: Implications for health and well-being. Unpublished manuscript. Southern Methodist University, Dallas, TX.

Loevinger, J., & Hy, L. X. (1996). Measuring ego development (2nd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

Martin, L. L., Tesser, A., & McIntosh, W. D. (1993). Wanting but not having: The effects of unattained goals on thoughts and feelings. In D. M. Wegner & J. W. Pennebaker (Eds.), Handbook of mental control (pp. 552-572). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

McAdans, D. P., & de St. Aubin, E. (1992). A theory of generativity and its assessment through self-report, behavioral acts, and narrative themes in autobiography. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 1003-1015.

McAdams, D. P., de St. Aubin, E., & Logan, R. L. (1993). Genera- tivity among young, mid-life, and older adults. Psychology and Aging, 8, 221-230.

Pennebaker, J. W. (1989). Confession, inhibition, and disease. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 22, pp. 211-244). New York: Springer-Verlag.

Pennebaker, J. W., Mayne, T. J., & Francis, M. (1997). Linguistic predictors of adaptive bereavement. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, 863-871.

Richards, J. M., Jr. (1966). Life goals of American college freshmen. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 13, 12-20.

Schwartz, S. H., & Bilsky, W. (1987). Toward a universal psycho- logical structure of human values. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 550-562.

Shedler, J., Mayman, M., & Manis, M. (1993). The illusion of mental health. American Psychologist, 48, 1117-1131.

Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological Bul- letin, 103, 193-210.

Weinberger, D. A. (1990). The construct validity of the repressive coping style. In J. L. Singer (Ed.), Repression and dissociation: Implications for personality theory, psychopathology, and health (pp. 337-386). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Zika, S., & Chamberlain, K. (1992). On the relation of meaning in life to psychological well-being. British Journal of Psychology, 83, 133-145.

The Quest for Long-Term Health and Happiness: To Play or Not to Play, That Is the Question

Jaak Panksepp Department of Psychology

Bowling Green State University

Public health issues are typically considered in terms of three major dimensions: (a) the genetic and physi- ological strengths and weaknesses of individuals, (b) the environmental factors that support us and stressors that assail us, and (c) the psychological processes that modify our behaviors in desirable and undesirable ways. The last of these dimensions is where psycholo- gists have traditionally had the most input, with one of the most important modern contributions being the analysis of self-efficacy (Bandura, 1995, 1997). In the arena of public health, population issues and personal issues rarely come together in meaningful ways.

56

Now, Ryff and Singer offer a wide-ranging post- modern conceptualization of individual human health and happiness, in which subjective personal issues loom larger than ever before. Taking a philosophical-psy- chobehavioral point of view, they entreat us to greater efforts in the pursuit of wholistic mind-body health as opposed to the traditional alleviation of bodily misery and illness. After summarizing some philosophy con- cerning "the goods" of life, they outline a broad and dynamic strategy for conceptualizing the psychological and physiological correlates of positive health-states of being that are notoriously hard to objectify.

This content downloaded from 194.29.185.145 on Sat, 14 Jun 2014 20:53:33 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions