165
UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTS EARLY HORIZONTAL RESTRAINT CASES: KEY LANGUAGE Chicago Board of Trade (US 1918) (Brandeis, J): “But the legality of an agreement or regulation cannot be determined by so simple a test, as whether it restrains competition. Every agreement concerning trade, every regulation of trade, restrains. To bind, to restrain, is of their very essence. The true test of legality is whether the restraint imposed is such as merely regulates and perhaps thereby promotes competition or whether it is such as may suppress or even destroy competition. To determine that question the court must ordinarily consider the facts peculiar to the business to which the restraint is applied; its condition before and after the restraint was imposed; the nature of the restraint and its effect, actual or probable. The history of the restraint, the evil believed to exist, the reason for adopting the particular remedy, the purpose or end sought to be obtained are all relevant facts. This is not because a good intention will save an otherwise objectionable regulation or the reverse; but because knowledge of intent may help the court to interpret facts and predict consequences.” Socony-Vacuum (U.S. 1940) (Douglas, J.): Footnote 59: “... a conspiracy to fix prices violates section 1 of the act though no overt act is shown, though it is not established that the conspirators had the means available for accomplishment of their objective, and though the conspiracy embraced but as part of the interstate or foreign commerce in the commodity.... Price-fixing agreements may or may not be aimed at complete elimination of price competition. The group making those agreements may or may not have the power to control the market. But the fact that the group cannot control the market prices does not necessarily mean that the agreement as to prices has no utility to the members of the combination. The effectiveness of price-fixing agreements 63

UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    0

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTS

EARLY HORIZONTAL RESTRAINT CASES: KEY LANGUAGE

Chicago Board of Trade (US 1918) (Brandeis, J): “But the legality of an agreement or regulation cannot be determined by so simple a test, as whether it restrains competition. Every agreement concerning trade, every regulation of trade, restrains. To bind, to restrain, is of their very essence. The true test of legality is whether the restraint imposed is such as merely regulates and perhaps thereby promotes competition or whether it is such as may suppress or even destroy competition. To determine that question the court must ordinarily consider the facts peculiar to the business to which the restraint is applied; its condition before and after the restraint was imposed; the nature of the restraint and its effect, actual or probable. The history of the restraint, the evil believed to exist, the reason for adopting the particular remedy, the purpose or end sought to be obtained are all relevant facts. This is not because a good intention will save an otherwise objectionable regulation or the reverse; but because knowledge of intent may help the court to interpret facts and predict consequences.”

Socony-Vacuum (U.S. 1940) (Douglas, J.): Footnote 59: “... a conspiracy to fix prices violates section 1 of the act though no overt act is shown, though it is not established that the conspirators had the means available for accomplishment of their objective, and though the conspiracy embraced but as part of the interstate or foreign commerce in the commodity.... Price-fixing agreements may or may not be aimed at complete elimination of price competition. The group making those agreements may or may not have the power to control the market. But the fact that the group cannot control the market prices does not necessarily mean that the agreement as to prices has no utility to the members of the combination. The effectiveness of price-fixing agreements is dependent on many factors, such as competitive tactics, position in the industry, the formula underlying price policies. Whatever economic justifications particular price-fixing activities are thought to have, the law does not permit an inquiry into their reasonableness. They are all banned because of their actual or potential threat to the central nervous system of the economy.

“The existence or exertion of power to accomplish the desired objective becomes important only in cases where the offense charged is actual monopolizing of any part of trade or commerce in violation of section 2....”

$ $ $ $ $ $ $

63

Page 2: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The Conspiracy Element Of Sherman Act §1 Horizontal Cases

I. How Do We Count to Two?

A. Need 2 actors to have section one claim. What if economically related?B. Courts have uniformly rejected “conspiracies” between

1. officers of corporation re corporate behavior 2. between parent & fully integrated subsidiary

C. Copperweld (1984): parent can't conspire w separately incorporated subsidiaryD. Current issues

1. Conspiracy between firm and agents of firm who have some independent economic interests: fact sensitive analysis

2. Common example: between members of hospital staff & hospital itself3. Sports Leagues: Single entity or agreement between competitors

II. Proving Conspiracy: General Concepts

A. OVERVIEW: Proving Agreement1. Often easy: express agreement 2. Often harder questions

a. Discussions without explicit agreementb. Parallel conduct without evidence of explicit agreement.

3. Approach to determining if agreement:a. Treat like detective story: collect circumstantial evidenceb. Motive: Do economic conditions that encourage cartels to formc. Means/Opportunity: does market allow cartel operation

i) need to be able to set pricesii) need to be able to monitor prices

B. Factors Suggesting Probability of Oligopoly Behavior1. Industry Structure

a. High market concentrationb. Entry conditions

i) high barriers to entryii) absence of potential entrants/fringe players

c. Profit & cost informationi) long run profits above normalii) high ratio of fixed to variable costs

d. structure of consumers' demandi) consumer insensitivity to priceii) relatively static demandiii) dispersion of buyers

64

Page 3: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

2. Nature of Producta. Homogeneous products make cartel easierb. Broad product line/differentiated product

i) difficult to maintain cartelii) may result in oligopoly structure

c. Products subject to technical change: hard to cartel3. Nature of Sales Process

a. uneven or secret sales: harder to cartelb. loyal buyers: easier to cartelc. best: buyer reports price info accurately

4. Price Patterns (often hard to interpret)a. parallel prices unclear indicatorb. price stability unclear indicatorc. price changes v. rest of economy

III. Cases Involving Parallel Behavior

A. Interstate Circuit (1939): motion picture exhibitor sent letters to 8 largest distributors demanding that they not allow competing theatres to charge low prices for 2d run showings or to run double features. All the distributors follow the demanded restrictions in 4 cities, but refuse to follow them in others. The Court infers a conspiracy.

B. Theatre Enterprises (1954): Motion picture distributors refuse to license first-run movies to a theatre in the outskirts of Baltimore, which claims a conspiracy to favor downtown theatres. Court finds that the distributors had good independent reasons not to deal, and refuses to infer conspiracy.

C. Bogosian: 3d Cir. 1977: (example of common test) proof of conscious parallel action not enough to show agreement unless

1. would be against the economic interests of defendant if acting alone AND2. defendant has a motive to enter the agreement

D. Mere parallel conduct won't establish conspiracy so look for plus factors:1. Evidence of communication2. motive3. actions against self-interest4. facilitating practices (see Unit IIE)5. too-strong coincidences

$ $ $ $ $ $ $

65

Page 4: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

NATIONAL SOCIETY OF PROFESSIONAL ENGINEERS v. U.S. 435 U.S. 679 (1978)

Mr. Justice STEVENS delivered the opinion of the Court. This is a civil antitrust case brought by the U.S. to nullify an association’s canon of ethics prohibiting competitive bidding by its members. The question is whether the canon may be justified under the Sherman Act … because it was adopted by members of a learned profession for the purpose of minimizing the risk that competition would produce inferior engineering work endangering the public safety. The District Court rejected this justification without making any findings on the likelihood that competition would produce the dire consequences foreseen by the association. The Court of Appeals affirmed. We granted certiorari to decide whether the District Court should have considered the factual basis for the proffered justification before rejecting it. Because we are satisfied that the asserted defense rests on a fundamental misunderstanding of the Rule of Reason frequently applied in antitrust litigation, we affirm.

I. Engineering is an important and learned profession. There are over 750,000 graduate engineers in the United States, of whom about 325,000 are registered as professional engineers. Registration requirements vary from State to State, but usually require the applicant to be a graduate engineer with at least four years of practical experience and to pass a written examination. About half of those who are registered engage in consulting engineering on a fee basis. They perform services in connection with the study, design, and construction of all types of improvements to real property–bridges, office buildings, airports, and factories are examples. Engineering fees, amounting to well over $2 billion each year, constitute about 5% of total construction costs. In any given facility, approximately 50% to 80% of the cost of construction is the direct result of work performed by an engineer concerning the systems and equipment to be incorporated in the structure.

The National Society of Professional Engineers (Society) was organized in 1935 to deal with the non-technical aspects of engineering practice, including the promotion of the professional, social, and economic interests of its members. Its present membership of 69,000 resides throughout the United States and in some foreign countries. Approximately 12,000 members are consulting engineers who offer their services to governmental, industrial, and private clients. Some Society members are principals or chief executive officers of some of the largest engineering firms in the country.

The charges of a consulting engineer may be computed in different ways. He may charge the client a percentage of the cost of the project, may set his fee at his actual cost plus overhead plus a reasonable profit, may charge fixed rates per hour for different types of work, may perform an assignment for a specific sum, or he may combine one or more of these approaches. Suggested fee schedules for particular types of services in certain areas have been promulgated from time to time by various local societies. This case does not, however, involve any claim that the National Society has tried to fix specific fees, or even a specific method of calculating fees. It involves a charge that the members of the Society have unlawfully agreed to refuse to negotiate or even to discuss the question of fees until after a prospective client has selected the engineer for a

66

Page 5: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

particular project. Evidence of this agreement is found in §11(c) of the Society’s Code of Ethics, adopted in July 1964.3

The District Court found that the Society’s Board of Ethical Review has uniformly interpreted the “ethical rules against competitive bidding for engineering services as prohibiting the submission of any form of price information to a prospective customer which would enable that customer to make a price comparison on engineering services.” If the client requires that such information be provided, then §11(c) imposes an obligation upon the engineering firm to withdraw from consideration for that job. The Society’s Code of Ethics thus “prohibits engineers from both soliciting and submitting such price information,”5 and seeks to preserve the profession’s “traditional” method of selecting professional engineers. Under the traditional method, the client initially selects an engineer on the basis of background and reputation, not price.6

In 1972 the Government filed its complaint against the Society alleging that members had agreed to abide by canons of ethics prohibiting the submission of competitive bids for engineering services and that, in consequence, price competition among the members had been suppressed and customers had been deprived of the benefits of free and open competition. The complaint prayed for an injunction terminating the unlawful agreement.

In its answer the Society admitted the essential facts alleged by the Government and pleaded a series of affirmative defenses, only one of which remains in issue. In that

3 That section, which remained in effect at the time of trial, provided:

Section 11—The Engineer will not compete unfairly with another engineer by attempting to obtain employment or advancement or professional engagements by competitive bidding... .

c. He shall not solicit or submit engineering proposals on the basis of competitive bidding. Competitive bidding for professional engineering services is defined as the formal or informal submission, or receipt, of verbal or written estimates of cost or proposals in terms of dollars, man days of work required, percentage of construction cost, or any other measure of compensation whereby the prospective client may compare engineering services on a price basis prior to the time that one engineer, or one engineering organization, has been selected for negotiations. The disclosure of recommended fee schedules prepared by various engineering societies is not considered to constitute competitive bidding. An Engineer requested to submit a fee proposal or bid prior to the selection of an engineer or firm subject to the negotiation of a satisfactory contract, shall attempt to have the procedure changed to conform to ethical practices, but if not successful he shall withdraw from consideration for the proposed work. These principles shall be applied by the Engineer in obtaining the services of other professions.

5 Although the Society argues that it has never “enforced” its ban on competitive bidding, the District Court specifically found that the record “support[s] a finding that NSPE and its members actively pursue a course of policing adherence to the competitive bid ban through direct and indirect communication with members and prospective clients.” This finding has not been challenged as clearly erroneous.

6 Having been selected, the engineer may then, in accordance with the Society’s canons of ethics, negotiate a satisfactory fee arrangement with the client. If the negotiations are unsuccessful, then the client may withdraw his selection and approach a new engineer.

67

Page 6: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

defense, the Society averred that the standard set out in the Code of Ethics was reasonable because competition among professional engineers was contrary to the public interest. It was averred that it would be cheaper and easier for an engineer “to design and specify inefficient and unnecessarily expensive structures and methods of construction.” Accordingly, competitive pressure to offer engineering services at the lowest possible price would adversely affect the quality of engineering. Moreover, the practice of awarding engineering contracts to the lowest bidder, regardless of quality, would be dangerous to the public health, safety, and welfare. For these reasons, the Society claimed that its Code of Ethics was not an “unreasonable restraint of interstate trade or commerce.”

The parties compiled a voluminous discovery and trial record. The District Court made detailed findings about the engineering profession, the Society, its members’ participation in interstate commerce, the history of the ban on competitive bidding, and certain incidents in which the ban appears to have been violated or enforced. The District Court did not, however, make any finding on the question whether, or to what extent, competition had led to inferior engineering work which, in turn, had adversely affected the public health, safety, or welfare. That inquiry was considered unnecessary because the court was convinced that the ethical prohibition against competitive bidding was “on its face a tampering with the price structure of engineering fees in violation of §1 of the Sherman Act.”

Although it modified the injunction entered by the District Court,8 the Court of Appeals affirmed its conclusion that the agreement was unlawful on its face and therefore “illegal without regard to claimed or possible benefits.”

II. In Goldfarb v. Virginia State Bar, 421 U.S. 773, the Court held that a bar association’s rule prescribing minimum fees for legal services violated §1 of the Sherman Act. In that opinion the Court noted that certain practices by members of a learned profession might survive scrutiny under the Rule of Reason even though they would be viewed as a violation of the Sherman Act in another context. The Court said:

The fact that a restraint operates upon a profession as distinguished from a business is, of course, relevant in determining whether that particular restraint violates the Sherman Act. It would be unrealistic to view the practice of professions as interchangeable with other business activities, and automatically to apply to the professions antitrust concepts which originated in other areas. The public service aspect, and other features of the professions, may require that a particular practice, which could properly be viewed as a violation of the Sherman Act in another context, be treated differently. We intimate no view on any other situation than the one with which we are confronted today.

421 U.S., at 788-789, n.17.

Relying heavily on this footnote, and on some of the major cases applying a Rule of Reason—principally Mitchel v. Reynolds, 24 Eng.Rep. 347 (1711); Standard Oil Co.

8 The Court of Appeals struck down the portion of the District Court’s decree that ordered the Society to state that it did not consider competitive bidding to be unethical. The court reasoned that this provision was “more intrusive than necessary to achieve fulfillment of the governmental interest.” The Government has not petitioned for review of that decision.

68

Page 7: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

v. U.S., 221 U.S. 1; Chicago Board of Trade v. U.S., 246 U.S. 231; and Continental T.V. v. GTE Sylvania, 433 U.S. 36—petitioner argues that its attempt to preserve the profession’s traditional method of setting fees for engineering services is a reasonable method of forestalling the public harm which might be produced by unrestrained competitive bidding. To evaluate this argument it is necessary to identify the contours of the Rule of Reason and to discuss its application to the kind of justification asserted by petitioner.

A. The Rule of Reason. One problem presented by the language of §1 of the Sherman Act is that it cannot mean what it says. The statute says that “every” contract that restrains trade is unlawful. But, as Mr. Justice Brandeis perceptively noted, restraint is the very essence of every contract;10 read literally, §1 would outlaw the entire body of private contract law. Yet it is that body of law that establishes the enforceability of commercial agreements and enables competitive markets–indeed, a competitive economy–to function effectively.

Congress, however, did not intend the text of the Sherman Act to delineate the full meaning of the statute or its application in concrete situations. The legislative history makes it perfectly clear that it expected the courts to give shape to the statute’s broad mandate by drawing on common-law tradition. The Rule of Reason, with its origins in common-law precedents long antedating the Sherman Act, has served that purpose. It has been used to give the Act both flexibility and definition, and its central principle of antitrust analysis has remained constant. Contrary to its name, the Rule does not open the field of antitrust inquiry to any argument in favor of a challenged restraint that may fall within the realm of reason. Instead, it focuses directly on the challenged restraint’s impact on competitive conditions.

This principle is apparent in even the earliest of cases applying the Rule of Reason, Mitchel v. Reynolds. Mitchel involved the enforceability of a promise by the seller of a bakery that he would not compete with the purchaser of his business. The covenant was for a limited time and applied only to the area in which the bakery had operated. It was therefore upheld as reasonable, even though it deprived the public of the benefit of potential competition. The long-run benefit of enhancing the marketability of the business itself–and thereby providing incentives to develop such an enterprise–outweighed the temporary and limited loss of competition.

The Rule of Reason suggested by Mitchel v. Reynolds has been regarded as a standard for testing the enforceability of covenants in restraint of trade which are ancillary to a legitimate transaction, such as an employment contract or the sale of a going business. Judge (later Mr. Chief Justice) Taft so interpreted the Rule in his classic rejection of the argument that competitors may lawfully agree to sell their goods at the same price as long as the agreed-upon price is reasonable. U.S. v. Addyston Pipe & Steel Co., 85 F. 271, 282-283 (CA6 1898), aff’d, 175 U.S. 211. That case, and subsequent 10 “But the legality of an agreement or regulation cannot be determined by so simple a test, as whether it restrains competition. Every agreement concerning trade, every regulation of trade, restrains. To bind, to restrain, is of their very essence.” Chicago Board of Trade; see also U.S. v. Topco Associates, 405 U.S. 596, 606: “Were §1 to be read in the narrowest possible way, any commercial contract could be deemed to violate it.”

69

Page 8: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

decisions by this Court, unequivocally foreclose an interpretation of the Rule as permitting an inquiry into the reasonableness of the prices set by private agreement.13

The early cases also foreclose the argument that because of the special characteristics of a particular industry, monopolistic arrangements will better promote trade and commerce than competition. U.S. v. Trans-Missouri Freight Assn., 166 U.S. 290; U.S. v. Joint Traffic Assn., 171 U.S. 505, 573-577. That kind of argument is properly addressed to Congress and may justify an exemption from the statute for specific industries,14 but it is not permitted by the Rule of Reason. As the Court observed in Standard Oil Co. v. U.S., 221 U.S., at 65, “restraints of trade within the purview of the statute ... [can]not be taken out of that category by indulging in general reasoning as to the expediency or nonexpediency of having made the contracts, or the wisdom or want of wisdom of the statute which prohibited their being made.”

The test prescribed in Standard Oil is whether the challenged contracts or acts “were unreasonably restrictive of competitive conditions.” Unreasonableness under that test could be based either (1) on the nature or character of the contracts, or (2) on surrounding circumstances giving rise to the inference or presumption that they were intended to restrain trade and enhance prices. Under either branch of the test, the inquiry is confined to a consideration of impact on competitive conditions. … [T]he inquiry mandated by the Rule of Reason is whether the challenged agreement is one that promotes competition or one that suppresses competition. …

There are, thus, two complementary categories of antitrust analysis. In the first category are agreements whose nature and necessary effect are so plainly anticompetitive that no elaborate study of the industry is needed to establish their illegality–they are “illegal per se.” In the second category are agreements whose competitive effect can only be evaluated by analyzing the facts peculiar to the business, the history of the restraint, and the reasons why it was imposed. In either event, the purpose of the analysis is to form a judgment about the competitive significance of the restraint; it is not to decide whether a policy favoring competition is in the public interest, or in the interest of the members of an industry. Subject to exceptions defined by statute, that policy decision has been made by the Congress.

B. The Ban on Competitive Bidding. Price is the “central nervous system of the economy,” Socony-Vacuum, and an agreement that “interfere[s] with the setting of price by free market forces” is illegal on its face. U.S. v. Container Corp., 393 U.S. 333, 337. In this case we are presented with an agreement among competitors to refuse to discuss prices with potential customers until after negotiations have resulted in the initial selection of an engineer. While this is not price fixing as such, no elaborate industry analysis is required to demonstrate the anticompetitive character of such an agreement. It operates as an absolute ban on competitive bidding, applying with equal force to both

13 85 F., at 293. See also U.S. v. Trans-Missouri Freight Assn., 166 U.S. 290, 340-342.

14 Congress has exempted certain industries from the full reach of the Sherman Act. See, e.g., 7 U.S.C. §§291-292 (Capper-Volstead Act, agricultural cooperatives); 15 U.S.C. §§1011-1013 (McCarran-Ferguson Act, insurance); 49 U.S.C. §5b (Reed-Bulwinkle Act, rail and motor carrier rate-fixing bureaus); 15 U.S.C. §1801 (newspaper joint operating agreements).

70

Page 9: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

complicated and simple projects and to both inexperienced and sophisticated customers. As the District Court found, the ban “impedes the ordinary give and take of the market place,” and substantially deprives the customer of “the ability to utilize and compare prices in selecting engineering services.” On its face, this agreement restrains trade within the meaning of §1 of the Sherman Act.

The Society’s affirmative defense confirms rather than refutes the anticompetitive purpose and effect of its agreement. The Society argues that the restraint is justified because bidding on engineering services is inherently imprecise, would lead to deceptively low bids, and would thereby tempt individual engineers to do inferior work with consequent risk to public safety and health.19 The logic of this argument rests on the assumption that the agreement will tend to maintain the price level; if it had no such effect, it would not serve its intended purpose. The Society nonetheless invokes the Rule of Reason, arguing that its restraint on price competition ultimately inures to the public benefit by preventing the production of inferior work and by insuring ethical behavior. As the preceding discussion … reveals, this Court has never accepted such an argument.

It may be, as petitioner argues, that competition tends to force prices down and that an inexpensive item may be inferior to one that is more costly. There is some risk, therefore, that competition will cause some suppliers to market a defective product. Similarly, competitive bidding for engineering projects may be inherently imprecise and incapable of taking into account all the variables which will be involved in the actual performance of the project. Based on these considerations, a purchaser might conclude that his interest in quality–which may embrace the safety of the end product–outweighs the advantages of achieving cost savings by pitting one competitor against another. Or an individual vendor might independently refrain from price negotiation until he has satisfied himself that he fully understands the scope of his customers’ needs. These decisions might be reasonable; indeed, petitioner has provided ample documentation for that thesis. But these are not reasons that satisfy the Rule; nor are such individual decisions subject to antitrust attack.

19 The Society also points out that competition, in the form of bargaining between the engineer and customer, is allowed under its canon of ethics once an engineer has been initially selected. It then contends that its prohibition of competitive bidding regulates only the timing of competition, thus making this case analogous to Chicago Board of Trade, where the Court upheld an exchange rule which forbade exchange members from making purchases after the close of the day’s session at any price other than the closing bid price. Indeed, petitioner has reprinted the Government’s brief in that case to demonstrate that the Solicitor General regarded the exchange’s rule as a form of price fixing. We find this reliance on Chicago Board of Trade misplaced for two reasons. First, petitioner’s claim mistakenly treats negotiation between a single seller and a single buyer as the equivalent of competition between two or more potential sellers. Second, even if we were to accept the Society’s equation of bargaining with price competition, our concern with Chicago Board of Trade is in its formulation of the proper test to be used in judging the legality of an agreement; that formulation unquestionably stresses impact on competition. Whatever one’s view of the application of the Rule of Reason in that case, the Court considered the exchange’s regulation of price information as having a positive effect on competition. The District Court’s findings preclude a similar conclusion concerning the effect of the Society’s “regulation.”

71

Page 10: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The Sherman Act does not require competitive bidding;21 it prohibits unreasonable restraints on competition. Petitioner’s ban on competitive bidding prevents all customers from making price comparisons in the initial selection of an engineer, and imposes the Society’s views of the costs and benefits of competition on the entire marketplace. It is this restraint that must be justified under the Rule of Reason, and petitioner’s attempt to do so on the basis of the potential threat that competition poses to the public safety and the ethics of its profession is nothing less than a frontal assault on the basic policy of the Sherman Act.

The Sherman Act reflects a legislative judgment that ultimately competition will produce not only lower prices, but also better goods and services. “The heart of our national economic policy long has been faith in the value of competition.” Standard Oil Co. v. FTC, 340 U.S. 231, 248. The assumption that competition is the best method of allocating resources in a free market recognizes that all elements of a bargain–quality, service, safety, and durability–and not just the immediate cost, are favorably affected by the free opportunity to select among alternative offers. Even assuming occasional exceptions to the presumed consequences of competition, the statutory policy precludes inquiry into the question whether competition is good or bad.

The fact that engineers are often involved in large-scale projects significantly affecting the public safety does not alter our analysis. Exceptions to the Sherman Act for potentially dangerous goods and services would be tantamount to a repeal of the statute. In our complex economy the number of items that may cause serious harm is almost endless–automobiles, drugs, foods, aircraft components, heavy equipment, and countless others, cause serious harm to individuals or to the public at large if defectively made. The judiciary cannot indirectly protect the public against this harm by conferring monopoly privileges on the manufacturers.

By the same token, the cautionary footnote in Goldfarb, quoted supra, cannot be read as fashioning a broad exemption under the Rule of Reason for learned professions. We adhere to the view expressed in Goldfarb that, by their nature, professional services may differ significantly from other business services, and, accordingly, the nature of the competition in such services may vary. Ethical norms may serve to regulate and promote this competition, and thus fall within the Rule of Reason.22 But the Society’s argument in this case is a far cry from such a position. We are faced with a contention that a total ban on competitive bidding is necessary because otherwise engineers will be tempted to 21 Indeed, Congress has decided not to require competitive bidding for Government purchases of engineering services. The Brooks Act, 40 U.S.C. §§541-544, requires the Government to use a method of selecting engineers similar to the Society’s “traditional method.” See n.6, supra. The Society relies heavily on the Brooks Act as evidence that its ban on competitive bidding is reasonable. The argument is without merit. The Brooks Act does not even purport to exempt engineering services from the antitrust laws, and the reasonableness of an individual purchaser’s decision not to seek lower prices through competition does not authorize the vendors to conspire to impose that same decision on all other purchasers.

22 Courts have, for instance, upheld marketing restraints related to the safety of a product, provided that they have no anticompetitive effect and that they are reasonably ancillary to the seller’s main purpose of protecting the public from harm or itself from product liability.

72

Page 11: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

submit deceptively low bids. Certainly, the problem of professional deception is a proper subject of an ethical canon. But, once again, the equation of competition with deception, like the similar equation with safety hazards, is simply too broad; we may assume that competition is not entirely conducive to ethical behavior, but that is not a reason, cognizable under the Sherman Act, for doing away with competition.

In sum, the Rule of Reason does not support a defense based on the assumption that competition itself is unreasonable. Such a view of the Rule would create the “sea of doubt” on which Judge Taft refused to embark in Addyston, and which this Court has firmly avoided ever since. … The judgment of the Court of Appeals is Affirmed.

Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, with whom Mr. Justice REHNQUIST joins, concurring in part and concurring in the judgment. I join Part[] I of the Court’s opinion and concur in the judgment. I do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court appears to me to do in intimating any ethical rule with an overall anticompetitive effect promulgated by a professional society is forbidden under the Sherman Act. In my view, the decision in Goldfarb properly left to the Court some flexibility in considering how to apply traditional Sherman Act concepts to professions long consigned to self-regulation. Certainly, this case does not require us to decide whether the “Rule of Reason” as applied to the professions ever could take account of benefits other than increased competition. For even accepting petitioner’s assertion that product quality is one such benefit, and that maintenance of the quality of engineering services requires that an engineer not bid before he has made full acquaintance with the scope of a client’s desired project, petitioner Society’s rule is still grossly overbroad. As petitioner concedes, §11(c) forbids any simultaneous consultation between a client and several engineers, even where the client provides complete information to each about the scope and nature of the desired project before requesting price information. To secure a price estimate on a project, the client must purport to engage a single engineer, and so long as that engagement continues no other member of the Society is permitted to discuss the project with the client in order to provide comparative price information. Though §11(c) does not fix prices directly, and though the customer retains the option of rejecting a particular engineer’s offer and beginning negotiations all over again with another engineer, the forced process of sequential search inevitably increases the cost of gathering price information, and hence will dampen price competition, without any calibrated role to play in preventing uninformed bids. Then, too, the Society’s rule is overbroad … when it prevents any dissemination of competitive price information in regard to real property improvements prior to the engagement of a single engineer regardless of “the sophistication of the purchaser, the complexity of the project, or the procedures for evaluating price information.”

My skepticism about going further in this case by shaping the Rule of Reason to such a narrow last as does the majority,* arises from the fact that there may be ethical rules which have a more than de minimis anticompetitive effect and yet are important in a progression’s proper ordering. A medical association’s prescription of standards of

* This Court has not always applied the Rule of Reason with such rigor even to commercial businesses. See Appalachian Coals, Inc. v. U.S., 288 U.S. 344 (1933); Chicago Board of Trade. I intimate no view as to the correctness of those decisions.

73

Page 12: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

minimum competence for licensing or certification may lessen the number of entrants. A bar association’s regulation of the permissible forms of price advertising for non-routine legal services or limitation of in-person solicitation, see Bates v. State Bar of Arizona, 433 U.S. 350 (1977), may also have the effect of reducing price competition. In acknowledging that “professional services may differ significantly from other business services” and that the “nature of the competition in such services may vary,” but then holding that ethical norms can pass muster under the Rule of Reason only if they promote competition, I am not at all certain that the Court leaves enough elbow room for realistic application of the Sherman Act to professional services.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $NCAA v. BOARD of REGENTS of the UNIV. of OKLAHOMA

468 U.S. 85 (1984)

Justice STEVENS delivered the opinion of the Court. The University of Oklahoma and the University of Georgia contend that the National Collegiate Athletic Association has unreasonably restrained trade in the televising of college football games. After an extended trial, the District Court found that the NCAA had violated §1 of the Sherman Act…. The Court of Appeals agreed that the statute had been violated …. We granted certiorari, and now affirm.

I. The NCAA. Since its inception in 1905, the NCAA has played an important role in the regulation of amateur collegiate sports. It has adopted and promulgated playing rules, standards of amateurism, standards for academic eligibility, regulations concerning recruitment of athletes, and rules governing the size of athletic squads and coaching staffs. In some sports, such as baseball, swimming, basketball, wrestling, and track, it has sponsored and conducted national tournaments. It has not done so in the sport of football, however. With the exception of football, the NCAA has not undertaken any regulation of the televising of athletic events.

The NCAA has approximately 850 voting members. The regular members are classified into separate divisions to reflect differences in size and scope of their athletic programs. Division I includes 276 colleges with major athletic programs; in this group only 187 play intercollegiate football. Divisions II and III include approximately 500 colleges with less extensive athletic programs. Division I has been subdivided into Divisions I-A and I-AA for football.

Some years ago, five major conferences together with major football-playing independent institutions organized the College Football Association (CFA). The original purpose of the CFA was to promote the interests of major football-playing schools within the NCAA structure. The Universities of Oklahoma and Georgia, respondents in this Court, are members of the CFA.

History of the NCAA Television Plan … On January 11, 1951, a three-person “Television Committee,” appointed during the preceding year, delivered a report to the NCAA’s annual convention in Dallas. Based on preliminary surveys, the committee had concluded that “television does have an adverse effect on college football attendance and unless brought under some control threatens to seriously harm the nation’s overall

74

Page 13: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

athletic and physical system.” The report emphasized that “the television problem is truly a national one and requires collective action by the colleges.” As a result, the NCAA decided to retain the National Opinion Research Center (NORC) to study the impact of television on live attendance, and to declare a moratorium on the televising of football games. A television committee was appointed to implement the decision and to develop an NCAA television plan for 1951.

The committee’s 1951 plan provided that only one game a week could be telecast in each area, with a total blackout on 3 of the 10 Saturdays during the season. A team could appear on television only twice during a season. The plan also provided that the NORC would conduct a systematic study of the effects of the program on attendance. The plan received the virtually unanimous support of the NCAA membership; only the University of Pennsylvania challenged it, … announc[ing] that it would televise all its home games. The council of the NCAA thereafter declared Pennsylvania a member in bad standing and the four institutions scheduled to play at Pennsylvania in 1951 refused to do so. Pennsylvania then reconsidered its decision and abided by the NCAA plan.

During each of the succeeding five seasons, studies were made which tended to indicate that television had an adverse effect on attendance at college football games. During those years the NCAA continued to exercise complete control over the number of games that could be televised. From 1952 through 1977 the NCAA television committee followed essentially the same procedure for developing its television plans. It would first circulate a questionnaire to the membership and then use the responses as a basis for formulating a plan for the ensuing season. The plan was then submitted to a vote by means of a mail referendum. Once approved, the plan formed the basis for NCAA’s negotiations with the networks. Throughout this period the plans retained the essential purposes of the original plan. Until 1977 the contracts were all for either 1- or 2-year terms. In 1977 the NCAA adopted “principles of negotiation” for the future and discontinued the practice of submitting each plan for membership approval. Then the NCAA also entered into its first 4-year contract granting exclusive rights to the American Broadcasting Cos. (ABC) for the 1978-1981 seasons. ABC had held the exclusive rights to network telecasts of NCAA football games since 1965.

The Current Plan The plan adopted in 1981 for the 1982-1985 seasons is at issue in this case. This plan, like each of its predecessors, recites that it is intended to reduce, insofar as possible, the adverse effects of live television upon football game attendance. It provides that “all forms of television of the football games of NCAA member institutions during the Plan control periods shall be in accordance with this Plan.” The plan recites that the television committee has awarded rights to negotiate and contract for the telecasting of college football games of members of the NCAA to two “carrying networks.” In addition to the principal award of rights to the carrying networks, the plan also describes rights for a “supplementary series” that had been awarded for the 1982 and 1983 seasons, as well as a procedure for permitting specific “exception telecasts.”

In separate agreements with each of the carrying networks, ABC and the Columbia Broadcasting System (CBS), the NCAA granted each the right to telecast the 14 live “exposures” described in the plan, in accordance with the “ground rules” set forth therein. Each of the networks agreed to pay a specified “minimum aggregate compensation to the participating NCAA member institutions” during the 4-year period

75

Page 14: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

in an amount that totaled $131,750,000. In essence the agreement authorized each network to negotiate directly with member schools for the right to televise their games. The agreement itself does not describe the method of computing the compensation for each game, but the practice that has developed over the years and that the District Court found would be followed under the current agreement involved the setting of a recommended fee by a representative of the NCAA for different types of telecasts, with national telecasts being the most valuable, regional telecasts being less valuable, and Division II or Division III games commanding a still lower price. The aggregate of all these payments presumably equals the total minimum aggregate compensation set forth in the basic agreement. Except for differences in payment between national and regional telecasts, and with respect to Division II and Division III games, the amount that any team receives does not change with the size of the viewing audience, the number of markets in which the game is telecast, or the particular characteristic of the game or the participating teams. Instead, the “ground rules” provide that the carrying networks make alternate selections of those games they wish to televise, and thereby obtain the exclusive right to submit a bid at an essentially fixed price to the institutions involved.11

The plan also contains “appearance requirements” and “appearance limitations” which pertain to each of the 2-year periods that the plan is in effect. The basic requirement imposed on each of the two networks is that it must schedule appearances for at least 82 different member institutions during each 2-year period. Under the appearance limitations no member institution is eligible to appear on television more than a total of six times and more than four times nationally, with the appearances to be divided equally between the two carrying networks. The number of exposures specified in the contracts also sets an absolute maximum on the number of games that can be broadcast.

Thus, although the current plan is more elaborate than any of its predecessors, it retains the[ir] essential features…. It limits the total amount of televised intercollegiate football and the number of games that any one team may televise. No member is permitted to make any sale of television rights except in accordance with the basic plan.

Background of this Controversy. Beginning in 1979, CFA members began to advocate that colleges with major football programs should have a greater voice in the formulation of football television policy than they had in the NCAA. CFA therefore … developed an independent plan, and obtained a contract offer from the National Broadcasting Co. (NBC). This contract, which it signed in August 1981, would have allowed a more liberal number of appearances for each institution, and would have increased the overall revenues realized by CFA members.

11 District Court explained how the agreement eliminates competition for broadcasting rights:

First, the networks have no intention to engage in bidding. Second, once the network holding first choice for any given date has made its choice and agreed to a rights fee for that game with the two teams involved, the other network is then in a monopsony position. The schools cannot threaten to sell the broadcast rights to any other network. They cannot sell to NBC without committing a violation of NCAA rules. They cannot sell to the network which had first choice over that particular date because, again, they would be in violation of NCAA rules, and the network would be in violation of its agreement with NCAA. Thus, NCAA creates a single eligible buyer for the product of all but the two schools selected by the network having first choice. Free market competition is thus destroyed under the new plan.

76

Page 15: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

In response the NCAA publicly announced that it would take disciplinary action against any CFA member that complied with the CFA-NBC contract. The NCAA made it clear that sanctions would not be limited to the football programs of CFA members, but would apply to other sports as well. On September 8, 1981, respondents commenced this action … and obtained a preliminary injunction preventing the NCAA from initiating disciplinary proceedings or otherwise interfering with CFA’s efforts to perform its agreement with NBC. Notwithstanding the entry of the injunction, most CFA members were unwilling to commit themselves to the new contractual arrangement with NBC in the face of the threatened sanctions and therefore the agreement was never consummated.

Decision of the District Court. After a full trial, the District Court held that the controls exercised by the NCAA over the televising of college football games violated the Sherman Act. The District Court defined the relevant market as “live college football television” because it found that alternative programming has a significantly different and lesser audience appeal. The District Court then concluded that the NCAA controls over college football are those of a “classic cartel” with an

almost absolute control over the supply of college football which is made available to the networks, to television advertisers, and ultimately to the viewing public. Like all other cartels, NCAA members have sought and achieved a price for their product which is, in most instances, artificially high. The NCAA cartel imposes production limits on its members, and maintains mechanisms for punishing cartel members who seek to stray from these production quotas. The cartel has established a uniform price for the products of each of the member producers, with no regard for the differing quality of these products or the consumer demand for these various products.

The District Court found that competition … had been restrained in three ways: (1) NCAA fixed the price for particular telecasts; (2) its exclusive network contracts were tantamount to a group boycott of all other potential broadcasters and its threat of sanctions against its own members constituted a threatened boycott of potential competitors; and (3) its plan placed an artificial limit on the production of televised college football.

… [T] he NCAA offered two principal justifications for its television policies: that they protected the gate attendance of its members and that they tended to preserve a competitive balance among the football programs of the various schools. The District Court rejected the first justification because the evidence did not support the claim that college football television adversely affected gate attendance. With respect to the “competitive balance” argument, the District Court found that the evidence failed to show that the NCAA regulations on matters such as recruitment and the standards for preserving amateurism were not sufficient to maintain an appropriate balance.

Decision of the Court of Appeals. The Court of Appeals held that the NCAA television plan constituted illegal per se price fixing. It rejected each of the three arguments advanced by NCAA to establish the procompetitive character of its plan. First, the court rejected the argument that the television plan promoted live attendance, noting that since the plan involved a concomitant reduction in viewership the plan did not result in a net increase in output and hence was not procompetitive. Second, the Court of Appeals rejected as illegitimate the NCAA’s purpose of promoting athletically balanced competition. It held that such a consideration amounted to an argument that “competition

77

Page 16: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

will destroy the market”–a position inconsistent with the policy of the Sherman Act. Moreover, assuming arguendo that the justification was legitimate, the court agreed with the District Court’s finding “that any contribution the plan made to athletic balance could be achieved by less restrictive means.” Third, the Court of Appeals refused to view the NCAA plan as competitively justified by the need to compete effectively with other types of television programming, since it entirely eliminated competition between producers of football and hence was illegal per se.

Finally, the Court of Appeals concluded that even if the television plan were not per se illegal, its anticompetitive limitation on price and output was not offset by any procompetitive justification sufficient to save the plan even when the totality of the circumstances was examined. …

II. There can be no doubt that the challenged practices of the NCAA … share characteristics of restraints we have previously held unreasonable. The NCAA is an association of schools which compete against each other to attract television revenues, not to mention fans and athletes. … [T]he policies of the NCAA with respect to television rights are ultimately controlled by the vote of member institutions. By participating in an association which prevents member institutions from competing against each other on the basis of price or kind of television rights that can be offered to broadcasters, the NCAA member institutions have created a horizontal restraint–an agreement among competitors on the way in which they will compete with one another. A restraint of this type has often been held to be unreasonable as a matter of law. Because it places a ceiling on the number of games member institutions may televise, [it] places an artificial limit on the quantity of televised football that is available to broadcasters and consumers. By restraining the quantity of television rights available for sale, the challenged practices create a limitation on output; our cases have held that such limitations are unreasonable restraints of trade. Moreover, the District Court found that the minimum aggregate price in fact operates to preclude any price negotiation between broadcasters and institutions, thereby constituting horizontal price fixing, perhaps the paradigm of an unreasonable restraint of trade.

Horizontal price fixing and output limitation are ordinarily condemned as a matter of law … because the probability that these practices are anticompetitive is so high; a per se rule is applied when “the practice facially appears to be one that would always or almost always tend to restrict competition and decrease output.” Broadcast Music, Inc. v. CBS, 441 U.S. 1, 19-20 (1979). In such circumstances a restraint is presumed unreasonable without inquiry into the particular market context in which it is found. Nevertheless, we have decided that it would be inappropriate to apply a per se rule to this case. This decision is not based on a lack of judicial experience with this type of arrangement,21 on the fact that the NCAA is organized as a nonprofit entity,22 or on our respect for the NCAA’s historic role in the preservation and encouragement of

21 While judicial inexperience with a particular arrangement counsels against extending the reach of per se rules, see Broadcast Music; U.S. v. Topco Associates, 405 U.S., at 607-608; White Motor Co. v. U.S., 372 U.S. 253, 263 (1963); the likelihood that horizontal price and output restrictions are anticompetitive is generally sufficient to justify application of the per se rule without inquiry into the special characteristics of a particular industry. See Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S., at 349-351; Professional Engineers.

78

Page 17: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

intercollegiate amateur athletics.23 Rather, what is critical is that this case involves an industry in which horizontal restraints on competition are essential if the product is to be available at all.

As Judge Bork has noted: [S]ome activities can only be carried out jointly. Perhaps the leading example is league sports. When a league of professional lacrosse teams is formed, it would be pointless to declare their cooperation illegal on the ground that there are no other professional lacrosse teams.

R. BORK, THE ANTITRUST PARADOX 278 (1978). What the NCAA and its member institutions market in this case is competition itself–contests between competing institutions. Of course, this would be completely ineffective if there were no rules on which the competitors agreed to create and define the competition to be marketed. A myriad of rules affecting such matters as the size of the field, the number of players on a team, and the extent to which physical violence is to be encouraged or proscribed, all must be agreed upon, and all restrain the manner in which institutions compete. Moreover, the NCAA seeks to market a particular brand of football–college football. The identification of this “product” with an academic tradition differentiates college football from and makes it more popular than professional sports to which it might otherwise be comparable, such as, for example, minor league baseball. In order to preserve the character and quality of the “product,” athletes must not be paid, must be required to attend class, and the like. And the integrity of the “product” cannot be preserved except by mutual agreement; if an institution adopted such restrictions unilaterally, its effectiveness as a competitor on the playing field might soon be destroyed. Thus, the NCAA plays a vital role in enabling college football to preserve its character, and as a result enables a product to be marketed which might otherwise be unavailable. In performing this role, its actions widen consumer choice–not only the choices available to sports fans but also those available to athletes–and hence can be viewed as procompetitive.

Broadcast Music squarely holds that a joint selling arrangement may be so efficient that it will increase sellers’ aggregate output and thus be procompetitive. Similarly, as we indicated in Continental T.V. v. GTE Sylvania, 433 U.S. 36, 51-57 (1977), a restraint in a limited aspect of a market may actually enhance marketwide

22 There is no doubt that the sweeping language of §1 applies to nonprofit entities, Goldfarb v. Virginia State Bar, 421 U.S. 773, 786-787 (1975), and in the past we have imposed antitrust liability on nonprofit entities which have engaged in anticompetitive conduct, Am. Soc. of Mechanical Engineers v. Hydrolevel Corp., 456 U.S. 556, 576 (1982). Moreover, the economic significance of the NCAA’s nonprofit character is questionable at best. Since the District Court found that the NCAA and its member institutions are in fact organized to maximize revenues, it is unclear why petitioner is less likely to restrict output in order to raise revenues above those that could be realized in a competitive market than would be a for-profit entity. Petitioner does not rely on its nonprofit character as a basis for reversal. 23 Although as the guardian of an important American tradition, the NCAA’s motives must be accorded a respectful presumption of validity, it is nevertheless well settled that good motives will not validate an otherwise anticompetitive practice. Chicago Board of Trade; U.S. v. Trans-Missouri Freight Assn., 166 U.S. 290, 342 (1897).

79

Page 18: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

competition. Respondents concede that the great majority of the NCAA’s regulations enhance competition among member institutions. Thus, despite the fact that this case involves restraints on the ability of member institutions to compete in terms of price and output, a fair evaluation of their competitive character requires consideration of the NCAA’s justifications….

Our analysis of this case under the Rule of Reason, of course, does not change the ultimate focus of our inquiry. Both per se rules and the Rule of Reason are employed “to form a judgment about the competitive significance of the restraint.” Professional Engineers. … Per se rules are invoked when surrounding circumstances make the likelihood of anticompetitive conduct so great as to render unjustified further examination of the challenged conduct. But whether the ultimate finding is the product of a presumption or actual market analysis, the essential inquiry remains the same–whether or not the challenged restraint enhances competition.26 Under the Sherman Act the criterion to be used in judging the validity of a restraint on trade is its impact on competition.

III. Because it restrains price and output, the NCAA’s television plan has a significant potential for anticompetitive effects.28 … Individual competitors lose their freedom to compete. Price is higher and output lower than they would otherwise be, and both are unresponsive to consumer preference.33 … A restraint that has the effect of reducing the importance of consumer preference in setting price and output is not consistent with this fundamental goal of antitrust law. Restrictions on price and output are the paradigmatic examples of restraints of trade that the Sherman Act was intended to prohibit. … At the same time, the television plan eliminates competitors from the market, since only those 26 Indeed, there is often no bright line separating per se from Rule of Reason analysis. Per se rules may require considerable inquiry into market conditions before the evidence justifies a presumption of anticompetitive conduct. For example, while the Court has spoken of a “per se” rule against tying arrangements, it has also recognized that tying may have procompetitive justifications that make it inappropriate to condemn without considerable market analysis. See Jefferson Parish Hospital Dist. No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S., at 11-12.28 In this connection, it is not without significance that Congress felt the need to grant professional sports an exemption from the antitrust laws for joint marketing of television rights. See 15 U.S.C. §§1291-1295. The legislative history of this exemption demonstrates Congress’ recognition that agreements among league members to sell television rights in a cooperative fashion could run afoul of the Sherman Act….33 “In this case the rule is violated by a price restraint that tends to provide the same economic rewards to all practitioners regardless of their skill, their experience, their training, or their willingness to employ innovative and difficult procedures.” Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S., at 348. The District Court provided a vivid example of this system in practice:

A clear example of the failure of the rights fees paid to respond to market forces occurred in the fall of 1981. On one weekend of that year, Oklahoma was scheduled to play a football game with the University of Southern California. Both Oklahoma and USC have long had outstanding football programs, and indeed, both teams were ranked among the top five teams in the country by the wire service polls. ABC chose to televise the game along with several others on a regional basis. A game between two schools which are not well-known for their football programs, Citadel and Appalachian State, was carried on four of ABC’s local affiliated stations. The USC-Oklahoma contest was carried on over 200 stations. Yet, incredibly, all four of these teams received exactly the same amount of money for the right to televise their games.

80

Page 19: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

broadcasters able to bid on television rights covering the entire NCAA can compete. Thus, as the District Court found, many telecasts that would occur in a competitive market are foreclosed by the NCAA’s plan.

Petitioner argues, however, that its television plan can have no significant anticompetitive effect since the record indicates that it has no market power–no ability to alter the interaction of supply and demand in the market. We must reject this argument for two reasons, one legal, one factual.

As a matter of law, the absence of proof of market power does not justify a naked restriction on price or output. To the contrary, when there is an agreement not to compete in terms of price or output, “no elaborate industry analysis is required to demonstrate the anticompetitive character of such an agreement.” Professional Engineers. Petitioner does not quarrel with the District Court’s finding that price and output are not responsive to demand. Thus the plan is inconsistent with the Sherman Act’s command that price and supply be responsive to consumer preference. We have never required proof of market power in such a case. This naked restraint on price and output requires some competitive justification even in the absence of a detailed market analysis.

As a factual matter, it is evident that petitioner does possess market power. The District Court employed the correct test for determining whether college football broadcasts constitute a separate market–whether there are other products that are reasonably substitutable for televised NCAA football games. Petitioner’s argument that it cannot obtain supracompetitive prices from broadcasters since advertisers, and hence broadcasters, can switch from college football to other types of programming simply ignores the findings of the District Court. It found that intercollegiate football telecasts generate an audience uniquely attractive to advertisers and that competitors are unable to offer programming that can attract a similar audience. These findings amply support its conclusion that the NCAA possesses market power. Indeed, the District Court’s subsidiary finding that advertisers will pay a premium price per viewer to reach audiences watching college football because of their demographic characteristics is vivid evidence of the uniqueness of this product. Moreover, the District Court’s market analysis is firmly supported by our decision in International Boxing Club of N.Y.. v. U.S., 358 U.S. 242 (1959), that championship boxing events are uniquely attractive to fans and hence constitute a market separate from that for non-championship events. … It inexorably follows that if college football broadcasts be defined as a separate market–and we are convinced they are–then the NCAA’s complete control over those broadcasts provides a solid basis for the District Court’s conclusion that the NCAA possesses market power… .

Thus, the NCAA television plan on its face constitutes a restraint upon the operation of a free market, and the findings of the District Court establish that it has operated to raise prices and reduce output. Under the Rule of Reason, these hallmarks of anticompetitive behavior place upon petitioner a heavy burden of establishing an affirmative defense which competitively justifies this apparent deviation from the operations of a free market. We turn now to the NCAA’s proffered justifications.

IV. Relying on Broadcast Music, petitioner argues that its television plan constitutes a cooperative “joint venture” which assists in the marketing of broadcast rights and hence

81

Page 20: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

is procompetitive. While joint ventures have no immunity from the antitrust laws, as Broadcast Music indicates, a joint selling arrangement may “mak[e] possible a new product by reaping otherwise unattainable efficiencies.” Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 365 (1982) (POWELL, J., dissenting). The essential contribution made by the NCAA’s arrangement is to define the number of games that may be televised, to establish the price for each exposure, and to define the basic terms of each contract between the network and a home team. The NCAA does not, however, act as a selling agent for any school or for any conference of schools. The selection of individual games, and the negotiation of particular agreements, are matters left to the networks and the individual schools. Thus, the effect of the network plan is not to eliminate individual sales of broadcasts, since these still occur, albeit subject to fixed prices and output limitations. Unlike Broadcast Music’s blanket license covering broadcast rights to a large number of individual compositions, here the same rights are still sold on an individual basis, only in a non-competitive market.

The District Court did not find that the NCAA’s television plan produced any procompetitive efficiencies which enhanced the competitiveness of college football television rights; to the contrary it concluded that NCAA football could be marketed just as effectively without the television plan. There is therefore no predicate in the findings for petitioner’s efficiency justification. Indeed, petitioner’s argument is refuted by the District Court’s finding concerning price and output. If the NCAA’s television plan produced procompetitive efficiencies, the plan would increase output and reduce the price of televised games. The District Court’s contrary findings accordingly undermine petitioner’s position. In light of these findings, it cannot be said that “the agreement on price is necessary to market the product at all.” Broadcast Music.53 In Broadcast Music, the availability of a package product that no individual could offer enhanced the total volume of music that was sold. Unlike this case, there was no limit of any kind placed on the volume that might be sold in the entire market and each individual remained free to sell his own music without restraint. Here production has been limited, not enhanced. No individual school is free to televise its own games without restraint. The NCAA’s efficiency justification is not supported by the record.

Neither is the NCAA’s television plan necessary to enable the NCAA to penetrate the market through an attractive package sale. Since broadcasting rights to college football constitute a unique product for which there is no ready substitute, there is no need for collective action in order to enable the product to compete against its nonexistent

53 Compare [the District Court opinion] (“The colleges are clearly able to negotiate agreements with whatever broadcasters they choose. We are not dealing with tens of thousands of relatively brief musical works, but with three-hour football games played eleven times each year”) with Broadcast Music (“[T]o the extent the blanket license is a different product, ASCAP is not really a joint sales agency offering the individual goods of many sellers, but is a separate seller offering its blanket license, of which the individual compositions are raw material. ASCAP, in short, made a market in which individual composers are inherently unable to compete fully effectively”).

82

Page 21: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

competitors.55 This is borne out by the District Court’s finding that the NCAA’s television plan reduces the volume of television rights sold.

V. Throughout … its regulation of intercollegiate football telecasts, the NCAA has indicated its concern with protecting live attendance. This concern, it should be noted, is not with protecting live attendance at games which are shown on television; that type of interest is not at issue in this case. Rather, the concern is that fan interest in a televised game may adversely affect ticket sales for games that will not appear on television.56

Although the NORC studies in the 1950’s provided some support for the thesis that live attendance would suffer if unlimited television were permitted, the District Court found that there was no evidence to support that theory in today’s market. Moreover, as the District Court found, the television plan has evolved in a manner inconsistent with its original design to protect gate attendance. Under the current plan, games are shown on television during all hours that college football games are played. The plan simply does not protect live attendance by ensuring that games will not be shown on television at the same time as live events.

There is, however, a more fundamental reason for rejecting this defense. The NCAA’s argument … is not based on a desire to maintain the integrity of college football as a distinct and attractive product, but rather on a fear that the product will not prove sufficiently attractive to draw live attendance when faced with competition from televised games. At bottom the NCAA’s position is that ticket sales for most college games are unable to compete in a free market.60 The television plan protects ticket sales by limiting output–just as any monopolist increases revenues by reducing output. By seeking to insulate live ticket sales from the full spectrum of competition because of its assumption that the product itself is insufficiently attractive to consumers, petitioner forwards a justification that is inconsistent with the basic policy of the Sherman Act. “[T]he Rule of Reason does not support a defense based on the assumption that competition itself is unreasonable.” Professional Engineers.

VI. Petitioner argues that the interest in maintaining a competitive balance among amateur athletic teams is legitimate and important and that it justifies the regulations challenged in this case. We agree with the first part of the argument but not the second.

55 If the NCAA faced “interbrand” competition from available substitutes, then certain forms of collective action might be appropriate in order to enhance its ability to compete. See Sylvania. Our conclusion concerning the availability of substitutes in Part III, forecloses such a justification in this case, however.56 The NCAA’s plan is not even arguably related to a desire to protect live attendance by ensuring that a game is not televised in the area where it is to be played. No cooperative action is necessary for that kind of “blackout.” The home team can always refuse to sell the right to telecast its game to stations in the immediate area. The NCAA does not now and never has justified its television plan by an interest in assisting schools in “blacking out” their home games in the areas in which they are played.60 Ironically, to the extent that the NCAA’s position has merit, it rests on the assumption that football telecasts are a unique product. If, as the NCAA argues, all television programming is essentially fungible, it would not be possible to protect attendance without banning all television during the hours at which intercollegiate football games are held.

83

Page 22: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Our decision not to apply a per se rule to this case rests in large part on our recognition that a certain degree of cooperation is necessary if the type of competition that petitioner and its member institutions seek to market is to be preserved. It is reasonable to assume that most of the regulatory controls of the NCAA are justifiable means of fostering competition among amateur athletic teams and therefore procompetitive because they enhance public interest in intercollegiate athletics. The specific restraints … that are challenged in this case do not, however, fit into the same mold as do rules defining the conditions of the contest, the eligibility of participants, or the manner in which members of a joint enterprise shall share the responsibilities and the benefits of the total venture.

The NCAA does not claim that its television plan has equalized or is intended to equalize competition within any one league.62 The plan is nationwide in scope and there is no single league or tournament in which all college football teams complete. There is no evidence of any intent to equalize the strength of teams in Division I-A with those in Division II or Division III, and not even a colorable basis for giving colleges that have no football program at all a voice in the management of the revenues generated by the football programs at other schools. The interest in maintaining a competitive balance that is asserted by the NCAA … is not related to any neutral standard or to any readily identifiable group of competitors.

The television plan is not even arguably tailored to serve such an interest. It does not regulate the amount of money that any college may spend on its football program, nor the way in which the colleges may use the revenues that are generated by their football programs, whether derived from the sale of television rights, the sale of tickets, or the sale of concessions or program advertising. The plan simply imposes a restriction on one source of revenue that is more important to some colleges than to others. There is no evidence that this restriction produces any greater measure of equality throughout the NCAA than would a restriction on alumni donations, tuition rates, or any other revenue-producing activity. At the same time, as the District Court found, the NCAA imposes a variety of other restrictions designed to preserve amateurism which are much better tailored to the goal of competitive balance than is the television plan, and which are “clearly sufficient” to preserve competitive balance to the extent it is within the NCAA’s power to do so. And much more than speculation supported the District Court’s findings on this score. No other NCAA sport employs a similar plan, and in particular the court found that in the most closely analogous sport, college basketball, competitive balance has been maintained without resort to a restrictive television plan.

Perhaps the most important reason for rejecting the argument that the interest in competitive balance is served by the television plan is the District Court’s unambiguous and well-supported finding that many more games would be televised in a free market

62 It seems unlikely, for example, that there would have been a greater disparity between the football prowess of Ohio State University and that of Northwestern University in recent years without the NCAA’s television plan. The District Court found that in fact the NCAA has been strikingly unsuccessful if it has indeed attempted to prevent the emergence of a “power elite” in intercollegiate football. Moreover, the District Court’s finding that there would be more local and regional telecasts without the NCAA controls means that Northwestern could well have generated more television income in a free market than was obtained under the NCAA regime.

84

Page 23: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

than under the NCAA plan. The hypothesis that legitimates the maintenance of competitive balance as a procompetitive justification under the Rule of Reason is that equal competition will maximize consumer demand for the product. The finding that consumption will materially increase if the controls are removed is a compelling demonstration that they do not in fact serve any such legitimate purpose.

VII. The NCAA plays a critical role in the maintenance of a revered tradition of amateurism in college sports. There can be no question but that it needs ample latitude to play that role, or that the preservation of the student-athlete in higher education adds richness and diversity to intercollegiate athletics and is entirely consistent with the goals of the Sherman Act. But consistent with the Sherman Act, the role of the NCAA must be to preserve a tradition that might otherwise die; rules that restrict output are hardly consistent with this role. Today we hold only that the record supports the District Court’s conclusion that by curtailing output and blunting the ability of member institutions to respond to consumer preference, the NCAA has restricted rather than enhanced the place of intercollegiate athletics in the Nation’s life. …

Justice WHITE, with whom Justice REHNQUIST joins, dissenting. … Although some of the NCAA’s activities, viewed in isolation, bear a resemblance to those undertaken by professional sports leagues and associations, the Court errs in treating intercollegiate athletics under the NCAA’s control as a purely commercial venture in which colleges and universities participate solely, or even primarily, in the pursuit of profits. Accordingly, I dissent.

I. … The NCAA … “exist[s] primarily to enhance the contribution made by amateur athletic competition to the process of higher education as distinguished from realizing maximum return on it as an entertainment commodity.” Ass’n for Intercollegiate Athletics for Women v. NCAA, 558 F.Supp. 487, 494 (DC 1983), aff’d, 735 F.2d 577 (1984). In pursuing this goal, the organization and its members seek to provide a public good–a viable system of amateur athletics–that most likely could not be provided in a perfectly competitive market. “Without regulation, the desire of member institutions to remain athletically competitive would lead them to engage in activities that deny amateurism to the public. No single institution could confidently enforce its own standards since it could not trust its competitors to do the same.” Note, Antitrust and Nonprofit Entities, 94 HARV.L.REV. 802, 817-818 (1981). The history of intercollegiate athletics prior to the advent of the NCAA provides ample support for this conclusion. By mitigating what appears to be a clear failure of the free market to serve the ends and goals of higher education, the NCAA ensures the continued availability of a unique and valuable product, the very existence of which might well be threatened by unbridled competition….

In pursuit of its fundamental goal and others related to it, the NCAA imposes numerous controls on intercollegiate athletic competition among its members…. Thus, the NCAA has promulgated and enforced rules limiting both the compensation of student-athletes, and the number of coaches a school may hire for its football and basketball programs; it also has prohibited athletes who formerly have been compensated for playing from participating in intercollegiate competition, restricted the number of athletic scholarships its members may award, and established minimum academic standards for recipients of those scholarships; and it has pervasively regulated the

85

Page 24: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

recruitment process, student eligibility, practice schedules, squad size, the number of games played, and many other aspects of intercollegiate athletics. … Significantly, neither the Court of Appeals nor this Court questions the validity of these regulations under the Rule of Reason. Notwithstanding the contrary conclusion of the District Court and the majority, I do not believe that the restraint under consideration in this case–the NCAA’s television plan–differs fundamentally for antitrust purposes from the other seemingly anti-competitive aspects of the organization’s broader program of self-regulation. … More generally, in my view, the television plan reflects the NCAA’s fundamental policy of preserving amateurism and integrating athletics and education. …

Before addressing the infirmities in the Court’s opinion, I should state my understanding of what the Court holds. … [T]he Court first holds that the television plan has sufficient redeeming virtues to escape condemnation as a per se violation of the Sherman Act, this because of the inherent characteristics of competitive athletics and the justifiable role of the NCAA in regulating college athletics. It nevertheless affirms the Court of Appeals’ judgment that the NCAA plan is an unreasonable restraint of trade because of what it deems to be the plan’s price-fixing and output-limiting aspects. As I shall explain, in reaching this result, the Court traps itself in commercial antitrust rhetoric and ideology and ignores the context in which the restraints have been imposed. But it is essential at this point to emphasize that neither the Court of Appeals nor this Court purports to hold that the NCAA may not (1) require its members who televise their games to pool and share the compensation received among themselves, with other schools, and with the NCAA; (2) limit the number of times any member may arrange to have its games shown on television; or (3) enforce reasonable blackout rules to avoid head-to-head competition for television audiences. As I shall demonstrate, the Court wisely and correctly does not condemn such regulations. What the Court does affirm is the Court of Appeals’ judgment that the NCAA may not limit the number of games that are broadcast on television and that it may not contract for an overall price that has the effect of setting the price for individual game broadcast rights. I disagree with the Court in these respects.

II. “In a competitive market,” the District Court observed, “each football-playing institution would be an independent seller of the right to telecast its football games. Each seller would be free to sell that right to any entity it chose,” and “for whatever price it could get.” Under the NCAA’s television plan, member institutions’ competitive freedom is restrained because, for the most part, television rights are brought and sold, not on a per-game basis, but as a package deal. With limited exceptions not particularly relevant to antitrust scrutiny of the plan, broadcasters wishing to televise college football must be willing and able to purchase a package of television rights without knowing in advance the particular games to which those rights apply. The real negotiations over price and terms take place between the broadcasters and the NCAA rather than between the broadcasters and individual schools. Knowing that some games will be worth more to them than others, the networks undoubtedly exercise whatever bargaining power they possess to ensure that the minimum aggregate compensation they agree to provide for the package bears some relation to the average value to them of the games they anticipate televising. Because some schools’ games contribute disproportionately to the total value of the package, the manner in which the minimum aggregate compensation is distributed among schools whose games are televised has given rise to a situation under which less

86

Page 25: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

prominent schools receive more in rights fees than they would receive in a competitive market and football powers like respondents receive less.

As I have said, the Court does not hold … that this redistributive effect alone would be sufficient to subject the television plan to condemnation under §1 of the Sherman Act. Nor should it, for an agreement to share football revenues to a certain extent is an essential aspect of maintaining some balance of strength among competing colleges and of minimizing the tendency to professionalism in the dominant schools. Sharing with the NCAA itself is also a price legitimately exacted in exchange for the numerous benefits of membership in the NCAA, including its many-faceted efforts to maintain a system of competitive, amateur athletics. For the same reasons, limiting the number of television appearances by any college is an essential attribute of a balanced amateur athletic system. Even with shared television revenues, unlimited appearances by a few schools would inevitably give them an insuperable advantage over all others and in the end defeat any efforts to maintain a system of athletic competition among amateurs who measure up to college scholastic requirements.

The Court relies instead primarily on the District Court’s findings that (1) the television plan restricts output; and (2) the plan creates a noncompetitive price structure that is unresponsive to viewer demand. These findings notwithstanding, I am unconvinced that the television plan has a substantial anticompetitive effect.

First, it is not clear to me that the District Court employed the proper measure of output. I am not prepared to say that the District Court’s finding that “many more college football games would be televised” in the absence of the NCAA controls, is clearly erroneous. To the extent that output is measured solely in terms of the number of televised games, I need not deny that it is reduced by the NCAA’s television plan. But this measure of output is not the proper one. The District Court found that eliminating the plan would reduce the number of games on network television and increase the number of games shown locally and regionally. It made no finding concerning the effect of the plan on total viewership, which is the more appropriate measure of output or, at least, of the claimed anticompetitive effects of the NCAA plan. This is the NCAA’s position, and it seems likely to me that the television plan, by increasing network coverage at the expense of local broadcasts, actually expands the total television audience for NCAA football. The NCAA would surely be an irrational “profit maximizer” if this were not the case. In the absence of a contrary finding by the District Court, I cannot conclude that respondents carried their burden of showing that the television plan has an adverse effect on output and is therefore anticompetitive.

Second, and even more important, I am unconvinced that respondents have proved that any reduction in the number of televised college football games brought about by the NCAA’s television plan has resulted in an anticompetitive increase in the price of television rights. The District Court found, of course, that “the networks are actually paying the large fees because the NCAA agrees to limit production. If the NCAA would not agree to limit production, the networks would not pay so large a fee.” Undoubtedly, this is true. But the market for television rights to college football competitions should not be equated to the markets for wheat or widgets. Reductions in output by monopolists in most product markets enable producers to exact a higher price for the same product. By restricting the number of games that can be televised, however,

87

Page 26: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

the NCAA creates a new product–exclusive television rights–that are more valuable to networks than the products that its individual members could market independently.

The television plan makes a certain number of games available for purchase by television networks and limits the incidence of head-to-head competition between football telecasts for the available viewers. Because competition is limited, the purchasing network can count on a larger share of the audience, which translates into greater advertising revenues and, accordingly, into larger payments per game to the televised teams. There is thus a relationship between the size of the rights payments and the value of the product being purchased by the networks; a network purchasing a series of games under the plan is willing to pay more than would one purchasing the same games in the absence of the plan since the plan enables the network to deliver a larger share of the available audience to advertisers and thus to increase its own revenues. In short, by focusing only on the price paid by the networks for television rights rather than on the nature and quality of the product delivered by the NCAA and its member institutions, the District Court, and this Court as well, may well have deemed anticompetitive a rise in price that more properly should be attributed to an increase in output, measured in terms of viewership.

Third, the District Court’s emphasis on the prices paid for particular games seems … erroneous as a matter of law. The distribution of the minimum aggregate fees among participants in the television plan is, of course, not wholly based on a competitive price structure that is responsive to viewer demand and is only partially related to the value those schools contribute to the total package the networks agree to buy. But as I have already indicated, this “redistribution” of total television revenues is a wholly justifiable, even necessary, aspect of maintaining a system of truly competitive college teams. As long as the NCAA cannot artificially fix the price of the entire package and demand supercompetitive prices, this aspect of the plan should be of little concern. And I find little, if anything, in the record to support the notion that the NCAA has power to extract from the television networks more than the broadcasting rights are worth in the marketplace.

III. Even if I were convinced that the District Court did not err in failing to look to total viewership, as opposed to the number of televised games, when measuring output and anticompetitive effect and in failing fully to consider whether the NCAA possesses power to fix the package price, as opposed to the distribution of that package price among participating teams, I would nevertheless hold that the television plan passes muster under the Rule of Reason. The NCAA argues strenuously that the plan and the network contracts “are part of a joint venture among many of the nation’s universities to create a product–high-quality college football–and offer that product in a way attractive to both fans in the stadiums and viewers on [television]. The cooperation in producing the product makes it more competitive against other [television] (and live) attractions.” The Court recognizes that, “[i]f the NCAA faced ‘interbrand’ competition from available substitutes, then certain forms of collective action might be appropriate in order to enhance its ability to compete.” It rejects the NCAA’s proffered procompetitive justification, however, on the ground that college football is a unique product for which there are no available substitutes and “there is no need for collective action in order to

88

Page 27: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

enable the product to compete against its nonexistent competitors.” This proposition is singularly unpersuasive.

It is one thing to say that “NCAA football is a unique product,” that “intercollegiate football telecasts generate an audience uniquely attractive to advertisers and that competitors are unable to offer programming that can attract a similar audience.” It is quite another, in my view, to say that maintenance or enhancement of the quality of NCAA football telecasts is unnecessary to enable those telecasts to compete effectively against other forms of entertainment. The NCAA has no monopoly power when competing against other types of entertainment. Should the quality of the NCAA’s product “deteriorate to any perceptible degree or should the cost of ‘using’ its product rise, some fans undoubtedly would turn to another form of entertainment.... Because of the broad possibilities for alternative forms of entertainment,” the NCAA “properly belongs in the broader ‘entertainment’ market rather than in ... [a] narrower marke[t]” like sports or football. Grauer, Recognition of the National Football League as a Single Entity Under§1 of the Sherman Act, 82 MICH.L.REV. 1, 34 n.156 (1983).

The NCAA has suggested a number of plausible ways in which its television plan might enhance the ability of college football telecasts to compete against other forms of entertainment. Although the District Court did conclude that the plan is “not necessary for effective marketing of the product,” its finding was directed only at the question whether college football telecasts would continue in the absence of the plan. It made no explicit findings concerning the effect of the plan on viewership and thus did not reject the factual premise of the NCAA’s argument that the plan might enhance competition by increasing the market penetration of NCAA football. The District Court’s finding that network coverage of NCAA football would likely decrease if the plan were struck down, in fact, strongly suggests the validity of the NCAA’s position. On the record now before the Court, therefore, I am not prepared to conclude that the restraints imposed by the NCAA’s television plan are “such as may suppress or even destroy competition” rather than “such as merely regulat[e] and perhaps thereby promot[e] competition.” Chicago Board of Trade.

IV. Finally, …I believe that the lower courts “erred by subjugating the NCAA’s educational goals … to the purely competitive commercialism of [an] ‘every school for itself’ approach to television contract bargaining.” Although the NCAA does not enjoy blanket immunity from the antitrust laws, it is important to remember that the Sherman Act “is aimed primarily at combinations having commercial objectives and is applied only to a very limited extent to organizations ... which normally have other objectives.” Klor’s, Inc. v. Broadway-Hale Stores, 359 U.S. 207, 213, n.7 (1959).

… The Court of Appeals, like the District Court, flatly refused to consider what it termed “noneconomic” justifications advanced by the NCAA in support of the television plan. It was of the view that our decision in Professional Engineers precludes reliance on noneconomic factors in assessing the reasonableness of the television plan. This view was mistaken, and I note that the Court does not in so many words repeat this error.

Professional Engineers did make clear that … [o] rdinarily, “the inquiry mandated by the Rule of Reason is whether the challenged agreement is one that promotes competition or one that suppresses competition.” Id. The purpose of antitrust

89

Page 28: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

analysis, the Court emphasized, “is to form a judgment about the competitive significance of the restraint; it is not to decide whether a policy favoring competition is in the public interest, or in the interest of the members of an industry.” Id. … But these statements were made in response to “public interest” justifications proffered in defense of a ban on competitive bidding imposed by practitioners engaged in standard, profit-motivated commercial activities. The primarily noneconomic values pursued by educational institutions differ fundamentally from the “overriding commercial purpose of [the] day-to-day activities” of engineers, lawyers, doctors, and businessmen, Gulland, Byrne, & Steinbach, Intercollegiate Athletics and Television Contracts: Beyond Economic Justifications…, 52 FORD.L.REV. 717, 728 (1984), and neither Professional Engineers nor any other decision of this Court suggests that associations of nonprofit educational institutions must defend their self-regulatory restraints solely in terms of their competitive impact, without regard for the legitimate noneconomic values they promote.

When these values are factored into the balance, the NCAA’s television plan seems eminently reasonable. … [T]he plan fosters the goal of amateurism by spreading revenues among various schools and reducing the financial incentives toward professionalism. … The collateral consequences of the spreading of regional and national appearances among a number of schools are many: the television plan, like the ban on compensating student-athletes, may well encourage students to choose their schools, at least in part, on the basis of educational quality by reducing the perceived economic element of the choice, [and] it helps ensure the economic viability of athletic programs at a wide variety of schools with weaker football teams…. These important contributions, I believe, are sufficient to offset any minimal anticompetitive effects of the television plan. For all of these reasons, I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals. ….

$ $ $ $ $ $ $Territorial Restraints: Introduction

I. Agreements to Allocate Geographic Areas ServedII. Topco (1972):

A. group of small supermarket chains put out own brand of foods 1. No pooling of earnings, profits, capital, advertising. 2. Together would be 4th largest nat'l supermarket chain. 3. Local market shares 1.5-16% (average 6%).

B. Agree to each sell Topco products in exclusive region C. Trial court found agreement allowed Topco to compete w big chains D. S.Ct. says allocation of market between competitors is per se illegal.

1. Intimates that all horizontal agreements are anti-competitive 2. Nothing in Antitrust laws gives authority to restrict competition in one market

to achieve it in another

$ $ $ $ $ $ $

90

Page 29: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

PALMER v. BRG OF GEORGIA, INC.498 U.S. 46 (1990)

PER CURIAM. In preparation for the 1985 Georgia Bar Examination, petitioners contracted to take a bar review course offered by respondent BRG of Georgia, Inc. (BRG). In this litigation they contend that the price of BRG’s course was enhanced by reason of an unlawful agreement between BRG and respondent Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Legal and Professional Publications (HBJ), the Nation’s largest provider of bar review materials and lecture services. The central issue is whether the 1980 agreement between respondents violated §1 of the Sherman Act.

HBJ began offering a Georgia bar review course on a limited basis in 1976, and was in direct, and often intense, competition with BRG during the period from 1977 to 1979. BRG and HBJ were the two main providers of bar review courses in Georgia during this time period. In early 1980, they entered into an agreement that gave BRG an exclusive license to market HBJ’s material in Georgia and to use its trade name “Bar/Bri.” The parties agreed that HBJ would not compete with BRG in Georgia and that BRG would not compete with HBJ outside of Georgia. Under the agreement, HBJ received $100 per student enrolled by BRG and 40% of all revenues over $350. Immediately after the 1980 agreement, the price of BRG’s course was increased from $150 to over $400.

… [T]he District Court held that the agreement was lawful. The United States Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit … agreed with the District Court that per se unlawful horizontal price fixing required an explicit agreement on prices to be charged or that one party have the right to be consulted about the other’s prices. The Court of Appeals also agreed with the District Court that to prove a per se violation under a geographic market allocation theory, petitioners had to show that respondents had subdivided some relevant market in which they had previously competed. …

In Socony-Vacuum Oil Co., we held that an agreement among competitors to engage in a program of buying surplus gasoline on the spot market in order to prevent prices from falling sharply was unlawful, even though there was no direct agreement on the actual prices to be maintained. We explained that “[u]nder the Sherman Act a combination formed for the purpose and with the effect of raising, depressing, fixing, pegging, or stabilizing the price of a commodity in interstate or foreign commerce is illegal per se.”

The revenue-sharing formula in the 1980 agreement between BRG and HBJ, coupled with the price increase that took place immediately after the parties agreed to cease competing with each other in 1980, indicates that this agreement was “formed for the purpose and with the effect of raising” the price of the bar review course. It was, therefore, plainly incorrect for the District Court to enter summary judgment in respondents’ favor. Moreover, it is equally clear that the District Court and the Court of Appeals erred when they assumed that an allocation of markets or submarkets by competitors is not unlawful unless the market in which the two previously competed is divided between them.

91

Page 30: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

In U.S. v. Topco Associates, 405 U.S. 596 (1972), we held that agreements between competitors to allocate territories to minimize competition are illegal:

One of the classic examples of a per se violation of §1 is an agreement between competitors at the same level of the market structure to allocate territories in order to minimize competition.... This Court has reiterated time and time again that “[h]orizontal territorial limitations ... are naked restraints of trade with no purpose except stifling of competition.” Such limitations are per se violations of the Sherman Act.

The defendants in Topco had never competed in the same market, but had simply agreed to allocate markets. Here, HBJ and BRG had previously competed in the Georgia market; under their allocation agreement, BRG received that market, while HBJ received the remainder of the U.S.. Each agreed not to compete in the other’s territories. Such agreements are anticompetitive regardless of whether the parties split a market within which both do business or whether they merely reserve one market for one and another for the other.6 Thus, the 1980 agreement between HBJ and BRG was unlawful on its face.

The … judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed….

$ $ $ $ $ $ $Concerted Refusals to Deal (Group Boycotts): Overview

I. Prototype I: Two-level Problem: Agreement between competitors at one level with necessary trade partners on another to refuse to deal with someone on one of the levels, making it harder for excluded party to compete

A. General Examples1. wholesalers may ask manufacturers not to sell to excluded wholesalers &

expressly or implicitly threaten to boycott those who do. 2. Can operate directly against those trying to vertically integrate. i.e., if

manufacturer tries wholesaling, wholesalers refuse to purchase from itB. Fashion Originators' Guild (1941): Guild of fashion designers agree not to sell to

retailers that sold copies of their designer garments. Elaborate system of an-cillary restraints to police and to protect designs. (Can be seen as Prototype III, but really elaborate form of prototype I: trying to get retailers to boycott competing manufacturers) ILLEGAL

C. Klor's v. Broadway-Hale Stores (1959): Dept. Store in SF agrees with appliance manufacturers that manufacturers will not sell appliances to small retail appliance store next door to one of its branches. ILLEGAL

II. Prototype II: Joint Ventures: Joint ventures including some but not all horizontal competitors involve a refusal to deal with firms on same level without involving firms on a different level.

A. Efficiency gains not found in other types of boycotts

6 See Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 344, n.15 (1982) ("division of markets" is per se offense).

92

Page 31: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

B. Radiant Burners (1961): Trade assn. (pipeline cos., gas distributors, manufacturers of gas burners) operated testing labs for gas appliances and gave safety seal of approval. Gas utilities relied on ratings--would not supply to unsealed appliances--thus excluding them. P alleged by objective standards its appliances were safer than those sealed. (could also see as prototype I (burner manufacturers conspiring to keep utilities from doing business with competing manufacturers). ILLEGAL (as alleged)

C. Silver v. New York Stock Exchange (1963): Stockbroker members pursuant to direction from NY Stock Exchange, refused to do business with P.. Securities Act allowed this (limited antitrust exemption) only if proper procedures followed. Here, not proper procedures, so ILLEGAL.

III. Prototype III: Cartelization of Non-Price Terms: Refusal to deal with firms at a different level except on specific terms.

A. Paramount Famous Lasky Corp. (1930): Group of Film Distributors (60% of market) agree not to do business with exhibitors except with standard contract. ILLEGAL

B. Can view Fashion Originator’s Guild this way.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $NORTHWEST WHOLESALE STATIONERS v. PACIFIC STATIONERY AND PRINTING CO.

472 U.S. 284 (1985)

Justice BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court. This case requires that we decide whether a per se violation of §1 of the Sherman Act … occurs when a cooperative buying agency comprising various retailers expels a member without providing any procedural means for challenging the expulsion. The case also raises broader questions as to when per se antitrust analysis is appropriately applied to joint activity that is susceptible of being characterized as a concerted refusal to deal.

I. … Petitioner Northwest Wholesale Stationers is a purchasing cooperative made up of approximately 100 office supply retailers in the Pacific Northwest States. The cooperative acts as the primary wholesaler for the retailers. Retailers that are not members of the cooperative can purchase wholesale supplies from Northwest at the same price as members. At the end of each year, however, Northwest distributes its profits to members in the form of a percentage rebate on purchases. Members therefore effectively purchase supplies at a price significantly lower than do nonmembers.2 Northwest also

2 Although this patronage rebate policy is a form of price discrimination, §4 of the Robinson-Patman Act [15 U.S.C. §13b] specifically sanctions such activity by cooperatives:

Nothing in this Act shall prevent a cooperative association from returning to its members, producers, or consumers the whole, or any part of, the net earnings or surplus resulting from its trading operations, in proportion to their purchases or sales from, to, or through the association.

93

Page 32: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

provides certain warehousing facilities. The cooperative arrangement thus permits the participating retailers to achieve economies of scale in purchasing and warehousing that would otherwise be unavailable to them. …

Respondent Pacific Stationery & Printing Co. sells office supplies at both the retail and wholesale levels. … Pacific became a member of Northwest in 1958. In 1974 Northwest amended its bylaws to prohibit members from engaging in both retail and wholesale operations. A grandfather clause preserved Pacific’s membership rights. In 1977 ownership of a controlling share of the stock of Pacific changed hands and the new owners did not officially bring this change to the attention of the directors of Northwest. This failure to notify apparently violated another of Northwest’s bylaws.

In 1978 the membership of Northwest voted to expel Pacific. Most factual matters relevant to the expulsion are in dispute. No explanation for the expulsion was advanced at the time, and Pacific was given neither notice, a hearing, nor any other opportunity to challenge the decision. Pacific argues that the expulsion resulted from Pacific’s decision to maintain a wholesale operation. Northwest contends that the expulsion resulted from Pacific’s failure to notify the cooperative members of the change in stock ownership. The minutes of the meeting of Northwest’s directors do not definitively indicate the motive for the expulsion. …

Pacific brought suit … alleging a violation of §1 of the Sherman Act. The gravamen of the action was that Northwest’s expulsion of Pacific from the cooperative without procedural protections was a group boycott that limited Pacific’s ability to compete and should be considered per se violative of §1. On cross-motions for summary judgment the District Court rejected application of the per se rule and held instead that rule-of-reason analysis should govern the case. Finding no anticompetitive effect on the basis of the record as presented, the court granted summary judgment for Northwest.

The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit reversed…. The court reasoned that the cooperative’s expulsion of Pacific was an anticompetitive concerted refusal to deal with Pacific on equal footing, which would be a per se violation of §1 in the absence of any specific legislative mandate for self-regulation sanctioning the expulsion. The court noted that §4 of the Robinson-Patman Act specifically approves the price discrimination occasioned by such expulsion and concluded that §4 therefore provided a mandate for self-regulation. Such a legislative mandate, according to the court, would ordinarily result in evaluation of the challenged practice under the rule of reason. But, drawing on Silver v. New York Stock Exchange, 373 U.S. 341, 348-349 (1963), the court decided that rule-of-reason analysis was appropriate only on the condition that the cooperative had provided procedural safeguards sufficient to prevent arbitrary expulsion and to furnish a basis for judicial review. Because Northwest had not provided any procedural safeguards, the court held that the expulsion of Pacific was not shielded by Robinson-Patman immunity and therefore constituted a per se group boycott in violation of §1 of the Sherman Act.

We granted certiorari to examine this application of Silver v. New York Stock Exchange in an area of antitrust law that has not been free of confusion. We reverse.

II. The decision … to expel Pacific was certainly a restraint of trade in the sense that every commercial agreement restrains trade. Whether this action violates §1 of the

94

Page 33: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Sherman Act depends on whether it is adjudged an unreasonable restraint. Rule-of-reason analysis guides the inquiry … unless the challenged action falls into the category of “agreements or practices which because of their pernicious effect on competition and lack of any redeeming virtue are conclusively presumed to be unreasonable and therefore illegal without elaborate inquiry as to the precise harm they have caused or the business excuse for their use.” Northern Pacific R. Co. v. U.S., 356 U.S. 1, 5 (1958).

This per se approach permits categorical judgments with respect to certain business practices that have proved to be predominantly anticompetitive. Courts can thereby avoid the “significant costs” in “business certainty and litigation efficiency” that a full-fledged rule-of-reason inquiry entails. Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 343-344 (1982). The decision to apply the per se rule turns on “whether the practice facially appears to be one that would always or almost always tend to restrict competition and decrease output ... or instead one designed to ‘increase economic efficiency and render markets more, rather than less, competitive.’” Broadcast Music, Inc. v. CBS, 441 U.S. 1, 19-20, (1979); see also NCAA (“Per se rules are invoked when surrounding circumstances make the likelihood of anticompetitive conduct so great as to render unjustified further examination of the challenged conduct”).

This Court has long held that certain concerted refusals to deal or group boycotts are so likely to restrict competition without any offsetting efficiency gains that they should be condemned as per se violations of §1 of the Sherman Act. See Klor’s v. Broadway-Hale Stores, 359 U.S. 207 (1959); U.S. v. General Motors Corp., 384 U.S. 127 (1966); Radiant Burners v. Peoples Gas Light & Coke Co., 364 U.S. 656 (1961); Associated Press v. U.S., 326 U.S. 1 (1945); Fashion Originators’ Guild of America v. FTC, 312 U.S. 457 (1941); Eastern States Retail Lumber Dealers’ Assn. v. U.S., 234 U.S. 600 (1914). The question presented in this case is whether Northwest’s decision to expel Pacific should fall within this category of activity that is conclusively presumed to be anticompetitive.4 The Court of Appeals held that the exclusion of Pacific from the cooperative should conclusively be presumed unreasonable on the ground that Northwest provided no procedural protections to Pacific. Even if the lack of procedural protections does not justify a conclusive presumption of predominantly anticompetitive effect, the mere act of expulsion of a competitor from a wholesale cooperative might be argued to be sufficiently likely to have such effects under the present circumstances and therefore to justify application of the per se rule. These possibilities will be analyzed separately.

A. The Court of Appeals drew from Silver v. New York Stock Exchange a broad rule that the conduct of a cooperative venture—including a concerted refusal to deal–undertaken pursuant to a legislative mandate for self-regulation is immune from per se scrutiny and subject to rule-of-reason analysis only if adequate procedural safeguards accompany self-regulation. We disagree and conclude that the approach of the Court in Silver has no proper application to the present controversy.

The Court in Silver framed the issue as follows:

4 Northwest raises no challenge before this Court to the conclusion of the Court of Appeals that the decision to expel Pacific was a “combination or conspiracy” affecting interstate commerce within the meaning of §1 of the Sherman Act.

95

Page 34: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

[W]hether the New York Stock Exchange is to be held liable to a nonmember broker-dealer under the antitrust laws or regarded as impliedly immune therefrom when, pursuant to rules the Exchange has adopted under the Securities Exchange Act of 1934, it orders a number of its members to remove private direct telephone wire connections previously in operation between their offices and those of the nonmember, without giving the nonmember notice, assigning him any reason for the action, or affording him an opportunity to be heard.

Because the New York Stock Exchange occupied such a dominant position in the securities trading markets that the boycott would devastate the nonmember, the Court concluded that the refusal to deal with the nonmember would amount to a per se violation of §1 unless the Securities Exchange Act provided an immunity. The question for the Court thus was whether effectuation of the policies of the Securities Exchange Act required partial repeal of the Sherman Act insofar as it proscribed this aspect of exchange self-regulation.

Finding exchange self-regulation–including the power to expel members and limit dealings with nonmembers–to be an essential policy of the Securities Exchange Act, the Court held that the Sherman Act should be construed as having been partially repealed to permit the type of exchange activity at issue. But the interpretive maxim disfavoring repeals by implication led the Court to narrow permissible self-policing to situations in which adequate procedural safeguards had been provided.

Congress ... cannot be thought to have sanctioned and protected self-regulative activity when carried out in a fundamentally unfair manner. The point is not that the antitrust laws impose the requirement of notice and a hearing here, but rather that, in acting without according petitioners these safeguards in response to their request, the Exchange has plainly exceeded the scope of its authority under the Securities Exchange Act to engage in self-regulation.

Thus it was the specific need to accommodate the important national policy of promoting effective exchange self-regulation, tempered by the principle that the Sherman Act should be narrowed only to the extent necessary to effectuate that policy, that dictated the result in Silver.

Section 4 of the Robinson-Patman Act is not comparable to the self-policing provisions of the Securities Exchange Act. That section is no more than a narrow immunity from the price discrimination prohibitions of the Robinson-Patman Act itself. … This section has never been construed as granting cooperatives a blanket exception from the Robinson-Patman Act and cannot plausibly be construed as an exemption to or repeal of any portion of the Sherman Act. …

In light of this circumscribed congressional intent, … §4 of the Robinson-Patman Act should [not] be viewed as a broad mandate for industry self-regulation. No need exists, therefore, to narrow the Sherman Act in order to accommodate any competing congressional policy requiring discretionary self-policing. Indeed, Congress would appear to have taken some care to make clear that no constriction of the Sherman Act was intended. In any event, the absence of procedural safeguards can in no sense determine the antitrust analysis. If the challenged concerted activity of Northwest’s members would amount to a per se violation of §1 of the Sherman Act, no amount of procedural protection would save it. If the challenged action would not amount to a violation of §1,

96

Page 35: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

no lack of procedural protections would convert it into a per se violation because the antitrust laws do not themselves impose on joint ventures a requirement of process.

B. This case therefore turns not on the lack of procedural protections but on whether the decision to expel Pacific is properly viewed as a group boycott or concerted refusal to deal mandating per se invalidation. “Group boycotts” are often listed among the classes of economic activity that merit per se invalidation under §1. See Klor’s; Northern Pacific R. Co.; Silver. Exactly what types of activity fall within the forbidden category is, however, far from certain. “[T]here is more confusion about the scope and operation of the per se rule against group boycotts than in reference to any other aspect of the per se doctrine.” L. SULLIVAN, LAW OF ANTITRUST 229-230 (1977). Some care is therefore necessary in defining the category of concerted refusals to deal that mandate per se condemnation.

Cases to which this Court has applied the per se approach have generally involved joint efforts by a firm or firms to disadvantage competitors by “either directly denying or persuading or coercing suppliers or customers to deny relationships the competitors need in the competitive struggle.” SULLIVAN, supra, at 261-262. See, e.g., Silver (denial of necessary access to exchange members); Radiant Burners (denial of necessary certification of product); Associated Press (denial of important sources of news); Klor’s (denial of wholesale supplies). In these cases, the boycott often cut off access to a supply, facility, or market necessary to enable the boycotted firm to compete, Silver; Radiant Burners, and frequently the boycotting firms possessed a dominant position in the relevant market. E.g., Silver; Associated Press; Fashion Originators’ Guild. In addition, the practices were generally not justified by plausible arguments that they were intended to enhance overall efficiency and make markets more competitive. Under such circumstances the likelihood of anticompetitive effects is clear and the possibility of countervailing procompetitive effects is remote.

Although a concerted refusal to deal need not necessarily possess all of these traits to merit per se treatment, not every cooperative activity involving a restraint or exclusion will share with the per se forbidden boycotts the likelihood of predominantly anticompetitive consequences. For example, we recognized … in NCAA that per se treatment of the NCAA’s restrictions on the marketing of televised college football was inappropriate–despite the obvious restraint on output–because the “case involves an industry in which horizontal restraints on competition are essential if the product is to be available at all.”

Wholesale purchasing cooperatives such as Northwest are not a form of concerted activity characteristically likely to result in predominantly anticompetitive effects. Rather, such cooperative arrangements would seem to be “designed to increase economic efficiency and render markets more, rather than less, competitive.” Broadcast Music. The arrangement permits the participating retailers to achieve economies of scale in both the purchase and warehousing of wholesale supplies, and also ensures ready access to a stock of goods that might otherwise be unavailable on short notice. The cost savings and order-filling guarantees enable smaller retailers to reduce prices and maintain their retail stock so as to compete more effectively with larger retailers.

97

Page 36: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Pacific, of course, does not object to the existence of the cooperative arrangement, but rather raises an antitrust challenge to Northwest’s decision to bar Pacific from continued membership.6 It is therefore the action of expulsion that must be evaluated to determine whether per se treatment is appropriate. The act of expulsion from a wholesale cooperative does not necessarily imply anticompetitive animus and thereby raise a probability of anticompetitive effect. See Broadcast Music. Wholesale purchasing cooperatives must establish and enforce reasonable rules in order to function effectively. Disclosure rules, such as the one on which Northwest relies, may well provide the cooperative with a needed means for monitoring the creditworthiness of its members.7

Nor would the expulsion characteristically be likely to result in predominantly anticompetitive effects, at least in the type of situation this case presents. Unless the cooperative possesses market power or exclusive access to an element essential to effective competition, the conclusion that expulsion is virtually always likely to have an anticompetitive effect is not warranted. Absent such a showing with respect to a cooperative buying arrangement, courts should apply a rule-of-reason analysis. At no time has Pacific made a threshold showing that these structural characteristics are present in this case.

… The foregoing discussion suggests … that a satisfactory threshold determination whether anticompetitive effects would be likely might require a more detailed factual picture of market structure than the District Court had before it. Nonetheless, in our judgment the District Court’s rejection of per se analysis in this case was correct. A plaintiff seeking application of the per se rule must present a threshold case that the challenged activity falls into a category likely to have predominantly anticompetitive effects. The mere allegation of a concerted refusal to deal does not suffice because not all concerted refusals to deal are predominantly anticompetitive. When the plaintiff challenges expulsion from a joint buying cooperative, some showing must be made that the cooperative possesses market power or unique access to a business element necessary for effective competition. Focusing on the argument that the lack of procedural safeguards required per se liability, Pacific did not allege any such facts. Because the Court of Appeals applied an erroneous per se analysis in this case, the court

6 Because Pacific has not been wholly excluded from access to Northwest’s wholesale operations, there is perhaps some question whether the challenged activity is properly characterized as a concerted refusal to deal. To be precise, Northwest’s activity is a concerted refusal to deal with Pacific on substantially equal terms. Such activity might justify per se invalidation if it placed a competing firm at a severe competitive disadvantage. See generally Brodley, Joint Ventures and Antitrust Policy, 95 HARV.L.REV. 1521, 1532 (1982) (“Even if the joint venture does deal with outside firms, it may place them at a severe competitive disadvantage by treating them less favorably than it treats the [participants in the joint venture]”).7 Pacific argues, however, that this justification for expulsion was a pretext because the members of Northwest were fully aware of the change in ownership despite lack of formal notice. According to Pacific, Northwest’s motive in the expulsion was to place Pacific at a competitive disadvantage to retaliate for Pacific’s decision to engage in an independent wholesale operation. Such a motive might be more troubling. If Northwest’s action were not substantially related to the efficiency-enhancing or procompetitive purposes that otherwise justify the cooperative’s practices, an inference of anticompetitive animus might be appropriate. But such an argument is appropriately evaluated under the rule-of-reason analysis.

98

Page 37: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

never evaluated the District Court’s rule-of-reason analysis rejecting Pacific’s claim. A remand is therefore appropriate for the limited purpose of permitting appellate review of that determination.

III. “The per se rule is a valid and useful tool of antitrust policy and enforcement.” Broadcast Music. It does not denigrate the per se approach to suggest care in application. In this case, the Court of Appeals failed to exercise the requisite care and applied per se analysis inappropriately. The judgment of the Court of Appeals is therefore reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $FTC v. INDIANA FEDERATION OF DENTISTS

476 U.S. 447 (1986)

JUSTICE WHITE delivered the opinion of the Court. … [D]ental health insurers, responding to the demands of their policyholders, have attempted to contain the cost of dental treatment by, among other devices, limiting payment of benefits to the cost of the “least expensive yet adequate treatment” suitable to the needs of individual patients. Implementation of such cost-containment measures, known as “alternative benefits” plans, requires evaluation by the insurer of the diagnosis and recommendation of the treating dentist…. [T]o carry out such evaluation, insurers frequently request dentists to submit, along with insurance claim forms requesting payment of benefits, any dental x rays that have been used by the dentist in examining the patient…. Typically, claim forms and accompanying x rays are reviewed by lay claims examiners, who either approve payment of claims or, if the materials submitted raise a question whether the recommended course of treatment is in fact necessary, refer claims to dental consultants, who are licensed dentists, for further review. On the basis of the materials available, supplemented where appropriate by further diagnostic aids, the dental consultant may recommend that the insurer approve a claim, deny it, or pay only for a less expensive course of treatment.

Such review of [their] decisions has been viewed by some dentists as a threat to their professional independence and economic well-being. …[T]he Indiana Dental Association, … comprising some 85% of practicing dentists in the State of Indiana, initiated an aggressive effort to hinder insurers’ efforts to implement alternative benefits plans by enlisting member dentists to pledge not to submit x rays in conjunction with claim forms.1 The Association’s efforts met considerable success: large numbers of 1 A presentation made in 1974 by Dr. David McClure, an Association official and later one of the founders of respondent Indiana Federation of Dentists, is revealing as to the motives underlying the dentists’ resistance to the provision of x rays for use by insurers in making alternative benefits determinations:

The problems associated with third party programs are many, but I believe the “Indiana Plan” [i. e., the policy of refusing to submit x rays] to be sound and if we work together, we can win this battle. We are fighting an economic war where the very survival of our profession is at stake.

How long can some of the leaders of dentistry in other states be so complacent and willing to fall into the trap that is being set for us. If only they would take the time, to see from whence come

99

Page 38: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

dentists signed the pledge, and insurers operating in Indiana found it difficult to obtain compliance with their request for x rays and accordingly had to choose either to employ more expensive means of making alternative benefits determinations (for example, visiting the office of the treating dentist or conducting an independent oral examination) or to abandon such efforts altogether. [Eventually,] fears of possible antitrust liability had dampened the Association’s enthusiasm for opposing the submission of x rays to insurers. In 1979, the Association and a number of its constituent societies consented to a Federal Trade Commission order requiring them to cease and desist from further efforts to prevent member dentists from submitting x rays.

Not all Indiana dentists were content to leave the matter of submitting x rays to the individual dentist. … [A] group of such dentists formed the Indiana Federation of Dentists … to continue to pursue the Association’s policy of resisting insurers’ requests for x rays. … Although the Federation’s membership was small, numbering less than 100, its members were highly concentrated in and around three Indiana communities: Anderson, Lafayette, and Fort Wayne. The Federation succeeded in enlisting nearly 100% of the dental specialists in the Anderson area, and approximately 67% of the dentists in and around Lafayette. In the[se] areas…, the Federation was successful in continuing to enforce the Association’s prior policy of refusal to submit x rays to dental insurers.

… [The FTC] issued a complaint against the Federation, alleging in substance that its efforts to prevent its members from complying with insurers’ requests for x rays constituted an unfair method of competition in violation of §5 of the Federal Trade Commission Act. Following lengthy proceeding including a full evidentiary hearing before an Administrative Law Judge, the Commission ruled that the Federation’s policy constituted a violation of §5 [because it] amounted to a conspiracy in restraint of trade that was unreasonable and hence unlawful under the standards for judging such restraints developed in this Court’s precedents interpreting §1 of the Sherman Act. The Commission found that the Federation had conspired both with the Indiana Dental Association and with its own members to withhold cooperation with dental insurers’ requests for x rays; that absent such a restraint, competition among dentists for patients would have tended to lead dentists to compete with respect to their policies in dealing with patients’ insurers; and that in those areas where the Federation’s membership was strong, the Federation’s policy had had the actual effect of eliminating such competition among dentists and preventing insurers from obtaining access to x rays in the desired manner. These findings of anticompetitive effect, the Commission concluded, were sufficient to establish that the restraint was unreasonable even absent proof that the Federation’s policy had resulted in higher costs to the insurers and patients than would have occurred had the x rays been provided. Further, the Commission rejected the

the arrows that are heading in our direction. The Delta Dental Plans have bedded down with the unions and have been a party to setting up the greatest controls that any profession has ever known in a free society. . . .

The name of the game is money. The government and labor are determined to reduce the cost of the dental health dollar at the expense of the dentist. There is no way a dental service can be rendered cheaper when the third party has to have its share of the dollar.

Already we are locked into a fee freeze that could completely control the quality of dental care, if left on long enough.

100

Page 39: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Federation’s argument that its policy of withholding x rays was reasonable because the provision of x rays might lead the insurers to make inaccurate determinations of the proper level of care and thus injure the health of the insured patients; the Commission found no evidence that use of x rays by insurance companies in evaluating claims would result in inadequate dental care. …

… [T]he U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit … vacated the order on the ground that it was not supported by substantial evidence. Accepting the Federation’s characterization of its rule against submission of x rays as merely an ethical and moral policy designed to enhance the welfare of dental patients, the majority concluded that the Commission’s findings that the policy was anticompetitive were erroneous. According to the majority, the evidence did not support the finding that in the absence of restraint dentists would compete for patients by offering cooperation with the requests of the patients’ insurers, nor, even accepting that finding, was there evidence that the Federation’s efforts had prevented such competition. Further, the court held that the Commission’s findings were inadequate because of its failure both to offer a precise definition of the market in which the Federation was alleged to have restrained competition and to establish that the Federation had the power to restrain competition in that market. Finally, the majority faulted the Commission for not finding that the alleged restraint on competition among dentists had actually resulted in higher dental costs to patients and insurers. The third member of the Court of Appeals panel concurred in the judgment solely on the ground that there was insufficient proof that cooperation with insurers was an element of dental services as to which dentists would tend to compete. We granted certiorari …. We now reverse.

II. … [T]he court must accept the Commission’s findings of fact if they are supported by “such relevant evidence as a reasonable mind might accept as adequate to support a conclusion.” Universal Camera Corp. v. NLRB, 340 U.S. 474, 477 (1951). The legal issues presented—that is, the identification of governing legal standards and their application to the facts found—are, by contrast, for the courts to resolve, although even in considering such issues the courts are to give some deference to the Commission’s informed judgment that a particular commercial practice is to be condemned as “unfair.” The standard of “unfairness” under the FTC Act is, by necessity, an elusive one, encompassing not only practices that violate the Sherman Act and the other antitrust laws, but also practices that the Commission determines are against public policy for other reasons. Once the Commission has chosen a particular legal rationale for holding a practice to be unfair, however, … a reviewing court may not consider other reasons why the practice might be deemed unfair. In the case now before us, the sole basis of the FTC’s finding of an unfair method of competition was the Commission’s conclusion that the Federation’s collective decision to withhold x rays from insurers was an unreasonable and conspiratorial restraint of trade in violation of §1 of the Sherman Act. Accordingly, the legal question before us is whether the Commission’s factual findings, if supported by evidence, make out a violation of Sherman Act §1.

III. The relevant factual findings are that the members of the Federation conspired among themselves to withhold x rays requested by dental insurers for use in evaluating claims for benefits, and that this conspiracy had the effect of suppressing competition among dentists with respect to cooperation with the requests of the insurance companies.

101

Page 40: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

As to the first of these findings there can be no serious dispute: abundant evidence in the record reveals that one of the primary reasons—if not the primary reason—for the Federation’s existence was the promulgation and enforcement of the [rule] against submission of x rays in conjunction with insurance claim forms.

As for the second crucial finding—that competition was actually suppressed—the Seventh Circuit held it to be unsupported by the evidence, on two theories. First, the court stated that the evidence did not establish that cooperation with requests for information by patients’ insurance companies was an aspect of the provision of dental services with respect to which dentists would, in the absence of some restraint, compete. Second, the court found that even assuming that dentists would otherwise compete with respect to policies of cooperating or not cooperating with insurance companies, the Federation’s policy did not impair that competition, for the member dentists continued to allow insurance companies to use other means of evaluating their diagnoses when reviewing claims for benefits: specifically, “the IFD member dentists allowed insurers to visit the dental office to review and examine the patient’s x rays along with all of the other diagnostic and clinical aids used in formulating a proper course of dental treatment.”

Neither of these criticisms … is well founded. The [FTC’s] finding that “[i]n the absence of ... concerted behavior, individual dentists would have been subject to market forces of competition, creating incentives for them to ... comply with the requests of patients’ third-party insurers,” finds support not only in common sense and economic theory, upon both of which the FTC may reasonably rely, but also in record documents, including newsletters circulated among Indiana dentists, revealing that Indiana dentists themselves perceived that unrestrained competition tended to lead their colleagues to comply with insurers’ requests for x rays. Moreover, there was evidence that outside of Indiana, in States where dentists had not collectively refused to submit x rays, insurance companies found little difficulty in obtaining compliance by dentists with their requests. A “reasonable mind” could conclude on the basis of this evidence that competition for patients, who have obvious incentives for seeking dentists who will cooperate with their insurers, would tend to lead dentists in Indiana … to cooperate with requests for information by their patients’ insurers.

The Commission’s finding that such competition was actually diminished where the Federation held sway also finds adequate support in the record. The Commission found that in the areas where Federation membership among dentists was most significant (that is, in the vicinity of Anderson and Lafayette) insurance companies were unable to obtain compliance with their requests for submission of x rays in conjunction with claim forms and were forced to resort to other, more costly, means of reviewing diagnoses for the purpose of benefit determination.

Neither the opinion of the Court of Appeals nor the brief of respondent identifies any evidence suggesting that the Commission’s finding that the Federation’s policy had an actual impact on the ability of insurers to obtain the x rays they requested was incorrect. The lower court’s conclusion that this evidence is to be discounted because Federation members continued to cooperate with insurers by allowing them to use more costly—indeed, prohibitively costly—methods of reviewing treatment decisions is unpersuasive. The fact remains that the dentists’ customers (that is, the patients and their insurers) sought a particular service: cooperation with the insurers’ pretreatment review

102

Page 41: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

through the forwarding of x rays in conjunction with claim forms. The Federation’s collective activities resulted in the denial of the information the customers requested in the form that they requested it, and forced them to choose between acquiring that information in a more costly manner or forgoing it altogether. To this extent, at least, competition among dentists with respect to cooperation with the requests of insurers was restrained.

IV. The question remains whether these findings are legally sufficient to establish a violation of §1 of the Sherman Act—that is, whether the Federation’s collective refusal to cooperate with insurers’ requests for x rays constitutes an “unreasonable” restraint of trade. Under our precedents, a restraint may be adjudged unreasonable either because it fits within a class of restraints that has been held to be “per se” unreasonable, or because it violates what has come to be known as the “Rule of Reason,” under which the “test of legality is whether the restraint imposed is such as merely regulates and perhaps thereby promotes competition or whether it is such as may suppress or even destroy competition.” Chicago Board of Trade.

The policy of the Federation with respect to its members’ dealings with third-party insurers resembles practices that have been labeled “group boycotts”: the policy constitutes a concerted refusal to deal on particular terms with patients covered by group dental insurance. Although this Court has in the past stated that group boycotts are unlawful per se, see Klor’s, we decline to resolve this case by forcing the Federation’s policy into the “boycott” pigeonhole and invoking the per se rule. As we observed … in Northwest Wholesale Stationers, the category of restraints classed as group boycotts is not to be expanded indiscriminately, and the per se approach has generally been limited to cases in which firms with market power boycott suppliers or customers in order to discourage them from doing business with a competitor—a situation obviously not present here. Moreover, we have been slow to condemn rules adopted by professional associations as unreasonable per se, see Professional Engineers, and, in general, to extend per se analysis to restraints imposed in the context of business relationships where the economic impact of certain practices is not immediately obvious, see BMI. Thus, as did the FTC, we evaluate the restraint at issue in this case under the Rule of Reason rather than a rule of per se illegality.

Application of the Rule of Reason to these facts is not a matter of any great difficulty. The Federation’s policy takes the form of a horizontal agreement among the participating dentists to withhold from their customers a particular service that they desire—the forwarding of x rays to insurance companies along with claim forms. “While this is not price fixing as such, no elaborate industry analysis is required to demonstrate the anticompetitive character of such an agreement.” Professional Engineers. A refusal to compete with respect to the package of services offered to customers, no less than a refusal to compete with respect to the price term of an agreement, impairs the ability of the market to advance social welfare by ensuring the provision of desired goods and services to consumers at a price approximating the marginal cost of providing them. Absent some countervailing procompetitive virtue—such as, for example, the creation of efficiencies in the operation of a market or the provision of goods and services, see BMI; Chicago Board of Trade—such an agreement limiting consumer choice by impeding the “ordinary give and take of the market place,” Professional Engineers, cannot be sustained

103

Page 42: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

under the Rule of Reason. No credible argument has been advanced for the proposition that making it more costly for the insurers and patients who are the dentists’ customers to obtain information needed for evaluating the dentists’ diagnoses has any such procompetitive effect.

The Federation advances three principal arguments for the proposition that, notwithstanding its lack of competitive virtue, the Federation’s policy of withholding x rays should not be deemed an unreasonable restraint of trade. First, … the Federation suggests that in the absence of specific findings by the Commission concerning the definition of the market in which the Federation allegedly restrained trade and the power of the Federation’s members in that market, the conclusion that the Federation unreasonably restrained trade is erroneous as a matter of law, regardless of whether the challenged practices might be impermissibly anticompetitive if engaged in by persons who together possessed power in a specifically defined market. This contention, however, runs counter to the Court’s holding in NCAA, that “[a]s a matter of law, the absence of proof of market power does not justify a naked restriction on price or output,” and that such a restriction “requires some competitive justification even in the absence of a detailed market analysis.” Moreover, even if the restriction imposed by the Federation is not sufficiently “naked” to call this principle into play, the Commission’s failure to engage in detailed market analysis is not fatal to its finding of a violation of the Rule of Reason. The Commission found that in two localities in the State of Indiana (the Anderson and Lafayette areas), Federation dentists constituted heavy majorities of the practicing dentists and that as a result of the efforts of the Federation, insurers in those areas were, over a period of years, actually unable to obtain compliance with their requests for submission of x rays. Since the purpose of the inquiries into market definition and market power is to determine whether an arrangement has the potential for genuine adverse effects on competition, “proof of actual detrimental effect, such as a reduction of output,” can obviate the need for an inquiry into market power, which is but a “surrogate for detrimental effect.” 7 P. AREEDA, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1511, p.429 (1986). In this case, we conclude that the finding of actual, sustained adverse effects on competition in those areas where IFD dentists predominated, viewed in light of the reality that markets for dental services tend to be relatively localized, is legally sufficient to support a finding that the challenged restraint was unreasonable even in the absence of elaborate market analysis.

Second, the Federation … argues that a holding that its policy of withholding x rays constituted an unreasonable restraint of trade is precluded by the Commission’s failure to make any finding that the policy resulted in the provision of dental services that were more costly than those that the patients and their insurers would have chosen were they able to evaluate x rays in conjunction with claim forms. This argument, too, is unpersuasive. Although it is true that the goal of the insurers in seeking submission of x rays for use in their review of benefits claims was to minimize costs by choosing the least expensive adequate course of dental treatment, a showing that this goal was actually achieved through the means chosen is not an essential step in establishing that the dentists’ attempt to thwart its achievement by collectively refusing to supply the requested information was an unreasonable restraint of trade. A concerted and effective effort to withhold (or make more costly) information desired by consumers for the purpose of determining whether a particular purchase is cost justified is likely enough to

104

Page 43: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

disrupt the proper functioning of the price-setting mechanism of the market that it may be condemned even absent proof that it resulted in higher prices or, as here, the purchase of higher priced service, than would occur in its absence. Professional Engineers. Moreover, even if the desired information were in fact completely useless to the insurers and their patients in making an informed choice regarding the least costly adequate course of treatment—or, to put it another way, if the costs of evaluating the information were far greater than the cost savings resulting from its use—the Federation would still not be justified in deciding on behalf of its members’ customers that they did not need the information: presumably, if that were the case, the discipline of the market would itself soon result in the insurers’ abandoning their requests for x rays. The Federation is not entitled to pre-empt the working of the market by deciding for itself that its customers do not need that which they demand.

Third, the Federation complains that the Commission erred in failing to consider … noncompetitive “quality of care” justifications for the prohibition on provision of x rays to insurers in conjunction with claim forms. …. The gist of the claim is that x rays, standing alone, are not adequate bases for diagnosis of dental problems or for the formulation of an acceptable course of treatment. Accordingly, if insurance companies are permitted to determine whether they will pay a claim for dental treatment on the basis of x rays as opposed to a full examination of all the diagnostic aids available to the examining dentist, there is a danger that they will erroneously decline to pay for treatment that is in fact in the interest of the patient, and that the patient will as a result be deprived of fully adequate care.

The Federation’s argument is flawed both legally and factually. The premise of the argument is that, far from having no effect on the cost of dental services chosen by patients and their insurers, the provision of x rays will have too great an impact: it will lead to the reduction of costs through the selection of inadequate treatment. Precisely such a justification for withholding information from customers was rejected as illegitimate in the Professional Engineers case. The argument is, in essence, that an unrestrained market in which consumers are given access to the information they believe to be relevant to their choices will lead them to make unwise and even dangerous choices. Such an argument amounts to “nothing less than a frontal assault on the basic policy of the Sherman Act.” Professional Engineers. Moreover, there is no particular reason to believe that the provision of information will be more harmful to consumers in the market for dental services than in other markets. Insurers deciding what level of care to pay for are not themselves the recipients of those services, but it is by no means clear that they lack incentives to consider the welfare of the patient as well as the minimization of costs. They are themselves in competition for the patronage of the patients—or, in most cases, the unions or businesses that contract on their behalf for group insurance coverage—and must satisfy their potential customers not only that they will provide coverage at a reasonable cost, but also that that coverage will be adequate to meet their customers’ dental needs. There is thus no more reason to expect dental insurance companies to sacrifice quality in return for cost savings than to believe this of consumers in, say, the market for engineering services. Accordingly, if noncompetitive quality-of-service justifications are inadmissible to justify the denial of information to consumers in the latter market, there is little reason to credit such justifications here.

105

Page 44: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

In any event, the [FTC] did not, as the Federation suggests, refuse even to consider the quality-of-care justification for the withholding of x rays. Rather, [it] held that the Federation had failed to introduce sufficient evidence to establish such a justification: “IFD has not pointed to any evidence—or even argued—that any consumers have in fact been harmed by alternative benefits determinations, or that actual determinations have been medically erroneous.” The evidence … on this issue appears to have consisted entirely of expert opinion testimony, with the Federation’s experts arguing that x rays generally provide an insufficient basis, standing alone, for dental diagnosis, and the Commission’s experts testifying that x rays may be useful in assessing diagnosis of and appropriate treatment for a variety of dental complaints. The Commission was amply justified in concluding on the basis of this conflicting evidence that even if concern for the quality of patient care could under some circumstances serve as a justification for a restraint of the sort imposed here, the evidence did not support a finding that the careful use of x rays as a basis for evaluating insurance claims is in fact destructive of proper standards of dental care.4 …

V. The factual findings of the Commission regarding the effect of the Federation’s policy of withholding x rays are supported by substantial evidence, and those findings are sufficient as a matter of law to establish a violation of §1 of the Sherman Act, and, hence, §5 of the Federal Trade Commission Act. … The judgment of the Court of Appeals is accordingly Reversed.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $Discussion Problem 2: Visa/Mastercard Joint Venture

INSTRUCTIONS

In class on a date TBA, we will discuss the Visa & MasterCard joint ventures and their exclusion of the owners of American Express and Discover. To prepare for the discussion, please do the following:

1) Read the description of the litigation between Discover and Visa (see link on reading list to prior edition of Antitrust Revolution)

4 It is undisputed that lay claims examiners employed by insurance companies have no authority to deny claims on the basis of examination of x rays; rather, initial screening of x rays serves only as a means of identifying cases that merit further scrutiny by the licensed dentists serving as consultants to the insurers. Any recommendation that benefits be denied or a less expensive course of treatment be pursued is based on the professional judgment of a licensed dentist that the materials available to him - x rays, claim forms, and whatever further diagnostic aids he chooses to consult - are sufficient to indicate that the treating dentist’s recommendation is not necessary to the health of the patient. There is little basis for concluding that, where such a divergence of professional judgment exists, the treatment recommendation made by the patient’s dentist should be assumed to be the one that in fact represents the best interests of the patient.

106

Page 45: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

2) Read the description of the Justice Dept. lawsuit against Visa and MasterCard (below);

3) Review the material on boycotts, focusing particularly on Northwest Wholesale Stationers;

4) Prepare the Questions for Discussion (below).

JUSTICE DEPARTMENT COMPLAINT

On October 7, 1998, the U.S. Department of Justice filed a complaint in the Southern District of New York against the Visa and MasterCard networks alleging that they had violated Sherman Act §1 by

(1) allowing both entities to be controlled by the same group of banks; and (2) adopting and enforcing exclusionary rules of the type at issue in the Visa/Discover

litigation.

The specific allegations in the complaint are summarized below:

Allegations Regarding Market Analysis: The relevant product market is “general purpose cards” (charge cards and credit cards) on the network level. The geographic market is the United States. Relevant market shares are:

% dollar volume % cards issued

Visa 50 53

MasterCard 25 33

Total 75 86

There are significant barriers to entry by establishing a new card network including investments to develop cardholder and merchant bases.

Allegations Regarding Joint Control: A group of the nation’s largest banks including Citibank, Chase Manhattan and Bank of America issue both Visa cards and MasterCards. These banks effectively control both networks through representatives serving on both Boards of Directors and on important policy-making committees. Because of this joint control and the large overlapping membership, all policy decisions made by one network are immediately accessible to the other. As a result, both networks have acted to limit some types of competition between themselves and between member banks. Both networks have repeatedly resisted proposals to increase network independence and enhance competition. The specific consequences of the dual control of the two networks allegedly included:

Failure to engage in competitive advertising to inform consumers of the relative value of different brands of charge/credit cards.

107

Page 46: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Reduced and delayed investment in new technologies, products and services such as internet technology and smart cards.

Allegations Regarding Exclusionary Rules: Visa and MasterCard both have rules that prohibit members from issuing Discover or American Express cards. Neither network forbids members from issuing the other’s cards or Diner’s Club. These exclusionary rules have had the effect of essentially preventing American Express or Discover from getting banks to issue cards on their networks. By contrast, in overseas markets where the exclusionary rules do not operate, some banks issue American Express or Discover cards in addition to Visa and MasterCard. This has resulted in increased competition and the introduction of new products and services. The government concluded from the overseas experience that the exclusionary rules are unnecessary and anti-competitive.

Relief Requested: The Justice Departments seeks injunctions:

(1) prohibiting the two networks from having representation on each other’s boards of directors or key committees;

(2) prohibiting giving members on the governing bodies off one network access to competitively sensitive information about the other network; and

(3) prohibiting enforcement of the exclusionary rules.

QUESTIONS FOR DISCUSSION

1) Given that there appears to be some real competition between the banks that issue Visa and MasterCard regarding pricing and services, how important is competition between networks?

2) What pro-competitive explanations might there be for the exclusionary rules employed by Visa & MasterCard? What anti-competitive explanations might there be?

3) Under Northwest Wholesale Stationers, should these agreements to exclude competitors be judged under the per se rule or the rule of reason? If proved, how would the alleged dual control of the two networks affect the analysis?

4) What kinds of evidence would be helpful to the Justice Department in proving that the networks’ dual control and exclusionary rules harm competition? What kinds of evidence would be helpful to the networks to show lack of harm to competition? Whose case looks stronger based on what you do know?

5) Try to articulate in your own words the property rights argument made by Visa in the Discover litigation. How convincing do you find it?

6) If you could create a rule without regard to existing precedent, when, if ever, should a joint venture be forced to allow a rival to from participate? Should we worry about exclusion by joint venturers with market power more or less than exclusion by monopolists?

108

Page 47: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

$ $ $ $ $ $ $Antitrust & The First Amendment: The Noerr-Pennington Doctrine

I. Generally: attempts to influence legislative or executive action not actionable under AT laws, nor are attempts to use govt. agencies & courts to advocate points of view re biz/economic interests--regardless of intent or purpose

II. Leading Examples of Protected BehaviorA. Noerr (1961): campaign by RR trade assn. to get anti-trucking legislation: tax on

trucks, preventing heavy loads; got Pa governor to veto bill allowing bigger trucks; hired public relations firm to foment distrust of truckers

B Pennington (1965): Unions & large coal cos. conspire to get Sec’y of Labor to impose hard regs on small coal cos. (high min wages, etc)

III. Political Boycotts: NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware (1982)A. boycott of white merchants by black citizens to protest discriminationB. political boycotts, even if incidental economic effect, governed by NoerrC. states' right to regulate economic activity doesn't justify prohibition of non-violent

politically motivated boycott designed to force governmental & economic change & to effectuate rights guaranteed by constitution

$ $ $ $ $ $ $ALLIED TUBE & CONDUIT CORP. v. INDIAN HEAD, INC.

486 U.S. 492 (1988.)

Justice BRENNAN delivered the opinion of the Court. Petitioner contends that its efforts to affect the product standard-setting process of a private association are immune from antitrust liability under the Noerr doctrine primarily because the association’s standards are widely adopted into law by state and local governments. Eastern Railroad Presidents Conference v. Noerr Motor Freight, 365 U.S. 127 (1961) (Noerr). The United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit held that Noerr immunity did not apply. We affirm.

I. The National Fire Protection Association (Association) is a private, voluntary organization with more than 31,500 individual and group members representing industry, labor, academia, insurers, organized medicine, firefighters, and government. The Association, among other things, publishes product standards and codes related to fire protection through a process known as “consensus standard making.” One of the codes it publishes is the National Electrical Code (Code), which establishes product and performance requirements for the design and installation of electrical wiring systems. Revised every three years, the Code is the most influential electrical code in the nation.

109

Page 48: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

A substantial number of state and local governments routinely adopt the Code into law with little or no change; private certification laboratories, such as Underwriters Laboratories, normally will not list and label an electrical product that does not meet Code standards; many underwriters will refuse to insure structures that are not built in conformity with the Code; and many electrical inspectors, contractors, and distributors will not use a product that falls outside the Code.

Among the electrical products covered by the Code is electrical conduit, the hollow tubing used as a raceway to carry electrical wires through the walls and floors of buildings. Throughout the relevant period, the Code permitted using electrical conduit made of steel, and almost all conduit sold was in fact steel conduit. Starting in 1980, respondent began to offer plastic conduit made of polyvinyl chloride. Respondent claims its plastic conduit offers significant competitive advantages over steel conduit, including pliability, lower installed cost, and lower susceptibility to short circuiting. In 1980, however, there was also a scientific basis for concern that, during fires in high-rise buildings, polyvinyl chloride conduit might burn and emit toxic fumes.

Respondent initiated a proposal to include polyvinyl chloride conduit as an approved type of electrical conduit in the 1981 edition of the Code. Following approval by one of the Association’s professional panels, this proposal was scheduled for consideration at the 1980 annual meeting, where it could be adopted or rejected by a simple majority of the members present. Alarmed that, if approved, respondent’s product might pose a competitive threat to steel conduit, petitioner, the Nation’s largest producer of steel conduit, met to plan strategy with, among others, members of the steel industry, other steel conduit manufacturers, and its independent sales agents. They collectively agreed to exclude respondent’s product from the 1981 Code by packing the upcoming annual meeting with new Association members whose only function would be to vote against the polyvinyl chloride proposal.

Combined, the steel interests recruited 230 persons to join the Association and to attend the annual meeting to vote against the proposal. Petitioner alone recruited 155 persons--including employees, executives, sales agents, the agents’ employees, employees from two divisions that did not sell electrical products, and the wife of a national sales director. Petitioner and the other steel interests also paid over $100,000 for the membership, registration, and attendance expenses of these voters. At the annual meeting, the steel group voters were instructed where to sit and how and when to vote by group leaders who used walkie-talkies and hand signals to facilitate communication. Few of the steel group voters had any of the technical documentation necessary to follow the meeting. None of them spoke at the meeting to give their reasons for opposing the proposal to approve polyvinyl chloride conduit. Nonetheless, with their solid vote in opposition, the proposal was rejected and returned to committee by a vote of 394 to 390. Respondent appealed the membership’s vote to the Association’s Board of Directors, but the Board denied the appeal on the ground that, although the Association’s rules had been circumvented, they had not been violated.1

1 … The Association subsequently approved use of polyvinyl chloride conduit for buildings of less than three stories in the 1984 Code, and for all buildings in the 1987 Code.

110

Page 49: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

[R]espondent brought this suit … alleging that petitioner and others had unreasonably restrained trade in the electrical conduit market in violation of §1 of the Sherman Act. … Petitioner conceded that it had conspired with the other steel interests to exclude respondent’s product from the Code and that it had a pecuniary interest to do so. The jury, instructed under the rule of reason that respondent carried the burden of showing that the anticompetitive effects of petitioner’s actions outweighed any procompetitive benefits of standard setting, found petitioner liable. In answers to special interrogatories, the jury found that petitioner did not violate any rules of the Association and acted, at least in part, based on a genuine belief that plastic conduit was unsafe, but that petitioner nonetheless did “subvert” the consensus standard-making process of the Association. The jury also made special findings that petitioner’s actions had an adverse impact on competition, were not the least restrictive means of expressing petitioner’s opposition to the use of polyvinyl chloride conduit in the marketplace, and unreasonably restrained trade in violation of the antitrust laws. The jury then awarded respondent damages, to be trebled, of $3.8 million for lost profits resulting from the effect that excluding polyvinyl chloride conduit from the 1981 Code had of its own force in the marketplace. No damages were awarded for injuries stemming from the adoption of the 1981 Code by governmental entities.2

The District Court then granted a judgment n.o.v. for petitioner, reasoning that Noerr immunity applied because the Association was “akin to a legislature” and because petitioner, “by the use of methods consistent with acceptable standards of political action, genuinely intended to influence the [Association] with respect to the National Electrical Code, and to thereby influence the various state and local legislative bodies which adopt the [Code].” The Court of Appeals reversed, rejecting both the argument that the Association should be treated as a “quasi-legislative” body because legislatures routinely adopt the Code and the argument that efforts to influence the Code were immune under Noerr as indirect attempts to influence state and local governments. We granted certiorari to address important issues regarding the application of Noerr immunity to private standard-setting associations.

II. Concerted efforts to restrain or monopolize trade by petitioning government officials are protected from antitrust liability under the doctrine established by Noerr; United Mine Workers v. Pennington, 381 U.S. 657, 669-672 (1965); and California Motor Transport Co. v. Trucking Unlimited, 404 U.S. 508 (1972). The scope of this protection depends, however, on the source, context, and nature of the anticompetitive restraint at issue. “[W]here a restraint upon trade or monopolization is the result of valid governmental action, as opposed to private action,” those urging the governmental action 2 Although the District Court was of the view that at trial respondent relied solely on the theory that its injury “flowed from legislative action,” the Court of Appeals determined that respondent was awarded damages only on the theory

that the stigma of not obtaining [Code] approval of its products and [petitioner’s] ‘marketing’ of that stigma caused independent marketplace harm … in those jurisdictions permitting use of [polyvinyl chloride] conduit, as well as those which later adopted the 1984 [Code], which permitted use of [polyvinyl chloride] conduit in buildings less than three stories high. [Respondent] did not seek redress for any injury arising from the adoption of the [Code] by the various governments.

We decide the case as it was framed by the Court of Appeals.

111

Page 50: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

enjoy absolute immunity from antitrust liability for the anticompetitive restraint. Noerr. In addition, where, independent of any government action, the anticompetitive restraint results directly from private action, the restraint cannot form the basis for antitrust liability if it is “incidental” to a valid effort to influence governmental action. Id. The validity of such efforts, and thus the applicability of Noerr immunity, varies with the context and nature of the activity. A publicity campaign directed at the general public, seeking legislation or executive action, enjoys antitrust immunity even when the campaign employs unethical and deceptive methods. But in less political arenas, unethical and deceptive practices can constitute abuses of administrative or judicial processes that may result in antitrust violations.4 California Motor Transport.

In this case, the restraint of trade on which liability was predicated was the Association’s exclusion of respondent’s product from the Code, and no damages were imposed for the incorporation of that Code by any government. The relevant context is thus the standard-setting process of a private association. Typically, private standard-setting associations, like the Association in this case, include members having horizontal and vertical business relations. See generally 7 P. AREEDA, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1477 (1986) (trade and standard-setting associations routinely treated as continuing conspiracies of their members). There is no doubt that the members of such associations often have economic incentives to restrain competition and that the product standards set by such associations have a serious potential for anticompetitive harm.5 Agreement on a product standard is, after all, implicitly an agreement not to manufacture, distribute, or purchase certain types of products. Accordingly, private standard-setting associations have traditionally been objects of antitrust scrutiny. When, however, private associations promulgate safety standards based on the merits of objective expert judgments and through procedures that prevent the standard-setting process from being biased by members with economic interests in stifling product competition, those private standards can have significant procompetitive advantages. It is this potential for procompetitive benefits that has led most lower courts to apply rule-of-reason analysis to product standard-setting by private associations.6

Given this context, petitioner does not enjoy the immunity accorded those who merely urge the government to restrain trade. We agree with the Court of Appeals that the Association cannot be treated as a “quasi-legislative” body simply because legislatures routinely adopt the Code the Association publishes. Whatever de facto authority the Association enjoys, no official authority has been conferred on it by any

4 Of course, in whatever forum, private action that is not genuinely aimed at procuring favorable government action is a mere sham that cannot be deemed a valid effort to influence government action. Noerr; California Motor Transport.5 “Product standardization might impair competition in several ways.... [It] might deprive some consumers of a desired product, eliminate quality competition, exclude rival producers, or facilitate oligopolistic pricing by easing rivals’ ability to monitor each other’s prices.” 7 P. AREEDA, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1503 (1986).6 … Concerted efforts to enforce (rather than just agree upon) private product standards face more rigorous antitrust scrutiny. See Radiant Burners v. Peoples Gas Light & Coke Co., 364 U.S. 656, 659-660 (1961) (per curiam). See also Fashion Originators’ Guild v. FTC, 312 U.S. 457 (1941).

112

Page 51: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

government, and the decisionmaking body of the Association is composed, at least in part, of persons with economic incentives to restrain trade. “We may presume, absent a showing to the contrary, that [a government] acts in the public interest. A private party, on the other hand, may be presumed to be acting primarily on his or its own behalf.” Hallie v. Eau Claire, 471 U.S. 34, 45 (1985). The dividing line between restraints resulting from governmental action and those resulting from private action may not always be obvious. But where, as here, the restraint is imposed by persons unaccountable to the public and without official authority, many of whom have personal financial interests in restraining competition, we have no difficulty concluding that the restraint has resulted from private action.

Noerr immunity might still apply, however, if, as petitioner argues, the exclusion of polyvinyl chloride conduit from the Code, and the effect that exclusion had of its own force in the marketplace, were incidental to a valid effort to influence governmental action. Petitioner notes that the lion’s share of the anticompetitive effect in this case came from the predictable adoption of the Code into law by a large number of state and local governments. Indeed, petitioner argues that, because state and local governments rely so heavily on the Code and lack the resources or technical expertise to second-guess it, efforts to influence the Association’s standard-setting process are the most effective means of influencing legislation regulating electrical conduit. This claim to Noerr immunity has some force. The effort to influence governmental action in this case certainly cannot be characterized as a sham given the actual adoption of the 1981 Code into a number of statutes and local ordinances. Nor can we quarrel with petitioner’s contention that, given the widespread adoption of the Code into law, any effect the 1981 Code had in the marketplace of its own force was, in the main, incidental to petitioner’s genuine effort to influence governmental action. And, as petitioner persuasively argues, the claim of Noerr immunity cannot be dismissed on the ground that the conduct at issue involved no “direct” petitioning of government officials, for Noerr itself immunized a form of “indirect” petitioning. See Noerr (immunizing a publicity campaign directed at the general public on the ground that it was part of an effort to influence legislative and executive action).

Nonetheless, the validity of petitioner’s actions remains an issue. We cannot agree with petitioner’s absolutist position that the Noerr doctrine immunizes every concerted effort that is genuinely intended to influence governmental action. If all such conduct were immunized then, for example, competitors would be free to enter into horizontal price agreements as long as they wished to propose that price as an appropriate level for governmental ratemaking or price supports. Horizontal conspiracies or boycotts designed to exact higher prices or other economic advantages from the government would be immunized on the ground that they are genuinely intended to influence the government to agree to the conspirators’ terms. Firms could claim immunity for boycotts or horizontal output restrictions on the ground that they are intended to dramatize the plight of their industry and spur legislative action. Immunity might even be claimed for anticompetitive mergers on the theory that they give the merging corporations added political clout. Nor is it necessarily dispositive that packing the Association’s meeting may have been the most effective means of securing government action, for one could imagine situations where the most effective means of influencing government officials is bribery, and we have never suggested that that kind of attempt to influence the

113

Page 52: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

government merits protection. We thus conclude that the Noerr immunity of anticompetitive activity intended to influence the government depends not only on its impact, but also on the context and nature of the activity.

Here petitioner’s actions took place within the context of the standard-setting process of a private association. Having concluded that the Association is not a “quasi-legislative” body, we reject petitioner’s argument that any efforts to influence the Association must be treated as efforts to influence a “quasi-legislature” and given the same wide berth accorded legislative lobbying. That rounding up supporters is an acceptable and constitutionally protected method of influencing elections does not mean that rounding up economically interested persons to set private standards must also be protected. Nor do we agree with petitioner’s contention that, regardless of the Association’s nonlegislative status, the effort to influence the Code should receive the same wide latitude given ethically dubious efforts to influence legislative action in the political arena simply because the ultimate aim of the effort to influence the private standard-setting process was (principally) legislative action. The ultimate aim is not dispositive. A misrepresentation to a court would not necessarily be entitled to the same antitrust immunity allowed deceptive practices in the political arena simply because the odds were very good that the court’s decision would be codified—nor for that matter would misrepresentations made under oath at a legislative committee hearing in the hopes of spurring legislative action.

What distinguishes this case from Noerr and its progeny is that the context and nature of petitioner’s activity make it the type of commercial activity that has traditionally had its validity determined by the antitrust laws themselves. True, in Noerr we immunized conduct that could be characterized as a conspiracy among railroads to destroy business relations between truckers and their customers. But we noted there:

There are no specific findings that the railroads attempted directly to persuade anyone not to deal with the truckers. Moreover, all the evidence in the record, both oral and documentary, deals with the railroads’ efforts to influence the passage and enforcement of laws. Circulars, speeches, newspaper articles, editorials, magazine articles, memoranda and all other documents discuss in one way or another the railroads’ charges that heavy trucks injure the roads, violate the laws and create traffic hazards, and urge that truckers should be forced to pay a fair share of the costs of rebuilding the roads, that they should be compelled to obey the laws, and that limits should be placed upon the weight of the loads they are permitted to carry.

In light of those findings, we characterized the railroads’ activity as a classic “attempt ... to influence legislation by a campaign of publicity,” an “inevitable” and “incidental” effect of which was “the infliction of some direct injury upon the interests of the party against whom the campaign is directed.” The essential character of such a publicity campaign was, we concluded, political, and could not be segregated from the activity’s impact on business. Rather, the plaintiff’s cause of action simply embraced the inherent possibility in such political fights “that one group or the other will get hurt by the arguments that are made.” As a political activity, special factors counseled against regulating the publicity campaign under the antitrust laws:

Insofar as [the Sherman] Act sets up a code of ethics at all, it is a code that condemns trade restraints, not political activity, and, as we have already pointed out, a publicity

114

Page 53: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

campaign to influence governmental action falls clearly into the category of political activity. The proscriptions of the Act, tailored as they are for the business world, are not at all appropriate for application in the political arena. Congress has traditionally exercised extreme caution in legislating with respect to problems relating to the conduct of political activities, a caution which has been reflected in the decisions of this Court interpreting such legislation. All of this caution would go for naught if we permitted an extension of the Sherman Act to regulate activities of that nature simply because those activities have a commercial impact and involve conduct that can be termed unethical.

In Noerr, then, the political context and nature of the activity precluded inquiry into its antitrust validity.9

Here the context and nature of the activity do not counsel against inquiry into its validity. Unlike the publicity campaign in Noerr, the activity at issue here did not take place in the open political arena, where partisanship is the hallmark of decisionmaking, but within the confines of a private standard-setting process. The validity of conduct within that process has long been defined and circumscribed by the antitrust laws without regard to whether the private standards are likely to be adopted into law. Indeed, because private standard-setting by associations comprising firms with horizontal and vertical business relations is permitted at all under the antitrust laws only on the understanding that it will be conducted in a nonpartisan manner offering procompetitive benefits, the standards of conduct in this context are, at least in some respects, more rigorous than the standards of conduct prevailing in the partisan political arena or in the adversarial process of adjudication. The activity at issue here thus cannot, as in Noerr, be characterized as an activity that has traditionally been regulated with extreme caution, or as an activity that “bear[s] little if any resemblance to the combinations normally held violative of the Sherman Act.” And petitioner did not confine itself to efforts to persuade an independent decisionmaker, cf. Noerr (describing the immunized conduct as “mere solicitation”); rather, it organized and orchestrated the actual exercise of the Association’s decisionmaking authority in setting a standard. Nor can the setting of the Association’s Code be characterized as merely an exercise of the power of persuasion, for it in part involves the exercise of market power. The Association’s members, after all, include consumers, distributors, and manufacturers of electrical conduit, and any agreement to exclude polyvinyl chloride conduit from the Code is in part an implicit agreement not to trade in that type of electrical conduit.

Although one could reason backwards from the legislative impact of the Code to the conclusion that the conduct at issue here is “political,” we think that, given the context and nature of the conduct, it can more aptly be characterized as commercial activity with a political impact. Just as the antitrust laws should not regulate political activities “simply because those activities have a commercial impact,” Noerr, so the antitrust laws should not necessarily immunize what are in essence commercial activities simply because they have a political impact.10

9 Similarly in California Motor Transport any antitrust review of the validity of the activity at issue was limited and structured by the fact that there the antitrust defendants were “us[ing] the channels and procedures of state and federal agencies and courts.” 10 It is admittedly difficult to draw the precise lines separating anticompetitive political activity that is immunized despite its commercial impact from anticompetitive commercial activity that is

115

Page 54: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co., 458 U.S. 886 (1982), is not to the contrary. In that case we held that the First Amendment protected the nonviolent elements of a boycott of white merchants organized by the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People and designed to make white government and business leaders comply with a list of demands for equality and racial justice. Although the boycotters intended to inflict economic injury on the merchants, the boycott was not motivated by any desire to lessen competition or to reap economic benefits but by the aim of vindicating rights of equality and freedom lying at the heart of the Constitution, and the boycotters were consumers who did not stand to profit financially from a lessening of competition in the boycotted market. Here, in contrast, petitioner was at least partially motivated by the desire to lessen competition, and, because of petitioner’s line of business, stood to reap substantial economic benefits from making it difficult for respondent to compete.11

… [T]he context and nature of petitioner’s efforts to influence the Code persuade us that the validity of those efforts must, despite their political impact, be evaluated under the standards of conduct set forth by the antitrust laws that govern the private standard-setting process. The antitrust validity of these efforts is not established, without more, by petitioner’s literal compliance with the rules of the Association, for the hope of procompetitive benefits depends upon the existence of safeguards sufficient to prevent the standard-setting process from being biased by members with economic interests in restraining competition. An association cannot validate the anticompetitive activities of its members simply by adopting rules that fail to provide such safeguards.12 The issue of immunity in this case thus collapses into the issue of antitrust liability. Although we do

unprotected despite its political impact, and this is itself a case close to the line. For that reason we caution that our decision today depends on the context and nature of the activity. Although criticizing the uncertainty of such a particularized inquiry, the dissent does not dispute that the types of activity we describe … could not be immune under Noerr and fails to offer an intelligible alternative for distinguishing those non-immune activities from the activity at issue in this case. Rather, the dissent states without elaboration that the sham exception “is enough to guard against flagrant abuse,” apparently embracing the conclusion of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit that the sham exception covers the activity of a defendant who “genuinely seeks to achieve his governmental result, but does so through improper means.” Sessions Tank Liners v. Joor Mfg., 827 F.2d 458, 465, n.5 (1987). Such a use of the word “sham” distorts its meaning and bears little relation to the sham exception Noerr described to cover activity that was not genuinely intended to influence governmental action. More importantly, the Ninth Circuit’s approach renders “sham” no more than a label courts could apply to activity they deem unworthy of antitrust immunity (probably based on unarticulated consideration of the nature and context of the activity), thus providing a certain superficial certainty but no real “intelligible guidance” to courts or litigants. Indeed, the Ninth Circuit concluded that the very activity the dissent deems protected was an unprotected “sham.” 827 F.2d, at 465.11 Although the absence of such anticompetitive motives and incentives is relevant to determining whether petitioner’s restraint of trade is protected under Claiborne Hardware, we do not suggest that the absence of anticompetitive purpose is necessary for Noerr immunity. As the dissent points out, in Noerr itself the major purpose of the activity at issue was anticompetitive. Our statement that the “ultimate aim” of petitioner “is not dispositive,” stands only for the proposition that, at least outside the political context, the mere fact that an anticompetitive activity is also intended to influence governmental action is not alone sufficient to render that activity immune from antitrust liability.

116

Page 55: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

not here set forth the rules of antitrust liability governing the private standard-setting process, we hold that at least where, as here, an economically interested party exercises decision-making authority in formulating a product standard for a private association that comprises market participants, that party enjoys no Noerr immunity from any antitrust liability flowing from the effect the standard has of its own force in the marketplace.

This conclusion does not deprive state and local governments of input and information from interested individuals or organizations or leave petitioner without ample means to petition those governments. Petitioner, and others concerned about the safety or competitive threat of polyvinyl chloride conduit, can, with full antitrust immunity, engage in concerted efforts to influence those governments through direct lobbying, publicity campaigns, and other traditional avenues of political expression. To the extent state and local governments are more difficult to persuade through these other avenues, that no doubt reflects their preference for and confidence in the nonpartisan consensus process that petitioner has undermined. Petitioner remains free to take advantage of the forum provided by the standard-setting process by presenting and vigorously arguing accurate scientific evidence before a nonpartisan private standard-setting body.13 And petitioner can avoid the strictures of the private standard-setting process by attempting to influence legislatures through other forums. What petitioner may not do (without exposing itself to possible antitrust liability for direct injuries) is bias the process by, as in this case, stacking the private standard-setting process with decisionmakers sharing their economic interest in restraining competition. …

Justice WHITE, with whom Justice O’CONNOR joins, dissenting. Noerr held that the Sherman Act should not be construed to forbid joint efforts by railway companies seeking legislation that would disadvantage the trucking industry. … Pennington and California Motor Transport applied the rule to efforts to seek executive action and to administrative and adjudicative proceedings. The Court now refuses to apply the rule of these cases to the participants in those private organizations, such as the National Fire Protection Association (NFPA), that regularly propound and publish health and safety standards for a variety of products and industries and then present these codes to state and local authorities for the purpose of having them enacted into law. The NFPA and those participating in the code-writing process will now be subject to antitrust liability if their efforts have anticompetitive effects and do not withstand scrutiny under the rule of reason. Believing that this result is a misapplication of the Noerr decision and an improvident construction of the Sherman Act, I respectfully dissent.

12 Even petitioner’s counsel concedes, for example, that Noerr would not apply if the Association had a rule giving the steel conduit manufacturers a veto over changes in the Code. 13 The dissent mistakenly asserts that we today hold that Noerr immunity does not apply to mere efforts to persuade others to exclude a competitor’s product from a private code. Our holding is expressly limited to cases where an “economically interested party exercises decisionmaking authority in formulating a product standard for a private association that comprises market participants.” (relying in part on the distinction between activity involving the exercise of decisionmaking authority and market power and activity involving mere attempts to persuade an independent decisionmaker). The dissent also mistakenly asserts that this description encompasses all private standard-setting associations. In fact, many such associations are composed of members with expertise but no economic interest in suppressing competition.

117

Page 56: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

This case presents an even stronger argument for immunity than did Noerr itself. That decision turned on whether the design or purpose of the conduct was to obtain or influence the passage or enforcement of laws. The Court concedes that petitioner’s actions in this case constituted a “genuine effort to influence governmental action,” and that this was its “ultimate aim.” In Noerr, the publicity campaign was dispersed widely among the public in a broad but necessary diluted attempt to move public opinion in hopes that government officials would take note and respond accordingly. The campaign apparently had some influence on the passage of tax laws and other legislation favorable to the railroads in New Jersey, New York, and Ohio, and procured the Governor’s veto of a bill that had been passed in Pennsylvania. Here, the NFPA actually drafted proposed legislation in the form of the National Electrical Code (NEC) and presented it countrywide. Not only were petitioner’s efforts in this case designed to influence the passage of state laws, but there was also a much greater likelihood that they would be successful than was the case in Noerr. This is germane because it establishes a much greater likelihood that the “purpose” and “design” of petitioner’s actions in this case was the “solicitation of governmental action with respect to the passage and enforcement of laws.” Noerr.

Rather than directly confronting the severe damage that today’s decision does to the Noerr doctrine, the majority asserts that the “ultimate aim” of petitioner’s efforts “is not dispositive.” That statement cannot be reconciled with … Noerr, where it was held that even if one of the major purposes, or even the sole purpose, of the publicity campaign was “to destroy the truckers as competitors,” those actions were immunized from antitrust liability because ultimately they were “directed toward obtaining governmental action.” The majority later doubles back on this statement, and suggests that it is important in this case that “petitioner was at least partially motivated by the desire to lessen competition, and ... stood to reap substantial economic benefits from making it difficult for respondent to compete.” It need hardly be said that all of this was also true in Noerr. Nobody condones fraud, bribery, or misrepresentation in any form, and other state and federal laws ensure that such conduct is punishable. But the point here is that conduct otherwise punishable under the antitrust laws either becomes immune from the operation of those laws when it is part of a larger design to influence the passage and enforcement of laws, or it does not. No workable boundaries to the Noerr doctrine are established by declaring … that everything depends on “the context and nature of” the activity…. One unfortunate consequence of today’s decision, therefore, is that district courts and courts of appeals will be obliged to puzzle over claims raised under the doctrine without any intelligible guidance about when and why to apply it.

If there were no private code-writing organizations, and state legislatures themselves held the necessary hearing and wrote codes from scratch, then business concerns like Allied, together with their friends, could jointly testify with impunity about the safety of various products, even though they had anticompetitive motives in doing so. This much the majority concedes, as it does that the major purpose of the code-writing organizations is to influence legislative action. These days it is almost a foregone conclusion that the vast majority of the States will adopt these codes with little or no change. It is untenable to consider the code-writing process by such organizations as the NFPA as too far removed from the legislative process to warrant application of the doctrine announced in Noerr and faithfully applied in other cases. …

118

Page 57: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The Court’s decision is unfortunate for another reason. There are now over 400 private organizations preparing and publishing an enormous variety of codes and standards. State and local governments necessarily, and as a matter of course, turn to these proposed codes in the process of legislating to further the health and safety of their citizens. The code that is at issue in this case, for example, was adopted verbatim by 25 States and the District of Columbia; 19 others adopted it with only minor changes. It is the most widely disseminated and adopted model code in the world today. There is no doubt that the work of these private organizations contributes enormously to the public interest and that participation in their work by those who have the technical competence and experience to do so should not be discouraged.

The Court’s decision today will surely do just that. It must inevitably be the case that codes such as the NEC will set standards that some products cannot satisfy and hence in the name of health and safety will reduce or prevent competition, as was the case here. Yet, putative competitors of the producer of such products will now think twice before urging in the course of the code-making process that those products not be approved; for if they are successful (or even if they are not), they may well become antitrust defendants facing treble-damages liability unless they can prove to a court and a jury that they had no evil motives but were merely “presenting and vigorously arguing accurate scientific evidence before a nonpartisan private standard-setting body,” (though with the knowing and inevitable result of eliminating competition). In this case, for example, even if Allied had not resorted to the tactics it employed, but had done no more than successfully argue in good faith the hazards of using respondent’s products, it would have inflicted the same damage on respondent and would have risked facing the same antitrust suit, with a jury ultimately deciding the health and safety implications of the products at issue.

The Court’s suggestion that its decision will not affect the ability of these organizations to assist state and local governments is surely wrong. The Court’s holding is “that at least where, as here, an economically interested party exercises decisionmaking authority in formulating a product standard for a private association that comprises market participants, that party enjoys no Noerr immunity from any antitrust liability flowing from the effects the standard has of its own force in the marketplace.” This description encompasses the structure and work of all such organizations as we now know them. The Court is saying, in effect, that where a private organization sets standards, the participants can be sued under the antitrust laws for any effects those standards have in the marketplace other than those flowing from their adoption into law. But the standards will have some effect in the marketplace even where they are also adopted into law, through publicity and other means, thus exposing the participants to liability. Henceforth, therefore, any private organization offers such standards at its peril, and without any of the breathing room enjoyed by other participants in the political process.

The alternative apparently envisioned by the Court is that an organization can gain the protection of the Noerr doctrine as long as nobody with any economic interest in the product is permitted to “exercis[e] decisionmaking authority” (i.e., vote) on its recommendations as to particular product standards. Insisting that organizations like the NFPA conduct themselves like courts of law will have perverse effects. Legislatures are willing to rely on such organizations precisely because their standards are being set by

119

Page 58: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

those who possess an expert understanding of the products and their uses, which are primarily if not entirely those who design, manufacture, sell, and distribute them. Sanitizing such bodies by discouraging the active participation of those with economic interests in the subject matter undermines their utility.

I fear that exposing organizations like the NFPA to antitrust liability will impair their usefulness by inhibiting frank and open discussion of the health and safety characteristics of new or old products that will be affected by their codes. The Court focuses on the tactics of petitioner that are thought to have subverted the entire process. But it is not suggested that if there are abuses, they are anything more than occasional happenings. The Court does speculate about the terrible practices that applying Noerr in this context could lead us to condone in future cases, but these are no more than fantasies, since nothing of the sort occurred in the wake of Noerr itself. It seems to me that today’s decision is therefore an unfortunate case of overkill.

Of course, the Noerr immunity is not unlimited and by its terms is unavailable where the alleged efforts to influence legislation are nothing but a sham. … [T]his limitation is enough to guard against flagrant abuse. In any event, occasional abuse is insufficient ground to render the entire process less useful and reliable. I would reverse the judgment below and remand for further proceedings.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $FTC v. SUPERIOR COURT TRIAL LAWYERS ASS’N

493 U.S. 411 (1990)

Justice STEVENS delivered the opinion of the Court. Pursuant to a well-publicized plan, a group of lawyers agreed not to represent indigent criminal defendants in the District of Columbia Superior Court until the District of Columbia government increased the lawyers’ compensation. The questions presented are whether the lawyers’ concerted conduct violated §5 of the Federal Trade Commission Act and, if so, whether it was nevertheless protected by the First Amendment….

I. The burden of providing competent counsel to indigent defendants in the District of Columbia is substantial. During 1982, court-appointed counsel represented the defendant in approximately 25,000 cases. In the most serious felony cases, representation was generally provided by full-time employees of the District’s Public Defender System (PDS). Less serious felony and misdemeanor cases constituted about 85 percent of the total caseload. In these cases, lawyers in private practice were appointed and compensated pursuant to the District of Columbia Criminal Justice Act (CJA).

Although over 1,200 lawyers have registered for CJA appointments, relatively few actually apply for such work on a regular basis. In 1982, most appointments went to approximately 100 lawyers who are described as “CJA regulars.” These lawyers derive almost all of their income from representing indigents. In 1982, the total fees paid to CJA lawyers amounted to $4,579,572.

120

Page 59: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

In 1974, the District created a Joint Committee on Judicial Administration with authority to establish rates of compensation for CJA lawyers not exceeding the rates established by the federal Criminal Justice Act of 1964. After 1970, the federal Act provided for fees of $30 per hour for court time and $20 per hour for out-of-court time. These rates accordingly capped the rates payable to the District’s CJA lawyers, and could not be exceeded absent amendment to either the federal statute or the District Code.

Bar organizations began as early as 1975 to express concern about the low fees paid to CJA lawyers. Beginning in 1982, respondents, the Superior Court Trial Lawyers Association (SCTLA) and its officers, and other bar groups sought to persuade the District to increase CJA rates to at least $35 per hour. Despite what appeared to be uniform support for the bill, it did not pass. It is also true, however, that nothing in the record indicates that the low fees caused any actual shortage of CJA lawyers or denied effective representation to defendants.

In early August 1983, in a meeting with officers of SCTLA, the Mayor expressed his sympathy but firmly indicated that no money was available to fund an increase. The events giving rise to this litigation then ensued. At an SCTLA meeting, the CJA lawyers voted to form a “strike committee.” The eight members of that committee promptly met and informally agreed “that the only viable way of getting an increase in fees was to stop signing up to take new CJA appointments, and that the boycott should aim for a $45 out-of-court and $55 in-court rate schedule.” On August 11, 1983, about 100 CJA lawyers met and resolved not to accept any new cases after September 6 if legislation providing for an increase in their fees had not passed by that date. Immediately following the meeting, they prepared (and most of them signed) a petition stating:

We, the undersigned private criminal lawyers practicing in the Superior Court of the District of Columbia, agree that unless we are granted a substantial increase in our hourly rate we will cease accepting new appointments under the Criminal Justice Act.

On September 6, 1983, about 90 percent of the CJA regulars refused to accept any new assignments. Thereafter, SCTLA arranged a series of events to attract the attention of the news media and to obtain additional support. These events were well publicized and did engender favorable editorial comment, but the Administrative Law Judge (ALJ) found that “there is no credible evidence that the District’s eventual capitulation to the demands of the CJA lawyers was made in response to public pressure, or … that this publicity campaign actually engendered any significant measure of public pressure.”

As the participating CJA lawyers had anticipated, their refusal to take new assignments had a severe impact on the District’s criminal justice system. … A few days after the September 6 deadline, PDS was swamped with cases. The handful of CJA regulars who continued to take cases were soon overloaded. The overall response of the uptown lawyers to the PDS call for help was feeble, reflecting their universal distaste for criminal law, their special aversion for compelled indigency representation, the near epidemic siege of self-doubt about their ability to handle cases in this field, and their underlying support for the demands of the CJA lawyers. …

Within 10 days, the key figures in the District’s criminal justice system “became convinced that the system was on the brink of collapse because of the refusal of CJA lawyers to take on new cases.” On September 15, they hand-delivered a letter to the

121

Page 60: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Mayor describing why the situation was expected to “reach a crisis point” by early the next week and urging the immediate enactment of a bill increasing all CJA rates to $35 per hour. The Mayor promptly met with members of the strike committee and offered to support an immediate temporary increase to the $35 level as well as a subsequent permanent increase to $45 an hour for out-of-court time and $55 for in-court time.

At noon on September 19, 1983, over 100 CJA lawyers attended an SCTLA meeting and voted to accept the $35 offer and end the boycott. The city council’s Judiciary Committee convened at 2 o’clock that afternoon. The committee recommended legislation increasing CJA fees to $35, and the council unanimously passed the bill on September 20. On September 21, the CJA regulars began to accept new assignments and the crisis subsided.

II. The Federal Trade Commission (FTC) filed a complaint against SCTLA and four of its officers (respondents) alleging that they had “entered into an agreement among themselves and with other lawyers to restrain trade by refusing to compete for or accept new appointments under the CJA program….” … The FTC characterized respondents’ conduct as “a conspiracy to fix prices and to conduct a boycott” and concluded that they were engaged in “unfair methods of competition in violation of Section 5 of the Federal Trade Commission Act.”

After a 3-week hearing, the ALJ found that the facts alleged in the complaint had been proved, and rejected each of the respondents’ three legal defenses–that the boycott was adequately justified by the public interest in obtaining better legal representation for indigent defendants; that as a method of petitioning for legislative change it was exempt from the antitrust laws under our decision in Noerr; and that it was a form of political action protected by the First Amendment under our decision in NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co., 458 U.S. 886 (1982). The ALJ nevertheless concluded that the complaint should be dismissed because the District officials, who presumably represented the victim of the boycott, recognized that its net effect was beneficial. The increase in fees would attract more CJA lawyers, enabling them to reduce their caseloads and provide better representation for their clients. “I see no point,” he concluded, “in striving resolutely for an antitrust triumph in this sensitive area when the particular case can be disposed of on a more pragmatic basis–there was no harm done.”

The ALJ’s pragmatic moderation found no favor with the FTC. Like the ALJ, the FTC rejected each of respondents’ defenses. It held that their “coercive, concerted refusal to deal” had the “purpose and effect of raising prices” and was illegal per se. Unlike the ALJ, the FTC refused to conclude that the boycott was harmless, noting that the “boycott forced the city government to increase the CJA fees from a level that had been sufficient to obtain an adequate supply of CJA lawyers to a level satisfactory to the respondents. The city must, as a result of the boycott, spend an additional $4 million to $5 million a year to obtain legal services for indigents. We find that these are substantial anticompetitive effects resulting from the respondents’ conduct.” Finally, the FTC determined that the record did not support the ALJ’s conclusion that the District supported the boycott. The FTC also held that such support would not in any event excuse respondents’ antitrust violations. Accordingly, it entered a cease-and-desist order “to prohibit the respondents from initiating another boycott ... whenever they become dissatisfied with the results or pace of the city’s legislative process.”

122

Page 61: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The Court of Appeals vacated the FTC order and remanded for a determination whether respondents possessed “significant market power.” The court began its analysis by recognizing that absent any special First Amendment protection, the boycott “constituted a classic restraint of trade ….” The Court of Appeals was not persuaded by respondents’ reliance on Claiborne Hardware or Noerr, or by their argument that the boycott was justified because it was designed to improve the quality of representation for indigent defendants. It concluded, however, that “the SCTLA boycott did contain an element of expression warranting First Amendment protection.” It noted that boycotts have historically been used as a dramatic means of expression and that respondents intended to convey a political message to the public at large. It therefore concluded that under U.S. v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367 (1968), a restriction on this form of expression could not be justified unless it is no greater than is essential to an important governmental interest. This test, the court reasoned, could not be satisfied by the application of an otherwise appropriate per se rule, but instead required the enforcement agency to “prove rather than presume that the evil against which the Sherman Act is directed looms in the conduct it condemns.” Because of our concern about the implications of the Court of Appeals’ unique holding, we granted the FTC’s petition for certiorari as well as respondents’ cross-petition.

III. Reasonable lawyers may differ about the wisdom of this enforcement proceeding. … Respondents’ boycott may well have served a cause that was worthwhile and unpopular. We may assume that the pre-boycott rates were unreasonably low, and that the increase has produced better legal representation for indigent defendants. Moreover, given that neither indigent criminal defendants nor the lawyers who represent them command any special appeal with the electorate, we may also assume that without the boycott there would have been no increase in District CJA fees at least until the Congress amended the federal statute. These assumptions do not control the case, for it is not our task to pass upon the social utility or political wisdom of price-fixing agreements.

… Prior to the boycott, CJA lawyers were in competition with one another, each deciding independently whether and how often to offer to provide services to the District at CJA rates. The agreement among the CJA lawyers was designed to obtain higher prices for their services and was implemented by a concerted refusal to serve an important customer in the market for legal services and, indeed, the only customer in the market for the particular services that CJA regulars offered. … The horizontal arrangement among these competitors was unquestionably a “naked restraint” on price and output. See NCAA.

It is, of course, true that the city purchases respondents’ services because it has a constitutional duty to provide representation to indigent defendants. It is likewise true that the quality of representation may improve when rates are increased. Yet neither of these facts is an acceptable justification for an otherwise unlawful restraint of trade. As we have remarked before, the “Sherman Act reflects a legislative judgment that ultimately competition will produce not only lower prices, but also better goods and services.” Professional Engineers. This judgment “recognizes that all elements of a bargain–quality, service, safety, and durability–and not just the immediate cost, are favorably affected by the free opportunity to select among alternative offers.” Id. That is equally so when the quality of legal advocacy, rather than engineering design, is at issue.

123

Page 62: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The social justifications proffered for respondents’ restraint of trade thus do not make it any less unlawful. The statutory policy underlying the Sherman Act “precludes inquiry into the question whether competition is good or bad.” Id. Respondents’ argument … ultimately asks us to find that their boycott is permissible because the price it seeks to set is reasonable. But it was settled shortly after the Sherman Act was passed that it “is no excuse that the prices fixed are themselves reasonable. See, e.g., U.S. v. Trenton Potteries Co., 273 U.S. 392, 397-398 (1927); U.S. v. Trans-Missouri Freight Assn., 166 U.S. 290, 340-341 (1897).” Catalano, Inc. v. Target Sales, Inc., 446 U.S. 643, 647 (1980). Respondents’ agreement is not outside the coverage of the Sherman Act simply because its objective was the enactment of favorable legislation.

Our decision in Noerr in no way detracts from this conclusion. In Noerr, we “considered whether the Sherman Act prohibited a publicity campaign waged by railroads” and “designed to foster the adoption of laws destructive of the trucking business, to create an atmosphere of distaste for truckers among the general public, and to impair the relationships existing between truckers and their customers.” Claiborne Hardware. Interpreting the Sherman Act in the light of the First Amendment’s Petition Clause, the Court noted that “at least insofar as the railroads’ campaign was directed toward obtaining governmental action, its legality was not at all affected by any anticompetitive purpose it may have had.” Noerr.

It of course remains true that “no violation of the Act can be predicated upon mere attempts to influence the passage or enforcement of laws,” even if the defendants’ sole purpose is to impose a restraint upon the trade of their competitors. Id. But in the Noerr case the alleged restraint of trade was the intended consequence of public action; in this case the boycott was the means by which respondents sought to obtain favorable legislation. The restraint of trade that was implemented while the boycott lasted would have had precisely the same anti-competitive consequences during that period even if no legislation had been enacted. In Noerr, the desired legislation would have created the restraint on the truckers’ competition; in this case the emergency legislative response to the boycott put an end to the restraint.

Indeed, respondents’ theory of Noerr was largely disposed of by … Allied Tube. We held that the Noerr doctrine does not extend to “every concerted effort that is genuinely intended to influence governmental action.” We explained:

If all such conduct were immunized then, for example, competitors would be free to enter into horizontal price agreements as long as they wished to propose that price as an appropriate level for governmental ratemaking or price supports. … Horizontal conspiracies or boycotts designed to exact higher prices or other economic advantages from the government would be immunized on the ground that they are genuinely intended to influence the government to agree to the conspirators’ terms. … Firms could claim immunity for boycotts or horizontal output restrictions on the ground that they are intended to dramatize the plight of their industry and spur legislative action.

IV. SCTLA argues that if its conduct would otherwise be prohibited by the Sherman Act and the Federal Trade Commission Act, it is nonetheless protected by the First Amendment rights recognized in Claiborne Hardware. That case arose after black citizens boycotted white merchants in Claiborne County, Mississippi. The white merchants sued under state law to recover losses from the boycott. We found that the

124

Page 63: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

“right of the States to regulate economic activity could not justify a complete prohibition against a nonviolent, politically motivated boycott designed to force governmental and economic change and to effectuate rights guaranteed by the Constitution itself.” We accordingly held that “the nonviolent elements of petitioners’ activities are entitled to the protection of the First Amendment.” SCTLA contends that because it, like the boycotters in Claiborne Hardware, sought to vindicate constitutional rights, it should enjoy a similar First Amendment protection. … [T]he association’s efforts to publicize the boycott, to explain the merits of its cause, and to lobby District officials to enact favorable legislation–like similar activities in Claiborne Hardware–were activities that were fully protected by the First Amendment. But nothing in the FTC’s order would curtail such activities, and nothing in the FTC’s reasoning condemned any of those activities.

The activity that the FTC order prohibits is a concerted refusal by CJA lawyers to accept any further assignments until they receive an increase in their compensation; the undenied objective of their boycott was an economic advantage for those who agreed to participate. It is true that the Claiborne Hardware case also involved a boycott. That boycott, however, differs in a decisive respect. Those who joined the Claiborne Hardware boycott sought no special advantage for themselves. They were black citizens in Port Gibson, Mississippi, who had been the victims of political, social, and economic discrimination for many years. They sought only the equal respect and equal treatment to which they were constitutionally entitled. They struggled “to change a social order that had consistently treated them as second class citizens.” As we observed, the campaign was not intended “to destroy legitimate competition.” Equality and freedom are preconditions of the free market, and not commodities to be haggled over within it.

The same cannot be said of attorney’s fees. As we recently pointed out, our reasoning in Claiborne Hardware is not applicable to a boycott conducted by business competitors who “stand to profit financially from a lessening of competition in the boycotted market.” Allied Tube. No matter how altruistic the motives of respondents may have been, it is undisputed that their immediate objective was to increase the price that they would be paid for their services. Such an economic boycott is well within the category that was expressly distinguished in the Claiborne Hardware opinion itself.11

Only after recognizing the well-settled validity of prohibitions against various economic boycotts did we conclude in Claiborne Hardware that “peaceful, political activity such as that found in the [Mississippi] boycott” are entitled to constitutional protection. We reaffirmed the government’s “power to regulate [such] economic activity.” This conclusion applies with special force when a clear objective of the boycott is to economically advantage the participants.

V. Respondents’ concerted action in refusing to accept further CJA assignments until their fees were increased was thus a plain violation of the antitrust laws. The exceptions derived from Noerr and Claiborne Hardware have no application to respondents’ 11 Respondents contend that, just as the Claiborne Hardware boycott sought to secure constitutional rights to equality and freedom, the lawyers’ boycott sought to vindicate the Sixth Amendment rights of indigent defendants. … Claiborne Hardware does not, and could not, establish a rule immunizing from prosecution any boycott based upon sincere constitutional concerns. Such an exemption would authorize the government’s contractors in nearly all areas to circumvent antitrust law on the basis of their own theory of the government’s obligations.

125

Page 64: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

boycott. For these reasons we reject the arguments made by respondents in the cross-petition.

The Court of Appeals, however, crafted a new exception to the per se rules, and it is this exception which provoked the FTC’s petition to this Court. The Court of Appeals derived its exception from U.S. v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367 (1968). In that case O’Brien had burned his Selective Service registration certificate on the steps of the South Boston Courthouse. He did so before a sizable crowd and with the purpose of advocating his antiwar beliefs. We affirmed his conviction. We held that the governmental interest in regulating the “nonspeech element” of his conduct adequately justified the incidental restriction on First Amendment freedoms. Specifically, we concluded that the statute’s incidental restriction on O’Brien’s freedom of expression was no greater than necessary to further the Government’s interest in requiring registrants to have valid certificates continually available.

However, the Court of Appeals held that, in light of O’Brien, the expressive component of respondents’ boycott compelled courts to apply the antitrust laws “prudently and with sensitivity,” with a “special solicitude for the First Amendment rights” of respondents. The Court of Appeals concluded that the governmental interest in prohibiting boycotts is not sufficient to justify a restriction on the communicative element of the boycott unless the FTC can prove, and not merely presume, that the boycotters have market power. Because the Court of Appeals imposed this special requirement upon the government, it ruled that per se antitrust analysis was inapplicable to boycotts having an expressive component.

There are at least two critical flaws in the Court of Appeals’ antitrust analysis: it exaggerates the significance of the expressive component in respondents’ boycott and it denigrates the importance of the rule of law that respondents violated. Implicit in the conclusion of the Court of Appeals are unstated assumptions that most economic boycotts do not have an expressive component, and that the categorical prohibitions against price fixing and boycotts are merely rules of “administrative convenience” that do not serve any substantial governmental interest unless the price-fixing competitors actually possess market power.

It would not much matter to the outcome of this case if these flawed assumptions were sound. O’Brien would offer respondents no protection even if their boycott were uniquely expressive and even if the purpose of the per se rules were purely that of administrative efficiency. We have recognized that the government’s interest in adhering to a uniform rule may sometimes satisfy the O’Brien test even if making an exception to the rule in a particular case might cause no serious damage. … The administrative efficiency interests in antitrust regulation are unusually compelling. The per se rules avoid “the necessity for an incredibly complicated and prolonged economic investigation into the entire history of the industry involved, as well as related industries, in an effort to determine at large whether a particular restraint has been unreasonable.” Northern Pacific R. Co. v. U.S., 356 U.S. 1, 5 (1958). If small parties “were allowed to prove lack of market power, all parties would have that right, thus introducing the enormous complexities of market definition into every price-fixing case.” R. BORK, THE ANTITRUST PARADOX 269 (1978). For these reasons, it is at least possible that the

126

Page 65: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Claiborne Hardware doctrine, which itself rests in part upon O’Brien, exhausts O’Brien’s application to the antitrust statutes.

In any event, however, we cannot accept the Court of Appeals’ characterization of this boycott or the antitrust laws. Every concerted refusal to do business with a potential customer or supplier has an expressive component. At one level, the competitors must exchange their views about their objectives and the means of obtaining them. The most blatant, naked price-fixing agreement is a product of communication, but that is surely not a reason for viewing it with special solicitude. At another level, after the terms of the boycotters’ demands have been agreed upon, they must be communicated to its target: “[W]e will not do business until you do what we ask.” That expressive component of the boycott conducted by these respondents is surely not unique. On the contrary, it is the hallmark of every effective boycott.

At a third level, the boycotters may communicate with third parties to enlist public support for their objectives; to the extent that the boycott is newsworthy, it will facilitate the expression of the boycotters’ ideas. But this level of expression is not an element of the boycott. Publicity may be generated by any other activity that is sufficiently newsworthy. Some activities, including the boycott here, may be newsworthy precisely for the reasons that they are prohibited: the harms they produce are matters of public concern. Certainly that is no reason for removing the prohibition. In sum, there is thus nothing unique about the “expressive component” of respondents’ boycott. A rule that requires courts to apply the antitrust laws “prudently and with sensitivity” whenever an economic boycott has an “expressive component” would create a gaping hole in the fabric of those laws. Respondents’ boycott thus has no special characteristics meriting an exemption from the per se rules of antitrust law.

Equally important is the second error implicit in respondents’ claim to immunity from the per se rules. In its opinion, the Court of Appeals assumed that the antitrust laws permit, but do not require, the condemnation of price fixing and boycotts without proof of market power.15 The opinion further assumed that the per se rule prohibiting such activity “is only a rule of ‘administrative convenience and efficiency,’ not a statutory command.” This statement contains two errors. The per se rules are, of course, the product of judicial interpretations of the Sherman Act, but the rules nevertheless have the same force and effect as any other statutory commands. Moreover, while the per se rule against price fixing and boycotts is indeed justified in part by “administrative convenience,” the Court of Appeals erred in describing the prohibition as justified only by such concerns. The per

15 In our opinion in Jefferson Parish Hospital District No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S. 2, 15-16 n.25 (1984), we noted that

[t]he rationale for per se rules in part is to avoid a burdensome inquiry into actual market conditions in situations where the likelihood of anticompetitive conduct is so great as to render unjustified the costs of determining whether the particular case at bar involves anticompetitive conduct. See, e.g., Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 350-351 (1982).

The Court of Appeals overlooked the words “in part” in that footnote, and also overlooked the statement in text that “there must be a substantial potential for impact on competition in order to justify per se condemnation.” [T]he Court of Appeals incorrectly assumed that the per se rule against price fixing is “only” a rule of administrative convenience….

127

Page 66: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

se rules also reflect a longstanding judgment that the prohibited practices by their nature have “a substantial potential for impact on competition.” Jefferson Parish Hospital District No. 2 v. Hyde, 466 U.S. 2, 16 (1984)…. “Once experience with a particular kind of restraint enables the Court to predict with confidence that the rule of reason will condemn it, it has applied a conclusive presumption that the restraint is unreasonable.” Arizona v. Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. 332, 344 (1982).

The per se rules in antitrust law serve purposes analogous to per se restrictions upon, for example, stunt flying in congested areas or speeding. Laws prohibiting stunt flying or setting speed limits are justified by the State’s interest in protecting human life and property. Perhaps most violations of such rules actually cause no harm. No doubt many experienced drivers and pilots can operate much more safely, even at prohibited speeds, than the average citizen.

If the especially skilled drivers and pilots were to paint messages on their cars, or attach streamers to their planes, their conduct would have an expressive component. High speeds and unusual maneuvers would help to draw attention to their messages. Yet the laws may nonetheless be enforced against these skilled persons without proof that their conduct was actually harmful or dangerous.

In part, the justification for these per se rules is rooted in administrative convenience. They are also supported, however, by the observation that every speeder and every stunt pilot poses some threat to the community. An unpredictable event may overwhelm the skills of the best driver or pilot, even if the proposed course of action was entirely prudent when initiated. A bad driver going slowly may be more dangerous than a good driver going quickly, but a good driver who obeys the law is safer still.

So it is with boycotts and price fixing.16 Every such horizontal arrangement among competitors poses some threat to the free market. A small participant in the market is, obviously, less likely to cause persistent damage than a large participant. Other participants in the market may act quickly and effectively to take the small participant’s place. For reasons including market inertia and information failures, however, a small conspirator may be able to impede competition over some period of time. Given an appropriate set of circumstances and some luck, the period can be long enough to inflict real injury upon particular consumers or competitors. …

Of course, some boycotts and some price-fixing agreements are more pernicious than others; some are only partly successful, and some may only succeed when they are buttressed by other causative factors, such as political influence. But an assumption that, absent proof of market power, the boycott disclosed by this record was totally harmless–

1 6 In sum, price-fixing cartels are condemned per se because the conduct is tempting to businessmen but very dangerous to society. The conceivable social benefits are few in principle, small in magnitude, speculative in occurrence, and always premised on the existence of price-fixing power which is likely to be exercised adversely to the public. Moreover, toleration implies a burden of continuous supervision for which the courts consider themselves ill-suited. And even if power is usually established while any defenses are not, litigation will be complicated, condemnation delayed, would be price-fixers encouraged to hope for escape, and criminal punishment less justified. Deterrence of a generally pernicious practice would be weakened. The key points are the first two. Without them, there is no justification for categorical condemnation.

7 P. AREEDA, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1509, pp. 412-413 (1986).

128

Page 67: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

when overwhelming testimony demonstrated that it almost produced a crisis in the administration of criminal justice … and when it achieved its economic goal–is flatly inconsistent with the clear course of our antitrust jurisprudence. Conspirators need not achieve the dimensions of a monopoly, or even a degree of market power any greater than that already disclosed by this record, to warrant condemnation under the antitrust laws.

VI. The judgment of the Court of Appeals is accordingly reversed insofar as that court held the per se rules inapplicable to the lawyers’ boycott.19 The case is remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.

Justice BRENNAN, with whom Justice MARSHALL joins, concurring in part and dissenting in part. The Court holds today that a boycott by the Superior Court Trial Lawyers Association …, whose members collectively refused to represent indigent criminal defendants without greater compensation, constituted conduct that was neither clearly outside the scope of the Sherman Act nor automatically immunized from antitrust regulation by the First Amendment. With this much I agree. In Part V of its opinion, however, the Court maintains that under the per se rule the [FTC] could find the boycott illegal because it might have implicated some of the concerns underlying the antitrust laws. I cannot countenance this reasoning, which upon examination reduces to the Court’s assertion that since the government may prohibit airplane stunt flying and reckless automobile driving as categorically harmful, it may also subject expressive political boycotts to a presumption of illegality without even inquiring as to whether they actually cause any of the harms that the antitrust laws are designed to prevent. This non sequitur cannot justify the significant restriction on First Amendment freedoms that the majority’s rule entails. Because I believe that the majority’s decision is insensitive to the venerable tradition of expressive boycotts as an important means of political communication, I respectfully dissent from Part V of the Court’s opinion.

I. The Petition and Free Speech Clauses of the First Amendment guarantee citizens the right to communicate with the government, and when a group persuades the government to adopt a particular policy through the force of its ideas and the power of its message, no antitrust liability can attach. “There are, of course, some activities, legal if engaged in by one, yet illegal if performed in concert with others, but political expression is not one of them.” Citizens Against Rent Control/Coalition for Fair Housing v. Berkeley, 454 U.S. 290, 296 (1981). But a group’s effort to use market power to coerce the government through economic means may subject the participants to antitrust liability.

In any particular case, it may be difficult to untangle these two effects by determining whether political or economic power was brought to bear on the government.

19 In response to Justice BRENNAN’s opinion, and particularly to its observation that some concerted arrangements that might be characterized as “group boycotts” may not merit per se condemnation, we emphasize that this case involves not only a boycott but also a horizontal price-fixing arrangement--a type of conspiracy that has been consistently analyzed as a per se violation for many decades. All of the “group boycott” cases cited in Justice BRENNAN’s footnote involved nonprice restraints. There was likewise no price-fixing component in any of the boycotts listed [in] Justice BRENNAN’s opinion. Indeed, the text of the opinion virtually ignores the price-fixing component of respondents’ concerted action.

129

Page 68: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The Court of Appeals thoughtfully analyzed this problem and concluded, I believe correctly, that there could be no antitrust violation absent a showing that the boycotters possessed some degree of market power–that is, the ability to raise prices profitably through economic means or, more generally, the capacity to act other than as would an actor in a perfectly competitive market. The court reasoned that “[w]hen the government seeks to regulate an economic boycott with an expressive component ... its condemnation without proof that the boycott could in fact be anticompetitive ignores the command of [U.S. v.] O’Brien that restrictions on activity protected by the First Amendment be ‘no greater than is essential’ to preserve competition from the sclerotic effects of combination.” (quoting O’Brien) The concurring judge added that if the participants wielded no market power, “the boycott must have succeeded out of persuasion and been a political activity.” This approach is quite sensible, and I would affirm the Court of Appeals’ decision to remand the case to the FTC for a showing of market power.

A. The issue in this case is not whether boycotts may ever be punished under §5 of the [FTC] Act … consistent with the First Amendment; rather, the issue is how the government may determine which boycotts are illegal. Two well-established premises lead to the ineluctable conclusion that when applying the antitrust laws to a particular expressive boycott, the government may not presume an antitrust violation under the per se rule, but must instead apply the more searching, case-specific rule of reason.

First, the per se rule is a presumption of illegality. 2 … We have freely admitted that conduct condemned under the per se rule sometimes would be permissible if subjected merely to rule-of-reason analysis. See Maricopa County Medical Society, 457 U.S. at 344 n.16; Continental T.V. v. GTE Sylvania, 433 U.S. 36, 50 n.16 (1977); U.S. v. Topco Associates, 405 U.S. 596, 609 (1972).

Second, the government may not in a First Amendment case apply a broad presumption that certain categories of speech are harmful without engaging in a more particularized examination. As the Court of Appeals perceptively reasoned, “the evidentiary shortcut to antitrust condemnation without proof of market power is inappropriate as applied to a boycott that served, in part, to make a statement on a matter of public debate.” “Government may not regulate expression in such a manner that a substantial portion of the burden on speech does not serve to advance its goals”; rather, government must ensure that, even when its regulation is not content based, the

2 I disagree with the Court that the government’s interest in employing the per se rule here is a substantial one. The per se rule’s conceded service of the goals of administrative efficiency and judicial economy cannot justify its application to activity protected by the First Amendment. “[T]he First Amendment does not permit the State to sacrifice speech for efficiency .” Riley v. National Federation of Blind of N.C., 487 U.S. 781, 795 (1988). Insofar as the per se rule is thought warranted by a speculation that even relatively small boycotts or those without market power might nonetheless inflict some measure of economic harm, the rule can be applied in ordinary antitrust cases where First Amendment freedoms are not implicated. … But where an expressive boycott is at issue, the same cannot be said; the First Amendment establishes that the social benefits involved are not “small in magnitude” or “speculative in occurrence.” Hence, even if it were possible that a boycott without market power might cause anticompetitive effects – a dubious proposition, since by definition market power is the ability to alter prices – the government still should be required to proceed under the rule of reason and demonstrate that such effects are actually present ….

130

Page 69: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

restriction narrowly “focuses on the source of the evils the [State] seeks to eliminate.” Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 799, and n.7 (1989). … I would hold in this case that the FTC cannot ignore the particular factual circumstances before it by employing a presumption of illegality in the guise of the per se rule.

B. The Court’s approach today is all the more inappropriate because the success of the Trial Lawyers’ boycott could have been attributable to the persuasiveness of its message rather than any coercive economic force. When a boycott seeks to generate public support for the passage of legislation, it may operate on a political rather than economic level, especially when the government is the target. Here, the demand for lawyers’ services under the … CJA is created by the command of the Sixth Amendment. How that demand is satisfied is determined by the political decisions of the Mayor, city council, and, because of the unique status of the District of Columbia, the Federal Government as well. As the FTC recognized, a typical boycott functions by transforming its participants into a single monopolistic entity that restricts supply and increases price. Indiana Federation of Dentists; NCAA.

The boycott in this case was completely different: it may have persuaded the consumer of the Trial Lawyers’ services–the District government–to raise the price it paid by altering the political preferences of District officials. Prior to the boycott, these officials perceived that at a time of fiscal austerity, a pay raise for lawyers who represented criminal defendants was not likely to be well received by the voters, whatever the merits of the issue. The SCTLA campaign drew public attention to the lawyers’ plight and generated enough sympathy among city residents to convince District officials, many of whom were already favorably inclined toward the Trial Lawyers’ cause, that they could augment CJA compensation rates without risking their political futures. Applying the per se rule to such a complex situation ignores the possibility that the boycott achieved its goal through a politically driven increase in demand for improved quality of representation, rather than by a cartel-like restriction in supply.

… [The] facts strongly suggest that the Trial Lawyers’ campaign persuaded the city to increase CJA compensation levels by creating a favorable climate in which supportive District officials could vote for a raise without public opposition, even though the lawyers lacked the ability to exert economic pressure. As the court below expressly found, the facts at the very least do not exclude the possibility that the SCTLA succeeded due to political rather than economic power. The majority today permits the FTC to find an expressive boycott to violate the antitrust laws, without even requiring a showing that the participants possessed market power or that their conduct triggered any anticompetitive effects. I believe that the First Amendment forecloses such an approach.

II. A. The majority concludes that the Trial Lawyers’ boycott may be enjoined without any showing of market power because “the government’s interest in adhering to a uniform rule may sometimes satisfy the O’Brien test even if making an exception to the rule in a particular case might cause no serious damage.” The Court draws an analogy between the per se rule in antitrust law and categorical proscriptions against airplane stunt-flying and reckless automobile driving. This analogy is flawed.

It is beyond peradventure that sometimes no exception need be made to a neutral rule of general applicability not aimed at the content of speech; “the arrest of a

131

Page 70: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

newscaster for a traffic violation,” for example, does not offend the First Amendment. Arcara v. Cloud Books, 478 U.S. 697, 708 (1986) (O’CONNOR, J., concurring). Neither do restrictions on stunt flying and reckless driving usually raise First Amendment concerns. But … we have held that even when the government seeks to address harms entirely unconnected with the content of speech, it must leave open ample alternative channels for effective communication. Although sometimes such content-neutral regulations with incidental effects on speech leave open sufficient room for effective communication, application of the per se rule to expressive boycotts does not. The role of boycotts in political speech is too central, and the effective alternative avenues open to the Trial Lawyers were too few, to permit the FTC to invoke the per se rule in this case.

Expressive boycotts have been a principal means of political communication since the birth of the Republic. … From the colonists’ protest of the Stamp and Townsend Acts to the Montgomery bus boycott and the National Organization for Women’s campaign to encourage ratification of the Equal Rights Amendment, boycotts have played a central role in our Nation’s political discourse. In recent years there have been boycotts of supermarkets, meat, grapes, iced tea in cans, soft drinks, lettuce, chocolate, tuna, plastic wrap, textiles, slacks, animal skins and furs, and products of Mexico, Japan, South Africa, and the Soviet Union. Like soapbox oratory in the streets and parks, political boycotts are a traditional means of “communicating thoughts between citizens” and “discussing public questions.” Hague v. CIO, 307 U.S. 496, 515 (1939) (opinion of Roberts, J.). Any restrictions on such boycotts must be scrutinized with special care in light of their historic importance as a mode of expression.

The Court observes that all boycotts have “an expressive component” in the sense that participants must communicate their plans among themselves and to their target. The Court reasons that this expressive feature alone does not render boycotts immune from scrutiny under the per se rule. Otherwise, the rule could never be applied to any boycotts or to most price-fixing schemes. On this point I concur with the majority. But while some boycotts may not present First Amendment concerns, when a particular boycott appears to operate on a political rather than economic level, I believe that it cannot be condemned under the per se rule.7 The Court disagrees and maintains that communication of ideas to the public is a function not of a boycott itself but rather of media coverage, interviews, and other activities ancillary to the boycott and not prohibited by the antitrust laws. The Court also notes that other avenues of speech are open, because “[p]ublicity may be generated by any other activity that is sufficiently newsworthy.” These views are flawed.

7 If a boycott uses economic power in an unlawful way to send a message, it cannot claim First Amendment protection from the antitrust laws, any more than a terrorist could use an act of violence to express his political views and then assert immunity from criminal prosecution. Thus, if a cartel in a regulated industry inflicts economic injury on consumers by raising prices in order to communicate with the government, it still would be subject to the per se rule. The instant case is different: there is a genuine question whether the SCTLA boycott involved any economic coercion at all. That is why a showing of market power is necessary before the boycott can be condemned as an unfair method of competition.

132

Page 71: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

First, … an expressive boycott necessarily involves “constitutionally protected activity.” Claiborne Hardware. That case … forecloses the Court’s approach today. … The Court contends that the SCTLA’s motivation differed from that of the boycotters in Claiborne Hardware, because the former sought to supplement its members’ own salaries rather than to remedy racial injustice. Even if true, the different purposes of the speech can hardly render the Trial Lawyers’ boycott any less expressive.

Next, although the Court is correct that the media coverage of the boycott was substantial, this does not support the majority’s argument that the boycott itself was not expressive. Indeed, that the SCTLA strove so mightily to communicate with the public and the government is an indication that it relied more on its ability to win public sympathy and persuade government officials politically than on its power to coerce the city economically. But media coverage is not the only, or even the principal, reason why the boycott was entitled to First Amendment protection. The refusal of the Trial Lawyers to accept appointments by itself communicated a powerful idea: CJA compensation rates had deteriorated so much, relatively speaking, that the lawyers were willing to forgo their livelihoods rather than return to work.

By sacrificing income that they actually desired, and thus inflicting hardship on themselves as well as on the city, the lawyers demonstrated the intensity of their feelings and the depth of their commitment. The passive nonviolence of King and Gandhi are proof that the resolute acceptance of pain may communicate dedication and righteousness more eloquently than mere words ever could. A boycott, like a hunger strike, conveys an emotional message that is absent in a letter to the editor, a conversation with the mayor, or even a protest march. In this respect, an expressive boycott is a special form of political communication….

Another reason why expressive boycotts are irreplaceable as a means of communication is that they are essential to the “poorly financed causes of little people.” Martin v. Struthers, 319 U.S. 141, 146 (1943). It is no accident that boycotts have been used by the American colonists to throw off the British yoke and by the oppressed to assert their civil rights. See Claiborne Hardware. Such groups cannot use established organizational techniques to advance their political interests, and boycotts are often the only effective route available to them.

B. Underlying the majority opinion are apprehensions that the Trial Lawyers’ boycott was really no different from any other, and that requiring the FTC to apply a rule-of-reason analysis in this case will lead to the demise of the per se rule in the boycott area. I do not share the majority’s fears. The boycott before us today is readily distinguishable from those with which the antitrust laws are concerned, on the very ground suggested by the majority: the Trial Lawyers intended to and in fact did “communicate with third parties to enlist public support for their objectives.” As we have seen, in all likelihood the boycott succeeded not due to any market power wielded by the lawyers but rather because they were able to persuade the District government through political means. Other boycotts may involve no expressive features and instead operate solely on an economic level. Very few economically coercive boycotts seek notoriety both because they seek to escape detection and because they have no wider audience beyond the participants and the target.

133

Page 72: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Furthermore, … there may be significant differences between boycotts aimed at the government and those aimed at private parties. The government has options open to it that private parties do not; in this suit, for example, the boycott was aimed at a legislative body with the power to terminate it at any time by requiring all members of the District Bar to represent defendants pro bono. If a boycott against the government achieves its goal, it likely owes its success to political rather than market power.

The Court’s concern for the vitality of the per se rule, moreover, is misplaced, in light of the fact that we have been willing to apply rule-of-reason analysis in a growing number of group-boycott cases. See, e.g., Indiana Federation of Dentists; Northwest Wholesale Stationers; NCAA; BMI. We have recognized that “there is often no bright line separating per se from Rule of Reason analysis. Per se rules may require considerable inquiry into market conditions before the evidence justifies a presumption of anticompetitive conduct.” NCAA.

In short, the conclusion that per se analysis is inappropriate in this boycott case would not preclude its application in many others, nor would it create insurmountable difficulties for antitrust enforcement. The plainly expressive nature of the Trial Lawyers’ campaign distinguishes it from boycotts that are the intended subjects of the antitrust laws. I respectfully dissent.

Justice BLACKMUN, concurring in part and dissenting in part. … [W]hile I agree with the reasoning of Justice BRENNAN’s dissent, I write separately to express my doubt whether a remand for findings of fact concerning the market power of the … Trial Lawyers would be warranted in the unique circumstances of this litigation. As Justice BRENNAN notes, the Trial Lawyers’ boycott was aimed at the District’s courts and legislature, governmental bodies that had the power to terminate the boycott at any time by requiring any or all members of the District Bar–including the members of SCTLA–to represent indigent defendants pro bono. Attorneys are not merely participants in a competitive market for legal services; they are officers of the court. Their duty to serve the public by representing indigent defendants is not only a matter of conscience, but is also enforceable by the government’s power to order such representation, either as a condition of practicing law in the District or on pain of contempt.

The Trial Lawyers’ boycott thus was a dramatic gesture not fortified by any real economic power. They could not have coerced the District to meet their demands by brute economic force, i.e., by constricting the supply of legal services to drive up the price. Instead, the Trial Lawyers’ boycott put the government in a position where it had to make a political choice between exercising its power to break the boycott or agreeing to a rate increase. The factors relevant to this choice were political, not economic: that forcing the lawyers to stop the boycott would have been unpopular, because, as it turned out, public opinion supported the boycott; and that the District officials themselves may not have genuinely opposed the rate increase, and may have welcomed the appearance of a politically expedient “emergency.”

I believe that, in this unique market where the government buys services that it could readily compel the sellers to provide, the Trial Lawyers lacked any market power and their boycott could have succeeded only through political persuasion. I therefore would affirm the judgment below insofar as it invokes the O’Brien analysis to preclude

134

Page 73: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

application of the per se rule to the Trial Lawyers’ boycott, but reverse as to the remand to the FTC for a determination of market power.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $

REVIEW PROBLEM #4: IVY LEAGUE PRICE-FIXING

Instructions

In addition to the assigned case study, consider the quotes below.

Fiske article: NYT 8/10/89: "From the consumer's point of view, the question becomes: Does an academically outstanding student who qualifies for financial aid have the right to negotiate a better aid package -- even if, from the colleges' view it means less money will be available for another financially strapped family."

6/24/92: (NYT) Dennis Carlton, U Chicago economist: "The effect of the ... meetings was not to raise price, as is typically the case with price-fixing, but rather to transfer dollars primarily from students with higher-income parents who would otherwise receive non-need based aid to other students."

9/3/92: (NYT) Charles A. James, Acting Asst. Atty Gen’l AT Div.: "The principle that we were primarily interested in establishing in this case is that these financial aid awards are a form of discount from the price charged by these universities, and should be set by market forces."

9/6/92: NYT editorial: "Here, both the purpose and effect, according to the evidence, were to transfer income to students who needed the money from students who didn't. The charitable intent might not be to the government's liking. But it is surely not a matter for antitrust law."

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS

(1) In assessing the significance of challenged practices, should the court have treated the universities’ financial aid pools as fixed or assumed that universities can always transfer funds from other parts of their operation?

(2) Assuming financial aid pools are fixed to some extent, what changes would you have expected to see in the student bodies of the relevant institutions if the challenged practices were eliminated?

(3) What changes would you expect to see in the decision-making of entering students if the challenged practices were eliminated?

(4) The Justice Dept. argued that the very best students are “entitled” to the “market price” in terms of discounts on tuition. Do you agree?

(5) Do you think that the agreement, on balance, benefited society?

135

Page 74: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

(6) Should higher education be subject to antitrust laws generally?

(7) Is it within the province of the courts to carve out an antitrust exception for higher education?

$ $ $ $ $ $ $Horizontal Restraints: Information About Pricing

I. OverviewA. Competitive markets depend on participants having good info, especially

about pricesB. Can exchange of information ever be harmful to competition?

1. Some cases find that “data dissemination” can facilitate price-fixinga. Can turn on specificity of info exchangedb. Can turn on whether market structure conducive to oligopoly

2. Problem: prohibiting exchange of information implicates 1st AmdtC. Can withholding information ever facilitate competition?

1. SCt holds no in some circs (Prof. Engineers; Indiana Fed. of Dentists)2. Allows extended inquiry in California Dentists

II. Early Data Dissemination CasesA. American Column & Lumber: (1921) trade assn. requires members to

exchange detailed price and sales information. Court finds exchange violates §1: information required is so specific, it's hard to imagine a competitive purpose.

B. Maple Flooring (1925): Trade assn. exchanges average cost and price information and freight rates from Flint, Mich. Court finds no violation, even though effect is to stabilize prices, noting that the character & use of the information does not lead "irresistibly to the conclusion that it would necessarily result in curtailing production."

C. Early Concerted Action/Boycott Cases Similar Issues1. Eastern States Retail Lumber Dealers (1914): circulated list of

wholesalers that also sold at retail; little purpose except anti-competitive; SCt finds conspiracy

2. Cement Mfrs Protective Assn (1925): Trade assn. circulated credit information re contractors. As a result, a number of manufacturers refused to do business with particular contractors. No violation. Case read as saying no proof of agreement.

D. Sugar Inst (1936): Trade assn. required advance announcement of prices & adherence to announced price. SCt enjoins only the adherence requirements; allows the announcements.

136

Page 75: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

$ $ $ $ $ $ $UNITED STATES v. CONTAINER CORPORATION OF AMERICA

393 U.S. 333 (1969)

Justice DOUGLAS delivered the opinion of the Court. This is a civil antitrust action charging a price-fixing agreement in violation of §1 the Sherman Act. The District Court dismissed the complaint. …

The case as proved is unlike any of other price decisions we have rendered. There was here an exchange of price information but no agreement to adhere to a price schedule as in Sugar Institute v. U.S., 297 U.S. 553, or Socony-Vacuum Oil Co.. There was here an exchange of information concerning specific sales to identified customers, not a statistical report on the average cost to all members, without identifying the parties to specific transactions, as in Maple Flooring Mfrs. Assn. v. U.S., 268 U.S. 563. While there was present here, as in Cement Mfrs. Protective Assn. v. U.S., 268 U.S. 588, an exchange of prices to specific customers, there was absent the controlling circumstance, viz., that cement manufacturers, to protect themselves from delivering to contractors more cement than was needed for a specific job and thus receiving a lower price, exchanged price information as a means of protecting their legal rights from fraudulent inducements to deliver more cement than needed for a specific job.

Here all that was present was a request by each defendant of its competitor for information as to the most recent price charged or quoted, whenever it needed such information and whenever it was not available from another source. Each defendant on receiving that request usually furnished the data with the expectation that it would be furnished reciprocal information when it wanted it. That concerted action is of course sufficient to establish the combination or conspiracy, the initial ingredient of a violation of §1 of the Sherman Act.

There was of course freedom to withdraw from the agreement. But the fact remains that when a defendant requested and received price information, it was affirming its willingness to furnish such information in return.

There was to be sure an infrequency and irregularity of price exchanges between the defendants; and often the data were available from the records of the defendants or from the customers themselves. Yet the essence of the agreement was to furnish price information whenever requested. Moreover, although the most recent price charged or quoted was sometimes fragmentary, each defendant had the manuals with which it could compute the price charged by a competitor on a specific order to a specific customer.

Further, the price quoted was the current price which a customer would need to pay in order to obtain products from the defendant furnishing the data. The defendants account for about 90% of the shipment of corrugated containers from plants in the Southeastern U.S.. While containers vary as to dimensions, weight, color, and so on, they are substantially identical, no matter who produces them, when made to particular specifications. The prices paid depend on price alternatives. Suppliers when seeking

137

Page 76: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

new or additional business or keeping old customers, do not exceed a competitor’s price. It is common for purchasers to buy from two or more suppliers concurrently. A defendant supplying a customer with containers would usually quote the same price on additional orders, unless costs had changed. Yet where a competitor was charging a particular price, a defendant would normally quote the same price or even a lower price.

The exchange of price information seemed to have the effect of keeping prices within a fairly narrow ambit. Capacity has exceeded the demand from 1955 to 1963, the period covered by the complaint, and the trend of corrugated container prices has been downward. Yet despite this excess capacity and the downward trend of prices, the industry has expanded in the Southeast from 30 manufacturers with 49 plants to 51 manufacturers with 98 plants. An abundance of raw materials and machinery makes entry into the industry easy with an investment of $50,000 to $75,000.

The result of this reciprocal exchange of prices was to stabilize prices though at a downward level. Knowledge of a competitor’s price usually meant matching that price. The continuation of some price competition is not fatal to the Government’s case. The limitation or reduction of price competition brings the case within the ban, for as we held in Socony-Vacuum Oil Co., interference with the setting of price by free market forces is unlawful per se. Price information exchanged in some markets may have no effect on a truly competitive price. But the corrugated container industry is dominated by relatively few sellers. The product is fungible and the competition for sales is price. The demand is inelastic, as buyers place orders only for immediate, short-run needs. The exchange of price data tends toward price uniformity. For a lower price does not mean a larger share of the available business but a sharing of the existing business at a lower return. Stabilizing prices as well as raising them is within the ban of §1 of the Sherman Act. As we said in Socony-Vacuum Oil Co., “in terms of market operations stabilization is but one form of manipulation.” The inferences are irresistible that the exchange of price information has had an anticompetitive effect in the industry, chilling the vigor of price competition…. Price is too critical, too sensitive a control to allow it to be used even in an informal manner to restrain competition.4 Reversed.

4 Thorstein Veblen in The Theory of Business Enterprise (1904) makes clear how the overabundance of a commodity creates a business appetite to regulate or control prices or output or both. Measures short of monopoly may have 'a salutary effect,' as for example a degree of control or supervision over prices not obtainable while the parties 'stood on their old footing of severalty.' But that relief is apt to be 'only transient,' for as the costs of production decline and growth of the industry 'catches up with the gain in economy,' the need for further controls or restraints increases. And so the restless, never-ending search for price control and other types of restraint.

We held in Socony-Vacuum that all forms of price-fixing are per se violations of the Sherman Act.

The elimination of so-called competitive evils is no legal justification for such buying programs. The elimination of such conditions was sought primarily for its effect on the price structures. Fairer competitive prices, it is claimed, resulted when distress gasoline was removed from the market. But such defense is typical of the protestations usually made in price-fixing cases. Ruinous competition, financial disaster, evils of price cutting and the like appear throughout our history as ostensible justifications for price-fixing. If the so-called competitive abuses were to be appraised here, the reasonableness of prices would necessarily become an issue in every price-fixing case. In

138

Page 77: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Justice FORTAS, concurring. I join in the judgment and opinion of the Court. I do not understand the Court’s opinion to hold that the exchange of specific information among sellers as to prices charged to individual customers, pursuant to mutual arrangement, is a per se violation of the Sherman Act.

Absent per se violation, proof is essential that the practice resulted in an unreasonable restraint of trade. There is no single test to determine when the record adequately shows an “unreasonable restraint of trade”; but a practice such as that here involved, which is adopted for the purpose of arriving at a determination of prices to be quoted to individual customers, inevitably suggests the probability that it so materially interfered with the operation of the price mechanism of the marketplace as to bring it within the condemnation of this Court’s decisions.

Theoretical probability, however, is not enough unless we are to regard mere exchange of current price information as so akin to price-fixing by combination or conspiracy as to deserve the per se classification. I am not prepared to do this, nor is it necessary here. In this case, the probability that the exchange of specific price information led to an unlawful effect upon prices is adequately buttressed by evidence in the record. This evidence, although not overwhelming, is sufficient in the special circumstances of this case to show an actual effect on pricing and to compel us to hold that the court below erred in dismissing the Government’s complaint.

… [T]he defendants sought and obtained from competitors who were part of the arrangement information about the competitors’ prices to specific customers. “[I]n the majority of instances,” the District Court found, that once a defendant had this information he quoted substantially the same price as the competitor, although a higher or lower price would “occasionally” be quoted. Thus the exchange of prices made it possible for individual defendants confidently to name a price equal to that which their competitors were asking. The obvious effect was to “stabilize” prices by joint arrangement – at least to limit any price cuts to the minimum necessary to meet competition. In addition, there was evidence that, in some instances, during periods when various defendants ceased exchanging prices exceptionally sharp and vigorous price reductions resulted. On this record, taking into account the specially sensitive function of the price term in the antitrust equation, I cannot see that we would be justified in reaching any conclusion other than that defendants’ tacit agreement to exchange information about current prices to specific customers did in fact substantially limit the amount of price competition in the industry. That being so, there is no need to consider the possibility of a per se violation.

Justice MARSHALL, with whom Justice HARLAN and Justice STEWART join, dissenting. I agree with the Court’s holding that there existed an agreement among the defendants to exchange price information whenever requested. however, I cannot agree that that agreement should be condemned, either as illegal per se, or as having had the purpose or effect of restricting price competition in the corrugated container industry in the Southeastern U.S.

that event the Sherman Act would soon be emasculated; its philosophy would be supplanted by one which is wholly alien to a system of free competition; it would not be the charter of freedom which its framers intended.

139

Page 78: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Under the antitrust laws, numerous practices have been held to be illegal per se without regard to their precise purpose or harm. … This Court has refused to apply a per se rule to exchanges of price and market information in the past. … I believe we should follow the same course in the present case.

Per se rules always contain a degree of arbitrariness. They are justified on the assumption that the gains from imposition of the rule will far outweigh the losses and that significant administrative advantages will result. In other words, the potential competitive harm plus the administrative costs of determining in what particular situations the practice may be harmful must far outweigh the benefits that may result. If the potential benefits in the aggregate are outweighed to this degree, then they are simply not worth identifying in individual cases.

I do not believe that the agreement in the present case is so devoid of potential benefit or so inherently harmful that we are justified in condemning it without proof that it was entered into for the purpose of restraining price competition or that it actually had that effect. The agreement in this case was to supply, when requested, price data for identified customers. Each defendant supplied the necessary information on the expectation that the favor would be returned. The nature of the exchanged information varied from case to case. In most cases, the price obtained was the price of the last sale to the particular customer; in some cases, the price was a current quotation to the customer. In all cases, the information obtained was sufficient to inform the defendants of the price they would have to beat in order to obtain a particular sale.

Complete market knowledge is certainly not an evil in perfectly competitive markets. This is not, however, such a market, and there is admittedly some danger that price information will be used for anticompetitive purposes, particularly the maintenance of prices at a high level. If the danger that price information will be so used is particularly high in a given situation, then perhaps exchange of information should be condemned.

I do not think the danger is sufficiently high in the present case. Defendants are only 18 of the 51 producers of corrugated containers in the Southeastern U.S.. Together, they do make up 90% of the market and the six largest defendants do control 60% of the market. But entry is easy; an investment of $50,000 to $75,000 is ordinarily all that is necessary. In fact, the number of sellers has increased from 30 to the present 51 in the eight-year period covered by the complaint. The size of the market has almost doubled because of increased demand for corrugated containers. Nevertheless, some excess capacity is present. The products produced by defendants are undifferentiated. Industry demand is inelastic, so that price changes will not, up to a certain point, affect the total amount purchased. The only effect of price changes will be to reallocate market shares among sellers.

In a competitive situation, each seller will cut his price in order to increase his share of the market, and prices will ultimately stabilize at a competitive level – i.e., price will equal cost, including a reasonable return on capital. Obviously, it would be to a seller’s benefit to avoid such price competition and maintain prices at a higher level, with a corresponding increase in profit. In a market with very few sellers, and detailed knowledge of each other’s price, such action is possible. However, I do not think it can

140

Page 79: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

be concluded that this particular market is sufficiently oligopolistic, especially in light of the case of entry, to justify the inference that price information will necessarily be used to stabilize prices. Nor do I think that the danger of such a result is sufficiently high to justify imposing a per se rule without actual proof.

In this market, we have a few sellers presently controlling a substantial share of the market. We have a large number competing for the remainder of the market, also quite substantial. And total demand is increasing. In such a case, I think it just as logical to assume that the sellers, especially the smaller and newer ones, will desire to capture a larger market share by cutting prices as it is that they will acquiesce in oligopolistic behavior. The likelihood that prices will be cut and that those lower prices will have to be met acts as a deterrent to setting prices at an artificially high level in the first place. Given the uncertainty about the probable effect of an exchange of price information in this context, I would require that the Government prove that the exchange was entered into for the purpose of, or that it had the effect of, restraining price competition.

I do not find the inference that the exchange of price information has had an anticompetitive effect as “irresistible” as does the Court. Like my Brother FORTAS, I would prefer that a finding of anticompetitive effect be supported by “evidence in the record.” I cannot agree that the evidence in this case was sufficient to prove such an effect. The Government has simply not proved its case.

The Court does not hold that the agreement in the present case was a deliberate attempt to stabilize prices. The evidence in the case, largely the result of stipulation, would not support such a holding. The Government points to a few isolated statements found in the depositions of industry witnesses, but I find these few fragmentary references totally insufficient. The weight of the evidence in the present case indicates that the price information was employed by each defendant on an individual basis, and was used by the defendant to set its price for a specific customer; ultimately each seller wanted to obtain all or part of that customer’s business at the expense of a competitor. The District Court found that there was no explicit agreement among defendants to stabilize prices and I do not believe that the desire of a few industry witnesses to use the information to minimize price cuts supports the conclusion that such an agreement was implicit. On the contrary, the evidence establishes that the information was used by defendants as each pleased and was actually employed for the purpose of engaging in active price competition.

Nor [has] the Government … proved that the exchange of price information has … had the necessary effect of restraining price competition. In its brief before this Court, the Government relies very largely on one finding of the District Court and upon economic theory. The Government has presented a convincing argument in theoretical terms. However, the evidence simply does not square with that theory. And, this is not a case in which it would be unduly difficult to demonstrate anticompetitive effects.

The record indicates that defendants have offered voluminous evidence concerning price trends and competitive behavior in the corrugated container market. Their exhibits indicate a downward trend in prices, with substantial price variations among defendants and among their different plants. There was also a great deal of shifting of accounts. The District Court specifically found that the corrugated container

141

Page 80: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

market was highly competitive and that each defendant engaged in active price competition. The Government would have us ignore this evidence and these findings, and assume that because we are dealing with an industry with overcapacity and yet continued entry, the new entrants must have been attracted by high profits. The Government then argues that high profits can only result from stabilization of prices at an unduly high level. Yet, the Government did not introduce any evidence about the level of profits in this industry, and no evidence about price levels. Not one customer was called, although the Government surely had ample access to defendants’ customers. The Government admits that the price trend was down, but asks the Court to assume that the trend would have been accelerated with less informed, and hence more vigorous, price competition.3 In the absence of any proof whatsoever, I cannot make such an assumption. It is just as likely that price competition was furthered by the exchange as is it that it was depressed.

Finally, the Government focuses on the finding … that in a majority of instances a defendant, when it received what it considered reliable price information, would quote or charge substantially the same price.4 The Court and my Brother Fortas also focus on this finding. Such an approach ignores, however, the remainder of the District Court’s findings. The trial judge found that price decisions were individual decisions, and that defendants frequently did cut prices in order to obtain a particular order. And, the absence of any price parallelism or price uniformity and the downward trend in the industry undercut the conclusion that price information was used to stabilize prices.6

The Government is ultimately forced to fall back on the theoretical argument that prices would have been more unstable and would have fallen faster without price information. As I said earlier, I cannot make this assumption on the basis of the evidence in this record. The findings of the Court below simply do not indicate that the exchange of information had a significant anticompetitive effect; if we rely on these findings, at worst all we can assume is that the exchange was a neutral factor in the market. … [T]he record indicates that, while each defendant occasionally received price information from a competitor, that information was used in the same manner as other reliable market information – i.e., to reach an individual price decision based upon all available information. The District Court’s findings that this was a competitive industry, lacking any price parallelism or uniformity, effectively refute the Government’s assertion that the result of those decisions was to maintain or tend to maintain prices at other than a competitive level. Accordingly, I would affirm the decision of the court below.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $3 There was no effort to demonstrate that the price behavior of those manufacturers who did not exchange price information, if any, varied significantly from the price behavior of those who did. In fact, several of the District Court’s findings indicate that when certain defendants stopped exchanging price information, their price behavior remained essentially the same, and, in some cases, prices actually increased.4 It should be noted that, in most cases, this information was obtained from a customer rather than a competitor, a practice the Government does not condemn.6 As mentioned above, no evidence was introduced that would indicate that more than minimal price cuts were economically feasible.

142

Page 81: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

CALIFORNIA DENTAL ASS’N v. FTC 526 U.S. 756 (1999)

Justice SOUTER delivered the opinion of the Court. … The [California Dental Association (CDA)] is a voluntary nonprofit association of local dental societies to which some 19,000 dentists belong, including about three-quarters of those practicing in the State. … The dentists who belong to the CDA … agree to abide by a Code of Ethics (Code) including the following §10:

… no dentist shall advertise or solicit patients in any form of communication in a manner that is false or misleading in any material respect. In order to properly serve the public, dentists should represent themselves in a manner that contributes to the esteem of the public. Dentists should not misrepresent their training and competence in any way that would be false or misleading in any material respect.

The CDA has issued a number of advisory opinions interpreting this section,1 and through separate advertising guidelines … has advised its dentists of disclosures they must make under state law when engaging in discount advertising.2

1 The advisory opinions, which substantially mirror parts of the California Business and Professions Code, include the following propositions:

A statement or claim is false or misleading in any material respect when it:

a. contains a misrepresentation of fact;

b. is likely to mislead or deceive because in context it makes only a partial disclosure of relevant facts;

c. is intended or is likely to create false or unjustified expectations of favorable results and/or costs;

d. relates to fees for specific types of services without fully and specifically disclosing all variables and other relevant factors;

e. contains other representations or implications that in reasonable probability will cause an ordinarily prudent person to misunderstand or be deceived.

Any communication or advertisement which refers to the cost of dental services shall be exact, without omissions, and shall make each service clearly identifiable, without the use of such phrases as “as low as,” “and up,” “lowest prices,” or words or phrases of similar import.

Any advertisement which refers to the cost of dental services and uses words of comparison or relativity–for example, “low fees”–must be based on verifiable data substantiating the comparison or statement of relativity. The burden shall be on the dentist who advertises in such terms to establish the accuracy of the comparison or statement of relativity.

Advertising claims as to the quality of services are not susceptible to measurement or verification; accordingly, such claims are likely to be false or misleading in any material respect.

2 The disclosures include:

1. The dollar amount of the nondiscounted fee for the service[.]

2. Either the dollar amount of the discount fee or the percentage of the discount for the specific service[.]

3. The length of time that the discount will be offered[.]

143

Page 82: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Responsibility for enforcing the Code rests in the first instance with the local dental societies, to which applicants for CDA membership must submit copies of their own advertisements and those of their employers or referral services…. The local societies also actively seek information about potential Code violations by applicants or CDA members. Applicants who refuse to withdraw or revise objectionable advertisements may be denied membership; and members who, after a hearing, remain similarly recalcitrant are subject to censure, suspension, or expulsion from the CDA.

The [FTC] brought a complaint against the CDA, alleging that it applied its guidelines so as to restrict truthful, nondeceptive advertising, and so violated §5 of the FTC Act.3 The complaint alleged that the CDA had unreasonably restricted … price advertising, particularly discounted fees, and advertising relating to the quality of dental services. An Administrative Law Judge (ALJ) … found that, although there had been no proof that the CDA exerted market power, no such proof was required to establish an antitrust violation under In re Mass. Bd. of Registration in Optometry, 110 F.T.C. 549 (1988), since the CDA had unreasonably prevented members and potential members from using truthful, nondeceptive advertising, all to the detriment of both dentists and consumers of dental services. He accordingly found a violation of §5 of the FTC Act.

The [FTC] adopted the factual findings of the ALJ except for his conclusion that the CDA lacked market power…. The [FTC] treated the CDA’s restrictions on discount advertising as illegal per se. In the alternative, the Commission held the price advertising (as well as the nonprice) restrictions to be violations of the Sherman and FTC Acts under an abbreviated rule-of-reason analysis. …

The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit affirmed…. The court thought it error for the [FTC] to have applied per se analysis to the price advertising restrictions, finding analysis under the rule of reason required for all the restrictions. But the Court of Appeals went on to explain that the Commission had properly

applied an abbreviated, or “quick look,” rule of reason analysis designed for restraints that are not per se unlawful but are sufficiently anticompetitive on their face that they do not require a full-blown rule of reason inquiry. See NCAA. … It allows the condemnation of a “naked restraint” on price or output without an “elaborate industry analysis.” Id.

The Court of Appeals thought truncated rule-of-reason analysis to be in order for several reasons. As for the restrictions on discount advertising, they “amounted in practice to a fairly ‘naked’ restraint on price competition itself.” The CDA’s procompetitive justification, that the restrictions encouraged disclosure and prevented false and misleading advertising, carried little weight because “it is simply infeasible to disclose all of the information that is required,” and “the record provides no evidence that

4. Verifiable fees[.]

5. [The identity of] [s]pecific groups who qualify for the discount or any other terms and conditions or restrictions for qualifying for the discount.

3 The FTC Act’s prohibition of unfair competition and deceptive acts or practices overlaps the scope of §1 of the Sherman Act, aimed at prohibiting restraint of trade and the [FTC] relied upon Sherman Act law in adjudicating this case.

144

Page 83: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

the rule has in fact led to increased disclosure and transparency of dental pricing.” As to non-price advertising restrictions, the court said that

[t]hese restrictions are in effect a form of output limitation, as they restrict the supply of information about individual dentists’ services.... The restrictions may also affect output more directly, as quality and comfort advertising may induce some customers to obtain nonemergency care when they might not otherwise do so.... [W]e think that the restriction is a sufficiently naked restraint on output to justify quick look analysis.

The Court of Appeals went on to hold that the … findings with respect to the CDA’s agreement and intent to restrain trade, as well as on the effect of the restrictions and the existence of market power, were all supported by substantial evidence. …

We granted certiorari to resolve conflicts among the Circuits on the Commission’s jurisdiction over … the occasions for abbreviated rule-of-reason analysis. We now vacate the judgment of the Court of Appeals and remand. … Because we decide that the Court of Appeals erred when it held as a matter of law that quick-look analysis was appropriate (with the consequence that the Commission’s abbreviated analysis and conclusion were sustainable), we do not reach the question of the substantiality of the evidence supporting the Commission’s conclusion.8

In NCAA, we held that a “naked restraint on price and output requires some competitive justification even in the absence of a detailed market analysis.” Elsewhere, we held that “no elaborate industry analysis is required to demonstrate the anticompetitive character of “ horizontal agreements among competitors to refuse to discuss prices, Professional Engineers, or to withhold a particular desired service, Indiana Federation of Dentists. In each of these cases, which have formed the basis for what has come to be called abbreviated or “quick-look” analysis under the rule of reason, an observer with even a rudimentary understanding of economics could conclude that the arrangements in question would have an anticompetitive effect on customers and markets. In NCAA, the league’s television plan expressly limited output (the number of games that could be televised) and fixed a minimum price. In Professional Engineers, the restraint was “an absolute ban on competitive bidding.” In Indiana Federation of Dentists, the restraint was “a horizontal agreement among the participating dentists to withhold from their customers a particular service that they desire.” As in such cases, quick-look analysis carries the day when the great likelihood of anticompetitive effects can easily be ascertained. …

The case before us, however, fails to present a situation in which the likelihood of anticompetitive effects is comparably obvious. Even on Justice BREYER’s view that bars on truthful and verifiable price and quality advertising are prima facie anticompetitive, and place the burden of procompetitive justification on those who agree to adopt them, the very issue at the threshold of this case is whether professional price and quality advertising is sufficiently verifiable in theory and in fact to fall within such a general rule. Ultimately our disagreement with Justice BREYER turns on our different responses to this issue. Whereas he accepts, as the Ninth Circuit seems to have done, that the restrictions here were like restrictions on advertisement of price and quality 8 We leave to the Court of Appeals the question whether on remand it can effectively assess the Commission’s decision for substantial evidence on the record, or whether it must remand to the Commission for a more extensive rule-of-reason analysis on the basis of an enhanced record.

145

Page 84: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

generally, it seems to us that the CDA’s advertising restrictions might plausibly be thought to have a net procompetitive effect, or possibly no effect at all on competition. The restrictions on both discount and nondiscount advertising are, at least on their face, designed to avoid false or deceptive advertising9 in a market characterized by striking disparities between the information available to the professional and the patient.10 Cf. Carr & Mathewson, The Economics of Law Firms: A Study in the Legal Organization of the Firm, 33 J. LAW & ECON. 307, 309 (1990) (explaining that in a market for complex professional services, “inherent asymmetry of knowledge about the product” arises because “professionals supplying the good are knowledgeable [whereas] consumers demanding the good are uninformed”); Akerlof, The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism, 84 Q.J. ECON. 488 (1970) (pointing out quality problems in market characterized by asymmetrical information).

In a market for professional services, in which advertising is relatively rare and the comparability of service packages not easily established, the difficulty for customers or potential competitors to get and verify information about the price and availability of services magnifies the dangers to competition associated with misleading advertising. What is more, the quality of professional services tends to resist either calibration or monitoring by individual patients or clients, partly because of the specialized knowledge required to evaluate the services, and partly because of the difficulty in determining whether, and the degree to which, an outcome is attributable to the quality of services (like a poor job of tooth-filling) or to something else (like a very tough walnut). See Leland, Quacks, Lemons, and Licensing: A Theory of Minimum Quality Standards, 87 J. Pol. Econ. 1328, 1330 (1979); 1 B. FURROW, T. GREANEY, S. JOHNSON, T. JOST, & R. SCHWARTZ, HEALTH LAW §3-1, p. 86 (1995) (describing the common view that “the lay public is incapable of adequately evaluating the quality of medical services”). Patients’ attachments to particular professionals, the rationality of which is difficult to assess, complicate the picture even further. Cf. Evans, Professionals and the Production Function: Can Competition Policy Improve Efficiency in the Licensed Professions?, in OCCUPATIONAL LICENSURE AND REGULATION 235-236 (S. Rottenberg ed.1980) (describing long-term relationship between professional and client not as “a series of spot contracts” but rather as “a long-term agreement, often implicit, to deal with each other in a set of future unspecified or incompletely specified circumstances according to certain rules,” and adding that “[i]t is not clear how or if these [implicit contracts] can be reconciled with the promotion of effective price competition in individual spot markets for particular services”). The existence of such significant challenges to informed

9 That false or misleading advertising has an anticompetitive effect, as that term is customarily used, has been long established. Cf. FTC v. Algoma Lumber Co., 291 U.S. 67, 79-80, (1934) (finding a false advertisement to be unfair competition).1 0 The fact that a restraint operates upon a profession as distinguished from a business is, of

course, relevant in determining whether that particular restraint violates the Sherman Act. It would be unrealistic to view the practice of professions as interchangeable with other business activities, and automatically to apply to the professions antitrust concepts which originated in other areas. The public service aspect, and other features of the professions, may require that a particular practice, which could properly be viewed as a violation of the Sherman Act in another context, be treated differently.

Goldfarb v. Virginia State Bar, 421 U.S. 773, 788-789, n.17 (1975).

146

Page 85: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

decisionmaking by the customer for professional services immediately suggests that advertising restrictions arguably protecting patients from misleading or irrelevant advertising call for more than cursory treatment as obviously comparable to classic horizontal agreements to limit output or price competition.

The explanation proffered by the Court of Appeals for the likely anticompetitive effect of the CDA’s restrictions … began with the unexceptionable statements that “price advertising is fundamental to price competition,” and that “[r]estrictions on the ability to advertise prices normally make it more difficult for consumers to find a lower price and for dentists to compete on the basis of price.” The court then acknowledged that, according to the CDA, the restrictions nonetheless furthered the “legitimate, indeed procompetitive, goal of preventing false and misleading price advertising.” The Court of Appeals might, at this juncture, have recognized that the restrictions at issue here are very far from a total ban on price or discount advertising, and might have considered the possibility that the particular restrictions on professional advertising could have different effects from those “normally” found in the commercial world, even to the point of promoting competition by reducing the occurrence of unverifiable and misleading across-the-board discount advertising.11 Instead, the Court of Appeals confined itself to the brief assertion that the “CDA’s disclosure requirements appear to prohibit across-the-board discounts because it is simply infeasible to disclose all of the information that is required,” followed by the observation that “the record provides no evidence that the rule has in fact led to increased disclosure and transparency of dental pricing.”

But these observations brush over the professional context and describe no anticompetitive effects. Assuming that the record in fact supports the conclusion that the CDA disclosure rules essentially bar advertisement of across-the-board discounts, it does not obviously follow that such a ban would have a net anticompetitive effect here. Whether advertisements that announced discounts for, say, first-time customers, would be less effective at conveying information relevant to competition if they listed the original and discounted prices for checkups, X-rays, and fillings, than they would be if they simply specified a percentage discount across the board, seems to us a question susceptible to empirical but not a priori analysis. In a suspicious world, the discipline of specific example may well be a necessary condition of plausibility for professional claims that for all practical purposes defy comparison shopping. It is also possible in principle that, even if across-the-board discount advertisements were more effective in drawing customers in the short run, the recurrence of some measure of intentional or accidental misstatement due to the breadth of their claims might leak out over time to make potential patients skeptical of any such across-the-board advertising, so undercutting the method’s effectiveness. Cf. Akerlof, 84 Q.J. ECON., at 495 (explaining that “dishonest dealings tend to drive honest dealings out of the market”). It might be, too, that across-the-board discount advertisements would continue to attract business indefinitely, but might work precisely because they were misleading customers, and thus just because 11 Justice BREYER claims that “the Court of Appeals did consider the relevant differences.” But the language he cites says nothing more than that per se analysis is inappropriate here and that “some caution” was appropriate where restrictions purported to restrict false advertising. Caution was of course appropriate, but this statement by the Court of Appeals does not constitute a consideration of the possible differences between these and other advertising restrictions.

147

Page 86: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

their effect would be anticompetitive, not procompetitive. Put another way, the CDA’s rule appears to reflect the prediction that any costs to competition associated with the elimination of across-the-board advertising will be outweighed by gains to consumer information (and hence competition) created by discount advertising that is exact, accurate, and more easily verifiable (at least by regulators). As a matter of economics this view may or may not be correct, but it is not implausible, and neither a court nor the Commission may initially dismiss it as presumptively wrong.12

In theory, it is true, the Court of Appeals neither ruled out the plausibility of some procompetitive support for the CDA’s requirements nor foreclosed the utility of an evidentiary discussion on the point. The court indirectly acknowledged the plausibility of procompetitive justifications for the CDA’s position when it stated that “the record provides no evidence that the rule has in fact led to increased disclosure and transparency of dental pricing.” But because petitioner alone would have had the incentive to introduce such evidence, the statement sounds as though the Court of Appeals may have thought it was justified without further analysis to shift a burden to the CDA to adduce hard evidence of the procompetitive nature of its policy; the court’s adversion to empirical evidence at the moment of this implicit burden-shifting underscores the leniency of its enquiry into evidence of the restrictions’ anticompetitive effects.

The Court of Appeals was comparably tolerant in accepting the sufficiency of abbreviated rule-of-reason analysis as to the nonprice advertising restrictions. The court began with the argument that “[t]hese restrictions are in effect a form of output limitation, as they restrict the supply of information about individual dentists’ services,” (citing P. AREEDA & H. HOVENKAMP, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1505, pp.693-694 (1997 Supp.)). Although this sentence does indeed appear as cited, it is puzzling, given that the relevant output for antitrust purposes here is presumably not information or advertising, but dental services themselves. The question is not whether the universe of possible advertisements has been limited (as assuredly it has), but whether the limitation on advertisements obviously tends to limit the total delivery of dental services. The court came closest to addressing this latter question when it went on to assert that limiting advertisements regarding quality and safety “prevents dentists from fully describing the package of services they offer,” adding that “[t]he restrictions may also affect output more directly, as quality and comfort advertising may induce some customers to obtain nonemergency care when they might not otherwise do so.” This suggestion about output is also puzzling. If quality advertising actually induces some patients to obtain more care than they would in its absence, then restricting such advertising would reduce the demand for

12 Justice BREYER suggests that our analysis is “of limited relevance,” because “the basic question is whether this ... theoretically redeeming virtue in fact offsets the restrictions” anticompetitive effects in this case.,” He thinks that the Commission and the Court of Appeals “adequately answered that question,” but the absence of any empirical evidence on this point indicates that the question was not answered, merely avoided by implicit burden-shifting of the kind accepted by Justice BREYER. The point is that before a theoretical claim of anticompetitive effects can justify shifting to a defendant the burden to show empirical evidence of procompetitive effects, as quick-look analysis in effect requires, there must be some indication that the court making the decision has properly identified the theoretical basis for the anticompetitive effects and considered whether the effects actually are anticompetitive. Where, as here, the circumstances of the restriction are somewhat complex, assumption alone will not do.

148

Page 87: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

dental services, not the supply; and it is of course the producers’ supply of a good in relation to demand that is normally relevant in determining whether a producer-imposed output limitation has the anticompetitive effect of artificially raising prices,13 see General Leaseways, Inc. v. National Truck Leasing Assn., 744 F.2d 588, 594-595 (C.A.7 1984) (“An agreement on output also equates to a price-fixing agreement. If firms raise price, the market’s demand for their product will fall, so the amount supplied will fall too–in other words, output will be restricted. If instead the firms restrict output directly, price will as mentioned rise in order to limit demand to the reduced supply. Thus, with exceptions not relevant here, raising price, reducing output, and dividing markets have the same anticompetitive effects”).

Although the Court of Appeals acknowledged the CDA’s view that “claims about quality are inherently unverifiable and therefore misleading,” it responded that this concern “does not justify banning all quality claims without regard to whether they are, in fact, false or misleading.” As a result, the court said, “the restriction is a sufficiently naked restraint on output to justify quick look analysis.” The court assumed, in these words, that some dental quality claims may escape justifiable censure, because they are both verifiable and true. But its implicit assumption fails to explain why it gave no weight to the countervailing, and at least equally plausible, suggestion that restricting difficult-to-verify claims about quality or patient comfort would have a procompetitive effect by preventing misleading or false claims that distort the market. It is, indeed, entirely possible to understand the CDA’s restrictions on unverifiable quality and comfort advertising as nothing more than a procompetitive ban on puffery, cf. Bates v. State Bar of Ariz., 433 U.S. 350, 366 (1977) (claims relating to the quality of legal services “probably are not susceptible of precise measurement or verification and, under some circumstances, might well be deceptive or misleading to the public, or even false”); id., at 383-384 (“[A]dvertising claims as to the quality of services ... are not susceptible of measurement or verification; accordingly, such claims may be so likely to be misleading as to warrant restriction”), notwithstanding Justice BREYER’s citation to a Commission discussion that never faces the issue of the unverifiability of professional quality claims, raised in Bates.14

The point is not that the CDA’s restrictions necessarily have the procompetitive effect claimed by the CDA; it is possible that banning quality claims might have no effect at all on competitiveness if, for example, many dentists made very much the same sort of claims. And it is also of course possible that the restrictions might in the final analysis be anticompetitive. The point, rather, is that the plausibility of competing claims 13 Justice BREYER wonders if we “mea[n] this statement as an argument against the anticompetitive tendencies that flow from an agreement not to advertise service quality.” But as the preceding sentence shows, we intend simply to question the logic of the Court of Appeals’s suggestion that the restrictions are anticompetitive because they somehow “affect output,” presumably with the intent to raise prices by limiting supply while demand remains constant. We do not mean to deny that an agreement not to advertise service quality might have anticompetitive effects. We merely mean that, absent further analysis of the kind Justice BREYER undertakes, it is not possible to conclude that the net effect of this particular restriction is anticompetitive.14 The Commission said only that “‘mere puffing’ deceives no one and has never been subject to regulation.” The question here, of course, is not whether puffery may be subject to governmental regulation, but whether a professional organization may ban it.

149

Page 88: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

about the effects of the professional advertising restrictions rules out the indulgently abbreviated review to which the Commission’s order was treated. The obvious anticompetitive effect that triggers abbreviated analysis has not been shown.

In light of our focus on the adequacy of the Court of Appeals’s analysis, Justice BREYER’s thorough-going, de novo antitrust analysis contains much to impress on its own merits but little to demonstrate the sufficiency of the Court of Appeals’s review. The obligation to give a more deliberate look than a quick one does not arise at the door of this Court and should not be satisfied here in the first instance. Had the Court of Appeals engaged in a painstaking discussion in a league with Justice BREYER’s (compare his 14 pages with the Ninth Circuit’s 8), and had it confronted the comparability of these restrictions to bars on clearly verifiable advertising, its reasoning might have sufficed to justify its conclusion. Certainly Justice BREYER’s treatment of the antitrust issues here is no “quick look.” Lingering is more like it, and indeed Justice BREYER, not surprisingly, stops short of endorsing the Court of Appeals’s discussion as adequate….

Saying here that the Court of Appeals’s conclusion at least required a more extended examination of the possible factual underpinnings than it received is not, of course, necessarily to call for the fullest market analysis. Although we have said that a challenge to a “naked restraint on price and output” need not be supported by “a detailed market analysis” in order to “requir[e] some competitive justification,” NCAA, it does not follow that every case attacking a less obviously anticompetitive restraint (like this one) is a candidate for plenary market examination. The truth is that our categories of analysis of anticompetitive effect are less fixed than terms like “per se,” “quick look,” and “rule of reason” tend to make them appear. We have recognized, for example, that “there is often no bright line separating per se from Rule of Reason analysis,” since “considerable inquiry into market conditions” may be required before the application of any so-called “per se” condemnation is justified. Id. at n.26. “[W]hether the ultimate finding is the product of a presumption or actual market analysis, the essential inquiry remains the same–whether or not the challenged restraint enhances competition.” Id. Indeed, the scholar who enriched antitrust law with the metaphor of “the twinkling of an eye” for the most condensed rule-of-reason analysis himself cautioned against the risk of misleading even in speaking of a “spectrum” of adequate reasonableness analysis for passing upon antitrust claims: “There is always something of a sliding scale in appraising reasonableness, but the sliding scale formula deceptively suggests greater precision than we can hope for.... Nevertheless, the quality of proof required should vary with the circumstances.” P.AREEDA, ANTITRUST LAW ¶1507, p.402 (1986).15 At the same time,

15 Other commentators have expressed similar views. See, e.g., Kolasky, Counterpoint: The Department of Justice’s “Stepwise” Approach Imposes Too Heavy a Burden on Parties to Horizontal Agreements, ANTITRUST 41, 43 (Spring 1998) (“[I]n applying the rule of reason, the courts, as with any balancing test, use a sliding scale to determine how much proof to require”); Piraino, Making Sense of the Rule of Reason: A New Standard for Section 1 of the Sherman Act , 47 VAND. L.REV. 1753, 1771 (1994) ( “[C]ourts will have to undertake varying degrees of inquiry depending upon the type of restraint at issue. The legality of certain restraints will be easy to determine because their competitive effects are obvious. Other restrictions will require a more detailed analysis because their competitive impact is more ambiguous”). But see Klein, A “Stepwise” Approach for Analyzing Horizontal Agreements Will Provide a Much Needed

150

Page 89: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

Professor Areeda also emphasized the necessity, particularly great in the quasi-common law realm of antitrust, that courts explain the logic of their conclusions. “By exposing their reasoning, judges ... are subjected to others’ critical analyses, which in turn can lead to better understanding for the future.” Id. ¶1500, at 364. As the circumstances here demonstrate, there is generally no categorical line to be drawn between restraints that give rise to an intuitively obvious inference of anticompetitive effect and those that call for more detailed treatment. What is required, rather, is an enquiry meet for the case, looking to the circumstances, details, and logic of a restraint. The object is to see whether the experience of the market has been so clear, or necessarily will be, that a confident conclusion about the principal tendency of a restriction will follow from a quick (or at least quicker) look, in place of a more sedulous one. And of course what we see may vary over time, if rule-of-reason analyses in case after case reach identical conclusions. For now, at least, a less quick look was required for the initial assessment of the tendency of these professional advertising restrictions. Because the Court of Appeals did not scrutinize the assumption of relative anticompetitive tendencies, we vacate the judgment and remand the case for a fuller consideration of the issue.

Justice BREYER, with whom Justice STEVENS, Justice KENNEDY, and Justice GINSBURG join, concurring in part and dissenting in part. I agree … that in a “rule of reason” antitrust case “the quality of proof required should vary with the circumstances,” that “[w]hat is required ... is an enquiry meet for the case,” and that the object is a “confident conclusion about the principal tendency of a restriction.” But I do not agree that the Court has properly applied those unobjectionable principles here. In my view, a traditional application of the rule of reason to the facts as found by the [FTC] requires affirming the [FTC]–just as the Court of Appeals did below.

I. The [FTC’s] conclusion is lawful if its “factual findings,” insofar as they are supported by “substantial evidence,” “make out a violation of Sherman Act § 1.” Indiana Federation of Dentists. To determine whether that is so, I would not simply ask whether the restraints at issue are anticompetitive overall. Rather, like the Court of Appeals (and the Commission), I would break that question down into four classical, subsidiary antitrust questions: (1) What is the specific restraint at issue? (2) What are its likely anticompetitive effects? (3) Are there offsetting procompetitive justifications? (4) Do the parties have sufficient market power to make a difference?

A. The most important question is the first: What are the specific restraints at issue? Those restraints do not include merely the agreement to which the [CDA’s] … ethical rule literally refers, namely, a promise to refrain from advertising that is “false or misleading in any material respect.” Instead, the [FTC] found a set of restraints arising out of the way the [CDA] implemented this innocent-sounding ethical rule in practice, through advisory opinions, guidelines, enforcement policies, and review of membership applications. As implemented, the ethical rule reached beyond its nominal target, to prevent truthful and nondeceptive advertising. In particular, the [FTC] determined that the rule, in practice:

Structure for Antitrust Review, ANTITRUST 41, 42 (Spring 1990) (examination of procompetitive justifications “is by no means a full scrutiny of the proffered efficiency justification. It is, rather, a hard look at the justification to determine if it meets the defendant’s burden of coming forward with–but not establishing–a valid efficiency justification”).

151

Page 90: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

(1) precluded advertising that characterized a dentist’s fees as being low, reasonable, or affordable;

(2) precluded advertising ... of across the board discounts; and

(3) prohibit[ed] all quality claims.

Whether the [CDA’s] basic rule as implemented actually restrained the truthful and nondeceptive advertising of low prices, across-the-board discounts, and quality service are questions of fact. The ALJ and the [FTC] … both … ultimately found against the [CDA] in respect to these facts. And the question for us–whether those agency findings are supported by substantial evidence–is not difficult.

The Court of Appeals referred explicitly to some of the evidence that it found adequate to support the [FTC’s] conclusions. … For example, … [CDA’s] “advisory opinions and guidelines indicate that ... descriptions of prices as ‘reasonable’ or ‘low’ do not comply” with the [CDA’s] rule; … in “numerous cases,” [CDA] “advised members of objections to special offers, senior citizen discounts, and new patient discounts, apparently without regard to their truth”; and … one advisory opinion “expressly states that claims as to the quality of services are inherently likely to be false or misleading,” all “without any particular consideration of whether” such statements were “true or false.”

The [FTC] itself had before it far more evidence. It referred to instances in which the [CDA], without regard for the truthfulness of the statements at issue, recommended denial of membership to dentists wishing to advertise, for example, “reasonable fees quoted in advance,” “major savings,” or “making teeth cleaning ... inexpensive.” It referred to testimony that “across-the-board discount advertising in literal compliance with the requirements ‘would probably take two pages in the telephone book’ and ‘[n]obody is going to really advertise in that fashion.’” And it pointed to many instances in which [CDA] suppressed such advertising claims as “we guarantee all dental work for 1 year,” “latest in cosmetic dentistry,” and “gentle dentistry in a caring environment.”

I need not review the evidence further, for this Court has said that “substantial evidence” is a matter for the courts of appeals, and that it “will intervene only in what ought to be the rare instance when the standard appears to have been misapprehended or grossly misapplied.” Universal Camera Corp. v. NLRB, 340 U.S. 474, 490-491. I have said enough to make clear that this is not a case warranting our intervention. Consequently, we must decide only the basic legal question whether the three restraints described above unreasonably restrict competition.

B. Do each of the three restrictions mentioned have “the potential for genuine adverse effects on competition”? Indiana Federation. I should have thought that the anticompetitive tendencies of the three restrictions were obvious. An agreement not to advertise that a fee is reasonable, that service is inexpensive, or that a customer will receive a discount makes it more difficult for a dentist to inform customers that he charges a lower price. If the customer does not know about a lower price, he will find it more difficult to buy lower price service. That fact, in turn, makes it less likely that a dentist will obtain more customers by offering lower prices. And that likelihood means that dentists will prove less likely to offer lower prices. But why should I have to spell out the obvious? To restrain truthful advertising about lower prices is likely to restrict

152

Page 91: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

competition in respect to price–“the central nervous system of the economy.” Socony-Vacuum; cf., e.g., Bates (price advertising plays an “indispensable role in the allocation of resources in a free enterprise system”). The [FTC] thought this fact sufficient to hold (in the alternative) that the price advertising restrictions were unlawful per se. Cf. Socony-Vacuum (finding agreement among competitors to buy “spot-market oil” unlawful per se because of its tendency to restrict price competition). For present purposes, I need not decide whether the [FTC] was right in applying a per se rule. I need only assume a rule of reason applies, and note the serious anticompetitive tendencies of the price advertising restraints.

The restrictions on the advertising of service quality also have serious anticompetitive tendencies. This is not a case of “mere puffing,” as the FTC recognized. … [S]ome parents may … want to know that a particular dentist makes a point of “gentle care.” Others may want to know about 1-year dental work guarantees. To restrict that kind of service quality advertisement is to restrict competition over the quality of service itself, for, unless consumers know, they may not purchase, and dentists may not compete to supply that which will make little difference to the demand for their services. That, at any rate, is the theory of the Sherman Act. And it is rather late in the day for anyone to deny the significant anticompetitive tendencies of an agreement that restricts competition in any legitimate respect, let alone one that inhibits customers from learning about the quality of a dentist’s service.

Nor did the [FTC] rely solely on the unobjectionable proposition that a restriction on the ability of dentists to advertise on quality is likely to limit their incentive to compete on quality. Rather, the [FTC] pointed to record evidence affirmatively establishing that quality-based competition is important to dental consumers in California. Unsurprisingly, these consumers choose dental services based at least in part on “information about the type and quality of service.” Similarly, … the ALJ credited testimony to the effect that “advertising the comfort of services will ‘absolutely’ bring in more patients,” and, conversely, that restraining the ability to advertise based on quality would decrease the number of patients that a dentist could attract. Finally, the [FTC] looked to the testimony of dentists who themselves had suffered adverse effects on their business when forced by petitioner to discontinue advertising quality of care.

The FTC found that the price advertising restrictions amounted to a “naked attempt to eliminate price competition.” It found that the service quality advertising restrictions “deprive consumers of information they value and of healthy competition for their patronage.” It added that the “anticompetitive nature of these restrictions” was “plain.” The Court of Appeals agreed. I do not believe it possible to deny the anticompetitive tendencies I have mentioned.

C. We must also ask whether, despite their anticompetitive tendencies, these restrictions might be justified by other procompetitive tendencies or redeeming virtues. This is a closer question–at least in theory. [CDA] argues that the three relevant restrictions are inextricably tied to a legitimate … effort to restrict false or misleading advertising. [CDA], the argument goes, had to prevent … the kind of truthful, nondeceptive advertising that it banned in order effectively to stop dentists from making unverifiable claims about price or service quality, which claims would mislead the consumer.

153

Page 92: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The problem with this or any similar argument is an empirical one. Notwithstanding its theoretical plausibility, the record does not bear out such a claim. … [T]he Court of Appeals wrote, in respect to the price restrictions, that “the record provides no evidence that the rule has in fact led to increased disclosure and transparency of dental pricing.” With respect to quality advertising, the [FTC] stressed that [CDA] “offered no convincing argument, let alone evidence, that consumers of dental services have been, or are likely to be, harmed by the broad categories of advertising it restricts.” Nor did the Court of Appeals think that [CDA’s] unsubstantiated contention that “claims about quality are inherently unverifiable and therefore misleading” could “justify banning all quality claims without regard to whether they are, in fact, false or misleading.” … In the usual Sherman Act §1 case, the defendant bears the burden of establishing a procompetitive justification. See Professional Engineers. And the Court of Appeals was correct when it concluded that no such justification had been established here.

D. I shall assume that the [FTC] must prove one additional circumstance, namely, that the … restraints would likely have made a real difference in the marketplace. The [FTC] … found that [CDA] did possess enough market power to make a difference. In at least one region of California, the mid-Peninsula, its members accounted for more than 90% of the marketplace; on average they accounted for 75%. In addition, entry by new dentists into the market place is fairly difficult. Dental education is expensive … as is opening a new dentistry office (which costs $75,000-$100,000). And [CDA] members believe membership in the Association is important, valuable, and recognized as such by the public.

These facts, in the Court of Appeals’ view, were sufficient to show “enough market power to harm competition through [CDA’s] standard setting in the area of advertising.” And that conclusion is correct. Restrictions on advertising price discounts in Palo Alto may make a difference because potential patients may not respond readily to discount advertising by the handful (10%) of dentists who are not members of the Association. And that … means that the remaining 90% will prove less likely to engage in price competition. Facts such as these have previously led this Court to find market power–unless the defendant has overcome the showing with strong contrary evidence. See, e.g., Indiana Federation. I can find no reason for departing from that precedent here.

II. In the Court’s view, the legal analysis conducted by the Court of Appeals was insufficient, and the Court remands the case for a more thorough application of the rule of reason. But in what way did the Court of Appeals fail? I find the Court’s answers to this question unsatisfactory–when one divides the overall Sherman Act question into its traditional component parts and adheres to traditional judicial practice for allocating the burdens of persuasion in an antitrust case.

Did the Court of Appeals misconceive the anticompetitive tendencies of the restrictions? After all, the object of the rule of reason is to separate those restraints that “may suppress or even destroy competition” from those that “merely regulat[e] and perhaps thereby promot[e] competition.” Chicago Board of Trade. The majority says that the Association’s “advertising restrictions might plausibly be thought to have a net procompetitive effect, or possibly no effect at all on competition.” It adds that

154

Page 93: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

advertising restrictions arguably protecting patients from misleading or irrelevant advertising call for more than cursory treatment as obviously comparable to classic horizontal agreements to limit output or price competition.

And it criticizes the Court of Appeals for failing to recognize … that “the particular restrictions on professional advertising could have different effects from those ‘normally’ found in the commercial world, even to the point of promoting competition....”

The problem with these statements is that the Court of Appeals did consider the relevant differences. It rejected the legal “treatment” customarily applied “to classic horizontal agreements to limit output or price competition”–i.e., the FTC’s (alternative) per se approach. It did so because the Association’s “policies do not, on their face, ban truthful nondeceptive ads”; instead, they “have been enforced in a way that restricts truthful advertising.” It added that “[t]he value of restricting false advertising ... counsels some caution in attacking rules that purport to do so but merely sweep too broadly.”

Did the Court of Appeals misunderstand the nature of an anticompetitive effect? The Court says:

If quality advertising actually induces some patients to obtain more care than they would in its absence, then restricting such advertising would reduce the demand for dental services, not the supply; and ... the producers’ supply ... is normally relevant in determining whether a ... limitation has the anticompetitive effect of artificially raising prices.

But if the Court means this statement as an argument against the anticompetitive tendencies that flow from an agreement not to advertise service quality, I believe it is the majority, and not the Court of Appeals, that is mistaken. An agreement not to advertise, say, “gentle care” is anticompetitive because it imposes an artificial barrier against each dentist’s independent decision to advertise gentle care. That barrier, in turn, tends to inhibit those dentists who want to supply gentle care from getting together with those customers who want to buy gentle care. There is adequate reason to believe that tendency present in this case.

Did the Court of Appeals inadequately consider possible procompetitive justifications? … The basic question is whether … some … theoretically redeeming virtue in fact offsets the restrictions’ anticompetitive effects in this case. … The [FTC] found that the defendant did not make the necessary showing that a redeeming virtue existed in practice. The Court of Appeals, asking whether the rules, as enforced, “augment[ed] competition and increase[d] market efficiency,” found the [FTC’s] conclusion supported by substantial evidence. That is why the court said that “the record provides no evidence that the rule has in fact led to increased disclosure and transparency of dental pricing”–which is to say that the record provides no evidence that the effects, though anticompetitive, are nonetheless redeemed or justified.

The majority correctly points out that “petitioner alone would have had the incentive to introduce such evidence” of procompetitive justification. Indeed, that is one of the reasons defendants normally bear the burden of persuasion about redeeming virtues. But despite this incentive, petitioner’s brief in this Court offers nothing concrete to counter the Commission’s conclusion that the record does not support the claim of justification. Petitioner’s failure to produce such evidence itself “explain[s] why [the

155

Page 94: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

lower court] gave no weight to the ... suggestion that restricting difficult-to-verify claims about quality or patient comfort would have a procompetitive effect by preventing misleading or false claims that distort the market.”

With respect to … advertising across-the-board discounts, … [t]he FTC found that the disclosure rules did bar [them] and that finding is supported by substantial evidence. … I accept as literally true the conclusion that the Court says follows from that [finding], namely, that “net anticompetitive effects” do not “obviously” follow from [it]. But obviousness is not the point. With respect to any of the three restraints found by the Commission, whether “net anticompetitive effects” follow is a matter of how the Commission, and, here, the Court of Appeals, have answered the questions I laid out at the beginning. Has the Commission shown that the restriction has anticompetitive tendencies? It has. Has the Association nonetheless shown offsetting virtues? It has not. Has the Commission shown market power sufficient for it to believe that the restrictions will likely make a real world difference? It has.

The upshot, in my view, is that the Court of Appeals, applying ordinary antitrust principles, reached an unexceptional conclusion. It is the same legal conclusion that this Court itself reached in Indiana Federation–a much closer case than this one. There the Court found that an agreement by dentists not to submit dental X rays to insurers violated the rule of reason. The anticompetitive tendency of that agreement was to reduce competition among dentists in respect to their willingness to submit X rays to insurers–a matter in respect to which consumers are relatively indifferent, as compared to advertising of price discounts and service quality, the matters at issue here. The redeeming virtue in Indiana Federation was the alleged undesirability of having insurers consider a range of matters when deciding whether treatment was justified–a virtue no less plausible, and no less proved, than the virtue offered here. The “power” of the dentists to enforce their agreement was no greater than that at issue here (control of 75% to 90% of the relevant markets). It is difficult to see how the two cases can be reconciled.

I would note that the form of analysis I have followed is not rigid; it admits of some variation according to the circumstances. The important point, however, is that its allocation of the burdens of persuasion reflects a gradual evolution within the courts over a period of many years. That evolution represents an effort carefully to blend the procompetitive objectives of the law of antitrust with administrative necessity. It represents a considerable advance, both from the days when the Commission had to present and/or refute every possible fact and theory, and from antitrust theories so abbreviated as to prevent proper analysis. … I hope that this case does not represent an abandonment of that basic, and important, form of analysis. …

$ $ $ $ $ $ $TEXACO INC. v. DAGHER

126 S.Ct. 1276 (2006)

JUSTICE THOMAS delivered the opinion of the Court. … [P]etitioners Texaco Inc. and Shell Oil Co. collaborated in a joint venture, Equilon Enterprises, to refine and sell gasoline in the western United States under the original Texaco and Shell Oil brand names. Respondents, a class of Texaco and Shell Oil service station owners, allege that

156

Page 95: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

petitioners engaged in unlawful price fixing when Equilon set a single price for both Texaco and Shell Oil brand gasoline. We granted certiorari to determine whether it is per se illegal under §1 of the Sherman Act, 15 U. S. C. §1, for a lawful, economically integrated joint venture to set the prices at which the joint venture sells its products. We conclude that it is not, and accordingly we reverse the contrary judgment of the Court of Appeals.

I. Historically, Texaco and Shell Oil have competed with one another in the national and international oil and gasoline markets. Their business activities include refining crude oil into gasoline, as well as marketing gasoline to downstream purchasers, such as the service stations represented in respondents’ class action.

…Texaco and Shell Oil formed a joint venture, Equilon, to consolidate their operations in the western United States, thereby ending competition between the two companies in the domestic refining and marketing of gasoline. Under the joint venture agreement, Texaco and Shell Oil agreed to pool their resources and share the risks of and profits from Equilon’s activities. Equilon’s board of directors would comprise representatives of Texaco and Shell Oil, and Equilon gasoline would be sold to downstream purchasers under the original Texaco and Shell Oil brand names. The formation of Equilon was approved by consent decree, subject to certain divestments and other modifications, by the Federal Trade Commission, as well as by the state attorneys general of California, Hawaii, Oregon, and Washington. Notably, the decrees imposed no restrictions on the pricing of Equilon gasoline.

After the joint venture began to operate, respondents brought suit in district court, alleging that, by unifying gasoline prices under the two brands, petitioners had violated the per se rule against price fixing that this Court has long recognized under §1 of the Sherman Act. The District Court awarded summary judgment to Texaco and Shell Oil. It determined that the rule of reason, rather than a per se rule or the quick look doctrine, governs respondents’ claim, and that, by eschewing rule of reason analysis, respondents had failed to raise a triable issue of fact. The Ninth Circuit reversed, characterizing petitioners’ position as a request for an “exception to the per se prohibition on price fixing,” and rejecting that request. We … granted certiorari to determine the extent to which the per se rule against price fixing applies to an important and increasingly popular form of business organization, the joint venture..

II. Section 1 of the Sherman Act prohibits “[e]very contract, combination in the form of trust or otherwise, or conspiracy, in restraint of trade or commerce among the several States.” This Court has not taken a literal approach to this language, however. See, e.g., State Oil Co. v. Khan (“[T]his Court has long recognized that Congress intended to outlaw only unreasonable restraints” (emphasis added)). Instead, this Court presumptively applies rule of reason analysis, under which antitrust plaintiffs must demonstrate that a particular contract or combination is in fact unreasonable and anticompetitive before it will be found unlawful. See, e.g., id. (concluding that vertical price-fixing arrangements are subject to the rule of reason, not per se liability). Per se liability is reserved for only those agreements that are “so plainly anticompetitive that no elaborate study of the industry is needed to establish their illegality.” Professional Engineers. Accordingly, “we have expressed reluctance to adopt per se rules ... ‘where

157

Page 96: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

the economic impact of certain practices is not immediately obvious.’” Khan (quoting Indiana Federation of Dentists).

Price-fixing agreements between two or more competitors, otherwise known as horizontal price-fixing agreements, fall into the category of arrangements that are per se unlawful. These cases do not present such an agreement, however, because Texaco and Shell Oil did not compete with one another in the relevant market—namely, the sale of gasoline to service stations in the western United States—but instead participated in that market jointly through their investments in Equilon.1

In other words, the pricing policy challenged here amounts to little more than price setting by a single entity—albeit within the context of a joint venture—and not a pricing agreement between competing entities with respect to their competing products. Throughout Equilon’s existence, Texaco and Shell Oil shared in the profits of Equilon’s activities in their role as investors, not competitors. When “persons who would otherwise be competitors pool their capital and share the risks of loss as well as the opportunities for profit ... such joint ventures [are] regarded as a single firm competing with other sellers in the market.” Maricopa County Medical Soc. As such, though Equilon’s pricing policy may be price fixing in a literal sense, it is not price fixing in the antitrust sense. See BMI (“When two partners set the price of their goods or services they are literally ‘price fixing,’ but they are not per se in violation of the Sherman Act”).

This conclusion is confirmed by respondents’ apparent concession that there would be no per se liability had Equilon simply chosen to sell its gasoline under a single brand. We see no reason to treat Equilon differently just because it chose to sell gasoline under two distinct brands at a single price. As a single entity, a joint venture, like any other firm, must have the discretion to determine the prices of the products that it sells, including the discretion to sell a product under two different brands at a single, unified price. If Equilon’s price unification policy is anticompetitive, then respondents should have challenged it pursuant to the rule of reason.2 But it would be inconsistent with this Court’s antitrust precedents to condemn the internal pricing decisions of a legitimate joint venture as per se unlawful.3

1 We presume for purposes of these cases that Equilon is a lawful joint venture. Its formation has been approved by federal and state regulators, and there is no contention here that it is a sham. As the court below noted: “There is a voluminous record documenting the economic justifications for creating the joint ventures. [T]he defendants concluded that numerous synergies and cost efficiencies would result” by creating Equilon as well as a parallel venture, Motiva Enterprises, in the eastern United States, and “that nationwide there would be up to $800 million in cost savings annually.” Had respondents challenged Equilon itself, they would have been required to show that its creation was anticompetitive under the rule of reason. 2 Respondents have not put forth a rule of reason claim. Accordingly, we need not address petitioners’ alternative argument that §1 of the Sherman Act is inapplicable to joint ventures. 3 Respondents alternatively contend that petitioners should be held liable under the quick look doctrine. To be sure, we have applied the quick look doctrine to business activities that are so plainly anticompetitive that courts need undertake only a cursory examination before imposing antitrust liability. See California Dental Assn. But for the same reasons that per se liability is unwarranted here, we conclude that petitioners cannot be held liable under the quick look doctrine.

158

Page 97: UNIT II: HORIZONTAL RESTRAINTSfaculty.law.miami.edu/mfajer/documents/matu2.doc · Web viewI do not join Part II because I would not, at least for the moment, reach as far as the Court

The court below reached the opposite conclusion by invoking the ancillary restraints doctrine. That doctrine governs the validity of restrictions imposed by a legitimate business collaboration, such as a business association or joint venture, on nonventure activities. See, e.g., NCAA; Citizen Publishing. Under the doctrine, courts must determine whether the nonventure restriction is a naked restraint on trade, and thus invalid, or one that is ancillary to the legitimate and competitive purposes of the business association, and thus valid. We agree with petitioners that the ancillary restraints doctrine has no application here, where the business practice being challenged involves the core activity of the joint venture itself—namely, the pricing of the very goods produced and sold by Equilon. And even if we were to invoke the doctrine in these cases, Equilon’s pricing policy is clearly ancillary to the sale of its own products. Judge Fernandez, dissenting from the ruling of the court below, put it well:

In this case, nothing more radical is afoot than the fact that an entity, which now owns all of the production, transportation, research, storage, sales and distribution facilities for engaging in the gasoline business, also prices its own products. It decided to price them the same, as any other entity could. What could be more integral to the running of a business than setting a price for its goods and services?

See also BMI (“Joint ventures and other cooperative arrangements are . . . not usually unlawful, at least not as price-fixing schemes, where the agreement on price is necessary to market the product at all”).

Because the pricing decisions of a legitimate joint venture do not fall within the narrow category of activity that is per se unlawful under §1 of the Sherman Act, respondents’ antitrust claim cannot prevail. Accordingly, the judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed.

$ $ $ $ $ $ $

159