17
DANIEL NOLAN THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM (Received 18 July 1995) “Modal Fictionalism” is a theory of modality that is gaining popu- larity in some quarters, but, at least in the form in which it is often presented, it faces at least three important difficulties in addition to the difficulties that have been already raised in the literature by Rosen (1990, 1993), Brock (1993) and others (e.g., Lycan (1993). These three problems, I will argue, each constitute a reason for abandoning at least one version of modal fictionalism as unworkable. Not all versions: for I will be distinguishing three main varieties of modal fictionalism, and I will only be arguing that the three prob- lems I raise are problems for one of the types of theory which employ the notion of fiction to explain some of our talk about modality, and particularly our talk about possible worlds. I will leave open the question of whether and to what extent these problems undermine the other two types of modal fictionalism, though as a matter of fact I suspect that the other varieties can avoid the problem fairly easily. However, even though I am only attacking only one specific variety of modal fictionalism, I do not take myself to be attacking a straw dummy either: while I will explain that there are genuine modal fictionalist alternatives to the type of theory I am attacking, I take it that the two most prominent modal fictionalisms that have appeared in the literature are versions of the type of modal fictionalism I will be attacking. These two theories are the modal fictionalism presented in Gideon Rosen’s paper named, not surprisingly, “Modal Fiction- alism” (Rosen 1990) and the modal fictionalist approach which was taken in D. M. Armstrong’s A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility (Armstrong 1989) It is not clear to me that either of these authors still holds the sort of modal fictionalist position they once argued for (or that Rosen ever held a modal fictionalist position, as opposed to his having merely suggested it). But a theory does not really need Philosophical Studies 87: 259–275, 1997. c 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

DANIEL NOLAN

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODALFICTIONALISM

(Received 18 July 1995)

“Modal Fictionalism” is a theory of modality that is gaining popu-larity in some quarters, but, at least in the form in which it is oftenpresented, it faces at least three important difficulties in addition tothe difficulties that have been already raised in the literature by Rosen(1990, 1993), Brock (1993) and others (e.g., Lycan (1993). Thesethree problems, I will argue, each constitute a reason for abandoningat least one version of modal fictionalism as unworkable.

Not all versions: for I will be distinguishing three main varietiesof modal fictionalism, and I will only be arguing that the three prob-lems I raise are problems for one of the types of theory which employthe notion of fiction to explain some of our talk about modality, andparticularly our talk about possible worlds. I will leave open thequestion of whether and to what extent these problems underminethe other two types of modal fictionalism, though as a matter of factI suspect that the other varieties can avoid the problem fairly easily.However, even though I am only attacking only one specific varietyof modal fictionalism, I do not take myself to be attacking a strawdummy either: while I will explain that there are genuine modalfictionalist alternatives to the type of theory I am attacking, I take itthat the two most prominent modal fictionalisms that have appearedin the literature are versions of the type of modal fictionalism I willbe attacking. These two theories are the modal fictionalism presentedin Gideon Rosen’s paper named, not surprisingly, “Modal Fiction-alism” (Rosen 1990) and the modal fictionalist approach which wastaken in D. M. Armstrong’s A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility(Armstrong 1989) It is not clear to me that either of these authorsstill holds the sort of modal fictionalist position they once argued for(or that Rosen ever held a modal fictionalist position, as opposed tohis having merely suggested it). But a theory does not really need

Philosophical Studies 87: 259–275, 1997.c 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

VICTORY: PIPS No.: 101378 HUMSKAPphil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.1

Page 2: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

260 DANIEL NOLAN

current defenders for it to be worth discussing, and I suspect that ifmodal fictionalism of the type I wish to object to is not dealt with,philosophers supporting it will reappear soon enough. The first thingI will need to do in this paper though, before I begin discussion theproblems, is explain what I am talking about – that is, what modalfictionalism is, the different kinds there are, and more specificallythe nature of the version of modal fictionalism that faces the threeproblems mentioned in the title.

The essence of modal factionalism is the claim that possibleworlds do not literally exist (that is, there are no non-actual statesof affairs, or no non-actual situations), but that when we engage intalk about possible worlds we are making claims which are literallyfalse (at least when we discuss non-actual worlds) but which aretrue according to a story we tell, and that this story is useful forour treatment of modality. This “truth in a story” is to be under-stood in the same way as we understand claims like “According tothe Lord of the Rings, it is true that there are many orcs in MiddleEarth”, or “According to the Monadology by Leibniz, it is true thatthere are many monads”. Of course, Leibniz himself did not take theMonadology to be merely a story – he took it to be a sober presenta-tion of the truth. Nevertheless, I take it, his views about the existenceof Monads were literally false. Analogously, modal fictionalists donot claim that possible world talk is always intended to be merelya story by those who use it – that would be absurd. The claim israther that in fact (nearly all) possible world talk is literally false,but also that some claims about possible worlds are true accordingthe possible-worlds story, and some are not. A simple claim aboutpossible worlds that would count as being part of the possible worldsstory, and is true according to the story is:

“There is a possible world where swans are blue”,

and a sample claim about possible worlds that is not true accordingto the story is:

“There is a possible world where there is a round squarecupola on Berkeley college”.

These are both fairly hackneyed examples, of course, but they doserve to illustrate the sorts of claims which are in the story and the

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.2

Page 3: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 261

sort that are not. Exactly where the boundary is, and why it is thererather than anywhere else, is an interesting question, but it is one thatwill be answered differently according to different modal fictions.

The general picture offered by modal fictionalism looks quiteattractive. If we are not going to be modal realists (that is, say thatevery possible world really exists in just the same way that thisone does), and we think that objects like sets of sentences or sets ofpropositions or bits of our heads or weird abstract selection-functionsare just are not the sorts of things that can do the work of possibleworlds – in other words, if we also reject so-called “Ersatzism”about possible worlds – then we probably want to say that possibleworlds (other than the actual one) do not exist. And given that weare tempted to say that, Fictionalism about these possible worlds isthe only obvious alternative that does not have a Meinongian tinge.Now none of that was meant to be an argument against Realism,Ersatzism or even Meinongianism, but given that as a matter of factmany philosophers find these options unattractive, one can see whythey would want to embrace fictionalism about possible worlds.

Suppose then we are to embrace fictionalism about possibleworlds. The question would arise as to what implications this wouldhave for our theory of modal claims. After all, if we decide that theclaim “There is a possible world where swans are blue” is literallyfalse, what are we to make of the claim “Possibly, swans are blue”?After all, didn’t we take in with our modal mother’s milk the bicon-ditional.

“There is a possible world where swans are blue iffPossibly, swans are blue.”?

Does fictionalism about possible worlds mean that we have to denythat there could have been blue swans? It is on the issue of the connec-tion between possible worlds talk and the truth of modal claims thatI wish to distinguish my three versions of modal fictionalism.

1. THREE VARIETIES OF MODAL FACTIONALISM: BROAD, TIMIDAND STRONG

The first modal factionalism I will consider recommends a fictionalapproach not only to possible worlds, but to modality as well. Since it

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.3

Page 4: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

262 DANIEL NOLAN

is fictionalist about both, I will dub this version “broad modal fiction-alism”. This sort of position would be very similar to an eliminativistposition on modality. For instance, suppose that you thought thatthere just was nothing in objective reality that corresponded to anynecessities or non-actual possibilities. Nevertheless, you might stillthink that talk what was possible or necessary was a useful device,or shorthand for dealing with, for example, causation or deductivereasoning. The fiction of possible worlds would then be seen as ahandy extension of the basic fiction of modality: not only wouldone sometimes ascribe the merely fictional properties of “necessity”or “possibility” to statements, or “essentiality” or “accidentality” toproperties, one could also use talk of non-existent worlds as a deviceto help manipulate these necessities and possibilities. The bicondi-tional could remain perfectly intact as a handy translation procedurefrom one fiction to another.

It is clear that the above position has a claim to be called “modalfictionalism”, for it is the most full-blooded variety of fictionalismabout things modal. I do not happen to be in sympathy with it: in fact,I am pretty sceptical about most attempts to be instrumentalist abouteveryday areas of discourse in this way. However, it is one of thevarieties of modal fictionalism that I will not address in this paper.To rebut this position would be to mount a defence of the basic claimthat there is an objective truth which our modal discourse attemptsto track – a task which is, while vital, beyond the scope of this paper.

The other two varieties of modal fictionalism have in common theclaim that normal modal statements are objectively true or false, andfurthermore that some statements about the possibility of the non-actual or statements about things being necessary are in fact true,and not just true according to a fiction. Where they differ is withrespect to the question of priority: are the statements about the factsof modality somehow true in virtue of the truth of the statementsabout possible worlds, or is it the other way around?

The thesis that the statements about possible worlds (or to bemore precise, how possible worlds are described in the fiction) relyon the facts of modality, rather than the other way around, is calledby Gideon Rosen a “timid fictionalism” (Rosen 1990), p. 354). Themain version of fictionalism proposed in his “Modal Fictionalism”is not this timid fictionalism, but he does not rule out the “timid

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.4

Page 5: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 263

fictionalist” strategy either. Another expression of this “timid fiction-alism” is the modal fictionalism of Hartry Field. In the introductionto Realism, Mathematics and Modality, he explicitly says “in myview,d possible worlds are just fictions” (Field 1989, p. 41). How-ever, he also takes “logical possibility” as a primitive, and says thathe “must accept” that this logical possibility is “not something thatmust be explained in terms of entities : : : e.g. : : : possible worlds”(Field, 1989, p. 86). When it comes to logical possibility at least,then, it appears Field is only a timid fictionalist.

I have some sympathy for this so-called timid fictionalism – andfurthermore, I believe that a timid fictionalism can be made outwhich avoids all the problems I will discuss in this paper, and further-more can deal with the other problems raised for fictionalism in theliterature. The problems I will discuss for modal fictionalism are notmeant to be problems for timid modal fictionalism. This leaves uswith the other variety of modal fictionalism which takes the truthof modal claims to be derived from claims about possible worlds.This sort of Fictionalism, which Rosen calls a stronger reading ofmodal fictionalism (Rosen 1990, p. 354), aspires to be a deflationisttheory about modal claims, one which reduces modal claims intonon-modal claims (in this case truth in fiction) – or, given that truthaccording to the fiction might still be some sort of modal notion,at least reduce many modal notions into one. It aspires to be an“analysis of modal language” (Rosen 1990, p. 348) itself, and not atheory merely about our possible-worlds talk.

Rosen employs this stronger understanding for the bulk ofhis “Modal Fictionalism” paper (Rosen 1990). Finally, the viewexpressed in Armstrong’s A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility(Armstrong 1989) was a variety of this strong fictionalism. Thestrategy was as follows:

We set up non-existent “merely possible worlds” alongside the actual world, usingcertain principles. : : : “It is possible that p” is then said to be true if and only if aworld can be found in which p is true. (Armstrong 1989, p. 51)

However, this dependence does not mean that the truth of claimsabout the merely possible is merely fictional truth: these claims arestill literally true on Armstrong’s account (Armstrong 1989, p. 50).So this third approach to modal fictionalism, which I have dubbed“strong modal fictionalism” is the approach taken by two of the

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.5

Page 6: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

264 DANIEL NOLAN

philosophers most concerned to argue for a fictionalist approach tomodality. However, as I said earlier, I think that this “strong” versionof modal fictionalism faces at least three major problems. The firstone concerns the artificality which apparently infects modality on astrong modal fictionalist understanding, while the second two focuson ontological inadequacies which strong modal fictionalism faces.

2. THE FIRST PROBLEM: ARTIFICIALITY

The “artificiality” worry is that strong modal fictionalism seems tomake modality too artificial. Of course, modal fictionalists want tohold that not just any old fiction that talks about possible worlds isthe fiction to be used in assessing claims about what is possible. BothRosen and Armstrong wish to have constrained fictionalisms, andwish to ground these constraints in something actual: Armstrongin basic combinatorial principles plus truths about universals andstate of affairs which actually exist, Rosen in basic world-principleswhich in turn, he suggests (Rosen 1990, p. 353), might be justified byappeal to facts about our imaginative practices. In addition, Rosenwishes to include as part of the story of worlds an “encyclopedia”of all truths about the actual world, which is needed, along with thebasic principles, to provide a complete fiction of possible worlds(Rosen 1990, p. 335).1

But there is still a sense in which the theory makes modalityartificial. As we know, fictions, theories etc. are artificial: we makethem up, and they do not exist before we make them up.2 Leibniz,for example, actually created the Monadology: he did not discoverit in the way that, for example, an explorer might be said to dis-cover a new island. Similarly, it is not the case that Conan Doylefound out about Sherlock Holmes by remembering a shadow of theForm of the Detective Story of some such: before Doyle, there wereno Sherlock Holmes stories, and after him there were. The ModalFiction is a fiction like the others – if people had not thought of orconsidered possible worlds, it would not have existed. So it seemsthat if people like Leibniz, Saul Kripke and David Lewis had notexisted, and nobody else thought up a theory of possible worldseither, then absolutely nothing would have been possible. In sucha world, when Aristotle muses about a sea battle, his musings are

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.6

Page 7: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 265

completely pointless: it would not have been possible either thatthere be a sea battle tomorrow or that there would fail to be one– and it would not have been necessary that either there was a seabattle or there was not. However important one thinks philosophersmight be, one should not think that philosophers are that important.This mind-dependence of possibility should be especially worryingto those who think that causal laws entail counterfactuals, and thatcounterfactuals involve claims of possibility and necessity – for thencausation becomes something that is only in the world because somepeople told some stories about possible worlds.3

There is one reply that might be attempted to this artificialityobjection, but it faces troubles as great as the one it is meant tosolve. This reply consists of admitting that the fiction is artificial butclaiming that this does not face the above problems if one adopts a“rigidifying strategy”. The traditional fictionalist translation schemefor modal claims was of the form “Possibly P iff according to theModal Fiction, P is true at some world”. The fictionalist followingthe rigidifying strategy will claim that the second half of this bicon-ditional is to be read rigidly, so the biconditional, when spelled outmore explicitly, should read “Possibly P iff actually according tothe Modal Fiction, P is true at some world”. Since the fiction cameto be in the actual world, the truths of modality are actually true.And since the fiction states that there are an infinite number of mind-independent worlds, the fact that in some of these worlds life does notarise, or the world ends upon Aristotle’s death, does not imply thatin those worlds nothing is possible or necessary – on the contrary,the way fictions like Rosen’s and Armstrong’s actually function, justas much (or almost as much) is possible in those worlds as is at ours.This is because while the fiction does not exist at such worlds, itexists in the actual world, and it is its existence at the actual worldfrom which modal truths are derived. So the counterfactuals like “Ifpeople had not come up with this fiction, nothing would have beenpossible” are not in fact true, and in fact are necessarily false. Thefictionalist who responds in this matter may think that the reasonwhy we are worried about artificiality is because the counterfactualslike the ones I have mentioned seem counterintuitive. Once it isrealised that these counterfactuals are not true, artificiality shouldnot be something to worry about.

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.7

Page 8: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

266 DANIEL NOLAN

So says the strong fictionalist following the rigidifying strategy.However, this merely makes it a little harder for us to express ourworry about the dependence of modality on the fiction. Harder, butnot impossible. Davies and Humberstone, in their (1980), amongothers, have argued that it makes good non-trivial sense to evaluateconditionals about what follows if the actual world were different.It is still “deeply contingent”, to use Gareth Evans’ phrase (coinedin Evans 1979), that anything is actually true according to the ModalFiction, and we can still object that modality is artificial in a worry-ing way according to strong modal fictionalism: this is becauseif there had actually been no Modal Fiction, no statement aboutcontents of worlds would have been true according to it. All theobjectionable conditionals can be re-raised as conditionals aboutwhat modality would be like if the world had actually been differ-ent. This of course relies on having a theory that does not takesuch “actually-conditions” to have trivial truth-evaluations, such asa theory employing two-dimensional modal logic for example, anda modal fictionalist might argue that such approaches are fundamen-tally flawed on other grounds. If a fictionalist is prepared to claimthat all counterfactuals with statements about how things actuallyare as their antecedents are to receive trivial truth-evaluations, thenthis response to the rigidifying strategy will have no bite. Then theworry about the rigidifying response would be the question of howthe fictionalist is to justify their claim that their theory is an explana-tion of modality, since if the fiction were to be different (or actuallydifferent) modality would be the same, and in no non-trivial counter-factual sense does modality objectively depend on the fiction. Oncewe go past the basic material biconditional to attempt an explanationof why the bioconditional holds, the rigidifying fictionalist will, Isuspect, face great difficulties.

3. THE SECOND PROBLEM: THE INCOMPLETENESS OF THE MORALFICTION4

The first of the two ontological worries is similar to an objectionLewis has brought against sparse linguistic Ersatzism (Lewis 1986),pp. 142–165). The point comes when we consider what it is forsomething to be “true according to the fiction”. Maybe this is a

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.8

Page 9: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 267

primitive, and I am happy to grant for purposes of this paper thatthe Fictionalist is entitled to treat truth according to a fiction as aprimitive notion. However, “primitive” does not mean the same as“totally mysterious”. At least a little can be said even about primitivenotions.

One thing that seems clear is that a sentence, or proposition, orwhatever is true according to a fiction if (but not necessarily onlyif) that sentence or proposition is part of the fiction, in the sensethat it is one of the assertions of the fiction. I will call the thingstrue in a fiction in virtue of their being one of the assertions whichmake up the fiction the explicit content of the fiction. (This usage isdifferent from the way the term “explicit content” is used normally indiscussion of fiction (e.g. in Lewis (1978, p. 41)) but is rather similarto Lewis’ notion of “explicit representation” which he employs inOn The Plurality of Worlds in his discussion of ersatz theories (seeLewis (1986, pp. 150–151)).

Now, it is clear that merely the explicit content of the candidatefictions will not be sufficient. If anything like the range of modalclaims which we take to be true are actually true, we will requirethe content of the fiction to be at least infinite. There are an infinitenumber of possibilities, and for a modal fictionalist this means thatthere an infinite number of statements which are true according tothe fiction. Now, take a look at the fictions actually put forward ascandidates for being the Modal fictions. Rosen suggests a modifiedversion of Lewis’s On the Plurality of Worlds (in Rosen 1990), andArmstrong in his (1989, p. 50) claims that there is a “great fiction”which says that there are many other fictions that each describe apossible world. This “great fiction” can be identified with what hesays about the arrangement of possible worlds in A CombinatorialTheory of Possibility. The other fictions supposedly described bythe great fiction need not concern us as much, since according toArmstrong they do not exist, but are themselves only fictional enti-ties. Both On the Plurality of Worlds and the fictional utterances in ACombinatorial Theory of Possibility are fictions that can be read in aday, and neither’s explicit content is detailed enough to support thepossibility claims we want to make. Furthermore, no fiction whichhumans could ever produce could have enough explicit content tosupport all the modal claims which we suppose to be true – annoy-

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.9

Page 10: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

268 DANIEL NOLAN

ing things like finite matter and energy will get in the way of such aproject.

So there is not enough of the Modal fiction for it to explicitly makeall the assertions we need. What we do have in these modal fictions,however, are a lot of universally quantified sentences (such as thosefound in principles of combination or other statements which apply to“all worlds”). “Aha”, the fictionalist can say, “these sentences implyall the content we need”. This is the sort of thing we can usually sayabout fictions – there is probably no sentence in Tolkien’s writingswhich states “Merry was a hobbit and Shelob was a spider”, butthis conjunction is implied by his fiction, as it says in one place thatMerry was a hobbit, and in another that Shelob was a spider (in fact,these claims may in turn have only been implied, as it is unlikelythat this information was conveyed in such a bald fashion). Here ishow finite works can have true according to them an infinite numberof propositions – they can imply them all!

This is not really open to the strong modal fictionalist, how-ever – implication, a modal notion (some might argue the modalnotion), is meant to be explained in terms of what is true in the storyabout possible worlds, not the other way around. If we are going toembrace implication as something relatively more fundamental thanthe Modal Fiction, or “relatively primitive” as compared with it (ifrelative primitiveness makes sense), then why not just be a timidfictionalist, especially since it looks like other modal notions aredefinable in terms of implication (e.g. P is possible iff it is not thecase that P implies not-P)? If, on the other hand, the modal fiction-alist cannot appeal to the implications of the fiction, it seems thatthe content must be explicit – in which case the fictions offered arewoefully inadequate. To state the problem succinctly: the fictionsdo not contain sufficient explicit content to perform the functionrequired by strong modal fictionalism and the theory cannot rely onany implicit content they might be supposed to have.5 In Rosen’scase the worlds are not described in enough explicit detail, and inArmstrong’s case it is the descriptions of the worlds which are notdescribed in enough explicit detail.

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.10

Page 11: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 269

4. THE THIRD PROBLEM: PROPOSITIONS

The third problem for the Modal Fiction is also an ontological worryof a different sort. It arises when we come to consider what proposi-tions are: in other words, what are the things that are true in the fictionsupposed to be? It seems that at least two strong modal fictionalistpositions come to grief when faced with this question: Rosen’s andArmstrong’s. As always, there are repairs that might be suggested,but once again, these come with a price in terms of plausibility forthe fictionalist theory.

The modal fictionalism in Gideon Rosen’s “Modal Fictionalism”is the one most obviously in trouble. The strategy there is to takeadvantage of the benefits of David Lewis’ theory of possible worlds,while avoiding paying the ontological cost, by being fictionalistrather than realist (Rosen 1990, p. 330; 1993, p. 73). Now, one of thebenefits of Lewis’ system is that he gives us an account of propo-sitions: propositions, for Lewis, are sets of possible worlds. Sincepossible worlds do not literally exist for the fictionalist, propositions(being sets of possible worlds) will not exist either – either that, oreach will be either the null set or the unit-set of the actual world,which does not nearly individuate them adequately. If the Fictionalistis left without propositions, there is nothing to be true according tothe fiction, and thus there will be no modal truths – a clearly unac-ceptable conclusion for the Rosen-style strong fictionalist.

Of course, these propositions may well exist according to thefiction, but to try to use this to get around the problem leads to avicious regress. Because then it is not true simpliciter that a proposi-tion P is true according to the fiction, but only that “according to thefiction, P (exists and) is true” is true according to the fiction. Andeven that will not be true simpliciter, for the proposition “accordingto the fiction, P exists and is true” does not actually exist, but onlyexists according to the fiction, so all we can say is that “accordingto the fiction, the proposition “‘P exists and is true according to thefiction” is true according to the fiction”’ is true according to thefiction. And we cannot stop here either – we must again qualify it.The problem is that we never arrive at a true statement: only state-ments which must be further qualified. This means that there is noacceptable paraphrase or expansion of “P is true according to thefiction” which is actually true – so we will come to the conclusion

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.11

Page 12: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

270 DANIEL NOLAN

that nothing is true according to the fiction. That the propositionssupposedly exist according to the fiction is not something that willsave the fictionalist who wants to embrace the Lewis story as theirfiction.

Armstrong, too, will have problem when it comes to the ques-tion of what the propositions involved with the Modal Fiction are.Perhaps “propositions” is not quite the right word for the thingswhich make up the fiction according to Armstrong, as Armstrongrejects ontological commitment to propositions (see Armstrong(1973, p. 46)). Let us call the things which appear in fictions “asser-tions” instead, as these are a species of entity Armstrong does allowinto his ontology. An account of fictions as sets or collections orother organisations of assertions will cause the following difficultyfor Armstrong: Armstrong admits, as anyone who is not anti-realistin the broad sense about modality, that there are possible states ofaffairs that have never been mentioned or described in throught or inspeech and in all probability never will be. Call one of these US (forunmentioned state of affairs). Yet for this to be so, then there mustbe a proposition which is true in the fiction to the effect that thereis a little fiction which contains US. Now, no actual assertions existwhich assert that US holds, so there is nothing actual to be the partof the fiction which asserts US. On the not unreasonable assump-tion that if US has never been mentioned, neither has any assertionwhich means “there is a little fiction that has true according to it US”been uttered, it follows that there is no assertion of the appropriatesort corresponding to the possibility of US: so it seems that US isnot possible after all. And again, an appeal to the fictional existenceof mentions of US will not help, for the same reason that appealto fictional possible worlds as the members of propositions did nothelp the Rosen-style fictionalist. The problem for both Rosen andArmstrong is that some propositions (or assertions) which they needto be true in their fictions in order for various states of affairs to bepossible do not even exist, and so cannot be true according to theirmodal fictions.

This net can be cast even wider still: any account of propositionswhich unavoidably involves modal notions, for instance, ones thatmake reference to non-actual acts of meaning something, or classesof inscriptions or utterances that include mere possibilia, or talk of

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.12

Page 13: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 271

“ideal” languages or descriptions of the world, where this ideality iscast as some sort of modal notion, and so on, will be incompatiblewith strong fictionalism.

This objection is not meant to be a decisive one: it only works ifthe modal fictionalist is guilty of smuggling something like modal-ity into his or her account of propositions. However, it seems clearthat we cannot just restrict ourselves to propositions correspondingto statements which have actually been made (or, more generously,which will be made at some time). For there are likely to be very fewstatements of the form “According to the Modal Fiction, P is true atsome possible world” – and at the price of seriously restricting thepossible (or being anti-realistic about possibility in the way I consid-ered above), we want our theory to say that possibly P is true evenwhen no-one can be bothered to utter the relevant statement aboutthe fiction, or fictively utter the relevant statement in the context ofthe fiction. What one can do to avoid this objection, of course,f issay that all possible propositions, both expressed and unexpressed,are actual. This Platonism about propositions will likely take propo-sitions to be abstract objects of some sort: maybe sets of some spe-cial sort, maybe “meaning stuff” in Plato’s heaven – who knows?I fully admit that this sort of theory of propositions avoids theobjection.

In fact, if one is to be Platonist about propositions, one can avoidall the problems raised in this paper. The Modal Fiction, if it is acollection of propositions or some set or ordered set of propositions,will not then be artificial – no matter what humans do, or evenif we do not exist at all, still the contents of Platonic heaven willexist. The artificiality objection would then have to be recast: theartificiality objection might be that it is somehow up to us whichof the innumerable fictions about pluralities of worlds comes to bethe fiction that is connected in the appropriate ways to our modalclaims. But this objection would not be nearly as strong, as it is opento the fictionalist to claim that it is an objective matter which fictionpropositions about possibility and necessity are about (or are madetrue or false by), and that this is not the sort of thing that is affectedby the musings of philosophers, or, indeed, the existence of sentienceor life at all. Furthermore, the fictionalist who is a Platonist aboutpropositions can supply the missing ontology to avoid the objection

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.13

Page 14: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

272 DANIEL NOLAN

based on the supposed incomplete content of the modal fiction: forPlatonic sets of sentences can be infinite, and a Platonic fiction canhave all of its assertions being explicit, and indeed describe everyone of the infinite possible worlds in total detail without having torely on implication, unlike any story which could be written into abook by mere inhabitants of the world of change and decay.

Why should a strong modal fictionalist not take this approachto propositions then? The first point is that commitment to suchPlatonism about propositions might be thought to be an ontologicalprice too high to be worth paying. It is difficult for me to see whatsorts of things actual abstract propositions might be, and if a reduc-tion of such objects to more orthodox entities, such a sets or factsor universals cannot be carried out, it seems we have, through ouranalysis, just swapped primitive modality for equally mysteriousprimitive propositions – and if this is so, it is not clear that we havea net saving in the parsimony of our total theory. Thus even if thequestion of propositions is answered in a non-modal way, the costof providing such an explanation of propositions may itself count asan argument against strong modal fictionalism. The second consid-eration is that this brand of strong modal fictionalism probably doesnot even deserve the name. It differs only slightly from linguisticersatzism (discussed in Lewis (1986)) – the only difference is thata linguistic ersatzism will identify worlds with what the fictional-ist takes to be descriptions of (admittedly non-existent) worlds. Astrong fictionalism which is Platonist about propositions will prob-ably suffer in comparison with such an ersatzism in fact, for it willpresumably face any problems which bedevil such ersatzisms, andwill have the additional problem of needing to invoke the troublingnotion of truth-in-fiction.6 This second point is not an objection todealing with modality with an ontology of Platonic propositions perse, of course: the point is rather that one who employs this approachis an ersatzer rather than a strong modal fictionalist, or at worst afictionalist who hopes to take advantage of Platonic propositionsholds a close relative to ersatzism which shares all of its costs andhas an additional cost of its own as well. So while Platonism aboutpropositions can be invoked by a strong modal fictionalist to avoidthe three problems discussed in this paper, it would seem to under-cut the original motives for modal fictionalism: neither the desire

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.14

Page 15: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 273

to avoid ontological cost nor the desire to develop an alternative toersatzism are well met by this strategy.7

5. AN ASSUMPTION RELIED ON BY THE INCOMPLETENESSOBJECTIONS, AND A DEFENCE THEREOF

Before I leave the topic of ontological incompleteness, I shouldprobably mention an assumption that runs through both versionsof the incompleteness objection and which both objections rely onto some extent, and mention why I think the fictionalist reply tothese objections which involves the denial of the assumption is notplausible.

The assumption is that when we say that a certain propositionis true according to a certain fiction, what we are saying is that arelation of a certain sort holds between a fiction and a proposition.It has been suggested to me that instead of seeing it as asserting thatthe relation of “being true according to” holds between a propositionand the Modal Fiction, rather it is the application of an irreduciblemonadic predicate to an object. This strategy, in different guises,supposedly provides an answer to at least one of the versions ofthe incompleteness objection, and perhaps to both. For if “is trueaccording to the Modal Fiction” is an operator on propositions thatdoes not imply any sort of relation (such as the part-of relation,or an implication relation) between a proposition and the ModalFiction, then it does not matter if the fiction does not have suchpropositions in it or even implied by it. By the same token, if “Pis true according to” is a monadic predicate applied to fictions thatdoes not require that there be any such proposition as P, then the non-existence of such propositions is no bar to saying, for some P, “P istrue according to the modal fiction”. Obviously, this strategy cannotbe used simultaneously to answer both halves of the incompletenessproblem. Apart from the fact that this strategy just screams “adhoc”, and flies in the face of a plausible first stab at analysis of “truthin fiction”, it faces another objection: either of these irreduciblemonadic predicates are utterly mysterious, and an analysis of anarea of discourse into an explanation in these terms lacks genuineexplanatory power. If these predicates are the best things strongmodal fictionalism can come up with to analyse modal discourse,then it seems to me that it would be better to embrace sui generis

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.15

Page 16: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

274 DANIEL NOLAN

modality rather than make our theory more complex just to introducesuch sui generis mystery further on.

6. CONCLUSION

As I said near the start of the paper, this discussion of problems wasby no means meant to be exhaustive: but it is my opinion that thesethree are enough on their own to make strong modal fictionalismvery unattractive. Strong modal fictionalism introduces artificialitywhere we would wish to avoid it and it raises ontological problems,both through the inadequacy of what limited things like fictionscan represent and through forcing us to give a non-modal accountof propositions. As in virtually any area of philosophy, salvagesare possible: but in both the cases of Platonism about propositionsand introduction of sui generis complex “according to” operatorsthe salvages themselves are very unattractive. Fictionalism aboutpossible worlds could turn out to be a very useful approach, sinceit is undisputable that we sometimes talk as if there are such things,and yet it would be nice if we could avoid the problems of actuallyembracing the view that this talk is to be taken at face value. IfFictionalism is to be accepted, however, we must not embrace it asit is often presented: we must not embrace strong fictionalism aboutpossible worlds.

NOTES

1 Giving a plausible and adequate account of the constraints on selection of themodal fiction is, I suspect, the most difficult task facing a strong modal fiction-alist: for instance, all but the para-consistent fictionalists will need to postulatenon-modal constraints that ensure the selection of a story that only claims con-sistent worlds exist. But since which non-modal constraints are argued for variesfrom account to account, this problem will not be further explored: whether a givenstrong modal fictionalism meets the requirements about constraints will need tobe determined by examination of the particular fiction in question.2 This is in fact controversial: for a discussion of the alternative Platonist theoryof fictions, see the last section of this paper. For now I will assume such Platonismabout fictions is false.3 This mind-dependence of possible worlds might not worry those with anti-realist or conceptualist inclinations when it comes to modality: but those withsuch sympathies would presumably prefer broad modal fictionalism over strongmodal fictionalism, as it would seem strange to claim that modality was anyless fictional than possible worlds if the whole area was to be understood anti-realistically or as being mind-dependent.

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.16

Page 17: Three Problems for “strong” Modal Fictionalism

THREE PROBLEMS FOR “STRONG” MODAL FICTIONALISM 275

4 Note that the Incompleteness Objection I will be discussing is quite differentfrom the “incompleteness problem” discussed by Rosen (1990, p. 341). Rosen isconcerned with deciding issues about which the Modal Fiction is silent but aboutwhich there are determinate facts of the matter according to modal realism, where-as my objection concerns difficulties involved with modal fiction being supposedto make many of the claims about which it is not meant to be silent.5 Thus I think that the “syntactic/inferential” account of the modal fiction (andany account relevantly similar) is in even worse shape than Lycan (1993, p. 10)argues, since Lycan admits that an adequate fiction might be able to be providedthrough using universal quantification over “all combinations” and such like.6 Of course, when it comes to comparing total theories the ersatzer will need togive an account of truth-in-fiction somewhere along the line: but the ersatzer willthen have the advantage of being able to use modal resources or talk of possibleworlds to help non-circularly explain the notion of fiction (the ersatzer could, forinstance, simply take over the account of fiction given in Lewis (1986)).7 Points quite similar to this are made against the Platonism-about-fictionsstrategy in Lycan (1993, footnote 18 on p. 16).

REFERENCES

Armstrong, D.M. (1989): A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility, Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

Armstrong, D.M. (1973): Belief, Truth and Knowledge, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Brock, S. (1993): ‘Modal Fictionalism: A Response to Rosen’, Mind 102, 147–150.

Davies, M. and Humberstone L. (1980): ‘Two Notions of Necessity’, Philosophi-cal Studies 38, 1–30.

Evans, G. (1979): ‘Reference and Contingency’, The Monist 62(2), 161–189.Field, H. (1989): Realism, Mathematics and Modality, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Lewis, D. (1986): On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Lewis, D. (1978): ‘Truth In Fiction’, American Philosophical Quarterly 15(1),

37–46.Lycan, W. (1993): ‘Armstrong’s New Combinatorialist Theory of Modality’, in

J. Bacon, K. Campbell and L. Reinhardt (eds.) Ontology, Causality and Mind,pp. 3–17, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rosen, G. (1990): ‘Modal Fictionalism’, Mind 99(395), 327–354.Rosen, G. (1993): ‘A Problem for Fictionalism about Possible Worlds’, Analysis

53, 71–81.

Philosophy ProgramThe Research School of Social SciencesThe Australian National UniversityCanberra, ACT 0200Australia

phil6938.tex; 15/07/1997; 13:56; v.6; p.17