4
May 28, 1998 Issue Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald, reply by Howard Gardner In response to: Evolutionary Psychology: An Exchange from the October 9, 1997 issue To the Editors: The exchange between Stephen Jay Gould and Steven Pinker [NYR, October 9, 1997] regarding the nature of evolutionary psychology and more specifically the notion of cognitive spandrels was entertaining and informative. Which aspects, if any, of our mental functioning are spandrels, as opposed to adaptive mechanisms “designed” by natural selection to solve the kinds of problems faced by our ancestors in their struggle to survive and reproduce (quoting Pinker), is an extremely important question that requires serious discussion and debate. But it also involves a study of precisely what those “kinds of problems” may have been, and quite how our ancestors solved them. In this regard a serious weakness in the current literature of evolutionary psychology is the almost blasé disregard for the archaeological, fossil, and palaeoenvironmental records that provide evidence to address these questions. Reading much of the evolutionary psychology literature as an archaeologist, I find it astonishing that gross generalizations are made about our Pleistocene hunter-gatherer past, with such little reference to the research of archaeologists who endeavor to reconstruct past lifestyles. Pinker did at least acknowledge the existence and value of the archaeological record, when commenting about whether reading may be a spandrel. But whatever its theoretical strengths or shortcomings as debated by Pinker and Gould, evolutionary psychology will not prosper until it takes the hunter-gatherer past as seriously as it claims to do so. The archaeological, fossil, and palaeoenvironmental records provide evidence about past behavior and cognition. To suggest, as Howard Gardner does in his review of my book The Prehistory of the Mind (Thames and Hudson, 1996), coincidentally in the same issue as the Pinker-Gould exchange, that discussions of prehistoric behavior cannot go beyond speculation appears to be a further reflection of this academic arrogance that pervades the cognitive sciences. Archaeology can go just as far beyond speculation about past behavior as can, say, a cognitive-development-psychologist when speculating about what might be going on in a child’s mind. Perhaps a lot further. Archaeology is no longer a young or naive discipline. The last thirty years has seen a veritable revolution not simply in its use of scientific techniques to extract ever greater amounts of information from stone artifacts, broken bones, or ancient sediments, but in its adoption of a scientific methodology to evaluate claims about past behavior, and indeed past cognition. To dismiss the work of archaeologists as being unable to go beyond speculation reflects not just an intellectual arrogance, but an ignorance of the theories, methods, and techniques used in modern archaeology. So while Stephen Jay Gould argues that evolutionary psychology could become a more fruitful science Font Size: A A A ‘The Prehistory of the Mind’: An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merli... http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1998/may/28/the-prehistory-of... 1 de 4 03/02/2014 18:59

‘The Prehistory of the Mind’_ An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald _ The New York Review of Books

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: ‘The Prehistory of the Mind’_ An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald _ The New York Review of Books

May 28, 1998

IssueSteven Mithen and Merlin Donald, reply by Howard Gardner

In response to:

Evolutionary Psychology: An Exchange from the October 9, 1997 issue

To the Editors:

The exchange between Stephen Jay Gould and Steven Pinker [NYR, October 9, 1997] regarding the

nature of evolutionary psychology and more specifically the notion of cognitive spandrels was

entertaining and informative. Which aspects, if any, of our mental functioning are spandrels, as

opposed to adaptive mechanisms “designed” by natural selection to solve the kinds of problems faced

by our ancestors in their struggle to survive and reproduce (quoting Pinker), is an extremely important

question that requires serious discussion and debate. But it also involves a study of precisely what

those “kinds of problems” may have been, and quite how our ancestors solved them.

In this regard a serious weakness in the current literature of evolutionary psychology is the almost

blasé disregard for the archaeological, fossil, and palaeoenvironmental records that provide evidence to

address these questions. Reading much of the evolutionary psychology literature as an archaeologist, I

find it astonishing that gross generalizations are made about our Pleistocene hunter-gatherer past, with

such little reference to the research of archaeologists who endeavor to reconstruct past lifestyles.

Pinker did at least acknowledge the existence and value of the archaeological record, when

commenting about whether reading may be a spandrel. But whatever its theoretical strengths or

shortcomings as debated by Pinker and Gould, evolutionary psychology will not prosper until it takes

the hunter-gatherer past as seriously as it claims to do so. The archaeological, fossil, and

palaeoenvironmental records provide evidence about past behavior and cognition.

To suggest, as Howard Gardner does in his review of my book The Prehistory of the Mind (Thames

and Hudson, 1996), coincidentally in the same issue as the Pinker-Gould exchange, that discussions of

prehistoric behavior cannot go beyond speculation appears to be a further reflection of this academic

arrogance that pervades the cognitive sciences. Archaeology can go just as far beyond speculation

about past behavior as can, say, a cognitive-development-psychologist when speculating about what

might be going on in a child’s mind. Perhaps a lot further. Archaeology is no longer a young or naive

discipline. The last thirty years has seen a veritable revolution not simply in its use of scientific

techniques to extract ever greater amounts of information from stone artifacts, broken bones, or ancient

sediments, but in its adoption of a scientific methodology to evaluate claims about past behavior, and

indeed past cognition. To dismiss the work of archaeologists as being unable to go beyond speculation

reflects not just an intellectual arrogance, but an ignorance of the theories, methods, and techniques

used in modern archaeology.

So while Stephen Jay Gould argues that evolutionary psychology could become a more fruitful science

Font Size: A A A

‘The Prehistory of the Mind’: An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merli... http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1998/may/28/the-prehistory-of...

1 de 4 03/02/2014 18:59

Page 2: ‘The Prehistory of the Mind’_ An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald _ The New York Review of Books

by respecting a plurality of evolutionary processes beyond natural selection, I believe it also needs to

mature by engaging more directly with the evidence for past human behavior and cognition as inferred

from the archaeological record. The discussion about spandrels is a case in point. Pinker, Gould, and

others can bicker as long as they wish about whether, say, propensities for art, religion, or a fear of

death are spandrels or whether they were selected to solve particular problems faced by ancestors. But

it is possible to get to work on such issues by exploring the evolutionary history of these propensities

by exploiting the fossil and archaeological records.

Obviously this is not an easy task; as Howard Gardner noted, the number of new discoveries in the last

few years that may change one’s understanding has been daunting. So I am not arguing that there are

any clear answers about cognitive evolution in these records of the past: cognitive abilities need to be

inferred from reconstructions of past behavior, just as psychologists need to infer the cognitive abilities

of children or apes from behavioral observations. But one can, I contend, reconstruct evolutionary

histories for many of those aspects of human cognition that appear to be uniquely human (but not, the

archaeological record suggests, necessarily unique to Homo sapiens sapiens). These evolutionary

histories should inform us as to the likelihood that we are dealing with spandrels or “engineered mental

solutions” to adaptive problems or at least lead to a more informed and interesting debate.

My own interpretation of the archaeological record as laid out in The Prehistory of the Mind concludes

firmly in the favor of Gould that many, perhaps most, of those peculiarly human mental propensities,

such as believing in supernatural beings and the pursuit of pure science, are indeed spandrels. These

seem to appear suddenly and dramatically in our evolutionary past. Original adaptive values appear

absent, but these propensities can be readily understood as byproducts of ways of thinking which did

indeed help solve adaptive problems faced by our recent human ancestors.

Yet I am an archaeologist, not as adequately versed in evolutionary theory or human psychology as I

would wish. Indeed, perhaps the greatest constraint on our understanding of how the human mind

evolved is that none of us are sufficiently well versed in a sufficient number of disciplines to make

sufficiently informed contributions about cognitive evolution. The structure of our academic

institutions or at least those in the UK continue to inhibit multidisciplinary research, and more

particularly teaching, on cognitive evolution. Some, such as my own of Reading University, are

working to change this with new multidisciplinary graduate degree programs. At Reading a recent

innovation has been an MA course taught jointly by archaeology, psychology, philosophy, and

linguistics. Hopefully graduates from such courses may be able to take our understanding of cognitive

evolution beyond that possible from those of us who have had our minds moulded by one discipline

alone.

Steven Mithen

Department of Archaeology

University of Reading, UK

To the Editors:

‘The Prehistory of the Mind’: An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merli... http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1998/may/28/the-prehistory-of...

2 de 4 03/02/2014 18:59

Page 3: ‘The Prehistory of the Mind’_ An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald _ The New York Review of Books

Howard Gardner criticized Steven Mithen’s book The Prehistory of the Mind because the author

proposed that ancient humans evolved a “general-purpose” form of intelligence. While I agree with

Gardner that Mithen is guilty of a misconception in the way he formulated his proposal, I think that

Gardner’s rather global criticism does not do complete justice to Mithen’s proposal.

Two quite different ideas are conflated in Mithen’s proposal, and they should be picked apart, because

only one of them is wrong. The first is the notion that human intelligence could be the result of a

general-purpose evolutionary adaptation. This idea is simplistic, and ignores most of what we know

about evolution. Adaptations always occur under specific environmental pressures, and within the

constraints of very specific brain designs. This results in specialized modifications, rather than general-

purpose ones. This rule applies to apes and humans, just as it applies to other species. In fairness,

Mithen may not have intended to convey what his terminology seems to suggest, but Gardner is right

to criticize him on this point.

The second idea is domain-generality, the notion that some mental faculties have a much wider reach

than others. This is an unassailable structural concept. The human mind has exquisite structure. One

can imagine it as a set of pyramids, each with its own hierarchy of modules, each of which mediates

some special skill. At the base of the pyramid stand many of the most basic reflexive functions. These

are the specialists of the mind, narrow-band modules designed to carry out specific functions, such as

focusing the eyes, or tasting food, with maximum efficiency. The mid-levels of the mind contain

somewhat integrative functions, for instance, spatial maps of the environment, or images of one’s own

body, both of which require synthesis across a few modules. And at the top levels, there are the most

powerful integrative systems, some of which approach true domain-generality in their reach. Language

is one of these. The fact that we can talk about what we hear, smell, touch, or feel, and also describe

our cognitive maps of the environment, testifies that our language brain has broad general access to the

knowledge gleaned by the specialized modules dedicated to hearing, smelling, touching, and feeling, as

well as those concerned with spatial mapping. In that sense, it is a domain- general capacity.

Thus Mithen was right in arguing that humans have evolved some remarkably powerful domain-

general capacities. The catch is that domain-generality in cognition should never be confused with the

notion of general-purpose adaptation. The two are not the same. Domain-generality is a purely

architectural conception, and has nothing whatsoever to say about the specific adaptations by which it

is achieved. Language is not the only domain-general system in the human mind. As both Gardner and

I have argued from quite different vantage points, we have other capacities that are domain-general in

an architectural sense. Because of this, we have many ways of representing the same reality. An artist

might draw his conception of an idea, while a speaker, a mathematician, a dancer, and an actor might

each capture the same idea in a very different way. There is a good case to be made that each of these

is a domain-general construction. Yet none of them can be called a product of “general intelligence.”

As he is undoubtedly discovering, Mithen wandered into treacherous waters when he formulated this

part of his proposal. On the whole, however, his project is a good one. He is forging a distinctively

archaeological “take” on the prehistory of the mind. In doing this, he might serve as a corrective

influence on psychologists such as myself who might lean too heavily on cognitive evidence, and not

‘The Prehistory of the Mind’: An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merli... http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1998/may/28/the-prehistory-of...

3 de 4 03/02/2014 18:59

Page 4: ‘The Prehistory of the Mind’_ An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merlin Donald _ The New York Review of Books

heavily enough on the corresponding cultural record.

Merlin Donald

Professor

Department of Psychology

Queen’s University

Kingston, Ontario

Howard Gardner replies:

I am surprised by Steven Mithen’s response to my review; it seems unnecessarily defensive and

inappropriately offensive. I wrote at length and respectfully of Mithen’s undertaking and commented

substantively on his various claims. I cannot subscribe at all to his boast that archaeology can proceed

as confidently about past behavior—and “perhaps a lot further”—than the field of developmental

psychology. Like geology, cosmology, and astronomy and other historically grounded sciences,

archaeology must deal with a necessarily scanty record of past events and is ever subject to radical

recalibration on the basis of new findings (as both Mithen and I note). In contrast, psychologists

participate in experimentally grounded science. Researchers are in a position to develop theories, test

hypotheses, run control groups, and, most crucially, replicate results at will, varying factors in a

systematic way. It is possible to establish the role assumed by language in the cognitive development

of children all over the world; it will never be possible to establish, with a comparable degree of

authority, the roles played by languages (and protolanguages) in the evolution of human cognition. I

find the distinction between the two kinds of science useful in evaluating the recent exchanges in these

pages about evolutionary psychology. Stephen Jay Gould and Steve Jones acknowledge the

fragmentary nature of the data on which evolutionary psychologists must base their (pre)historical

reconstructions. As Jones notes, “The mind may have evolved through something quite invisible to

experimental science.” In contrast, Steven Mithen and Steven Pinker hope that the interplay among the

archaeological record, cross-species comparisons, findings about human development, and the

principles of natural selection will yield a cumulative and increasingly reliable science.

Merlin Donald makes a judicious point in his letter. It is true that language has the power to refer to

multiple domains. Note, however, that language can never substitute for music, dance, architecture, or

other systems of meaning. As the dancer Isadora Duncan once phrased it, “If I could tell it to you, I

would not have to dance it.”

© 1963-2014 NYREV, Inc. All rights reserved.

‘The Prehistory of the Mind’: An Exchange by Steven Mithen and Merli... http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/1998/may/28/the-prehistory-of...

4 de 4 03/02/2014 18:59