27
The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy) [email protected] Paper (Zombies cannot be there) available at http://edu.supereva.it/ giuntihome.dadacasa

The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies

Marco GiuntiUniversity of Cagliari (Italy)[email protected]

Paper (Zombies cannot be there) available athttp://edu.supereva.it/giuntihome.dadacasa

Page 2: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Two concepts of reduction [1/21]

Ontological reduction

Facts of type T1 (which hold in world w) do

not exist independently of facts of type T0

(which hold in the same world w).

Epistemic reduction (or Reductive explanation)

Facts of type T1 (which hold in world w) are

reductively explained by facts of type T0

(which hold in the same world w).

Page 3: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

How can we analyze either concept of reduction? [2/21]

Standard answerBy means of a relationship of entailment

between types of facts or, equivalently, a relationship of supervenience between the corresponding types of properties.1

NoteEntailment between facts and supervenience

between properties are interdefinable. Therefore, we can choose either concept as primitive. I choose the first one for convenience.

Page 4: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

What is entailment between types of facts? [3/21]

Standard answerIt is the implication that holds in virtue of the

meanings, or the intensions, of the properties involved in such types of facts.

• Since we can distinguish several different kinds of intensions,1 we obtain a corresponding entailment for each kind.

• As a consequence, we get different analyses of ontological or epistemic reduction depending on which entailment is taken be appropriate.

Page 5: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

What is my position on the analysis of ontological or epistemic reduction? [4/21]

• I just maintain that, probably, some kind of entailment is needed for an adequate analysis of ontological reduction.

• I am more doubtful about epistemic reduction. Epistemic reduction might be better analyzed in terms of representation relationships between models (isomorphisms, homomorphisms, or other concepts of a similar sort, like emulation or realization between dynamical systems).

Page 6: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Distinction between phenomenal and psychological consciousness [5/21]

• Let us stipulate that F* stands for the set of all physical facts that hold in the actual world w*, and CF* for the set of all phenomenal facts that hold in w*; I also call the latter set phenomenal consciousness (in the actual world).

• “First-person fact of consciousness”, “internal fact of consciousness”, and “conscious experience” are three synonyms for “phenomenal fact”.

• “Third-person fact of consciousness”, “external fact of consciousness”, and “conscious function” are three synonyms for “psychological fact”.

• Let us finally stipulate that CP* stands for the set of all psychological facts that hold in the actual world; I also call the latter set psychological consciousness (in the actual world).

Page 7: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

What is my position on entailment between F* and CF*? [6/21]

• My view does not depend on any specific entailment.

Terminology – Let us indicate with I an arbitrary kind of intensions and with |=I the corresponding entailment.

• My thesis on entailment between F* and CF* can be expressed as follows:Logical thesis – for any kind of intensions I, if F* |=I

CP*, then F* |=I CF*.• From the logical thesis, we obtain the following

corollary.Philosophical thesis – if there is an adequate

analysis of reduction (ontological or epistemic) in terms of some notion of entailment, then, if CP* is reducible to F* (ontologically or epistemically), CF* is reducible to F* as well (ontologically or epistemically).

Page 8: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

How do I argue for either thesis? [7/21]

My strategy consists of the following three steps.1. Set up a formal possible world ontology where we can

represent or express intensions of any kind, and thus any notion of entailment between types of facts.

2. Show how, within this ontology (equipped with-abstraction), we can give a formal explication for each of the two concepts: (i) internal fact of consciousness (or conscious experience); (ii) external fact of consciousness (or conscious function).

3. On the basis of this analysis, prove that the two concepts individuate the same set of facts, i.e. prove that phenomenal consciousness is identical to psychological consciousness.

Both the logical and the philosophical theses are immediate consequences of 3.

       

Page 9: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

What about zombies? [8/21]

• An easy consequence of the logical thesis is:

Chalmers’ dilemma (logical version) – for any kind of intensions I, if F* |=I CP*, then a zombie copy of the actual world does not exist.1

• Also note that, from the logical version of Chalmers’ dilemma, it immediately follows:

Chalmers’ dilemma (philosophical version) – if there is an adequate analysis of reduction (ontological or epistemic) in terms of some notion of entailment, then, if CP* is reducible to F* (ontologically or epistemically), a zombie copy of the actual world does not exist.

Page 10: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 1 – The formal ontology (1/4)

Axioms [9/21]

An intensional ontology is a structure (D, P, W, w*) that satisfies the following four axioms.

1. D is a non empty set;D is called domain;

2. P is a non empty set; each element of P is an ordered pair (P, n) such that 1 n;any such pair is indicated with the notation Pn; every element of P is called a property; the number n is called its arity (or its number of places).

3. W is a set of functions; each of them, to any property Pn P, associates a set {(x1, … , xn)} of n-tuples of elements of D;every function w W is called a possible world; the set of n-tuples assigned by w to Pn is called the extension of Pn in world w;

4. w* W;w* is called the actual world.

Page 11: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 1 – The formal ontology (2/4) [10/21]

• It is then clear that any kind of intensions I can be expressed or represented within this formal ontology, for each I determines a specific model of this theory.1

• Given an arbitrary intensional ontology, we can then define facts, their holding in a world, and the entailment relationship relative to the given ontology.

Page 12: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 1 – The formal ontology (3/4)

Definitions [11/21]

Def. 1 [fact, predicate, subject]f is a fact iff: f is an ordered pair of the

type (Pn, (x1, … , xn)), where Pn P and (x1, … , xn) is an n-tuple (n 1) of elements of D;

the property Pn is called the predicate of f;

the n-tuple (x1, … , xn) is called the subject of f;

we write for brevity Pn(x1, … , xn) instead of (Pn, (x1, … , xn)).

Page 13: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 1 – The formal ontology (4/4)

Definitions [12/21]

Def. 2 [holding in a world]f holds in w iff: f = Pn(x1, … , xn) is a

fact, w W, and (x1, … , xn) w(Pn).

Def. 3 [entailment between sets of facts]

F1 |= F2 iff: for any w W, if for any f1 F1, f1 holds in w, then for any f2 F2, f2 holds in w.

Page 14: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (1/7) – Formal explicationThe analysis strategy [13/21]

INTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

INTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOR SOMEONE

INTERNAL FACTFOR SOMEONE

FACT OFCONSCIOUSNESS

EXTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

EXTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

EXTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOR SOMEONE

EXTERNAL FACTOF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOR SOMEONE

EXTERNAL FACTFOR SOMEONE

EXTERNAL FACTFOR SOMEONE

FACT OF CONSCIOUSNESS

FACT OF CONSCIOUSNESS

Page 15: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (2/7) – What is an internal or an external fact for someone? [14/21]

• The fact f = George is running is an experience (internal fact) for George, but f is an external fact for anybody else.

• Why? Because George, and nobody else, is the subject of the fact, i.e., only George is located internally to f in the role of bearer of the predicate of f. Thus, let us define:

Def. 4f is an internal fact for x iff: f is a fact and x is the

subject of f.

Def. 5 f is an external fact for x iff: f is a fact and x is not

the subject of f and, for some n, x is an n‑tuple of elements of D.

Page 16: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (3/7) – What is a fact of consciousness? [1/3] [15/21]

Typical examples1. Mary is conscious of her running;2. Mary is conscious of John’s speaking.

NoteMary is seeing a red spot is not a typical example, because

in this case the logical form of the fact of consciousness is disguised.1

By observing the two typical examples, we notice: i. in each of them, the binary property x is conscious of f

occurs; this is a relation between an element x of the domain and a fact f;

ii. the subject of each fact of consciousness is x (Mary in the examples).

Page 17: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (4/7) – What is a fact of consciousness? [2/3] [16/21]

To formalize the examples so that conditions i and ii be satisfied, we need

I. a binary property C, for which we assume that it may only hold between elements of the domain and facts (axiom 5). Intuitively, C is to be identified with the relationship being conscious of;

II. the abstraction operation ; is governed by straightforward adaptations of two standard principles of the ‑calculus (axiom 6 – abstraction, and axiom 7 – instantiation).

Page 18: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (5/7) – What is a fact of consciousness? [3/3] [17/21]

• By employing C and , we get:Mary is conscious of her running =

[(m)C(m, f0)](m), where

f0 = Mary is running = R(m);• the form of this fact satisfies i and ii.

Intuitively, the facts of consciousness are all those facts with a form like the one of the fact above. Let us thus define:

Def. 6 f is a fact of consciousness iff: there is x D, there

is a fact f0, such that f = [(x)C(x, f0)](x).

Page 19: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (6/7) – What is an internal or an external fact of consciousness for someone? [18/21]

Def. 7f is an internal fact of consciousness for

x iff: f is an internal fact for x and f is a fact of consciousness.

Def. 8f is an external fact of consciousness

for x iff: f is an external fact for x and f is a fact of consciousness.

Page 20: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 2 (7/7) – What is an internal or an external fact of consciousness? [19/21]

Def. 9f is an internal fact of consciousness iff:

there is x such that f is an internal fact of consciousness for x.

Def. 10 f is an external fact of consciousness iff:

there is x such that f is an external fact of consciousness for x.

Page 21: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 3 (1/2) – The proof that CF* = CP* [20/21]

Suppose f is an internal fact of consciousness. Then, by def. 9, 7 and 4, f is a fact and f is a fact of consciousness. Since f is a fact, let x be its subject. Then, by def. 5, f is an external fact for the pair (x, x). Since f is a fact of consciousness, it follows from def. 8 that f is an external fact of consciousness for the pair (x, x). Therefore, by def. 10, f is an external fact of consciousness. Hence, CF* CP*.

Page 22: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Step 3 (2/2) – The proof that CF* = CP* [21/21]

Conversely, suppose f is an external fact of consciousness. Then, by def. 10, 8 and 5, f is a fact and f is a fact of consciousness. Since f is a fact, let x be its subject. Then, by def. 4, f is an internal fact for x. Since f is a fact of consciousness, it follows from def. 7 that f is an internal fact of consciousness for x. Therefore, by def. 9, f is an internal fact of consciousness. Hence, CP* CF*.

Q.E.D.

Page 23: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

That’s all

Thank you

Page 24: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Three main kinds of intensions, and corresponding entailments [1A/4]

1. A‑priori intensions – the primary intensions in Chalmers’ sense, indicated by I1;

A‑priori entailment – indicated by |=1. 2. Weak a‑posteriori intensions – the secondary

intensions in Chalmers’ or Kripke’s sense, indicated by I2;

Weak a‑posteriori entailment – indicated by |=2.3. Strong a‑posteriori intensions – they determine

strong metaphysical necessities and cannot be described within Chalmers’ two dimensional framework. Indicated by I3;

Strong a‑posteriori entailment – indicated by |=3.

Page 25: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Different analyses of ontological or epistemic reduction depending on which entailment is taken be appropriate [2A/4]

|=1 |=2 |=3

Ontological Reduction

Type-A materialists

Chalmers and Jackson (1996, 1998, 2001)

Block and Stalnaker (1999)

Type-B materialists [weak]

Levine (1983, 1993)

Type-B materialists [strong, possibly with limitation to physical reduction of phenomenal consciousness]

Epistemic Reduction

Type-A materialists

Chalmers and Jackson (1996, 1998, 2001)

Levine (1983, 1993)

Block and Stalnaker (1999)

Type-B materialists [weak]

? [perhaps some strong Type-B materialists]

Page 26: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Does physics entail phenomenal consciousness? Different answers depending on the kind of entailment [3A/4]

F* |=1 CF* F* |=2 CF* F* |=3 CF*

YES Type-A materialists

Type-A materialists Block and Stalnaker (1999)

Type-B materialists [weak]

Levine (1983, 1993)

Type-A materialists

Type-B materialists [strong]

NO

Block and Stalnaker (1999)

Type-B materialists [weak and strong]

Levine (1983, 1993) Chalmers [zombie worlds are possible according to primary intensions]

Jackson [Mary’s argument]

Chalmers and Jackson [the relation between F* and CF* is unlike that between x is H2O and x is water]

Chalmers [strong a-posteriori intensions do not exist]

Page 27: The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)

Analysis of sensory facts of consciousness [4A/4]

Mary is seeing a red spot = Mary is conscious of her being in

neurophysiologic state r = [(m)C(m, f0)](m), where

f0 = Mary is in neurophysiologic

state r = [(m)S(m, r)](m)