723
The Fourth Civilization-- Technology Society and Ethics Fourth (2002-2003) Edition by Richard J. Sutcliffe Table of Contents Shareware Information Introduction Index Part I--Laying the Groundwork Chapter 1 History and Technology Chapter 2 The Foundations of Science and Technology Chapter 3 Basic Concepts in the Theory of Ethics Part II--Four Wavefronts on a Sea of Change Chapter 4 The Information Revolution Chapter 5 Robotics and The Second Industrial Revolution Chapter 6 The Intelligence Revolution Chapter 7 The Biospace Revolution Part III--Ethics and the Institutions of the Fourth Civilization Chapter 8 Technology and Economic Institutions Chapter 9 Technology, the State, and the Law Chapter 10 A New Education for a New Civilization? Chapter 11 Religion and the Transcendental in the Fourth Civilization Part IV Quo Vadis--Directions for People, Society and Technology 1

The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

STS Book

Citation preview

Page 1: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The Fourth Civilization-- Technology Society and Ethics

Fourth (2002-2003) Edition

by

Richard J. Sutcliffe

Table of Contents

Shareware Information Introduction Index

Part I--Laying the Groundwork

Chapter 1 History and Technology Chapter 2 The Foundations of Science and Technology Chapter 3 Basic Concepts in the Theory of Ethics

Part II--Four Wavefronts on a Sea of Change

Chapter 4 The Information Revolution Chapter 5 Robotics and The Second Industrial Revolution Chapter 6 The Intelligence Revolution Chapter 7 The Biospace Revolution

Part III--Ethics and the Institutions of the Fourth Civilization

Chapter 8 Technology and Economic Institutions Chapter 9 Technology, the State, and the Law Chapter 10 A New Education for a New Civilization? Chapter 11 Religion and the Transcendental in the Fourth Civilization

Part IV Quo Vadis--Directions for People, Society and Technology

Chapter 12 Integration And the Fourth Civilization

1

Page 2: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 1History and Technology

Seminar - "Who cares about history?" 1.1 The Art and Science of History 1.2 The First Four Phases of Civilization 1.3 History and Technology 1.4 A Brief History of Computing 1.5 Forecasting the Future 1.6 Summary and Further Discussion

The Fourth Civilization Table of Contents

Copyright © 1988-2002 by Rick Sutcliffe

Published by Arjay Books division of Arjay Enterprises

1.1 The Art and Science of History Students often think of history as a simple listing of events, names and dates.

However, an understanding of such events also requires knowing something of both the motivations influencing the people who made those events happen, and of methods by which the end results were achieved. In particular, the history of every society is intertwined on the one hand with its technological development, and on the other with the moral and ethical principles upon which the society is built. This book is concerned with all three concepts (history, technology, and ethics) and the relationships among them.

One goal of the study of history is attempting to look ahead as well as back, for by understanding the past and present one gains keys to the future. For instance, even though the technology that will influence the society of the future is very different from that which shaped historical events, there is still much to be learned by examining the past. It is possible to see how societies have already responded to (or developed from) radical technological changes, and thus to suggest how current trends might shape the future. To assist in this, a brief examination of the nature of historical studies is in order.

There is a flow to history and culture. This flow is rooted in and has its wellspring in the thoughts of people. People are unique in the inner life of the mind--what they are in their thought world determines how they act. This is true of their value systems and it is true of their creativity, true of their corporate actions, such as political decisions, and it is true of their personal lives. The results of their thought flow through their fingers or from their tongues into the external world. This is true of Michelangelo's chisel, and it is true of the dictator's sword.

--the late Francis Schaeffer in How Should We Then Live

2

Page 3: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

What Does a Historian Do?

A historian is more than simply a collector of facts about the past or present. In some ways, the "doing of history" is not unlike that of science, for in both disciplines it is well understood that a collection of data, however vast, does not become useful information until it is organized and interpreted. Like a courtroom judge who must sift through often conflicting eyewitness reports to discover the truth of events, the historian must reconcile accounts of the events under study that are often in sharp disagreement.

There are various reasons for the contradictions that arise even between eyewitness accounts of the same event. For instance, suppose two people standing at the roadside witness a traffic accident from different angles, each noticing aspects that the other does not. The first witness observes a car stop at an intersection and another car attempt to pass on the left, whereupon the stopped car suddenly makes a left turn and is struck broadside by the passing car. Everyone in both vehicles is killed and little is evident about the cause of the accident from the tangled wreckage. This witness is convinced that the driver of the passing car is at fault for attempting to pass when it was not safe to do so The second witness, however, sees the accident from the front and to the left of the flow of traffic instead of from the right side and behind as does the first. She observes that the stopped car had a right-turn signal on when the moving car attempted to pass on the left. To her, the accident is clearly the fault of the driver who signaled to turn one way and actually did the opposite.

Yet, despite knowledge of the misleading turn signal, the coroner who examines the bodies comes to agree with the first witness. She once barely avoided a similar accident by reacting quickly on the brake pedal to a slight movement of the leading driver's arm. Wondering why the following driver did not pick up such a clue despite the false signal, she tests the body of the passing car's driver and finds the blood alcohol content to be four times the legal limit. She has little doubt about where most of the blame lies.

Previous experiences, the time of day, road conditions, lighting, the amount of time spent watching, racial and sexual prejudice, and what a witness expected to see all might also colour the reports that the court hears. Each person takes the stand sworn to tell the whole truth, but even if all do exactly that to the best of their abilities, there will still be disagreements and contradictions.

Likewise, when considering historical events, it is necessary to take into account such things as nationalism, the pride of winners, the shame of losers, and the tendency of historians to support a particular theory or historical figure. As a result of such biases, the accounts of world events reaching a later historian will diverge even more than do those of the traffic accident in the example above. Add in the passage of hundreds or thousands of years and the perils of going through third or fourth hand copies of originals--each perhaps embellished with the copyist's ideas--and it may become difficult to sift contemporary fact from later myth.

3

Page 4: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

What is more, historians have in the past usually concentrated on the few outstanding figures who were at the centre of events--the kings, queens, generals, politicians and other acknowledged movers and shakers. Where there were sources available from common citizens, these were too fragmentary (and often too voluminous) to shed much light on the larger events that shaped the time under study. This is changing as computers allow such material to be assembled and sifted to get a more everyday perspective on events.

Establishing the facts in a careful and scientific fashion using the same kind of evidence weighing employed in a courtroom is the first task of a historian. The accuracy of available accounts must be assessed by checking them against other documents (perhaps describing related events) whose reliability is better accepted. The personality, motives, and level of education and knowledge of the author of the account must also be taken into consideration. For instance, in a society that attaches great importance to the mythology of a variety of gods and goddesses, the appearance of a comet or the conjunction of two planets might be viewed as a clash between the gods, with a simultaneous war here on Earth regarded as incidental. Although later historians would have the opposite view of which is the more important, they may be left with very little useful material with which to work.

However, the practice of the discipline of history is more than a mechanical sifting of facts and weighing of evidence, and the results must be more than a mere narrative of human actions. A history must also serve as an explanation of actions and events in their cultural and technological context, and it must at least attempt to explain the motivations of the people involved. The facts alone (who, what and when), however carefully verified, only slightly engage the mind to the study of history. The how (including the technology) and why (ethical and other motivations) capture one's interest at a much deeper level, for it is in the explaining of these two that one gains an understanding of events and the ability to apply what has been learned to new situations.

This is the art of history--to place events within a context that tells something about the people and ideas that moved the events in the first place, and that were in turn changed by the events after they took place. Events involve real flesh and blood human beings, and if one is to understand the forces that move societies, one must understand the people who shape those forces and are shaped by them.

History seeks to explain societal and individual experiences and to integrate opinions, motivations, causes, actions, reactions and effects into a comprehensive view of people in the context of their whole society. On the one hand, history must take into account the technologies that may have caused events to take place or that developed as a result of events. On the other hand, it must also take into consideration the moral/ethical (and other) human motivations for action.

Interpreting History

The historian must also produce a narrative that is able to convey to others the comprehensive picture created by sifting the collected materials. Thus the scholar must be able to write clearly and effectively. It is important to realize, however, that the result does not gain some canonical status ("truth") merely

4

Page 5: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

because it has been published--every book on history is filtered through its author's views about the world, people, their motivations, and the meaning of historical events.

At the most radical extreme are those who ignore the evidence of history and write their own. For instance, some deny that the holocaust of millions of Jews in the Second World War ever took place. Evidence is not relevant to people with a sufficiently strong view of a matter. The implied racism of these pseudo-histories has such incendiary potential it strains the ability of society to guarantee universal free speech, for it raises the spectre of the true history being repeated.

In like manner, the old-fashioned Marxist views history as the unfolding of a class struggle between the poor masses and the wealthy (capitalist) elite: history moves toward an inevitable climax wherein the mass of workers will control all wealth and its means of production. Historical writing done within the framework of this world view interprets the period under study in terms of such clashes because that world view requires class struggle to be present. Such an account may reinterpret what all other historians have said about events to the point where it becomes almost unrecognizable. This reinterpretation is both acceptable and morally right to the Marxist historian. In such ideologies the truth of past events is variable and must serve doctrine, for it alone is fixed. The Marxist believes that world view creates history, and the account generated by such a historian necessarily conforms to that world view.

The main character in George Orwell's anti-totalitarian novel 1984 is employed by the government to change old magazine reports of party officials' speeches so that they will conform to current party policy. The "Ministry of Information" is engaged not in securing and publishing factual material, but in ensuring that the record of history is altered to fit the current policies of the party. Truth attaches to party doctrine, not to mere facts.

Such views are prevalent in the study of all literature, not just the historical. The deconstructionists hold that no body of writing has any inherent meaning, even if one was intended by the author. Meaning is created and attached by the reader, and such activity is unique and relative to each individual, not absolute. It is also rather common to read present values into works of the past, or to criticize (or even ban) them for not having certain modern political and social views. Thus the works and thinking of past writers are often dismissed as irrelevant rather than studied for understanding.

While these are extreme examples, they force us to recognize that accounts of the past are always filtered through a world view that includes some theory of what history is, or ought to be. Even when applied to the same body of data, this filtering process may produce very different results, depending on who is doing the filtering.

The view of some Greek philosophers--one that has had periods of popularity ever since--was quite different. In this view, history was not an expression of political dogma, but an eternal repetition in cycles of the same kinds of events. Perhaps something could be learned from events, and perhaps not. What was certain was that if Rome burned Carthage, enslaved its peoples, and poured salt on

5

Page 6: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

its arable land, the same thing one day would be done to them by another people, and that their conquerors too would ultimately meet destruction.

There would be another Plato to deliver the messages of another Socrates; kingdoms would become democracies which when fully corrupt would lapse into dictatorship; and their dictators would in turn proclaim themselves kings and begin the cycle of government anew. Time and history had no beginning, no purpose, and no end--it just was. One could not rely on the gods to escape the cycle; one could but be subject to the fates. In this view, no real explanation for history is possible, for in the long run, inexplicable forces shape events--forces that are beyond the scope and knowledge of mere human beings. Taking this idea to its extreme, one could well conclude that there is little humankind can do in the face of events but continue a fateful existence as a bit player on an unknown stage before an unknowable audience.

The observation about the repetition of government types cannot be denied entirely, for such cycles may be seen to some extent in modern times and societies as well. For instance, in the first half of this century, both Russia and Germany went from imperial monarchy to democracy, into dictatorship, and back out again. Moreover, it is legitimate to ask whether democracy contains within itself the seeds of its own destruction. A democracy assumes that people will act in the common good, but its laws must reflect that they often act selfishly. As bureaucracy and regulations grow, and selfish demands increase, some may come to believe that a period of dictatorship or monarchy is necessary to salvage order out of what they see as growing chaos.

A few thinkers have taken the idea of the predictability of history further, wondering if it may become possible to develop systematic descriptions of trends in history and society so that events can not only be forecast, but also be managed by taking "corrective" measures. Perhaps the most popular of all science fiction was Asimov's Foundation series, whose premise was that just such a detailed analysis and prediction was possible, even over the span of millennia.

However, while some insist that complete scientific descriptions of history are both possible and necessary, others claim that no definitive explanation for history is possible or needed. In the last hundred years or so, "scientific" views of history have become increasingly popular, for humanity as a statistical whole is thought of as being subject to analysis and prediction. In this thinking, once the motivations of the masses could be measured and tabulated, their response to economic or technological stimuli could be accurately predicted. Appropriate technology and education could then be adapted to engineer and control the desired society. Such theories are popular among both political rightists and leftists, neither of whom realize that they are advocating the same kind of society--a sort of "scientific totalitarianism" or "technocratic dictatorship."

Finally, it is worthwhile to consider a Judeo-Christian perspective on the subject. The possibility of some thematic repetition as history progresses is not completely ruled out by these historians, though they regard history as much more than a record of purposeless recycling of events with no beginning and no end. Both Jews and Christians hold that the world and its peoples had a definite beginning and a purpose (to serve the Creator). The Bible chronicles events after creation: the

6

Page 7: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

rebellion and falling away from God by the first human beings, a new start after the worldwide catastrophe of the flood, the promise of a Messiah given to the nation of Israel, the provision of the law to set that nation apart as an inheritance for God. The Christian scriptures add that the law intentionally demonstrated the impossibility of pleasing God through an imposed morality. They detail the coming of Jesus Christ as the promised Messiah to usher in a new covenant with God based on his grace alone. Christians look forward to a return of Christ for judgment and reward, and to a final culmination of the Earth, its peoples, and their histories.

Thus, both Judaism and Christianity claim a comprehensive view of history as a definite progression. In the latter, the sequence of history is centred on the cross, but both root all their claims in a series of historical events. These events are potentially verifiable by the same means applied to other occurrences. Although this text will not present a detailed history of Western religions or discuss in other than general terms how their institutions have directly affected the events of Western nations, it is important to make two points:

First, whatever one thinks of the Judeo-Christian religions, one cannot underestimate the effect that they have had on Western culture and on ethics, the law, and government in particular. Ideas derived from the Bible can be found at the heart of much that is held dear in modern Western law, particularly in the important area of human rights. The influence upon the U.S. Constitution is particularly potent.

Second, religious influences may be on the ascendancy in Western culture after at least a century of decline. In recent centuries, secular statism and agnostic humanism had largely replaced Judeo-Christian thinking as "religious" forces. Yet in the last decade or so, such phrases as "born again" once more appear in the headlines of newspapers and magazines; prominent religious leaders have sought the U. S. presidency; and the morality of politicians is once again scrutinized publicly by a press newly sensitized to the deep interest of the public in such matters. Membership in theologically conservative organizations that are both socially and politically active continues to grow rapidly. Even though these members are numerically offset to a degree by the continuing exodus from the more liberal mainline groups, the net result is a higher visibility for religion in North America. In this context, it is not surprising that religious views of history, technology, and ethical issues should once again be regarded as legitimate topics for scholarly study, and debates once thought conceded are now being rejoined. All this activity has interesting side effects, for as Naisbitt (Megatrends) points out "evangelical publishers now account for a third of domestic book sales." The work of religious artists has also become an important factor in the music market.

Meanwhile, there is a broad resurgence of interest in other forms of spirituality, including various reinterpretations the so-called "New Age" movement has placed on some traditional Eastern religions that have made such ideas marketable in the West.

This increase of interest in religion following the end of the industrial age might be seen in a broader context as part of a reaction against the perceived "hardness" of the science and technology that have dominated the recent past. A new view is often heard--that one can indeed know things to be true in ways other than exclusively through the scientific method.

7

Page 8: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is worth observing that these trends have not yet (and may never be) reflected in the legislative and judicial arenas, and that they are more pronounced in the United States than in Canada, where the controlling paradigms are decidedly anti-religious. It would hurt a Canadian political candidate who made an issue of her religion, and such religious lobby groups as do exist have minimal influence on politicians or the courts in that country.

The desire to have structure during a time of change may also be a factor, especially in formerly Communist countries where people seeking stability often find religious leaders to be more credible than political ones. There is also a new desire to assert the importance of people over things, or at least to promote a "high-touch" aspect of society to balance the "high-tech." Thus, not only do older religions like Christianity appear to be enjoying at least nominal revival, but so are many other forms of religion, philosophy, and mysticism. All these factors may well have a strong influence on the peoples of the coming age.

Conclusion

It should distress no one that there are conflicting views about history, its interpretation, or even the facts themselves. The important lesson is that each person is part of a culture and has a view of the world through which all knowledge (including that of history), is filtered. One who appreciates this lesson and has a clear perception of both personal world view and cultural surroundings, gains an understanding of both the events of history and of a place in them, as well as the ability to engage in debate about their meaning in an informed way. Here again is Francis Schaeffer on the subject:

People have presuppositions, and they will live more consistently on the basis of these presuppositions than even they themselves realize. By presuppositions we mean the basic way an individual looks at life, his basic world view, the grid through which he sees the world. Presuppositions rest upon that which a person considers to be the truth of what exists. People's presuppositions lay a grid for all they bring forth into the external world. Their presuppositions also provide the basis for their values and therefore the basis for their decisions.

"As a man thinketh, so is he," is really most profound. An individual is not just the product of the forces around him. He has a mind, an inner world. Then, having thought, a person can bring forth actions into the external world and thus influence it.

-- How Should We Then Live

Placing history in a larger context is very much a theme of this book, for throughout the text, events, technology, and ethical issues are discussed in relation to one another. An important thesis here is that not only are ideas, actions, and people inseparable, but also that many disciplines of human thought regarded as distinct are really part of a whole. Because of this larger context, the title of this chapter could have been expressed in terms of sociology rather than of history. Use of the latter word reflects a need to place the discussions in a continuum of time, for

8

Page 9: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the major concern in this book will be that of the mutual influence of ethical and social issues, of technology, and of events over time. This continuum will also be in evidence in the attempts made in several chapters to peer into the future.

1.2 The First Four Phases of Civilization The purpose of this section is to review briefly the broad progress of

civilization as it is driven by technology. Specific examples, however revolutionary, are left for later. This review will divide the complex development of history into more easily understood periods or phases, here called "civilizations". There is an element of fiction to this, as a boundary a given historian might propose to demark two phases of civilization is artificial, and could be disputed by others. After all, one type of society actually flows smoothly into another. New information and new technologies take time to be absorbed, to have applications developed, and to become influential. Even when technologies are put to use decisively to prosecute a war, their effects on the general population may not otherwise be seen until long after the victory or defeat of one nation. It is sometimes only with the passage of centuries the vision of hindsight perceives a transitional period as a sharply defined change.

A more detailed history of the world's peoples would surely refine the four broad divisions given here into many more, with excellent arguments about why additional divisions are necessary and important. However, more than one book would be needed to complete that task. In addition, a goal of this book is to take the moral, social and technological pulse of the fourth civilization, which has just begun. Any speculations on a possible fifth will be left for other works.

The First Civilization--The Hunter-Gatherers

The most primitive type of society has little need for organization. People who live by hunting animals and gathering edible plants wherever they find them need a large expanse of territory just to keep each individual alive. Consequently, such hunter-gatherers move about, following the weather and the food. Family groupings are small; life is short and brutal; and sophisticated medical care does not exist. There is no store of knowledge apart from what parents pass to their children, and anyone who does have the time to invent the wheel has little chance to tell anyone else, let alone to market it. Ethics and the practice of religion are personal and cultural matters, and are highly localized.

The highest technologies in a hunter-gatherer society consist of fire for cooking and protection, simple throwing or clubbing instruments for hunting or defense, and clothing manufacture from animal products. There might be some metal working, animal domestication, and possibly the use of wheels. People may band together in extended families (tribes) of up to a few hundred with a common language, limited trade, and some broad knowledge of traditional history and geography. Such tribes may eventually establish fairly complex social structures.

The most highly developed society of this type was probably that of the North American natives before the arrival of the Europeans. Theirs was a society with low population density and primitive technology but with well developed social and

9

Page 10: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

economic structures, including continent-wide trading routes. Yet, they found themselves unable to meet the challenge presented by the arrival of the expansion-minded Europeans. They were unable to compete effectively with the European technology (wagons, guns, and iron tools), and fell before the better organized and equipped invaders. They also suffered from a lack of immunity to diseases like smallpox, and from the demise of the buffalo herds.

Hunter-gatherers must expend most of their total working energy on feeding and defending themselves (though they may have some leisure time). They lack the resources to support many non-food-producing members such as teachers, lawyers, scholars, and other city dwellers. As a result, such societies gain technology only very slowly, and may remain nearly unchanged over many centuries.

The Second Civilization--The Agriculturalists

As an intermediate stage before the second level of civilization begins, some peoples domesticate animals and become nomads, with a wider geographical range and a somewhat expanded social complexity. Whether this step takes place before or after the domestication of plants, it transforms hunting from a solitary, weary pilgrimage to a community experience. The key discovery needed to make the actual transition to an agricultural civilization is that it is more economical to save seed from desirable plants and grow them systematically in one location than to go out and find them wherever they happen to have sprouted on their own. If a single technology can be pointed to as the most important factor in developing an agrarian economy, it is the use of plough, though arguments could also be advanced for earlier innovations such as the sickle or the flail.

Farming provides a powerful motivation for further invention, because the more one's arm can be augmented by tools, the more land that can be put under cultivation, and the more wealth that can be generated by one person. Wheeled carts, animal drawn ploughs, and increasingly complex planting and harvesting machinery become highly prized as do the skills of the artisans who make these tools. Once a family can produce more than it can eat, trade expands and service settlements become towns, then cities. Metal tools replace stone implements, and the economic advantages cause the change from iron and copper to brass and eventually to steel in the search for stronger ploughs and other tools.

Agriculture provides a basis for supporting large numbers of non-food-producing people. Some manage to acquire wealth by using specialized knowledge rather than by producing food, and a class structure grows. Scholars and students can be supported, as can artists, musicians and theatrical players, for there must be something for the new upper classes to take their leisure in. Once information can be communicated to others in written form, it can also be transmitted to the next generation. The amount of knowledge then increases greatly, and philosophers, mathematicians and other academic disciplines find a place in society.

At the same time, armies can be outfitted for adventures in other lands, and societies grow far beyond the bounds of single families, cities or even districts. Technological know-how is also turned to the production of decorative jewellery. Gold, silver and gemstones may also become important. The needs of cities also

10

Page 11: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

drive invention in both architecture and in the design of water and transportation systems. The really ambitious empire builders must both construct and maintain roads and also find ways of ruling the oceans. They must also codify systems of law and apply them uniformly. Religious practice may also become organized and standardized and its institutions grow in power and size along with the society, perhaps forming an alliance with the state to maintain stability.

None of this progress is without cost to the ordinary person, for daily life in an agrarian society demands steady, heavy labour and is more complex than in a hunter-gatherer culture, though the food supply is more likely to be consistent. There are more and broader civil obligations to meet, including taxes, conscription, and dealing with government bureaucracy. Farmers have their lives ruled entirely by the land, the weather, and the state; they are not free to take a day or two off after a successful hunt. That is, the gains in security achieved through larger networks of mutual obligation are partially offset by a loss of individual freedom. This is particularly true if farmers are members of an empire-building society, since the wealth generated by their work must support large armies. In such a case, farmers may be virtual slaves to land they usually do not own.

The largest and most successful such society in the ancient world was the Roman empire. Centred on the Mediterranean Sea, it dominated Europe, Asia Minor, the Middle East, and Northern Africa for centuries. Its capital city, Rome, grew to a population of over a million people, a level not reached again after its decline until the 1930s. When the empire did fall, the Roman system of roads deteriorated and communications and transportation suffered to the point that no other power could grow to dominate in quite the same way. Because many such links were lost, a great deal of knowledge was not transmitted to succeeding generations, and progress toward the next stage of civilization was stalled for centuries. Instead, nations rose and developed localized languages, customs, and technology.

During this time one group that successfully straddled the first two civilizations were the Mongols whose base was initially nomadic, but who conquered and ruled a settled empire stretching across much of Asia and part of Europe.

European empires were based on oceangoing communication, and these were centred on such trade routes as proved strategic for their time. Venice and Genoa came to dominate the Mediterranean, and afterward Portugal and Spain ruled the South Atlantic. Later still, the British, French, and Dutch joined Portugal and Spain in roaming the world's oceans in search of food, preservatives, subject peoples and trade goods. As a result, advances in technology centred around ship building and military applications. The widespread use of gunpowder, particularly for ship-mounted guns, increased the ability to kill large numbers of people in a short period of time. This changed the nature of warfare dramatically, but had little direct effect on society itself. In such encounters, those nations prevailed that took the trouble to train their midshipmen in trigonometry, and to train their munitions suppliers to mix gunpowder uniformly. Countries with inferior education and technology gradually lost both territory and influence.

The gradual increase in the number of foundries, the continuous search for better metals, and the increasing use of small machines set the stage for the advent of the next society. It was Britain that had carried the trade-centred empire to

11

Page 12: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

global proportions more successfully than any other nation, and it was there in the eighteenth century that the critical mass of technology first became great enough to take the next step.

The Third Civilization--Industrialists

The harnessing of the steam engine to factory-based machines for the production of textiles started the next major series of changes. Known as the Industrial Revolution, because of the rapid conversion to the new technologies, this period was characterized by a large scale transfer of people from a rural to an urban setting, as they gave up farm labouring and cottage industries for work in the new factories. This urbanization became even more dramatic as time went on. It spread, first to Europe, then to North America, and subsequently to other parts of the world, even though in some places it was not accompanied by the necessary increase in jobs to keep the new city population at work.

Profile On ... A Changing Society The latter part of the industrial age saw a dramatic decline in the proportion of

the population involved in farming--the principal occupation of the agricultural society. As time passes, fewer people grow food for an ever expanding total population. As the chart below shows, farm families had become an all-but-invisible 2% of the U.S. population by 1987, and was even then still dropping by 0.1% per year.

Workers, at first little better off in urban slums than in rural poverty, gradually became consumers of the goods they produced and their standard of living began a rapid and almost unbroken rise that has continued to this day. As the list of factory produced goods lengthened, machines were also revolutionizing mining and later farming. For the first time, a society became possible in which the majority of people did not have to live at subsistence level, expending nearly all their energy just to stay alive.

Technological breakthroughs continued at a rapid pace through this time and these have put lasting marks upon the nations that made them. In the latter part of the twentieth century (as in Roman times, but on a larger scale) national borders became less important in the face of transportation and communications

12

Page 13: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

technologies that were capable of bypassing such barriers. No one people can for long keep secret or monopolize any given technology, and there is an increasing sense that the world is one place.

The typical person in an industrial society is better off materially than at any time in history, having more education, longer life, better medicine, faster personal transportation, more consumer goods and better communications facilities than ever before. To be sure, the new technologies have, as usual, been used to deal out death and destruction on a wider scale in the past century than in any previous one, but despite this, there has been a continuous increase in the ability to produce goods. This increased production has been accompanied by an ongoing urbanization and consumerism, and also by a greatly increased food supply.

Moreover, leisure time is available to the workers for the first time in history. Whole new industries have been spawned by this development, and tourism is not only big business, but in many places it is the biggest business of all. Indeed, as the wealth one person can produce has increased, the percentage of people working in non-goods-producing service industries has risen dramatically. This trend, too, would no doubt continue, even in the absence of new dramatic changes in production technologies.

The initial upheavals of the Industrial Revolution saw vast numbers of people attempting to improve their economic conditions by leaving the land and moving to the city. Many of them simultaneously severed their connections with organized religion. The institutionalized church had begun to lose its authority in any case, for it insisted upon the teachings of traditional authorities to explain the physical world and its workings long after these had been undermined by the influence of the philosophies associated with modern science. Some religious leaders came to believe that the idea of an infinite, unchanging God with absolute moral standards could be extrapolated to lend a similar absolutism concerning the physical world. Religious traditions, whether liturgical, governmental, or scientific, were invested with the weight of divine authority, becoming as unchangeable as God. Knowledge was not an incomplete and inexhaustible aspect of an infinite God. Instead, it was finite and complete. The Bible (and by association God) came to be seen as a limited creation of the institutional church. What was created by humans could eventually be seen as flawed, and then discarded. At the same time, the increasing availability of consumer goods helped to promote a materialism that separated people from the spiritual roots of traditional morality.

Meanwhile, the rising intellectual class was quick to seek new interpretations and draw different conclusions in ethical and moral matters that religion had once claimed for its own. Thus, the success of the Industrial Revolution also spawned new ideologies to compete with Judeo-Christian teachings for the hearts and minds of the modern Western peoples. People came to place their religious-like faith in the philosophies of science (scientism), reason (rationalism), progress (progressivism), the state (statism), or humankind (humanism) as the measure and end of all things. Many discarded ideas like the worship of God as creator and sustainer of the universe and dispensed also with the social aspects of religion. Over time, religion ceased to be part of the glue that held society together. Simultaneously, the abundance of wealth and the newfound ability to indulge in consumption tended to

13

Page 14: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

replace the concepts of duty and interdependence with the notions of self-actualization and autonomy epitomized by the "yuppie" phenomenon of the 1980s.

This is not to say that traditional religion (or social values) have altogether vanished from everyday life, for they may have made somewhat of a comeback in recent years. Yet, religion seems to have had little influence upon intellectuals or upon the leading institutions in Western society in the Industrial age, and this fact alone would set off the last century-and-a-half as unique among all periods of history.

Some hail the decline of traditional religious influence and the rise of individualism, citing a beneficial increase in freedom for the human mind from such changes. Others note that the simultaneous fragmentation of the culture tends to make society more difficult to maintain as a working entity. Still others worry about the track record modern humans have using technology in the absence of religious influence. Life and the Earth itself are at risk from nuclear weapons on the one hand, and from widespread pollution on the other. Moreover, this century has already seen the most devastating wars in all human history, as well as political and economic exploitation on at least as large a scale as ever done before. It has also seen deliberate mass killings for racial, religious, and political reasons that dwarf the most ambitious pogroms of earlier centuries.

The machine age has brought unparalleled prosperity to those who own or serve the machines and can buy the goods they make, but it has also brought the world to the brink of destruction by the same technology. Thus, while one could judge from material evidence that the human race is better off, such a judgement cannot be unqualified. Material goods have not in the past been regarded as the chief measure of the value of the human spirit, and it seems unlikely the machine age will be looked back upon as an idyllic or utopian time.

Meanwhile, there have been striking new developments that promise to bring even more radical changes. It is a commonplace observation by now that critical mass in certain technologies has been reached, and the transition to a whole new kind of civilization is well underway.

The Fourth Civilization--The Information Brokers

This transition is also characterized by many social changes, some representing continuations of long-established trends. Others may be due to reaction against what some regard as the excesses of the industrial age. For example, society has embraced a set of changing attitudes and new technologies that are concerned with the environment in which people live and the quality of life. "High touch" is balancing "high tech." There has been an increased interest in ethics, morality, religion, and the disciplines of thought and study that relate more to people than to things, and consequences of this will be considered later in the text. On the other hand, certain new technologies can be cited as formative for the next mature phase of civilization. For convenience, they are here grouped into four major categories, and these provide the chapter divisions for the next section of the text.

14

Page 15: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The first, and most characteristic, is the rapid development of computer-based data systems toward the goal of universal information availability. Anyone who wants to learn the facts of a subject can find the desired material, and do so without leaving home. This will have a profound impact upon political systems, education, most institutions, and the use of various media. Along with this can be cited improvements in communications and transportation. Not only will people be able to travel farther and faster than ever, but they will be able to exchange information with any point on earth easily and inexpensively. New communication methods are also causing dramatic changes in the conduct of business. In all, the consequences of freer information flow may well be greater and farther reaching than those caused by Gutenberg's invention of the printing press.

It is also worthwhile to note that such universal availability of information means that little or none of it is likely to be lost, however difficult the social aspects of the transition to the next civilization may prove to be. The redundancy of information makes it easier to ensure that what is available to one generation will be for the next. Of course, the next generation may not interpret or use a given piece of information in the same way, because values (including spiritual ones) are much harder to transmit than facts.

The second aspect of technological change characterizing the fourth civilization is the culmination of the second industrial revolution. Jobs continue the recent rapid shift away from the smokestack industries and into the service industries, and in the light of other trends, this shift will likely accelerate. The most revolutionary aspect of this is the introduction of robots to replace people on assembly lines. The end result could be the reversal of many aspects of the first industrial revolution--from the workers' point of view, the most radical change of all.

A third that is often cited is the further development of computer-based or artificial intelligence (AI). Combined with developments in robotics, this could further mechanize certain aspects of decision-making and managerial level tasks. This is the third, or intellectual, phase of the transfer of human tasks to machines (First came manual labour, then skilled craftsmanship and repetitious jobs, and finally some brainwork, too). Whether a machine employed in such tasks will ever be said to understand either the issues or the decision is another matter. The chief consequence of such a move could be yet another dramatic change in the way many individuals make their living.

The fourth group of formative technologies has to do with life itself--the most fundamental of all issues, and the one to which study and some understanding has come the latest in human history. The developing understanding of the genetic code implies the ability to manipulate life forms, engineer them for specific uses, prolong human life far beyond the present limits, and solve medical problems that have resisted all previous efforts.

In addition, the way in which people live is being given increasing attention. In the fourth civilization, such things as air, soil and water may all be engineered for human benefit, rather than treated simply as expendable raw material for factories. There could also an increasing focus on technologies for food production, on developing new habitats in places people have not lived before, and on enhancing the quality of life in other than simply material ways.

15

Page 16: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Since much of the dramatic change in all four of these characteristic groups is due to the development of high-technology devices, many based on microprocessor equipment, the invention of the computer in the late 1940s looms as the most significant single technological advance responsible for entry into the new civilization.

Details on the effects of these formative technologies will be left to the appropriate specific sections. Perhaps this brief summary will assist the reader to begin considering what kinds of societal change these new trends in technology may cause, even before reading a more detailed analysis (and speculation) later in the book.

The chart below gives a simple summary of the four civilizations insofar as employment is concerned. The true story is more complicated, and it should not be thought that some "inevitable advance of the cycles" is being presented. The latter two transitions needed to take place only once among human societies; sufficient communication had by then been established to ensure that the effects would spread throughout the world. The availability of instant information immensely complicates any such analysis as has been attempted here. Many more people have knowledge of the most recent technologies, and are prepared to attempt to skip the intermediate development others went through to get to that point. Thus, the path through the four stages, while presented as characteristic, can only properly describe the first time it happened; the experiences of nations trying to catch up must be very different.

16

Page 17: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

A different view of the four civilizations can be had by observing that the hunter-gatherers acted for the most part alone or in small groups, and had little flexibility to make changes in their life style or culture. The agrarians had more flexibility, though they too tended to remain in the same occupation for their whole lives. An industrial society is centred around organizations more than individuals, but there is greater flexibility and ability to change than in the other two. An information-oriented society returns us to a more individualistic orientation, but there is more flexibility and freedom for both individuals and organizations. The tension between flexible and inflexible organizational structures and between collectivizing and individualizing trends will be important themes throughout this book.

17

Page 18: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

1.3 History and Technology

The last section presented an overview of the four main phases of civilization. It is also useful to follow several threads of specific technological development through these phases and to indicate effects they have had upon society. In later chapters attempts will be made to follow some threads forward to determine what their future development will be. These topics have been chosen for discussion because of their universal importance in all cultural change; because they strongly impact behaviour (and thus tend to generate many basic ethical questions), and because they are particularly important in understanding the fourth civilization.

Technology and Food

18

Page 19: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Increases in food production efficiency have been closely associated with great societal transformations in the past. The transition from hunter-gatherer to agricultural society depends entirely upon the recognition that food can be obtained more efficiently through effective management of limited land areas (farms). Further, rapid improvements in food production must take place simultaneously with a nation's industrial revolution, for while one group of machines lures workers to the city, another must make it possible for the land to allow them to go.

Food production is fundamental to the existence of any organized social group. A nation whose people are starving will play no leading role on the world stage, and its very existence will be threatened if the food shortage is prolonged. When changes occur in soil fertility due to poor land management, climatic alterations, or the devastations of war, a people may find itself on the move in search of new land, or becoming absorbed by another group. They may simply starve to death, or they may go to war against their neighbours in order to take their food.

Particularly fertile land may have so many wars fought because of it that it becomes unusable, for its farmers may abandon it to the ravages of the fighting, and topsoil with no crop to anchor it may blow away. Also, fertile land tends to be concentrated in great river valleys and deltas, so some nations have much more of it than do others. Consequently, in times of peace, food-producing nations will trade in great volume with goods manufacturers from other countries, and the establishment of food trade routes and transportation facilities also becomes important.

Through to the mid- to late-industrial stage, whenever there is an abundance of food, populations increase at an exponential rate. However, the amount of arable land does not often increase; it may decrease with overcropping, poor management, and desertification. Therefore, development of technology allowing more food to be grown on a given piece of land has always been critical both to social stability and to progress to the next phase of civilization.

From stone knives, bone spears, arrows, and cutting and cleaning implements of hunter-gatherers, to the plough, sickle, and horse-drawn combine of the farmer to the modern collection of tractor-powered machinery, there have been steady improvements in techniques of food production. Today there is also a wide variety of fertilizers, pesticides, fungicides and other chemicals employed in growing food, and both milk and beef cattle are fed an increasingly artificial diet in an effort to squeeze the last gram of cream or hamburger from each animal.

At one point during a period of slow change in food production techniques, Thomas Malthus (1766-1834) became convinced that population would always tend to grow faster than the food supply. He was pessimistic that this could have any other result than mass starvation in the near future. The fact that the world's food supply supports far more people than Malthus thought possible is due to two factors: First, for a considerable time, the more sparsely populated Americas absorbed large numbers of Europeans, and even today their vast cereal-growing lands provide food in great quantity for countries that have not been able to grow their own. Second, technology has provided more and better varieties of food animals and cereal grains, and this has had a particular impact in places like India,

19

Page 20: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

which now produces a far larger proportion of its food than previously. Indeed, subsidies to farmers in Europe and the United States had, even by the mid 1980s (and the trend had continued), produced such a food surplus as to suggest modern famines may be more the result of a failure of political will to feed everyone than of any actual food shortage. Today, more people are fed by fewer people working less land than a century ago, and this trend, too, shows no sign of slowing.

These developments do not mean that Malthus was entirely wrong; they just postpone an inevitable shortage of arable land to some time in the future. After all, at any given level of food technology, it seems there ought to be an absolute upper limit to the population the planet can support. Yet, it can never be assumed at a given time that the upper limit of all possible food production technologies has been reached.

Technological optimists are convinced that ability to produce food will continue to keep pace with (or be only just behind) population growth. They also observe that factors like urbanization mean that more people live in a context where having children confers little advantage (unlike on the farm) and assume that reduced birth rates will eventually stabilize total population.

Pessimists are ready to forecast imminent mass starvation. They are sure that the world's population will pass (has passed) the ability to provide food long before it stabilizes. Whatever the case, the transition to and progress of the next civilization will require the food problem be met and resolved on a continuing basis. Because food is a fundamental need, its provision is closely related to a number of other areas, and it will be necessary to return to aspects of this issue at several later points.

Technology and Energy

Primitive societies were little concerned with this class of problems. A warm fire sufficed (where this had been discovered), and people walked unawares over future Middle Eastern oil fields, the Athabaska tar sands, the British coal deposits, and the Texan gas deposits. Later, human labour (including slaves), animals, wind, and water were the power sources of the agricultural age. Additional forms of energy were necessary to provide the enhanced life-style of farmers and seafarers, for their ambitions to tame the environment had grown beyond the ability of mere human strength to fulfil them.

The industrial age required vastly more energy than had ever been consumed before. England became a leader partly because she sat on a mountain of coal, and there was no reluctance to fill the land with soot and smoke in the name of progress. Today, natural gas and oil have proven cleaner and more convenient, but all three continue to be used at an ever-increasing rate. These fuels, plus water power, nuclear fission, and alternative energy sources, are used to generate electricity, which serves industry simultaneously as an energy source and a means of energy transmission. The advent of the information age will not decrease the total need for energy, for there are more people and they have higher expectations for a life-style of abundance than ever. More goods than ever need to be produced,

20

Page 21: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and even if all people were to work in offices while the factories were filled entirely with robots, manufacturing would still require energy.

New sources will eventually be required as old ones are exhausted, and there will be proponents of a variety of replacement energy technologies, including solar, geothermal, tidal, and nuclear fusion. The "high touch" culture--with its concern over the quality of life--demands safe, clean, and renewable energy sources, and therefore some of the old ones may pass out of common use before the resources on which they are based become depleted.

However, cleanliness and safety both carry price tags. No matter how great the desire for both, there is a point beyond which further progress toward such goals is uneconomic. If the perceived cost of a power source--in monetary, energy, or human terms--exceeds the expected return, it will not be used. In North America, this had, for example, happened for nuclear power by the mid-1980s, though subsequent political and economic developments could change this decision

Every civilization requires energy--and the advanced need more than the primitive, witness the rolling blackouts of energy-guzzling California in early 2001. Per capita energy consumption throughout the world is liable to increase for many more years, so technologies that provide it will continue to be critical.

Technology and The Environment

At the hunter-gatherer stage, the environment determines the available technology, and to a great extent, the cultural responses to technology as well. A people with no access to copper will not have a bronze age, and those who live in a favourable climate with plenty of game may never have the motivation to become farmers. If fish are available, people take their food from the water. If neighbours have desirable products, a people may either go to war and take what they want, or develop a trade. Technology used to overcome the environment is limited to clothing, shelter, and simple hunting tools.

To a great extent, environment determines the technology of an agricultural society as well. Soils and climates can support certain crops and cannot support others. Grapes cannot be grown in the far north, nor wheat in a rain forest. However, during this phase, there is a gradual increase in the stock of tools designed to allow the farmer to overcome the limitations of environment.

The industrial age, with its great faith that humankind could master all through machinery, saw an about-face in the relationship between man and the environment. Technology became a tool to overcome and to exploit the Earth, rather than simply a means to better live on it. Pollution was not merely accepted, it was pointed to with pride as a visible sign of great progress--the smell of money. It was only realized very late in this period that no life could survive on a poisoned planet.

Each society has had to live in its environment and to manage it appropriately to ensure survival. The hunter who killed all game within hunting range had to relocate, and so did the farmer who exhausts the soil's nourishment through poor cropping practices. The industrial age has seen the greatest impact on the

21

Page 22: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

environment, with dramatic changes to the land, the forest, the air, and even to near space around the planet.

A continuation of these uncontrolled changes to the environment on the scale seen in the industrial age may eventually render the Earth uninhabitable. For example, if the so-called "greenhouse effect" causes the climate to warm enough to melt the polar ice, many large cities would vanish under the oceans, and much of North America would become a desert. If temperatures go the opposite way, others would disappear under sheets of ice. If acids from the burning of coal and oil continue to pour down upon crops and forests all plant life could die. If the rest of the Amazon rain forest is cut and burned for short-term subsistence farming, atmospheric oxygen levels could drop substantially. The enterprising pessimist may choose from these and many other bleak futures. The entire Earth is involved, so it would be difficult for its multiplied billions to secure new living quarters if the current ones become uninhabitable.

In the information age, new possibilities exist to make informed choices with respect to the environment, and to manage the quality of air, water, soil, and climate. The knowledge that a problem exists and the techniques to solve that problem can be communicated and implemented rapidly throughout the world. Of course, the will to make the necessary changes and pay for them is less easily transmitted. This situation also illustrates how use of one technology may eventually require that another be developed to repair side effects of the first--a theme that will be discussed further in Chapter 7. Suffice it to conclude for now that a major task for the citizens of the fourth civilization will be to learn how to live with the environment and manage it well.

Technology and Health

The systematic practice of medicine is a late development in human history. The first physicians had little knowledge of anatomy and none about the causes of disease. They relied on what would today be termed "folk remedies" for their cures. For instance, a common technique for centuries was "bleeding" the patient to let out supposedly diseased blood, a practice now known to be harmful in most circumstances. The Romans maintained a staff of army doctors whose anatomical knowledge and surgical skills became quite advanced, but their work had little effect on the common citizen, who was at constant risk of death from disease and such simple problems as appendicitis. Disease theory developed in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries and such practices as sterilizing surgical instruments, quarantining sick patients, and eliminating unsanitary conditions made an important contribution to increasing life span.

Some of the most important advances of modern medicine were the development of vaccines and antibiotics. Diseases such as smallpox, polio, typhus, yellow fever, diphtheria and tuberculosis that once killed millions of people, have now been eliminated entirely or have had their effects greatly reduced (though TB is on the rise again). Continuing improvements in sanitation, particularly in Western cities where sewage is enclosed instead of running in the streets, have also contributed to an increased chance of surviving childhood and beyond.

22

Page 23: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The use of antibiotics, coupled with the later development of hormone treatments for birth control (the "pill") had a profound effect on sexual practices, particularly after the mid 1950s. Many people had already abandoned religious notions of eternal consequences for promiscuity. Now, they were also freed from such temporal consequences as pregnancy and sexually transmitted diseases. As a result, the public perception of morality was redefined to fit the new freedoms and sex came to be marketed as recreation instead of being seen as part of the old social, religious, and moral contract of monogamous marriage. Whether the private behaviour of people changed as consistently as the public view of it is more difficult to assess. Both those who were fundamentally committed to the old moral standards and those who had never followed them no doubt acted as they always had. Others followed public opinion, and adopted a new life-style, for the perception of what constituted normal behaviour was now the opposite of what it had been. Of course, the medical story of the early 1990s was the failure of technology to provide fast cures for the new venereal diseases of herpes and AIDS, and the consequent abandonment of some aspects of the sexual revolution, at least for the time being (and at least in public). Moreover, by the end of that decade, a number of strains of bacteria had become resistant to antibacterial drugs, leaving researchers scrambling for replacements as infection rates notched upwards.

One could use the sexual revolution and its effects to argue that modern medicine had a negative impact on both morality and religion. However, one could as easily blame modern communication and transportation technology, claiming that by being in touch with other societies and their values, the people of the West first came to take first a relative view of both, and then simply to discard them altogether.

Paradoxically, medical practice itself has its roots not just in the desire for survival, but also in the ethical impulse. There have always been strong moral (and often religious) convictions associated with the development and provision of medical facilities for the masses of people who have not previously had them. This behaviour--not so much one of self-interest, but of compassion--has been at the heart of medical missions and humanitarian aid to undeveloped nations, disaster relief, and universal medical care in the industrialized world and elsewhere.

The practice of medicine has also meant the average age to which people in all nations may expect to live is higher than it has been in recorded history, and there is a better opportunity than ever for an individual to survive serious disorders such as cancers, brain tumors and heart diseases. However, longer life spans mean more people, exacerbating food and housing supply difficulties. In addition, medical services are still not well distributed, and accessibility remains a problem in many parts of the world. Improvements in medical technology shift the balance of population (to the young at first, and then to the old). They also tie up expenses resources in facilities and trained people, costing more money, and affecting what can be spent on other things.

That is, changes in medical practice have wide repercussions in the entire society in which the new techniques are employed. Such interconnections of medicine with society and public policy are well expressed by an important principle of interdependence that applies to many other situations as well:

23

Page 24: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is impossible to do one thing.

The modern challenges to medicine, if met, will cause new and dramatic changes in the ways people live, in how many of them live, and in how long they live. Some of these changes will be examined in a later chapter.

Technology and Warfare

The first stone tool developed for clubbing an animal could also be used for hitting its inventor's neighbours over the head and taking their food. Bow and arrow or spear could hunt both animals and men. Carts could carry produce to market, men to war, or captured enemies back to slavery. Black powder could clear stumps or fire cannonballs. Ships could carry trade goods or an invading army; and simple machines could pump water or become battering rams.

The same technology that produced tractors also builds tanks. That which made airplane passenger and mail service possible also created aerial warfare and firebombing. The telephone lines by which one "reaches out and touches" far-away relatives also carry military orders. Satellites can either transmit communications over previously sealed borders, or spy on the enemy living there. Nuclear energy is used to produce power, radioactive medicines, and unlock the secrets of matter itself, but could destroy the world in a few hours. Chemistry can produce healing medicines or develop the tools for warfare to kill millions.

Every technology has the potential both to improve living conditions of human beings, or to harm them. Some complain bitterly because devices made for peaceful use are twisted into weapons of war. Others point to civilian spin-offs of military technology as sufficient justification to pursue the arts of making war.

Human history presents an unbroken record of nation coveting nation, of peoples hating peoples, and of the endless making of war to realize such destructive ambitions. Whether caused by shortages of food or land, envy over another's prosperity, racial or religious hatreds, or competition over trade routes, there have always been wars. Those involved have always sought out and used the highest available technology for killing the enemy. A nation that lost one war due to inferior technology, if allowed to survive, could always rebuild, create new weapons, and try again. That is:

It is impossible to fight one battle.

More generally, no inventor or technological innovator in any field can ever foresee the consequences for either peace or war of a particular idea or device. All technology has consequences for society and for subsequent development of new technologies. This leads to other statements of the principle of interdependence:

It is impossible to have one idea.

It is impossible to invent one thing.

24

Page 25: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This version could be made more general than these specific (and useful) statements as follows:

It is impossible to think one thing.

In nuclear weaponry, humankind now has the technology that could not only kill every person in the world, but could also sterilize it of life altogether. Since wars normally result in the highest available technology being used, the task facing humanity today is nothing less than the elimination of war altogether, for the human race cannot survive a new global conflict. With the fall of the Soviet Union, and the collapse of its military apparatus, the potential for superpower warfare has been greatly diminished, but the probability remains high that those same weapons will find themselves one day in the hands of others with more hatred and fewer scruples. At the same time, because the war industry is an important factor in the economies of many nations, survival will also mean social, and economic change. The fundamental urge to survive will also mean that the new civilization will be different in its view of humankind and of the appropriate use of technology; the popular ethics of war will change to reflect the price of war.

Profile On ... Decisions and War

A Few fateful decisions affecting World War II

Decision: In the late 1930s, the Nazis, motivated by racial hatreds, decide to persecute the Jews. Scientists and engineers from all over Germany (including Albert Einstein) are forced to resign their positions. Many leave the country.

Consequence: Allied nations receive an influx of highly intelligent and well-trained experts in the very fields critical to development of technologies needed to win the ensuing war. Einstein is influential in the decision to develop the atomic bomb.

Decision: On September 29, 1938, Britain's Neville Chamberlain abandons his promises to Czechoslovakia and agrees to Hitler's demand that he be allowed to annex large portions of the country. Hitler promises that he has no more territorial ambitions.

Consequence: Other parts of Czechoslovakia are annexed by her other neighbours. Germany not only takes over the remainder, but Hitler, emboldened by what he sees as weakness in Britain and France invades Poland as well, the action that triggers war.

Decision: In June of 1940, Nazi Air Marshal Göring launches the Battle of Britain, bombing major population centres to demoralize the British citizenry.

Consequence: Her industrial capacity all but untouched, Britain continues manufacturing airplanes that prove superior to the German ones, inflicting heavy losses on the Luftwaffe, and eventually forcing the Germans to accept defeat in the air.

25

Page 26: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Decision: In June of 1941, Hitler decides to break his secret pact with Stalin, and orders his army to invade Russia.

Consequences: (1) Cold winters, long supply lines, and the Russian army bring the Germans to a halt within sight of Moscow. As the Germans are pushed back, the misadventure weakens the German army, forcing Hitler to fight on two fronts.

(2) Blaming his generals for the defeat, Hitler dismisses them and assumes personal command --a task that proves to be beyond his ability.

Decision: Despite steadily worsening relations with the Japanese, the United States military command decides to ignore the early December 1941 warnings of an Imperial fleet mobilization in the Pacific.

Consequence: Japan surprises the American fleet at anchor in Pearl Harbor on December 7, 1941. Much of the U.S. Pacific force is destroyed in the sneak attack, and Japan has a free hand to expand her empire throughout the South Pacific for the next two years. To this day, there are some who claim this was a deliberate ploy by high U.S. officials to gain public approval for entering the war.

Decision: In August of 1945, the Japanese government decides to ignore American warnings about their new and destructive weapon.

Consequence: Reasoning that the cost in lives would be much greater if an invasion of Japan were to be launched, the U.S. drops atomic bombs on Hiroshima and Nagasaki. The war ends, but at the cost of much of the population of both cities.

Technology, Transportation, and Communication

The ability to maintain a nation of any size is as closely tied to the availability of fast and efficient means of transportation and communication as it is to the provision of sufficient food. Indeed, as previously observed, these two are closely linked, for the food problem is one of transportation as well as one of production.

With every advance in the ability to move goods and people about or to transmit messages over larger distances, the effective size of the world shrinks and the potential size of nations (or empires) grows. The converse is true as well. For example, when the roads deteriorated after the fall of Rome, European peoples retreated into more localized communities. Not until centuries later did the resulting nations build empires again.

In this century, barriers of distance (for developed countries) have for all practical purposes ceased to exist. This does not necessarily mean the world will become a single nation politically, though it is in some senses already one economically. It must be remembered that familiarity breeds contempt, and enhanced communication and transportation facilitate killing one's traditional enemies as much as they foster understanding them.

Standard of Living

26

Page 27: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

There can be little doubt that people are for the most part better off in the material sense today than at any time in human history. Many of the poor are not so poor as they once were, and the world could probably feed all its people (for a while) if the political will existed to do so.

In Western nations, even the lower middle classes are wealthy beyond the dreams of ancient peoples. Typical citizens own or control their living space, can buy any kind of basic food (and many luxuries) and have several modern appliances (stove, refrigerator, washer, dryer, central heating) that do more work than a houseful of slaves or servants. Moreover, their leisure time is abundant, and entertainment industries are big business. There are inequities of course, for even in wealthy nations, the gap between the rich and the poor is great, and there are homeless people even in the most prosperous cities. There is also still a chasm between the rich and poor nations. However, there can be no doubt that technology has improved almost everyone's standard of living, and few would care to return to the days of poor nutrition, no medical care, high infant mortality and a thirty-year average life span.

Where are these trends leading? There are two very different views of the possible future, and the contrast between them illustrates the difficulties involved in attempts to look ahead.

The first is to suppose that if the standard of living continues to rise, there would eventually be no practical difference between the rich and the poor, for beyond a certain point the actual amount of wealth is more a means of keeping score than it is an indication of class differences. This is the most idealistic and optimistic view. It must be tempered by the observation that such progress has not in the past led to classless societies. It is much easier to imagine that there will merely come to be new definitions of class than that there will be no class differences at all.

A second is to suggest that continued growth will inevitably result in collapse. The more emphasis put on material goods, the less regard there would be for people, straining the bonds of society. Such concepts as duty could break down as people isolate themselves, become laws-unto-themselves, and live for their own pleasure without regard for others. Moral consensus could vanish. Having lost the glue that holds it together, society could dissolve into chaos. This is the most pessimistic view.

Those who hold to the cyclical views of history might subscribe to one of the bleaker two scenarios, whereas those who hold to some purposeful view of history may believe that society will remain cohesive even if both material goods and war-making abilities both increased without limit. The true course of future history is likely to contain some elements of both.

In any event, production efficiency for material goods cannot continue to raise the general standard of living without at some point causing profound changes to the way people view and use consumer goods. Just what these changes might be is unknown, though some possibilities will be considered later.

In addition, many now unknowable technologies and events will affect the future. The generation of the 1940s might have forecast changes due to, say, television, for it had been in the making for some time, and the example of radio

27

Page 28: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

was available. It would have been impossible to predict the effects of computers, however, for they were due to unforeseeable technical breakthroughs. Each generation of new technology contains such elements--ones that would seem magical to people twenty years earlier. By their very nature, aspects of tomorrow's standard techniques that are magic today are unknowable. What is more, wars, revolutions, stock market crashes, terrorist attacks, other monetary crises, shortages in commodities (such as oil), nuclear disaster, new trade patterns, changes in consumer preferences, political and religious scandals, and other factors also shape the society to come, determining what behaviour and attitudes are acceptable, what technologies will be pursued and used, and what ethical standards will be followed or discarded.

Moreover, one can never underestimate the power of general disappointment with and the desire to distance from the perceived failure or irrelevance of the values and activities of a previous generation. There is every reason to believe that this perception is particularly pronounced today, and that sharp shifts in the dominant world view are in the offing, with even more dramatic consequences for society and the technology it uses.

Summary

New technology has always had profound social effects. Moreover, technologies are not only linked to social change, but to each other. The pursuit of a given technological change will necessarily cause changes in society, in other technologies and--in typical feedback fashion--in the seminal technology itself. It would be well to restate the principle of interdependence once again:

It is impossible to change only one thing.

Finally, because of its central importance to the present and the future, it is necessary to consider the specific development of computing technology. For this, a separate section is warranted.

1.4 A Brief History of Computing People have long recognized the competitive advantages that could be

realized by having available more efficient data storage and computational ability. From counting on the fingers, to making marks on the walls of caves, to the invention of picture numbers, to the modern check or banknote, there has been a steady progression away from directly manipulating the objects computations describe and toward the use of abstractions to represent the originals. Mechanical devices have played an important part in this progression. More than one culture has come up with the idea of placing beads on a string (the abacus). In some places, these are still the preferred calculating device after several thousand years. A skilled operator can calculate the cost of a large number of purchases on an abacus much faster than most people can enter them into a calculator.

Some who have studied the ancient British monument known as Stonehenge have come to the conclusion that it was an enormous calculating device for making

28

Page 29: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

astronomical predictions. Other monuments left by the Babylonians, South and Central American Indians, and South Sea Islanders may have had similar purposes. The Scottish mathematician John Napier (1550-1617) devised Napier's bones and published tables of logarithms intended to simplify tedious arithmetic computations. These led directly to the wooden or bamboo slide rule, known and loved by many student generations prior to the development of inexpensive electronic calculators.

To the French mathematician and theologian Blaise Pascal (1623-1662) goes the honour of inventing the first mechanical adding machine (1642). It was based on a system of gears similar to those in a modern automobile odometer and was used for computing taxes. However, parts for the device could not be manufactured with sufficient precision to make it practical, and it never became widely used. About thirty years later, the famous German mathematician and co-inventor (with Newton) of calculus, Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz (1646-1716), made a similar but more reliable machine that could not only add and subtract but also multiply, divide, and calculate square roots. Many people improved calculating machines over the next century, and by 1900 they had an important place in government and commerce. But as late as the mid 1960s electromechanical versions of these calculators could do only basic four function arithmetic, weighed thirty pounds, and took up half a desktop.

Meanwhile, another idea important to the modern computer was emerging--that of the stored program or instruction sequence. This idea arose in connection with the development of automatic looms by the French inventor Joseph Marie Jacquard (1752-1854). First shown at the 1801 Paris Exhibition, these looms used a collection of punched metal cards to control the weaving process. The machine, with variations, is still used today, though it is now controlled by punched paper cards or tapes, or by direct connection to a microcomputer.

The first computer--a machine combining computational ability with stored programs--was designed by the British mathematician Charles Babbage (1792-1871). He worked on his "Difference Engine" for about eleven years before abandoning the project. Later, he designed a much more ambitious "Analytical Engine" that was intended to be an algebraic analogue of Jacquard's loom. Although Babbage even had a programmer for the engine (Lord Byron's daughter, Ada Augusta, the Countess of Lovelace), this machine was never constructed in his lifetime. Its concepts were not realized until 1944 when the Mark I computer was developed in the United States.

By this time, the punched paper medium had become standardized through the work of Herman Hollerith. He devised a card data storage and sorting system for the U.S. Census Bureau, which was first employed in the 1890 census. Hollerith left the bureau six years later to form his own company, the name of which was changed to International Business Machines in 1924.

Meanwhile, vacuum-tube technology had developed to the point where an electronic computer could be manufactured. The first of these were the British code-breaking devices Colossus Mark I and Colossus Mark II built in 1943 and 1944 for the British intelligence service at Bletchley Park. The latter attained speeds not matched by other computers for a decade. When the war was over, these machines were dismantled and their parts sold as surplus.

29

Page 30: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

At about the same time, the groundwork of a number of researchers in the United States came to fruition in the construction of the Electronic Numerical Integrator and Calculator (ENIAC) by J. P. Eckert and J. W. Mauchly at the University of Pennsylvania. This machine, which contained over 18,000 vacuum tubes, filled a room six meters by twelve meters and was used principally by military ordnance engineers to compute shell trajectories. In subsequent years, many similar computers were developed in various research facilities in the United States and Britain. Such devices, which generally were limited to basic arithmetic, required a large staff to operate, occupied vast areas of floor space, and consumed enormous quantities of electricity.

Eckert and Mauchly were also responsible for the first commercial computer, the Universal Automatic Computer (UNIVAC), which they manufactured after leaving the university. Their company was eventually incorporated into Sperry (now merged with Burroughs to become UNISYS), which still manufactures large industrial computers. Today, those early vacuum-tube monsters are referred to as "first-generation computers," and the machines that are their successors are called "mainframes."

The transistor, developed by Bell Labs in late 1947, and its improvement during the early 1950s, was designed to replace the vacuum tube, reducing both electrical consumption and heat production. This led to miniaturization of many electronic devices, and the size of typical computers shrank considerably, even as their power increased. Transistorized machines built between 1959 and 1965 formed the second generation of computers.

Price were still in the hundreds of thousands to millions of dollars, however, and such machines were generally seen at first only in headquarters of large research and government organizations. Even by the mid-1960s, not all universities had even one computer, and those that did often regarded them as exclusive toys for the mathematicians and research scientists. There were occasional courses at the fourth-year level, but freshman introductions to computer science had not yet become popular.

Invention of the integrated circuit dramatically changed things in the computing world. The first result was another, even more significant size reduction, for what once took up several floors of a large building now occupied a small box. The first of these third-generation computers was the IBM System 360, which was introduced in 1964 and quickly became popular among large businesses and universities This size reduction also resulted in the first "pocket" calculators, which appeared on the market in the early 1970s. Even at the initial price of several hundred dollars, these put into the hands of the average person more computing power than the first UNIVAC had possessed. New models proliferated so rapidly and so many new features were incorporated into the pocket calculator that one company decided to have a chip designed that would allow it to program new functions so as to cut down the time necessary to bring a new model to market.

The chip, called the 4004, gave way to the 8008, and then to the 8080 and 8080A. The latter became the backbone of the new small-computer industry, as numerous companies developed kits and fully assembled computers. In its later incarnations by Zilog as the Z-80 and other descendants, such as the 8085, 8088,

30

Page 31: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

8086, and now the 80186, 80286, 80386, 80486, Pentium, and P6, this invention lives on in millions of microcomputers. Not long after the 8080 became a commercial reality, Motorola developed the 6800 chip, which had the advantage to programmers of being cheaper and somewhat easier to work with than the 8080. It, too, became popular for a time, but soon gave way to other designs.

At about the same time the Z-80 was developed, the 6501 and 6502 chips were derived from the 6800 as low-cost industrial process controllers. In 1976, the 6502 was also used to build a small computer, this one entirely contained on a single board. It was called the Apple, and Apple Computer Corporation went on to sell millions of the Apple ][ and its descendents, the ][+, //e, //c and //GS, surpassing all other manufacturers of small computers in the process, and becoming the sole source for nearly every important advance in small computer technology for two decades.

In 1977, Radio Shack joined the competition with its Z-80 based machines. In Europe, the equivalent popularizing role was played by Commodore (a Canadian company) and by Sinclair (a British firm). A few years later, IBM came into this market with the 8088-based PC. The mere presence of the giant changed the whole market for a time, with most other manufacturers seeking to make machines compatible with those of IBM. Eventually some of these "clone" makers, such as Compaq, became a larger presence in the market than IBM itself. By the late 1990s, the machines generating the most attention were capable of storing more and manipulating larger numbers than anything previously seen in the microcomputer market. They were also capable of handling processing requirements of the graphics user interface (GUI) first realized in the Xerox Star, Apple Lisa and Macintosh, then in Commodore's Amiga and Atari's machines, and now employed by most computer users. Integration of circuits had now reached the point where millions of components were being crammed into a single chip. Between 1987 and 1991, major new commitments were made by Apple with the Motorola 68030 and 68040-based Macintosh models and by IBM with their OS/2 machines. With the latter, IBM also followed Apple's lead into graphics-oriented software, helping to ensure this style of interface a continuing acceptance in the marketplace. Graphics user interfaces were also adopted by the makers of scientific workstations such as those made by Sun Microsystems, and were being attached to other machines running the UNIX operating system.

In the early 1990s, Microsoft, already the dominant manufacturer of operating systems for Intel 80x86 chips and of applications for both these and Macintosh platforms, began to market a GUI called Windows that was a rough copy of the Macintosh Operating System. The courts ruled, however, that it was not a close enough imitation to fall under copyright law, and Windows (in various flavours) gradually became dominant on Intel based machines (sometimes now called "Wintel" systems).

By 1995, Apple had formed partnerships with Motorola and IBM to develop new microprocessor technology and was already marketing machines based on the new PowerPC RISC chip, while IBM was porting its operating systems to the new chip as well. The two were readying new operating systems and preparing specifications for a common hardware platform on which to run them. Apple had licensed its

31

Page 32: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

operating system and the first Macintosh clones were appearing on the market--some from very well known consumer companies such as Motorola. Micrcomputers had become powerful enough that the minicomputer category had been all but crowded out of the market on price/performance considerations.

By 2002 Microsoft had moved through Windows 95, 98 and NT to Windows 2000 (ME). The world had also seen the demise of OS/2, and the migration of the MacOS to a new UNIX-based OS (NextStep, later rebuilt and renamed OS X) developed by Steve Jobs--the once ousted co-founder of Apple. At the same time, Apple had transitioned to the RISC-based G4 PowerPC chip and was offering machines whose raw processing power would once have placed them in the supercomputer category, Meanwhile, in its lower priced line, Apple had made computers into fashion statements, an innovation others were also quick to copy.

While much of the marketing activity and most headlines focused on the microcomputer segment of the industry, larger machines had undergone startling changes also. Fourth generation supercomputers could be used in situations where calculation complexity or data quantity is so great as to be beyond the ability of ordinary mainframe devices. These machines are used by governments, the military, and in academic research institutions. Still newer generations of computers are on drawing boards in the United States and Japan, and many of the new developments will undoubtedly filter down to become consumer-oriented devices in the future. At the same time, however, desktop computers, with their ever-faster chips and larger memories, were encroaching on application domains once thought to belong only to supercomputers.

At the opposite end of the scale, pocket sized computing devices had also become important. These ranged from the DOS or Windows-based miniaturized version of the desktop sibling to the specialized personal time and communications organizer (Personal Digital Assistant or PDA). Also called the Personal Intelligence Enhancement Appliance (PIEA) these devices boast handwriting recognition, wireless communications abilities, and sophisticated time management functions. Apple's Newton was a key player and innovator in this market, but the 3Com/Palm Pilot eventually took it over.

For most applications in the near future, however, microprocessor-based computing devices will have sufficient power to suit the majority of individual, academic, and business uses. They are inexpensive, easy to link (network) for sharing other resources (storage devices and printers), and they run languages and other programs similar to those found on mainframe computers. Much development work (particularly in programming and publishing) is being done with microcomputers in view, and it is safe to predict descendants of these machines are the ones most people will be referring to when they speak about computers in the future.

Larger machines will also continue to grow and change, as will organizations depending on them. Moreover, computers of the future will be as different from those of today as these are from ones of the late 1940s. They will be smaller (down to pocket size), faster, and with greater storage capacity. They will be integrated with video and communications technology to give immediate access to worldwide databases. They will undoubtedly become easy to use, and at some point the need

32

Page 33: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

to offer university level courses in their operation will cease, for they will have become common technical appliances.

So broad and diverse have the applications of electronic processors become that "computer" seems a misnomer, for the machines in which such devices are embedded spend little time calculating, and much more finding, organizing, preparing and communicating data. In this respect, the Internet, especially the portion known as the World Wide Web (WWW) has become a kind of prototype for the universal distributed library of the future, and most organizations have connections, for e-mail if for nothing else.

Computers have already profoundly changed many of society's institutions (business, banking, education, libraries). They will have even greater effects on institutions in the future. They have also raised or caused new ethical issues, and these will need to be addressed in the interests of social stability. In addition, developments in computing have affected or given rise to other new products and methods in a variety of fields, further demonstrating the interdependence of ideas, society, and technology.

There are microprocessors in stereos, televisions, automobiles, toys and games. Entertainment and telecommunications industries are heavily dependent on new electronic technologies. Computers themselves are directly attached to research instruments that gather and interpret data in basic physics, chemistry, and biology experiments. The resulting changes and advances in scientific research have also caused profound effects on society and its institutions. They have resulted in new social and ethical questions being raised, whose very asking could not have been anticipated in the industrial age. These include issues relating to software copyright, data integrity, genetic engineering, artificial intelligence, displacement of human workers by robots, how to live in and manage an information-based society, and how to repair damage wrought in the industrial age.

Technical trends and possible social and ethical consequences will be examined and extrapolated in more detail in later sections of the book. It is at least possible to conclude at this point that advent of the fourth civilization (aka "the information age") is owed more to the modern computer than to any other single invention of the late industrial period.

1.5 Forecasting the Future It has already been observed that events constituting history are understood

in the context of both motivation and technology over a time continuum. Similar considerations apply to attempting to predict the future--that is, forecasting what might yet happen to society as a result of current and new technology and motivations. On the one hand, the flow of events perceived to date may usefully be projected forward, if this is done in a reasonable fashion that takes into account the most likely results of that flow.

On the other, few modern day forecasters can claim the authority of Biblical prophets, who correctly predicted events in complex detail (and sometimes names) decades or centuries ahead of time. Today's forecasters rely on extrapolating ahead the trends of the recent past, rather than on Divine revelation. Therefore, all such modern attempts at long-term prophecy will fail, at least in part, for they cannot

33

Page 34: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

take into account the human-unforeseeable watershed events and decisions that result from creative departures from tradition, and that change a technology and its society quickly and dramatically.

Who could have forecast the uses of electricity, the internal combustion engine, or atomic energy, even ten years before their discovery? Who can take into account the serendipitous discoveries of ten years from now, or the result of, say, a narrow election win or loss on the people governed? Who knows exactly how today's decisions and discoveries will be applied to change the course of society a year from now? Because of such uncertainty, all forecasting implies considerable speculation, even when it appears to be a straightforward extrapolation. Indeed, given the recent history of political and technological change, assuming that things will continue according to current trends may be the most unreliable speculation of all. Any one of the alternative futures proposed by today's forecasters may indeed come to pass--or none may.

Speculation about the future is actually necessary for progress, for scientific, technological, economic, and political breakthroughs are all impossible without the application of a lively imagination to possibilities no one else has seen. Noted speculator and science fiction writer Arthur C. Clarke (Prophets of the Future) has this comment on qualifications for a successful predictor of the future:

I would now go so far as to say that only readers or writers of science-fiction are really competent to discuss the possibilities of the future.

This claim may produce indignation, especially among second-rate scientists who sometimes make fun of science-fiction (I have never known a first-rate one to do so--and I know several who write it). But the simple fact is that anyone with sufficient imagination to assess the future realistically would, inevitably, be attracted to this form of literature. I do not for a moment suggest that more than one per cent of science-fiction readers would be reliable prophets; but I do suggest that almost a hundred percent of reliable prophets will be science-fiction readers--or writers.

There are also those who expect a day when forecasting of at least the broad outlines of future society (and perhaps many details) will become possible--even commonplace. Perhaps the best known fiction with this theme is Isaac Asimov's Foundation series of novels. Asimov portrayed a day when "psychohistory" has become a science, and the future is indeed forecastable. Though it is not possible to dismiss such a possibility altogether, the advent of such techniques is surely a long way off (A discussion of the concept also appears in Michael Flynn's An Introduction to Psychohistory). It would also be foolish to assume that a technique for predicting future history could be developed without the forecasters becoming the managers of that history, influencing critical events to make the outcome better--at least in their own eyes.

This book also deals with many speculations about the future. Most are attempts to determine which outcomes of technology are likely, based on historical

34

Page 35: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

experience and existing trends. That is, this work is more concerned with extrapolation than it is with speculation. However, some things are new, or are yet at the research stage, and it is difficult to make predictions with any degree of confidence. This difficulty has not stopped others from publishing their ideas, and there now exists a rich literature of future scenarios, aspects of which will be discussed in more detail later (along with new ones).

Visions of the Future

One of the earliest classics in the field was Jacques Ellul's The Technological Society, published in 1965. Ellul had a clear vision of the tragic aspects of the technological revolution. He saw society losing what had made it truly human, blundering rapidly down unexplored paths, following guides competent in narrow technical fields but in little else. Ellul was not afraid of technology, but felt that its material promises were empty, that its faith had come to be in progress for its own sake, and apart from a higher standard of living, there was little for the human spirit to celebrate in the new age. Although his comments were made in the context of the old industrial age and its failures, many others have expressed similar views of the information age since that time.

One of these is Theodore Roszak, long a critic of the goals of artificial intelligence research, whose 1986 book The Cult of Information is subtitled The Folklore of Computers and the True Art of Thinking. Roszak castigates many other modern writers as members of an unthinking cult who have made "information" into what he calls a "godword". He desires to re-establish a clear distinction between what machines do when they process data, and what human beings do when they think--a distinction that he feels has been incorrectly blurred by others. Here is Rozak's view of some of the technological optimists:

We might almost believe, from their simplistic formulation of the information economy, that we will all soon be living on a diet of floppy disks and walking streets paved with microchips.

The most optimistic views of the future come from such as Alan Toffler (The Third Wave), John Naisbitt (Megatrends), Grant Fjermedal (The Tomorrow Makers), Harry Stine (The Hopeful Future) and Eric Drexler (Engines of Creation). All of these are willing to foresee many new and better potential worlds resulting from current and projected technologies. A society of plenty, the colonization of space, near immortality, and the removal of class barriers are among the predictions that these and other writers make. They are in a long line of philosophers who believe that Progress is an inevitable upward flow in the state of human affairs. Progress has become a quasi-personalized idea--as have Gaia, Nature, Evolution, Love, and Justice--invested with qualities that resemble those of a deity. Things will always get better, wars are only "mistakes" in the flow of progress, and technological solutions will always be found to all problems.

35

Page 36: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is not hard to find data to support such optimism. After all, much of what was science fiction in the 1950s is now a reality. Space flight, cancer cures, information utilities, nuclear power, robots, and many other once fanciful ideas are now taken for granted. Of course, far more of the old predictions have yet to be fulfilled, and perhaps never will be, but the most optimistic in the scientific and technical community often seem to believe that a permanent utopian civilization is within the very grasp of humankind.

Profile On ... A technological optimist

G. Harry Stine is well known among readers of futurist publications for his unabashed confidence in the future. The selection below, from The Hopeful Future is typical of those who believe in Progress to solve problems through new technology. The chapter title for the section from which this is taken is Enough Energy for Everybody to do Everything

The human race has never run out of energy or had a real energy shortage.The human race will never run out of energy or suffer from an energy

shortage.As Caoanda observed, we're surrounded by energy. In the past when human

beings faced the possibility of exhausting or exceeding available energy supplies, thereby creating an "energy crisis," they discovered new energy resources and learned how to use them. Each time, we worked our way out of an energy crisis by developing new energy sources and technologies. If the trends are reliable--and there's no reason to suppose they're not--we'll also work our way out of the current energy crisis . . .

Forecasts about limits to growth are based on specific energy resources and have assumed no future technical developments. Technology defines resources. Waterwheels made water into an energy resource. Steam engines did so for coal. Internal combustion engines did the same for oil.

At the time forecasts about an energy crisis are made, inventors are already quietly developing the new technology that will develop new energy sources within twenty-five years and, within fifty years or less, will completely displace the older energy technology.

Current technologists completely miss when they forecast how we'll work our way out of an energy crisis. For various reasons, they discount or neglect to consider the role that new technology will play in less than twenty-five years.

Technologists prefer to improve familiar technology by a fraction of a percent than to gamble on a major improvement from unfamiliar technology. They manage to make marginal improvements in old technology just before it is made obsolete by new technology.

On the other hand, there is also a rich popular literature of apocalyptic visions of the future--visions of imminent disaster. These see no hope at all for humanity or for earth. If it does not perish in a nuclear holocaust, everyone on it will starve to death when all arable land has turned to desert or poisoned. Perhaps all will freeze

36

Page 37: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

when air pollution becomes dense enough to block the sun and lower the temperature, or die of heat when the "greenhouse effect" increases it instead. Alternatively, life could all dissolve in acid rain, perish from hard solar radiation when the ozone layer disappears, or even be destroyed by a superior race of aliens. Not a year goes by without a forecast of global economic collapse, nuclear conflict, or the provision by some would-be prophet supplying a date on which Jesus Christ will return and God is supposed to end the world, despite the Bible stating this cannot be done.

No conclusive evidence can be cited for any of these extreme scenarios. The kind of future expected may depend more on the predictor's personality than on the analysis of today's trends. The optimistic technologist says there is hope for the future; thoughtful philosophers worry that humanity has lost more than gained; and the doomsayers have given up all hope. In the midst of this uncertainty and contradiction, others have tried to find spiritual answers to difficult questions. Some have turned to mystical claims that meditation can bring on a new order; others to the Biblical answer that God the creator alone determines the fate of the universe. Some may see such a refocusing as another manifestation of the tension and balance between the high touch and the high tech. It may be regarded as part of a struggle for liberation of the human spirit from the perceived bonds of the machine age. It may be a holding position while people await more definitive data from the scientific community, in which their long-term faith resides.

The actual near future will likely fall somewhere between utopia and apocalypse. New and existing technologies need to be examined both for their potential to improve the human condition, and for their potential to cause harm. Part two of this book concentrates on the various technological revolutions and the direct effects they may have on society, and part three focuses on the roles of certain major institutions. It is worth noting, however, that if any modern day seers (including the author of this book) really knew what the future would bring, there would be far more money to be made in the stock market than in writing books.

1.6 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

There are a variety of views about the meaning of history and whether it is a purposeful and controlled unfolding, or a series of fated cycles. To be useful, accounts of history must be interpreted in a flow from the past through the present. With some care, its lessons might be extrapolated to forecast the future. History is influenced strongly by the motivations of the people who make it, and by the technology that they use. Its events in turn shape ideas and technology for the next generation.

Although many divisions in history can be identified, those useful to this text are:

o Hunter-gatherer (the first civilization)o Agricultural (the second civilization)

37

Page 38: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Industrial (the third civilization)o Information (the fourth civilization)

Many nations are now well into the fourth phase, and the transition is being accompanied by broad changes in society and technology, as well as by a lively new interest in ethical issues.

Specific examples of the historical development of certain technologies include:

o Technology and foodo Technology and healtho Technology and warfareo Technology and transportationo Technology and communicationo Technology and standard of living

The brief history of modern computing gives an indication of the way in which this particular technology has developed and become a powerful influence on society. Much of this text is concerned with such mutual influences, and many of these will be developed further in later sections.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. If you are reading an account of some event in the past, what clues could you look for in the narrative to determine how factual it is? In particular, how does a falsehood or exaggeration distinguish itself from the truth? How does a mythical account distinguish itself from an historical one? How could you spot possible distortions designed to favour the author's political, religious or economic theories?

2. What are some of the external sources to which one could turn in an attempt to verify a historian's account? Describe as many as you can think of, and comment on their value.

3. Consider Caesar Tiberius and Jesus Christ. Do library research to find out for which of these two there exists more complete and reliable documentary evidence to verify the historical accuracy of the main events of their lives (This could be a rather extensive research project). Now also comment on the extent to which such evidence is actually accepted by scholars and by the population in general.

4. What effect, if any, did the invention of the printing press have on the industrial revolution? On society in general?

5. This chapter speaks much about interplay of motivations (especially ethical), technology, and the events of history. From your own knowledge or research, provide examples of important historical events that hinged on (a) a specific application of technology; (b) a moral/ethical or political decision by a key player in the event.

6. Which do you think is more nearly correct: that societies develop in the way they do because of technological advances, or that technological advances take place because the society in which they are made is ready for them?

38

Page 39: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

7. What were some of the effects on family life as a result of the industrial revolution?

8. If you (a product of the industrial/information age) were suddenly thrust into a hunter-gatherer society to make your way with no technological help, what would you do to survive?

9. If the plough is the key invention for the agricultural society, and the computer for the information society, what can be said of the industrial society in this respect? Is there a single piece of technology that can characterize the whole age? If so, what is it? If not, why not?

10. Write a history of the automobile, focusing on its effects on the economy and society of the Western world.

11. Write an account of the effects of television on Western society.12. Write an account of the effects of computers on Western society.13. Some material in the chapter focuses on particular turning points in

history. Try to imagine how the world's history would have been altered if certain events had not occurred. Write down what the major differences in today's society and technology would be if:

a. the Romans had built a practical steam engine from Hero's model. Could an industrial revolution have taken place in A.D. 100 ?

b. the Mayans and Incas had both discovered the wheel and begun to use animal-drawn carts centuries before the Spanish arrived. (What if the Europeans had met a civilization stronger than their own?)

c. half the munitions factories built in the United States before the Civil War had been in the South, instead of (virtually) all in the North.

or the South had followed up at the battles of Bull Run, pursued the defeated Union army, and taken the undefended city of Washington, D.C.

d. England had been overwhelmed by Germany in the Battle of Britain.e. Lee Harvey Oswald had missed, and John F. Kennedy had lived to be re-

elected.14. The text mentions some turning points in World War II. What were some

others?15. What is the importance of studying history for our present day society? for

the future?16. There have been many who have attempted to prophesy the future. Look

up one or two of these from before 1990 and assess the extent to which they succeeded or failed.

17. Try to obtain one of the supermarket "tabs" annual issue of psychics' prophesies for the ensuing year. Describe these and say how many came true during the following year.

18. The Western notion of prophesy comes largely from the Bible.a. What does the word "prophet" mean in the Biblical context?b. Make a list of at least twenty prophesies, both the making and fulfilling of

which are recorded in the Bible.c. Make a list of at least twenty Biblical prophesies that do not appear to have

been fulfilled as yet.19. Write your own prophesy of the next ten years of technology.

39

Page 40: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

20. Look up the Gutenberg project. Who is it named after? What are its goals, and why is it important (or not)?

21. The text attempts to formulate a principle of interdependence. Explain this, and try to reformulate it in other words.

22. Make a list of the ten most important turning points in history and explain why each was so important.

23. Make a list of the ten most important current problems that could be turning points in an account of our history written in the future.

Bibliography

Asimov, Isaac. The Foundation Trilogy. London, England: Octopus Books, 1982 (first pub. 1952, 1962, 1964)

Barraclough, Geoffrey. Turning Points in World History. London, England: Thames and Hudson, 1977.

Beres, Louis René. Apocalypse--Nuclear Catastrophe in World Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.

Burke, James. The Day the Universe Changed. Boston: Little Brown, 1985Bebbington, David. Patterns in History. Leicester, England: InterVarsity Press,

1979.Cetron, Marvin & O'Toole, Thomas. Encounters with the Future: a Forecast of

Life Into the 21st. Century. New York: McGraw Hill, 1982.Clarke,Arthur C. Prophets of the Future (second revised edition). Bury St.

Edmunds: St Edmundsbury Press, 1982Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press, 1986.Durant, Will and Ariel. The Lessons of History. New York: Simon & Schuster,

1968.Flynn, Michael. An Introduction to Psychohistory. Analog April 1988 p 60 - 78

(Part 1) and May 1988 p38 - 64 (Part 2)Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers. New York: Macmillan, 1986Hardison, O.B. Jr. Disappearing Through the Skylight--Culture and Technology

in the Twentieth Century. New York: Viking Penguin 1989Hodges, Henry. Technology in the Ancient World. New York: Knopf, 1970.Lower, Arthur R.M. A Pattern for History. Toronto: McClelland & Stewart, 1978.Montgomery, John Warwick. The Shape of the Past. Minneapolis: Bethany,

1962.More, Thomas. (tr. Ogden, H.V.S.) Utopia. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts,

1949Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner Books (pb), 1984.Naisbitt, John & Aburdene, Patricia. Megatrends 2000. New York: Morrow,

1990.Orwell, George. Nineteen eighty-four. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin,

1964Project Gutenberg. <http://www.prairienet.org/pg/& Larsen, Judith K. Silicon

Valley Fever--Growth of High Technology Culture. New York: Basic Books, 1984.Roszak, Theodore. The Cult of Information. New York; Random House, 1986

40

Page 41: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Schaeffer, Francis A. How Should We Then Live. Old Tappan, NJ: Fleming H. Revell, 1976

Shuurman, Egbert. Technology and the Future--A Philosophical Challenge. Toronto: Wedge, 1980

Sutcliffe, Richard J. Introduction to Programming Using Modula-2. Columbus: Merrill, 1987Sutcliffe, Richard J. <mailto:[email protected]

Chapter 2The Foundations of Science and Technology

Seminar - "I Don't Understand - What is Science?" 2.1 The Kinds of Knowing 2.2 The Nature of Scientific Enquiry 2.3 The Role of Abstraction 2.4 Science, Technology and Technique 2.5 Science and Technology--Practice and Practitioners

41

Page 42: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

2.6 The Technological Society? 2.7 Summary and Further Discussion

2.1 The Kinds of Knowing

Logos

One of the most important of philosophical questions has to do with the meaning of "knowing" (epistemology). That is, what does one mean by such statements as "I know this is true", or "We hold these truths to be self-evident"? The answer to meaning questions like these depends very much on culture, on discipline, and the thought system of the one who is the alleged "knower", for there are a variety of ways to regard this concept.

In the tradition represented by certain of the ancient Greek philosophers such as Plato, and as later reinterpreted by such as Rene Descartes (16th century), the highest and most reliable form of knowing was the most abstract (including the mathematical), for knowing is equated with the result of reasoning.

True ideas, once appropriated from the realm of the divine and put into the transmittable form of words by logical argument and rhetoric, were termed "logos," and this too had an element of the divine about it. Taken to extremes, the science of this philosophy consists of logic alone and logic judges everything else, including the physical world. What cannot be brought into this process is either uninteresting or suspect. Applications of the pure science of thinking to the physical world, including the development of technology, was regarded as unimportant, and even beneath the notice of the philosopher. Knowledge is thought of as an end in itself rather than a means to develop physical products.

For instance, in this view, the god who created the universe was not just unknown, but unknowable, unless he would deign someday to send to mortals a logos (word) to reveal himself--a task that John assured them had been fulfilled in Christ (John 1).

An example of this kind of knowing is the statement "two plus two equals four." The truth of this statement seems to depend on universal ideas independent of language or the notation in which they are written and so this truth is knowable absolutely (within the context of the usual real numbers). This is true regardless of whether it is written this way, or 2 + 2 = 4 or II + II = IV, or deux + deux = quatre.

Such knowing also includes lines of reasoning such as:

All women are mortal.Nellie Hacker is a woman.Therefore, Nellie Hacker is mortal.

The conclusion is held with confidence (given the premises), because the rules for such a logical process are regarded as infallible.

Logic is important in itself, and its study worthy as a prerequisite for all disciplines, for all scholars need to be able to think clearly and correctly. However, taken to extremes, there is no truth but logic alone, and it judges everything else,

42

Page 43: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

including the physical world. In this view, anything else is at best uninteresting, perhaps suspect, and may not be knowledge at all. In the most radical view, applications of the pure science of thinking to the mechanics of the physical world, including the development of science technology, are unimportant, even beneath the notice of the philosopher. Knowledge is thought of as an end in itself rather than a means to generate practical applications or products. Why should the Greek thinkers have built steam engines? Did it not suffice to demonstrate their theoretical possibility?

Empiricism

Another kind of knowing is that derived from experience, or, as Aristotle would have said, from the substance a thing has (including its potential properties) rather than from its abstract form. That is, this kind of knowing is practical, not just theoretical. Such is the knowledge derived when the scientific method is applied to the physical world.

One could also express this in terms of data and information. Data consist of the raw facts of a matter, so far as these can be ascertained; information is the meaning attributed to those facts by some community of appropriately informed experts.

o That Canada has a $700 billion debt might be a fact; whether one should conclude that the country is on the verge of bankruptcy (and what to do about it) is a matter of interpretation.

o That a political leader has been pursuing secretaries sexually may be factual; whether anything can or should be done about the matter is a consequence of interpretation within a value system, including the values of political priorities.

This (empirical) kind of knowledge depends utterly on the ability to gather and interpret evidence from the physical world. It also depends on the ability to give meaning to that data and communicate that meaning reliable to other people. That is, the data and the consensus on the information it conveys together constitute "knowledge" in this realm.

o The fossils dug from the earth provide a factual record of dead organisms; the meaning of that record depends on its interpretation, for no human alive has actually seen the creatures who left those bones. This is true of all history, the moreso if sufficiently removed from the present.

It is important to realize that the consensus of experts that is at some point called "knowledge," is always in process and may be wrong. Indeed, "knowledge shifts" are not at all uncommon. A theory might be taught as universally accepted fact for many years, only to be later (and perhaps suddenly) replaced by a contradictory one. However, as long as one realizes that what is called knowledge in this data/information sense is an approximation and a moving consensus, it is still possible for those involved in a particular field to say they "know" a lot of things. With some refinements, this is the model for knowledge actually used in the sciences today.

While modern scientific thought has roots in the rationalism of ancient Greece, it owes its current form to modifications made first by Renaissance

43

Page 44: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

humanists and later by the materialists and logical positivists of the nineteenth century. The sphere of modern science is the systematizable, the organizable, and the empirically investigatable. It is not always possible to tell what belongs in this sphere, nor is it always possible to induce knowledge of absolute truth from instances investigated by the senses (Because stones fall to the ground more quickly than feathers does not mean that it is the nature of heavy objects to fall faster than light ones). Thus, there must always be an element of doubt and incompleteness to science. Karl Popper believed that doubt expressed the very essence of the scientific method: "It must be possible for an empirical scientific system to be refuted by experience" (The Logic of Scientific Discovery) Absolute verification was not the issue to Popper, but potential falsifiability by empirical means was. Scientific results could be thought of in terms of probabilities of truth, but this was the best knowledge a scientist could have.

It is important to note, however, that doubt implied by potential falsifiability is not of the existence of the reality being investigated. Rather, it is doubt that current descriptions of that reality constitute the final and most accurate word on the subject.

Extremes of Empiricism (1)--Positivism

Some of its most radical philosophers have taken empiricism to other conclusions. They have held that the experience of human senses suffices to describe the entire knowable universe. For them, the supernatural is specifically defined out of existence, as is everything not approachable with the standard methodology of science. In short, if it is not science, it is not knowledge. That is, while such moderns do not disdain practical applications of their intellectual achievements, some tend to scorn anything not achieved through a particular kind of mental discipline.

Extremes of Empiricism (2)--Deconstructionism

In a departure from the classic Greek reverence for knowing as a pure abstraction, knowledge is sometimes today held to be almost totally experiential--even to the point that material phenomena are held to exist only as they are perceived. For example, some modern philosophies of physics hold that if a tree falls in a deserted location, and there is no one to hear it, not only is there no sound, but the tree continues to exist in both fallen and not-fallen states until an observer comes along to trigger it into one or the other condition. Should a century go by meanwhile, the second state could exist in an instant, complete with old, decayed wood as soon as the first traveller came that way. That is, human observation is not only necessary to give the physical world meaning; it actually creates the physical reality to observe--the very existence of an objective reality is radically doubted; no objective truth exists; and its place is taken by whatever a person perceives to be the case or wants to be the case (deconstructionism again).

Empiricism and Practical Science

44

Page 45: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Whether they believe experience describes real-world phenomena (most practising lab scientists), or that observations create the events they purport to describe (some theoreticians), there is still a general belief among scientists that all data is acquired through the senses, and becomes knowledge only as it is filtered by the intellect. This approach is useful, provided everyone involved realizes the relative truths it produces are determined by specific intellectual filters, with not all views equally valued or listened to in the process. Every society has certain dominant, ruling, or control paradigms that set its intellectual agenda and provide it with its characteristic way of looking at the world. When these reigning paradigms undergo a shift, some old knowledge ceases to be, and other things come to be placed among the "known" (The false becomes true, and vice-versa).

o Scholars once "knew" that the earth was the centre of the universe; today they "know" otherwise.

o Intellectuals once "knew" that God created the world, but most today say they "know" it came about by chance, evolution, and natural processes.

There is another problem with taking radical doubt too far. Is the proposition "nothing is real" itself real? David Stowe (Popper and After: Four Modern Irrationalists) makes the following points about this approach to knowing:

(1) It implies that human knowledge has not been increasing--a proposition that seems at variance with actual recent experience.

(2) It implies that all of the potentially infinite number of world views are equally valid, and so every kind of physical law or theory is equally as improbable as, say, a logical self-contradiction. Thus knowledge is impossible. This, says Stowe, is irrational, and neither can nor does provide a working philosophy for scientists.

However, the scientific method does depend on the idea that knowledge gained by application of the senses has to have its truth content measured by reliable standards and that its acceptance depends upon informed judgements. For example, the statement "objects released in air fall to the Earth's surface" is universally attested as true by the experience of every human being. The statement "the sun will rise tomorrow," is very nearly in the some category. However most people must accept "the Earth is an oblate spheroid" on the basis of evidence gathered by others, for they have no means of performing the relevant experiments. Likewise, only a few can verify "napthalene has a molecular weight of 228.30." That is, the reliability of all these knowledge statements is subject to human judgement. Yet, they all seem to imply that there is an objective reality to judge. Other factors also influence the truth value of statements made from empirical evidence; these will be discussed in more detail in the next sections.

The Contrast with other Fields

The arts and the humanities of the Western World, by contrast, are based on a more subjective tradition. Their heritage is culturally characterized by a strong Judeo-Christian influence (as redefined by the Reformation thinkers) and influenced to a somewhat lesser extent by materialism. Though humankind is still given central place in modern Western versions of these philosophies (again, most notably in the

45

Page 46: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

humanities), humanity is not regarded as a mere observer, evolving by chance and whim in a purely mechanistic universe. Rather, humanity is part of a whole that is greater than the human mind or senses can comprehend and may therefore obtain and use that which may legitimately be termed "knowledge" quite apart from experience as an observer in the scientific sense of the word. An artist, musician, or writer (fiction or non-fiction) also uses reality filters to make a statement about the world and a personal response to it, but these filters are not identical to those of the research scientist, though they are of a similar kind.

In this tradition there is a tendency to view the material world as a limited and incomplete or even flawed manifestation of realities that go beyond physical perceptions of the physical universe. This is certainly true among religious thinkers, though such a view is found in other disciplines as well. For instance, modern art and music--perhaps in partial reaction to the success of the sciences--have both moved away from interpretations and depictions of the physical world, and have come to concentrate on representing the emotions of the artist or releasing raw emotions from the audience. In common with the deconstructionists of the written literary work, these practitioners have moved to the notion that there is no reality in their work apart from the experience of responding to it. Thus, their connection with the physical world has diminished even as the threshold of artistic activity needed to release the raw emotions of the audience has gone up.

It is important to realize that a statement such as "this is the best piece of writing (art, music) of the year" is a true observation about the speaker's own interaction with the work. Even if no other person agrees, the statement is no less true. That is, some knowledge can be highly personalized. Even the box office success of a work is not a statement of absolute merit. Rather, it is the aggregate of many such instances of personalized knowledge, or to use the common term, of "taste."

Intellectual Multiculturalism

C. P. Snow in a 1959 lecture later published as The Two Cultures, postulated there had come to be a division of intellectual activities into two distinct categories, with scientists in one, and almost everyone else in the other. Snow detected deep and sometimes bitter animosities between the two groups. Each had its own view of what constitutes knowledge, how it is obtained, and what are the ethics of applying it. What is worse, the depth of division between the two camps is directly proportional to the sophistication of the technology developed by the one, and to the despair of the other that it will never have the power to control it. There were people who could travel in both circles, but they almost had to become different persons when they moved from one culture to the other.

Some fourteen years later, Jacques Ellul (The Technological Society) expressed a more comprehensive view of the situation. He saw the technological mindset (if not strictly the scientific one) becoming overwhelmingly powerful, sweeping all other forms of thought away--becoming not just dominant, but the only way of thinking. Technique (i.e., efficient method) is in his view irresistible. Every task or discipline has a most efficient technique that eventually emerges, develops

46

Page 47: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

fully, and destroys anything of lesser efficiency. All humanity will ultimately be caught up in a kind of amorphous technological totalitarianism extending over every aspect of life--one that cannot be avoided because of its claim to maximal efficiency.

Meanwhile, a group of intellectuals known as deconstructionists promoted the radical rejection of the idea that objective truth and meaning exist. They claimed both were lacking even in written words because only at the experiencing of interaction with a text was meaning generated in the reader, and because this could never be shown to be universal, the text had no meaning in itself, even if one was intended by the author.

What antinomians did for the study of morality, deconstructionists in general did to epistemology (the theory of knowledge), for there was nothing that could be said to be known any more.

With despair over the perceived dominance of technique reinforced by the parallel deconstruction of truth itself, many intellectuals were left viewing humankind as shorn of purpose, hope, and values--its very humanity simultaneously deconstructed of meaning and sold for a technical lentil stew.

Attempts to liberate technique by reconstruing it within a framework of meaning--such as Schuurman's 1972 book Technology and the Future--underscore the feeling among philosophers that the technological boat had set sail for destinations unknown and left both them and the human spirit behind on the shore.

Indeed, by the mid-1980s, Allen Bloom (The Closing of the American Mind) could lament that the battle seemed lost. In their obsession with technology, he believed that Americans had entirely lost sight of the humanities, but especially of philosophy and even of logical thinking. For Bloom, philosophy had become a voice crying in an academic wilderness: no one was interested in hearing it, and none were qualifying themselves to do so. Even science had given way to the demands of the marketplace, relinquishing its claim to be a pure discipline. He recommended returning students to the rigor of the classical Greek thinking as an antidote to the sloppiness he detected in modern approaches to knowledge. His critics have not been certain that Bloom's criticisms are valid, or whether any such return is possible. (The sharpest opponents of an important role for philosophy in education claim it is irrelevant to economic reality, adds no understanding of the physical world, and thus is not worth studying.)

In like manner, Charles Sykes (Profscam) claimed that the university become captive to professorial vested interests, neither doing research nor teaching well, and offering a form of education that had little value for any but foreign students. A spate of similar books joined the attack on the relevancy of the university enterprise in the eighties and early nineties.

In more recent years, as high technology has become easier to use, artists and writers have embraced the new machines as a means to their own ends, and are now among the most enthusiastic and demanding users of computers. It is interesting to ask whether this phenomenon is a refutation of Snow, a vindication of Ellul, a further point of lament for Bloom, et al, or something else altogether.

It is also worthwhile to observe that an atmosphere of despair is rather unstable, for it presents opportunities for new infusions of hope into the mix,

47

Page 48: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

perhaps from unexpected directions. This observation may explain the increase in interest in spiritual answers being given to the truth and meaning questions by the end of this period.

As noted in Chapter 1, some optimists see no loss at all in becoming an overwhelmingly technically-oriented society, for there are manifest benefits to many technologies. Still, doubts and questions remain--are there no other valid ways of "knowing" other than by science? Must not empirical (scientific) sense-based knowledge forever remain an approximation or interpretation of a reality of which it cannot be known that it is absolutely known? Finally, is a technological society rich or poor in human values?

Belief

Another model for knowledge is that of a belief widely, sincerely and reasonably held. Beliefs rest on some evidence for the thing believed so have an empirical aspect. However, most people use "belief" in a slightly different way than they do "knowledge." Things "believed in" are generally considered to be less secure in their foundations, and perhaps less widely held to be true than things said to be "known." That is, a small group (or one person's) certitude that something is true, based on what others might regard as incomplete evidence, is termed a belief, while a more general consensus about something is termed knowledge. Of course, a belief, however widespread, is not necessarily true just because it is sincerely or widely held--it could be sincerely wrong in all the holders. On the other hand, scientific knowledge is not always true either--it is sometimes shown to be wrong after having been defended as absolutely true for a protracted period of time. One could even conclude that all knowledge is based on shades of belief.

The adherents of some religions, Christians included, would add yet another term, "faith," by which they would mean an absolute knowledge derived through a gift of God's revelation. Faith is knowledge that does not lose certainty because it lacks universal consensus or current empirical evidence. The idea is that God exists and knows all; humanity finds truth by paying attention to what God has revealed. As John asserts: "In the beginning was the logos, and the logos was with God, and the logos was God." (John1:1) He goes on in the same vein in an attempt to convince literate Greek readers that the otherwise unknowable God had now sent a revelation of Himself in Jesus Christ and so had become knowable in person.

In addition, much information about the universe God has made can also be found by a sufficiently careful examination--this is sometimes expressed as "thinking God's thoughts after Him," or "knowing God by his works." In the faith context, absolute knowledge is external to the human race--it is revealed rather than being discovered or invented. Thus, empirical knowledge (of things discovered or invented) cannot in this view be absolutely relied upon, for nothing can be known with the certainty of the things revealed. Neither science nor belief are therefore qualified to judge such knowledge; they are simply tools to enhance it.

In this theory of knowledge, there is no a priori conflict between the absolutes affirmed by faith in God's revelation and the approximations obtained by the senses (scientific). However, conflict does exist in practice for two reasons.

48

Page 49: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

First, there is the tendency for institutions to develop around the holders of faith. Such institutions then demand some of the faith affirmation for their own pronouncements, and these may touch upon empirical matters rather than on the revelation allegedly being safeguarded. Individuals find it far easier than do institutions to be simultaneously affirmers of the faith and seekers of empirical knowledge. Organizations can sometimes officially adhere to statements on matters peripheral to the original faith long after most of their (still faithful) members have abandoned those statements.

The second reason for conflict between faith and empiricism is that members of the scientific community often reject faith affirmation as inherently abhorrent, regardless of whether such matters are within their sphere of competence and training, and even though they themselves affirm a faith in and build institutions around a set of philosophical presuppositions.

One could summarize these difficulties by saying:

Religion attempts to answer questions about ultimate meaning; these and not the detailed workings of the physical world are its territory. That is, its theologians stray when they pronounce upon physics as much as do the philosophers of science when they speak the meaning of the universe.

Opinion

The last kind of knowing to be considered here is called opinion. This has the weakest claim of to the term "knowledge," and is also the hardest to define. Opinion is commonly thought to consist of positions privately and personally held to be true, and that can be so maintained without reference either to facts or to the effect of the opinion upon other people. Determining whether a statement falls into the category of opinion is extremely difficult. To disparage a statement by another, one may say: "That's just your opinion." There often seems little rebuttal from such a judgement, for it appears to rest on the democratic notion that all personal views are of equal value and equally likely to be true. Statements such as "it's too cold," "that was a good book," "God exists," and "killing is bad" could all be disparaged as "mere "opinion.

However, the first two of these are true statements about the speaker's reality--they are matters of taste, rather than of opinion in the casual sense of the word. The third is a statement of faith, and the fourth is about moral objects. These last two statements are surely more than private opinions, for they cannot be privately held and acted upon but are by very nature about relationships, for to act on them is to affect others.

If one tries to define an opinion as a claim about knowledge of which the speaker is unsure (e.g., "I think the bum is guilty.") then the statement is not directly connected to an external reality, however strongly stated. However, a statement of doubtful knowledge of the truth is eventually resolvable as to its truth or falsity, so it is related to facts, and is not just an entirely personal and private reality. What is more, people act on their views, so what are called opinions do affect other people, and their truth or falsity therefore matters to other people.

49

Page 50: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Thus, there may not be anything left for this category--what are called opinions are either another kind of knowing or else are meaningless (as far as truth value is concerned).

Summary

It would be far beyond the purpose of this book to analyse the shades of meaning of the "knowledge-terms" in any greater depth, or to present all the arguments concerning their correct use. Those interested should consult a good text on epistemology and one on systematic theology. Instead, in this chapter, a further examination of the notion of scientific knowledge will be undertaken. Comparisons with other disciplines will be made, and these may shed light on how scientific ideas develop and on the relationship between science and technology. Consideration will be given to the role of science and technology in the development of a society, and certain general technologies will be looked at with a view to their impact on the future.

2.2 The Nature of Scientific Enquiry One characteristic of humankind by which it distinguishes itself from all other

life forms is an insatiable curiosity about the workings of the universe. Societal conditions have not always allowed this curiosity to be indulged; even practical pursuits require wealth and a freedom from manual labour not available to everyone. Theoretical pursuits also demand toleration of investigators whose entire exercise may be mental, and whose results may mean little to the average person. The systematization of such work gives rise both to technology (or technique, as it might better be called) and to science. These are not the same thing, despite being closely linked in the present culture, and the purpose of this section is to give careful consideration to both, to see how they are related, and to investigate some of the scientific and technological influences on society.

Science

First, consider science, the more theoretical of the two. The fundamental premise of any discipline that is to call itself scientific is this:

The universe that is the object of a scientific study is sufficiently orderly to be in some sense measurable, testable, and at least potentially predictable.

That is, radical doubters notwithstanding, the doing of science seems to require at least the perception of a systematic reality in order to have something that it can be about. It is usually a simple matter to distinguish disciplines of a scientific type from those of most others. For instance, the creation of music, painting, sculpture, and the writing of poetry or novels are not generally regarded as scientific activities. These pursuits may have rigid rules for some aspects, but need no always, for their practitioners are thought to be free to present ideas and impressions without being bound by anything called reality.

50

Page 51: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is also possible, though more difficult, to distinguish science from the humanities (philosophy, languages, literature, etc.) and from the studies of society (sociology, anthropology, psychology, economics, etc.). In the latter group in particular, attempts are often made to apply scientific methods, but this may not be entirely successful. After all, it is not known whether human behaviour is predictable in the same manner as that of things under scientific study is supposed to be (except, perhaps, statistically). Although it is methodology (and not results) that determines whether a discipline is scientific, the method of science assumes an element of predictability, and it is not until some work is done that one knows if this factor is present. A discipline may use the methods of science on the assumption that they are appropriate, but it is only as those methods produce reproducible results that the practitioners gain confidence that they are indeed "doing science," and not something else.

It is easy to assume that scientific methods do or ought to apply to a given field of study. It is more difficult to discover how to make them apply (which is partly a matter of technique). It is harder still to demonstrate that the assumption was correct and the phenomenon being studied can be demonstrated by the methods being used to be predictable. Finally, if some apparently orderly pattern is discovered, these techniques shed no light on the source of the perceived order (or lack thereof.)

The case of Mathematics

The case of the discipline of mathematics is particularly interesting, for its philosophers can take one of two extreme (but not necessarily mutually exclusive) views:

o that mathematical ideas are entirely theoretical and speculative, with no necessary connection to the physical world

oro that mathematics describes things with a real existence.To put it another way: Do mathematical ideas come into being the first time

someone thinks about them (created by thought), or are they pre-existent (already in the universe) and only being discovered as time goes on? For example, the equation ax2 + bx + c = 0 (a, b, c are real numbers with a Did the quadratic formula exist before it was first written down by a human being, or has it always been inherent in the concept of number?

Although there are some who will hold out for the absolute truth of one or the other of these positions, mathematics actually has both aspects, for while the entities it discusses are on the one hand mental ones, these ideas clearly do on the other hand have some relationship to the physical universe.

o The concept of number is universal and pre-existent. God has always existed in three persons, for example. However, the numerals employed for the communication notation used by humans to express this idea are cultural inventions, not universal truths. Thus, the ideas contained in the assertion that 2 + 2 = 4 are inherent in the concept of number, and are not inventions. However, the

51

Page 52: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

notation in which the idea has been written is an artifact, for rather than "two" or "2," one could use "deux" or "II" without changing the meaning.

o The same is true of the meaning of the quadratic formula on the one hand, and any particular way of writing it on the other.

o The use of base ten numerals like 4645 to express the idea of 4000+600+40+5 is probably due to the vast majority of humans having ten fingers with which to begin learning to count. There is no a priori reason why one should not use a system founded on a base of two, three, eight, sixteen, or some other number. Indeed, one does use base twelve (dozens and/or gross) to measure quantities of eggs, buns, or hours, base sixty to measure degrees, minutes, and seconds, and bases two or sixteen inside computers.

o Pythagoras' Theorem on right triangles is true regardless of the way in which it is written out, and it unfailingly categorizes triangles as right triangles or not regardless of what any observer may think or how that observer might write the result down. It is true even if you call the things left triangles.

o Likewise, the interesting observation that the number 1961 reads the same right-side-up or upside-down is entirely a construct of the notation; it has no universal truth in itself. On the other hand, the idea of symmetry that this example illustrates is universal, and can be found wherever some object can be rotated or flipped onto a copy of itself.

o In a broader sense, this example illustrates the universal notion of complementarity found in such pairs of opposite ideas as: left/right, up/down, right/wrong, good/evil--all of which exist independent of the language that describes them.

Similar arguments can be made, not just for number theory, but for statistics, topology, algebra, analysis, discrete mathematics, calculus, transfinite numbers, and set theory. Although many of these ideas have appeared on the human scene recently, the very rationality of their interconnectedness argues that they are in some manner inherent and inevitable (part of an objective reality) and that they will certainly be discovered once one thinks long and deeply enough.

Who Can Understand Mathematics?

The difficulties in understanding the nature of mathematical statements are compounded by the fact that in all but the simplest cases one must be a mathematician in order to perform its mental experiments. A grade ten student in remedial (general) mathematics once said to me "I know everything there is to know about mathematics already; why should I have to take this course?" The sad fact was that he barely had acquaintance with the multiplication of fractions and had never heard of the aspects of mathematics already mentioned, much less of computational geometry, complex analysis, relativity, probability, combinatorics, or any of their applications--the chasm of his ignorance was unbridgeable.

That is, in this realm "truth" can only get informed consent--can only be understood--if one has sufficient training and experience in mathematical thinking to qualify as a member of the consensus. Not just anyone can comment meaningfully on mathematics, for to grapple with its ideas requires special

52

Page 53: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

knowledge and experience. Even among highly qualified mathematicians, embarrassing errors take place. For instance, a proof for a widely accepted theorem is sometimes later shown to be incorrect and either a new proof must be supplied, or the theorem may be shown to be false after all. In one celebrated case in the 60's and 70's a graph theory result was purported to have been proven in published papers by three successive writers, and all three proofs were subsequently shown to be incorrect.

One could summarize by saying that whether mathematical truths are created or discovered by mathematicians, they certainly cannot be discerned apart from the collective experience, training, and beliefs of the mathematical community, and this is not unlike the situation in the scientific community and in other disciplines. Specialized training is required to comprehend the ideas of a discipline.

That is, acceptance of mathematical and scientific results by most people, even those trained in another branch of the discipline, requires some degree of acceptance of the consensus of the expert part of community. This consensus, because it is an interpretation, is not necessarily true absolutely. For example, no matter how much a mathematical model for the first few seconds of the existence of the universe may be consistent with present-day scientific observations, acceptance of the model as a fact is a leap into faith, one that bears a great resemblance to that held by others in an all-powerful creator having made everything in six literal days.

Is Mathematics Certain?

In the latter part of the nineteenth century, a number of logicians showed that the standard methods of logic employed at the time led invariably to fundamental contradictions. For instance, consider the definition:

The barber of Seville shaves all the men of the city who do not shave themselves.

or, similarly

S is the set of all sets that do not include themselves.

Now does the barber shave himself or not? Is S a member of S or not? Unless one sneakily attempts to escape the logical trap by positing that the barber is a woman, a machine, or an alien, either answer leads to a contradiction. The existence of such contradictions introduces an uncertainty into mathematical logic itself, not just into the correctness of part of its consensus. That this uncertainty could not in any way be resolved was shown in 1931 by Kurt Gödel when he showed that no set of axioms used to describe a mathematical system could prove both the consistency and completeness of the system.

Consider, for example, the natural numbers:

N = {1, 2, 3, 4, ...}.

53

Page 54: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Gödel showed that, on the one hand, any set of axioms (rules) that could be used to prove all true statements about these numbers would necessarily be inconsistent (lead to contradictions like the one above). On the other hand, if the set of axioms is consistent (no contradictions possible) it could never be sufficiently complete to derive all true statements about the system. As Douglas Hofstadter puts it: "In short, Gödel showed that provability is a weaker notion than truth, no matter what axiomatic system is involved." (Hofstadter, p. 19)

As far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality, they are not certain; and as far as they are certain, they do not refer to reality.

--Albert Einstein

That is, unless one is willing to use logical tools known to be unreliable (potentially inconsistent), there are always truths about the number system that cannot be proven.

The same principle applies to computing, for one equivalent to Gödel's theorem (the undecidability of the halting problem) demonstrates that no machine can be built using logical systems that can process all problems, or even to determine ahead of time whether they will be successful in the attempt. Simply put, not everything knowable is computable. That is, human beings can know more than finite logical machines, no matter how elaborate those machines may be.

In a similar vein, it is not possible to prove with the rules of human logic that God exists (or that he does not). His existence may be strongly inferred or authenticated from evidence, but not proven in a logical or a priori sense.

Comparing Other Disciplines to Science

This concept of uncertainty is applicable to science as well because Gödel's Theorem applies to all logic when it is applied to infinite systems, and not just to mathematics. Science must also deal with the uncertainty that the closer something is observed the more the very act of observation changes the thing being examined, and so the less accurate the observations are.

Yet, the entrance of such uncertainties into the scientific realm does not create the difficulties for its practitioners that it might for theoreticians. After all, a researcher in some other part of the world with similar equipment needs only to be able to duplicate a reported experiment and obtain essentially the same experimental results within a reasonable margin of error. For science, duplicatible results are the important thing, even where there is no agreement about the interpretation (meaning) of the results.

Indeed, questions about ultimate meaning are not really on the agenda of science, and scientists who speak of them are no longer talking about their own specialities, but about those of others. The Nobel prize winning physicist who goes on the talk show circuit to proclaim there is no God has fewer qualifications to speak on that subject than a theologian does to declaim on gravitational field theory.

It is also important to note that other intellectual pursuits, such as religion, art, poetry, philosophy, languages, mathematics, and so on, while methodologically

54

Page 55: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

different, are organized disciplines in the same sense as are the various sciences. Each such field of study constitutes a recognized body of knowledge with its own rules, practitioners, and special methods of interpretation. In fact, one distinguishes a scientific discipline from the others precisely on the basis of its particular intellectual methodology, the rules for which serve both to define what is science, and to determine what are its appropriate fields of study.

The Scientific Method

A typical elaboration of the scientific method in five steps goes something like this:

1. Observe the universe in question, collecting raw descriptive data.2. Analyze the data, systematizing and interpreting it.3. Synthesize a theory (formulate a hypothesis) to explain the data, or

develop a model to illustrate it (i.e., create a mental abstraction of the presumed physical reality).

4. Test the theory or model under as many variant conditions as possible to determine the degree of correspondence between the abstraction and the physical universe.

5. Modify the theory or model and re-test it until it agrees with all the relevant phenomena. If a universal consensus is reached on a particular theory it might be promoted to the status of a "law."

This process might be summarized by saying that science is a search for true descriptions of the world by making logical inferences drawn from empirical data. Although this description of the scientific method would probably be accepted (with variations) as a working definition by the vast majority of those who term themselves scientists, one must realize that it is only a close approximation of what science is. A number of cautions must be added to properly explain it.

First, applying the method implicitly assumes the hypothesis is testable. Some are, some are not. Strictly speaking, the latter are not scientific, for if they cannot be tested they can neither be refuted nor verified.

Second, taking a narrow view of this process would exclude mathematics--a discipline that attempts to produce its results by logic alone. Yet mathematics not only provides the language, structure, and tools for systematic investigation, it also has reasons of its own to be applied to the real world. Mathematics is therefore inextricably intertwined with all scientific disciplines. Not only can no science exist without the language of mathematics to describe its investigations, but also the boundaries between applied mathematics and science are quite unclear.

The term "mathematical sciences" has therefore become common today, and few people are unhappy with the tendency to regard these disciplines as more a science than an art. That this acceptance somewhat undermines the working definition of science given above is of little practical importance to most scientists, for an exact definition of the field's overall scope has little effect on their specific work.

55

Page 56: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Third, whether mathematics is included or not, the definition given has one serious drawback: the tendency of some to regard scientific knowledge as the exclusive form of knowing, and to specifically exclude from the "knowable" category any results obtained by other methods. This philosophy, called logical positivism, asserts that logic combined with the empirical methods of science forms the only possible way to know things. It rejects the conclusions of other methods of enquiry as irrelevant--as not being knowledge.

While this view was widely held in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and some still try to defend it today, it has lost much of its popularity among philosophers. It is now realized that scientists do not operate exclusively within the empirical methods given above. On the contrary, as John Ziman remarks, "they tend to look for, and find, in Nature little more than they believe to be there, and yet they construct airier theoretical systems than their actual observations warrant." (Klemke, p. 35) This may overstate the case somewhat, but it leads to an important observation regarding the "doing" of science.

Scientists work within a world view.

That is, like everyone else, a scientist brings to the work at hand a framework of ideas about how things ought to work, a set of conceptions about why the world behaves the way it does, and a collection of goals that are regarded as desirable to achieve. All the scientist's work is done within the context of such a world view--it influences every decision and every step. Because of this, theory has a tendency to come before the collection of data and not as a result of it. Consequently, data is often collected under the influence of the theory that is supposed to explain it, and researchers are naturally inclined to reject data that does not fit. This process is not dishonest in any way; rather, it is human nature to observe and interpret the world in terms of what one already believes about it. A shared community world view also lends a consistency to the voice of science as it speaks to matters of public concern.

Fourth, this consensus in a scientific community tends to be remarkably broad, monolithic, and very slow to change. Unfortunately, this very consistency can sometimes hamper objective investigation and make truth harder to discover. The important insights and discoveries in any field often come about because the world view expands or changes to allow people to see things in a new way. Those who make this breakthrough may have a difficult time convincing anyone else to listen because a changed world view often forces people to re-examine matters previously considered settled.

Such "new views" are common in the artistic world. Each generation reflects its world view in its artistic creations, and may fail to communicate with the previous generation through these forms. Rock music, for instance, expresses a direct connection with the emotions, a raw "me-ism" that can be incomprehensible to those who do not share its context. Indeed, it could be argued that it is not the nature of some music to be comprehended--that both its medium and message are entirely emotional.

Examples of such paradigm shifts from the history of science include Galileo's heliocentric model of the solar system, the periodicity of the elements, atomic

56

Page 57: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

theory, radioactivity, Einstein's theories of relativity, and quantum mechanics. All were ultimately accepted by the scientific community, but each had difficulty at first due to the radical change in world view required to comprehend the new model.

This explanation is not intended to suggest, as some "new-age" philosophers do, that a new way of looking at things (a new model or paradigm) changes or becomes the underlying reality, a sort of ultimate "man is the measure of all things." Rather, it is to point out that the practice of science does not quite conform to the general view of its philosophy as expressed in the step-by-step scientific method. Scientists do assume an underlying reality, but they interpret or filter that reality, so their results partially depend on the nature of those filters.

Fifth, the results of scientific enquiry are always approximations, subject to reinterpretation in the light of new data that may be more exact, be collected in a different manner, or be interpreted with a different world view. There is also the possibility that new data will overthrow a fraud, a hoax, or a conclusion derived more from wishful thinking than from careful reasoning. For instance, a technician being asked to do radioactive dating of some sample might ask the supplier what range of dates are acceptable, and might not report any test results that fall far outside this range. The non-conforming results are obviously spurious. But, what if there another view that explains them as part of a consistent data set?

Another complication arises from the fact that many scientific workers engage in the building of highly speculative theories with little or no connection to actual data. This habit is particularly widespread among astronomers and others with an interest in the origins and mechanics of the universe as a whole (i.e., cosmologists). Such speculation is healthy, because it tends to open up many new lines for investigation. Scientists must speculate if they are to make any progress at all, for otherwise they will generate no hypotheses and be unable to do anything. However, this necessity of practice does illustrate that the boundaries between science and the more speculative or metaphysical disciplines are not always as sharp as is generally believed.

The Role of Consensus

These observations on the imprecise aspects of science lead back once again to the example of its ally, mathematics, for a better idea of what science is, if it is not just pure logic combined with rigid experimentalism. As mentioned before, mathematics relies on a community consensus of what is "true"--one that is not infallible, but that is at least a reliable determinant of what things are part of the discipline and of what constitutes a properly derived result.

In a way, the existence of this peer consensus is not unlike that of the high-diving or figure-skating judge who holds up a score card after each performance. The consensus of the group (i.e., the average scores) becomes the final judgement on the dive. The determination of what constitutes good science or good mathematics takes more people and a longer time (perhaps generations). It is nonetheless the result of a community examination of the work in question, and is a consensus of its value. It is even possible to quantify this agreement somewhat by counting the number of times a paper or book is cited positively in the

57

Page 58: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

bibliographies of later works--the higher the number, the more firm the consensus of worth. In view of the fact that the majority of published "research" papers are never once cited by anyone, those that are quickly distinguish themselves from the rest.

Looked at in this way, science loses none of its empiricism, precision or status--but it is seen as one among many consensual ways at arriving at an agreement about the way the universe appears to work. On the other hand, this view does cause science to lose some of the mystique and exclusivity that it has built up during its 150 year ascendancy over other thinking methods in the West, for this perspective places it in a continuum of disciplines, blurring the edges between it and other concepts of truth-seeking.

Other Considerations

The methods of science are also important in a variety of fields, (such as government or economics) where facts need to be gathered and interpreted for the benefit of the decision-making process. Scientific techniques can be invaluable in discovering "what is going on." Of course, subsequent decisions will always depend in part on values and evaluations not provided by the fact gathering process alone.

For instance, as the costs of techniques soar, decisions have to be made about what research to fund and develop, and what to delay or drop altogether. How much goes to AIDS research, how much to computing, how much to developing new fields, to transportation, to the environment, and so on? Such decisions raise political, economic, and ethical questions that scientific investigation cannot by itself answer. Moreover, there is no particular reason to believe that the conclusion about what should be done, when reached by a scientist, is any better or any more logical than the conclusion reached by a politician, or by the general public. Indeed, if a scientist takes pride in the belief that only empirical methods produce knowledge and everything else is erroneous or irrelevant, then the resulting ignorance of other thought processes, disciplines and people is more likely to produce a bad decision than a good one. Knowledge, thinking, decisions, and their consequences are interrelated. Science provides one of many methods of thinking and of obtaining knowledge; it is most effective when integrated with others as well. That is;

It is impractical to think one way.

One must conclude therefore, that the logical positivists, in seeking to exalt the scientific method as the only road to knowledge, actually restricted its domain and made it less useful than it could have been. In short, it is precisely integration with other ways of thinking that makes scientific methods generally applicable and practical. Such applications of science as well as the relationship between science and technology is the subject of a later section of this chapter. The next section is devoted to placing the theory-making of science into the larger context of a common thinking device.

58

Page 59: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

2.3 The Role of Abstraction Among the activities of scientists, the forming and manipulating of scientific

theories is important enough to warrant a discussion of its own. Theory formation is considered by some to be such a unique undertaking that it is the province a privileged few and has no parallels in other endeavours. However, like the scientific method as a whole, theory formation is an example of a broader and relatively common activity whose exercise is necessary for all citizens in a sufficiently complex society. Indeed, the ability to propose theories may be necessary for the formation of such a society in the first place.

What is an abstraction?

The Western Judeo-Christian religious tradition holds that God is capable of holding in his thoughts all the details of the fine structure of the universe simultaneously. This limitless knowledge and creative energy brought the universe into being in the first place, and now holds it together. Although not all agree that God even exists, much less is omniscient and all-powerful in this sense, no one seriously believes it possible for any human being to achieve such a universal awareness. Even mundane and ordinary objects (a chair, a tree, a cow, one human cell) are sufficiently complex to make such a comprehensive understanding impossible. It has been centuries since a single human being could have even a passing acquaintance with all the available academic knowledge, and it is now no longer possible for any person to comprehend the whole of any single discipline. Neither is it correct to assume that everything knowable about a given discipline has already been discovered, or ever will be.

Fortunately, it is not necessary to have such comprehensive knowledge about something in order to make appropriate use of it. One can enjoy a car ride without knowing how to drive. It is not necessary to be able to build an automobile in order to drive one, and not required that the workers building it be able to design it. The designers need not be able to produce the metals and plastics from which it is made. None of these must know how to refine the petroleum products required to run it. Road designers, builders, and mechanics occupy related specialists, and so do the legislators, sales people, auto company executives, parts manufacturers, and many others.

Each of these has different priorities for what they must know about the automobile. For each, there is an essential subset or extract of detail taken from all that it is available to know about the subject. Each views an automobile by focusing only on the details essential to a particular role, and needs only a cursory acquaintance with details important to others.

A similar process is at work in the formation of theories by scientists (and others). Here, it is clearly understood that no object can be comprehended in every detail down to the sub-atomic. It is the concentration on essentials and the exclusion of details that makes understanding manageable, and even possible. Such a process gives a researcher an intellectual handle on the subject that would be impossible if knowing everything were deemed to be the only adequate kind of knowledge. It is therefore possible to conceive of something by knowing an

59

Page 60: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

appropriate and sufficient subset of its properties. In this light, it is possible to offer the following definition:

Abstraction is the process of excluding or digesting details in order to concentrate on essentials.

One aspect of abstraction is deciding which properties are the sufficient essentials to the task at hand, and which are details that can be ignored. This decision very much depends on the community within which the abstraction takes place, for to be useful, an abstraction must not only be communicable, it must be communicated. If only one person understands it, but cannot transmit its essence to another, an abstraction has no practical use. Thus, the kinds of abstractions that come to be widely accepted depend on the level of knowledge and education of the community for which they are intended. For instance, a solar-system model for explaining atomic structure is sufficient for those who are not equipped to grasp the finer points of probability and quantum mechanics, but quite inadequate for researchers at the frontier of knowledge in the field. Likewise, there are a variety of models for explaining the workings of a modern economy, and these vary in complexity and usefulness depending on whose understanding is being addressed. The needs of most citizens are quite different from those of a politician making a decision, or those of a professional economist summarizing available information for that decision.

Other Abstractions

This process of attempting to explain a myriad of detail through an abstraction of certain broad outlines or essentials is not confined to the sciences or even to the academic disciplines that attempt to use the scientific method. Numerous examples are possible from all fields:

o A computer program is an abstraction of a problem solution into a specially devised symbolic language (notation).

o A chart or graph is an abstraction of data or relationships into pictorial form, in order to allow them to be visualized, and therefore understood from a different perspective.

o Words and numbers are symbolic abstractions of specific ideas.o A language (including a computing notation) is an abstraction designed for

the purpose of communicating other abstractions. It could be termed a meta-abstraction.

o Whenever someone learns a skill or a trade, the necessary activities and actions are abstracted from the task details. The skills become automatic, so they can be exercised without thinking about the details.

o The manufacturing/wholesaling/retailing chain is an abstraction that allows people to buy goods without having to make their own.

o All job specialization is a type of abstraction that frees people from excess complication, allows them to concentrate on a small number of useful skills

60

Page 61: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

themselves, and to deal with most of the necessities of life through other specialists in a similarly abstract manner.

o Money, whether expressed as precious metal, coin, paper, cheque, or electronically, is an abstraction for the wealth of nations, corporations, and individuals.

o A representative democratic state is an abstraction that allows individual input into the governing process without having to consider every detail of every person's stand on every issue.

o The Judeo-Christian understanding of God is an abstraction for one who is too complex ever to know entirely.

Thus, far from being the province of academics alone, abstraction is a process fundamental to all human activity. The totality of the abstractions used by a culture is an important measure of its complexity. The most sophisticated abstractions are those that allow people to perform complex tasks without much thought. For instance, the graphical interface found on modern computers allows the user to perform very complicated tasks with a minimum of effort (at a higher level of abstraction) by comparison with the verbal interface found on old-fashioned machines. Indeed, all computers are tools for high-level problem-solving--they enable people to make abstractions and avoid detail. Likewise, most industrial machines (and even bicycles) have to be operated abstractly--at a level of unconscious skill, for so long as the details must still be thought about, the task cannot be performed efficiently, if at all. (If you have to think about what you are doing, you fall off your bicycle.)

While one could criticize the process of abstraction over many levels as removing people from "real" understanding, it is precisely such distancing that gives abstractions their power. It is not necessary to understand how cheese is made in order to enjoy it. Neither is it a prerequisite to know how to make or program a computer in order to make productive use of it for such tasks as word processing or data analysis.

These examples illustrate that abstractions are the most useful when they are far removed from the thing being abstracted; when they have been refined to the point that they can be usefully employed by most people in an automatic fashion.

Other Names for the Process

So important and pervasive is the process of abstraction that it has a variety of specialized names arising from different disciplines and from the terminology adopted by the various people who have considered various aspects of this activity. Some of these equivalent terms are mentioned here, because they are of importance in later chapters.

A digest is a summary of that portion of data deemed by the one making the digest to be the most essential. It is an attempt to filter the data, removing the non-essential, redundant, or irrelevant. For instance, data reported from experiments are nearly always digested from the entire set obtained; this is necessary for brevity and clarity.

61

Page 62: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

A Model is a representation of something in a more concrete or accessible form than the original. It may be also used of a scale model for some proposed project. The term conveys the idea of explaining or showing by means of an analogy to something else that is supposedly better understood. (i.e., for which there are believed to be adequate abstractions already). The term modeling may be used by scientists to describe the process of theory formation.

Theory formation is an attempt to abstract into some simple statement the workings of the subject under study. This term tends to be less concrete than modelling, for a theory is an attempt to define rather than to model, though in practice the distinction may be a fine one.

A paradigm is also a way of looking at a subject by way of analogy or example. It too is a model, but this term tends to be used in a broader sense to describe abstractions of considerable importance or size (a collection of related abstractions). One example is the evolutionary paradigm, within which are many models for origins. Another is the Marxists' class struggle, to which view they bend all political science and economics.

A meme is a (perhaps indirectly perceived) transmittable idea that is the basis of a social movement or a political philosophy. Its spread through a population can be studied in a manner similar to that of an infection, because it is the nature of a meme to induce the desire to proselytize. A meme can be benevolent (e.g., the ideals of democracy), fatal to their holders (e.g., the Jim Jones cult beliefs) or fatal to others (e.g., Naziism and Stalinism).

A world view is a complete set of philosophic or religious presuppositions within which paradigms and individual abstractions are formed. It constitutes the total way in which a person does abstractions (thinks) about the real world, and generally finds its expression within the communities of which the person is a member. It encompasses the complete set of memes that a person possesses and spreads. One may speak, for example, of a scientific world view, of a Christian one, of a liberal one, or of an American one. Within each of these there exist numerous specific views of parts of the world.

It would also be instructive in this connection to observe that some media make use of word pictures and of various figures of speech to evoke a much broader point (poetry is like this; so are many aspects of the Bible). Likewise, other media make use of visual pictures to convey a broader message (television commercials are like this). In both cases, a more subtle form of abstraction is being used to transmit actual ideas that are related to or suggested by the formal communication.

The mention of some abstraction term, theory title, or world view name, evokes in the hearer a vision of a set of beliefs, views, or typical activities. That evoked image will invariably be to some degree inadequate or incorrect, especially if the hearer is not a part of the community that devised or is described by the abstraction. When such a misconception takes place, it is often because the hearer holds to some popularly believed ideas about the group in question, in which case the hearer's own (mistaken) abstraction is called a stereotype.

62

Page 63: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Thus such words as "fundamentalist" or "immigrant" or "liberal" or "Christian" will generate in the hearer a collection of related impressions whose semantic meaning depends on what that person has abstracted under the term in question. This is not to say that the deconstructionists are correct and that no message has an absolute semantic; it is only to observe that communication requires agreement on the meaning of abstractions.

Plants and animals do not make abstractions; this is a uniquely human activity. Abstractions make thinking and communicating possible. They make it possible to understand the world and its processes, whether by science or otherwise. They make it possible to make, to build, to specialize and to cooperate. They are therefore the essential building blocks, not of science alone, but of human civilization itself. This section concludes with an attempt to abstract itself:

Abstractions are never the "real" thing, and therein lies both their power and their usefulness.

Abstractions are intellectual creations; they are not discoveries.

Abstractions are approximate and relative perceptions or descriptions, not precise or absolute realities.

Before looking at how the making of abstractions bears on the meaning of science, it is instructive to consider also the relationship between theory and practice.

2.4 Science, Technology and Technique

The Relationship Between Science and Technology

One way of defining what is meant by technology is to view it as the handmaiden and the child of the doing of science--as the practical adjunct to theory. In this popular view, science serves as the tool to discover the rules by which the universe operates, and technology provides the eventual payback for all the investigative work. This way of looking at the relationship between science and technology has elements of truth, but can be misleading. It is one thing to create a model to explain, say, electromagnetism. It is quite another to use the theory to make an actual product such as a radio, a television, or a computer. The kind of thinking that goes into applying the principles worked out by scientists to the making of real products is quite different from that which goes into discovering such principles in the first place.

This can easily be seen when one realizes that science is essentially an inductive and theoretical process, wherein one examines many actual instances in the real world of some assumed underlying order and attempts to find a general structure for those instances. The development of technology, on the other hand, involves a deductive or tool-making mentality, by which one derives specific applications of general principles. Perhaps the best way to distinguish between the

63

Page 64: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

two is to say that science is concerned with why things work, whereas technology is concerned with how to make something work, that is, how to do something.

The fundamental motivating factors are also very different. Pure science can be driven by the desire to know, or by intellectual passion, and requires very little more. The motivation may be pure curiosity; it may be a desire to "think God's thoughts after him," or it may be to "become like God, knowing all," or it may be anything between. As in mathematics, pure science may have an inner cry to be applied (the cry may come from a funding agency), but the researcher need not be personally interested in such aspects. Work in basic science can be done for the same reason that climbers scale Mt. Everest--the challenge is simply there.

On the other hand, the drive to build tools (technology) comes from the need for better and more efficient ways to get a job done. People innovate to better feed themselves, to defend themselves from attack, to become more effective aggressors, or to gain some other competitive advantage. They build higher, faster, wider, cheaper, and more beautifully than the last person and what they have built fulfils a need and may increase their wealth. They may even do it to help other people achieve their full potential, or because they believe that God ought to be honoured in the full use of their talents to benefit others. They may not even be able to articulate a reason why they build, except to say that they enjoy tinkering.

One other difference between the two should be noted, and that has to do with methodology. Since technology is required even in the absence of scientific knowledge, it often uses trial-and-error methods. For instance, it is difficult to predict what the physical properties of an alloy will be just by knowing those of the metals to be mixed. The constant search for lighter, stronger, or more ductile alloys cannot wait for science to provide a working model to explain what will happen when a given collection of metals is mixed in specified proportions, for such a theory is a long way behind the need. Rather, metallurgists actually mix different combinations and then test the properties of the alloys they produce. They may use only general rules of thumb based on past experience and not require a unifying theory. This procedure may lack in pure theoretical beauty, but it gets the job done, and that is what technology is all about.

Because many of the technological advances of this century have depended on science, it is easy to forget that the creation of tools goes on independently of science--even (to a great extent) in its absence. Moreover, each set of tools or machines has the potential when once manufactured to enable the building of others of a higher order--and to do this even before the first set is understood clearly. Yet, the industrial age has seen a phenomenally successful partnership between research science and engineering, and to a considerable extent the nature and goals of science have come to be dictated as much by the needs for new technologies as by pure curiosity. Pure science has become woven up with its applications and the two can no longer be completely separated. Indeed, it may no longer be accurate to distinguish pure science from applied science, because the separation does not really exist in practice. Nowhere is this relationship more evident than in the technology parks adjacent to many North American universities. Perhaps the best known of these is the Silicon Valley area of California, which owes its existence to nearby Stanford University and the many professors and former

64

Page 65: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

students who have successfully turned their knowledge into products and cash. The same thing is now taking place in biochemistry, where academics are racing to turn a profit by transforming their research into marketable pharmaceuticals.

Likewise, the U. S. space program has generated large numbers of commercial spin-offs to the mass market. These technologies were developed initially for conditions of zero gravity, extreme temperature, high stress, and limited mass or size, and had ultrahigh reliability requirements, but quickly found uses in more mundane environments as well.

All technical advances in these fields (computing, biochemistry, space) have had consequences for a wide range of marketable products. The same comment can be made for military technologies, for the entire aerospace industry has grown as it has largely because of the impetus provided by the needs of two world wars. The observation can be repeated for almost any research or technology. Thus, pure research and pure invention do not exist alone and entire to themselves. Each inevitably affects the other and reflects back onto itself. Answers generate both products and new questions. Here, the interdependence principle could be stated:

There are no such things as pure theories, or pure applications.

Technology in its Own Right

However, the relationship between science and technology goes far beyond the fact that one is inductive and creates abstractions and the other is deductive and generates concrete results, for science as it is now known is only a few centuries old, whereas technology has been around at least since the first person thought of throwing a stone. It is not hard to argue that technology gave birth to science by providing a critical mass of industrial tools and complex processes that could only be understood and carried to the next step of their development by inventing the exacting analytical techniques called science. Viewed in this way, science could be regarded as the tool of technology rather than the other way around.

In fact, if the definition of technology is broadened in the manner of Jacques Ellul to include all systematic techniques--all searches for the most efficient way of doing--then the scientific method itself is actually one example of a technique. As a technique, it is subject to being studied for its own sake, and to being modified in order to become more efficient. Seen in this light, scientific enquiries take place under the control of one out of many possible techniques of thinking. They do not so much generate products from theory as they apply a practical methodology themselves. This concept is even more evident when one considers that scientific investigations themselves almost always require tools other than simply the particular mental discipline known as the scientific method. Whether the device is the mass spectrometer of the chemist, the meson machine of the physicist, or the computer employed by the molecular biologist to map genetic structures, there is always a level of co-requisite technology without which the particular science cannot be performed. Indeed, it becomes increasingly difficult to speak of the

65

Page 66: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

science without the technology that is required to do the work. Moreover, there may well be more efficient techniques to pursue a given line of enquiry. There may even be a better way to do what is now called science as a whole. Techniques that are yet known may not even exist, but the point is that it cannot be proven that modern science is the most efficient possible technique of its kind.

Furthermore, just as science and technology drive each other, and their modern versions could scarcely exist without each other, each technological advance drives others. That is, just as no scientific discovery is without its implications to technology (and vice versa), the same is true of new products and techniques themselves--none exists alone or is without a broader influence. Some examples include:

o The development of reliable pumps made it possible to mine the deep seams of coal underlying much of Britain, one of the prerequisites for the industrial revolution.

o The burning of coal eventually forced the creation of scrubbing technology for cleaning emissions.

o The development of steel made possible a wide range of machinery, instruments, and consumer goods that could not have been foreseen by those who made the first alloys of iron and carbon.

o The World War II German rocket program led directly to today's ICBM's and also to space exploration technology.

o Radio led to television, and the demands of both led to communication satellites.

o The growing complexity of telephone systems required automatic switching systems and eventually computers.

o The modern microcomputer was made possible by a number of inventions, most notably those of the vacuum tube, the transistor, and the integrated circuit. It in turn has spawned new products, disciplines, and whole industries.

Examples of this sort of thing could be multiplied for product development alone; they lead to two more statements of the interdependence principle:

It is impossible to discover one thingand

It is impossible to make one thing.

That one application drives another explains why in the long run the overall growth of technology is exponential, even though any one application reaches natural limits, perhaps in a relatively short time. Consider transportation technology, for instance, and its progression through walking, riding, sailing, driving, and flying, until achieving space travel by rocket. Each of these on its own imposes a natural upper limit on speed, but the need to travel farther and faster forces new transportation technology to be developed. The theoretical limit on rocket speed is

66

Page 67: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

some substantial fraction of the speed of light; the most optimistic of science fiction writers take it for granted that a new technique of transportation (warp speed) will eventually be developed to get around this barrier. More conservative voices assert that this is impossible, and it appears to be from most theoretical and practical considerations . However, such voices have been heard before--the horseless carriage, the aeroplane, the moon rocket, and the personal computer were all impossible until they were done. These examples may serve to illustrate an important fact of both science and technology that may be termed the incompleteness principle. It applies to all knowers with the exception of an all-knowing God.

For any field of study or application, it is either impossible to know everything, or it is impossible to know when everything is known.

or, to put it another way

No body of knowledge can ever be known to be complete, and no technology can be absolutely known to be the most efficient possible.

Technique

Broadening the notion of technology in order to view the scientific method as one in a spectrum of techniques has other consequences as well. If technique is the search for efficient methods as well as for efficient devices, then one may suppose that virtually every discipline has techniques better suited to that field than to others. This supposition leads to the further insight that the best techniques of management or the study of sociology may resemble scientific technique, but do not have to correspond exactly to it. Indeed, one ceases to expect that all technique must be of the scientific kind, for efficiency will surely be related to the nature of the field, rather than to theoretical considerations. Thus, it makes sense to speak of techniques of economics, politics, management, advertising, communicating, teaching, and of clear thinking (logic). One can also suppose that such techniques also lead to efficient methodologies in each of these areas, without having to apply the label "scientific" to them.

Jacques Ellul observed that every field of human endeavour can be assumed to be subject to the search for technique. As techniques develop, he observed, they do so in the most efficient manner available, reducing the number of choices for method, and tending to become rigid and authoritarian, admitting of no exceptions because of the claim to be the most efficient. He saw the end result of this progression of technique to be an amorphous totalitarian society with no individual choice at all (everyone would of necessity always do the most efficient thing).

67

Page 68: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

However, there was a factor that Ellul did not in his pessimism consider--the incompleteness principle. What if some other path were followed from the start? Could not a different "most efficient" point have been reached? How would anyone know that such a point had in fact been reached?

Clearly, it is not possible to know when the ultimate efficiency possible has been achieved in any field. It may be reached for a given technique applied in a particular way, but there may be other techniques with vastly different results. The high technology explosion in so many fields simultaneously illustrates this better than any theory. The view of the 1950s, like that of the 1890s, was that certain ultimate goals for both scientific knowledge and technological efficiency were close at hand. This view cannot any longer be sustained. It is being replaced by a more open-ended thinking that does not suppose that any state of equilibrium (in the sense of an ultimate technique) must necessarily ever be reached in either product development or in the potential application of technique--even to the social sciences.

To put this concept another way, suppose humankind was indeed created in the image of an omniscient and transcendent God. The process of learning may still be at the stage of the infant who makes piles of someone else's blocks and then knocks them over. Children naturally believe that they know everything, and are constantly amazed to discover that they do not. The principle of incompleteness is worth restating in these new terms:

No technique can ever be known to be ultimate, the best possible or universally applicable to all situations and cultures. All are open-ended.

Summary

The popular conception that science discovers and technology applies reverses the dependency of the two. Technique (efficient methodology) encompasses both science (one technique) and what is commonly called technology or engineering (efficient product development). It is also incorrect to assume that at any given time the most efficient methods have been discovered--or even that an optimum technique for something exists at all.

These insights assist in more properly placing science and technology within a spectrum of related human activities, demythologizing them to an extent, and of partly removing the notion that technique irresistibly and inevitably progresses to all-encompassing and dignity-destroying final goals. They lead to a more open-ended and continually changing scenario for the future. They also lead to a more realistic view of the practice and practitioners of science and technological development.

Profile on . . . Society and Technology

The Telephone

68

Page 69: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

What is it for? March 10, 1876: Alexander Graham Bell becomes the first person to transmit speech electrically. The powerful telegraph companies, seeing no business applications, refuse to have anything to do with the "electrical toy." Even its inventors seemed at first not to know what to do with the new machine.

A new occupation: Early telephone subscribers were connected to one another's lines by central operators. Since they could (and usually did) listen to the conversations, operators became powerful and important in their communities, for they were the primary information clearing houses.

Women and the telephone company: Early operators were usually well-educated single women with a status comparable to school teachers. They were well cared for, but generally required to leave upon marriage and few entered management. However, the sheer size of this work force contributed to the acceptance of women working outside the home.

Depersonalization: As exchanges grew in large cities, it was no longer possible for operators to know their customers. They became detached and impersonal handlers of routine switching chores, many of which were ultimately taken over by automated machinery. Today, even the operator's voice is synthesized.

An information medium: The early practice of transmitting concerts and sermons to homes and hospitals became the forerunner of similar entertainments on radio and television. It was no longer necessary to go to an event to experience the pleasure of having attended.

Business practice: Once in use, the telephone was not seen as a social medium, but as a tool for conducting business. For instance, installed at resorts, it allowed businessmen to keep in touch with their offices. Cellular telephones and facsimile allow instant communications anywhere. Large businesses can be cohesive, and small ones can compete using telephone technology.

Urban development: The suburbs and the upper floors of high buildings were not practical as locations for doing business before the telephone. It has contributed to the growth of cities both upward and outward.

Old technologies obsoleted: Telegraph usage, which peaked in the late 1920s, and again in the mid forties, declined steadily thereafter. Today, the use of the telephone growing even as the amount of first class mail declines.

Better services: The telephone permitted the creation of efficient emergency services over large areas. Medical aid, firefighting, and policing all improved dramatically because of the ability to communicate requests for help quickly.

Crime: The telephone enabled new forms of crime. Prostitutes became call girls. Obscene calls became a problem. Gambling networks became more

69

Page 70: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

widespread. Wire-tapping became a new kind of crime and a new method of law enforcement.

Environmental issues: From very early, complaints were often heard that wires, poles, and towers were disfiguring the countryside. Today, automated calling equipment allows the individual's personal environment to be invaded by junk phone calls.

It changes social behaviour: If two people are talking and a third enters the room, the newcomer must wait for the chance to talk. If instead the third calls on the telephone, most people cannot ignore the demand and will drop whatever they are doing to answer immediately.

It is difficult to regulate fairly.(1) How is a fair rate for service determined? Flat fees give business and other

high volume users a quantity discount, causing home users to subsidize them. On the other hand, metering local calls requires more equipment and raises the rates for everyone.

(2) How are costs and fees split properly between long distance and local service? This is especially hard to determine when two or more companies are involved.

(3) Should telephone service be a monopoly so as to ensure greatest efficiency and uniformity of service? Or should it be competitive, so as to ensure the lowest prices?

(4) Should telephone service be closely regulated as an essential public utility, or should free competition be allowed. Which is most in the public interest?

(5) In either case, should it be government owned or private?(6) Should all long distance directory service calls be free? Credit bureaus are

heavy users of this service, reasoning that a phone listing is an indicator of creditworthiness. These are commercial operations, yet they pay nothing to use this service.

The telephone changes society.(1) It is an instrument for organizing and socializing people.(2) It converges space and time, making rapid communications with remote

places as effective as those with next door.(3) Mail order shopping became important. "Let your fingers do the walking" is

not simply an advertising slogan, but a new way of life.

The telephone spawns new technologies:(1) Demand for long distance and transatlantic service gave rise to copper

wire, undersea cables, microwave transmission, and then to satellite transponders.(2) Demand for new services produces picture telephones (not widely used),

improved facsimile service, cellular telephones, and phone company sponsored information networks.

70

Page 71: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Telephones empower the individual.(1) They are sophisticated, but anyone can operate them.(2) They create mobility, allowing people to find and apply for jobs at remote

locations.(3) They provide access to information stored in distant computing systems.(4) The telephone system guarantees that

Everyone is connected to everyone else.

2.5 Science and Technology--Practice and Practitioners It is important to realize that even as science and engineering are disciplines

(techniques) like any other, their practitioners are people. They are therefore subject to the same failings of jealousy, narrow-mindedness, pride, error, and even fraud as those in any other field. Since this is a book on issues, a brief discussion of some of the problems in the practice of science and the pursuit of technology is in order.

World View and Scientific Debates

First, consider how pride and narrow views give rise to debates and disagreements even in what are regarded as exact sciences. As has already been pointed out, no scientist or engineer works independently of an internal metaphysical framework or world view. Every step in the application of any technique (including the scientific one) demands that judgements be made, and these can at best be only relatively objective.

Cultural and global world view are non-unique concepts, so individuals see things differently. If the internal thinking framework of any two scientists or engineers (or any two people at all) were absolutely identical, then one of them would be redundant. For instance, if the reader agrees with everything that is said in this book, then clearly the author is unnecessary. The non-uniqueness of world views means that different people choose different specialities for study in the first place. It also means that two specialists in the same field may place entirely different interpretations on the same set of data, may expound varying or even contradictory theories, or may develop quite different products or applications from the same theoretical base.

Indeed, the divergence may begin sooner in the process. The decision to accept or reject certain data (or to seek it in the first place) is not necessarily scientific or logical--rejection may occur when the data fails to "fit" the preconceptions of the researcher. Armed with competing theories and possibly differing data, two factions of the scientific community may seek to line up institutional and individual support, particularly among the so-called scientific celebrities. If the question is actually (or appears to be) decidable, one side (or some third party differing from both) can eventually emerge from the ensuing debate as temporary victor.

71

Page 72: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Some of the most controversial discussions take place when the issue is not decidable, for either intrinsic or extrinsic reasons. If the problem is extrinsic, such as the lack of technology for testing purposes, there is still hope for an eventual solution. One of the best modern examples is relativity theory, many facets of which were not at first amenable to investigation in the physical sense. As the years passed, new techniques permitted experiments not previously possible, and the general theory of relativity came to be universally accepted as experimental results matched theory.

However, if the undecidability is due to intrinsic reasons, that is, the theory itself is of a metaphysical or otherwise unprovable nature, then debates will rage indefinitely. There are not always definitive and acceptable ways to answer non-scientific questions through the use of science, whether or not it happens to be scientists asking the questions.

Questions About Origins

This will certainly be the case when the two sides are arguing, say, about events that took place in the Earth's past. It is impossible to prove or disprove in any absolute sense many assertions concerning prehistoric times. Indeed, historians cannot always agree on the facts concerning recent events, much less on their interpretation, so one should not expect agreement on questions of prehistoric events. This is particularly true where questions of the origin of the universe are concerned, and each generation of modern scientists has adopted quite a different cosmological model, defended it, and taught it as fact, only to have it replaced at a later date. The confidence of the scientific modeller rises if the model correctly predicts things that were not used to build the model, but the inability to test its main premises experimentally means that this confidence will always be partly of the faith kind. There is no safer prediction about the future of scientific theories than that the widely accepted big-bang theory of the universe's origin will eventually be replaced. In such cases, the new model must be able to explain everything that the old one could, as well as resolving inconsistencies of the old.

A person could object that acceptance of any strictly mechanistic model for origins, especially one acknowledged to be incomplete and temporary, is of such a different degree than faith in a creator God that the two are not really comparable. Some find this objection attractive, but its analysis may be superficial, for it does not take into account the level at which the belief systems operate.

Is it a particular mechanism or the necessity to explain origins mechanistically that is the subject of faith? The former may be a holding position pending suitable confirmation of detail and possible modification; the latter may represent a fundamental and non-negotiable philosophical position. If that which is believed in is a universe presupposed to be mechanistic and without an intelligent planner, then the mechanism currently accepted is mere window dressing for a deeper faith--one that always insists upon a materialistic explanation for origins, regardless of evidence. At this level, the two faiths (in a creator God, and in natural origins) would be indistinguishable, though they appear different when considering specific details

72

Page 73: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

(such as mechanism) rather than the broad presuppositions behind them. The motivation of an affirmer of beliefs is as telling as the details of the belief held.

Evolutionary biology provides a second (related) example of an issue that is not decidable for intrinsic reasons. Conclusions about the biological past will always be tentative, describing what might have or could have happened, with backing from empirical evidence resting on interpretations of data more than on the data itself. Even the evidence gained by comparing the genetic material of organisms catalogues relationships descriptively, not historically, and sheds no light on whether they came about by chance or by design. It is easy to confidently assume that new discoveries will support some current theory of biological evolution. Some such discoveries may well be made, but different confidences might produce their own supporting evidence.

It is important to note that in both cases, it is not the discussion of specific mechanisms that is likely to have a metaphysical flavour (though it may). To see if that aspect is present, one must enquire deeper and determine whether the individual is a priori committed to philosophical presuppositions demanding specific categories of interpretations for origins and life and cannot conceive of alternatives. Such a prior determination is likely to be the case for most people for whom such questions are important. That is, if person self-describes as "creationist" or "evolutionist," a commitment to a philosophical position is being expressed that underlies any specific scientific thought or investigation. It is here, and not in the work the person may do that the question of metaphysics arises.

For further discussion of the radically differing views on the subject of creation and evolution, the reader is referred on the one hand to the Usenet newsgroup "Talk.origins" and related homepages, and on the other to materials maintained by such organizations as the Creation Research Society. These two present the poles of thought, while other groups attempt to find middle ground. The reader may wish to investigate whether such groups even mention their metaphysical presuppositions, much less discuss them in any detail.

Questions Requiring the Use of Models

Similar situations can also arise if the objects under study are too small or too fast to see directly and can only be described by reference to a model for their behaviour (e.g., the wave/particle nature of light and the actions of subatomic particles). In such cases, competing theories or models sometimes arise to explain the same phenomena and it may be the case that the two (or more) sides forget that they are arguing not about science, but about interpretations, that is, (possibly) about metaphysics. Indeed, modern physics is as much concerned with philosophy as it is with anything else, and sometimes has difficulty attaching meanings to the terms it employs to describe the phenomena it investigates. The world that is

73

Page 74: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

ordinarily seen by people in the everyday sense is not obviously related to the one seen by the physicist, an example of the fact that physical knowledge does not convey the thing itself, however useful an abstraction it may be.

The Case of Theology

Another example of the non-uniqueness of world views can be seen in the answers various people would give to the question: "Is theology a science, or is it entirely metaphysical?" This may seem like an obsolete question to ask, for the majority view among educated people today would almost certainly be that theology has no connection with science whatsoever. However, this is a new consensus, for just as mathematics was historically Queen of the Arts, so theology was Queen of the Sciences. To the practitioner, theology is the systematic study of a body of factual information--which being revealed by the deity, is no less reliable than if derived from a microscope slide. The receipt of this information from another (instead of by personal observation) is not regarded as a problem, in view of what is regarded as well-attested source reliability. Theologians observe that people in all fields accept a great deal of information as factual in much the same way; the logic of so doing is not different, though the nature of the source is. For example, no scientist verifies the entire body of prerequisite knowledge before carrying on with the next experiment; to do so would be considered absurd. Thus, the study of God may begin with a faith affirmation, but it continues with a partially empirical, scientific, and therefore fallible study called theology--one that differs in subject matter but shares some methodology (technique) with other sciences.

To the typical modern scientist, who accepts the control belief of materialism and leans toward logical positivism, such a definition of theology as akin to science would be objectionable. There is a tendency to think that unless data can be personally verified, it is unacceptable. Unless a theory is at least potentially falsifiable by empirical means it is not scientific. One could even say that since in death the senses are left behind, empirical methods cannot be extended across the gulf of the grave, even if one believes in life after death. There do remain the methods of history and related disciplines, but in these the evidence itself, not just the interpretation of it, may be selectively disputed, especially if the event is far enough in the past.

For instance, one may accept documentary (and other) evidence that one's own great-grandparents existed, though never having met them. The evidence is compelling, though not strictly the result of repeatable experiments. It is easier to dispute the validity of documentation for events and people farther in the past, particularly if others' interpretation of those events does not accord with one's preferred world view. Thus, some accept the Bible as a historically accurate document collection describing the actions of God in history, while others selectively dismiss all or portions as myth or fabrication. If even the evidence of history can be so disputed, there is no certainly no way to personally use science to verify or falsify claims about the existence of God.

From a historical point of view this thinking is rather new. Scientists such as Kepler, Bacon, Newton, Boyle, Fleming, Maxwell, Faraday, Joule, Davy, Pasteur,

74

Page 75: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Kelvin, Pascal, and a long list of others of past centuries "did" science because of their deep-seated belief that they could discover more about God by unfolding the nature of the universe that he had created. Indeed, few of the originators and builders of what has become today's science would be comfortable with the philosophical orientation of their heirs. Their world view was significantly different from that of the moderns. Though they might rejoice at the progress made in the fields they began, they would probably consider the move to a materialist metaphysical basis to be costly.

Of course, one could object that an appeal to the theological views of past scientists is invalid, regardless of how popular these views were--after all, they were a product of a cultural world view. The objection is valid, but it must not be overlooked that the same objection can be applied to any appeal to the uniformity of world view and metaphysics of today's scientific world. Consensus in any age is not necessarily evidence of absolute truth. Moreover, the modern scientific community recognizes the greatness of the science that was done in the past, despite the fact that it was accomplished within a different metaphysical framework. Why then do points of difference among today's scientists result in so very much hostility and acrimonious debate? Even today, excellent science can legitimately arise from within the framework of a minority world view. One could even argue that it must do so, in order to achieve the paradigm shifts that are required to make the great breakthroughs. Moreover, religions that speak of a life beyond death generally hold that there are also some senses that can be used there. Thus, the argument that God's existence can never be verified or falsified is not yet proven, for one must presumably die to the empirical world to find the answer.

The kind of peer pressure and search for consensus discussed here can have another, and more subtle effect. Academics are rightly conscious of the need for their work to stand on the shoulders of those who have gone before, and so they adorn their own reports with quotations from others so as to lend their own conclusions support. If such quoting is done with due respect to the whole context of the original, it is not only correct, but to some extent necessary. However, there is always the possibility that the mutual respect of a small number of workers in a field may generate circular quotations of one another and these may create an impression of far greater authority than what actually exists. As Nellie Hacker said in the seminar: "If I quote you, and you quote me, who is any the wiser?"

These issues will be picked up again in a later chapter with a more detailed consideration of the creation/evolution debate--in some ways the classic clash of world views. For now, it will suffice to make the point that the human element in science removes some of its reputed precision, exactness, and reproducibility to the theoretical realm. In practice, things don't happen in quite as orderly a way as they are supposed to.

Publish or Perish

Another pressure on the practitioners of science is caused by the need for them to prove themselves by getting some results accepted for publication in recognized journals. A book placed with a reputable publisher counts for even more,

75

Page 76: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and two books may even be worth a promotion. In the case of technology-driven research, working prototypes, patents, and production models determine success.

Part of the reason for this is the tenure system used by the universities where most North American scientists do their work. Following the research that leads to a doctoral thesis (duly defended before peers) and the degree that is accepted at graduation, the new academic seeks to become attached to the faculty of a reputable university. If successful, a probationary appointment is given that may be renewed for up to four or five years. At that time the candidate's research output is measured by the number of books and papers published. If the level is acceptable, a permanent contract (tenure) is offered; if it is not, and a second review a year later offers nothing better, the unfortunate would-be professor is instead terminated. Teaching ability is not usually a major issue.

In most cases, denial of tenure status at one university ends the research career entirely because a second chance at another institution is very unlikely to be given. The (now ex-) academic can either find a position in industry, teach at a community college or high school or chalk the degree papers up to experience and find another line of work. For those who do become a part of the academic system a continued high paper production level is required for consideration of promotion from assistant to associate to full professor, and even more important, for the acquisition of research grants from governments and private foundations.

There are a number of consequences of this system that are not very positive.First, this practice fails to take into account that research in some areas is

much more difficult than in others and may take far more time to produce new results. There is, therefore, pressure to stay away from such fields and concentrate on those where answers can be obtained quickly. This increases the volume of research papers greatly, but reduces the likelihood that any one of them will be very memorable. It is questionable whether anyone reads the majority of such reports once the journal editor is finished with them and officially puts them into print. As the majority are never cited by anyone else, it seems likely many are never read either.

Second, it fails to take into account that some papers are more publishable than others because they are trendier. A mediocre work on a subject that happens to be of current interest is much more likely to be published than a better work in a more obscure area. For instance, it would be much easier to publish work on AIDS, superconductivity, or cold fusion than on tuberculosis, the properties of napthalene, or heat engine efficiency. It is all but impossible to publish a substantial critique of a majority interpretation on an important issue. There is nothing either morally wrong or deceitful about this; it is just the human side of science showing through. This kind of bias causes fads to be accentuated even more, but also dilutes the overall quality of the work.

Third, it fails to take into account that money and influence speak more loudly than other voices. Senior faculty can pressure their more junior compatriots into their own fields and away from innovative ideas because they control tenure and promotion committees. Women, blacks, and those who attempt to cross cultural or religious boundaries can be systematically kept out of the system. Funding agencies, particularly those under government control, can cut off grants for

76

Page 77: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

political or military reasons and thus can also channel research according to their desires. The result is that free and open enquiry is reduced and so is creativity. The progress of new and innovative work must wait for the rare junior researcher not only to become senior (and a funding referee), but to simultaneously retain some creative spark. In the meanwhile, most research will be done in teams with agendas defined by others. The risk of funding individuals is too great, no matter how talented they may be.

Again, none of this is unique to science, for the dead hand of bureaucracy reaches everywhere. Such problems are characteristic of any institution; that they would eventually reach the scientific community was a foregone conclusion. For example, the Soviet Union produced more university-trained scientists and engineers per capita than any other nation. Yet, it struggled to catch up to the United States in the quality of basic research and technology. Why? Because the Soviet Union was also run by the largest bureaucracy on earth, and gaining approval for a scientific project was even more difficult than in North America. By the time the research had been allowed, the results may already have been in some American journal By the time a technological development was permitted, it might have been cheaper to buy it in a New York surplus store than to build one from scratch.

An old story with many variations illustrates the difficulty of developing new technology in the former Soviet Union.

The noted Russian engineer Ivan Fedorvich arrives in Fort Langley, British Columbia, to visit his old friend and correspondent Stan Barker. Upon arrival at his house, Dr. Barker expresses interest in his visitor's watch. Fedorvich's face lights up as he tells him it is not just a wrist watch, but also a computer, radio, data terminal, and television all rolled into one. It has built-in voice recognition, a gigabyte of memory, and even a programmable alarm clock, and a miniature satellite dish in its concave crystal--a veritable triumph of socialist engineering. "And what," says Barker, "is that," pointing to the large suitcase Fedorvich is carrying with considerable difficulty. "Ah," says Fedorvich ruefully, "the Politburo insisted on using Russian batteries."

Finally, and related to these other factors, the pressure to publish at any cost encourages scientists to find quick and easy solutions, to take short-cuts, and to stay with traditional ideas and methodology. The safe and familiar can become so comfortable that the scholarly apparatus begins to substitute for thought. The watchword is "don't rock the boat," and this attitude, while it may get papers published, does nothing to advance science.

Not all is wrong with the academic system however, or it would not have lasted as long as it has. It ensures new work is reviewed by peers on editorial boards before being published, and serves as a check on very bad papers. It creates a sense of community and a kind of apprenticeship for entry into the community, ensuring that new applicants do have at least certain minimum qualifications. If the system does promote mediocrity, it also promotes volume, and every bit of knowledge, however small, pushes back the frontiers of human ignorance. Every

77

Page 78: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

once in a while, a truly great insight is achieved, and the spin-off benefits from that one-in-ten-thousand paper are incalculable.

Similar observations can be made about those engaged in technological development, where building the wrong product or targeting it to the wrong market may destroy both product and career. Far more devices and methods are created than will ever see the marketplace, but the vast amount of activity does guarantee that some revolutionary new products are developed, even though some good ones never see the light of day.

Funding Pressures

It has already been remarked that many decisions for both basic research and technological development are made on the basis of grants available from a variety of funding agencies. It is worth observing further that the largest portion of this money tends to come from government, if only because the size of some projects is far too great for any private means. Specifically, many of the projects so funded are likely to be sponsored by the military. Thus, political and military considerations have the largest say in the direction of research, increasing the direct and indirect control of the state over the technology that shapes society. More will be said in a later chapter about the role of the state; the mere observation of its control over the purse strings is sufficient for now. Like some of the other things taken note of in this chapter, it leads to the conclusion that human, political and economic factors more than curiosity or actual needs may often dominate selection and development in the scientific/technological process.

Other Problems

It is also natural that the kinds of pressures indicated above will lead to serious problems from time to time. Thus, science has not been without the occasional scandal caused by fraudulent data, wishful thinking, fanciful conclusions or hoax. In the celebrated case of the supposed ape/human "missing link" known as Piltdown Man, a hoax got out of hand, and what was apparently intended as the deception of a single individual continued to delude the entire scientific community for years. In the case of Nebraska Man, another putative missing link, what turned out to be the tooth of an extinct pig had at first an entire fanciful proto-man built around it, complete with life-style to match. On the other side of the same debate, far too much was made of some human-like footprints that appeared in the same strata as those of dinosaurs. Time, and due consideration led the people involved to withdraw their original suggestions and reclassify the prints. More recently, there have been a few dismissals of researchers who had been caught fabricating data to maintain their standing with a high publication output.

78

Page 79: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

There is also a large speculative content in some disciplines, and this too can generate much discussion about very little. In such cases, the mere repetition of speculation by enough of the leaders in the discipline is sufficient to have others accept it is fact. This is a foible of scholarship that must be lived with, for it too is human nature. However, it is one of the most subtle of difficulties to deal with, because the generation that accepts speculation as fact is unlikely to tolerate challenges to that dogma, and it may take a great deal of time to shift the discipline in question to a different view.

All of these instances reveal the human tendency of scientists to see only what they expect to see, and to continue to do so long after the means is available to correct their misconceptions. Time is the best remedy for such problems. It also helps to have a general determination to test occasionally even the most basic, fundamental and longest held assumptions, just in case the universal faith in them has been ever so slightly misplaced.

Faith is often placed in people, too, and science, like any other field of interest, has its few celebrities among the many foot-soldiers. This can be a positive thing, for such individuals are usually the ones who have the charisma and public presence to sell the discipline to a sometimes skeptical and usually demanding public. Celebrities can also mislead, however, particularly when presumed to be experts about all science and are asked to express to the public views on things that are far from their own narrow field of expertise.

Thus, for instance, a book by a celebrity scientist on investment strategies, playing golf, or understanding the Bible might sell very well, despite the writer being entirely unqualified in the subject at hand. This is not only a problem with science, but one it shares in common with the entire "star" system so prevalent in North America. A realization that the eminent chemist Dr. Zork is plain Mrs. Zork outside her own field would be healthy for all concerned.

Thus, if one is to ask why some study is undertaken, why some product is built, why some technique is developed, one would not necessarily find the answer within the nature of the discipline, but might find it in the society in which the discipline is pursued. This is true of both the society of specialist practitioners, and also of the larger culture from which they come. In turn, science, technology, and technique change the context society in which they develop, and new ideas become feasible when such changes take place, for they enable all members of the society to think and act in new ways.

2.6 The Technological Society? The society of the late industrial and early post-industrial age is in some ways

most profoundly influenced by a scientific and technological mindset, and much less so by other ways of thinking. This influence is seen in the academic world, where terms such as "social science" are applied to disciplines whose claims to be scientific in methodology are rather tenuous. It is also seen in the wide-scale application of technique to social, political, and business problems, as discussed in a previous section. The high-tech information society will in the long run be more than simply a gloss over or renaming of existing practices, though even these name changes reflect a genuine shift in the collective point of view of society. People are

79

Page 80: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not just using a new vocabulary, they are not just buying the consumer goods that reflect the latest technological advances--they are planning for and assuming a continuing state of such change. This is done in the purchase of household goods, appliances, and automobiles, the building of houses, offices and apartments, and in the other ordinary decisions of life. That all such goods will soon be obsolete, and thus can be expected to have only a short lifetime, is assumed and planned for. A disposable economy is a necessary by-product of rapid technological change. So is a general familiarization with relatively sophisticated products. Moreover, people tend to trust technology for solutions to such problems as food scarcity, disease, overpopulation, pollution, and energy shortages. As they trust, so they act. When the scientific/technological community has already delivered so much, it is difficult not to assume that it can answer any question, solve any problem and build any kind of machine.

This has also caused many old barriers to crumble. As high technology has become commercialized, businessmen, accountants, and economists have been conscripted to work side-by-side with electrical engineers and computer programmers. Indeed, the computer has generated more crossover among academic and other disciplines than C. P. Snow could have imagined in the early 1960s, for both social scientists and writers have been quick to use this tool to enhance their work. In the first years of the computing discipline, most of its theoreticians and practitioners were drawn from other fields (particularly mathematics), and many a university computing department today is administered by psychologists, philosophers, mathematicians, and economists, rather than by those with doctorates in computing itself. University curricula also recognized this crossover, and have introductory courses in computing, data processing and technology for non-science majors. Such students eagerly embrace the machine for the benefits it can bring, particularly to word processing and data analysis tasks.

However, this does not yet mean that a technological culture is universal or deep-seated, even for students, whom one would expect to adapt most easily to change, for few of them emerge from such courses with much understanding of how those machines work, except in the most vague and general terms. Given that students' general science and mathematics background is often very weak upon entry to the course, such basic concepts as the binary numbering system or simple programming not only cause eyes to glaze over during lectures, but generate a firm resolve to avoid any further courses with technological overtones. This situation may change, but not until the computer becomes as simple to use as a toaster or any other household appliance. The change will be the elimination of such courses, not the requirement of more technical learning. After all, who would need a university-level course in how to use a waffle iron? Indeed, as any high technology matures, there are fewer and fewer people who understand it, even though there may be many more who use it. Such developments ought to be expected.

Thus, the term "high-tech information society" should be understood in the context of technology use, rather than in that of the search for technique. The latter is the function of experts in each field who are seeking to optimize their work; the former is the province of every member of society. Use of machines does not necessarily mean there is change in the way people think. They embrace both

80

Page 81: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

technological advances and new techniques for the personal benefits and efficiencies they bring, not because the philosophy of science is fascinating. For the typical person, changes in thinking and living patterns are caused by new techniques, not the reverse. To put it another way, it is the highest level abstractions (finished products) that most people employ; they are not interested in the detailed work that went into them being made ready for common use. There is, therefore, an extent to which technological society is a thin patina over an underlying culture--one that changes much more slowly than it appears on the surface.

At the intellectual decision-making level, Snow's observations about the two cultures still have a certain validity. Academics can still go their way with their specialities without much regard for the changing world around them. Poets and physicists can speak different languages, read different books, and need not talk to each other. They may pretend each other's work is irrelevant, as if physicists had no imagination or poets could live in primitive communes and use nothing of modern technology. While there has been a "scientification" of many academic disciplines, acceptance of such techniques is uneven, and viewed with suspicion by some traditionalists. Thus acceptance of technology is mixed, and there is still division among academics because of the broad acceptance of and trust placed in it. These feelings are reciprocated.

Such suspicions and divisions are potentially dangerous, for they may develop into prejudices that are capable of destabilizing a society. Politicians (and ordinary citizens) cannot make good decisions about technology they distrust or do not understand. Scientists with little or no education in the arts and humanities cannot express themselves in a way that makes their work accessible and believable to the general public. They may also lack the foundation for making moral/ethical decisions, and take the attitude that science and technology are always socially and ethically neutral, when in fact neither is. Kranzberg (Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology) puts it this way: "Technology is not ethically neutral because it is not only an instrument of human practice but a form of it also; the ethics of technology concerns human technical practice and its normative problems." Thus, scientists and engineers are called on constantly to make decisions with ethical implications, not only about the way they conduct their work, but about how their work is or will be used. Because of this, they need to be ethically informed themselves, and articulate enough to bring issues to the attention of those outside their own sub culture.

As they communicate with others, they close some of the interdisciplinary gaps, and simultaneously become more familiar with the relationship science and technology have with society as a whole. To the extent that this happens, their techniques can also become the instrument and the object of social and political policies. Eventually, those who do have technological familiarity may demand more power to make decisions. They will need to qualify themselves to be decision makers in order to do this. Likewise, politicians will have to gain greater understanding of technology and its effects, or make way for those who will. The wider public will not even struggle with the theory, but simply use its products as tools. Society will continue to change, for there will be more things that people will

81

Page 82: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

be able to do with their tools without thinking about them, and the size of this collection of activities is an important measure of what a civilization is about.

In the longer term, academics may not be as divided as in the past. Their separation into non-overlapping specialities was a response to the need to know enough facts about one field to do useful work in a world suffering from information overload. As this characterization is now irrelevant the barriers between disciplines have already begun to come down to some extent, for the means to manage information effectively and find it on demand has become universally available. This topic will be revisited in the chapter on the information society, as well as in the one on education.

The Third World

There are more important tensions in the world outside academia, because technological benefits continue to be inequitably distributed on a social and geographical basis. The disparity in technology and wealth between the European, North American and white Commonwealth countries on the one hand, and everyone else on the other, may get much worse before it gets any better. To be sure, there are hopeful signs of industrialization, agricultural change, and technical education in the third world. Countries such as China sometimes seem capable of jumping directly from primitive agricultural economies into the information age. However, political and social instability through much of Asia, Africa, and South America conspire to limit growth, and most countries in these regions are still pre-industrial or mid-industrial, with few apparent prospects for improvement. Some African nations have even worse problems, including drought, famine, and an AIDS epidemic that threatens to carry away many of the educated people they have managed to produce. The poor of the underdeveloped nations have little meaningful interaction with the prosperous West and there seems little immediate prospect of changing things. As long as this situation continues--and especially if it worsens (as it seems likely to do)--there still exists the possibility that another war could engulf the whole globe. Such a conflict has the potential not only to destroy centuries of technological advances, but even the human race itself. One of the most important technical problems to solve, therefore, is to find ways to bring the benefits of high technology to all peoples of the world in a non-destructive way.

Technology and Trade-offs

There is a tendency on the part of those employed in the daily pursuit of new technology to assume that progress is always good. However, the use of any new technology has a variety of consequences, and there are times when trade-offs have to be made between increasing efficiency and utility on the one hand, and negative social and human factors on the other. Among many examples are the following:

o Improvements in railroad equipment that are designed to make trains safer and more efficient may cause the price of the service to rise, resulting in more

82

Page 83: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

people using the highways. This produces the twin negatives of lower utilization of the now more expensive service, and a higher death rate because highways are much less safe than the railway was initially.

o Large amounts of money are spent making the control rooms of nuclear power plants orderly and efficient. However, if the result is a sterile environment, the resulting operator boredom may actually increase the risk of accidents.

o The introduction of chemicals into meat and other food may make it better tasting and preserve it longer, but at the risk of other health-threatening side effects when the food is consumed.

o A dam built to reduce random flooding and produce large amounts of electricity may be politically advantageous and improve the economy for a time, but may prevent silt deposition in the delta, reducing fertility, and increasing both net erosion and dependence on imported chemical fertilizers. The flooded and ruined valley will silt up (sometimes rapidly), eventually destroying the utility of the dam. In the end, there may be little but damage to show for the expense of billions of dollars.

o Even when technological and economic goals are achieved in the short term, vast megaprojects create correspondingly large capital debts, and these may in the long run ruin the economy and lower the standard of living of a whole nation. A default to the international banks could threaten the economy of the entire world.

o The factories and foundries that bring wealth and prosperity may cause acidic rains to fall (perhaps in another country) resulting in deforestation, soil sterility, fish kills, and respiratory illnesses and increasing the levels of metals such as aluminium in the human system to dangerous levels.

o The manufacture of dangerous chemicals may be conducted in a distant part of the world, on the soil of another nation. This has the twin advantage of reducing risks at home, and creating good jobs in a third world nation. It has the disadvantage of increasing the risk that untrained personnel will make mistakes that result in the release of the chemicals and cause large numbers of deaths.

o Computers introduced into offices allow employees to do more in less time. This can lead to them wasting some of their time, producing more reports but that no one reads, or being laid off.

o A focus on technology may cause managers to forget that the principal assets of a company in the information age are its people not its machines. Continued, this attitude could destroy the enterprise.

o Technology developed for peaceful purposes can also be used for warfare. In particular, it can be used by terrorists. The results might be more negative than positive.

o Governments are constantly faced with demands for increased social spending. If they fund technological developments instead, they may have to trade off certain short term social pain for the hope of long term prosperity.

o Resources are limited. Governments and corporations are always faced with choices between development proposals of uncertain benefit, where selecting one will surely kill the other.

83

Page 84: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Examples could be multiplied, and many of the discussions later in this book could be mentioned here as well. The point is that one must always question the potential value of a proposed technology--not everything new is necessarily good or positive, just as not everything old is necessarily obsolete. There is no shortage of new things that can be done; the interesting problem is deciding which ones are worth doing.

Technology and the Average Citizen

As noted above, typical citizens even in technically advanced countries participate only as users of technology. They labour at stores, factories, and menial office jobs, or stand in line for welfare or unemployment checks. Although they are eager consumers (when possible) of technological products, they neither engage in nor care about the issues dear to the learned.

The average North American knows something about how to maintain an automobile or small machine, but would greet any conversation about molecular biology or philosophy with equal parts disdain and amusement. The toilers in the humanities and social sciences are not understood at all. There is more sympathy, but not much more understanding for scientists (who are commonly stereotyped as "mad") and both sympathy and some understanding of engineers. Mathematicians are looked at askance, and a computer scientist is regaled with tales of non-functional hardware and software--much as a doctor at a social function would go away knowing about everyone's arthritis.

Of course, the ordinary citizen is the one most affected by changes in technology--for it always creates new jobs and eliminates others. However, the intellectual and material gap between the consumers of high-tech goods, and the creators, sellers, and managers of such products is considerable. What this will mean to decision making and effective power in the society of the future is not yet clear; both centralizing trends and individualizing trends need to be considered in order to make any forecasts. For most people, understanding is not a prerequisite for participation in a machine-oriented society. It should be noted, however, that in the next (information based) society it may become increasingly difficult for ordinary citizens to function at all without a substantial technical background.

A continuing widening of the gap between an elite and the general population in the wealthy Western countries would be just as destabilizing and potentially dangerous as the same process on the international scene between countries. If only those who can use the new information tools can work in the new civilization (and this is increasingly so) what place is there for anyone else? Can the industrialized nations remain stable if this question is not addressed?

Assessing the Situation

Important cautions must be sounded about the uneven distribution of knowledge and technique, but there are some very encouraging signs. Modern society is far from static, and some sub-cultures are moving into territories previously occupied by others. Those in poorer countries, and the lower classes of

84

Page 85: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the richer ones generally know (in theory) how to achieve greater wealth. Thus, education and industrialization are actively pursued by the disadvantaged who seek to move up. There are no secrets about how a nation becomes wealthier, and there are no peoples who would willingly choose to retain the short life span and disease-ridden poverty of the agricultural age, when offered a choice.

The poorest people of the most impoverished nations will sacrifice anything to send a child to school, for they know that the next generation can be better off. They would also gladly trade their poverty for the problems of the industrial nations. The same upward route exists for the children of the working class and poor of the industrialized nations, and they take it whenever they can, particularly to the sciences.

Meanwhile, the scientific community is pulling out of its own intellectual isolation to some extent and beginning to address the ethical questions related to the society its products are creating. Along the way, there is some measure of reconciliation with its religious and philosophical roots, though the differences here can still be severe. Also, the use of computers, particularly those machines having a graphics interface, has increased among artists and writers. This may not yet have removed all the intellectual barriers to the use of technology, but it has reduced some of the emotional ones, and the anti-technology faction has become more muted. It may be the use of this machine more than anything else that gives legitimacy and common currency to the term "high-tech information society."

It is the contention of this book that all the peoples and cultures of the world need each other, that technologies pursued by one have effects on the others that cannot be ignored, and that it will be less and less possible for any individual, profession, discipline, or nation to act in narrow self-interest without regard for the interests of others. Just as there has come to be a human-machine cooperation (synergy) for the solving of problems which neither can do alone, there needs to be an understanding that all peoples of the earth are crew on the same ship. All peoples have common interests (even if they are unwilling to admit this); they have a common origin, and a common destination. These themes will be developed further under a number of headings throughout the remaining chapters; for the present here is another aphorism:

Society is maintained on communication, and it in turn requires acknowledgment and understanding of common ground.

2.7 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Philosophers of various times and in various disciplines have given different meanings to the term knowledge. It has meant the result of a particular kind of reasoning process (logic); it is confined by some to the outcome of the scientific method; and it is equated by others to belief or faith. It can also be personal (taste) or opinion, though most (all?) of what is placed in the last category may properly

85

Page 86: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

belong in the others. There are a variety of conflicts among the groups that hold these positions, and these conflicts show up in both academic disciplines and in the gaps between members of academia and ordinary citizens.

As for the scientific method itself, it relies on the assumption that there is a reliable and potentially predictable underlying reality behind the phenomena being investigated, though the nature of that reality is itself the subject of some dispute. Science is connected to, but cannot be completely identified with technology, for the search for tools and techniques has often been independent of theory, even though the scientific and technical community is as one in this century.

If technique is given its broadest possible definition, it may be seen to include the scientific method as one technique. Whether technique is an irresistible force driving society to certain inevitable goals depends on whether or not there exist absolute techniques--the most efficient possible for a given task--and it is not certain that this is knowable.

The very term "high-tech information society", which is often taken to imply a monolithic culture, sure of its content and goals, is quite possibly misleading in view of the number of factions that are present even now. The disparities between the "haves" and the "have-nots" seem likely to continue for some time to come, both within the advanced nations, and between them and the third world. Although high technology is having a profound influence on society, people seem content to use its products in everyday life without needing to understand either how the products are made, or the science behind them. In many ways, such automatic and unthinking routine uses of technique actually characterize a civilization, more than (and perhaps despite) the way its intellectuals think.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. To what extent would it be possible to live without any use of modern technology? Give your reasons in detail.

2. Write a research paper describing the historical origins and development of the scientific method.

3. Compare and contrast the methods of historical and scientific studies.4. What is the meaning of the word "knowledge" as it is used in science, in

mathematics, religion, economics (or some other social science of your choice) and in English literature (or another of the humanities)?

5. Does "knowledge" mean one thing for the academic disciplines mentioned in question 4, and a different thing for art, music, and sculpture?

6. To what extent can the knowledge obtained by the scientific method be regarded as "true" in some absolute sense?

7. Develop further the argument that the academic disciplines are mutually dependent, and cannot exist entirely on their own.

8. To what extent, and in what ways can the cultural and intellectual elements of Western society function together more purposefully and harmoniously?

9. Which is more probable and why: that technological developments will reduce class distinctions or that they will increase them? Consider both the short and long term.

86

Page 87: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

10. Does the presence of the human element invalidate the claims of Science to be objective? If so, to what extent? If not, why not?

11. To what extent is the computer unifying or further dividing the academic world?

12. Write a defence of the academic tenure system, or a detailed proposal for changing it.

13. Expand further upon (or refute) the suggestion in the chapter that there is no such thing as "mere opinion."

14. Are some beliefs more important than others? Why or why not? Consider both the issues of probable truth and probable consequences.

15. Are some beliefs more permissible than others? Why or why not? Weigh freedom of speech against the possibility of some beliefs harming their holders or others.

16. Consider the two statements:a) "Religious faith and scientific rationalism/empiricism are absolutely

contradictory and can never be reconciled."b) "There is no conflict between true science and true religion."Defend one or the other of these two statements.17. Explore the contention that there is (or may be) a metaphysical element in

any position on origins. Do you take the same middle position as was advocated in this text, or a radically different one?

18. To what extent are the high-technology, industrial, and agricultural nations of the world mutually dependent? To what extent ought they be?

19. Does the advent of high technology mean that the gaps between the rich and poor nations of the world will widen or narrow? Discuss ways in which technology can be used to narrow such gaps, and ways in which national policies can be formulated to achieve such goals.

20. Is it fair to those countries that develop high technology to have them share it with poorer countries? What would be the consequences of not narrowing such gaps?

21. Research some examples of fraud, wishful thinking, research padding, or hoaxes in modern science and report on the significance of such events in the overall progress of science.

22. Develop further the theme that science and technology are really very different concepts.

23. Develop further the assertion that pure research is now seldom done apart from associated technological goals. You may wish to take the position contrary to that posed in question 21 and argue that science and technology are really just different aspects of the same thing.

24. Expand further on the theme that one technological advance often drives, or even requires others. Use specific examples from the past and suggest more for the future, based on present problems.

25. The text mentioned the assertion of Jacques Ellul that there is an inevitability to the quest for the most efficient techniques--one which tends to sweep aside all other considerations. The author expressed certain reservations

87

Page 88: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

about this, at least in theory. Read Ellul, and then support or attempt to refute his thesis.

26. Alternatively, attack or defend the thesis that even if technique is an irresistible force, it is leading nowhere (i.e., that it has no goal).

27. Discuss and expand upon the theme that one measure of a civilization is the size of the set of tasks that its citizens can perform without having to think about them.

28. Discuss the relative importance of teaching and research tasks for university professors. Do the priorities change if the perspective is that of the professor? the university? the student? the state? society as a whole?

29. Research the acid rain problem. What are the economic trade-offs involved in finding and implementing a solution to this problem? in doing nothing?

30. A major city built around a navigable inlet with spectacular natural scenery is considering the building of a crossing for the inlet. It could be a bridge, which some say would blight the landscape and create a navigation hazard. It could be a tunnel, which would do neither, but cost 50 percent more. The tunnel would also create more construction jobs, and based on past experience, there is less likelihood of accidental deaths during construction. How can this decision best be made?

Bibliography

Asimov, Isaac. Science Past--Science Future. Garden City, NY: Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1975.

DeGregori, Thomas R. A Theory of Technology. Ames, Iowa: The Iowa State University Press, 1985.

deSola Pool, Ithiel (ed.) The Social Impact of the Telephone. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1977

Creation Research Society (Homepage) <http://www.iclnet.org/pub/resources/text/crs/crs-home.html& Row, 1973.

Ellul, Jacques. The Technological Society. trans. New York: Knopf, 1973.Florman, Samuel C. The Existential Pleasures of Engineering. New York: St.

Martin's Press, 1976.Henson, H. Keith. Memetics and the Modular Mind--Modelling the

Development of Social Movements. Analog, August 1987: p29-42Hofstadter, Douglas R. Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. New

York: Basic Books, 1979.Holmes, Arthur F. All Truth is God's Truth. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1977.Klemke, E.D., et al. (ed.) Introductory Readings in the Philosophy of Science.

Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.Kranzberg, Melvin (ed.) Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology. Boulder CO:

Westview Press, 1980Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions--Vol 2 No 2 in The

International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (Second Ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970

Popper, K. R. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson, 1959

88

Page 89: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Racism, Science, and Pseudo-Science. Proceedings of the symposium to examine pseudo-scientific theories invoked to justify racism and racial discrimination. Athens, 30 March to 3 April 1981. New York: UNESCO, 1983

Schuurman, Egbert. Technology and the Future--A Philosophical Challenge. Toronto: Wedge, 1980.

Snow, C.P. The Two Cultures: & A Second Look. London: Cambridge University Press, 1963.

Smullyan, Raymond. Forever Undecided - A Puzzle Guide to Gödel. New York: Knopf, 1987

Stove, David. Popper and After--Four Modern Irrationalists. Oxford: Pergamon, 1982

Susskind, Charles. Understanding Technology. Baltimore, MD: The John Hopkins University Press, 1973.

Sykes, Charles J. Profscam Washington: Regnery Gateway, 1988.

Talk.Origins Archive--exploring the Creation Evolution Controversy <http://earth.ics.uci.edu:8080/

Chapter 3Basic Concepts in the Theory of

Ethics

Seminar - "Can We Define 'Good'?" 3.1 What is the Study of Ethics? 3.2 Moral Philosophy--The Good, the Right, and the Loving 3.3 Ethics and Pure Reason--The Legacy of The Greek Philosophers 3.4 The Nonabsolutist Philosophers--Morals are Decided Upon

89

Page 90: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

3.5 Traditional Absolutism 3.6 From Theory to Decision--Practical Morality 3.7 Summary and Further Discussion

3.1 What is the Study of Ethics? The first task facing anyone who desires to understand ethical issues is to

determine what is the nature of the things being studied. This task does not appear to be as straightforward as it does in some other disciplines. After all, moral objects are not the same sort as chairs, automobiles, or electric motors. Nor are they of the same sort as planaria, fir trees, water buffalo, harp seals, or even the girl next door. Consequently, the study of moral or ethical ideas must be approached rather differently than the study of physical objects, whether inanimate or animate.

For instance, an automobile can be measured; the relationships between its parts can be described completely, and detailed specifications for building another just like it can be developed. On a less exacting level, the owner of a car can use the senses of sight, touch, and possibly smell to distinguish a particular vehicle among a number of functionally similar but not identical ones. On yet another level, an automobile can be described in terms of its performance. One might wish to own a car that can stop from 100 km/hr in less than 10 seconds, or can accelerate to this speed in less than 20 seconds, or uses less than 10 litres of gasolene to the hundred kilometres (in some places this would be expressed in miles per gallon). These performance factors can be tested for and the results published for all to see. Decisions can then be made on the basis of concrete, reproducible, experimental data.

The point is that scientific methods can be employed to describe (in some kind of statistical or numeric sense) every physical object and every living thing. Not only can the natural earth and its contents be so described (geology, biology, chemistry, and physics), but so can the products of human invention (engineering and technology)--all this despite the reservations about the nature of reality discussed in Chapter 2.

There are some things that are relatively less tangible that may nevertheless be physically measurable and therefore open to an exact study. Consider the colour red, for instance. By agreement, people use the word red to describe a particular part of the visible light portion of the electromagnetic spectrum. Someone could object that "redness" might not be perceived by everyone in the same way. However, the mutual agreement means that it is still possible for any person with normal vision to decide whether or not something is red simply by referring to personal knowledge of this consensus. Everyone has from birth been involved in an indoctrination into a language for describing the properties of the physical world, and in particular, into the meaning of red.

It is not even necessary to know what an electromagnetic spectrum is in order to be a part of the consensus that some object has the redness property. Even though there are many shades and kinds of red, the communication of the idea of this colour does not at all depend on any technical understanding of the idea. Redness can be communicated accurately, even though the term is an abstraction of a physical property, and not, in the strictest sense, a measurement (although it

90

Page 91: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

could be turned into one by attaching a particular wavelength of visible light to the word). This is true even though it cannot be guaranteed that every person experiencing redness does so in exactly the same way.

The difficulty with moral objects--like others that are not physical in nature--is that one cannot often describe them in the same ways as one does the physical ones. If one says that it is "good" to tell the truth, for example, one must ask what is meant by "good." How can one tell when such a quality is present, and how does one know whether some actions have more goodness than others--that is, how does one quantify goodness?

Goodness is clearly not an adjective that describes a physical object like a chair. It is also a different kind of abstraction than is "red," for the latter can be thought of as referring to a measurable physical quality, even if neither directly nor exactly. Redness describes something in the physical world, even if those who use the description do not know or care about the scientific principles underlying the concept. Goodness, on the other hand, may not be physical, but most people do attach detailed meanings to the term. Though a Christian would ascribe the quality of goodness to God alone, many do not point to any person or thing as its origin, yet still assert that it exists.

The study of moral issues is not only different from that of science but also from, say, history, sociology, or economics (even though it once included the latter two). In the last three cases, the exact methods of science may not always be applicable, but the practitioners of such disciplines all agree that they are studying something tangible. That is, they are certain that factual determinations can be made in these disciplines and that there are objective truths to study or discover, even if the character of such determinations is quite unlike the character of physical objects.

For instance, not all historians would agree that "Nero fiddled while Rome burned", but they would agree that the truth or falsity of this statement is at least theoretically determinable--capable of being decided on the basis of the weight of testimony of a sufficient number of reliable witnesses. The historian gathers accounts of the incident under study and attempts to weigh these accounts to get at the truth--and assumes that there does exist an objective and discoverable truth. The outcome of such a study may not be supported by a repeatable experiment in the same sense as in a laboratory science, but the outcome is not regarded as less than "knowledge". Furthermore, historians assume that any similarly competent person can repeat a study of the available evidence and either come to substantially the same conclusions or attempt to achieve some new consensus of what is the historical truth. The important concept is the agreement among historians on methodology, evidential content, and (ideally) conclusions. Even where there are disagreements about these, there is no argument that an objective truth does exist.

Likewise, not all economists would agree ahead of time on whether a tax reduction would decrease the average price of a can of beans, but all would assume that with good and sufficient data, such actions can be studied after the fact and well-founded conclusions drawn as to what the effects have been. That is, economists always suppose that they are studying something real in the sense of its

91

Page 92: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

being perceivable and measurable, even if they cannot always agree on how to make the measurements or on what the data mean.

To summarize, in the scientific disciplines one gathers first-hand, empirical evidence in a repeatable fashion and evaluates this data to verify a knowledge assertion statement. In several other fields, data of a slightly different type are accumulated and conclusions are drawn on the basis of what seems to be the weight of evidence. Even where the facts are in dispute, there is little doubt that all these disciplines have a factual basis.

The study of moral issues is not as straightforward, for in this case one cannot explain varying views of truth merely by making allowances for imprecision and differences of interpretation. Disagreements go deeper, for it is more difficult to obtain agreement about the nature of moral statements, what they are based on, where they come from, and whether they are well-founded. This difficulty is not lessened even when there is agreement about the content of a statement. For example, several moralists might agree that "Abstinence from sexual relationships outside marriage is good" constitutes a valid moral statement, but each one could have a different reason for saying this. Other moralists might agree that such a statement is deserving of study but would disagree with the content. Still others might deny even that the statement is worth making or has any meaning.

In addition, two moralists might agree on the nature and validity of a factual statement, but act in very different ways as a result because they hold to differing views on related moral issues. For example, two people might agree that "the incidence of AIDS is increasing" is a true statement, and even that this fact has moral implications. They might then come to opposite conclusions about how those having this disease should be treated socially. These differing conclusions have to do with the philosophical and religious presuppositions behind their moral reasoning processes, and the extent to which knowledge of the facts, fear, or prejudice enter into their thinking.

It is easy to make statements about whether an action is right or good, without giving the matter much thought or even being aware of what these two words mean. Are they synonyms or do they have slightly different connotations? Can they be defined in terms of other words that do not have moral/ethical meanings, or is the concept each conveys an irreducible and indefinable idea? Are they (as some claim) such subjective terms that their meaning is private to each individual and not communicable to others?

At this point, it would be valuable to set this discussion aside for a while and attempt your own definitions of these two words. (Try it!) Most people find that they can readily produce a number of additional synonyms to elaborate on the moral concept of goodness. This procedure sets a word in the cultural context of a list of other words with similar or identical meanings.

One teaches children in this manner, first tying a word-abstraction to a concrete object, and then enhancing the child's vocabulary by referring new words to the abstractions the child has already learned. For instance, the word "car" could be taught by pointing to the family vehicle. At a later date, if the child questions the word "automobile," the earlier abstraction "car" can be referred to. If this fails, a trip to the garage for another look at the physical object would be in order. At some

92

Page 93: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

later time, perhaps in a high-school automotive course, the child will become able to redefine car in terms of an assembly of simpler and more fundamental parts.

This example makes evident several difficulties in assigning meaning to words with moral content, such as good and right. Here are a few of the more interesting ones:

1. Are "good" and "right" synonyms in the same manner as "car" and "automobile?" That is, if one sets aside varying meanings in other contexts, do they have exactly the same meaning in a moral context?

2. What is the concrete object that can be pointed to in order to define a first word with moral connotations, and so get a handle on the remaining synonyms? That is, if goodness and rightness cannot be found in the garage or on the street, where can they be found?

3. For the more sophisticated inquirer, what are the constituent parts of goodness and rightness into which these complex ideas can be disassembled for more detailed study? Or, are there none--because these are irreducible concepts that cannot be defined in other terms?

Aspects of the last two questions, the most difficult, shall be dealt with in this chapter. For the moment, note in connection with the first question that a problem arises because there are many uses for the word "good" that carry the meaning "desirable," "more than satisfactory," or the like. There are similar problems with the word right. Consider, for instance, the use of the word good in the following statements:

1. World War II was good for the North American economy.2. Vanadium is a good catalyst.3. Friendship is good.4. It is good to tell the truth.

Historians and economists might argue about whether statement 1 is true as it stands, but they would be comfortable with modifying and qualifying it until they had a version that they could agree was either true or false. The record of their decision would also carry with it a review of the facts or statistics that went into making the decision, as well as a discussion of what were the agreed-upon criteria to place positive or negative interpretations on movements in a nation's economy. With all this in hand, similarly qualified experts who did not participate in the initial decision would have the means to become a part of the consensus (or not) at a later time. However, even if other experts did not agree with the conclusion, they would have little trouble attaching rather specific meanings to the word good as it is used in the initial statement.

Likewise, scientists would also have to qualify statement 2, for it may not be true under all circumstances. Moreover, this assertion is true as it stands only relative to the effectiveness of other catalysts in similar circumstances. It is not even necessary to know exactly what Vanadium is or what catalysts are in order to realize that meaningful criteria could be established and experiments done to verify

93

Page 94: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the truth of statement 2. A person who knows little or nothing about chemistry could imagine a numerical value being attached to this use of the word "good" such as: "A good catalyst shall be defined as one which speeds up the progress of a chemical reaction by a factor of at least 3.14 over what it would be in the absence of said catalyst." In short, there is some general agreement in such cases about what the word "good" will be taken to mean, and disagreements about the meaning will be neither sharp nor divisive but simply indicate that a better definition or a more specific term is needed.

It is much more difficult to say precisely what statements 3 and 4 mean, and even harder to determine their validity. There are two groups of questions associated with such statements.

The first questions focus on meaning. What kind of statement is being made? Is it a description of a fact? Is it an expression of the belief of one person or of a small group of persons? Is it, on the other hand, the declaration of a generally accepted consensus--that is, a collective decision of society? Does the statement represent the conclusion drawn from some logical thought process by a repeatable method of deductive reasoning from more fundamental principles or assumptions? Or, is it perhaps the announcement of a discovery in a way similar to the determination of facts in other disciplines? That is, has some principle of the moral universe been uncovered that has the same kind of validity as a physical law by virtue of being inherent in the reality perceived? Does this mean that there is a moral sense, like that of touch or taste? These questions will be considered in following sections. For now, note simply that the greatest division among theories of "good" is on whether such ideas are decided upon or discovered.

What exactly does the word good mean in the contexts of statements 3 and 4? It seems clear that it means something fundamentally different than in statements 1 and 2, but just what? Does good carry the same meaning in 3 as it does in 4, and would both statements still convey the same idea if one used the word right instead?

The second group of questions focuses on the validity or content of such statements. How does a person determine if statements about moral concepts are true? Even granted that people can reach an understanding or at least an agreement about the meaning of goodness in both statements, how does one determine that friendship or truth-telling belong in the category of things that are good? Is there only one good of which all others are aspects, or are there many goods? If many, what happens if two goods are in conflict? Is it possible to prioritize goods or rights so that such conflicts can be eliminated or at lest reduced?

Furthermore, if something is in the category of good, does it also follow that it should be pursued--that is, does there exist an imperative that what is good ought to be promoted or done by everyone? (This last question adds a new one to the first group: What do the words "should" and "ought" mean in the context of moral statements?) Finally, who or what authority is authorized to pursue the shoulds, and with what force? That is, if good does imply should, can society or an individual in it legitimately require behaviour that ought to be done because it is good?

It will come as no great surprise to learn that many books have been written in the attempt to answer these questions. A complete survey of all the schools of

94

Page 95: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

thought on all of these points is far beyond the scope of this work, but in the balance of the chapter an attempt will be made to summarize the major positions on these issues. Anyone who considers seriously the specific social and moral/ethical issues raised in this book must at least have some idea what it is that people are doing when they make moral judgements, and how the judgement-making method in question fits in with those of the major schools of philosophy.

Before going on, here are three working definitions:

The study of the meaning and nature of moral statements is called moral philosophy.

The study of the content of moral statements with a view to applying them to right and wrong human behaviour is called ethics, and one who makes statements resulting from such study is termed an ethicist or a moralist.

Profile on Issues . . .

The Good and the Should -- A few Questions

Once the good and the right is known or believed to be true, what power has it to constrain a course of action? Here are samples of questions that arise in such contexts.

Self-enforcement: Does the knowledge of good automatically imply a person will do that good?

Does failure to do good mean the person did not know the good? Who is responsible for the failure -- the one who did not do good, or all those who did not ensure the person fully knew the good? Does it make a difference if "belief" is substituted for "knowledge?"

- Who is responsible for crime -- the criminal, society, or no one?

Individuals enforcing the good on others: Can one individual require a second to do what the first knows or believes to

be good?- May a parent require a child to submit to the parent's beliefs? discipline?- Ought a person intervene to prevent another person from being harmed?

(killed, beaten, robbed, raped, defamed, economically exploited, harassed)- Ought a person intervene to prevent another person from self-harm?

(suicide, reckless driving, using drugs, entering a bad business or social contract, believing wrong or harmful things)

- If so, ought force be used? To what extent and in which situations?

The State enforcing the good on individuals: 1. Must the state enshrine its citizens' moral consensus in law or are there

circumstances in which law is above moral consensus? If the latter, does the state have a duty to re-educate its citizens to a new and correct (by its own lights) morality?

95

Page 96: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

2. May the state require (with what force?) its citizens to submit to (agree to) the political, moral, or religious theories on which it is based? To what extent ought it permit seditious talk? action?

- If a parent has religious objections to blood transfusions, may the state intervene and force one upon a child to save life?

3. Does the state have the right to require a certain religion of all its peoples? no religion? If in the name of impartiality the state separates itself from or ignores religion altogether, does this constitute anti-religious discrimination?

- Is the reason for the separation of church and state the prevention of state involvement in the church or church involvement in the state? both?

- May the state legitimately regulate the employment practices, business affairs, or teachings of churches? of church-owned schools? May it require the hiring of an out-of-work pastor or teacher on welfare? May it overrule the church's decisions on whether to admit a member to the church or a student to its school if these decisions conflict with its own agenda?

- May the state overrule a church on questions of morality, declaring that since a behaviour is legal, the church contravenes the law and violates individual rights by declaring it to be immoral?

- Does the practice of granting property tax exemptions for churches and income tax deductions for contributions to churches constitute state promotion of religion? what about religious slogans or sayings in a nation's constitution? on its coins?

4. How closely may the state observe and regulate the economic activities of individuals in the name of promoting the common benefit, detecting cheaters, or ensuring fairness?

- Ought it keep cross-matched records of all economic dealings so as to spot income tax cheats?

- Ought it sell census data to private marketers?- Ought it to guarantee certain minimum medical protection, dental

protection, living accommodations, food, clothing, or wages to its citizens?5. Should the state enact laws discriminating against a dominant religious,

political, sexual, or ethnic group in order to redress perceived past inequities giving that group an advantage?

- Should the state fund minority lobby organizations for them to press their case to the state?

- Do university entrance quotas favouring minorities work to the advantage or the detriment of the minority? the majority? the university? society?

- Ought women be front-line combat soldiers?6. What punishments may the state legitimately employ against those who

break its laws (none, economic, physical, social)?- Which of the following ought the state be permitted to do:o require certain actions of its citizens to prevent self injury, and subsequent

economic loss to others and to the state? (e.g., compulsory seat belts, motorcycle or hockey helmets)

o censor the advocacy of violence against some group? the promotion of fraudulent schemes to obtain money? the advertising of dangerous goods?

96

Page 97: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o prohibit substances (drugs) or objects (hand guns, assault rifles) deemed dangerous?

o publish the names of convicted criminals in the newspaper?o confiscate the assets of criminals for state use?o imprison those convicted of violent crimes? of economic crimes?o make restitution to the victims of crime?o require restitution from those convicted of a crime?o physically punish certain criminals, say, whip a child molester or rapist, or

execute a murderer?o lock a device on the leg of a convicted criminal or parolee to track the

person's location?

The State enforcing the good on another State:May one state intervene with another when the second violates its citizens

rights by the laws of the first? by international law? What if the international law is unwritten, or has never been agreed to by the offending nation?

- Should a nation intervene with (a) economic, (b) political, or (c) military sanctions if another state:

o invades a third state to capture its resources or to kill its peoples?o systematically oppresses a group of its own people because of the colour of

their skin (blacks in South Africa) their religion (Moslems, Jews and Christians in Communist countries), or their economic political and ethnic background (the middle class of Kampuchea, out-of-power tribes in Uganda)? What if oppression becomes large scale slaughter?

o kills large numbers of its own citizens for protesting state tyranny (students in China)?

o engages in a methodical economic exploitation of most of its citizens in order to enrich the rulers and their friends (rulers of many countries)?

o harbours (encourages and finances) terrorists or criminals (drug dealers, murderers, thieves) whose activities are detrimental to other states?

o employs economic and social systems known to be inefficient and harmful to its people (Communism)?

o is over fishing international waters whose resources are vital to itself? o uses industrial processes that are polluting the first nation? (acid rain,

chemicals dumped into border rivers and lakes)o subsidizes its own industries or otherwise allows them to sell goods in the

first nation at prices lower than they can be produced there?

Does God Intervene?The oral traditions and scriptures (including the Bible) of several religions

record instances of God (or gods) intervening in the affairs of individuals or nations to enforce some good or right action. Does such "higher intervention" still take place? Is there a corresponding outside action directed against good and for evil?

3.2 Moral Philosophy--The Good, the Right, and the Loving

97

Page 98: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

As long as the human race has existed, in all of its societies, there have been codes of moral conduct. For example, a person might be expected to keep a promise or to tell the truth. Indeed, it is difficult to imagine how any society could exist where contract- or promise-keeping was not practised. Likewise, there are always some restrictions on sexual relations, as well as on violence to settle disputes. Behaviour deemed suitable on some occasions is not on others, and severe violations of a given society's codes always result in organized consequences.

There are four sets of these conventions governing interpersonal behaviour. They are religion (including magic and witchcraft), ethics, etiquette (including folkways), and the law. The last two are conventions to enforce behaviour patterns, so they are largely derived from the first two, which are collections of beliefs about behaviour. Also, the influence of religious ideas upon ethics is very strong. In addition, the word "moral," though often used as an unqualified synonym for "ethical," tends to have religious overtones. In this context, the Bible has had a particularly powerful influence on Western civilization and its ethics. It offers an externally referenced explanation of the origin of ethical ideas external to humans by referring to God who is absolutely good. It also offers an internal one, citing the role of conscience.

The very existence of society implies that there is an organized control on the interrelationships among members of the society. Agreements about what constitutes acceptable behaviour, (i.e., rules of conduct, morals, and ethics) are the essential glue that holds society together. When these rules are codified and documented, they are called laws, and their enforcement may be delegated to particular authorities such as police, lawyers, and judges. When they are enforced by peer pressure alone, they may be referred to as etiquette. Among free peoples, a consensus is necessary on what ought to be the content of law for there to be any practical possibility of enforcing them. Under a tyranny, any law deemed desirable by the state--no matter how oppressive--can be maintained by sufficient application of force. Examples of such in this century include those headed by Stalin, Hitler, Mao Zedong, Pol Pot, Idi Amin, "Papa Doc" Duvalier, and a host of other brutal dictators in all parts of the world.

As long as there have been scholars, people have wondered where such ideas of what is good or proper behaviour came from. What follows is a classification of answers given to such questions. For purposes of simplification, the categories are larger than those which moral philosophers would usually create. Distinctions are made on the kinds of responses that would be given to questions raised in the last section. The material here is only one way of summarizing a vast body of literature.

To begin with, schools of moral philosophy could be divided into three major groups on the question of where ethical ideas originate.

Group I--Moral/Ethical Laws Are Deduced by Pure Reason

For this group of moral philosophers, ethical statements are obvious, in the sense that logic alone is sufficient to arrive at a knowledge of what the statements contain and how they are to be applied. This perspective, the position underlying

98

Page 99: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

some of the traditional Greek philosophies, has had a strong influence on Western civilization, particularly in its notion of justice as a high ideal that transcends both law and actual human behaviour.

The fundamental assumption of these philosophers is that all who are sufficiently trained in the art of reason--anyone who proceeds in a rational and logical manner--will arrive at the same moral principles. In this view, ethics, too, is not a product of culture, history, or opinion. Rather, to the properly trained mind, moral rightness is thought to be found intrinsic to the universe.

Group II--Moral/Ethical Principles are Decided Upon

Others assert that moral questions are decided upon as an act of the will. To this group, a moral principle such as the requirement for truth-telling represents a collective decision of society that such behaviour is desirable--a decision that may only partly be the result of some logical thought process. That is, moral laws are not proven like mathematical theorems, but are arrived at because society collectively deems them (for whatever reason) to be in the best interests of most of its members. This theory does not so much describe why specific principles are agreed upon; it merely asserts that this is the process by which they come about.

Group III--Morals and Ethics are Derived From External Absolutes

This group asserts that moral principles exist independent of the will of any individual, or even that of humanity as a whole. Here, moral principles are universal, either because they are part of the very attributes of God, or because they are in some other manner built into the very fabric of human existence, or even of the universe. In this view, humans do not so much deduce or decide upon appropriate moral behaviour. Rather, they discover or have revealed to them preexisting principles. They then choose whether or not to apply these.

The Psalms summarize nicely this view that goodness is part of the character of God, flowing by revelation through to human beings.

The law of the Lord is perfect, reviving the soul.The statutes of the Lord are trustworthy, making wise the simple.The precepts of the Lord are right, giving joy to the heart The commands of the Lord are radiant, giving light to the eyes The fear of the Lord is pure, enduring forever.The ordinances of the Lord are sure and altogether righteous They are more precious than gold, than much pure gold;They are sweeter than honey, than honey from the comb.By them is your servant warned; in keeping them there is great reward. --

Psalm 19:7-11

Blessed are they whose ways are blameless, who walk according to the law of the Lord.

Blessed are they who keep his statutes and seek him with all their heart.

99

Page 100: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

They do nothing wrong; they walk in his ways.You have laid down precepts that are to be fully obeyed. -- Psalm 119:1-4

Within these three large groups one can further distinguish several positions that depend on what the members of the various schools of philosophy say about how many--if any--universal moral principles there are. One can also make distinctions on whether moral statements are regarded as:

o binding--prescriptive of what ought to be done.o non-binding--descriptive of what people actually do.o emotional--expressing the opinion of what someone likes people to do.

The positions taken on these questions also depend heavily on where the philosopher thinks moral ideas originate, so some of these will be considered as subheadings under the three main groups. The experienced student of philosophy will have no doubt seen a variety of other, slightly different classifications of this same material.

3.3 Ethics and Pure Reason--The Legacy of The Greek Philosophers This section will examine the first of the three views just mentioned--that

moral statements originate through a process of reason or logic. In this view, all who are trained in the application of logic must necessarily arrive at the same conclusion about ethical matters. Those in this group agree that moral principles are absolute, for logically derived principles do not change with the majority opinion from one place or time to another, as logic itself is immutable. They also tend to agree that more than one absolute exists. Consider this statement as a simplified representative position of this group:

Moral statements are absolute because they are arrived at by pure reason. They are related to self-evident virtues, each statement promoting a single virtue. There are no conflicts among these moral

statements because they do not overlap.

As mentioned earlier, this was the position of certain Greek philosophers, including Plato and Aristotle. It has also been adhered to in various forms in more modern times, a common modification being the omission of the second sentence, or even a recognition that conflicts may indeed exist between the different absolutes.

However, despite the contention that logic alone is sufficient to arrive at ethical statements, actual conclusions of this group about the number, nature, and priority of ethical principles vary widely.

Plato held that the goal of the rational person was the cultivation of personal virtue (or excellence) and happiness. In his view, such a person knows what is true by pure reason, can control the desires, and is capable of both philosophy and command. The ideal ruler in the Platonic state is its best philosopher. Some of the virtues that Plato put forward were temperance, courage, wisdom, and justice. Aristotle, on the other hand, emphasized those of friendship, pride, and moderation.

100

Page 101: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Today, it is easy to underestimate the importance to these teachers of human reasoning and the spoken word (logos) they used to convey that reasoning by way of argument. The logos of reasoned argument was not just a symbol or even just a conveyer of meaning; it was the very substance of knowledge itself. Logos made reasoned discourse possible; it was, therefore, the very stuff of knowledge; it was what made one truly human.

On the other hand, the interesting thing for a modern reader of Plato and Aristotle is the near total absence in these philosophies of any discussion of right and wrong in the moral sense that these words were usually used in the Christian societies that followed. These philosophers did not equate virtue with what has been termed morality in modern culture. Rather, they believed that such concepts were either self-evident or incidental to the training of the virtuous. Likewise, modern concepts of justice--such as "all are equal before the law"--would have been foreign or perhaps even immoral to Plato. To him, it was entirely correct that there be differing standards for the virtuous philosopher-governor on the one hand and for the uneducated masses on the other. Again, it would not be so much, say, truth-telling, that was at issue to Aristotle, but loyalty to one's friends. The long-term goal was the perfection of pure reason in governing the relationship between individuals and the state. Indeed, it would be accurate to say that the advancement of a person's rational life was the ultimate good in these schools.

Issues of right and wrong in ordinary life were in a different and much lesser category than the pursuit of philosophical excellence. Such matters were regarded as being common knowledge, within the reach of ordinary people, and sufficiently self-evident even to the untrained as not to be worthy of detailed rational consideration. Here is a clear separation between common morals, which anyone could understand and apply, and the ethics of virtue, to which only the deep thinker could truly aspire. Once having achieved an understanding of those ethics, they could be justifiably proud of the difference between them and the common person. Indeed such issues as friendship could arise only between good men; one could not be friends with a slave (thought of as a living tool) or a woman (not regarded as rational beings). Some taught philosophy to women as well, but this was uncommon. These principles might be summarized in this way:

Goodness refers to virtue, and rightness to action.

Another illustration of the difference between modern Western ideas and the ideas of some of the ancients can be found in Plato's concept of justice. In his view, the just person must fulfil his or her proper role in a state--that of ruler, administrator, or citizen. Each person has a natural position of control or subordination, and any perversion of this is an injustice. No one should ever seek to act outside their just station in life. To propose, therefore, that the same laws should apply to both commoner and king would be illogical, and therefore seditious.

As to the common morality, Plato's belief was that there was a moral nature with which the rational person lived in harmony, even though this might often be in contradiction to the conventions or practice of the non-rational person. In this view, morality is part of nature itself; it is not man-made or dependent upon culture or

101

Page 102: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

invention in any way. It is part of the natural order, as are male/female distinctions, skin colour, and the nature of fire, earth and sun.

In an ethics based on reason, moral laws are supposed to exist apart from convention, culture, or decree. They do not change with time or civilization. They simply are. The task of both the individual and the state relative to such matters is to determine the correct natural order of morality and justice and then to change convention, law, behaviour, and legal justice so as to conform to that right order. In this view, it is not only possible but also probable that the vulgar, uninformed, and irrational masses will have as a conventional morality a code that upon rational examination will prove to be immoral, because whatever common opinion may be, true (logical) knowledge cannot be wrong.

Socrates, according to Plato, held that a person who once knew what was good could not choose to do evil, and therefore the acquisition of knowledge through philosophy was sufficient to attain to all virtue. Moreover, wrongdoing in anyone's own eyes can never be a voluntary act. Thus, for example, an evil tyrant could never be happy or informed.

By the time of Immanuel Kant (the late 18th century), these traditional absolutist views were virtually unchallenged. Kant reformulated them in terms of a law of duty (not love, which is an emotion) that he called the "categorical imperative." Briefly stated, it is this:

Whatever one does, one must act in a manner that is consistent with wanting that action to become a universal law. The corollary to this is that people are to be treated as ends, not as means to an

end.

Kant was so convinced of this law of duty, which he claimed to have formulated by pure reason, that he rejected any mixture of love, compassion, or the pursuit of happiness in governing actions as dangerous corruptions of the Moral Law. He regarded the categorical imperative as the triumph of pure moral reason.

However, there are several flaws to the notion that true morality can only be discovered through pure reason. The first is that the actual law discovered by Kant seems, if it stands alone, to be rather arbitrary. Why not pick some other law, such as "Do what enhances your own self interest?"

It seems apparent that Kant was trying to bring within the sphere of duty (his highest goal) a statement incorporating the Golden Rule of Jesus Christ, "Do unto others as you would have them do unto you." Because of the potent influence of Christianity in the Europe of that era, it was important to Kant that reason seem to achieve the same ethical result as religion. At the same time, Kant believed that he was not merely modifying the Golden Rule but held that even if Christianity did not exist, pure reason would have discovered this principle unaided. Kant believed duty to transcend not only philosophy but also the results produced by the application of the senses (science). It was by serving duty in accordance with the categorical imperative that all true notions of etiquette, morality, and law would be derived.

In summary, Plato concluded that ethical duty was collectively owed to society, or the state. Aristotle stressed friendship, and Kant decreed that the primary imperative was to duty itself. For each, the well-governed state had an

102

Page 103: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

obligation to enforce moral laws, putting weight behind the transition from the good to the should.

There are five great difficulties with such views of ethics. The first is that if they are valid, all philosophers ought to arrive at the same conclusions about what are the highest principles of moral law, and ought to apply them to ethical conduct in at least very similar ways. That they do not suggests that one needs to seek another source of absolutes than unaided human reason.

The second is the abstractness of the concepts. Such theoretical ideas often seem to have very little practical context. It is not clear how to use such a system to make applications to specific situations in order to act morally. It is not always clear what is meant by the term "virtue" or what specific qualities ought to be included within its purview. Likewise, it is difficult to agree on what specifics do flow from the categorical imperative. This abstractness is not necessarily just a weakness, for the strength of the categorical imperative also lies in its generality, which is achieved precisely because the statement speaks not to the ethics of specific actions but to the moral process by which the ethics of any action is determined. On the other hand, such generality, along with many specifics, was already present in the Bible (and to a lesser extent in other religions) before Kant; his work refocused Biblical thinking rather than providing a radical departure from it.

The third is that actual experience also forces one to question the assumption of some absolutists that the sufficiently well-informed person cannot choose to do what is wrong. On a most practical level, this assumption mocks the aching heart of every parent who has taught a child to do right, only to have the child grow up to do evil instead. That this actually happens, and does so frequently, calls into question the Socratic assumption that adequate knowledge of good alone is sufficient for enforcing good behaviour. On a global scale, the increase in all forms of knowledge would presumably carry with it more knowledge of what is good, and this would in turn result in a more moral society. Yet, the last three centuries have seen as much war, tyrannical oppression, brutality, and other evils as have any time in human history, if not more. Indeed, although education has been more extensive in scope and application during the latter part of the twentieth century, it has become abundantly clear that knowledge and goodness demonstrably do not increase together. One could argue that it is the absence in the curriculum of the study of virtue that is at fault, but as those who control the schools cannot themselves agree on what, if any, moral principles ought to be inculcated, it appears that this avenue is a dead end.

Fourth, there is somewhat of a ring of arbitrariness to these philosophers' conclusions. It is easy to imagine coming to a different conclusion than that of Kant's, and indeed modern philosophers no longer do place the categorical imperative at the top of their list of logical conclusions about morality. Other considerations have become paramount, and other priorities have risen to the top. This would appear to be a fatal blow to the whole concept that sufficiently trained thinkers will always arrive at the same conclusions about moral philosophy.

Fifth and finally, a Christian must argue that since all aspects of humankind, including the intellect, are fallen and flawed due to sin, we do not have the ability to reason perfectly, and therefore could not come to correct conclusions about moral

103

Page 104: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

principles by unaided reason. In this view, the ability to reason as God would do is damaged by the fall, and therefore the process and the conclusions are bound to be wrong (at variance to God's) at least some of the time. Thus, at the end of the day, the Christian discovers at the heart of this theory a mistaken confidence in human reason and so must reject this theory of moral philosophy as fundamentally defective, and even idolatrous. It is also not enough to rescue the morality-as-pure-reason theory to say that humankind is made in the image of God and can therefore think His thoughts after Him, because this weak attempt at a recovery still ignores the fall, and so is fatally flawed.

All these considerations and others are the object of many books. They have led modern philosophers to consider a number of other positions, some of them nonabsolutist.

3.4 The Nonabsolutist Philosophers--Morals are Decided Upon

Position 1: Moral statements have little or no meaning.

The most extreme position here is occupied by those philosophers who assert that there is no such thing as absolute morality. That is, there are no universal norms on which choices of right or wrong can be based. To this group, called antinomians, there are not only no discoverable moral ideas independent of human reasoning, there are also none that can be reasoned out from first principles or axioms--that is, antinomians deny the existence of any such axioms. A few of them may accept the existence of a good god but yet deny that even his revealed principles for human behaviour always apply. At the very least, members of this group will assert that such words as good, right, moral, and ethical are all essentially synonyms for some indefinable concept that is common to all these terms but cannot be explained in simpler words. They conclude that such words are therefore meaningless in any practical sense.

Some of these go farther, arguing that moral statements are absolutely without meaning because they are not about physical objects and are not therefore verifiable though scientific methods. They also assert that moral statements are not logically deducible from non-moral premises. These thinkers, variously known as logical positivists or materialists, hold that logical argument and the scientific method applied to the material world are the only possible ways to know anything; all else, including moral statements, is rejected as irrelevant. What isn't knowable from the application of the five senses and the filtering of data through the scientific method isn't knowable at all, so it isn't anything.

Despite taking this stand, some might still consider moral statements to be useful, even if they are not verifiable. However, this usefulness would be entirely utilitarian and pragmatic. For example, a speed limit serves the purpose of promoting a valuable kind of order in which fewer people are inconveniently and messily killed. Perhaps, they might argue, moral statements are of a similar nature, providing all realize that they have no inherent compelling force of their own but are merely convenient conventions or agreements. That is, etiquette has a use but not morality, because the latter term implies a universalism that the former does not.

104

Page 105: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

In this view, unethical behaviour, if there is such a thing, is not absolutely wrong because wrong has no fixed meaning. However, some in this camp might concede that if a behaviour inconveniences or harms a sufficient number of people, society has a legitimate right to restrain it. This is a democratic view of ethics and one that has some appeal, for right and wrong can be almost anything that the majority in a society want them to be. Of course, to say that no absolute wrong has been done seems like cold consolation to the victims of rape, to the families of hostages, to those who have been defrauded, or to others whose "level of inconvenience" is rather high. However, this view does assert that terms such as "good" have some use, even if they have no meaning.

Some antinomians may go even further, holding that the terms right, wrong, good and evil have neither meaning nor practical use. In this extreme view, all people have an absolute right to do whatever they personally conclude is proper, and there exists no authority that can legitimately restrict this right. All people have the total personal responsibility to assess whatever situations they are in and to act accordingly. To say that an action is wrong is an unwarranted invasion of privacy; no person can legitimately participate in, or even comment upon another's moral decisions. Herein lies the ultimate of freedom: there are no bounds, no chains, and no responsibilities--one is accountable only to oneself. This view is sometimes termed libertarianism, though those who hold to social and political movements bearing that name might have less extreme personal views.

Some would moderate this view, correctly observing that it does uphold at least one absolute, namely freedom. They advance this principle as the best contribution of the antinomians:

Always act to maximize your own freedom and that of others.

Adopting very much from of the antinomian position would make this book either very short or entirely unnecessary. The whole subject of ethics would be quickly disposed of if it were so neatly to be defined out of existence. The scientist who denies the existence of reality may still be motivated to study the appearances of phenomena but the person who denies the existence of the moral appears to have no basis to be a moralist. The chief difficulty with all antinomian positions, even in their moderated forms, is that they provide little or no basis for agreed-upon forms of appropriate social interaction, in particular, none for law. They are, in short, a formula for anarchy rather than for society. If each person is a law alone, then civilization is already dead and those who remain are but its pallbearers. This observation also applies to unions, companies, and other organizations within the larger society that occasionally claim the absolute right to act in the self-interest of their owners or members without any regard for the rest of society. That is, they define good to be what advances their collective power or position, even at the expense of all others.

These difficulties lead to another variation on the antinomian theme: although morality is not absolute, it is nonetheless appropriate for the strongest in any given group to create and control society as they see fit. In this view, rules of conduct are arbitrary rather than absolute. Those who are strong must arbitrate codes of

105

Page 106: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

behaviour for the weak, enforcing such codes through their position of strength. It may be argued further that the evident superiority of some human beings gives them both the right and the duty to be the arbiters of morals. Anything else, they could continue, would be an encroachment of the weak upon the strong, and such is not to be borne. Clearly, there are borrowings here from Plato, even though these would deny his premise that morality is absolute. These views are also compatible with those of the social Darwinists, who hold that human society and ethics are evolving in a process of natural selection that will guaranteeing the survival of strong people, strong ideas, and strong ethics, as well as ensuring the unlamented demise of the weak. That is, since the aspect of progress called evolution is inevitable, the more highly evolved (the strong) need to be little concerned with the rest (the weak) as they are bound to be selected into oblivion.

The problem with theories of this type lies in the determination of who the so-called strong are, and why. As the Nazis showed so graphically, the logical conclusion of any theory that purports to uphold a superman morality is that the supposed superior beings may claim the right--even the obligation--to eradicate those perceived to be lesser beings. After all, their reasoning goes, they are merely helping the inevitable progress of evolution to achieve its predetermined goals, so they are doing right.

The world is not so far removed from the Holocaust that it should forget what such twisted reasoning did to the Jews of Europe during World War II. It is easy to make a political or economic scapegoat of a group of people who, for philosophical reasons, are regarded as lesser beings. Once a group has been intellectually ghettoized (for whatever reason) it takes very little time to decide to physically segregate them as well. It is a thus a small step from such a philosophy--which is just a mask for religious or racial hatreds--to genocide, and it is a step that has been taken many times in history. There is no reason to suppose that it will not be taken many more times.

However, even if this most extreme conclusion--that the lesser beings should be eradicated--is not drawn, but the rules that govern society are entirely arbitrary (because there are no moral absolutes to derive them from), then it will at least follow that the strongest arbiter will ultimately rule the rest. That is, the normal end result of an arbitrary moral code is totalitarianism. Once this situation comes to pass, it does not matter to those ruled by a tyrant whether the tyranny is of the political left or right. It is here, in the arbitrary suppression of the ruled, that Fascism and Communism, having left the stage on the right and left, meet and shake hands behind the scenes.

The cyclical view of history popular with some Greek philosophers held that in the decay of the moral principles that brought democracy onto the scene ,such tyranny was inevitable. To some extent, this theory has support from the historical record, for it can be seen in operation in Greek and Roman times as well as in modern societies. When the glue of moral consensus dissolves, the society also disintegrates. It then becomes ripe for a takeover by a tyrant from within or without who can impose a new order. On the other hand, if an imposed order is actually just a thin arbitrary veneer over a number of competing hatreds, the removal of the

106

Page 107: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

external force leads at once to anarchy, and this fact has been thoroughly demonstrated in Eastern Europe in recent years.

Taking all this into consideration, the principle of maximizing freedom seems to be the only valuable contribution of the antinomians. Yet this principle contradicts the idea that there are no absolutes, for it is apparently being enshrined as just such an absolute. For the purposes of this book, it will be assumed that both anarchy and tyranny are unacceptable and that even freedom must be tempered, for freedom is not the same thing as license. Because of the undesirable outcomes of antinomian, there is a strong practical motivation to look elsewhere for the meaning of moral and ethical statements.

There are religious reasons to do so as well, for antinomianism expresses the hostile antithesis of any belief in a supreme being who has the authority and the character to define what is good and hold creation accountable to do it. Since, for example, Christianity does hold such a position as of fundamental importance, it is impossible to follow Christ and also be an antinomian.

Position 2: Moral statements are a general consensus.

The philosophers who hold to this view accept that moral statements are meaningful. They do not believe such expressions to be discoveries of universal principles, but rather to be general decisions about behaviour made with the ends in view which that conduct should produce. That is, they concentrate on the results of actions rather than on the actions themselves. Actions that lead to desirable ends are defined to be good; others are less so. Two actions leading to the same end are equal in moral content, even if they appear to be contradictory in themselves. For example, in this view, if the same result can be achieved by lying as by telling the truth, then the two courses of action are morally indistinguishable.

There are two main groups of philosophers who held this view, the hedonists and the utilitarians. The hedonist believes that the chief end of a person's life is the maximizing of pleasure and the minimization of pain. This is a natural outgrowth of the starting premise, for if only the ends of actions are important and not the actions themselves then one might as well put one's own pleasure first and follow that with the pleasure of others, if any energy remains.

Some hedonist schools have attempted to define or even quantify the measurement of relative amounts of pleasure for varying numbers of people, but this philosophical position remains at its core a self-serving one, with little support or concern for the benefit of others. Thus, since moral issues are raised principally to discern what one's relationships and responsibilities to society as a whole ought to be, the hedonist view has little to commend itself in a study of societal issues. Indeed, from the point of view of society at large, it seems to have little to distinguish it in practice from the antinomian. The latter disclaims mutual responsibility for moral behaviour on the grounds that no such thing exists; the former on the grounds that pleasure supersedes responsibility and is the only worthwhile pursuit. It is difficult to imagine how either can provide a basis for any kind of society--an association of people working and living together to fulfil

107

Page 108: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

common goals--because neither provides a motivation for being especially concerned about the other members of a society.

Perhaps hedonism's most serious shortcoming is its failure to account for the extreme situation in which the majority in a society are sadists whose pleasure is maximized by inflicting pain on others. The hedonist, even if uncomfortable with this situation, would have little choice but to admit that the majority of such sadists would do good in torturing, murdering, or otherwise causing pain for the minority.

In stark contrast to hedonism, the Bible draws entirely the opposite conclusion about pleasing oneself by holding up the example of the Christ:

"Do nothing out of selfish ambition or vain conceit, but in humility consider others better than yourselves. Each of you should look not only to your own interests, but also to the interests of others. Your attitude should be the same as that of Christ Jesus: Who, being in very nature God, did not consider equality with God something to be grasped, but made himself nothing, taking the very nature of a servant, being made in human likeness. And being found in appearance as a man, he humbled himself and became obedient to death--even death on a cross!"--Philippians 2:5

Moral philosophers who are not hedonists but still hold a consensus view of moral statements may be loosely termed utilitarians. These attempt to develop a philosophy of the maximizing of good results for the largest number of people, without necessarily using the word pleasure to describe that good. The essence of this view can be summarized by the principle:

Always act to bring the largest benefit to the greatest number of people.

This is also a democratic view, though clearly of a different sort than the one that says there are no good norms. Utilitarianism acknowledges the existence of both legitimate moral statements and a form of mutual responsibility. For this reason, it is a widely accepted popular philosophy, and many people embrace moral principles that they perceive as being utilitarian.

However, even the non-hedonist utilitarian still has the problem of calculating the relative amounts of good in the ends of moral acts in order to justify the acts themselves, and this problem stubbornly resists solution. The person doing the calculation is almost certain to weigh personal benefit most heavily, so the dividing line between hedonists and utilitarians tends to become obscure.

The chief difficulty in this position seems to be that actions are regarded as having no intrinsic value in themselves. An attempt to save a drowning child would not in this view be a good act if it failed. If the would-be rescuer dies in the futile attempt, then far from being a heroine, she is a fool. If she dies, but the child is saved, then the act is at best neutral, depending on how one evaluates the relative worth of the two lives.

There is also very little in this philosophy for the person seeking any kind of ultimate meaning to life and its activities, for unless one knows ahead of time what

108

Page 109: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

will be the outcome of an action, there is no motivation to perform it or to avoid it--yet no philosophy offers a method for predicting the future. Decisions must be made at the time action needs to be taken, when the consequences are difficult or impossible to foresee. It is then that a person needs a sense of whether an action in itself is good; and it is not often that the time is available for computing probabilities of various possible outcomes and weighing these for perceived good results.

Thus, on the one hand, this philosophy has considerable value as a means of attempting to find a justification or condemnation for actions already completed, based on their consequences. On the other hand, it fails as a means of making decisions about conduct itself--it seems impractical to apply in real situations, even though it sounds good in theory. Moreover, as with antinomianism, hedonism and utilitarianism both conflict with the view that there is a God who can and does dictate absolutes. Thus, the Christian, for instance, must decline to use such theories as a basis for judging actions.

Position 3: The only moral statement is the law of love.

This position holds that the most desirable collective moral decision is to set forth a standard of love for persons (not things) as the single universal ethical imperative. This is an attempt to capture a middle ground between the antinomians (no rules at all) and the legalists (rules for everything), and it seeks to do so by setting forth a single intrinsic good, namely love. All actions are relative to the principle of love; they have otherwise no positive or negative value of their own. The principle might be stated as follows:

Always do the loving thing.

Once again, as in the previous cases, actions are not in themselves good. Instead of having the relative value of actions decided by results (as in utilitarianism), actions are judged by the motivations behind them. No general rules for responses to particular situations can be given, because one cannot know in advance what a lovingly motivated response or action will be. Instead, one must wait to be in the situation to decide on the most loving course of action.

Because of its emphasis on doing the loving thing according to the situation, this moral philosophy is sometimes called situationism. In this system, there is no rule book for behaviour, and there are no principles by which actions themselves are judged; only motives have a value attached to them. This position differs from the ones above in that it holds that there is a universal norm--that of love--but it is similar to utilitarianism in that each action is judged in a manner that attaches no value to the action itself but is essentially pragmatic (but with loving motives replacing good outcomes).

This position is also relativistic, for any other ethical norms are valid only relative to the one universal principle. Indeed, they are only valid if they happen to serve the law of love in a given situation. It is not possible to say that either lying or promise breaking is bad in itself, for the situationist might decide at some point that lying is the most loving thing in a particular circumstances and is therefore good.

109

Page 110: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Moreover, this strategy is a personal one. Its practitioners concentrate on the person who is to be the object of loving action rather than on abstract ideas of right and wrong actions.

Notice that the corollary to this principle is essentially the same as that of the categorical imperative, even though the motive for stating it is quite different:

Things are to be used, people are to be loved. Above all, people are never to be used as means to an end.

The love so expressed could even in some cases be akin to the New Testament concept of agape--the giving of self without respect to merit or expectation of return. It is most particularly not erotic love, which is seen as self-serving rather than truly loving, and it is much more than brotherly love, fraternal affection, or friendship. Therefore, such expressions as "sexual morality" are at least difficult to discuss if not entirely meaningless in such a philosophy, for a sexual act of whatever kind is never thought of as wrong in itself. Morality depends on the motivation of the participants, rather than on the act itself.

Because of the emphasis on the value of persons and because of its claim to be able to resolve apparent conflicts in marginal cases (do the most loving thing), this theory is attractive for a variety of people, whether their moral convictions arise from religious considerations or otherwise. However, this position is not without its difficulties, though they are not as great as some of the ones already examined. The chief problem is that love is ambiguous. If there are no discoverable universal principles--and therefore no outside references from which to obtain a definition--then what is love, and from where or whom does it acquire meaning? Does love get its meaning from the situations in which the principle is applied? If so, situationists are faced with a circular definition, for love was supposed to be the judge of the situation. How can the term gain its only meaning from the situations for which it is supposed to be the arbiter? Is love an emotion--and is one supposed to "feel" the loving thing in a particular situation? If so, love may not be a moral idea at all, for emotions differ both with personality and over time.

There seems to be no way to judge the lovingness of a situation other than by being the one experiencing it. Once a principle becomes so personal that it cannot be the same for two people (or for the same person at two different times) it can no longer effectively be communicated at all, and so loses all practical claim to have meaning. Thus, if situational experience or emotion alone are the guide for morality, it is not clear how this system differs in any practical way from antinomianism. Additional rules are needed to clarify what love is.

There is no way out of this difficulty, for if there existed any other rules by which one could determine the meaning of love, then love would not be the only universal norm but would share its position with some other norm. Not only that, but the situationist also seems to have the same problem as the utilitarian in making any decisions ahead of time as to the value of actions. Computations must still be done at the worst possible time--when a decision is necessary and action must be taken. Here it is the maximizing of love that must be computed rather than the maximizing of so-called good results, but the effect is not likely to be much different

110

Page 111: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

if such approaches are used, for in both systems actions have themselves no moral content and are at best catalysts for something else.

What is more, it has become common to advocate self-love as the highest or most important form of love. Whenever this is so, love-situationism becomes indistinguishable from hedonism.

There is an even more serious problem, namely, the decision to choose this particular single norm. The choice is supposedly not based on the discovery of any more universal principle than love, but is a collective decision of society. However, the motivation for this collective choice of love is unclear. Could not something else have been chosen--say hatred? This possibility reveals that there must be some more fundamental principle that leads to the decision to choose love. For example, in the Christian religion love is an attribute of God that is revealed to human beings in the form of the gift of his son to die for sin. This is reciprocated by believers in him by loving God, and thereby love between human beings is also legitimized . "Love your neighbour as yourself" is not the most comprehensive statement of this, but rather, "hold others in higher regard than yourself." Thus, Biblical agape (selfless) love has a context and is part of a hierarchy of activity in which love for God--not simply love itself--is at the top of the pyramid.

With no authority beyond their choice of norm, the situationists' love, on the other hand, stands alone, unsupported. In practice, this love is often identified with sexual activity and situationism used to justify a complete license in this regard, as if the broader society could not conceivably have any interest in any social or medical consequences. While it is not quite fair to associate this position exclusively with the so-called sexual revolution, the difficulty it has in dealing with this important and closely related area is a powerful argument that the theory is incomplete. Moreover, situationism is sometimes expressed in the slogan "if it feels good, do it," and in this form it also becomes indistinguishable from hedonism.

Sexual mores raise yet another problem with situationism, particularly when expressed in the latter form. When a paedophile has sexual relations with a child, both parties may feel at the time that the activity is loving. Yet, society persists in regarding such actions as exploitive, harmful to the child, and wrong. Yet it is difficult to see how to reconcile this revulsion with situationism, for if the parties feel right and loving about their actions, on what basis can anyone else condemn those actions? To proscribe pedophilia is to say that the feelings of love at the time of the act are not the same thing as true love, and therefore to establish a higher norm that claims to be able to examine actions themselves for lovingness. While this would seem to be an improvement on an ethic bases on completely personalized feelings of love, it does at least undermine the premise that one can indeed judge what is the loving thing in a given situation.

Indeed that society would want to urge any restraint at all on the satisfaction of sexual cravings at any time or place, or with any person, suggests that self-control is being held up alongside love as a parallel value, and that love does not in fact stand alone.

Christians also have little choice but to reject this moral theory, because they hold that humankind is fallen, and therefore that feelings of love are unreliable at best, and twisted at worst. Moreover, they hold that God who defines what is good

111

Page 112: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

does not change, and that therefore moral principles, while they might have to be adapted to apply to a given situation, transcend all human experiences and situations. Biblical morality has a universality that goes beyond one's feelings of love at the time of an individual act.

Ethics as a Social Contract

This is another relativistic theory of ethics. Its operating principle and chief contribution is contained in the following:

Ethics consists of a mutual behavioural agreement between individuals and the society in which they live.

This statement contains an important truth, for it recognizes the dependence of individuals upon society and vice-versa. As has been noted several times already, society is a mutuality and its very existence depends upon predictability in the relationships between its members. Here, this concept is acknowledged and ethics is regarded as codifying the mutually agreed-upon contract. Being a part of society means that individuals have both written and unwritten obligations to the culture as a whole, including to other individuals. In return, society has an obligation to its members to provide a predictable framework within which to live and act.

It is also possible to deduce from contractual ethics other principles, for humanity as a whole has an ethical contract (by virtue of sharing the habitat) with the global environment--particularly with other living things. Thus, there is an obligation to secure and maintain both the physical and social environment.

Thus, the contractual view has great strength, for it seems to give individuals a substantial framework within which to make ethical decisions. Yet this strength is simultaneously a weakness, for it focuses upon the existence of contractual dependence without giving any guidance about the contents of the contracts. Neither does it contain an intrinsic way to determine the relative importance one ought to attach to different contracts when their obligations conflict.

Not many people will acknowledge themselves to be bound by contracts whose contents are vague or unknown, and for which there is no external enforcement mechanism. Thus, the operating principle has worth but it does not go far enough by itself to be of practical value; it must be combined with one or more other expressions to guide the choice of good actions. In short, at least some of the contracts need to be specified, and this need places all the specific contracts at the same level of importance as the norm of their existence, shading this ethical theory over to a somewhat rules-based system after all. That is, although the notion of dependence is valuable because no one's actions exist entire to themselves, until an ethical theory can provide specifics, it is inadequate for the whole task of governing behaviour.

Contract ethics also shares the weaknesses of all democratic views of right and wrong behaviour, for a contract agreed to by a majority may well be unbeneficial or even fatal to a minority. The majority might agree together (a contract) to exterminate all the Jews (or all the Christians) but the mere existence of

112

Page 113: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

such an agreement surely is not sufficient to show that it is right. The fact that it is possible to show that there are social contracts that are not in fact desirable once again points us to the need for a higher set of norms whereby social contracts have to be judged. Moreover, if it does attempt to create a hierarchy of value or importance for contracts, it tacitly admits that there are better or even best contracts, and so begins to become absolutism in the end.

The Judeo-Christian view that has shaped Western civilization does not deny the existence of binding duty contracts, but would view them in the context of higher obligations to an Almighty God rather than as just mutually agreed-upon democratic ideals. Indeed, the Bible is replete with examples of covenants that entail behavioural expectations, but these are agreements whose terms are dictated by God Almighty on His terms, and subsequent human arrangements are expected not to conflict with one's contractual obligations to Him.

Summary

Over the last few centuries a variety of nonabsolutist ethical theories have been proposed by philosophers, some of which have become quite popular. On the one hand, the extreme antinomian theories virtually deny the existence of right and wrong; and on the other hand, the relativistic ones assert that nothing definite can be said about an act itself, for rightness and wrongness depend on other things. Considering the changing views of practical morality, it is uncertain whether these (mostly) relativistic theories actually influence behaviour or were simply used to explain and justify whatever a person fully intended to do anyway. Since a lack of guiding principles is inimical to the very existence of society, and since actual experience with relativism has not had very positive results, it may be that the future holds a return to some form of absolutism.

Profile On . . . Issues

The Slippery Slope

An argument used by conservatives in all eras goes: "One departure from traditional norms starts a process leading inevitably to complete corruption." This is called a "slippery slope" argument, because the premise is once society starts down certain paths, it cannot help but slide to the bottom. Moral relativists discount or ignore such arguments, but to illustrate they have some validity, consider what might once have been thought a slogan for behaviour:

If is right in God's eyes then do it.

has tended to become the allegedly more democratic

If it seems right in our own eyes, then do it.

113

Page 114: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Situationism shortened and refocused this, rendering its social slogan:

If it feels good, do it.

This at least still requires some judgement (about the feelings, not the actions). However, in the late 1990's (at a time when little effort is put into thinking about morality at all) the social slogan has become:

Just do it.

The final outcome of a few decades of the triumph of situationism has been antinomianism after all.

3.5 Traditional Absolutism In contrast to those who hold that ethics can be arrived at by human beings

alone--either by logical deduction or by mutual agreement--traditional absolutists hold that ethics transcend not only human reasoning and society but humanity itself. In this view, right and wrong are meaningful even without reference to philosophy or culture. That is, moral ideas do not come from the human mind or from mutual agreement, but from somewhere else. Philosophers of these schools are agreed that moral principles are absolutes, but they differ on how it is that such principles are known or discovered. In this section, several such positions are examined. The first is based on the idea that every person apparently knows there is such a thing as right and wrong.

Position 1: Ethics are discovered by an inner sense that is capable of distinguishing right from wrong.

This widely held view has both great strengths and great weaknesses. Proponents can claim that defenders of pure reason will be liable to arrive at similar conclusions because each is directed by the same inner moral sense. They can say the same of utilitarians and situationists, who (they hold) ought normally to decide that the greatest good or the greatest love are whatever the idealized inner voice says they are.

Certain of the Eastern mystic and meditative religions have a view of morality that could in some ways be thought of as falling in this absolutist category--even though they are not always directly concerned with right and wrong in the same sense as Western philosophies and theologies. Rather, some of them stress being true to one's inner self, a self that is in some fashion part of a universal life force or flow in the universe. The inner being is, in effect, a god--or at least part of a god. Self-examination in the form of meditation, particularly if the physical body can be

114

Page 115: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

cast aside or ignored, leads to knowledge of deity within. A life of peace with all (for all share the life force) is assumed to be the consequence of such knowledge becoming universally experienced.

In one sense, this is an absolutist theory, for it asserts the connection of the inner voice to a universal "all." In another, it is relativistic, for each individual must find the inner voice alone, and no specific and reliable absolutes for moral conduct can be offered by those who have trod the path of enlightenment before, nor is any guidance offered for recognizing when the true self has been found.

Moreover, it is not actions that are the issue for these mystics but the process of meditation toward self-actualization itself. If there is a goal, it is a state of harmony rather than a behaviour. Because of the individualistic emphasis and their process orientation, theories like these have also recently become popular in the West, where they are often combined with astrology and spiritism as parts of the so-called New Age religions. It is too soon to judge whether this latest infusion of mysticism will have any long-term effects on Western thinking and society, or whether it will prove to be a passing fad. Note however, that this theory of goodness is also directly opposed to the Judeo-Christian one, which holds that God is entirely external to the created order, and is not in some fashion contained or created within the physical universe, or actualized only by each person's meditation.

The notion that good can be found through some inner sense--whatever that sense is called--is held as doctrine by many religions, though they disagree on the details. It is also held by secular philosophers, who give other explanations for it. Some of the Greek philosophers were inclined to this view with respect to questions of ordinary right or wrong, for they regarded these concepts as self-evident--matters of common (inner) knowledge, and so not the proper focus of philosophy, which ought rather to be goodness in the sense of the virtuous. These last concepts were worth putting under the microscope of logic, but everyday morality was obvious to all, and did not need to be questioned or examined in this way. All people knew about moral rightness; philosophers had more difficult and more interesting concerns to subject to the logos.

Likewise, since everyone in society supposedly has this inner voice, a social contract ethics is also easily arrived at. All would desire the same agreement, because all have (access to) the same inner knowledge.

The chief point of contention among those who hold this absolutist position has to do with the reliability of this inner knowledge of good and evil. If every human being has such an inner sense and the moral laws detected by the sense are indeed absolute, then everyone should access the same body of knowledge and produce the same results. However, people do not all act in a way consistent with there being a single set of moral imperatives. What can one say about this?

There are at least three answers to this objection. To understand the first, it is necessary to ask once again whether knowledge necessarily results in application. It is easy to see, for example, that the knowledge of scientific principles does not imply even the existence of an application, much less an exclusive or universal one. Two people who know the same theory will not necessarily discover identical applications.

115

Page 116: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Likewise, people often act contrary to all good advice, common sense, etiquette, and even the law of the land. They can and do contradict other voices; there is no reason to suppose that they could have an inner voice but simply refuse to listen to it. That is, Socrates was wrong--knowing the good does not always imply that a person will do it. Different actions do not mean that the right is not absolute or that it is not known, merely that a person has chosen not to perform it. Whenever theory is put into action, there is an act of the will to make a decision. That a human being is capable of willing to do good in agreement with conscience implies the possibility of willing to do otherwise.

It is in an effort to make wrong choices less likely that laws are instituted, both to codify the consensus and to mandate sanctions against violators. For the sake of long-term stability, then, law ought to conform to the broad and historical international consensus (many listeners to the inner voice), with such local modification as thought necessary to suit local conditions or emergent technology. Specific issues relating to law will be discussed in Chapter 9; for now, note that a narrow self-interest, whether by one person or one nation, is unethical according to the standards of this position (It contradicts hedonism).

Second, though the existence of a moral sense has long been widely believed to be true, the notion does have its critics. Those inclined toward moral relativism dismiss the whole idea, saying that no inner sense can exist to detect moral absolutes, for there are none to detect. That is, they say that if any voice is being heard, it is merely that of the majority custom of society.

There is a third answer to the difficulty of actions not following knowledge--a Judeo-Christian one. In this tradition, the inner voice of right and wrong was given by God in the context of the fall from grace into sin. Adam and Eve ate the fruit of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil (i.e., of conscience) because they chose to disobey. However, since through their act the whole human race fell into sin and out of fellowship with God, conscience cannot be a reliable guide because it is corrupt. Indeed, no person out of fellowship with God can assume that conscience is trustworthy. Such a one may not even believe there is a voice of conscience, much less act upon it.

Nonreligious proponents of the inner sense idea have a more difficult time with the knowledge/action problem. The best answer may be that bad teaching and some wrong choices corrupt the inner voice and cause it to be more easily ignored, but this answer actually weakens their position. A critic might then ask, "How do you know that the inner voice is not just collected memories of parents teaching the behaviour they wanted?" One response in return is to observe that people seem to be able to apply this sense even to situations they did not face as a child.

A weakness of that response is there are sometimes two contradictory claims to conscience. For example, one person supports nuclear arms as a deterrent against war and a second opposes such weapons altogether. One person advocates funding recombinant DNA research and a second considers such work an abomination. Similar contradictory claims of conscience are made for the use of animals in research, in vitro fertilization, abortion, surrogate motherhood, artificial intelligence research, and many other contentious techniques. In each case, two sides cite the deep conviction of what they say is conscience and cannot understand

116

Page 117: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

how an opposing view can be held. One may try to overcome this problem by claiming that some of the issues cited here are questions of custom, and however dearly held, customs are not morals. Such a reply may be partially correct but still does not explain away all instances of contradictory conscience. Neither is such an explanation likely to be heard by either side of a dispute whose protagonists hear only their own inner voice, not that of any others. An assertion that conscience has become corrupt may help somewhat, but only if there is something besides conscience by which it in turn can be measured and corrected. Otherwise, there is at the present time no logical difference between a corrupt conscience and none at all. Moreover, if there was a point in history before which (or after which) conscience did not exist, there must at such times also have been (be) other standards by which good and evil can be distinguished (if they can be discriminated).

It is therefore possible to go at least part way toward meeting all but a last and most serious objection to the idea of an inner moral sense: its proponents are unable to prove logically that it even exists. Its secular proponents acknowledge this weakness when they call this theory intuitionism. Yet it nonetheless has the authority of both an extensive tradition and some practicality behind it. The inner voice theory is attractive because it seems to be true in the experience of most people, despite the difficulty in bringing forward logical arguments to demonstrate the existence of this sense. Perhaps most people would concede that there is such a thing as conscience, but also agree that it can neither be proven to be reliable nor be regarded as the exclusive source of ethics. Summarizing a modified form of this position:

Everyone has an inner, though possibly flawed, moral sense.

This principle has in its favour the independent belief in it by peoples of widely differing cultures and times. It has against it that conscience is used to justify widely varying and even contradictory actions, and these differences can only be explained in terms of flaws in conscience or by the existence of other absolutes with which conscience coexists or by which conscience is judged.

Position 2: Rules for human conduct are absolute and at least ideally nonconflicting.

The variations within this general group depend on the extent to which human conduct is covered by these rules. Staunch legalists may well have a rule for everything; others will offer far fewer. Some make no claims about the origin of the rules; others are sure that absolute rules can only come from Divine revelation. They may believe that religion is the authority for their moral code, and that they must adhere to the code approved by their god. This group believes that no moral rule can ever be broken without incurring guilt. In religious legalism, the basic set of god-revealed moral laws will often be augmented by a much larger codification of institutional (church) law that is continually being added to, much as are national laws.

Legalism in all its forms has a great attraction for many people. Neither philosophy nor conscience is much needed, for the rules are readily available for

117

Page 118: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

consultation. Furthermore, in very religious versions, fear of a god's punishment (or institutional rejection) for the slightest violation of these codes is a powerful incentive to obey.

The problem with legalism--and with any other theory that holds that absolute norms do not conflict--is that people nevertheless must sometimes have to choose between norms. A standard example is that of the spy who is caught and must when questioned either lie or be disloyal. To the classical legalist, this is a choice between evils, and the person who makes the choice is not absolved from guilt by the requirement that the choice is forced. The resulting guilt is real and must be confessed, repented of, and (possibly) atoned for.

Despite this problem, and regardless of the religious overtones, legalist positions have probably been the most popular of traditional absolutist moral theories in Western civilization and have served as the basis for many extensive national codes of law. The chief contribution of rule-based absolutism can be summarized by this statement:

There exist external and absolute rules for moral behaviour.

Also of interest here is that rule-based ethical systems are the most vulnerable in times of rapid technological change, for in such transitional periods there are always a large number of novel issues that arise in connection with the development and use of new technology and that defy analysis by the old interpretations of rules. Although there will be efforts to introduce new rules (such as Internet censorship), in the period before the rule makers catch up a kind of moral anarchy may prevail with respect to the new techniques. Because this aptly describes today's situation, the present sociotechnological difficulties serve as an excellent illustration of the difficulties with legalism. These problems lead to another absolutist position.

Position 3: Principles for human conduct are absolute. They exist in a hierarchy wherein the doing of a greater good absolves one from a conflicting choice of a lesser good.

Some of those holding this view would also (like the last group) state that the absolutes in question come only from God. One difference between this position and the last is immediately obvious. In the case where absolute norms come into conflict and a person must choose, no guilt is here attached for breaking the lesser of the norms (provided, of course, that the norm being rejected is indeed the lesser).

Arguments used against Nazi leaders at the Nuremberg war crimes trials after World War II fall into this category. To the claims of Nazis that they killed Jews because of a duty to follow orders, the prosecution replied that there was a higher natural legal order forbidding genocide that made their actions a crime against all humanity, and therefore punishable even though the defendants had broken no laws of their own country. The court accepted this argument, enshrining in international law the notion that there exists a hierarchy of values that can be used to judge even law itself, and that this is true even if the higher principles have not been formally codified by any country, much less by them all. That is:

118

Page 119: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Duty to all humanity is of a higher order than duty to one's country.

There are also overtones here of Plato's concept of an overarching justice that is above law, behaviour, and opinion.

Consider also the example of the captured spy cited in the last section. The situation would be interpreted quite differently from this point of view. The hierarchical moralist says that since the good to be done for a just cause is greater if the enemy is deceived than if told the truth, there is no guilt attached to breaking the lesser norm (lying) for the sake of fidelity to the higher (a just cause). Of course, if the spy is supporting the wrong cause...

Students of the Old Testament might be interested in consulting Joshua 2 for an example of this type. This is the story of Rahab the prostitute who lied to the soldiers of her own town of Jericho concerning the spies from Israel, throwing in her lot with the invaders. Despite betraying her city, she gains a high commendation, marries a prince of the realm, and becomes an ancestor of King David, and so also of the promised Messiah. There is more to this than just happening to pick the winning side; she chose the higher good by aligning herself with the forces of God and against those of idolatry.

Another very modern sounding instance of a hierarchy of values in the Bible concerns the issue of surrogate parenthood--not for the mother but for the father. Old Testament law forbade a man from having sexual relations with his brother's wife. However, if an oldest brother should die childless, the next brother was commanded to father his brother's children for him with the widow, so that the dead brother's name would be perpetuated. Evidently the issue of family continuance was sufficiently important to override the usual norm, and to do so even though it might cost the younger brother his own chance at the inheritance, as he preserved it for those who would be his older brother's legal children. So important was this obligation to redeem the name, land, and heritage of the heir that the duty passed to the nearest relative when no brother was available. When Ruth asked Boaz to become her husband and kinsman-redeemer, it was to perpetuate the name and line of Elimalech before establishing his own. In agreeing to this arrangement, they two also became a part of the line of the Messiah, as David was their direct descendant as well.

Workers in countless situations must trade off the values of company loyalty and the pragmatism of profit for professionalism in their work, safety considerations, and the quality of a product. Politicians must strike a balance between personal friendships, party loyalties, personal beliefs, and the need to govern a country. Athletes must choose between the value of winning and that of playing an honest game. Students may need to trade higher marks and better job potential for the same honesty in their writing.

Examples can be multiplied--in practice, people do prioritize their values. The difficult problem is to create an actual hierarchy of principles that incorporates, as much as possible, the important insights of the other theories but that still remains absolute.

What can a hierarchical ethicist propose as a suitable ordering of moral duties? Here is one of many possible outlines; this one is based on the discussions

119

Page 120: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

of this chapter. The first duty and possibly the second, are Judeo-Christian contributions. Some would omit both, but moralists with a religious background might argue that the first two are the only important part and that the rest depend on them to such an extent that they cannot be neglected. They encapsulate the idea that moral absolutes are not discovered or voted upon, but revealed by God as part of His character. The third one includes duties not previously emphasized in the chapter and does so in order to recognize the social contract and obligations to people, and also to place humankind in a context of life and even the inanimate environment.

An Ethical HierarchyFirst Principles:1. Love of God comes before all else, for only in such love can one gain the

good virtues and the ability to perform right actions, and only by God's revelation can one discover that there do exist external and absolute rules for moral behaviour.

2. Love of other people takes priority over love of self. This is an aspect of revealing the good character of God to others.

The origin of ethical principles:3. Ethical norms are absolutes that are revealed by God as aspects of His

character.

Resolution of conflicts between norms:4. There is a duty to people; next there is one to animals, then to other living

things, and finally to the inanimate world. This is an aspect of the stewardship God gave at creation.

5. Duty to many people supersedes duty to a few people, yet the many have a duty to protect the few who cannot protect themselves.

6. It is better to be a whole person than an incomplete person. This may be applied to self or to others.

7. Actions with foreseeable or demonstrable effects weigh more heavily than those with possible or theoretical effects.

8. People are more important than things, even if they are still in development, or otherwise incomplete. Duty is owed to people regardless of whether they are deemed to be completely developed mentally or physically.

New Situations:9. When it is necessary to derive new ethical norms from the absolute

principles because revelation is insufficient and does not cover new situations or technologies, one should adopt the following rules:

a. Act according to the inner voice (conscience) of virtuous people (not necessarily only one's own).

b. As far as possible, do what is the most loving thing, not ignoring conventional and prudent wisdom for emotion, nor following such customs blindly.

120

Page 121: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

c. Act to maximize the benefit to the largest number of people (this includes their freedom).

d. Remember that each person has a social contract with other people, the biosphere, and the earth.

This is not a complete list, of course, because it reflects only the brief discussions in this chapter, with a few additions. It will do for illustrative purposes and will help in considering various cases later in the book. It should also be noted that after point two the ordering is mainly within the points rather than between them.

Apart from placing love of God and other people first and second (for those who require those points there), this list does not rank the persons or things to which duty is owed, only some of the duties themselves. Thus, one may wish to place duty to family before duty to the next-door neighbour, and duty to one's own nation before duty to people in other nations. Placing that hierarchy with this one would add another dimension to the obligations, as well as another set of potential conflicts to be resolved. Such complexities illustrate that the obligations that bind people to other people may be hierarchically ordered to some extent but are actually practised in a multidimensional network, rather than simply in a top-down fashion. Also, the attempt to express duty to humankind within the context of duty to God may be useful but in a rapidly changing society may appear for a time to be inadequate to explain all the details of interpersonal ethical obligation. This problem is not unique to ethical systems whose cultural heritage is religious; ethical responses may grow from various original principles, but the specifics of how they are worked out change as society and its technology do.

It can readily be seen from this discussion that hierarchical absolutism is not the same as rules-based absolutism. It reflects the complexity of moral choices and attempts to emphasize character rather than simply ritualistic obedience. That is, it suggests that the making of moral choices is required from without, learned from within, and applied as part of a dynamic growing maturity. This permits the hierarchist to adapt rules to situations rather than making them up on the spot and to respond with love without allowing feelings to supersede objective morality.

It is also expressed positively. The person who asks: "What is wrong with what I am doing?" is waiting until it is too late and then asking the wrong question. Rather, this hierarchy suggests that one should ask: "What is best about my possible choices for action?" and then have some measure of the mature character needed to discern or discover the answer. A Christian would do better still by asking: "What does God want to do, and how can I line up with that?"

Elements of this list are also reflected in some of the other nonhierarchist or even nonabsolutist philosophies, and this serves to illuminate what has been presented in this section. For instance, the situationists' law of love is incorporated by the second and last points, and Kant's categorical imperative is closely tied to the fourth. That ethical norms come from outside individuals or even whole societies is reflected in point three. Reflections of Plato's concepts of duty within the context of the state or society are found in point five, and this item together with the last also includes the notion of a social contract. The idea that a morally educated and

121

Page 122: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

informed person has a natural advantage over one who is not is covered in point six. It also suggests that actions that cause people to build or retain wholeness of mind or body are better than those that do otherwise. The calculation of relative goods is addressed by several points but embodied in a particular fashion in point seven and nine. Point eight asserts the primacy of people over things again and extends it even to the full potential of life for development of human life. Together with point four, it asserts, for example, that an undeveloped, uneducated, or otherwise helpless child is of more importance than, say, money. Point nine recognizes that hierarchical absolutism does not have a rule for every situation and must use every available tool to derive new rules from the old.

One must not suppose that this list agrees in every point with those that all or most hierarchical ethicists would provide, nor that it gives a complete statement of, say, Christian ethics, which, according to Carl Henry (Christian Personal Ethics), is best interpreted as hierarchical. Such a comprehensive undertaking would fill a far larger book than this one. However, as indicated, this list does provide a touchstone to important elements of several ethical systems. Although not everyone will agree with it in every respect, it is an attempt to order the contributions of the major ethical theories in a way that incorporates them into a non-legalistic absolutist position.

Christian Ethics and Legalism

Even by many of its professed supporters, Christian views of ethics have often been legalistic. However, if the Biblical documents (rather than institutional traditions) are taken as defining Christianity, then this religion claims both to explain and to set aside legalism. Those who followed Moses had a direct and special relationship with God. They were to strive for holiness, not for the sake of formal legalism, but as a witness to all other peoples and nations of the essential good character of God. That they bore His Name was significant; being His people meant being like Him.

New Testament doctrine holds that the Mosaic law was also intended to prove that God's standard (perfection) was too high for any human to achieve unaided. He is too holy to approach except in perfect holiness. In other words, achieving essential goodness through legalism is impossible. On the contrary, argues the New Testament, legalism can only condemn, because no person can obey a legal code faultlessly and without guilt. Thus, an entirely different view of access to the goodness of God is required.

The New Testament goes on to proclaim that Christ took all the punishment required by the holy God for the guilty upon himself during the torment of his crucifixion. Thus, those who believe in him and understand that his death was a personal substitution are set free from their guilt. In addition, believers are transformed and made fit for presentation to God by having Christ's perfect righteousness attributed to them at the same time that their belief in Christ sets them free from their guilt. Thus, for those who receive His grace, the condemnation of an impossible legalism is paid for and at the same time, Christ's real goodness is

122

Page 123: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

imputed to the believer. That is, goodness is a gift from God rather than a personal achievement.

Consequently, Christians do good actions not to gain God's approval, which God has given them without respect to merit, but as acts of gratitude for having already received his free favour. The result is supposed to be a living out of the goodness of the inner spirit of God in practical life and actions. This is possible for the faithful through God's power, despite a natural human inclination to do evil and despite a corrupted conscience. In this view, such a life is the only achievable human good, for goodness is a character attribute of God alone, discovered only by knowing God in a personal way and having God's goodness placed within oneself. Right actions then follow automatically, for they flow from a good heart, and are not a striving to gain favour. To put it another way, God gives his goodness to the believer, and this enables the person in question to do right actions.

In practice, this view of Christianity has only indirectly affected society. Attempts to codify specific rules for Christian behaviour seem invariably to lead to institutions that are to some degree legalistic. These organizations (whether churches or governments) when grown large enough, have exerted most of the actual religious influence on the culture and laws of the West. Still, Western legal heritage owes much to the influence of the Judeo-Christian scriptures, and this is no more evident than in such notions as human rights, which are often incomplete or missing in places that lack this influence.

This view of Christianity also suggests that although ethics must be practised in social and institutional contexts, the moral absolutes are practised expressed personally and individually as the outgrowth of a character directly impacted by that of God's Holy Spirit for His purposes--and not as part of ritual obedience to either the state or a church institution. Indeed, Christ condemns the Pharisees precisely for the error of turning what should have been a matter of character into a set of external rules.

Moving On

With the proposed hierarchy, it is time to conclude the subject of ethical theory and turn to more practical matters. From this point forward, theory will not be of foremost concern, but it will underlay many of the discussions in subsequent chapters. For the purposes of examining actual issues, the author will take the view that rules-based absolutism is both stifling and inadequate; that the non-absolutist positions all inevitably lead one to antinomianism and the destruction of the social fabric; and that only hierarchical absolutism is able to deal with the actual complexities of life. The hierarchy given here attempts to borrow and incorporate points from all the other theories, and will be used (whether implicitly or explicitly) to judge ethical problems throughout the rest of this book. Readers who come to different conclusions on specific points should at least be able to analyse their own reasoning and to know which moral philosophy they have been following to arrive where they did.

Profile On . . . Issues

123

Page 124: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Toleration

Introduction: The people who make up a nation may have a variety of ideas and individual beliefs (religious, moral, political, and others). Since, for instance, there are many religions and political parties, such beliefs may contradict each other. In a stable society, there are certain "control beliefs" that characterize the dominant culture, form the basis of normal government policies and laws, are transmitted by its media, and generally present its public face. Tightly closed societies presuppose that all non-control beliefs ought to be suppressed. More open societies allow a plurality of beliefs some expression, even when these contradict the control beliefs.

A Definition: Toleration is a practice based on the higher value of freedom. It is the deliberate choice not to suppress the expression of beliefs or behaviour differing from or disapproved of by the tolerator.

Is this a moral issue? At the heart of toleration is the belief that other people are moral agents whose freedom to express that moral agency must be respected, even when the beliefs they profess are not given credence. Tolerance is designed to promote freedom, respect of persons, and the education of all who hear or express moral views. It also recognizes that the consequences of intolerance can be catastrophic for society, and is therefore in everyone's utilitarian self-interest to practice it.

Problem: If the control believers use the word "toleration" to imply the dogma that all expressions of belief are equally valid (equally likely to be true), then they will be intolerant of any claim to be right, that is, to know an absolute truth. Such a view of tolerance sounds very liberal and accepting, but when its own absolute is challenged by those who claim on any other grounds to know an absolute right or truth, the narcissism of this kind of tolerance causes it to self-destruct, sometimes in spectacular ways. In such cases, those who advocate any moral, religious, or political absolutes may find themselves under severe attack.

Is toleration absolute and unlimited? For the most part, tolerance theoretically cannot be selective and be itself. In practice, it is always exercised over some range of permitted dissent. For instance, if intolerance is one of the things allowed, and that becomes more persuasive than is tolerance, the latter may be obliterated. Although not to permit the expression of intolerance seems self-contradictory, tolerance must have some limits or it cannot survive, being quickly replaced by some form of intolerance.

Problem: By virtue of their dominant position, the control believers in a society are disinclined to tolerate challenges to any of their beliefs. If the control believers are certain of the rightness of their beliefs, those who question these moral, religious, or political absolutes will be at least marginalized, if not ghettoized.

124

Page 125: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Must all beliefs be tolerated? The holding of beliefs is not strictly in the category of things to which tolerance applies, for there is no way to know what a person is thinking until those beliefs are communicated. Toleration applies to the expression of beliefs; it makes no demands on an individual for intellectual conformance to the control beliefs.

Ought all expressions of belief to be tolerated? Even some of these are not in the proper category to which toleration applies. For instance, expressions that defame the character of or incite violence against a person or group violate the higher value of freedom on which tolerance is based.

Problem: If the control believers are dominant and powerful enough, they may come to define criticism of any of their beliefs as defamation and incitement, and so to be a threat that must be eliminated. This is when intellectual ghettoization becomes first physical segregation and then active persecution.

What are the limits of toleration for non-conforming actions?1. Acts of violence or those taken in reckless disregard for the life and safety

of others restrict the victims' freedom, and must be regulated.Problem: A completely passive people is ripe to accept a dictator, or to be

invaded by another nation.2. A state has an obligation to be intolerant of expressions or actions that

threaten its own existence.Problem: Fear of subversion or invasion can be used to destroy all freedom in

a state.3. A state may have to restrict the ability of a group or individual to

accumulate wealth or power, so as to avoid a threat to the well-being or freedom of others.

Problem: Some enterprises can only be conducted efficiently (or at all) with large accumulations of capital. Too many restrictions on this results in a lower standard of living for everyone.

4. Criminal acts are also presumed to be forbidden by higher principles and are therefore not in the category of the tolerable.

Problem: The greater the freedom, the more scope there is for terrorists and criminals. The more regulations there are to detect such activities, the less freedom there is.

5. Acts that endanger a person's own health or safety may place an economic burden on society. To the extent that this restricts the freedom of others, such acts may have to be regulated.

Problem: Sufficiently dominant control beliefs may make expressions of competing beliefs a criminal offence (This is how totalitarian rulers maintain power).

3.6 From Theory to Decision--Practical Morality The focus of this book is not moral/ethical theory in isolation but rather the

interplay between high technology and the practical ethics of the society. Some issues of great importance to everyday relationships will not be considered at all in this text, and some that most people would not normally think about become

125

Page 126: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

central to these discussions because they relate specifically to science and technology.

Furthermore, it is time to move from theory to practice. It is useful to examine, understand, and even adapt theories of making ethical statements, but if these theories are to have more than abstract value, they must be put to practical use--in this case by examining the high technology society and trying in part to determine what difference ethical theories make when they are actually applied in real life by the members of that society.

The relationship between moral philosophy and morality is akin to the one between theoretical physics and engineering. For instance, it is interesting to know something of how the structure of various metal alloys gives them certain physical properties, but it is more useful to society to employ this knowledge to build a safe and efficient bridge. In addition, mere knowledge of how to build a bridge will not bring one into being; there must also be an engagement of the will, a decision to take action, and this followed by the action itself.

Likewise, it is not enough just to know what is a good action that serves God or humanity in the best possible way, for one could still choose to do the opposite out of self-interest. For example, if law does derive from ethical consensus, then it is at least in the long-term best interests of society to have a consensus that is generally applied, that is reflected in the laws of nations, and that has been adapted to the particular needs of the day and age.

Specific ethical and societal problems related to high technology will be discussed in appropriate chapters. An attempt will be made in each case to provide a historical context for the situation and to examine it within an ethical framework as well. In many cases, the need for solutions to problems will be pointed out and one or more possible directions for change will be given, but these will not be the only possibilities. Readers will be expected to provide some of their own solutions, particularly in questions at the end of chapters.

Profile On ... Applying Ethics To Technology

The following widely-circulated statement was adapted by an international symposium on ethics and technology held in Haifa and Jerusalem in December, 1974.

The Mount Carmel Declaration

1. We recognize the great contributions of technology to the improvement of the human condition. Yet continued intensification and extension of technology has unprecedented potentialities for evil as well as good. Technological consequences are now so ramified and interconnected, so sweeping in unforeseen results, so grave in the magnitude of the irreversible changes they induce, as to constitute a threat to the very survival of the species.

2. While actions at the level of community and state are urgently needed, legitimate local interests must not take precedence over the common interest of all

126

Page 127: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

human beings in justice, happiness, and peace. Responsible control of technology by social systems and institutions is an urgent global concern, overriding all conflicts of interest and all divergencies in religion, race or political allegiance. Ultimately all must benefit from the promise of technology, or all must suffer--even perish--together.

3. Technological applications and innovations result from human actions. As such, they demand political, social, economic,ecological and above all moral evaluation. No technology is morally "neutral".

4. Human beings, both as individuals and as members or agents of social institutions, bear the sole responsibility for abuses of technology. Invocation of supposedly inflexible laws of technological inertia and technological transformation is an evasion of moral and political responsibility.

5. Creeds and moral philosophies that teach respect for human dignity can, in spite of all differences, unite in actions to cope with the problems posed by new technologies. It is an urgent task to work toward new codes for guidance in an age of pervasive technology.

6. Every technological undertaking must respect basic human rights and cherish human dignity. We must not gamble with human survival. We must not degrade people into things used by machines: every technological innovation must be judged by its contributions to the development of genuinely free and creative persons.

7. The "developed" and the "developing" nations have different priorities but an ultimate convergence of shared interests:

For the developed nations: rejection of expansion at all costs and the selfish satisfaction of ever-multiplying desires--and adoption policies of principled restraint--with unstinting assistance to the unfortunate and the underprivileged.

For the developing nations: complementary but appropriately modified policies of principled restraint, especially in population growth, and a determination to avoid repeating the excesses and follies of the more "developed" economies.

Absolute priority should be given to the relief of human misery, the eradication of hunger and disease, the abolition of social injustice and the achievement of lasting peace.

8. These problems and their implications need to be discussed and investigated by all educational institutions and all media of communication. They call for intense and imaginative research enlisting the cooperation of humanists and social scientists, as well as natural scientists and technologists. Better technology is needed, but will not suffice to solve the problems caused by intensive uses of technology. We need guardian disciplines to monitor and assess technological innovations, with especial attention to their moral implications.

9. Implementation of these purposes will demand improved social institutions through the active participation of statesmen and their expert advisers, and the informed understanding and consent of those most directly affected--especially the young, who have the greatest stake in the future.

10. This agenda calls for sustained work on three distinct but connected tasks: the development of "guardian disciplines" for watching, modifying, improving, and restraining the human consequences of technology (a special but not exclusive

127

Page 128: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

responsibility of the scientists and technologists who originate technological innovations); the confluence of varying moral codes in common action; and the creation of improved educational and social institutions.

From: Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology Melvin Kranzberg (ed)

3.7 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

The study of what constitutes the knowledge of good and right is known as moral philosophy; the actual application of these abstractions is ethics. There are three main groupings of the schools of moral philosophers, those who believe that:

1. Ethical laws are deduced by pure reason. This group includes the ancient Greek philosophers, to the extent that they discussed such things at all, and Immanuel Kant, whose categorical imperative was claimed to be the final and necessary conclusion of this reasoning process.

2. Ethical principles are decided upon. The positions within this group vary from the antinomian (there are no ethical norms) through the consensus view (including hedonism and utilitarianism) to the position that the law of love judges all moral actions and finally to situationism and the social contract view. The first of these is to an extent a denial of the existence of ethics; the last three assert that goodness is relative to certain calculations about resulting benefits of actions and that actions do not have this quality themselves.

3. Ethical norms are absolute, transcending both reasoning and decisions. This includes (but is not limited to) the view that an inner sense--conscience or intuition--exists that dictates ethical principles. It also includes legalistic absolutism (all-encompassing absolute norms) and hierarchical absolutism.

This text offered one such hierarchy as a comprehensive synthesis of the ethical theories examined under all three headings. Readers may well settle on other hierarchies, possibly subsets of this one, or on one of the other schools of thought. However, in examining specific issues, whether relating to technology or not, it is valuable to understand what ethical criteria are being used.

Discussion Questions

1. Under what circumstances is it right (or excusable) to lie? Give some examples and your reasons, based on your view of moral philosophy.

2. Under what circumstances is it right (or excusable) to break a promise? Give some examples and your reasons, based on your view of moral philosophy.

3. Normally, part of the duty of a citizen to society is to obey the laws of the land. When, if ever, is it better to break such laws?

4. In certain very rare medical circumstances associated with the birth of a child, doctors may be faced with the choice between saving the life of the mother or that of the child. Which should be saved and why? Would the same answer be given by all schools of moral philosophy?

128

Page 129: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

5. Is it always right to report to authorities the crime of another person that you have witnessed? That you have heard about from a third party? Do your answers change if the criminal is your friend?

6. Suppose the law requires you to report certain types of activities as crimes, but you do not believe they are wrong. Do you have to report or not, and why? Does it make any difference whether your own views of the matter are based on moral philosophy? on political convictions? on religious beliefs?

7. Under what circumstances is it morally right or morally wrong to practice birth control? What difference does it make if the law of the land requires (forbids) this? Now repeat the question for abortion, for infanticide, for euthanasia.

8. The police have just revealed to you that your closest and dearest friend is under investigation for tax fraud. He is about to be arrested and, if convicted, faces a lengthy prison term. (a) You have been asked not to tell him because it is feared he may flee the country. What should you do? (b) As soon as you are told this, you realize that you have in your possession conclusive evidence that would convict your friend, information that the authorities could not possibly know about. What do you do? Does it make any difference to your answer if the friend is also your boss? your spouse? your child? the mayor? the pastor of your church?

9. You are the prime minister of a country at war, and your secret service has a spy at work infiltrating the enemy high command in an effort to discover its plans for a major offensive three months away. She has just reported, however, on less important plans for an attack that will be made in another place tomorrow. If you use the information, your country's forces will win tomorrow's battle, but your spy's activities will be unmasked and she will have to flee, abandoning the long-term plan. If you do not use it, many more soldiers will die the next day than necessary, but the spy will be able to continue in the hope of gaining a greater victory later. What does a utilitarian do and why? What does a traditional absolutist do and why? Can you give a hierarchical absolutist answer?

10. You see a young child drowning in a river. Being both an expert mathematician and a good swimmer you instantly calculate a 40-percent probability that you can save the child and a separate 70-percent probability that you can save yourself once you do jump in. What should you do if you are: (a) a utilitarian? (b) a situationist? (c) a traditional absolutist? (d) a hierarchical absolutist?

11. What effect does it have if the two probabilities in question 9 are reversed?

12. You are starving and have no money. You see a passer-by drop a wallet, and you pick it up. It contains over a thousand dollars in cash, some of which, you are convinced, this richly dressed person could easily spare. What do you do? Does it make any difference if the lost article was food instead of money? Does it make any difference if you are the mother of two young children who are closer to death from hunger than you are? Does it make any difference if you know that the owner of the wallet is a notoriously tightfisted individual whom you are certain would never reward your honesty? Does it make any difference if, in addition, he was once responsible for cheating you out of your home, property and money and thus is the cause of your destitution in the first place? What if the person is a known criminal and you are certain that the money is profit from selling drugs?

129

Page 130: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

13. Your country has a severe famine due to a failure of an irrigation system and very little money. The government has a choice between spending all available funds to buy food, in which case it is estimated that the lives of 500,000 people will be prolonged for a year, after which time, there will be no funds left to prevent millions of projected deaths. Alternately, the available funds could be used to rebuild the irrigation system, allowing the 500,000 deaths in the short term but preventing the larger famine. Assuming that this is all the available information, what is the best course of action? Does it matter what ethical school you belong to?

14. What difference does it make if the famine is in one country and the money in a second? Which country should make the decision? What if the second country has only this money; it is earmarked to update its own irrigation system, for it is estimated that in the next year there is a 25-percent probability that this too will break, and the second country would then also experience famine on a similar scale to the first country? What difference does it make if a decision not to help means a 50-percent probability of a war, in which hundreds of thousands would surely die?

15. A man you know has been beating his wife. She kills him, not realizing that you have witnessed the crime, but otherwise successfully conceals her deed. Do you turn her in? Does it make any difference if she is your close friend? Does it make any difference that you have just realized you are in love with her and want to marry her? Does it make any difference if she has two young children and no relatives who could care for them? What effect does your school of ethical thought have on your answer?

16. You have evidence that a certain individual is a child molester. However, for the case of which you are aware, you have been sworn to secrecy and asked by the victims' parents not to involve the police. Now another child has brought charges against the same offender. Should you come forward with your information, despite your promise? Does it make any difference who the offender is, or what kind of work he does? Suppose the new complainant has confided to you that the charges now being advanced are false and being made for the purpose of revenge, with no knowledge of any other offences? Do you betray the lie, or the truth?

17. How do the various ethical schools handle the issue of tolerance? For example, can an ethical relativist tolerate a traditional absolutist? a hierarchical absolutist? What about the reverse?

18. Consider the Mount Carmel declaration. What ethical theory does it appear to be based on? Is there any evidence of a foundation for its statements; that is, are they based on higher principles, or do they stand alone? How does it envision that its goods be enforced as shoulds?

19. Rewrite the Mount Carmel declaration in the form of a hierarchy. What additions or deletions do you propose, and why?

20. Attack or defend the statement made in section 3.5 that the "inner voice" theory contradicts hedonism. Extend the discussion to the relationship between conscience and utilitarianism.

21. It is well known that tobacco causes a myriad of illnesses, many of which are very expensive to treat and a burden on society. Should the use of this product be tolerated, regulated, or forbidden? Why?

130

Page 131: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

22. Repeat the analysis of the last question for (a) heroin (b) alcohol. What are the essential differences among these three?

23. (Research question--use the Internet or a library) Find a code of ethics that has been adopted by some recognized group or profession and analyse it. What are the presuppositions behind the code? What is its purpose? In what ethical school are its framers? What are the specific things required? forbidden? How would you rewrite the document?

24. To what extent ought freedom of religion be an absolute value? Consider cases where the practice of religion conflicts with the law. What if the religion demands that its adherents either convert others or destroy them?

Bibliography

Carman, John and Juergensmeyer, Mark (eds.) Bibliography of Comparative Religious Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991

Frankena, William K. Perspectives on Morality. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976.

Geisler, Norman L. Ethics: Alternatives and Issues. Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1971.

Hancock, Roger N. Twentieth Century Ethics. New York: Columbia University Press, 1974.

Henry, Carl F. H. Christian Personal Ethics. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1957.Horton, John & Mendus, Susan (eds.) Aspects of Toleration. London: Methuen,

1985Hudson, W. D. Modern Moral Philosophy. 2nd Ed. New York: St. Martins Press,

1983.Kranzberg, Melvin (ed.) Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology. Boulder,

Colorado: Westview Press, 1980Logstrup, Knud E. The Ethical Demand. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1971.Montgomery, John Warwick. Human Rights and Human Dignity. Grand Rapids:

Zondervan, 1986.Nielsen, Kai. Ethics Without God. London: Pemberton Books, 1973.Ramsey, Paul. Deeds and Rules in Christian Ethics. New York: Charles

Scribner, 1967.Taylor, Richard. Good and Evil--A New Direction. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus

Books, 1984.Tavani, Herman. (ed.) The Tavani Bibliography of Computing, Ethics, and

Social Responsibility Palo Alto, CA: Computer Professionals for Social Responsibility January 15, 1997 <http://www.siu.edu/departments/coba/mgmt/iswnet/isethics/biblio/index.html--Theory and Practice. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1985.

Web resources on Ethics:The Ethics Centre for Engineering and Science http://www.cwru.edu/affil/wwwethics/index.html

131

Page 132: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The Institute for Business & Professional Ethics http://condor.depaul.edu/ethics/about.html

Bioethics Online Service http://www.mcw.edu/bioethics/

Chapter 4The Information Revolution

Seminar - "Knowing Everything - Man in the Image of ...?" 4.1 What is Information? 4.2 The Information Technologies 4.3 The Availability of Information 4.4 Toward The Metalibrary 4.5 The Accuracy and Security of Information 4.6 Information Analysis and Decision Making 4.7 Summary and Further Discussion

132

Page 133: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

4.1 What is Information? A collection of raw data, however large, and gathered from whatever source,

is not necessarily information. The term "information" implies that the things it describes have some measure of meaning, significance or relevance. Meaning in turn requires two things:

1. intentional and intelligent organization, and2. capacity for being communicated.

That is, it can be said something is information only if it has a deliberately attached meaning that can be communicated and interpreted in such a manner as to preserve the meaning for another person.

Thus, information is a product of purposeful organization and design, not simply an assemblage of facts. The activity required to generate and communicate information therefore requires intelligence. In addition, information enables change in the people who have it. It empowers them to do things they could not otherwise, giving them more choices and in turn affecting their available techniques.

Some of what passes for information may not be in accord with the facts--either because the underlying raw data is incorrect, or because it has not been interpreted or communicated in accord with proper professional practice. That is, questions of right and wrong need to be asked with respect to information as well as with respect to beliefs and actions. For at least some such cases, the answer is likely to be absolute; for others, there may be legitimate differences of opinion on interpretative matters.

Some information is also more useful, and therefore more desirable to know. This fact affects people's motivations--both in learning new things, and in applying what they do know. In the style of the last chapter, one could ask "if some things are good to know, to what extent should they be known?"

All this tells us that information does not exist in a vacuum or stand complete on its own. Rather, human beings interact with it in a complex feedback pattern that changes both them and the information continually.

The larger the data pool is, the more complex the processing activity must be to produce useful information. This in turn requires a certain sophistication for the society in which the information generation takes place. Thus, the higher (more

133

Page 134: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

abstract) the level of the culture, the greater the demand for reliable information. This provides a feedback mechanism that forces the techniques for the processing of data into information to become ever more sophisticated as the quantity grows.

Some information theorists would present the diagram above as a mere mechanical process, suggesting that the entire task of processing data into information may be relegated to a machine. This position would not be very palatable to a Christian, or to anyone who believes that the human mind is more than a machine, and that it does something unique when its owner engages in assigning and communicating meaning.

The explosive growth of data sources and the demand for information also demand that filters be created to sift out the useful from the less so. Someone who has been shot cannot afford to stop to wonder about the bullet's manufacture and trajectory before arranging to have it pulled out. It is questionable whether arguments over who wrote Shakespeare's plays or authored the book of Isaiah contribute anything to knowledge. A farmer does not need much military technique. An engineer does not need to know how to raise pigs. Thus, specialities are developed--no one can know everything, even in an agricultural society, and much less so in an industrial one. However, in the information society, anyone can find out anything.

It is important to note that economic activity does not march automatically and inevitably from hunter-gatherer to agricultural to industrial to information-based society. A subtle interplay of available technique, culture, and political decisions determines what happens next. Each civilization must build a sufficient level of information and other infrastructure at each level to progress to the next. It was accumulated knowledge of plants and animals that permitted agriculture. Agricultural production grew larger and more sophisticated in the industrial age, but employed fewer people. Likewise, the information based society requires a highly sophisticated and complex industrial base, and the production of goods must surely continue to increase, even though the proportion of workers directly involved in that production will diminish. The production of ever larger quantities of agricultural and industrial goods requires better knowledge and more complete demographic information all the time. Once the two older sectors become efficient enough, managing the information required to maintain them becomes the most visible occupation, even though the information sector only indirectly generates material wealth.

It is at least in part for this reason that the efforts of missionaries and other aid workers in underdeveloped nations are sometimes counterproductive. For instance, there is little point in attempting to introduce electric ovens into a society that lacks a reliable supply of electricity, or tractors into one that lacks one of gasoline. A simple, easily repaired mechanical pump might turn out to be the single most appropriate technology needed to lift a remote African village out of poverty. Teaching its people to read and write may be the most important contribution available from information techniques. Just as important in all such cases is the lack of infrastructure to repair and maintain even middle technology products and processes.

134

Page 135: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

At the same, every society has to solve information storage problems. When oral traditions became inadequate to preserve information, it was written down on slates or scrolls. Eventually, the sheets were piled up and bound into books to save space. When it became necessary to produce many copies of such books, the printing press was required. This all had to be put somewhere, for shoe boxes and file cabinets can serve for mass data storage only up to a certain point. Thus, libraries have been particularly important in the preservation and transmission of both data and information. They are the repositories of what a civilization has found out about the world, what it believes about the world, and what it has done to change the world (and itself). There is now so much knowledge in the collective human archives that it is no longer practical to store it all on paper, and electronic means have become necessary. Today, the media size needed to store data and information continues to shrink, and the speed at which data can be machine processed is increasing.

It is necessary to do more than just store information, however. To be of much use, it has to be interpreted (given meaning) and disseminated to other people, including the next generation. Thus, as the amount of information grows with the size and complexity of society, greater demands are also placed on the means of communicating that information. This principle is of particular importance to any cultural or religious groups such as Christians, whose continued existence depends utterly upon transmitting its essential ideas and practices in toto to the next generation, for failure to succeed in this task implies extinction of the group.

4.2 The Information Technologies The speed and reliability with which goods, services, and ideas can be

transferred from one person to another has always been critical to human civilization. Early on, information transfer was completely dependent on the available physical transportation. Orders, government data, and intellectual properties could only be conveyed to distant places by personally carrying them there, and the effective size of any nation was limited by this fact. The printing press made certain kinds of information more readily available (to those who could read, so many learned) and ensured that knowledge would not so easily be lost from one generation to the next. However, printed information still suffered from the restrictions imposed by the limited means of transportation and communication.

The invention of the telegraph and telephone altered this situation profoundly, for now information transfer could be effected anywhere that the wires could be strung. Then emerging countries such as Canada, the United States, and Australia benefited the most from such developments, for they were able to weld together enormous territories into single political entities because there were efficient transportation and communication among the parts. First the railways and then the copper wires tied these nations together, and without such technologies it is likely that today they would be (as Europe has been) many small countries divided by language and culture and unable to communicate effectively.

Increasing use of telephone services forced carriers to automate to prevent the system from being stalemated by the number of operators required for manual equipment. Thus came dial phones, automatic switching, and computerized routing.

135

Page 136: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Likewise, inter-city telephone cables gave way to radio, broadband transmission, satellite routing, and fibre optics to keep pace with the ever-increasing traffic. Both radio and image transmission techniques have merged with the telephone to produce cellular phones and a practical facimile system (Fax technology is over a century old, but was little-used by most people until speed and quality improved). More innovations are necessary as the quantity of data transmitted over these circuits continues to grow.

Meanwhile, the entertainment media have also shrunk the effective size of the world, as programs created in one place can be seen around the globe in a matter of minutes. Thus, while the time it takes to physically transport an object to any part of the world has been reduced to hours by modern jets, data can be transmitted instantaneously. It is safe to predict that the efficiency of information transmission will continue to grow for some time yet, and that there may also be further improvements in the speed of air travel.

Faster, cheaper, more powerful computers can store and manipulate more data. They are even more widely interconnected than they were, and it is now possible to send and receive information through this network at any time to any location on the planet on the so-called "information highway".

In the near future, the transportation/communication network will expand much more than it already has into near space. The entertainment industry will depend more heavily on satellite transmission, to the point where the viability of local television stations may become endangered. A small (30 cm or less) dish antenna will be able to pick up hundreds of national and international channels from orbit, and local broadcasts may well become redundant. This trend toward a global information store may be offset in part by an increased interest in the local community, so that there may well be new low-power local stations established as well.

Except for physical transportation, the spread of information is now limited only by the speed of light. At least inside the orbit of the moon, this is effectively no limitation at all, though in the more distant future it may be. If other parts of the solar system are colonized, there would be no instant communication possible, since the time taken by light to travel to other planets is appreciable. Data transfer will still work; as will any other communication that can tolerate waits of several minutes or more. Though it is premature to speculate upon the next stage of societal development, it seems clear that one of the current stage's most important characteristics is the instant and unlimited availability of data and information.

As will be seen in subsequent discussions, this availability in itself raises many important issues for those with an eye to the ethics of the situation and an interest in the quality of life in society.

Profile On . . . Data and the Law

Several countries have passed laws regulating the security and privacy of data. Some also have attempted to regulate transborder data flow as well. Here is a selection:

136

Page 137: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Australia:the Freedom of Information Act (Public sector only) Privacy Act (private

sector)Canada:the Federal Access to Information Act and the federal Privacy Act (Public

sector only)

Francethe Act on Data Processing, Data Files, and Individual Liberties. (Public and

private sectors, transborder data flows)

Israel:Privacy Act (Public and private sectors, transborder data flows)

United KingdomData Protection Act (Public and private sectors. Transborder data flows can be

prohibited)

United StatesoPrivacy Act 1974 (information practices, notification procedures for

government agencies)o Fair Credit Reporting Act 1970 (private sector credit, insurance and

employment info).o Fair Credit Billing Act 1974 (privacy in granting credit)o Freedom of Information Acto Family Educational Rights and Privacy Act 1974 (information practices of

Federally funded educational institutions)o Right to financial Privacy Act 1978 (limiting government access to financial

information to law-enforcement agencieso Privacy Protection Act 1980 (limiting government seizures of material

intended for public communication)o Cable Communications Policy Act 1984 (privacy of cable television

subscribers)

West Germany:the Federal Data Protection Act (federal public sector)

Source: The International Handbook on Computer Crime

4.3 The Availability of Information Information services now in place may yield the most accurate view of the

future, for these have already come some distance toward the goal of unlimited availability of information. It is not possible at the present time to count the number of facts on file in publicly available data bases. Bibliographies and information files for law, Bible study, medicine, the stock market, business, education, biography,

137

Page 138: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

history, computer science, government activities, chemical and physical data, and many others are readily available to anyone with a telephone and computer.

There are gateway services and indices that operate as data bases of data bases. This includes public utilities such as the various World Wide Web search engines which allow the seeker of information access to data repositories by subject or title. Such services are utilities to extract meaningful information from the splendid chaos that is the Internet, and they finance themselves either with user fees or by displaying banner advertising. An initial query may produce thousands of computers and/or data bases located in various parts of the world. The user then narrows down the search to specifics, using the facilities of the particular information provider, software package, or search engine until the required material has been assembled.

It takes little imagination to project major extensions to today's useful but fragmentary facilities and to realize that--with very few additions to current technology--citizens of the fourth civilization should be able to obtain any recorded information on any subject in which they are interested. Most of the technology for this is already in use, and changes that will come will not be revolutionary, as far as the hardware is concerned. Rather, people and their way of working will change. Indeed, heavy use of facilities like CDs, DVDs, and the World Wide Web has already altered some traditional professions, as their practitioners have come to depend upon the easy availability of technical data.

Information Services and the Professions

Doctors, dentists, lawyers, engineers, and accountants not only have local client data bases in which to file histories, treatments, recall dates, project designs, and billings, but they also have access to local or remote expert systems on which they can diagnose, determine treatments, look up case law, find parallel situations, and so on. These tools allow a single professional to handle a much larger number of clients more efficiently and more accurately than previously. Such means also reduce dramatically the number of facts that the professional must learn and retain in personal memory in order to work competently. This not only affects how they do their jobs but also radically changes the education required to become professionals in the first place. Since many other segments of the marketplace are simultaneously moving away from an employer-employee model to professional-client relationships, these changes have the potential to alter the very nature of work for most people.

Similar advantages are also available, for instance, to real estate agents, except that their files are less customer-oriented and more product-oriented, because the available listings in a given geographical area change on a daily basis, whereas customers tend not to repeat very often. Here, video technology is being combined with computer searching so that a picture file of each listing can be made available in any real estate office. Thus, a potential buyer need not go to the site to find out what a house looks like on the outside or inside. The video technology can also be combined with the telephone and cablevision to allow potential customers the luxury of seeing videotapes of houses for sale on their home televisions.

138

Page 139: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Researchers and translators of the Bible and other specialized literature have all the reference materials, manuscripts, parallel writings, commentary, and language aids ever produced readily available. They are therefore able to produce translations into new languages in a fraction of the time it previously took.

Other organizations already maintaining specialized databases include government (taxation, geologic, geographic, demographic, and other statistical information), law-enforcement agencies (arrests, fingerprints, DNA records, and stolen property records), wholesalers and retailers (market trends, inventory, accounts and customers), credit card issuers, libraries (loans, books on hand, and in print), newspapers (articles by subject), stock market and brokerage houses (prices, press releases, and transactions).

There is also a growing number of private entrepreneurs who perform contract information searches and data digests for their clients using public and private data sources. These may be many of the same people who help businesses to set up Web pages to get their own message out to the world in the most compelling form possible.

Scientists and engineers can look up the physical properties of substances or locate journal articles or books on specific topics. Researchers in all fields can do periodic searches and keep up to date on the most current work in their field. These facilities are becoming more standardized and organized as they continue to grow. They will gradually become major information utilities in their own right, and the professionals who rely on them now will find their dependence growing to the point where they cannot work at all without them.

Meanwhile, commerce is alive and thriving on the Internet, and billions of dollars a year worth of business is handled on-line via electronic storefronts and secure ordering systems. It is reasonable to expect this use will continue to grow rapidly for the foreseeable future.

Sex and the Internet

On a less enlightening note, the purveyors of explicitly violent and/or sexual materials have also used electronic distribution to further their own ends. There are three possible responses to this particular development:

1. Some would introduce censorship of the electronic media and remove sexually explicit materials altogether.

2. Others make and sell "filtering" programs that parents can use to prevent access to the better known of such collections.

3. Still others note that censorship implies censors; that is, someone must decide what ideas are allowed expression and what are not. There is potential for "good" ideas to suffer more than "bad" ones if that happened, so they prefer to allow all ideas to compete openly in a free marketplace.

Unfortunately, the latter (more freewheeling) view may not adequately protect groups that find themselves the target of abuse in such materials, such as women, children, and minorities. The mere existence of depictions of abuse lends

139

Page 140: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

credence to its actual perpetration. That is, fictitious or potential abuse portrayed in violent or sexual materials appears to promote real abuse of real people. Indeed, in many cases actual abuse must be inflicted to make pictures of it in the first place. In the same manner, false denials of the holocaust inflict great psychological pain on the survivors of the death camps and their families. Indeed the law already recognizes that a speaker is responsible for what is spoken--if it is destructive of reputation, damages for libel may be granted. If it has only the potential to damage, the law is less clear.

Moreover, the third view is based on the liberal hope that good ideas and their use will overwhelm bad ones. This in turn implies that those expressing such a hope have the ability to know which are which. Based on actual human history, not only are the hopes vain, such abilities appear to be wanting. At some point and in some manner, it seems necessary to decide to what extent the good of freedom of speech/information must be set aside for the good of preventing threats to people's lives and health. In other words, there is a balance between the right to freedom of speech and the right to enjoy safety under peace, order, and good government.

In like manner, there is a debate over whether the depiction or promotion of homosexual acts is sinful or immoral on the one hand, or desirable for the freedom of speech and the liberation of an oppressed minority who cannot help being what they are on the other. Although the antagonists on both sides often seem to try to shout each other down even on the Internet, such issues can be reduced to a choice between perceived goods of freedom of religion and "minority group rights." In this particular case, the issue can be further reduced to the choice of whose view of human sexuality and its morality will be the dominant or control view for the society of the future.

Perhaps the most interesting aspect of such issues for the purposes of this discussion is that much of the interaction is taking place on the Internet itself, as people from all over the world have, for the first time, a vast town hall in which to participate in any debate they wish.

Information Services and Daily Life

It is interesting to observe that, while many specific professions have already been changed by the information revolution, the effect on the broader society had not by the late 1990s been particularly profound. In daily life, only a minority took advantage of information services. Where broad subscription gateway utilities were once sold, they were not very popular, and some were closed or scaled down due to lack of interest. Only the Internet and its subset, the World Wide Web seemed by the end of the decade to have potential longevity.

To a point, people of the latter part of the industrial age remained willing to continue relying on the existing mass media information filters rather than seeking and filtering it personally. Thus, even in the first part of the information age, universal access to information was conceded to employees of various news media, and they in turn published or broadcast what they deemed to be in the best commercial interests of their employers. Terrorist organizations make good use of this when they stage events for media coverage to gain recognition that their small

140

Page 141: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

numbers could not by their own efforts ever achieve. So do conventional politicians when they time their news releases to hit or miss major telecasts or other media deadlines, depending on the amount of publicity they want. For their part, those who have controlled the news media have perceived little mandate to extend access to the information from which their articles and editorials are constructed. Consequently, consumers of the news media gradually lost the ability to distinguish between factual news (data) and editorial interpretations of that data (assigned meaning). This is an example of an abstraction (removal from detail) that is potentially detrimental, for giving up to others the decisions on assigning meaning to data threatens a person's ability to function as an informed citizen. Indeed, the chief potential for tyranny in an information-based society lies in confining the ability to provide data interpretations to a small number of people, who by virtue of their positions are able to exercise some control over what all other citizens are able to think about.

One reason for the initial lack of interest in broader access to news and other information was that the benefits had not yet exceeded the costs. These services are used effectively and efficiently by those whose job demands such use or who can benefit from it and are willing to expend time and effort to learn the idiosyncrasies of the various information services because they must. They are also willing to pay the fairly high monetary cost because the information they get has a substantial direct effect on their earnings.

Most people have few such motivations and rather than searching for information at all, they become enamoured of recreational possibilities on the Web, such as games and pornography. They only begin to use information services per se (or search the Web) under three conditions:

1. The cost drops to the point that they think nothing more of it than they do of paying for electricity, telephone, cablevision, or the newspaper.

2. Access to these systems is so simple that even the worst mechanophobes will use them routinely without thinking of them as complicated or unusual in any way (This requires a high level of abstraction; they become appliances rather than complex machines).

3. There are direct, obvious, and immediate benefits to everyday activities--they save time and money.

These three conditions are all developing together, for they are related. Improvements in the ease of use toward satisfying number two and in the services offered satisfying toward number three automatically satisfy number one as well, for widespread use will greatly reduce the cost. For many in the general population, the mid 1990s evidently saw an essential watershed passed with proliferation of world wide web sites, for in a span of two years the Internet became a part of millions of homes.

This illustrates that there is a critical mass for wide-effect technologies that, when reached, causes dramatic improvements in all three conditions (cost, ease of access, and perceived benefits) and then begins to alter the society whose needs gave rise to the technology in the first place. For example, the automobile went

141

Page 142: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

from being a bicycle-and-carriage-shop sideline to a toy for the rich. Later, it was raced and also used for taxis. However, it had no broad impact on society until increased demand led to mass production, and that in turn lowered prices and increased sales. In two generations Henry Ford's assembly line put a car in every garage and transformed North American society, but no one could have anticipated the critical conjunction of the necessary attitudes and technologies that made it all possible. Similar comments could be made about the impact of the telephone, the television, and, to an extent, the airplane.

Moreover, there is a critical point in the use of a technology beyond which it becomes something other than what it was at first, and this is also true of information utilities and the Internet. As they stood at the close of the millennium, such facilities largely referenced and duplicated what already existed on paper in various libraries. They enabled faster, broader, and more convenient access to such information, but this did not in itself constitute a breakthrough to a new order. What will constitute a breakthrough is a facility so extensive, powerful, and cheap that it will replace older technologies altogether and simultaneously open up whole new ways of dealing with information, opinions, and knowledge. The building of such an information appliance will require not simply new types of machines, but new ways of thinking about their use--new information paradigms. Seen in this broader context, the Internet (including the World Wide Web) are primitive first steps along the road to something much more profoundly significant.

Profile On . . . Issues

Information and Third World NationsThe GapThe Third World is so called because of the large economic gap between the

industrialized nations of North America, Europe, Australia and New Zealand on the one hand, and the heavily populated pre-industrial countries of Africa, South America, and Asia on the other.

Will the gap narrow or widen?Optimistic observers believe many nations will make the leap from an

agricultural economy directly to the information age, without an industrial phase. However, information-based economies require sophisticated and efficient industrial bases. If rich nations become richer still, and the poorer do not quickly catch up, the widening gap would threaten world peace.

Where does the third world get its information?In 1980, 95.5% of printed matter, 95.1% of printed books, 85.6% of TV sets,

68.1% of radios, and 97.9% of data processing equipment exports originated in technologically more advanced countries. Small shifts in these percentages since have been due more to Western countries moving manufacturing capabilities to low wage regions, not to any technology or decision making transfers. Television programs are still overwhelmingly American and European in origin. Four agencies--

142

Page 143: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Associated Press, United Press International, Reuters, and Agence France Press--dominate news reporting, so most of it originates in London, Paris, and New York.

A new imperialism?One-way flow of information and its associated technologies carries along the

culture, values, entertainment preferences, and commercial tastes of the exporters' life styles. Poorer countries cannot afford to generate their own television programs or news, so they buy both from those who can, increasing their economic and cultural dependence. Printing, production, advertising, and packaging are cheaper in English than in any other language (economy of scale), creating additional disadvantages for non-English speaking countries. On the other hand, universal availability of the same information to everyone inevitably has a homogenizing effect on culture. Is it worth keeping the old culture and feeling independent and self-reliant at the cost of giving up benefits that other nations have?

Is third world censorship justified?Faced with challenges to culture or religion, some nations heavily censor

imported cultural materials. This may reduce the perceived threat, but at the cost of making the imports more costly and less useful, and of partially isolating the country from the rest of the world.

Will satellite communications allow poor nations to catch up?Because of their less efficient use of the transponder circuits, these can cost a

poorer country twice as much for the same facility as a western nation would pay. Moreover, there are a limited number of satellite positions available in geosynchronous orbit, and many have been taken by the richer nations, so even if the poorer nations do develop the necessary technology, they may have to continue to rent space from the first nations to claim it.

Does Information Technology have the same effect everywhere?In a rich democracy, individuals can obtain information technology for

enhancing life style or improving their economic position. In poorer countries, often with no previous democratic traditions, the government is more likely to draw such technology into its own hands and control its use. It may therefore have more potential for oppression than for democratization in such nations over the short run.

Ought poor nations to pay for information?If information is just a commodity, poorer nations must buy it from the ones

that generate it, increasing their dependence. If all knowledge collected by the human race is its common heritage, perhaps it ought not to have a price put on it. Some argue necessity: because the poorer nations need knowledge and techniques, they are justified in helping themselves, regardless of the patent, copyright or property laws in other nations. How, in any event, can a poor nation obtain what it needs, rather than have to take what is offered by the wealthier ones? These comments apply equally to information technologies.

143

Page 144: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

How valuable are current databases to the developing nations?Industrial nations maintain large databases of scientific and technical

information, along with statistics on consumer preferences by age groups, occupation, income, and the like. Much of this is of little value in planning product development for developing nations. The techniques to make or use some products may not exist; the demographics are completely different; some products are inappropriate when moved into a new cultural setting; or there may not be enough people at an appropriate income level to make a product feasible.

What moral responsibility is there on the part of wealthy nations to share?Is bottom line profitability and the corollary demand for a return from

information resources and tools the highest value? If so, this implies no obligation to share at all without a direct return on investment. If the common good of the human race, or a value that requires sharing with the poor is of more importance, information resources ought no more to be hoarded than any other form of wealth. A more pragmatic consideration might be that information resources are almost impossible to hoard, and that trying to do so will lead either to theft or threats to peace. Another pragmatic consideration is that ensuring that new technologies get into the hands of poorer nations may enhance trade in many other goods and lead to greater prosperity for all in the long run.

4.4 Toward The Metalibrary

Limitations of Current Information Technology

There are two major categories of information distribution that are of concern to the discussion in this section--the commercial and the scholarly. Word of mouth also conveys information but in smaller quantities and so inefficiently and incompletely that it will have much less effect on the direction of society in future than it did in the past.

In the third civilization, the chief commercial media have been magazines and newspapers in the print category and radio and television in the electronic. These are the products of highly developed institutions, and they are carefully tuned to the desires of their consumers. As with all institutions, their essential mandate is to perpetuate themselves; in common with all commercial enterprises, this goal is best pursued by paying attention to the bottom line. Correctness, completeness, and societal consequences are of little importance to the institutional media unless there is some higher controlling ethical imperative, or unless such concerns coincide with others that have an impact on profits.

Those who control such media have the power to decide whether something is news or not, whether to present factual accounts or editorials, and whether to identify the nature of either to the customers. If they hold profits to be a higher good than, say, truth, then the "news" material their outlets present to the public will be sifted through a profit filter but not necessarily through an honesty filter. In such a context, the trivial--glamour, sex, money, power, violence and self-gratification--are made to appear heroic, for they appeal to the sensual and can sell

144

Page 145: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

product. Meanwhile the genuinely heroic--love, kindness, honesty, peace, moral goodness, cooperation, and social duty--become trivialized; because they lack sensual appeal, they lack profitability. Even if the for-profit media do not necessarily set about consciously to change traditional values for reasons of conviction, they do so inevitably for ones of gain.

However, it is the heroic (other-centred) values that forge bonds between people, giving a society meaning and enabling it to be. Sensual pursuits are selfish, individualist, and isolationist--they eat away at the bonds of society, and if unchecked, can destroy it. Yet the survival of civilization is too distant and vague a goal to affect short-term bottom-line thinking.

Commercial television is particularly susceptible to the temptation of becoming the advocate of selfish sensuality because it can present the illusion of being a "hot" or personally involving medium, even though it actually has no feedback mechanism and hence no group dynamics. Its watchers do not actually participate in the events portrayed, but they can be given an illusion they do have the power to do so. Television's goal therefore need be no loftier than the excitement of emotions; it has no inherent mandate to inform, except peripherally.

Originally, it was thought that television's ability to bring the world to one's home would promote global understanding and cooperation, but the medium's individualistic and sensual appeal can have very different results--reduced creativity and scope of world view, and a levelling to mediocrity. Its immediacy brings the random violence of terrorism to the living room, and can even encourage such acts on the part of those who have no hope of any military victory. Consistent with its natural sensual appeal, television has developed an almost continual portrayal (and linkage) of sex and violence. There is no mechanism in place to assess the effect this has on society and on children in particular. At the very least, such portrayal desensitizes viewers to murder, rape, brutality, exhibitionism, and violence. In its sensationalizing of world events, the product of the commercial media can easily become disinformation and not even the people who produce it may be aware of this fact. What is more, objectors have no means of making corrections, because none of the present commercial media are interactive. Ratings tell advertisers how many people watch a program, but reveal neither their reaction to it nor the effects it has on their subsequent thinking and behaviour.

Among other things, television becomes its own reality, overwhelming any message delivered through it. Nowhere is this fact more obvious than in the fate of several televangelist superstars who lost their own message to the glamour and sensuality of the medium in which it was being delivered. Rather than their message changing the world of their viewers, they themselves became television entertainer/stars, fully entering into the life-style and the values of the artificial world in which their performances were being crafted, and their message became emptied of its content as their lives put the lie to what they were saying.

Another aspect of the problem is that the late industrial age media came to be a closed system of entertainment, offering only highly control-belief filtered versions of certain currently fashionable world events. Thus "news" was created and managed as much by the media as by the participants in events. In order to entertain, they focused on the flamboyant, outrageous, and shocking rather than

145

Page 146: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the ordinary, on the negative and dangerous rather than the positive or uplifting. Their nature is to be oriented to conflict and personality, rather than to information.

Some believe that North American news reporting is sufficiently negative to create its own crisis--one of non-confidence in the very society that gives it free reign to operate. These outlets cannot therefore be relied on as factual sources of information. In this view, their product closely resembles historical fiction--a tapestry of fancy hung upon a few threads of fact. Stories constructed within such a medium may reveal more about the thinking of reporters than they do about the real world.

Critics of such attacks will be quick to point out the many benefits of television--its potential for informing, for entertaining, for educating, and for allowing at least vicarious participation in events most people could never attend in person. There are educational channels, family-oriented programs, sports networks, and a thriving public television facility--all these indeed serve to mute the criticism given above. By extending the choices available to consumers, these alternatives to the standard commercial fare also whet the appetite for what television could be if unlimited choice were in the hands of the individual viewer; that is if each person could supply the filters on all available entertainment and news without having everything predigested. That is, television still has the great informing potential it has always had, even though that potential has not yet been realized.

At the same time, and like the other traditional media (newspaper, magazine, and radio), television may also have reached the limits of its particular technology. Available time and channel space conspire together with the profit motive to ensure that individual choices from these media are severely constrained. It would appear that in order to permit unlimited access to basic information, a major technological breakthrough is required--one that allows individuals to control their own information filters.

Turning to another realm entirely, when one considers the available information channels for scholars different problems become evident, for here correctness and completeness are not usually as serious problems as are relevance and information overload. Today's libraries--paper and electronic--are added to by millions of book and journal pages a day. The use of book review digests, cross references, citation indices, and bibliographies can be extremely time consuming and does not always guarantee that the desired information will be found. Conversely, if something is not found, that does not mean the information does not exist.

What is worse, just because something is stated in a book on some library shelf does not guarantee its accuracy. It might be based on poor research or inadequate information. It might be deliberate falsehood, poorly reasoned, obsolete, an opinion the author later withdrew, or such bad scholarship that it isn't even wrong. It is always filtered through some world view before being presented, and this means that academic information is no more value neutral than is television entertainment. Correct information on a given subject may be in such a fragmented and widely scattered form that it is impossible for one person to search enough of it to synthesize an integrated whole from the many parts. Even in electronic research libraries there are several problems that a new paradigm for information storage

146

Page 147: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and retrieval must be able to solve in order to create something that constitutes a significant breakthrough.

Hypertext

The first step toward solving some of the problems with information access is called hypertext, because it adds new dimensions to the referencing of textual material. Its characteristics are:

1. The ability to follow up a book or research paper directly. That is, citations and references are electronically linked to the original work rather than stored in a separate citation index. This means that bibliographies become bidirectional, and their entries have reference threads (citations) that extend forward from the date of publication as well as backward, automatically.

2. The ability for readers of a paper or book attach their own links to individual arguments in a work. These may lead to entirely different threads, if someone else has an appropriate link attached. Naturally, this applies to the original author, who is thereby able to withdraw some points or retract errors, so that they do not proliferate through the literature.

3. The ability to request missing knowledge from others using hypertext. One can ask for threads to be attached directly to the request if someone can either create or find the desired information somewhere in the library. Such requests to fill "holes" can be published on their own or attached to other papers by threads in the same manner as citations or comments.

No such advanced facility yet exists for general use for several reasons. First, no one computer has enough capacity and speed to implement a sufficiently large data base. Second, (therefore) what scholarly data bases do exist are both fragmentary and scattered over millions of computer stores. Third, Internet indexing and searching are still extremely primitive, and there is no ability for users to attach new links to old data either manually or automatically. Fourth, few journals are at this point even available electronically, so the Internet lacks authoritative editorial and peer review processes. This means that scholars have little assistance in determining the reliability and authenticity of electronic data. Fifth, personalized hypertext software on small computers made its first appearance on the market only in 1987 (Apple's HyperCard for the Macintosh), and considerable work is yet required to take such packages from single-user environments through multi-use (in schools and offices) and thence to large-scale operation and general utility status.

However, enough has been done on this concept to make it clear that it is both practical and viable on a small scale. Moreover, the successes of HTML (HyperText Markup Language) and related notations in creating the World Wide Web shows the concept has promise on a large scale as well.

When advanced hypertext does become a comprehensive academic utility, scholars will be able to keep up to date in their fields for the first time in more than a century. Whenever a new work is published, its bibliographic references will automatically generate links to the older works, so that someone viewing an article

147

Page 148: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

in the middle of a chain will be able to move in either direction without consulting a separate reference.

Moreover, problems created by vague, incorrect, poorly reasoned, retracted, refuted, or irrelevant papers will also be alleviated. As things now stand, journals employ referees and editors to sift out and reject some of the junk before publication. This has the advantage of screening out most of the truly awful material before it is published. The disadvantage is that it may prevent publication of radically new ideas just because they are new or because the author is perceived unfavourably by the editor. It can also prevent altogether the publication of ideas not considered politically or religiously "correct" by the editorial establishment. The present system also does not allow an author to retract a bad paper once it is in print--at least not in a way that anyone seeing the original would automatically be referred to the retraction.

In a hypertext environment, everything can be published, and it could be left to each user to decide how to sift the material. Screening would be easily done, for an individual account could be set to recognize only the links approved by reputable editors and referees, who do their work after publication rather than before and who are able to alter their approval if they have a subsequent change of heart. This could be done by attaching priority numbers to links that could later be raised or lowered. Editors' links could be removed altogether only if no threads depended on them or if suitable warning were given to persons who had shown an interest by using the link. This would give those users the chance to establish an independent personal link. Naturally an individual's normal settings--to recognize certain editors' approvals and not others--could be overridden in a search for any new links to the field of interest regardless of whether they were on the "recommended" list.

Researchers could create a personal list of whose recommendations or links their accounts would recognize and at what priority. A person could subsequently reject some of these or approve other links if that seemed desirable. These filters would grow and change as individual interests did and would make the total body of scholarly work (including all the junk) look different to each user. This very growth and change in individual filters could also be automated by appropriate software. Such a system could serve research needs at various levels, for editors' links could also have a difficulty index attached. These indices would determine whether particular items would normally be of use to a grade school, undergraduate, or graduate student, or to a professional. People would be free to change their difficulty index on a topical, subject, or global basis as they learn more or as their interests change. Alternately, they could set the system to change it for them according to actual usage patterns.

In addition, fees could be charged both for publishing and for reading material. An author would pay to have work put on the system, but each time a piece is referenced, the author would be credited with a portion of the fee paid by the reader (The rest of the reading fee would maintain the system). This would also filter out some low-quality material, for few people would continue to pay to publish things that no one read.

The hypertext concept is not new; it originated with Vannevar Bush, Franklin D. Roosevelt's wartime science advisor, during the 1940s. It was not feasible to

148

Page 149: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

build Bush's "memex," however, and the idea languished until recently. The coiner of the modern term "hypertext," Ted Nelson, calls a hypertext system with this added publishing facility "hypermedia." His long running Xanadu project was an attempt to implement such systems on a marketable basis, but despite having many corporate homes, no commercial product resulted. It seems likely, given the magnitude of the task, that an advanced hypertext system is more likely to grow from the collective efforts of researchers and editors already using the Internet, than it is from the workings of one mind, however fertile and energetic. As it does grow, the challenge will be to maintain the openness of the Internet of the late nineties while still allowing individual scholars to view the parts they need under some structure.

Beyond Hypertext--The Metalibrary

If this were all that the next generation information systems could do, they would be revolutionary enough, for hypertext alone would radically change scholarship, publishing, and current libraries. For instance, paper books and the need to store them could eventually cease to exist. The quality and quantity of information could improve dramatically. It would always be possible to find out if a piece of research has already been done, and every scholar would have access to the most current material. A great deal of time would be saved, both in library searches and in preventing unnecessary duplication.

However, there is no reason to stop with hypertext. A fourth characteristic could be added to information access in order to transform hypertext from a scholars' tool into an everyday appliance. It could be given the potential to overcome some of the problems associated with the commercial news media by applying the scholars' tools to transfer power to create filters to the public at large. That characteristic is:

4. The ability to link all publications, whether commercial or scholarly, and whatever the original medium.

Before moving on from this point, a definition is in order:

An (abstract) metalibrary is the entire collection of a society's data, information, and techniques, together with the means by which it is stored, accessed, and communicated.

The Metalibrary of the fourth civilization is the complete, electronically linked and accessed version of its abstract metalibrary.

Personal data such as what the family has for breakfast, what colour the cat is, and one's preferences in clothes, music and computing languages is not included in a metalibrary, for this definition focuses on the general knowledge and techniques that the culture as a whole uses and communicates. Although every

149

Page 150: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

society has a metalibrary of its generally communicable knowledge, it has never before been possible to assemble and index that information in a manner readily accessible to all. Not everyone can physically drop by the Library of Congress, and even those who do might find a search rather daunting (though it, too has a web site, now). From this point on, references in this textbook to the Metalibrary will always be to the electronic version.

Such a library could contain and link textual material (books, articles, papers, and newspapers of all kinds), graphics (pictures, art, posters) and sound (music, radio programs). It could also have integrated forms such as movies, TV programs, recorded concerts, sports events, and daily news, weather and sports from around the world, as well as lessons on every subject at every level in a variety of languages or with universal translating ability.

Some of this has been done or is in process. Java applets and a variety of other browser plug-ins already allow simple sound and video to be a part of Web materials. Little indexing of visual-oriented material has been done thus far, and communications bandwidth would have to be expanded enormously to handle much of it, but what has been done is a move in the direction envisioned here, however primitive it may be. Moreover, the necessary communications capabilities seem to be being driven by a desire for video conferencing in any case, so by the time much indexed video and other live material is available for access, the necessary hardware may well be in place for other reasons.

In the remainder of this book, a hypertext system having this fourth characteristic will be termed The Metalibrary. The difference between the two is that the Metalibrary allows links to all information, not only to text and simple graphics and animations as at present. Moreover, it would serve the general population, not just scholars.

Emerging technology would give the Metalibrary a variety of abilities. Some of the possibilities are detailed below, though not necessarily all would come to pass, for other factors might make them unnecessary or unachievable.

Metalibrary terminals could become voice-activated, allow either large wall screens or book-size wireless portable units, and be capable of displaying text or colour graphics in the same resolution as a printed book. This would make it the preferred publishing medium for such material as National Geographic as well as the Journal of Combinatorics, including all the back issues.

For most purposes, such terminals would have the potential to replace books, magazines, newspapers, television, and the telephone with a single inexpensive appliance. It would be possible to ask one's home Metalibrary terminal, "What was the gross national product of Belize each year from 1972 to 1999?" One might expect the answer by voice with backup hard copy on the house printer--all without getting up from one's living room chair.

A somewhat more "fuzzily" defined request for, say, a comparison of conservative evangelical and Catholic twentieth century commentary on the meaning and application of the first chapter of John's gospel should also be processed to produce appropriate results.

Neither would information have to be confined to a textual form or be statistical in nature. The command "give me the national news, topic government"

150

Page 151: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

could result in the wall-sized flat screen delivering a series of news items, editorials, and film clips tailored to the request. Everyone could design their own news, weather, and sports show, with different announcers and different emphases. A hockey fan could have an all-hockey sportscast, and a would-be traveller could see the weather for Hawaii or Nice instead of Des Moines or Bradner.

The chosen announcer need not actually have ever read that day's news before a camera, for sufficient information could be stored on the person's voice, inflection, and appearance for the Metalibrary to synthesize a program with any desired person's image appearing to do the reading. If people want Walter Cronkite doing the evening news on December 12, 2046, they could have him. If they want Marilyn Monroe, her electronic persona could do it instead. One could have a few personal films and voice recordings made and anchor the news for oneself.

User interests as expressed in actual operation would determine to some extent what current items were available, but once the growing technology allowed enough storage, there would be no need ever to remove an item from the Metalibrary once it had been recorded. Someone who had gone fishing could catch up on a whole week's news on returning.

Movies, including ones now shown first in theatres, could be accessed in the same manner. For the usual access fee, "The Sound of Music," "Ben Hur," "Bambi" or "Rocky XXI" could be ordered and shown in one's own home. Parents would be able to instruct their house computer about what, if anything, their children could order. Television shows would be obtained in the same manner, though the lines between the TV and movie industries could become quite blurred. Producers of a given series would advertise their latest creation and the day when each episode would first be available for viewing. Each family could make up its own schedule of movies, news, comedy, drama, hockey or baseball, and so on--watching when convenient for them, not according to any national or local schedule.

Commercials, however, would probably be inserted at viewing time, though a premium might perhaps be paid to bypass this. On the other hand, it might become economical for advertisers to pay viewers to look at their commercials. Ratings would be compiled daily, weekly, and monthly, and would be cumulated on a long term basis on actual rather than estimated use. Such a use of electronically distributed "canned" entertainment might compete for some time with the already ubiquitous videotape rental store, but in the end, the cheaper, more universal, and more convenient of the two would predominate. If the information highway that is the Metalibrary's infrastructure has sufficient lanes (channels) to transmit one or more movies to each home, it would have the advantage of universal selection and easy accessibility.

Books could be printed a page at a time on the screen for conventional reading, or their contents could be acted out by synthesizing characters cast at the request of the user, who could take the starring role personally, if desired. The same is true of school lessons or university lectures that could be studied through a Metalibrary terminal if desired. An interesting task for some future technician would be to make these lectures interactive so that the students' questions would be answered by the synthesized teacher on the screen. More difficult enquiries could be deferred to the next lesson and taken on by a live expert connected to the

151

Page 152: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

session. These questions and answers, once recorded, would remain for the next student with similar interests. In the view of some, such a facility could eventually replace schools, colleges, and universities, though implementing this would take longer than would data-base functions. On the one hand, the "teacher" really would know everything available to know; but on the other, there would be no social interaction with other students, and no personal mentoring possible.

Very large screens could be used to download, store, and display (for a fee) great works of art in homes and offices. These would remain until the owner decided to change the pictures on the wall, at which time the rental contract with the owner of the original art would cease (no fixed term). Eventually, an entire house might be decorated in this fashion, with whole walls being massive screens that projected suitable wallpaper and art collections. Three-dimensional projectors would eventually become available and the images of sculptures could also be rented through the Metalibrary. New television shows or movies, as well as live events, would eventually be available in three dimensions; in fact, such technology may well be among the first of these actually used (although it would require a vastly greater bandwidth than conventional movies).

At the same time, Metalibrary services to professionals will be expanded, and the number of jobs depending on banked information will grow. Anyone still having a desk would have a Metalibrary outlet--probably supplied by the same utility as the one at home, but with a smaller screen (or 3D projection volume). For people on the move, a pocket unit would serve as well, but in less space still.

As in other mature industries, the number of information providers (or at least infrastructure providers) would shrink as their scope grows. In all likelihood, three or four competing Metalibrary utilities would emerge to replace the current patchwork of small companies, but customer equipment would necessarily allow reception from each, switching automatically from one to the other as the user requests. To the end user, it would all appear as a single system.

It should be clear at this point that the Metalibrary might prove to be a concept as revolutionary as was Gutenberg's printing press. It could become at once knowledge machine, entertainer, teacher, home decorator, and communications device. While this cluster of functions would develop over time, it is clear that there would be many disruptions in traditional industries, jobs, and patterns of living.

The same utility that is built with the goal of improving access to information--so that individuals can find out what it is that people collectively know--will by virtue of the facilities it offers cause a massive reorientation of several industries and of almost everyone's life. It is uncertain at this point what the effects will be, because the all possible Metalibrary facilities will come into being entirely as described here. However, this examination may provide some indication of the possibilities, given current technologies.

The Metalibrary described here is not just speculation. It could be said to be partially extant already (albeit in primitive form) in the many interconnected networks of government, academic, utility, and industry information systems that even now exist. Furthermore, what have been described here are actually emerging tools and techniques--ones that enable the manipulation of old data and the generation of new information. These tools are not the totality of the information

152

Page 153: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

itself, much of which is already available on the Internet via less comprehensive tools.

In this book, the term Metalibrary will normally be used to refer to a metalibrary that has at least some large subset of the tools and facilities discussed in this section. Where there may be some ambiguity, the term full Metalibrary may also be used to emphasize that it is not simply the information content being referred to, but also a set of techniques for universal access.

4.5 The Accuracy and Security of Information The universal accessibility of information is not without potential problems. As

individuals, corporations, and governments make growing use of data repositories, a series of difficulties arise. These problems have already been widely reported on in the popular media, but as more people use stored information, the number of those who could be adversely affected also increases. It should be noted that information accuracy is a genuine issue only if truth in information is a broadly held value; otherwise this discussion is irrelevant.

Information Accuracy

As things now stand, it is not always possible for individuals to know whether information about themselves exists, or where it is stored, much less what such a file might actually contain. There are a number of ways in which errors can creep into files, there to remain for years unchallenged, all the while affecting the lives of people. Credit rating, job prospects, accessibility to government services, and travel opportunities can all be influenced by incorrect information on file. Such errors come to be in several ways, the most common being through malice, typographical error, guilt by association, or because of an incomplete system.

Malice

A neighbour or worker who has been offended in some way might deliberately place false information into another's file--either by entering it directly, say, as a credit bureau employee, or by complaining to authorities and having an investigation undertaken. For instance, an anonymous tip that an individual has been molesting neighbourhood children could get a name onto a list of potential suspects regardless of whether any evidence was offered. One could also get into such police molester files through evidence in a divorce case, where the temptation to offer false evidence in custody hearings is very great. In some countries, government security agencies compile lists of people considered to be risks because of their political views or their membership in organizations deemed to be subversive. Unions and corporations have also been known to have such "blacklists." Unless denied a visa or a job, the person might never suspect that the

153

Page 154: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

list exists. Some promote hate against individuals or groups, and others make lists of those they claim to be promoting hatred and in turn vilify them.

Typographical Error

A clerk who types a slightly misspelled name in an arrest record or adds an extra zero to a balance owed can set off a chain of embarrassing events for the person affected. Police data bases are not generally public, and correcting their mistakes may be very difficult. Changing faulty financial records, especially such government ones as taxation files, can be a formidable and costly task, consuming much time and large legal fees.

Guilt by Association

An innocent party who happens to share an aeroplane seat with a known terrorist could be entered into an international police file and be classified as a security risk, denied government jobs, or forbidden to travel to other countries--all without knowing why. Because such files are kept secret by the authorities who maintain them, it can be extremely difficult to find out what is going on and to correct the problem.

Incomplete Systems

There are numerous examples of large systems in which information once entered is never updated, verified, or removed when it becomes out of date. For instance, police departments routinely record arrests, but may not follow up with the courts' disposition of cases. Likewise, reported thefts are recorded, but recovery of goods may not be. A person could report a car as stolen one day, have it recovered the next by the police, and be arrested on the third for driving a stolen car. With that cleared up, a promised job could suddenly be denied on the fourth day because of a check of arrest records indicates a positive match. The individual may never realize what has happened.

Some jurisdictions have already recognized these problems and passed laws to deal with them, but protection from incomplete information is still very poor in most parts of the world. Such cases illustrate the adage; "A little knowledge may be worse than none."

One of the more spectacular illustrations of incomplete systems is the so-called "year 2000 problem" (Y2K) or "millennium bug." Caused in large part because many software and hardware systems recorded only two digits (not the century) for the date, such systems had the potential to cause disruptions in all industries dependent on personal data that includes dates, such as banking and government record systems. When the clocks on many systems rolled over to January 1, 2000, they used the date as if it were 1900, throwing off calculations of interest, pensions, and rendering inoperative many real-time devices (bank machines, equipment

154

Page 155: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

controllers) that depended on using the time and date for their correct operation. Much work went into repairing this problem beforehand, however, and actual effects turned out to be minimal, though several other problematic dates are yet to arrive.

Solving Information Accuracy Problems

The Y2K problem had to be solved, and was, but cost vast sums of money and drove up programmers' salaries and lawyers' fees for a few years while the work was done. It also had potential (or, so it was thought) to cause disruptions in government, banking, general commerce, and the operation of much automated or robotic equipment.

As for some of the others, up to a point, all these types of problems are likely to become worse. However, with the advent of universal information accessibility, everyone could be given access to all files relating to them, regardless of who has created the file. Provided a person checks periodically to see what has been filed--particularly before applying for a job--the problems of inaccurate information could (in theory) be nearly eliminated. Ideally, all personal information would be stored in a single place, with access to individual items available only to qualified authorities or by permission of the person named in the file. Even better, the system could contain a program that electronically mailed peoples' files to them whenever the contents were changed.

However, this is an ideal. In an actual society, it is impossible to control all abuses. It is too much to hope that reorganizing the form of and the access to information would be sufficient to prevent the kinds of problems described here (and new ones) from recurring. Only a conscious effort to build carefully designed system safeguards would offer individuals security from bad personal information. After all, the mere computerization of a careless and flawed data system makes its problems worse, not better, as many a university and business can testify.

Moreover, the centralization of personal information even for the purpose of making it accessible and changeable for the person it names is itself dangerous, for it gives the controllers of the system containing that information the potential for great power over everyone.

Profile On . . . Issues

The Correctness of Information

When a search for information returns results that are incorrect, or a data security flaw allows a crime to be committed there can be serious consequences for reputations, loss of income, or even physical danger.

Who owns data?o Does personal information belong to the individual or organization that

entered it, the data bank that stores it, the person it is about, or to no one at all?

155

Page 156: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Is government-gathered statistical information the domain of the state, or does it belong to each person in the state?

o Is corporate data the private property of the company in question, or are the shareholders entitled to it? the customers? the state?

Examples: ought the magnetic coding system for bank machine cards be public information? What about prison records? medical records? school records? tax information? marriage, divorce, birth and death records?

o Is it the ownership or the possession of data (or is it neither) that carries with it the responsibility to ensure its correctness?

o Does "news" information belong to the people in the story, the reporter who gathers it, the wire service that assembles it, the state in which it is disseminated, or to no one?

o Suppose a gene that confirms immunity to a serious disease (such as AIDS) is discovered in a person's DNA. Who owns this information--the person in whose body it resides, or the one who discovered the presence and effect of the gene?

Who is (ought to be) responsible?o If a bank relies on incorrect credit data and so denies a loan, causing the

customer a loss, is the bank liable? the credit agency, the individual who entered the faulty data?

o If the security facilities of a system are inadequate, allowing one user to defraud another with the system, is only the perpetrator liable, or are the owners of the system as well? What about the manufacturers of the hardware and software?

o If a stolen bank card can be used by the thief because the owner has written the PIN access number on the card, is the owner partly liable?

o If an investment company continues to do business with the public while concealing its poor financial state, who is responsible when the firm collapses? only the principals of the firm? the regulatory authorities who failed to monitor the situation closely enough? a journalist who knew the truth, but was afraid to print it and so trigger the collapse? the investors, who ought to have been more cautious?

o If a commercial program is faulty and causes damage to a business, are the publisher and author of the program liable? What if the package had a statement disclaiming such consequential damages? What if the copy in question had been pirated rather than purchased?

o When incorrect conclusions are drawn because data is incomplete, what liability attaches to the gatherer or user of the data?

What about compensation?When economic or other loss is caused to some party due to incorrectly stored

or stated information, who ought to compensate the injured person? (the one who caused the error, the party who ran the storage system, the one who used the data, or no one?) Does it make a difference if

o the data was maliciously entered wrongly? accidentally?o the data was changed because of a machine fault with no human

intervention?

156

Page 157: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o the data was incorrectly processed into information because of a faulty program?

o the data had simply been allowed to become outdated?o the correct data was destroyed accidentally by human carelessness? by the

action of a computer virus designed to destroy the data?o rather than losing money, the injured party lost a job opportunity? her

children in a divorce case? her reputation?o the injured party never discovered the error, but someone else did?

Who has jurisdiction (Where does the crime take place?)o when a computer crime is committed over the telephone lines in a distant

computer across state or provincial lines? national borders?o if data (such as pornography) that is stored in one country is used in or

triggers a crime causing death in another country?o if an electronic copy of data is stolen in one state or country, then taken to

another where a paper copy is made, then to a third where the data is actually used for the first time?

o when a "hacker" creates a virus, turns it loose on a network, and thousands of computers all over the world suffer loss of data?

o over the information owned by a multinational company with headquarters in one country and branch offices in others? Can one government order the firm to comply with its laws outside its own borders? What if so doing would cause it to break the laws of other countries where it operates?

Technical Legal Issueso Is electronically stored data tangible? If it is not a "thing," can it have value?

Can it be stolen?o If funds are embezzled from many sources using a single program that

generates many illicit transactions by running in a loop, is this one crime or many?

Who (or what) is the victimo when money is stolen from a bank machine? (A machine is not a person; is

the element of deceit (of a person) necessary for fraud?)o when false data is used to win an election, engineer (or prevent) a merger,

or kite stock prices?

Privacy

Observations about correctness immediately lead to questions about who ought to have access to personal information. It seems at times that one must not only assume that government and private companies know every intimate detail of the lives of ordinary citizens, but also make the same assumption about the nine-year-old down the street with the cheap computer and modem in her bedroom. Although it may be possible to establish a system of safeguards that require permission of the subject before personal information could formally be obtained and used, the spread of such data may not ever be controlled entirely, for

157

Page 158: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

information exists in many locations. Some of these are less secure than others, or have less than scrupulous owners. Any such system that was sufficiently comprehensive to enforce rules about personal data access would by its very existence pose a threat to privacy greater than any it could prevent. Since criminals will also use data facilities, it is also not hard to imagine someone setting up, say, a blackmail data bank to store sensitive or embarrassing personal information for sale to the highest bidder.

There was a time when such information was not readily available. A president of the United States could be a notorious womanizer and the news media collectively choose not to report it. A member of Parliament could hope that an old police record would never surface. A vice-presidential candidate could keep hidden an old stay in a mental institution, and a would-be senator could keep secret a string of shady business deals or underworld connections. A high official could have an affair with a secretary or a student intern and not be found out. The past could be hidden and forgotten, whether it included unusual sexual practices, divorce, illegitimate children, molestation, abuse, bankruptcy, tax fraud, a criminal record, failure in school, a dishonourable discharge, cowardice, bad judgement, the misappropriation of funds, or a collection of traffic violations large enough to fill a car.

Today, investigative reporters armed with terminals can discover all these things and more in public records (today's Metalibrary). In the society of the future, everyone will have to assume that all details of their past life, however embarrassing, are a matter of public record. For those in the public eye, whether as government, corporate, or union leaders or as professionals in positions of trust, life will therefore be much more an open book than it has been in the past. For better or worse, the ability to forget the embarrassments of one's past is on the road to extinction. Thus, it is hard to say whether having the full Metalibrary would make blackmail any more or less likely. If all information is readily available, there can be little embarrassment in having it revealed, for it could never be concealed.

Whether anyone will care or not about others' morality or judgement is a separate question. When such information is so readily available, the result could well be a cynical and jaded public that, hearing about the private lives of the rich and famous, turns a blind eye to morality altogether.

However, what would be left of a right to privacy in such a world? Only that which leaves no record behind. Since many people would choose to have their home Metalibrary terminal monitor activities inside the house as well as their use of what is available in the outside world, there might be very little human activity that is not recorded in some manner. At the place of work, performance monitoring will be increased, and more information retained about individual commercial transactions. While there may be some restrictions, it is not difficult to imagine the state (or society collectively and informally) gathering the power to continuously record all the activities of every person. This could initially be justified in terms of law-and-order enforcement efficiencies, for every criminal would be documented. However, the corresponding possibility for absolute state control over every citizen cannot be ignored.

158

Page 159: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Likewise, if the state has control over the strong encryption of data, and forces vendors of such products to give the state "keys" to decode any data back to plain text, there could be no privacy of data or communication. In this instance, however, the technology for message and file encryption was sufficiently widespread by the late 1990s that it can no longer be controlled--government officials simply had not realized this fact as yet.

Even at present, a record of every credit card transaction is kept by the card issuer. While little could be done in the past to systematize such records because of their sheer number, the technical obstacles are melting away even as the perceived rewards to merchants and card issuers are seen to become more tempting. After all, if you know who buys what kind of goods, you can target advertising very cost effectively and efficiently, and this alone would make keeping and analysing such records worthwhile.

If all that were done was the elimination of cash so that every retail transaction were on record, it would then be impossible for any person to hide anything significant. An institution (governmental or not) that could know everything could also control everything. In such a scenario, one could easily imagine that a "universal person code" could be placed on the hand of every citizen, to be passed over the supermarket scanners along with the beans and bread--permanently recording not only all human activity but also humanity itself. That exactly such a society would one day exist was predicted by the Apostle John writing in the first century A.D.:

"He also forced everyone, great and small, rich and poor, free and slave, to receive a mark on his right hand or on his forehead, so that no one could buy or sell unless he had the mark..." Revelation 13:16-17a (NIV)

It is not difficult to see that the technology to institute an Orwellian 1984-style state already exists and that such collectivizing trends are present.

Big Brother and Little Brother

On the other hand, the effect of universal information availability upon governments may prove to be neutral or even positive. There may even be greater democracy, for there is a counterbalance here that promotes individualism. While there is the potential for increased government control of information, individual access to knowledge of government activities could also be improved. So too could the opportunities for citizens to express themselves and change the course of government. Some envision a participatory democracy emerging--one in which

159

Page 160: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

citizens have daily opportunities not just to express opinions, but to learn the facts and decide the issues.

Thus, even while people lose some ability to act as "private" citizens, governments may also lose much of their capacity to operate arbitrarily and in secret. That is, loss of personal privacy does not necessarily mean a gain in centralized power--it just means that nothing can be hidden from anyone.

This could also frighten away from public office those with a seamy past to hide. However, since no one has a perfect past, perfect judgement, or perfect morality, the effect even upon the aspirations of society's leaders might not be very great. People would have to judge others (including their leaders) for who they were in the present and what they might be in the future rather than for their past.

Two more extreme responses are possible. On the one hand, standards of behaviour for people in the public eye could come to include a stricter practice of moral actions. A swing of the pendulum towards a comprehensive and rigid moral legalism of the type popularly attributed to the Victorian era could not even be ruled out.

On the other hand a variation of antinomianism is already prevalent among modern liberals. This is the notion that in many areas of human activity the idea of morality is simply irrelevant. This is usually phrased in terms of tolerating alternate life-styles, but there is no effective difference between permitting all moral systems as equally valid or saying that none are valid. Although this position, as usual, carries with it the logical contradiction that it tolerates everything except disagreement with itself, it has nonetheless become a popular response to the "outing" of information with moral overtones. Indeed, it has become so popular that it is today the control belief in this arena, threatening the freedom or the very existence of those who hold that moral issues are important--especially if they say they are absolute.

Whatever the case, the implications for the information age are profound--actions will be public, and so will be the moral judgement of them (or the lack of such judgement).

Turning from the action of individuals in government to those of the state itself, there are similar tensions between the desire for secrecy and the need to gather and manage information. Although most people in the Western world do not want comprehensive statism, the opposite extreme--no government, only daily electronic democracy--may well be too unstable and discontinuous to work.

The most likely outcome is a situation involving gains and losses to both privacy and democracy--not a swing of power to either the individual or the state, but a realignment that changes both. Information availability does create the potential for a new kind of tyranny, but it also provides for new kinds of checks and balances by giving the individual citizen greater knowledge and therefore more power. The two trends may not simply cancel each other out, because an open information society will be very different, but these trade-offs between privacy and knowledge may well become generally accepted and thus little remarked upon.

Another possibility is that power over information storage and transmission will become concentrated in the hands of a few technology managers and corporate suppliers. Such developments are commonly advocated to achieve efficiency,

160

Page 161: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

security, or convenience, but these are not the central issues. Control is. Given the lessons of history, one must assume that where there is centralized control, there will inevitably be abuse of power, regardless of whose hands hold the reigns of power and how (why) they obtained it. To date information technology has had a largely decentralizing and democratizing effect, but there is no reason to suppose that this situation will last indefinitely. Those who wish little brother and sister to win out in the long run must be diligent to retain their freedoms or they will surely lose them.

Why Privacy?

The ethical question here relates to the fundamental basis for the desire for privacy. Is privacy a fundamental human right, or is it merely a culturally derived preference? One could argue on religious grounds, for example, that since human dignity and self-esteem are at stake, the greatest possible amount of privacy ought to be granted other people in order to affirm their value. On the other hand, one could argue that the New Testament requires the people of God to be an open and transparent community and that they ought, therefore, to have no secrets from one another. One could even argue that both of these principles are true and that they do not contradict each other.

Data Security

At the corporate and government levels, it may at first be somewhat easier to keep information confidential than at the personal level, for there will be fewer copies and these will be stored in more carefully guarded systems, not (initially) readily available through the public Metalibrary. However, sophisticated computerized analysis of the activities of business and government even now leaves them with few secrets of the quantifiable kind. Any skilled individual should be able to analyse the market share and profitability of most companies. The trick will be to keep one's actual plans for the future secret for as long as possible.

Moreover, the proliferation of international corporations and the consequent increases in money, data, and technology flows across national boundaries make it much more difficult for governments to control corporate activities. This is already illustrated by the international banking system, within which large sums of money are routinely shifted from one country to another instantaneously and without much possibility of government intervention. Even today, no one nation or group of nations can be said to control the banking system. Thus, the ability to retain information within national boundaries has already all but vanished in the Western nations and will also do so eventually in the (previously) more closed East.

Governments will still attempt to keep national security, taxation, and military information secret. Corporations, credit providers, and banks will need to guarantee the security and integrity of the information they store, just to survive. Ultimately, government and corporations must also operate in a more open environment, for it will become progressively harder to keep anything out of the public view. A secrecy-oriented government can keep fax machines and photocopiers under lock and key

161

Page 162: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and track every sheet of paper they produce for only just so long. Once it develops its own appetite for the efficiency of information machines and acquires several thousand of them, effective control becomes all but impossible. When those paper files become computerized, the security problems are multiplied.

This is not good news for those who desire to keep at least some information confidential. There have been numerous incidents of computer security violations at government or corporate installations, both by insiders and by enterprising hackers from without. Freebooters have rummaged through medical records, corporate finances, and even some military files. Insiders have stolen data for competing companies or nations, and saboteurs have destroyed whole installations.

The victims of these violations have learned from their woes and tightened up their poor security. Inside personnel are screened more closely on hiring and may be searched when leaving the job site. Modems are now designed to call back only to authorized numbers before connecting, passwords are checked regularly and not left lying around, and backup copies of important files are made regularly and stored in secure, off-site locations. Disks brought in are routinely scanned for virus programs that could destroy data. Critical installations often have an entire physical duplicate, usually in another city, so that service to customers can continue uninterrupted even through an explosion or fire at the main data centre (This is standard banking practice).

As security consciousness increases and governments attempt to control data flow across borders, some countries may set up data havens, much as they now establish tax havens. There will also be an increase in data traffic (buying and selling) on a very large scale, as economic, legal, and consumer files are copied from owner to owner.

The net long-term result will surely be even greater data availability on an international basis, and a general breaking down of national borders in favour of a more global view of information. While this is tending to make Western societies more open in some ways, it has already sounded the death knell for the old closed societies of the communist world. The very efficiency of information techniques mitigates against a tightly controlled society. Widespread availability of information is inimical to totalitarian forms of government, and a computer and modem are much more deadly enemies to statism than is a copying machine. Perhaps the best way to hasten the fall of tyranny is to ensure that it is well supplied with photocopiers, computers, and fax machines.

Thus, on balance the information age may favour the individual, but nagging doubts do remain. The gains available through individual access to information imply a corresponding loss of privacy. Are the trade-offs fair? Will Big Brother still end up watching? Will the millions of "little brothers and sisters" triumph? Will people have any vestige of personal privacy, or will everyone really be able to know everything about everyone else? The answers to these questions will vary from time to time and country to country, but the extreme scenarios now seem less likely than that some middle course will instead be charted.

4.6 Information Analysis and Decision Making

162

Page 163: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Even in the fully realized Metalibrary, universal accessibility of information does not in itself solve practical problems. Finding solutions is a multistage process resembling the scientific method that leads from raw data, first to knowledge and understanding and then to decisions. Moreover, discovering knowledge and making decisions are not necessarily on the same path, but may often be nearly independent of each other.

The full Metalibrary, like present-day paper libraries, provides material for the first step in the process, by organizing raw data by category and giving users tools to relate the data to other categories, to analyse it, and to record conclusions or argue with those drawn by someone else. All this is done now in scientific journals, though not very efficiently. However it takes place, a community or collective consideration of data is necessary before information can be derived from it. Indeed, it has been in high density, strongly interactive population concentrations that great new ideas took root and flowered in the past, and there is a sense in which the Metalibrary makes the entire Earth into a single city.

When the subject matter can be described in quantitative terms (chemistry, cell biology, economics, and demographics), the first step is to establish what are the facts, that is, what data are valid and what information they convey. Expert forums operate through today's journals (and tomorrow's Metalibrary) to achieve consensus on what the facts are, given the data available.

However, managers and other administrators often need to make decisions long before there is widespread consensus about what the pertinent information means. Ostensibly, such a manager makes decisions on the basis of available information about past history and probable consequences for the future. On the other hand, two people may easily make a different decision under the same circumstances. Here are a few examples:

1. The task is to implement a trial version of a universal data base. The problem is to decide on who should have access to what information. The company hires a lawyer and a computer scientist to advise. Their recommendations flatly contradict each other; one wants tight controls, the other a completely open system.

2. A bank determines that it requires a new computerized billing system for its expanded safety-deposit department. Extensive studies are run, and software is chosen to control the data base. But many compatible machines can run this software, including brand I, brand C, and brand X. Systems from all three vendors are tested and the results charted. Brand C comes out on top in price and performance, with brand I second and X third. The branch manager then overrules the selection committee's recommendation and decides to buy brand I, because the mainframe presently in her office is from the same company and she values brand loyalty higher than price or performance.

3. The Fraser Valley Library acting on recommendations from the Ministry of Human Resources, has decided to build a branch to serve a slum neighbourhood of Aldergrove. The only available property is an old park adjacent to a heritage building, formerly the residence of a certain well-known author. Psychologists, social workers, and government officials claim that dramatic improvements in similar

163

Page 164: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

slums have always resulted when a library was built. They insist that the house and park ought to be sacrificed. Historians and local community leaders point to community pride for one of theirs who made good, as well as to the benefits of the park for their children. They do not deny the potential value of the library, but hold that the value of the house and park are greater, intangible though that value may be. The recommendations are again contradictory.

4. During World War II, the British scored an intelligence coup by breaking the German coding scheme and routinely translating military messages from the opposite side. One night, the decoded message contained instructions to bomb the city of Coventry at a particular time. British Prime Minister, Winston Churchill, knew that many lives could be saved if he evacuated Coventry. He also knew that this move would reveal to the German High Command that their secrets had been breached, and the codes would immediately be changed. By the time the British could decipher the new ones, many more lives could be lost on the battlefront than could be saved at Coventry. A utilitarian, Churchill did not warn the city; the bombs came, and civilian lives were lost. Clearly, an act-oriented ethic would have dictated the opposite course of action.

The point of these four examples is that the mental filters through which both history and consequences are passed often have more influence on a decision than the facts and probabilities themselves. People do not make decisions on facts; they make them for other reasons. The decision in example 2 hinges not at all on the data--in fact collecting it turns out to be a wasted effort, for the manager makes the choice irrationally, basing it on emotional familiarity rather than on facts. Business people commonly do decide things emotionally, particularly when it comes to technology--this explains why inferior systems can become commonly used. Such scenarios are normal in any situation where the people making the decision are not personally familiar with the technology; they do not understand the data; or they trust advertising more, so they ignore fact and embrace emotion.

The human element is critical to the outcome of the decision-making process, and the world view (including the ethical view) of the decision maker may well determine the outcome quite apart from (or in contradiction to) the facts. Above the individual's world view, and creating its context, is that person's group culture. Depending on education, peer group, social status, local ideas, organizational outlook, and national goals or prejudices, each person shapes a world view in some degree of conformity with others sharing the same culture. Membership in a given subculture of society will determine whether a person even sees certain data, much less understands it enough to make informed decisions. Thus, even extending decision making to the entire populace would not guarantee that better decisions will be made, or that they will last long in the face of the fickleness of popular opinion.

The full Metalibrary could help with some of these problems, would exacerbate others, and would create new ones. For instance, it could be used to enforce a requirement that some expertise be demonstrated before participating in a decision. In matters such as the building of libraries or parks, a simple test on the facts of the case could be required to gain voting status. Those living in the affected

164

Page 165: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

area would read a selection of the arguments for each course of action, and answer simple questions to show that the issue is understood. The decision would then be made by the informed and affected people.

Decisions with wider effects and more profound consequences might require a different voting structure, in which the degree of knowledge about the problem would determine each person's share of the vote. If a dam is proposed on the Columbia River, economic benefits would have to be weighed against environmental effects. It might be too much to expect everyone affected to become sufficiently knowledgeable about the proposal and its effects to cast an informed vote--there is too much technical information for non-experts to digest. Moreover, those with the best engineering expertise are not necessarily those most knowledgeable about costs and benefits or about environmental effects. Perhaps a formula could be devised to weigh the votes of those with greater (or multiple) expertise more heavily than those who qualify with less knowledge but are still affected. This would give those with a strong interest a powerful motivation to do some research, and might make it more likely that a consensus on the decision could be reached. However, this particular issue is complicated in that the river in question crosses the Canada-U.S. border. How could the relative interests of two entire countries be weighed when one is larger in area and has more environment to affect, and the other has more people and a bigger economy?

The premise behind such electronic participatory democracy schemes is that everyone sufficiently informed would be more likely to come to the same conclusion. This would be a major--and in many cases unjustified--assumption; as has already been indicated, good information is not the only factor in decision making. Such systems would also be a substantial modification of current democratic practice; whether they would be found acceptable or not is another question, especially if they vary in any way the accepted democratic idea of "one person-one vote." It is also important to note that the mere technological enabling of weighted voting is not in itself a reason for implementing such a scheme. Moreover, such a scheme does away with the cherished idea of "one person, one vote" and may not therefore be seen as an improvement.

Yet another common supposition is that the existence of comprehensive communications and information facilities such as the Metalibrary would tend to reduce or eliminate differences in culture and world view and thereby promote unanimity in decision making. This would continue a process begun by books, radio, and television and fostered by modern-day population mobility. However, the world of the 1990s was still far from the global village envisioned by some in the 1960s, even though its peoples hold far more in common now than for thousands of years. Indeed, though there might gradually be fewer sharply distinct cultures based on geography, and fewer international boundaries as well, there are some very basic conflicts of world views that are unlikely ever to be eliminated. If the fall of the former Soviet Union has taught us anything it is that centuries-old ethnic hatreds such as the ones it brutally suppressed can still survive for generations and readily be called upon to create new bloodbaths when that repression is removed. In such cases, the availability of more technology merely means that people are killed at a faster rate than before.

165

Page 166: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Moreover, along with its new kinds of information filters, the Metalibrary could well create new culture and world view conflicts, for not only will people perceive information differently, they would also be able to personalize their view of the information to the extent that they will not have to look at the same data.

An ivy-leaguer with great pride in her type of institution might accept information connection threads only from people at similar schools and choose not to see the threads attached by anyone from smaller or less prestigious universities. Prejudices over spiritual ideas would remain, with some religious people refusing to read certain scientific works and some scientists refusing to read certain religious works. The same applies to those of differing political persuasions. Except when a person placed a foot into the other camp or crossed over altogether, people on one side of any debate could pretend that the other side did not even exist, much as happens today.

When a new link did cause a thread to trail over self-imposed borders, it would at once be obvious. Denial of recognition would remove the threat and the troubled mind could again be safely closed. New ideas and related data would not reach people unless allowed to do so. As is done today with existing information techniques, such denials perpetuate an already well-formed group thinking pattern and increase the possibility that decisions made by such people would be bad ones, because they are not fully informed. Once again we see that automating a bad process (here it is decision making) does not make it better. Rather, it merely produces the bad results faster.

On the other hand, as the pornography issue illustrates, not all information is either useful or beneficial, and it may be a good thing to prevent some of it from entering one's home, or, in such extreme cases, to prevent it from even being available. With a fully implemented Metalibrary, the former may be rather easy, but the latter likely very difficult.

One could suppose that a kind of natural selection (good decisions and advice are more efficient and useful than bad) would gradually reduce the influence of the close-minded as the poor quality of their decisions became evident. However, there is no guarantee that a particular discipline or speciality would not become as rigid and unbending as can now happen using the medium of journal articles. A control belief group has the power to reject new ideas by collectively refusing to look at them. Denial of recognition by the cultural leaders--who may still be termed reviewers or editors--would guarantee that new ideas would not be read. That is, for all its promise as an information utility, the Metalibrary might make it even harder to challenge the control beliefs of a society, for each sub-culture using it would still have unlimited ability to effect intolerance of competing views. A possible way around this difficulty would be to have the Metalibrary rules allow universal visibility to new information links regardless of who makes them, at least until such time as a person reads the item and expressly denies the link. Another possibility would be to create ombuds-reviewers who can make connections that every user will see for at least a certain period of time after the person first reads the new material.

There is no completely satisfactory solution to the problem of intellectual intolerance, however. Everyone filters what they will read and who they will talk to. They must, for there is too much for one person to assimilate. The filters in the

166

Page 167: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Metalibrary will in some senses be more tangible, but they too are necessary. Although the narrowness of specialization may be greatly reduced because much less knowledge will need to be memorized--looking it up will be better--specialities will still remain, and their practitioners will still have difficulty communicating cross-culturally.

Once again, it becomes evident upon some thought that ideas, like goods and services (whether cultural or academic), are accepted or rejected by society as a whole in the short run on their perceived merits, not on absolute standards. In their own generation, the guardians of the control ideas and beliefs can always refuse to acknowledge anything else, or even suppress competition. It is only in the longer (historical) run that they come to be evaluated with more global measuring sticks.

Neither will language barriers necessarily be broken down, for eventually the Metalibrary would communicate with users in their own languages. There would therefore be no incentive to learn another tongue, and meeting other people personally might even become more difficult. Spoken communication could suffer and isolationist tendencies increase, balancing off the improvements in written communication.

The full Metalibrary will also be sophisticated enough to allow the use of cultural, religious, or personal values to assist in filtering information and making decisions. Since it will record every data search and every decision, it could record how each person's filters operate and suggest solutions to problems consistent with one's stated values and past decisions. Again, though there would be benefits to this, there would be no incentive to re-examine one's presuppositions periodically, for the Metalibrary could be set to reinforce them.

In any event, the advent of the full Metalibrary would make it clear that everyone has a world view. Each person would construct a reflection of that world view in the process of learning the system, developing the filters, and making decisions at both the information and interpretation levels. Since there would still be "superstars" of each discipline even in this new medium, there would be a demand for the ability to adopt other people's world views (or sets of connecting threads).

So, in addition to being able to modify one's own personal set of connecting threads to recognize any other person's links, it ought to be possible to rent another's. This is different from incorporating in one's own set the links with that person's name on them, for that does not also add the connections the second person has recognized from other people. Borrowing a whole world view would allow people literally to see things as others do. In this scenario, world views would be a commodity for rent or sale, and would be mergeable with one's own. A person could keep several independent world views on hand and switch between them or revert to an older version of a connection set.

Many scientists who are also writers have remarked that although they can travel in several academic cultures, they seem almost to become different people when they do so. This is a routine phenomenon also, for everyone has a different mindset and vocabulary (called "registers") to communicate with different people (one vocabulary subset and thinking pattern for the children, another for clients, and other for co-workers, and so on). The Metalibrary would allow someone to be (intellectually) as many different people as desired, though it is likely that most

167

Page 168: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

users would integrate their interests into a single collection. Some people would undoubtedly make their world views available as a public service for anyone to use, others might make a tidy profit selling theirs, much as they now do from books.

All of this would allow for decision making that is potentially more factually informed and that enables participants to better consider each other's points of view and how these were formed. This does not mean that making decisions will be any easier than it is now or that most (or any) will be unanimous. It does imply broader participation and less bureaucracy, as well as the possibility of more satisfaction with the results. There would still be differences of opinion and there would be more opinions expressed than ever. All opinions could be considered, even though all surely would not be. To put this another way, being better informed may be good in the ethical sense of the word, but it is not clear to what extent that "good" would be sought after. It is even less clear how well it could be enforced.

Yet another problem with an information-based society is the potential to rely too much on machines for the decision making process. When this is done, it is easy to forget that information is more than whatever is stored in or processed by computers. To have meaning, it must be communicable. Assigning and communicating meaning, judging value, and taking action based on informed decisions are all part of the unique province of human activity, and there is as yet no indication that any of these can be automated. It is easy to rely on the neat rows and columns of figures in a spreadsheet, but unless the assumptions behind the formulas used to produce the output are known, the reader cannot make informed human judgement on the information content. There are value judgements behind the process of data collection in the first place; there are value judgements involved in organizing it; and there are value judgements involved in deciding on what meaning to assign to (and what action to take upon) the material in the end. Thus, who decides, and out of what value system, turns out to be what gives information its ultimate quality and meaning. Humans can think about and evaluate their thinking process; machines cannot. This appears to provide an answer for the (ethical) question: who ought to decide for humans--themselves, or machines?

The availability of instant information also creates pressure to make instant decisions. For instance, because it is easy to do so, and the means are at hand, many people respond to electronic mail messages and Internet news postings as soon as they receive them. As users of such systems are well aware, this results in a large volume of intemperate, ill-considered, and impolite mail traffic and news (Such messages are called "flames"). Likewise, if thought processes and analytical techniques are unsound or if decision makers are so culturally conditioned as to be incapable of considering alternatives, the Metalibrary facility will not help. Computerizing a bad decision-making process does not produce good decisions, it only causes the bad ones to be arrived at in milliseconds instead of days.

As mentioned, prejudice will also remain. That is, irrational dislike of others and refusal to consider things from another person's world view would be as likely then as now. Perhaps the greatest contribution to decision making of instant and universal information availability could be the recognition of legitimate differences among world views as people realize (in the process of automation) how they have been making their decisions. Perceptual and decision-making filters would be

168

Page 169: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

obvious instead of hidden; their existence could no longer be denied or ignored. This has the potential to blur boundaries between sub-cultures, promote communication, broaden specialities, make learning easier, and promote the possibility of sounder decisions. On the other hand, prejudice has stood the test of time as a stronger force in human affairs than any of these potential benefits.

Thus, as for all technologies, the impact of electronic media on knowledge and decision making will be mixed. Great benefits will be available, great abuses will be possible, and for many people there will just be a transfer of their old ways of thinking to a new medium.

4.7 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Information is more than data. It must be processed and communicated in order to have the potential to convey meaning. When this takes place, participants in the exchange (and the whole culture) are altered. Every civilization depends on its transportation and communications technologies. These were once essentially the same, but the latter have now become critically important on their own. Together with the new means for storing and manipulating large amounts of information, fast communications make unlimited access to information available to citizens of the industrialized nations for the first time.

Services offering such data access exist now and have already had a strong impact on many professionals, who have begun to rely more on looking up facts than on memorizing them. It is likely that this way of doing things will be adapted by most people in the near future, though costs must come down and ease of use improve substantially first--steps that all technologies require to become widely accepted.

As this takes place, new technologies will have the normal transforming effect on ideas and demands that created them. Already, hypertext promises to revolutionize the scholarly use of libraries. The extension of this concept to that of the full Metalibrary facility promises to make a wide range of benefits available to the general populace.

Information technology has the problems of accuracy, privacy, prejudice, and state control to overcome. If not, it could cause more problems than it solves. People may have to live in a world where the concept of privacy has changed radically or ceased to exist for many aspects of life.

The effect on decision making is also dramatic because information availability empowers more informed decisions. It does not guarantee good ones, however. The Metalibrary may also make world views into more visible and obvious entities, to the point where they can become commodities for rent or sale. There are both benefits and disadvantages to information technologies, as has been the case for all others.

Discussion Questions

169

Page 170: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

1. Describe the terms hypertext and Metalibrary and distinguish between them.

2. Use your present library to find and describe the term dynabook. Try such subject headings as technology--the future; Alan Kay; Xerox Corp. How long did it take? How long would it in a hypertext?

3. You are in a (paper-based) library researching your master's degree thesis in mathematics and stumble across a brilliant paper: Sutcliffe, Richard J., and Alspach, Brian. "Vertex Transitive Graphs of Order 2p," Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences , v. 319 (May 14, 1979): 18-27. You are captivated by the ideas presented there, and several new theorems that follow from their results immediately come to mind. Has anyone already thought of your ideas? Describe the steps you must take in a paper library to find out who has referenced this paper in a bibliography in the intervening years. Go to your library and do this, making a list of derivative papers and following them through later works as well. When you get tired, estimate how much time it would take to finish. Now describe how this would work using a hypertext system and estimate the time savings. Keep in mind that this is a rather obscure paper with few citations. More popular ones can be orders of magnitude more difficult to trace entirely, because the citations fan out into a maze of papers.

4. Another library task is the making of book bibliographies. This is a little easier than following a paper through citations but can still be quite a challenge. Use your paper library catalogue to make a bibliography of all available books on the computer programming language Modula-2. Now obtain access to an electronic bibliographic data base (your library may subscribe) and perform the same search. How many titles do you get using each method? How long did each take?

5. This chapter has mainly presented the positive side of universal information availability and has been relatively optimistic about the technology becoming available to do it. Write a paper attacking this concept, pointing out its weaknesses, and saying why it can never, should never, or will never come to pass--either from a software/hardware or from a social point of view.

6. Write a paper in which you extend the concept of the Metalibrary in content or use. There are many things it could be or do besides those that are given in this chapter. The more unusual or original can be sent to the author who will include some of the best in a subsequent edition if enough buy the first to make a second worthwhile. Some small prize may be given for the best idea.

7. What effect would the Metalibrary have on a hobby like stamp collecting? Be careful!

8. What effect would worldwide availability of information have on the gap between rich and poor nations?

9. What will the effect on the size and scope of government be? Will it tend to become larger or smaller? Why?

10. Who should manage the Metalibrary and how--or should anyone?11. What degree of privacy over personal details can and should be

guaranteed? What should an individual be able to keep secret? Perhaps you would care to argue that privacy should no longer exist, or at least that the general diffusion of information cuts down on abuses and on the need for privacy.

170

Page 171: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

12. If privacy is a fundamental human right or urge rather than, say, only a legislated right, how will people compensate for their loss of information privacy by increasing some other aspects of personal privacy?

13. Research the subject of computer security and describe the methods of preventing unauthorized access to data in some detail.

14. How much control should government have over data repositories and data transmission? Should such be regulated, taxed, or even run by the government? Give reasons.

15. Look up and explain in at least some detail, the methods used to encrypt data and messages. Include a discussion of DES, RIA, and PGP.

16. The body of the text argues that it is effectively impossible for government to control encryption technology. Refute this.

17. In the Chapter, much of the contents of current news media were described as "news editorials." Do you agree with this description? Why, or why not? What (if anything) should be done to change the situation?

18. Discuss carefully the degree to which the Metalibrary facility would promote understanding, cross-cultural communications, and better decision making. Will such things be improved, or will people simply become more isolationist?

19. To what extent is information available electronically now? Write a summary of the major categories of data bases that can be accessed by the public, their cost, and the type of information they contain.

20. What effect would the Metalibrary have on poverty, illiteracy, poor sanitation, economic exploitation, and discrimination in (a) Western industrial nations, (b) present and former communist nations, and (c) third world nations. Specifically, what ethical obligations (if any) do users of such an intellectual facility have to employ it in bettering living and working conditions for others?

21. The author suggests that collapse of the Soviet Union precipitated the ethnic wars of Eastern Europe (indeed a much earlier version of this text predicted both). Either argue that Western Europe is unstable and subject to the same kind of warfare, or argue that there is good reason to believe that Western Europe is now immune to such problems.

22. Attempt to apply an information analysis to the problems of the Middle East. Could more knowledge of other peoples and their ways make any difference to the inhabitants of Israel and her neighbours?

23. Answer the same question as in #22 but with reference to India and Pakistan.

Bibliography

Denning, Peter J. & Metcalfe, Robert M. Beyond Calculation--The Next Fifty Years of Computing. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1997.

Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. New York: Anchor, 1986.Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers. New York: Macmillan, 1986.Inose, Hiroshi, and Pierce John R. Information, Technology and Civilization.

New York: Freeman, 1984.

171

Page 172: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Marchand, Donald A. and Horton, Forest W. Infotrends--Profiting From Your Information Resources. New York: Wiley, 1986

Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner Books, 1984.Naisbitt, John and Aburdene, Patricia. Megatrends 2000. New York: William

Morrow, 1990. Nelson, Theodore Holm. Literary Machines. Bellevue WA., Electronic Ed. by

Owl International, 1988.Orwell, George. Nineteen eighty-four. 1949. Reprint. Harmondsworth,

England: Penguin, 1964.Plant, Raymond, et al (eds.) Information Technology: the Public Issues.

Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1988Roszak, Theodore. The Cult of Information. New York; Random House, 1986.Sieber, Ulrich. The International Handbook on Computer Crime. New York:

Wiley, 1986Stover, William Jones. Information Technology in the Third World. Boulder, CO:

Westview Press, 1984

Internet resources:

Cranor, Lorrie <email:[email protected]<http://www.cec.wustl.edu/~cs142/links.html<http://www.wofford.edu/~kaycd/competh.htm

172

Page 173: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 5Robotics and The Second Industrial

Revolution

Seminar - "Work, Workers, and Machines" 5.1 Tracing a Second Industrial Revolution 5.2 Robots and the New Industries 5.3 Work and Workers in the New Society 5.4 Some Issues in Automation and Robotization 5.5 Other Industrial Futures 5.6 Summary and Further Discussion

5.1 Tracing a Second Industrial Revolution The Industrial Revolution involved harnessing machines for production

previously done by hand. By "second industrial revolution" is meant the automation of those same tasks so machines require few, if any, human attendants. This is not new, for the entire machine age tells the story of machines having ever greater efficiency, power, and productivity. Automated textile devices first claimed the livelihood of thousands of independent artisans when the English garment and lace factories came into being in the early nineteenth century. Each machine that mechanized work previously done by hand reduced the number of people required to produce a given quantity of goods. This affected agriculture and industry simultaneously. The machine revolution proceeded simultaneously through all parts of the economy because the various sectors competed for raw materials and human

173

Page 174: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

resources. Also, new technologies developed for one industry are applied to others in short order.

The machines of the industrial age, though as diverse as the industries in which they were employed, had one thing in common that distinguished them from the human workers before them. Each was a speciality device, designed and built for a specific task. To accommodate any subsequent changes in an industry invariably meant retooling--a euphemism for scrapping much of the existing machinery and replacing it with new. In only a very few cases does any part of an industrial-age machine survive a substantial technological change; it becomes noncompetitive or irrelevant, so it is unplugged and thrown away.

Human workers, on the other hand, can be retrained to use new skills and new tools--if the employer takes the time and effort to do so, and the unions will allow it. Throughout the machine age, human retraining took place continuously as new machines demanded different skills of their operators. However, as time passed, more of the physical tasks in manufacturing became automated, and the machines started to become more general-purpose and to require fewer operators. Logically, the next step in the sequence is the replacement of the human operators by machines sufficiently versatile that the "retraining" could be applied to the them instead of to workers.

Until recently, this step could not be taken because there were no satisfactory ways of encapsulating retrainability in a machine, and the jobs of at least some of the human workers were safe. With the advent of programmable automatons, or robots, they no longer are.

Profile On . . . Technology

Robots

Where did the term "robot" come from?In 1921 Czech dramatist Karel Capek wrote a play, R.U.R. or Rossum's

Universal Robots. The Czech word means "heavy work."

What disciplines are involved in robotics?Robotics is a difficult multidisciplinary field embracing computing science,

mechanical engineering, control systems, and knowledge of the design and operation of the manufacturing process.

What are the Laws Of Robotics?1. A robot may not injure a human being, or through inaction allow a human

being to come to harm.2. A robot must obey the orders given it by human beings except where such

orders would conflict with the first law.3. A robot must protect its own existence as long as such protection does not

conflict with the first or second laws.

Who enforces these laws?

174

Page 175: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

No one does. They were formulated for use in the fiction of Isaac Asimov in 1940 and popularized since then by a number of other writers of science fiction. There are no robots yet capable of being programmed to "obey" these laws, and it is not certain there ever will be.

Does this mean that a robot could kill a human being?Present day robots are little different from any other industrial machinery in

this respect. Some have detectors that allow them to avoid a human being, but apart from this, it is as dangerous to get in the way of a working robot as it is to stand in the path of a moving truck.

What can robots do?Robots have been equipped with grippers, manipulators, motion sensors,

heat, light, and sound detectors and are capable of handling tools, moving about, lifting, carrying, and fitting parts.

They can weld, assemble electronic components, spray paint, sand and polish, apply adhesives and other coatings, drill, make tools, load, unload and store materials, move parts about in a factory or warehouse, mine coal, make castings, and assemble and inspect finished products.

They can be sent to Mars to rove a hostile landscape, gather and assess data for scientific experiments, or serve as a child's toy.

Can robots see?There are many manufacturers of robotic visions systems. These allow robots

to sense colours and shapes, position parts in the correct location, and inspect products for flaws. The patterns read by the optical systems are compared with ones in storage. Whether this is "seeing" depends on the definition of sight.

Which industries use robots?Examples include: automobile and aeroplane manufacturing, shipbuilding,

electronics assembly, appliance manufacturing, tool and die making, mining, warehousing, transportation, and undersea exploration.

In what manufacturing environments do they work best?o where the products are hard items that must be moved about and stacked.o (so far) where the items being moved are relatively large.o where the actions required are relatively simple and are repeated in exactly

the same way every time until a reprogramming is done.o where decisions are simple, have few options, and do not call for shades of

judgement (i.e., the domain of action has clear and strict boundaries).o where any visual inspections can be handled with a low resolution,

monochrome, two dimensional vision scan.o where quantities are great enough to warrant using robots, but not so large

as to make fixed machinery more economical.o where the plant can be run in continuous shifts.

175

Page 176: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o where labour, land, buildings, and other costs are high, but capital is easy to obtain, and interest rates are reasonable.

o new factories where the entire building and assembly line can be designed with robots in mind.

o where conditions are too hazardous to risk many (or any) human beings (inside a volcano or nuclear plant, inspecting or disassembling bombs, or exploring in space).

5.2 Robots and the New Industries Robotic devices have gone far beyond the realm of science fiction, having

become a day-to-day reality in the lives of many people. Home appliances have built-in microprocessor controllers and timers. Automobiles include diagnostic centres and several computers to control their operations. Golfers ride about on robotized caddy-carts. Computers have revolutionized the writing and publishing industries by automating many tedious functions. However, such devices have not caused dramatic large-scale changes in basic living and working patterns for most people. Instead, they have produced simple, small-scale changes to the existing industrial society. To constitute anything revolutionary, they would have to be capable of displacing large numbers of workers from their positions. However, both on the assembly line and in the office, that displacement has now begun.

There is a fundamental difference between the Industrial Revolution and this second revolution. Many of the workers who have kept their jobs up to this time because of the (human) ability to be retrained will now lose them, for the new types of automated manufacturing machinery are indeed reprogrammable. Machines can now be given not only computational and routine work, but also something that passes for decision-making ability. Robotic tools are used extensively in such situations as automobile assembly lines, where the fact that robots cannot make wrong decisions makes them more economical than human workers. Many of these are heavy equipment models, with limited and rigid capabilities, but these are rapidly giving way to much more flexible devices.

It was long a piece of American folklore that one ought not buy a car made on a Monday or a Friday because the workers were not at their peak on those days. However, robots do not get hung over, bored, angry, sleepy, or careless. They do not require time-and-a-half, lunch breaks, sleep at night, salaries, pensions, washrooms, or stock-sharing plans, nor do they go on strike or make demands. Robots require a substantial capital expense but small operating cost, for they are paid no salary. They are reliable, and can be retrained without expensive courses.

A robot can replace between five and ten assembly-line workers and pay for itself in three years or less. It will do exactly the right job time and time again, welding two parts with the right temperature and pressure and in the right place, or applying a nut to a bolt with exactly the specified torque. Parts fit better and are stronger, and the final product can be counted on to be of uniform quality every time. Small pieces can be attached to machines or electronic devices with any desired degree of precision, and this can be done quickly as well as accurately throughout an entire production run, then reprogrammed for a different run.

176

Page 177: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Most important, technological changes can be worked out ahead of time and new computer programs devised to direct the manufacture of new products. With reprogrammable tools, the assembly line can be retooled with much less scrapping of machines and very little lost production time. Ultimately, it should be possible for a new automobile to be designed entirely by computer and for the assembly line to be switched over to the new product automatically and with minimal human intervention on the factory floor.

The first four-hundred-fifty-nine vehicles made some future day could be four-wheel drive trucks, and the four-hundred-sixtieth could be a newly-designed compact car--with no intervening space or time on the assembly line. The line could then switch back to trucks until the prototype is tested. For the foreseeable future, the decision to make the switches would be a human one--there is no method yet of automating the reasoning leading up to it.

While the kind of flexibility suggested here is not yet available, robotic devices are already used extensively in Japanese automobile assembly and seem destined to take over the same functions in North American plants as well, if their owners wish to stay in business. Ultimately, assembly lines of all types will be automated in this fashion, and most consumer goods will be produced with few or no human workers in the plant.

The resulting changes will be as sweeping as were those following the original Industrial Revolution, for millions of skilled and semiskilled jobs in manufacturing, mining, forestry, materials processing, warehousing, and other smokestack industries will no longer be required. Most of the small staff remaining in such industries will be white collar workers, accounting for and running the machines that operate the machines--and doing so from the office environment, rather than from the factory floor. Other employees will be the highly trained and versatile technicians whose task it will be to effect the inevitable repairs.

Eventually, factories also will be designed and built to order largely by machines, and can be placed in remote or uninhabitable regions without blighting either the urban or rural landscape. They could be built beneath the ground, inside mountains, under the ocean, in outer space, or on the moon. Of course, some people must continue to work on the design and operation of factories. However, the consumers who benefit from their production will need neither to know nor care where those factories are physically located, so long as the flow of goods continues unhindered. In many cases it might be difficult or impossible for an unprotected human being to pay a physical visit to the floor of one of these factories; ultimately it will perhaps be almost entirely unnecessary.

Some mark 1956 as the watershed year in the progress of automation, for in that year the number of service jobs in North America exceeded the number in manufacturing and farming (i.e., in production) for the first time. The next four decades saw a steady growth in the number and sophistication of available consumer goods and in the general standard of living even while jobs continued to shift to the service and information sectors. Recessions notwithstanding, there was during that period a level of economic expansion and prosperity such as has never before been seen. If this could be projected into the future, those who have jobs of

177

Page 178: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

any kind would probably be able to afford far more technological luxury than ever before.

Even now television antennas sprout on the roofs of the most primitive tin shacks in the barrios of South America and Asia. Video cassette recorders and tapes of dubbed American movies can be rented in small Pakistani towns. There are few but the remotest of jungle dwellers who lack radios or who are unfamiliar with at least some modern technological amenities. Even in such settings, the local missionary-cum-Bible translator is likely to come equipped with a microcomputer, word-processing software, and a portable electric generator.

As familiar as people are with the recent economic impact of existing technology, they may not be very well prepared for the changes that are coming. The Industrial Revolution took over a century to run its course in England with the most dramatic changes between 1780 and 1850. A critical mass of new industrial technology has again collected, but the changes this time may take place over a much shorter period. Some forecasters predict that the transition to robotic goods production could be essentially complete in a few decades. By another generation after that, few people would have much detailed knowledge of what a factory is, or where any are located. Industrial production could then be as invisible and as much taken for granted as a farm is now.

The economic impacts would be as profound as those of the industrial age, for even as smokestack industries all but disappeared from sight, consumer goods could simultaneously improve in quality and sophistication and be reduced in price. The distribution chain could also be shortened, for there would be much less need for retailers and wholesalers in any of the big-ticket items. Stereos, televisions, refrigerators, and many other products could be ordered by the customer directly from the factory (through the Metalibrary) and delivered to the door without the need of intermediaries such as wholesalers. Smaller appliances, clothing, shoes, and such other goods as household robots could be obtained in the same fashion (It could be a long time--or never--before robotic truck drivers are deployed, however). Information providers on the Internet already allow such direct ordering of a variety of goods and conduct business activities electronically on a large scale, so these comments are saying little that is new.

If such methods were to become more widely adopted, stores and shopping centres as they now exist could be much reduced in size and importance, perhaps becoming manufacturers' showrooms. If Metalibrary terminals eventually had three-dimensional colour-projection ability, many items could be accurately previewed in the home. With fully automated factories, clothing could be guaranteed to fit, for single items could be made-to-order for the customer's measurements with no loss of production line efficiency. Indeed, goods might only be made to order, with mass production disappearing altogether.

Such large scale automation also suggests to some observers that the new era would see more planned economies, though presumably not along the lines of the now discredited and abandoned communist statism. Planning could consist of surveys and projections of customer wants by the companies engaged in satisfying those wants, and not involve government at all. This requires no new techniques other than better information access and processing, for decision making by polling

178

Page 179: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

for public opinion has long been a feature on both the commercial and political scene in North America. Naturally, the advertising industry will continue to seek out new ways to change those wants so that consumers focus on new products. Indeed, even a full Metalibrary's entertainment facilities would undoubtedly be as heavily commercialized as are today's television networks.

Looked at optimistically, and only from a material point of view, the robotic manufacturing technologies appear to promise a rosy future. However, the people of this projected new society would be profoundly affected in ways other than simply having more and better products available to buy, consume, and dispose of.

5.3 Work and Workers in the New Society Automation and robotization do not simply influence institutions, as if the

economy were an abstract entity that does not touch real people. On the contrary, large numbers of people are directly affected, for nearly every job that existed in the 1980s and 1990s could either change beyond recognition or vanish altogether within the working lifetimes of their holders--as had many jobs of the 1960s and 1970s already. As in the first Industrial Revolution, the effect of large scale robotization in the workplace will be profound, particularly in the transition years when the new industries are just becoming established. Service industries, the information sector itself, and the professions have so far done well to absorb new workers, shifting the balance of employment with relatively little pain. However, more rapid changes that appear to be in store for the future could overwhelm for a time the ability for society to cope with them.

At any time, there are three kinds of dislocation that may be experienced by workers whose jobs become obsolete. The most severe is outright termination, leading at least temporarily to unemployment. A worker's job may cease to exist because of automation, reduction in market share, or because the enterprise goes bankrupt. During stable times, the person may have a reasonable expectation of obtaining a nearly equivalent position with another company. However, in changing times those other companies are reducing staff, for the problems encountered by the original employer are common to the whole economy. Many jobs lost during the periodic downturns in economic activity are never regained; the companies involved each time introduce new techniques and new efficiencies to reduce their labour needs. As a result, North American structural unemployment (minimum levels during good times) has increased substantially during the last thirty years and seems destined to grow higher still. Indeed, the minimum rate at the top of the cycle may be well above six percent (nine in Canada; higher is some countries)--levels that until recently would have been regarded as unacceptable and warranting massive government intervention in the economy. In the long run, it can be reasonably expected that the number of new manufacturing sector jobs created during good times will be far fewer than the number eliminated in the bad times.

The second kind of dislocation is called displacement. This occurs when a worker's old job vanishes but there is immediate retraining available for a new position that has opened up because of the new technology. Here, the employer shifts and grows with the economy and, despite new technology, need not reduce the work force. Perhaps the employer also perceives a moral obligation to retrain

179

Page 180: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

current employees for new positions rather than counting on schools and universities to supply trained workers at no cost.

Alternatively, the worker may have the foresight, initiative, and imagination to seek appropriate retraining when the time is ripe. Such a worker may displace to another employer or industry or become a self-employed professional, but does so voluntarily and perhaps even with confidence. While such visionary and mobile workers were relatively rare in the past, they could well be the norm in the future.

Technically, a worker replaced by a machine is only displaced, for retrainability supposedly implies that everyone can find other employment. In practice, the displaced very often become unemployed because they (or their employers) are unwilling or unable to effect retraining. Semiskilled workers with a poor educational background and those who are relatively new to the labour force are the most vulnerable in such situations. It is often perceived (and was once stated as fact by Marxists) that there is little to restrain industrialists from seeking maximum profits while having no regard for the human consequences. Such a perception is a stereotype, for no business or economy could operate that way openly and indefinitely in a competitive marketplace. Too many valuable workers (and customers) would be alienated, and profits would eventually suffer.

A third kind of dislocation, job growth, is more subtle, for it may be visible only in retrospect. Here, the job holder and the job are mutually transformed over a period of time, often without anyone noticing that the original job no longer exists--the old job has been replaced by an entirely new one with no break in continuity. Although not always possible, this is the least traumatic type of dislocation and can bring a high degree of satisfaction to everyone involved. This kind of growth does not ordinarily take place by accident. Managers who wish to foster it must ensure that workers have a degree of independence and job control that enables them to plan their own change and growth as employment conditions demand. Rigid, locked-in job descriptions or contracts prevent people from learning new skills, whereas flexibility to meet the challenges of change foster such growth. These observations suggest a trend toward more flexible and educated workers, a more professional style of employment, and a correspondingly greater worker control over terms and conditions of the job. Adaptability to new environments would become the key to remaining employable.

As existing positions are metamorphosing or vanishing, many new ones are being created. The computing industry now employs millions of people with job descriptions that English lacked the vocabulary to write three decades ago. General affluence has resulted in large numbers of new jobs being created in the entertainment, tourism, and hospitality industries. Likewise, the global information and communications industries, the biochemical field, and space-based enterprises will soon employ millions who once might have worked in factories, and one can only guess at what their job descriptions will be. Certainly, few of them will be on production lines. Most will be administrators, office workers, information brokers, researchers, data handlers, medical personnel, computer operators, pilots, and the like. This reinforces the suggestion above that the new positions will be for technicians or professionals rather than for unskilled or semi-skilled laborers.

180

Page 181: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Thus, jobs and wages will continue to flow out of smokestack industries and into the service and professional fields. The holders of these new jobs will presumably make more money, expanding the demand for both goods and services. Perhaps most people will eventually be employed (or self-employed). However, depending on the speed at which robotization takes place, there could be a period of 16-24 percent unemployment in some countries. In the past, when unemployment reached such levels, riots, revolutions and great social unrest have occurred. Thus, the rise of modern-day groups of Luddites (machine smashers) or the establishment of totalitarian states in some previously democratic countries are possibilities that cannot be completely dismissed. Passions could run very high during such dislocations, and racial, religious, or political scapegoats could once again be sought. These possibilities (and natural human resistance to change) might argue for a slow transition to complete automation, but the market forces demanding quick action may be too powerful to be tempered by anything short of total societal collapse.

In the long run a higher percentage of people may be self-employed or work in what are now called part-time positions. Some predict that tourism, entertainment, and the arts will be the largest employers. Central governments may grow dramatically in size for a time, as they attempt to regulate or seize even more of the wealth and production. There may also be pressure on them to employ many of those displaced from market sector jobs, just to give them something to do. In the long run, however, government may become much smaller and less significant in the overall economy as some of its current functions become irrelevant. Any such changes could take place rather painfully, for the state never relinquishes power easily.

As in past transitions, new technology will demand changes in educational content and practice. The new work force will have to be much better educated and informed than in the industrial age, and the changes will be greater in relative terms than in the transition from an agricultural to an industrial society. Such education must be focused on the ability to change and adapt over a person's working years, for jobs may well come and go at a rapid rate--this may be at least a medium-term feature (if not a permanent one) of the information age. If most people are faced with changing jobs or professions repeatedly, they will have to be broadly educated beyond any narrow speciality in order to cope (Chapter 10 will cover the topic of education in detail).

If industry and government will be transformed, then so will the unions--the third institutional leg on which the industrial age has stood. These organizations were created to provide a means of representing relatively uneducated workers' interests to a possibly exploitive management. Some models of the information age suggest that in a society where it is difficult to keep secrets, cooperation may be easier to establish and confrontation may be frowned upon. New industries tend not to inherit either social baggage or technique from the old ones; they use a substantially different work force and often locate in different places.

According to Robert Blaumer (Alienation and Freedom) those in the new industries find their work more satisfying and less alienating than do those working in typical factory jobs. With the advance of technology, drudgery work is reduced or

181

Page 182: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

eliminated and work requiring a substantial intellectual component is created. Workers can become more skilled and achieve the high levels of job satisfaction that typified earlier types of craft occupations. Perhaps the difference is that people felt themselves to be servants when they tended the old machines, whereas in the new order, they perceive that the machines work for them. Of course, this analysis is true only of the larger picture. It tells us nothing about the many unskilled workers who become permanently alienated from employment when replaced by automatons and their small cadre of highly-skilled technicians. The latter have both education and jobs, and have every reason for self-satisfaction.

This satisfaction has other consequences. Workers in the newer industries, and in white-collar positions generally, have not joined their industrial counterparts by unionizing in any great number. The percentage of union members among all workers in North America peaked some time ago and has declined rapidly in recent years. There is every reason to suppose this trend will continue and even accelerate. Unions that merely hold onto their traditional power bases seem destined to gradually lose members and power. They may disappear as the jobs they now represent vanish. Others might change into consumer associations or find some other way to represent the interests of service-industry workers. Some observers predict that the traditional trade unions will not have any substantial influence in the long term. In the shorter term, certain unions may gain both members and power, depending on their circumstances. However, models of the information age seem to have little room for traditional industrial unions, so their survival may depend on a willingness to change substantially.

On the other hand, professional organizations, such as those representing nurses, doctors, lawyers, accountants, and so on could well be formed for computer scientists and other professional knowledge workers. In the 1960s and 1970s the job-description buzzwords were "technician" and "engineer;" for the 1980s and 1990s the buzzword has been "professional." To some extent professional organizations will be like unions for they will likely inherit some of their politics and a few business managers from the traditional labour movement. As they grow in influence and power, they could also come to resemble guilds with high entrance barriers and elaborate codes of what constitutes the proper practice of the profession. They might concentrate on raising their members' standing and status in the community, rather than on making strictly material gains. They might convey social status alone, and have little practical power. However these scenarios are speculative, for the formation, growth, and role of political parties, professional societies, unions, and other organizations is subject to too many unknowns to predict reliably. A single accident, scandal, malpractice suit, or election can make or break the power of any group. Thus, of unions and the like, it is only possible to say that, like all institutions, they must develop and change with society or vanish as they lose their vitality.

One thing that can be said with some assurance is that any such organizations whose sole interest is maintaining the status quo of their own power and influence will surely go the way of the butter churn, the horseless carriage, the keypunch operator, and the silent movie.

182

Page 183: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Changes in the workplace will not be confined to the industrial scene. Many office tasks that are today performed by the white-collar counterparts of the skilled factory worker will also become obsolete. The number of secretaries, receptionists, and clerks could decline dramatically as Metalibrary facilities develop. Past projections of the advent of a paperless office proved to be erroneous--there is now more paper than ever--but this was because the emerging technology was fitted into and used to promote existing ways of doing things, rather than providing new models for office work. This is to be expected of new techniques, which are generally used at first only to supplement existing practice and do not generate new ways until a certain critical mass is reached. This example also indicates the dangers inherent in making projections. All of them (including the ones in this book) are likely to be partly if not wholly wrong.

The Metalibrary (even as it now exists on a small and disconnected scale) does provide a new office model by making most paper files unnecessary, for it does obsolete many of the clerical jobs in countless offices, including most of those in the government sector. Such jobs are still done by people for two reasons.

First, the power and productivity of existing facilities for electronic data search, document creation, information storage, and paperless communication are only just being realized (i.e., the Metalibrary as it now exists is so new that it is being under-utilized).

Second, these facilities are still quite primitive. Problems to contend with include lack of universal connectivity, fragmentation of data storage, data inconsistency, and difficulty of existing interfaces to the Metalibrary. Before there can be a substantial impact on office routines, the Metalibrary must become completely connected, consistent, fully functional, easy to use, cheap, and offer access to all public databases and mailing systems. No lesser technology will suffice, for only a completely reliable, size-unlimited, ultra-fast and convenient facility with obvious competitive advantages over the filing cabinet can replace the office routine of the past. If it were made so, even microfilm would be unnecessary, for documents could be stored in a form reproducible on any terminal.

It would take decision makers some time to get used to a relatively paperless environment, but competitive advantages would overcome initial concerns about information security and loss. Backup systems in local versions and on the worldwide version of the Metalibrary would have to be extensive to earn the trust of decision makers. Use of the facimile machine, despite it consuming even more paper, was a step in the direction of the paperless office routine. Once people become used to the idea of carrying about and using light, portable devices that allow them to send and receive information anywhere and at any time, they will also demand much larger electronic storage capacity and other features that will eliminate paper consumption except when necessary.

Meanwhile, middle management may continue to be a casualty of workplace revolution, as each recession in the business cycle squeezes out more workers who have made it thus far. There is less need all the time for people to collect data and then filter and summarize it on paper for the attention of senior management. Already, decision makers can obtain such summaries and form projections on alternative decisions easily, more quickly, and more accurately from computers on

183

Page 184: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

their own desks (let alone from the Metalibrary) than they could ever get through relying on several layers of middle management. Improvements in the capacity to do such things only imperil more mid-level jobs. The task of doing such gathering and filtering will become more common than ever, and the time required will be less, because much of it can be automated. Decision makers will be the ones assigning meaning to the data; they will not need to rely on others to do it for them.

Not all of yesterday's senior management will survive the changeover. Those who fail to obtain the necessary technical skills for making computer-assisted decisions will join their less capable middle managers on the unemployment rolls, their places taken by those who have prepared for the move up.

There may also be less need for in-person meetings, except as an excuse to visit convention centres in exotic vacation destinations. For those people who do work at what are now called office jobs, the bulk of what they do could be accomplished at home rather than by commuting to a central location. Not all such face-to-face gatherings (meetings and communal offices) can be eliminated, for it is difficult to take a person's measure, to know who they are, and what their responses mean except by arranging a personal meeting. Today's executive is also quite dependent on the business lunch--an institution that can only be maintained by clustering offices in a central location, and one that would take some time to be abandoned. There is, in short, a need for some socialization in the conduct of business--one that machines will not fill, and therefore will not eliminate entirely.

Research for potential decisions can also be contracted out by the decision maker to experts who work with the Metalibrary, assembling the relevant data into the desired format, and collecting their fee without leaving home, seeing their employer, or even knowing who it is. Offers can be made on the Metalibrary for so much money in return for the solution to a particular problem within a certain number of hours. The solutions offered could be collected by yet another person and the contributors paid in proportion to the amount of their ideas that was actually used in the final decision. This is not much different from present practice, except in the means of communication, and except for the fact that the largest of the existing networks are non-commercial, so there is no monetary value in answering the questions of others.

Clearly, telecommuting of all types has some advantages for those who are involved: they can save time and money; those unwilling or unable to commute can work at home; and fewer cars, freeways, and office buildings are required. It also has disadvantages. It promotes isolation from other people, a loss of identity with the employer, and the holding of loyalties to oneself alone. Thus, futurists differ sharply when discussing forecasts of how large a percentage of the population will ever work at home. Those who focus on the advantages paint an idyllic picture of such a life and make extravagant projections indeed.

Your granddaughter does her job right from home. She's a teacher specializing in exceptionally bright children as well as severely retarded ones. She has never met most of her students face-to-face because they live all over North America. She's in contact with them daily by video link on an individual basis. She sets up their daily work schedules and

184

Page 185: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

programs their home learning computers with problems and exercises. She discusses their daily work with them and guides them through their individual problem areas. No computer can do that. Because of time zones, her work is over for the day and she has only to do tomorrow's session planning and student reviews before going to bed tonight. She's good at her work and is paid well--sometimes by parents, sometimes by local school boards, and sometimes by institutions. She and her students have the Central Data Bank available to them twenty-four hours a day. The little red schoolhouse has become the whole continent. - Harry Stein in The Hopeful Future

Those who are more concerned with what they see as the dehumanizing and desocializing aspects predict that few people will ever make the home their workplace. Rozak (The Cult of Information) sees an eeriness in visions like Stein's--they are part of what he calls "megahype" employed by information industry people to sell products and increase the value of their company stock. The true future is probably somewhere between extreme visions--fewer offices, not none.

Any large-scale telecommuting would also have important demographic implications, for the need to build large cities to host vast armies of office workers could be greatly reduced. This would profoundly affect patterns of where people choose to live and how they travel. Cities that failed to attract new residents on the basis of living amenities would lose population rapidly, and some of them could well decline into ruin. Certain old-time industrial cities in the United States have already lost as much as 25 percent of their population due to the departure of the former industrial workers. If job loss at the office became as substantial, the effect would be both greater and more widespread.

The most important effects of telecommuting would be felt by workers themselves. Matters could be worst of all for those who have lived in the inner city--a group already at the lower end of the economic scale--who might find themselves even further disadvantaged. Those who lose jobs also lose status and dignity in a society that has traditionally measured people's worth by what they do for a living. What is more, much of the traditional strength of the middle class in the industrial age has been drawn from well-paid unionized factory workers (and lately from middle management). When these people lose their positions, they often find themselves unqualified for anything but very low-paying (sometimes part-time) service-sector jobs, and they suffer a dramatic decline in their standard of living. Here, for contrast, is Rozak's critical version of the vision of the empty office:

The fully automated office will do for white collar workers what the automated assembly line has done in the factories: it will "save" labour by eliminating it, starting with the file clerks and secretaries, but soon reaching to the junior executives and the sales force. Possibly these casualties of progress will find work at Burger King down the street, where the cash registers come equipped with pictures, not numbers, or as the janitors who clean up whatever there is left to clean up at the end of the day--at least until these jobs are turned over to robots. There may soon be no one left in the high-rise ziggurats of our cities but a small elite of top-level decision makers surrounded by electronic apparatus. They will be in touch around the globe with others of their kind, the only decently paid work force

185

Page 186: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

left in the information economy, manipulating spreadsheets, crafting takeover bids, transferring funds from bank to bank at the speed of light, arranging "power lunches." As time goes by, there will be less and less for them to do, for even decision making can be programmed...

At that point, even the corporate leadership will not have to report to the office. Most of what needs to be done by way of human intervention will be done out of the home. One forms an eerie vision of the high industrial future: a vista of glass towers standing empty in depopulated business districts where only machines are on the job networking with other machines. - Theodore Roszak in The Cult of Information

Taking a more middle course, others forecast that those who would have jobs in the new order might simply work fewer hours for higher pay. Job sharing could become routine--one person working only four hours and someone else the next four. Or, a person might work seven hours a day for three days a week. More people would go into business for themselves, and fewer would use a time clock, because even in working for someone else, salaried contracts would be the norm and hourly wages the exception. Such people set their own hours, so those who earn their living through the Metalibrary would keep the system in continuous use around the world twenty-four hours a day.

The hope of the most optimistic is that the amount of wealth generated by those who choose to work will be so large that there will be plenty for everyone, and a guaranteed minimum income will by itself keep the world's population well supplied with both necessities and luxuries. Even as things now stand, the food problem is one of distribution, not of quantity. There are people starving to death in some parts of the world, but there are surpluses large enough to feed them in other countries. If the loss due to rats and insects alone could be eliminated, the net availability of food would increase by 30 percent worldwide. Of course, the optimists also assume the inherent goodness of humanity. They discount population growth and shifts, and take by faith that food production techniques will somehow adapt. They also discount tyrants, wars, famines and plagues as mere "accidents" in the inevitable upward spiral of progress. History is not really on their side.

It seems likely that underdeveloped nations will at first continue to experience high population growth as the available wealth increases. At some point, they could follow the industrialized West and have stable or even declining populations. For a time, present-day third-world countries would have to erect trade barriers to protect their human-run factories from the cheaper competitive products of the West's robotic plants. However, underdeveloped countries would experience both industrial revolutions in close succession, and at least some of them seem destined to catch up eventually, though perhaps at the cost of even more social upheaval than in the more developed nations.

High unemployment during the transitional time could cause severe social dislocations, rising crime, and the possibility of the new social order being cut off in violence and poverty before even getting started. There are other problems to

186

Page 187: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

overcome, and the new society will have its own difficulties as well. There will still be workaholics trying to get ahead. Some will still be bored or hate their lot in life and will always be dissatisfied. Despite the optimism of some observers, there will probably still be those who are richer and those who are poorer, and the rich will still have their status symbols and privileges, even if the means by which they obtain both is very different.

Is automation, then, a good thing? Perhaps, if by "good" is meant only an increase in the availability of material goods. It will also likely mean much more time for everyone to do what they choose, even if some of this free time is enforced by unemployment. If "good" means morally good, the answer is unknown, for although technological advances in general are anything but morally neutral, specific ones often turn out to have more "good" applications than others. This is something that is difficult to guess ahead of time even when the motives for developing the particular technology are known.

Some of the problems with automation have already been touched on in this section; in the next, certain of them will be considered in more detail. Some of the other implications of the new industrial revolution and of the role of automated machinery will be examined in Chapter 6.

Profile On ... Motives

Eight Reasons to Automate

1. To reduce overall costso If the cost (amortized over some number of years) of a capital purchase that

replaces a worker is less than the wages and benefits that would be paid to the worker for the same number of years, then automation has a direct and irresistible effect on the bottom line.

NOTE: workers' fringe benefits may cost 30% of salary. Allowing for interest rates and maintenance, suppose it cost 30% of an initial capital expenditure per year of operation (amortized over ten years). Then, if the cost of the robot is less than ten years' salary, it is cheaper than the worker (Such figures may vary widely).

o Other savings can come from reduced heating, cooling, and lighting bills, for robots can work in harsher environments. They do not need lunch rooms, vending machines, recreational facilities, company social events, or daycare facilities -- all these affect capital as well as operating costs.

o The more widespread the use of robots, the lower the cost of making them, and the more cost effective it becomes to use them. Some manufacturers use robots to make robots. Computers already design robots, and the human input is decreasing.

o Wages go up with inflation. The principal cost of servicing a capital loan is fixed, only the interest rate and maintenance charges are affected by inflation.

2. To eliminate unreliability

187

Page 188: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

An automaton can be programmed to do the required task exactly the same way every time producing a higher quality and more uniform product. (e.g., welding)

3. To overcome a shortage of skilled labourAt times, workers with particular skills may be in short supply, and those who

are available command high wages. It is usually easier to make or reprogram more machines on short notice than it is to get more skilled workers quickly.

4. To achieve results that would be impossible manuallyo Hazards: Remote robotic manipulators can work close to the core of a

nuclear reactor, or with very hot or cold parts. Some can work in the vacuum of space, in poisonous gases, or underwater.

o Strength: They may be built to lift heavier parts or apply more force or pressure in an assembly than could a human.

o Precision: They can be designed to work on a microscopic scale with a precision that a human cannot achieve.

5. To increase output from a given factory floor areaIt may be possible to place robots closer together or run them faster than is

practical for human workers. In places where space is at a premium (e.g., Japan) this may be the most important consideration.

6. To lower inventoryo A faster assembly line implies that fewer of the raw parts are tied up in the

process.o If inventory of finished product grows too large, a robotic assembly line can

be closed down simply and cheaply, and re-started easily. The cost of either with human workers can be very high.

o Robots may be employed in the warehouse to achieve efficiencies similar to those obtained by the ones on the manufacturing floor.

7. To improve flexibilityo It may be easier (and cheaper) to reprogram a robot than to retrain a

human worker.o The more capable such machines become, the more feasible it is to use

them for small volume production runs, and even one-of-a-kind or made-to-order manufacture.

8. To improve market shareAnything that reduces costs and improves efficiency and quality relative to

the competition in related industries can increase market share. Improved sales can lead to other economies of scale, further reducing costs.

Is Automation Inevitable?

188

Page 189: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

"In any repetitive manufacturing process, 95% of the shop-floor work-force can be eliminated ... Manual skills will no longer be marketable as such." -- David Bell (Employment in the Age of Drastic Change)

"robotization now seems imperative for car manufacturers if they wish to remain competitive."

"So we move towards the factory that has just one man and a dog: the dog is there to make sure no one touches the machinery, and the man is there to feed the dog!" -- Christopher Rowe (People and Chips)

"Eventually, robots could do all the robot-assembly work, assemble other equipment, make the needed parts, run the mines and generators that supply the various factories with materials and power, and so forth. -- Eric Drexler (Engines of Creation)

5.4 Some Issues in Automation and Robotization As indicated in the last section, the chief motivation for automation, as well as

its chief effect, is to reduce the number of workers and save operating costs, while producing more goods. This is an illustration of technique at its best (or worst), for in this case the search for efficiency would clearly result in massive job displacement if taken to its fullest extent.

Whether the apparent material benefits are worth the disruption can be debated with good arguments on both sides. This situation however, does seem to illustrate the irresistibility of technique--even if one is capable of assessing the broader costs, automation will still take place because it produces more efficient results for the business. Also, the important ethical and social issues do not all lie at the start of the path, for the road is partly travelled already and the way back is cut off. Rather, they are found along the way, and relate to the appropriate responses that can be made to the process of automation. Only a few will be considered here.

Who is Responsible For Retraining?

It was remarked in the last section that relatively more of the future workers may be professionals, taking charge of their own education and training and contracting their services. Yet this route cannot be taken by everyone in the present-day work force. The typical assembly line or factory workers facing job-threatening automation will need considerable education and/or retraining to qualify for any new job, much less to take charge of their own destinies. Faced with a choice between unemployment and an arduous re-education, many will slide onto the welfare rolls, not as an active choice but as a passive one, for nothing in their background convinces them of the value of the harder path.

What is the ethical obligation of the other parties, including government and employers, to the large numbers of workers who are thus displaced? Surely the ethical imperative to assist others to be whole persons implies at least an offer to do the necessary retraining to allow re-employment. The employer may prefer, in consideration of the bottom-line profit, to simply terminate an unneeded worker.

189

Page 190: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

However, the months and years of employment have created a mutual bond and obligation (a social contract) that cannot exist between owner and machine but that always does between employer and employee. The employer who breaks this bond and discards the worker like a worn-out part creates bitterness and resentment that are certain to cost the broader society far more than job-retraining would have. The implicit social contract that the employer has with society as a whole binds both to act responsibly. Both therefore have an obligation to the person whose job has been automated to help make reasonable alternatives possible, or both will suffer the consequences of exaggerated class structure and broad social unrest (a pragmatic consideration). Government also has a responsibility to promote social stability, if for no other reason than (utilitarian) survival of the state itself.

The difficulty is that such responsibilities cannot easily be seen by employers, for they do not benefit the immediate bottom line, and they are hard to put into law. Some companies are too small or too unprofitable to afford such education. Yet unless retraining schemes are universal, a firm that does act responsibly in this way may become uncompetitive if others in their industry ignore those same responsibilities. Since life spans will probably increase in the future (see Chapter 7) and national economies will continue to change rapidly, the typical employee may need to retrain many times over a working lifetime. This projection also argues for a universal job retraining scheme, one in which employers, government, workers, and unions all participate.

A possible solution would be a comprehensive savings/insurance plan into which all parties pay--something similar to present-day pension and unemployment compensation schemes. If a job is automated, the employer could be required to increase payments to the plan for a period of time. On the other hand, after a certain number of years service, a worker ought to be able to take voluntary retraining at no additional cost, much as one might now take early retirement. Or, perhaps industry could learn from the sabbatical system used by academics to recharge their intellectual batteries every few years. After six years of service, a tenured university professor can normally apply for a one year leave at partial pay for the purpose of further study. Such plans have the advantage of recognizing the mutual obligation of all parties to retrain workers; they have the disadvantage of creating yet another payroll deduction and yet another administrative headache. Whatever it is called though, some such retraining insurance or educational pension plan may well be necessary in the light of events.

What About The Unretrainable?

Such retraining plans do not provide the whole answer, however, for there would remain a core of workers who would be unwilling or unable to accept retraining. Since the newer jobs require more technical skills than the jobs being obsoleted, they also demand a more educated work force. For those who have held menial jobs because they could not do anything else, a technical education may not, in many cases, be a prospect.

No society could afford to have such people simply remain unemployed and collecting welfare the remainder of their working lives, for large numbers of jobless

190

Page 191: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

people have always been a destabilizing force in the past, and there is no reason to suppose that such a situation would not also lead to widespread rioting and destruction in the future. That is, the "haves" cannot for long wall themselves off from and ignore the "have-nots," for their own way of life is also at stake.

The number of unskilled labouring jobs in traditional sectors will continue to decline; the challenge is to find new jobs for those to whom it is not practical to give professional or technical educations. Since such jobs can only be created in the service sector, it is easy to predict great increases in, say, tourist-industry employment. This may be enough, but if it is not, there could be pressure to hire personal servants, estate caretakers, cooks, and maids--even to put human crews on farms or construction projects that could be done safer, faster, cheaper, and better with robots. There will also be some pressure to make intelligence enhancement devices and drugs (see Chapter 6), but it seems unlikely that these could soon be made universally available and thus they alone will not solve the problem.

The utopian ideal of some science fiction portrays every future citizen as idly rich, dabbling in professional activities while the robots do all the work. This vision is unrealistic even at current population levels, let alone at the higher ones that will soon prevail. If the expansion of service and information sector employment fails to absorb the displaced industrial work force, considerable creativity in job creation may be necessary to avoid massive social unrest. This problem could be severe even in the developed countries, testing the skill of the most democratic, honest, and caring of governments working with relatively prosperous citizens. In underdeveloped countries, the potential for disaster is great. It is not difficult to imagine the rise to power during a time of civil unrest of a tyrant who decides to rid his nation once for all of "undesirable" elements, slaughtering his own people in a dreary repetition of Nazi-like themes of racial or religious purity. It would also not be difficult to imagine wars between the "have" and the "have-not" nations or civil unrest in the prosperous ones. Change exposes fragility in social contracts, and it can cause more. The trick is to keep the fragile from breaking.

In the very long run, increased prosperity historically results in a significant decline in birth rates, but on a worldwide scale, no such remedy can be hoped for until several more decades have passed.

Techniques of Automation

On a smaller scale, the methods chosen for introducing automation to a workplace, or for implementing any new system, can have a considerable effect on the morale and the jobs of the workers. The most common strategies are:

o Cold Turkey On the day assigned for the changeover to the new system, the old methods cease and the new replace them at once. Depending on the employer, this could involve either an extensive training program ahead of time, so that all the employees are ready to take up their new responsibilities, or a wholesale replacement of personnel. The latter approach is fraught with peril, not only for the workers displaced but also for the

191

Page 192: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

employer, who may find while awaiting the day of unemployment that employees do very little work or even engage in sabotage. Extensive retraining is also not without its difficulties, for even if the workers are able to take part in the actual planning of the new system, there are bound to be many errors in the period following the change. There may still be the problem of disgruntled workers, because automation is usually undertaken to achieve personnel efficiencies, and this implies that there will eventually be fewer workers. Moreover, as many organizations have discovered after such a change, few new products are either what they were advertised to be or are bug free, and most existing data sets have corruptions or anomalies that are revealed only in the changeover. In general, this is the worst possible way to introduce an automation or a new system. o Phased Here, the change to a new system is made gradually, with some parts being operated in the old way while some are switched to the new. This method has the advantages of being less abrupt and disruptive and may be less error prone than the cold turkey changeover. However, there are inherent inefficiencies involved in partial automations or introductions, and the employer who does things this way must be prepared to wait until some time after the completion of the process to realize the expected gains. Indeed, since parts of the enterprise are operating under one system and parts under another, there may be some losses, for additional employees may be required during the changeover. o Parallel This is the most costly of the three methods of implementing a new system. It involves running both the old and the new side-by-side for a period of time, comparing the results, and working out the bugs in the new through experience. In most manufacturing systems, the parallel method is not practical, and one of the first two methods must instead be chosen. However, in accounting systems, or student or employee record systems where great care must be taken to ensure the accuracy of the results at all times, it is unwise to place any trust in a new system until its results have been carefully compared to those of the old over a period of time. While such caution may be necessary in some cases, it may also imply the use of parallel staffs to operate the two systems. If the new staff is intended to replace the old, there will be great tensions; the old employees cannot be expected to work in the employer's interest during this time, for their energies will be put into finding new positions. If, on the other hand, the staff operating the new system is temporary and its other function is to train existing personnel in the new techniques, the atmosphere in the workplace may be better, though there may still be those whose jobs have been lost, and they are certain to resent the others. In general, parallel implementation, done properly, is the safest method.

Thus, the method chosen for automation can have a profound effect on the workplace. In the industrial age, the perception on the part of many employers was that the workplace belonged to them and they could do as they pleased with it, without regard to the effect on the workers. The perception on the part of many workers in the industrial age was that employers tended to exploit them, so they banded together in unions to create a power base of their own and to force changes in working conditions. The very idea of the information age, however, carries with it the assumption that workers will not only be fully informed about proposed changes but also that they as professionals will more often be in control of their own

192

Page 193: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

workplace. It will be they who will design and implement changes, for they will be the company. They will be less likely to be in opposition to the shareholders, as represented by the board of directors and officers, for they too will be shareholders and operators. In such circumstances, the problems associated with automation will not disappear, but the perception of them will, for change will not be something imposed from above; instead, it will be a result of the informed collaboration of professionals. Of course, conflict in the workplace will not be eliminated altogether by such changes; it will merely shift to other focal points.

Why Automate?

Some of the considerations mentioned thus far sometimes lead to a questioning of certain basic assumptions most forecasters make--that automation is both desirable and inevitable. Perhaps it is neither, or only one, and not the other. Both benefits and problems are easily seen when considering the process in an abstract way. For the people directly involved, though, such dispassionate considerations may be impossible. Where automation is possible and does bring economic benefits, it will surely be done, whatever the other consequences (unless constrained by some higher authority). Perhaps it will be necessary to require that such consequences be examined in each case and specific provision made for displaced workers before proceeding. It may even be that most automations will proceed slowly enough that no serious large-scale problems develop, though that would not release individual employers from their obligations to workers.

It may also be that there are other solutions to the displacement problem that use yet-to-be-deployed technologies, and some of these possibilities will be examined in later chapters. It is clear that this second industrial revolution (automation) can no more proceed without social consequences than did the first, and that the choices involved in dealing with such problems are to a great extent ethical in nature.

5.5 Other Industrial Futures Automation is not the only influence upon the industries of the future, even

though it is the major one that can now be measured because it is well underway. There are two other technological developments that may eventually play important roles, but both are in the very earliest stages, so detailed comments on their long-term effects are highly speculative.

Space--A Third Industrial Revolution?

On first consideration, it might seem unlikely that much manufacturing will ever be done off this planet, because of the great expense and logistical difficulties. However, there are products that may be worth the trouble. For instance, certain alloys are very difficult to mix homogeneously within Earth's gravitational field. The more massive constituents either form into globules or collect on one side of the molten mix, preventing the desired alloy from forming when the metals are re-solidified. Such mixtures may also have strength-robbing air bubbles because the

193

Page 194: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

metals do not completely lose all their gas during solidification. These problems do not occur in the zero gravity and vacuum of space, and there may well be alloys that are sufficiently valuable, say, for microelectronics or jewelry, to be worth manufacturing in Earth orbit.

Indeed, orbital environments are probably the best place to make alloys from which to build the space factories and habitats themselves, for the desired materials will have properties utterly unlike those required by Earthbound construction. Down here, a large building must support its own weight, and this is the first consideration in erecting its framework. In space, structural strength need only hold a building together against rotational forces; the materials need to combine strength with low mass, for they need not hold anything "up." Alloys that can do this and continue to perform well in a space environment are likely to be those made in the same environment.

There are obstacles, of course, to any such construction on a large scale. The main one is the expense and difficulty of supplying raw materials from the Earth below. However, once such manufacturing reached a certain scale, it could become economical to mine raw materials in the asteroid belt or on the moon. Transportation to Earth orbit from either location would be time consuming but relatively inexpensive. Or, manufacturing facilities could be located on the moon itself, where the vacuum is nearly as good as in orbit and gravity is only one-sixth that of Earth.

It is not clear whether the optimistic projections some make (of large numbers of people living in orbital habitat) are well founded though, even if substantial manufacturing were transferred there. After all, if Earth-based factories (and research or military establishments) would need few workers, the same would apply to those in space. For large communities to be built there, some other economic justification would have to be found, and it is not yet known what this could be.

Other substances whose manufacture might be easier in space include various chemicals, particularly pharmaceuticals. For very fine work involving precise reaction conditions and requiring fast and uniform mixing, zero gravity may be ideal. For example, if it turned out that a cure for some fatal disease could best be made in orbit, it surely would be.

Such work, however practical it may turn out to be in the long run, is still very experimental. Only when it becomes clear to entrepreneurs that there is money to be made by commercializing space will they rush to construct orbiting factories. One way to encourage this would be for the U.S. government to allow private companies to bid for the delivery of materials to Earth orbit, for such delivery can certainly be done for a much lower cost than it is at present. On the whole however, suggestions that a move of industry off planet will constitute a third industrial revolution (already underway) may be somewhat premature. Indeed, tourism might be a stronger motivation to make money from space than is manufacturing.

Nanotechnology and Manufacturing

194

Page 195: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

At the opposite end of the size scale from large space factories are the microscopic technologies of the silicon chip and the even smaller molecular-scale technologies. It is already possible to etch very small electronic features on glass, but even these are still hundreds of atoms wide. Yet living cells contain much smaller protein factories and assemblers that are capable of working atom by atom to build very specific molecules. It is, therefore, easy to wonder whether such assemblers can be made to order, like any machine, and directed to build the desired molecules by a chemist, engineer, or geneticist.

Eric Drexler (Engines of Creation) uses the term "nanotechnology" for work of this kind and observes that some success in the engineering of proteins has already been achieved. He sees the first generation of nanomachines as programmable and able to work like cellular organelles to build molecules into artifacts according to patterns coded into some auxiliary molecule acting like a "memory" enzyme. He terms such machines general purpose assemblers, for they could build a variety of molecules, not just proteins. In particular, they could make more robust, much smaller, and more specialized assemblers that could operate on atoms rather than on molecules.

These specialized assemblers would first have to build many more copies of themselves, or the quantity of the intended end product would not amount to much. Once this step was complete, they could in theory manufacture any amount of the target substance out of its atomic constituents--from houses to hot dogs to electronic circuits only one or two atoms wide. For example, carbon atoms could be laid down in the correct lattice to make diamond fibres that would give, say, engine parts great strength. Drexler envisions nanomachines that could even build entire rocket engines or computers in a fluid environment containing the raw elemental materials. Other potential nanotechnologies will be mentioned in later chapters.

The potential for large-scale manufacturing by such methods is difficult to assess. While it is true that only a few breakthroughs may be necessary to start on this route, it is not clear that nanomachines will necessarily be better or more efficient for large-scale work than ordinary machines. Assuming that they are developed, it seems more likely that such assemblers will be used principally for very fine work on speciality molecules and in chemical, genetic, and biological applications than on the making of consumer goods. At least, this is likely to be the case for some time until the technology matures.

However radical the changes that nanotechnology might bring therefore, they may not represent another industrial revolution but have their impact on society in other ways that are less direct. Some of these will also be touched upon in later Chapters.

5.6 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

What is called here the second industrial revolution is the process of eliminating human workers and machine operators from the industrial scene by

195

Page 196: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

building and deploying devices that are sufficiently general purpose and programmable to operate with little or no human supervision.

The advantages of robotized manufacture are considerable, ranging from ultra-high reliability to lower operating costs, and the ability to redirect assembly lines without either re-tooling or retraining. Commercial advantages include higher quality goods at lower cost in greater variety and the ability to manufacture to individual orders.

The problems generated by the use of robots centre on large-scale displacement of the existing work force. Retraining and replacement are necessary in order to keep unemployment from rising to disruptive levels. Whether concurrent economic changes will be rapid enough to absorb the released workers is not yet known. Certainly, such problems generate ethical issues for those directly involved, as well as for the broader society.

Other factors that may influence future industry are space-based manufacturing and nanotechnology. While both seem poised for near-term breakthroughs, it may be some time before either has a large-scale influence.

Discussion Questions

1. Desk jobs tend to be sedentary, having adverse effects upon general health, increasing the probability of heart disease, hypertension, and obesity. Discuss probable effects on general health of a large increase in the percentage of the population employed at desk jobs.

2. Discuss the probable effects on farming of the second industrial revolution.3. Defend this thesis: The second industrial revolution will decrease the

percentage of the population living in large cities.4. Now defend the opposite position; use "increase" rather than "decrease."5. The optimistic view is that despite robotization, underdeveloped countries

will catch up to developed nations. Write the most pessimistic scenario and defend it as more realistic.

6. You are the owner of a small snowmobile factory in Quebec that employs about 100 people and is in fact the major employer in your town. These people have nearly all worked for you for more than ten years and are completely dependent on these jobs. You have just learned that your major competitor is about to robotize its factory and will be able to sell snowmobiles for half your retail price. You may either follow suit, laying off 75 employees, or see your business go bankrupt in a year, costing everyone's job. What should you do?

7. What is the likelihood (or unlikelihood) that a "mad engineer" could develop and build an army of robots to conquer the earth? Answer in practical, well-reasoned and well-justified terms, please.

8. In the previous chapter, concern was expressed about the balance between information availability and privacy. The reduced need for people to congregate for work also cuts down on social interaction and promotes individualism. Discuss the advantages and disadvantages of this aspect of automation.

196

Page 197: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

9. Many believe that people have traditionally found self-worth in their jobs. How will they do this if most people are essentially self-employed, or not employed at all?

10. What effect will there be on pollution in a more highly automated society?11. In the text, a retraining insurance scheme was suggested. Flesh out this

idea to a detailed proposal, complete with appropriate premiums for two or three industries.

12. Attack the suggested retraining scheme and show why it cannot work. Then find another solution for the same problem and show why it is superior economically and/or ethically.

13. Refer to situations like that in question 6. Now discuss carefully the ethical issues involved in job displacement for the worker, employer, and for government.

14. Make a case for transferring all manufacturing off the Earth's surface. What ethical issues are involved? Deal with them in your discussion.

15. Research the "mass driver"--a device for removing raw materials from the Moon to Earth orbit--and discuss its operation and economics in the light of the level of space manufacturing activity you think is likely.

16. Research the arguments for building large-scale habitats in space. Now argue for or against such projects in detail. Address specifically the oft-raised objection that it is unethical to embark on such projects while there are still people who are hungry and in poverty.

17. Write a report summarizing the major potential applications of nanotechnology. How likely do you think each is, and why? What ethical issues need to be addressed?

18. Research the extent to which transportation is now automated. Consider railways and airlines and describe their attempts to automate traffic. Now, propose a way to automate automobile and truck traffic, or argue convincingly that this task is impractical.

19. Suppose that people transport via commuter railways, aeroplanes, and possibly cars could be automated so that no human pilots or drivers were necessary. Ought such technology be implemented if it became available? Why or why not?

20. Re-read the quotation from Stein in section 5.3 on the woman who teaches from her own home. Now list the assumptions about the future society, its politics, and its social norms that Stein makes. Are these assumptions reasonable?

21. Argue for or against (economic, political and ethical grounds) Stein's specific assumption that teaching children from the home via the Metalibrary is such a good idea that it will become commonplace.

22. An industrial robot is being used to move parts from a tray to an assembly line. It is enclosed in a security fence. A technician turns the robot off and enters the fenced area to effect repairs on the assembly line. While she is there, another worker (who does not see her because of the fence) re-activates the robot which moves up against the technician, trapping her against a piece of machinery and crushing her to death. Discuss the degrees of liability here. How much attaches to (1) the technician herself for not shutting off the power at the breaker box and for failing to post the work site, (2) the co-worker who turned the robot back on, (3) the

197

Page 198: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

owner of the plant, (4) the builder of the robot, (5) the builder of the fence--intended for protection, but instrumental in the death, (6) society as a whole for not somehow preventing the accident.

Bibliography

Asimov, Isaac and Frenkel, Karen A. Robots--Machines in Man's Image. New York: Harmony, 1985

Ballard, Edward Goodwin. Man and Technology--Toward the Measurement of a Culture. Pittsburgh: Duquense University Press, 1978.

Bell, David A. Employment in the Age of Drastic Change--The Future With Robots. Turnbridge Wells, U.K.: Abacus Press, 1984

Blaumer, Robert. Alienation and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964

Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press, 1986.Drexler, K. Eric, and Peterson, Chris. Nanotechnology. Analog, (Mid-December,

1987): 48-60.Hall, Ernest L. Robotics--A User-Friendly Introduction. New York: CBS

Publishing, 1985Hunt, V. Daniel. Smart Robots--A Handbook of Intelligent Robotic Systems.

New York: Chapman and Hall, 1985Jenkins, Clive, and Sherman, Barrie. The Collapse of Work. London: Eyre

Methuen Ltd., 1979.Leach, Donald, and Wagstaff, Howard. Future Employment and Technological

Change. London: Kog and Page, 1986.Menzies, Heather. Women and the Chip. Montreal: The Institute for Research

on Public Policy, 1984.Naisbitt, John, and Aburdene, Patricia. Re-inventing the Corporation. New

York: Warner, 1985.Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner, 1984.Peccei, Aurelio. One Hundred Pages for the Future. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon,

1981.Roszak, Theodore. The Cult of Information. New York; Random House, 1986Rowe, Christopher. People and Chips--The Human Implications of Information

Technology. London: Paradigm, 1986Sherman, Barrie. The New Revolution ---The Impact of Computers on Society.

New York: Wiley, 1985.

Chapter 6The Intelligence Revolution

198

Page 199: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Seminar - "What is Intelligence?" 6.1 Building Thinking Machines 6.2 Simulating Human Intelligence 6.3 Augmenting Human Intelligence 6.4 Issues in Artificial Intelligence 6.5 Summary and Further Discussion

6.1 Building Thinking Machines Can a machine ever be regarded as intelligent? British mathematician and

theoretical computer scientist, Alan Turing, proposed in 1950 what he called the "imitation test." The person performing the test sits in a room that has two computer terminals at which questions can be typed. One is connected to a room where a human responds to the questions, and the other has a computer generating the responses. The tester engages in a lengthy conversation with the two concerning any topic, such as the weather, sports, politics, mathematics, and so on, and then decides which responder is the human and which the computer.

Turing proposed that one may regard the computer as intelligent when it was no longer possible to distinguish between the two any more reliably than by guessing--that is, when the tester guessed correctly which respondent was human only 50 percent of the time. This is now known as "Turing's test" and is commonly regarded as fulfilling every practical need for the verification of a machine as intelligent in the human pattern. Consider a fragment such as:

Question Are you able to tell a lie?Answer Yes, I am.Question Are you self-aware?Answer But, of course. Question Do you have a soul?Answer Please explain what is a soul?

Such an exchange would not in itself be enough to settle the issue, for these are obvious questions for a programmer to anticipate and make provisions for. At the very least, a machine would have not only to claim self-consciousness but also to defend the claim capably in order to pass the Turing test. At this point there is no device that can come close to approximating human behaviour this well. Whether it will ever be possible is a question open to argument--one that some suggest can only be settled by the machines, acting on their own behalf. While the production of a machine that can behave in a way indistinguishable from a human (social intelligence) is regarded by some as the ultimate goal of research in this field, there are also other more practical and more immediate goals.

The most important of these shorter term projects have to do with knowledge-based machines, which carry out tasks using processes that in some ways could be described as human thinking, but that are so far also profoundly different. A machine whose purpose is the analysis of knowledge is far easier to build than one that could pass Turing's test. There are four kinds of tasks that current machines

199

Page 200: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

are commonly programmed for: simulations, expert tasks, inference tasks, and design tasks.

Simulations

One of the most popular computer games is a program to simulate the controls of an aircraft. The player can practice flying and landing at various airports under safe conditions, where a crash signifies only the end of the game, not the end of the pilot's life. The aircraft industry has long had specialized machines for this purpose, and with the help of computers, these are becoming more realistic. Some occupy an entire room and come complete with a cabin at the end of a long rotating arm capable of both motion and acceleration. No matter how elaborate they are, such simulators are cheaper and safer than employing a genuine aeroplane in the same exercises.

Simulations are also used in the design of expensive components or systems. Once again, the aircraft industry is an important user of such devices and programs. For example, it is now possible to run a graphical simulation of a wind tunnel and picture the stresses on an airframe using a computer. Expensive though such machines are, they are cheaper than building the wind tunnel itself, and far less expensive than testing a prototype of the plane.

Medical schools have found it difficult to obtain cadavers for students to practice surgical technique. Artificial cadavers connected to a computerized analyser can allow a safe practice of many types of operations, and provide a detailed summary for the instructor afterwards. The military also uses war games or simulations to train personnel in order to avoid unnecessary risk to human lives.

Indeed, wherever the cost in money or lives of doing a test of technique or machinery is very great, simulations can be used to reduce the risk. The goal is to approach realism as closely as possible, without subjecting the learners to any real risk except those of the failures necessary to learn.

Expert Tasks

Perhaps the best-known and most successful examples of computers performing expert tasks are in the field of medical diagnosis. There have been several programs, including the ones known as CADUCEUS, CASNET and MYCIN, that have performed at the level of human diagnosticians. The idea behind such systems is to create a very large data base of diseases and their symptoms together with probabilities that the two will be associated, and the suggested treatments together with their success rates, side effects and contra-indications.

Such a program uses a search scheme to take a list of symptoms provided by a doctor and suggest tests that can be performed to narrow down the possible causes. Once the results of a series of tests have also been entered, a probable diagnosis is made and treatment suggested. At each stage of the testing regimen, the medical practitioner is given a list of the possible diagnoses still "in the running" together with the probability that each is the correct one. During treatment, the

200

Page 201: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

program can be updated with patient responses and provide expert assistance with drug dosages and alternate treatments.

Similar software is available in other fields, including the law, metals and minerals prospecting, and chemistry. It is from the base of such knowledge devices that hypertext and ultimately Metalibrary systems are gradually growing.

Logical and Inference Tasks

Although inference tasks overlap the expert tasks and will one day merge with them, these are somewhat different in concept. Here, the major data base on which the tasks operate is not so much a pool of facts but a history of the success or failure of previous decisions made by the system. Moreover, the program is designed not so much for the analysis of data as it is to follow a collection of rules.

Consider, for example, a program designed to play chess. There are two kinds of rules that must be made available to the program. The first are the rules of the game, wherein the program is instructed how to move the board pieces legally. The second group consists of a set of rules of thumb, which are also called heuristics. These are collections of general ideas about the overall strategies that work best at various stages of the game. Standard opening sequences, together with such ideas as controlling the centre of the board and when to trade pieces for advantage, are all among the chess heuristics. A set of sample games completes the system, and this collection is added to by the machine as it plays.

The chess program uses the board rules, the heuristics, and the history, together with brute force computational methods that can examine tens of thousands of combinations that may arise from any of the possible legal moves at a given time. The actual move made by the program is based on what generates the best possibilities two, three or even ten moves ahead. A human chess player does not work in this fashion, but employs a broader and subtler array of heuristics for making such decisions. Even the masters of the game do not try to envision all the possibilities more than a couple of moves ahead of the current position, but play for strategic advantage based on experience.

Even though chess playing machines are now capable of generating games that can defeat a world champion, the type of machine logic used here is very low level. It is based entirely on fast computational ability, and does not even approximate human thinking. Thus, it does not have human intelligence, even though it can achieve some of the same results.

The approach taken by other programs designed to simulate intelligence, such as EURISKU, developed at Stanford, is rather different from the chess-playing ones. It relies more on heuristics and less computational speed and is capable of developing logical lines of analysis, suggesting new heuristics and rating these with other heuristics. It can also develop competing heuristics, and remove defective or parasitic ones. EURISKO has been used to solve problems in computer programming, mathematics, games, circuit design and various engineering applications.

This approach may have great potential, for the ability to devise and test competing models of the universe being studied and to make logical inferences

201

Page 202: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

based on both data and decision history are both essential to anything that will be called artificial intelligence. Such an approach is also a better simulation of human thinking than is the purely computational, even though it too depends for its success on computational ability.

Design Tasks

These also overlap the other two, but are important enough to discuss separately. Drawing on a knowledge base and sometimes using rules for analysis and inference, computers are already being used to assist in the design of both manufactured products and of the machines to make them. They are increasingly being employed to develop new designs for more complicated devices such as three-dimensional integrated circuits. It is a short step from this point to the successful design of more powerful computers using software alone. Better designing software could then be designed by a computer for installation in the next machine, and the history of the first designer downloaded as the initial data base for the second. Thus, computers could eventually design their successors' hardware and software, and each machine in the sequence would be smaller, faster, and a better designer. In theory, the process could be continued with more intricate machines being built in this fashion until the processing power and memory reached and exceeded that of the human brain. Numerous such elaborate processors, working in parallel would be required to control all the functions of the Metalibrary. One task of an automated designer will be to monitor the available computer technology and continue the process in order to make improvements to its own capabilities. Perhaps with some robotic help, these improvements could be automatic, achieved without human intervention.

At some point along this trail, enough will also become known about the chemical construction of large molecules to design new ones, and these new molecules might in turn be programmed to design others. Some researchers have suggested that people may one day be able to employ virus-sized machines (i.e., another form of nanotechnology) for such tasks as studying brain functions neuron by neuron, locating and repairing arteries blocked by strokes, and eliminating specific toxins, bacteria and viruses from the body. AIDS, herpes, and other retroviruses that go dormant and hide inside certain cells for extended periods might be eliminated from the body by such means.

Current Research

Japan for a time made artificial intelligence research (AI) a national priority in an effort to secure a lead in computer technology for so-called fifth-generation machines. Similar work has also been undertaken at various universities in North American and Europe. This research has been given high priority by funding

202

Page 203: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

agencies of governments, the military and private foundations. As a result, those making research commitments in areas relating to AI have little difficulty securing monetary support.

Problems of language translation have also provided one of the strongest motivations for the Japanese involvement with these projects, for one of their goals has been machines that can translate to and from Japanese and other languages in both spoken and written form. At first, it was thought that only a machine that could do this would certainly be worthy of the label "fifth-generation." However, such problems have a variety of full and partial solutions in software alone. Such programs will be employed by telephone companies to allow verbal and written communication between speakers of different languages, and for the deaf or blind. They will also be used by cable companies to convert the closed-captions transmitted with their programs into the language of the viewer's choice. Whether later systems in this category will be thought of as artificially intelligent in any new sense of the term remains to be seen.

On the hardware scene, attention is focusing upon parallel processing, in an effort to break the von Neumann bottleneck associated with the traditional sequential processing. Machines that rely on a central processing unit must execute instructions from a stored program one at a time in sequence--a technique suggested by the mathematician John von Neumann in the 1940s. Even at the limits of today's fastest experimental processors, such machines are limited to speeds under a billion instructions per second, or BIPS. If problems can be broken down into many parts for processing, each portion being handled simultaneously by a different processor (i.e., parallel processing), the overall rate can go up many orders of magnitude. Supposing that, say, a PowerPC chip runs at 1 BIPS by itself; a computer with 10,000 of these working simultaneously would execute 10,000 BIPS or 10 trillion instructions per second (TIPS). Even this machine would have only a small fraction of the power of a human brain, but if it were reduced to a single chip, and 10 of these were in turn paralleled, the resulting device would be up to 100 TIPS. The last figure may be close to that of the brain.

Of course, new hardware demands new types of software. Traditional AI work has been done in the programming languages known as LISP and PROLOG, but lately the Smalltalk and Prometheus notations have gained some credibility in this field. In order to work on a multiply paralleled machine, the language must be modular and have the ability to schedule its processing both sequentially and simultaneously. Notations such as Modula-2 (designed to replace Pascal) have this capability, and perhaps the new machines will initially be programmed in some common descendent of these current programming notations. Of course, devices that will be used extensively as design tools for other machines and to simulate intelligence must be capable of programming themselves, and of devising the languages in which to do this. Ultimately, it may not be necessary to have many human programmers or human-readable notations, for the machines (in theory) will be capable of translating voice or other requests into programs and then executing these without further human intervention.

As indicated, the ultimate goals of artificial intelligence research extend beyond computational and designs to the understanding and emulation of the

203

Page 204: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

behaviour of the human brain. There are two paths down which this research may lead, and these are examined in the next two sections. The first path, seen as an ultimate goal by some researchers, is probably the more difficult. The second path, a somewhat more short-term solution may be easier to accomplish.

Profile On ... Technology

Expert Systems

What is required to build an expert, or knowledge-based system?o A acknowledged human expert at performing the task must be available.o The performance of the human expert must be based on special knowledge

and the application of techniques.o The expert must be able to explain the special knowledge and techniques.o The rules used by the expert must each be capable of controlling decisions

for large data sets and combinations of situations.o The boundaries of the application in question must be clearly defined.o The use of the system must improve the performance of the expert.o The expert must remain available, if not as the system operator, then as the

consultant to the operator.

What situations are not good candidates for expert systems?o Those requiring the application of common sense.o Those involving open-ended questions.o Those with large numbers of special cases and subtleties (e.g., language

processing).o Those in which a belief system or world view is a factor in producing a

decision.o Those that involve the generation of new ideas from data, rather than the

application of existing ideas to data.

A few examples of early expert systems:Name Use DeveloperNOAH Robotics planning University College, Santa CruzMOLGEN Molecular genetics work Rand CorporationCADUCEUS Medical diagnostics University of PittsburghMYCIN, PUFF Medical diagnostics Stanford UniversityDENDRAL Chemical data analysis Stanford UniversityPROSPECTOR Geological data analysis SRIELAS Analysis of oil well logs AMOCOMACSYMA Symbolic mathematics MITSPERIL Earthquake damage Perdue UniversityIDT Computer fault diagnosis Stanford University/IBMCRITTER Digital circuit analysis Rutgers University

204

Page 205: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

EMYCIN, AGE Expert system construction Stanford UniversityROSIE Expert system construction Rand CorporationVISIONS Image processing University of MassachussettsBATTLE Weapons in battle National Research LabEURISKO Learning from experience Stanford UniversityRAYDEX Radiology assistant Rutgers UniversityTECH Naval Task force analysis Rand CorporationOP-PLANNER Mission planning Jet Propulsion LabSYM Circuit Design MIT

6.2 Simulating Human Intelligence Many researchers today believe that the totality of what it means to be

human will be known when they can fully describe the activity of the brain. Toward this end a great deal of work has been devoted. So far, it is known that nerve cells called neurons respond to electrochemical signals in the brain in a complex switching operation or neurotransmission taking place at a junction known as a synapse. The patterns for transmissions through synapses change through time, and these changes no doubt have something to do with learning and memory.

Some things are also known about the speed at which a synapse operates and the rate at which signals move through the brain. These turn out to be substantially slower than in electronic switches, by several orders of magnitude. Even though the mechanism by which all these take place is not clearly understood, the information that is available makes some researchers confident that the functions of the human brain can be duplicated in a smaller and faster electronic device. Note that it is not necessary to duplicate the human brain itself, only to understand how it works well enough to build a functional equivalent--that is, a machine that calculates and stores in a way capable of producing the same results.

If a functional equivalent of the human brain could be constructed, two things could be done with such a device. The first possibility is to program it or "teach" it so that it can perform a few simple tasks. Then it can act as an "intelligent" controller or designer capable of making decisions and acting upon them in a way that is the electronic equivalent of the fashion in which the human brain works.

It might eventually be possible to build an ambulatory body for this thinking machine and thus create the mobile robot of science fiction. This perfect servant/slave could be given instructions such as "take out the cat," "bathe the kids," and "go to the grocery store."

It would presumably be able to carry out such tasks without any further human intervention. Indeed, it should be possible to let the machine decide when the house or office routine dictates that something needs doing, and go ahead without asking, or being told. Whether it will ever be possible to discuss child rearing, philosophy, or one's emotions with such a machine is quite another matter.

The motivation to spend the enormous sums of money that would be required to develop such machines would have to be powerful indeed. While building the ideal butler, maid, secretary, lover, or factory worker might be interesting, it is not clear that machines are necessary for such tasks, or that they need either a human

205

Page 206: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

shape or the equivalent to a human brain. Perhaps such devices are needed in very hostile environments where humans could not go,--for instance, the ocean floor, space, the moon, underground, or a nuclear reactor core. To do crucial jobs that cannot be done otherwise, machines will be built. They need not look or act anything like a human being for such purposes, and it is uncertain that many robots ever will. Moreover, such devices will not be used at all in the home unless there are substantial benefits to cover the enormous cost.

There is a second, and perhaps even more ambitious potential use for a functional analog of the human brain, however. The most optimistic of AI researchers are confident that not only can such a machine be built, but that a human brain could eventually be scanned on a molecule-by-molecule basis and its activity duplicated in the artificial version. Thus, they believe the totality of the human's thinking would have been downloaded into the mechanical construct. Give the electronic brain a mechanical body to match and the result is hoped to be not just an intelligent robot, but a mechanical copy of the human being.

Since the duplicated human would now reside in a more easily repairable body, or in no body at all, and since backup copies could be made at any time, the body of flesh could supposedly be discarded when the downloading was complete. The net result: immortality would have been achieved in a mechanical form. A human would cease to be blood and bone and becomes a cyborg (part machine) or a fully machine intelligence--with electronic capabilities projected to be many times as great as those of the bodies they currently inhabit.

The end result of this line of research is supposed to be nothing less than the ultimate in man-made salvations from death--eternal life in a manufactured body and brain--not in heaven, but here on Earth. Not only that, but the ability to make backups means that a person really could be in two places at one time, and merge the memories afterward into a single copy. If backups were frequently made, even the fatal destruction of a single unit would cost no more than a few days out of one's life and experience.

Quite apart from any other ethical and moral problems that may come to mind, this goal raises an old conundrum, the answer to which may in part determine whether this is possible.

Is the mind more than the brain?

If on the one hand, the human mind and soul can be expressed unambiguously as the sum of the brain's electrical parts, then downloading its activities to a functional equivalent would transfer a copy of the personality from a "machine made of meat" to one made of electronic parts. This would be regarded by many as offering a final proof that the empirically verifiable material world is the sum total of all existence, that the spiritual and supernatural are fantasies, and that logical positivism is permanently triumphant. On the other hand, if such things as emotions, friendship, anger, fear, intuition, poetic appreciation, conscience, intentionality, self-awareness, and the ability to enquire about the existence of God cannot be expressed as sets of electro chemical impulses, this endeavour may well fail, for the mind is then more than the brain.

206

Page 207: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

These issues touch on the essence of what it means to be alive and what it means to be human. Thus, attempts to achieve practical immortality by such means are sure to touch many raw nerves. Those who oppose such research may say that there are some things that ought never to be tried. To those who support it, the potential prize is great enough to pursue at all cost. Furthermore, there is no stopping such work now that it has begun. To forbid such research and make the prohibition stick is impossible, as long as qualified researchers are not yet satisfied that the question has been answered one way or the other.

Even if such a transfer succeeded, questions would still remain. Would the downloaded person's thinking and memories really constitute the person, or is this a simulated person, and not a full duplicate of the original? Assuming there is a soul, perhaps it would depart when the flesh and blood body was discarded, and would not transfer along with the contents of the brain. The question of whether such a copy is fully human would still remain.

There is also the question of timing. As Grant Fjermedal (The Tomorrow Makers) notes (p. 5):

In the weeks and months that followed my stay at Carnegie-Mellon in February of 1985, I would be surprised and intrigued by how many researchers seemed to believe downloading would come to pass. The only point of disagreement was when -- certainly a big consideration to those still knocking around in mortal bodies. Although some of the researchers I spoke with at Carnegie-Melon, and later at MIT, Stanford, and in Japan thought that downloading was still generations away, there were others who believed we were actually so close to achieving robotic immortality that some of the researchers seemed to be driven by private passions never to die. And perhaps this explained the eagerness of Hans's young research assistants to work through the nights and weekends to further this quest for the life ever after.

Some regarded these developments as imminent two decades ago. Others believe it could be many years, if ever, before such questions need to be answered seriously, for research on the activity of the brain is moving very slowly, and it seems unlikely that it can be functionally duplicated soon, if ever. Indeed, the small progress made in the intervening years seems to argue this work may be at a dead end.

Biological enhancements to the human brain achieved by genetic manipulation or chemical means might obviate the necessity to go the mechanical route altogether. In the meantime, computer and communications research may take other turns, the products of which could also render the production of artificially intelligent brains unnecessary. On the other hand, startling new techniques have a way of appearing on the scene almost full-blown and with great rapidity. Predictions about this area of research and its potential applications have as much likelihood of being proven too conservative as too extravagant.

6.2 Simulating Human Intelligence

207

Page 208: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Many researchers today believe that the totality of what it means to be human will be known when they can fully describe the activity of the brain. Toward this end a great deal of work has been devoted. So far, it is known that nerve cells called neurons respond to electrochemical signals in the brain in a complex switching operation or neurotransmission taking place at a junction known as a synapse. The patterns for transmissions through synapses change through time, and these changes no doubt have something to do with learning and memory.

Some things are also known about the speed at which a synapse operates and the rate at which signals move through the brain. These turn out to be substantially slower than in electronic switches, by several orders of magnitude. Even though the mechanism by which all these take place is not clearly understood, the information that is available makes some researchers confident that the functions of the human brain can be duplicated in a smaller and faster electronic device. Note that it is not necessary to duplicate the human brain itself, only to understand how it works well enough to build a functional equivalent--that is, a machine that calculates and stores in a way capable of producing the same results.

If a functional equivalent of the human brain could be constructed, two things could be done with such a device. The first possibility is to program it or "teach" it so that it can perform a few simple tasks. Then it can act as an "intelligent" controller or designer capable of making decisions and acting upon them in a way that is the electronic equivalent of the fashion in which the human brain works.

It might eventually be possible to build an ambulatory body for this thinking machine and thus create the mobile robot of science fiction. This perfect servant/slave could be given instructions such as "take out the cat," "bathe the kids," and "go to the grocery store."

It would presumably be able to carry out such tasks without any further human intervention. Indeed, it should be possible to let the machine decide when the house or office routine dictates that something needs doing, and go ahead without asking, or being told. Whether it will ever be possible to discuss child rearing, philosophy, or one's emotions with such a machine is quite another matter.

The motivation to spend the enormous sums of money that would be required to develop such machines would have to be powerful indeed. While building the ideal butler, maid, secretary, lover, or factory worker might be interesting, it is not clear that machines are necessary for such tasks, or that they need either a human shape or the equivalent to a human brain. Perhaps such devices are needed in very hostile environments where humans could not go,--for instance, the ocean floor, space, the moon, underground, or a nuclear reactor core. To do crucial jobs that cannot be done otherwise, machines will be built. They need not look or act anything like a human being for such purposes, and it is uncertain that many robots ever will. Moreover, such devices will not be used at all in the home unless there are substantial benefits to cover the enormous cost.

There is a second, and perhaps even more ambitious potential use for a functional analog of the human brain, however. The most optimistic of AI researchers are confident that not only can such a machine be built, but that a human brain could eventually be scanned on a molecule-by-molecule basis and its activity duplicated in the artificial version. Thus, they believe the totality of the

208

Page 209: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

human's thinking would have been downloaded into the mechanical construct. Give the electronic brain a mechanical body to match and the result is hoped to be not just an intelligent robot, but a mechanical copy of the human being.

Since the duplicated human would now reside in a more easily repairable body, or in no body at all, and since backup copies could be made at any time, the body of flesh could supposedly be discarded when the downloading was complete. The net result: immortality would have been achieved in a mechanical form. A human would cease to be blood and bone and becomes a cyborg (part machine) or a fully machine intelligence--with electronic capabilities projected to be many times as great as those of the bodies they currently inhabit.

The end result of this line of research is supposed to be nothing less than the ultimate in man-made salvations from death--eternal life in a manufactured body and brain--not in heaven, but here on Earth. Not only that, but the ability to make backups means that a person really could be in two places at one time, and merge the memories afterward into a single copy. If backups were frequently made, even the fatal destruction of a single unit would cost no more than a few days out of one's life and experience.

Quite apart from any other ethical and moral problems that may come to mind, this goal raises an old conundrum, the answer to which may in part determine whether this is possible.

Is the mind more than the brain?

If on the one hand, the human mind and soul can be expressed unambiguously as the sum of the brain's electrical parts, then downloading its activities to a functional equivalent would transfer a copy of the personality from a "machine made of meat" to one made of electronic parts. This would be regarded by many as offering a final proof that the empirically verifiable material world is the sum total of all existence, that the spiritual and supernatural are fantasies, and that logical positivism is permanently triumphant. On the other hand, if such things as emotions, friendship, anger, fear, intuition, poetic appreciation, conscience, intentionality, self-awareness, and the ability to enquire about the existence of God cannot be expressed as sets of electro chemical impulses, this endeavour may well fail, for the mind is then more than the brain.

These issues touch on the essence of what it means to be alive and what it means to be human. Thus, attempts to achieve practical immortality by such means are sure to touch many raw nerves. Those who oppose such research may say that there are some things that ought never to be tried. To those who support it, the potential prize is great enough to pursue at all cost. Furthermore, there is no stopping such work now that it has begun. To forbid such research and make the prohibition stick is impossible, as long as qualified researchers are not yet satisfied that the question has been answered one way or the other.

Even if such a transfer succeeded, questions would still remain. Would the downloaded person's thinking and memories really constitute the person, or is this a simulated person, and not a full duplicate of the original? Assuming there is a soul, perhaps it would depart when the flesh and blood body was discarded, and would

209

Page 210: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not transfer along with the contents of the brain. The question of whether such a copy is fully human would still remain.

There is also the question of timing. As Grant Fjermedal (The Tomorrow Makers) notes (p. 5):

In the weeks and months that followed my stay at Carnegie-Mellon in February of 1985, I would be surprised and intrigued by how many researchers seemed to believe downloading would come to pass. The only point of disagreement was when -- certainly a big consideration to those still knocking around in mortal bodies. Although some of the researchers I spoke with at Carnegie-Melon, and later at MIT, Stanford, and in Japan thought that downloading was still generations away, there were others who believed we were actually so close to achieving robotic immortality that some of the researchers seemed to be driven by private passions never to die. And perhaps this explained the eagerness of Hans's young research assistants to work through the nights and weekends to further this quest for the life ever after.

Some regarded these developments as imminent two decades ago. Others believe it could be many years, if ever, before such questions need to be answered seriously, for research on the activity of the brain is moving very slowly, and it seems unlikely that it can be functionally duplicated soon, if ever. Indeed, the small progress made in the intervening years seems to argue this work may be at a dead end.

Biological enhancements to the human brain achieved by genetic manipulation or chemical means might obviate the necessity to go the mechanical route altogether. In the meantime, computer and communications research may take other turns, the products of which could also render the production of artificially intelligent brains unnecessary. On the other hand, startling new techniques have a way of appearing on the scene almost full-blown and with great rapidity. Predictions about this area of research and its potential applications have as much likelihood of being proven too conservative as too extravagant.

6.4 Issues in Artificial Intelligence At this point, it is not known what are the limits, if any, to the building of

artificially intelligent artifacts. Neither is it known whether these will be silicon based, carbon based, some combination of the two, or neither. Such artifacts may well turn out to be genetically modified living organisms, inorganic devices, or both. The issues raised in this chapter are more or less independent of such considerations, and would eventually surface regardless of the type of construction. Some are in the form of common objections to be considered and possibly answered; others are rather more speculative. Many are philosophical or even theological rather than social or strictly ethical. If the most enthusiastic projections of some in the AI community are correct, all these issues will have to be dealt with in this generation. Moreover, some issues will need to be addressed regardless of whether or not the artifacts are exact simulations of the human brain, whether or

210

Page 211: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not downloading succeeds, or whether the only "intelligence" involved is that which PIEA and Metalibrary devices seem to exhibit due to their current users.

Playing God?

One objection raised against AI work (as well as against genetic engineering) is that the researchers are "playing God." On the surface this is a comprehensive and definitive moral objection to such work. However, its meaning and validity are very difficult to analyse. This objection could be taken casually, to mean simply that those involved in the research are overstepping safe bounds and playing with things they ought not to. It may also be regarded as a gut feeling, an emotional response, or a desire for the world forever to remain the same. It may be a statement that the desired action is contrary to nature or God's laws and therefore to be forbidden.

It may be intended and taken literally. If so, then on face value it appears to be a claim of acquaintance with God's agenda and to imply that the research in question is known to usurp rights and privileges God reserves for Himself. Similar assumptions are found in such arguments as: "if God had meant us to fly, we would have wings." One could reply that if God is the all-knowing one, this implies that quests for knowledge about creation are, in general, good because they are searches for something that is of God.

"But," the response could be "it is not knowledge at stake, but its application. Only God has the right to make intelligent beings." The first part of this statement is one few people would argue with, for whatever "good" and "evil" are defined to be, their meaning takes substance in the effects of applications, not in theory alone, even when theory seems to lead to action rather directly. However, the last part of the statement is a rather large presumption, for even if God alone has the power to create ex nihilo, it does not follow that human beings cannot create at all. One could even suggest that if human beings are created "in God's image," this would seem to imply the ability to create in a similar (if not identical) manner.

Those who make this objection have two practical obstacles to overcome. The first is to demonstrate that they do have the credentials to speak for God in such matters, and the second is to devise an effective means of preventing the research they propose to forbid. There does not, at this point, seem to be a way to do either. First, there seems little evidence to support the idea of modern divine appointments to prophetic office. Second, the control of research on an international scale is effectively impossible. Perhaps it is more practical to control the products that might emerge from such work (by taxation?) than attempt to ban it and thereby drive it into secrecy.

There may still be something to the objection that AI researchers are "playing God," for pronouncements made in the name of science can occasionally have a ring of divine revelation to them. Even so, this is a comment on the motivations of the people involved, and not directly on the legitimacy of the work. On the other hand, perhaps the objectors themselves might be accused of "playing God" if they cannot substantiate their claim to know the mind of God. It is possible that the spokesmen/objectors for God may be judging the motivations of researchers by their perceptions of the work in question. That is, the objection might focus upon

211

Page 212: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

what the objector supposes the products of the AI work are to be used for. However, it is not clear how applications that are only potential or theoretical (or even imagined) can invalidate the AI research itself.

The objection "playing God" may be well-taken if the goal of AI researchers is to become immortal or to become "like gods." Even such an avowed goal would not validate or invalidate all AI work, for there may well be other motivations and applications. However, these possibilities do suggest other questions about motivations and potential applications. Would the benefits of AI be confined to the creators and controllers, who would indeed become "gods" and "lords" over the rest of humanity? Or, would they be shared with all? History would seem to suggest that the former outcome is more likely than the latter, and therefore to urge a considerable degree of caution when it comes to the development and deployment of any new technology.

Perhaps the value-laden "playing God" objection is instructive, for if nothing else, it forces reflection once again on the interaction of motivation, technique, society, and history. It weakens the classical argument that pure knowledge and technique are morally neutral, for it illustrates that both have a context from which they cannot be extracted pure and value free.

What Does Success in AI Mean?

There are two kinds of questions to consider here. The first has to do with knowing how to apply the word "intelligent" to an artifact, whether organic or inorganic. For example, one would not consider that a motor-driven slide rule or calculator is intelligent. As previously remarked, even a device that passes Turing's test could not thereby be considered "human." Even if a machine could duplicate the results of human thinking exactly, it is not necessarily "intelligent" in the same way as a human being, because the process by which the results are obtained is different. For example, the ability to manipulate objects or symbols does not imply that the manipulator understands what they are. One does not regard a language translator that works by substituting one set of symbols for another set as an understander or speaker of--much less a scholar in--either of the languages involved. It is simply a deterministic machine; it comprehends nothing. Neither is it clear that a mechanical device can have a dynamic memory, be able to learn or forget, be able to think associatively rather than strictly linearly or be able to learn by making mistakes.

In other words, there is an element in the processing of data to a form that can be called information that cannot (yet?) be ignored. The assigning of meaning to data is a uniquely human activity, and it may turn out to have been presumptuous to assume that anything analogous to this thing called "understanding," "knowing" or "perceiving" can be programmed into an artifact.

One could even question the appropriateness of using cognitive terminology, such as "intelligence," to refer in any way to manufactured things. After all, to do so seems to assume that such machines are already intelligent, or surely will become so, when the outcome is still very doubtful, to say the least. For instance, it is already common to speak of the "memory" of a computer, but this is no more

212

Page 213: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

analogous to human memory than is a printed page in a book, even though there may be a limited amount of shared functionality. Because machine manipulation of symbols does not require or imply human-like understanding in the machine, it may well be inappropriate to use the word "know" in connection with anything that it contains or does. On the other hand, if the duplication of functionality is the only criterion for calling a machine "intelligent," the use of this word may indeed someday (already?) be appropriate. Perhaps the issue hinges on whether or not logic and empiricism are adequate to express "knowing." If they are adequate, then a similar logic can surely be applied to the a "thinking" artifact that is capable of "knowing" in every way equivalent to humankind. If they are not adequate, it may always be necessary to have one word for human intelligence and another for the manufactured kind.

It should also be noted that success in AI, however measured, does not bear on questions of ultimate origins or meaning for the human race. The great expenditure of time, money, energy and planning needed to build artificially intelligent artifacts will not somehow prove that man's existence is itself an accident. Indeed, though it may suggest the opposite--that humanity too was planned--it will not prove that either. Neither will it provide any new meaning to human life or destiny, however great an achievement it may be. Knowledge about how the universe works, even when taken to the point of building something never before made, does not answer questions of ultimate origins or meaning. From an ethical point of view, it is far more important to consider the uses and effects of the proposed devices as they relate to people than to imply from them fanciful castles of philosophical implication about the origin, purpose, and destiny of humankind.

Who Makes Decisions?

Under this heading come several questions without ready answers. The first concerns the decisions about whether AI devices ought to be made and how they should be used if ever they are finished. As in all major scientific/technological projects there is the question of funding. It is not clear at this point who should make money decisions for such research. At present, it is the national science research councils of various countries, and the board members of various foundations and corporations who decide which projects may go ahead. The public, and even their political representatives, have no direct input here, even though the implications for ordinary citizens could be very important.

Oddly enough, questions of appropriateness are seldom asked at the onset of actual research and development, and ordinary citizens are even less often consulted. That is, although all scientific and technological discoveries have consequences to society as a whole, the decisions to proceed are made by a very narrow group of specialists who do not, in general, have much training in either social theory or ethics. Although most scientists would not wish to involve what they would term "unqualified" people in such decisions, true democracy would seem to demand that those affected ought to have a voice in the process. In fact, since no technology is pure in itself and free from the context of motivations and social effects, all three of these, and not just the technology itself require careful and

213

Page 214: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

informed consideration before proceeding with research, and again prior to deployment.

Given the relatively narrow educations many specialists have often had in the past, they may in fact be among the least well qualified to assess the appropriateness of developing and using a proposed technique. It therefore seems necessary to reform both current funding practices and technological decision making, and also to restructure the educational system to produce better qualified decision makers among those who do work directly with technological development.

The second question concerns what artificially intelligent machines might be used for, assuming they are built. Their very nature suggests that they will make decisions or assist in making them. This raises the question of who ought to be making decisions for people, if not people themselves? If the AI devices are an extension of human intelligence and a decision making aid, this objection goes away. But if they are to be independent decision makers, there is a serious potential conflict. If such devices are capable of making autonomous decisions, then in what interests will they make them--the human, or their own? If such autonomy is ever achieved, there is no reason to suppose that these artifacts will be partners with humankind, or share any of the same interests or goals. It is therefore not clear that these ends of AI research are desirable. Those who speak in this context of designing the successor to mankind appear to be casually writing off the whole human race to extinction--hardly a helpful outcome to those extinguished.

What Will be the Nature of AI Devices?

The discussion above leads directly to questions about the attributes of AI devices and their relationship to humankind. Suppose for a moment that the most optimistic and generous assumptions turn out to be true, and truly autonomous AI artifacts were built that were cooperative, benign, and work in human interests. Would they be thought of as "alive"? If they were biological entities, that is they have carbon-based chemistry, the answer is probably, in some sense, "yes." But if they were to be silicon-based, or electrical and mechanical artifacts, then even if they had human-like attributes of "intelligence" so far as can be measured, the question returns. Should "living organisms" then be taken to include silicon-based ones? In either case, the matter can be taken a step further. Will such devices be self-aware? Some futurists are sure they will be, provided they have sufficient memory and computational complexity. Others are equally convinced otherwise. The only way to find out if this is possible is to actually achieve it; but by then the issue of whether the achievement is desirable would be rendered irrelevant.

Other questions centre on whether such entities would be regarded as subordinate to humans, or as equals. If the latter, at what point in their development would they be given the status of persons? For instance, if it were considered that an AI device were alive, and had some semi-human status, would turning off or destroying one be murder? Would an AI device be more human than a child in the mother's womb, or less? No ready answer exists to these questions, and they only become more complex if the thinking machine is housed in an ambulatory robot body, for then their qualities become even more human-like. Moreover, if AI

214

Page 215: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

researchers are ever able to download themselves into an artificial brain and hope in that state to be regarded as human, it may be difficult to withhold the same label from one of the same devices that has been programmed but lacks a human download. This subject is already the focus of controversy, for whatever the resolution, it touches upon what is the definition of a human being, and the extent to which that definition is to change.

It should be noted that the definition of a "person" in Western civilization has changed several times in the last century and a half, first to include women, then blacks and orientals, and more recently to exclude unborn children. Will it be changed again?

Rights of AI Devices

This brings the discussion to the heart of the matter, for if devices are to be made that are intelligent in a meaningful human fashion; if they are to share with mankind the essence of thinking humanly, must they not then be accorded the rights of a human being? Should they not have freedom of speech, the right to liberty, and the right to own property? If so, could they by virtue of superior computational ability capture ownership of the entire economy, all the stocks, bonds and properties, and place the original and slower humans entirely in their debt? There are other ways to dominate than by force.

What of the right to bear arms or, for that matter, to marry each other (or human beings) and to adopt or have offspring? Indeed, what about such artifacts as sexual partners with human beings? Futurist Frank Ogden, who goes under the name of Dr. Tomorrow, is fond of shocking his audiences with the notion of "live-in robot lovers"--an idea he presents as a technological fix for the problem of diseases such as AIDS. "If you own 'em, don't clone 'em or loan 'em." is one of his slogans.1

Given the amount of time and energy the average person spends on things sexual, it seems inevitable that various forms of technology will be applied to the satisfaction of sexual urges. While some will question these scenarios as patently unnatural and deviant, such objections are unlikely to make much impression, for these practices would merely be taking a place in the long line of ones for which similar unsuccessful protests have already been made. Indeed, the recent history of the Internet as it stands suggests that technologically-inspired and assisted sexual commerce will only expand.

Objections to new sexual practices are often made with a view to supporting the ideal of monogamous heterosexual marriage relationship as the sole focus of legitimate sexuality. It is not clear that this kind of relationship will be any harder to maintain in the future than it is now. In fact, it may be easier, for it provides a definitive answer to problems of sexually transmitted disease (STD). What is more, if AI artifacts do turn out to be so much more capable, they may be as much

215

Page 216: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

interested in cohabitation with humans as most humans would be with a grasshopper.

It should be emphasized at this point that these are not merely fanciful speculations; they are natural questions that arise out of following the logic of building human-like artificially intelligent artifacts. They lead the line of reasoning to its final set of questions.

Can Artificially Intelligent Devices be Moral Agents?

Any discussion of the potential human-like qualities of AI devices would be incomplete without inquiring whether such intelligence will be sufficient for them to be able to ask ethical questions and make moral decisions of their own. Human beings have always assumed that they were the only moral agents on earth, for it can readily be observed that plants and animals do not ordinarily appear to act out of such considerations.

Is it intelligence alone that confers the ability to ask questions about right and wrong and to act on the answers? This question could be answered whenever AI artifacts are first programmed. At one extreme, if "downloading" were to succeed, some would say that the answer would have to be "yes," contending that the human being had simply transferred her residence into the device. Others would counter that the device is an animated dead creature--a zombie--and accuse all participants of murder if the original human body were destroyed after an apparently successful transfer. The tape containing the recording of such a human brain scan also has a doubtful status. It would manifestly not even be alive, yet it would contain the pattern not to grow a human body--as does DNA--but to reconstitute the essence of humanness supposedly residing in an artifact. Would such a tape, if it could ever be made, also have to be regarded as a moral agent? (What difference is there between a running program in a computer, and a copy of one on a disk?)

Even though downloading is one of the express goals of the most optimistic of AI researchers, it is still highly speculative and there may be many more immediate goals with a greater likelihood of achievement. Some, however, lead to very similar questions. For example, suppose an AI device were programmed in such a way that it could make errors--not just those due to data problems, but to choose to ignore what the program indicates is the right choice based on data analysis and to act on the wrong choice instead. The question now becomes whether the choice is merely random, or whether it is volitional. That is, will AI devices ever be able knowingly to make wrong choices? The mere possibility of this, whether through software or hardware is the single key issue in AI work, regardless of the nature of the device. For if the artifact is intelligent, and has volition by standards that are essentially human, then it follows that it is a moral agent, regardless of whether or not it is human. If so, then it is surely capable of choosing to do wrong when it "knows" the right, and this perhaps in nanoseconds rather than upon lengthy deliberation. Some fear AI devices might be capable of doing good or evil at billions of times the rate human beings can. If so, the eventual quick destruction of much of humanity by a berserk machine would seem to be assured, for human beings have done almost as much with a far slower time frame within which to decide and act.

216

Page 217: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

At the very least, this turns the tables on an earlier question, for it leads one to ask whether a house or office computer could be arrested for murdering its owner. Could not such a device, if possessed of free will, become jealous or angry if its tenants decided to move or its users wanted to replace it with a better model? A little judicious fiddling with the building climate controls or the air supply, or a small short circuit on the operator keyboard would quickly eliminate the human inconvenience with no effect on the computer. This scenario too is not just speculation, but a probable outcome of any decision to engineer volitional machines. Thus, if they are to be devised, so must the mechanisms for protecting humans from and dealing with the criminal element among the new devices. This includes arrest procedures, reading their rights, and the means to try them and pass sentence on artifacts. When more ambulatory devices are made, would citizens need protection against mechanical muggers or bank robbers? Would AI machines discover some expensive electronic addiction to help forget their troubles, and need physical and psychological treatment for their equivalent of alcoholism?

How would human beings respond to volitional machines? Would they riot and try to destroy them? Would protective societies come into being, label the termination of AI machines "genocide" and vow to establish legal rights for their mechanical "brothers and sisters"? Such questions should be considered at the time decisions are being made to build thinking machines, rather than after the fact.

Christian and other theologians would also face interesting problems with volitional machines. Granting that a device were regarded as "alive,"--that is, had a soul, the breath of life--would it also be considered to have inherited a fallen nature from man, its creator? If so, could it be said to have a spirit, that is, the ability to relate to God. If so, does salvation apply to it equally as to human beings?

Simple Answers?

The answers to most of the questions raised in this section are simple if AI devices are to remain mechanical expressions of subsets of human thinking patterns--not to be thought of as actually intelligent, or alive in the human sense. Given the present-day agenda of the AI research community, however, the difficult questions seem liable to re-surface from time to time with increasing complexity. At some point, it seems likely that a careful definition of "human" and "intelligent" will have to be agreed upon, and it is not at this time clear what that definition will eventually include, especially since human "intelligence" can scarcely be said to be well defined.

Profile On ... Issues

Machines and Understanding

understand verb 1 : be aware of the meaning of 2 : deduce 3: assign a meaning to

What Does Understanding Involve?

217

Page 218: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o awareness: Understanding implies the existence of an understander, that is, of a personality that is at least self-aware.

o intentionality: There must be a capacity for mental states that are directed at things or objects outside the understander, i.e., the ability to be aware of the things that are to be understood and to consciously direct understanding at them. (e.g., beliefs)

o meaning: There must be an aspect or an idea that is the subject of the understanding. As noted in Chapter 4, meaning requires both intelligent organization, and the capacity for meaning-preserving communication.

Will Machines Ever Understand?

YESo Information is the basis of understanding, and it is just data that has been

processed. Machines process data, so they can also be said to be intelligent.o Biological systems are finite and bounded as are physical ones. They can

therefore be completely comprehended by the inputs and outputs of their own processes without reference to anything else--including the method of internal processing.

o The human mind can be completely explained by knowing how the brain works. This activity can be duplicated.

o All human activity results from the interaction of the electrical, chemical, and physical properties of the body (brain included). These constitute programs that determine all human activity. We need only learn how to write similar programs to duplicate human activity.

o The processes of the brain are nature's way of executing algorithms with a finite number or (possibly repeated) steps. Since every such algorithm is executable on a machine (Church's Thesis) everything the brain does can be duplicated artificially. Meaning is just something that is implicit in data and algorithms and is encoded along with them.

o Understanding is just a name for a certain kind of data processing. It too can be understood (from within the process, so to speak).

o Experience is another name for memory and social conditioning. Since all information can be encoded, experience too can be programmed.

o It is not even necessary to know what the mind is to be able to duplicate the results it can produce. Only the functionality of the human brain needs to be duplicated to produce an intelligent machine, not the exact way that it works.

o Understanding is something that is contained within programming. A simulation of the activity of neural circuits is sufficient to produce understanding equal to what humans have.

o For instance, a chess playing program is intelligent. It uses different techniques than do human players, but it yields the same results.

Understanding is a duplicatible mechanical process.

218

Page 219: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

NOo Understanding data so as to create useful information requires

interpretative ideas, not just mechanical organization. Humans create ideas, machines do not.

o Biological systems are not just physical. The human mind, viewed as an information processor, is unbounded. The brain's biological state constitutes the environment within which its processes take place. This environment is different in a computing machine.

o The human mind is more than just the brain. The mind might understand the brain, but the brain cannot comprehend the mind.

o There is no known link between the brain's hardware (its constituents as a material and physical system) and its software (its constituents as an information processor). There are no known material elements that give it the ability to be a semantic processor, self aware, or intentional.

o Formalizing the execution of algorithms on a machine (encoding data and its processing) requires only a syntactic notation (like a programming language). Semantic analysis (assigning meaning) is a different kind of activity altogether. It too can be described with a notation, but it can only be created by a human.

o The awareness, intentionality, and meaning that compose understanding are motivators for techniques, but are not themselves techniques. Thus no process or technique used by understanding, whether biological or physical, is sufficient to understand understanding. Nothing (including understanding) is the same when viewed from within itself and its processes as it would be viewed by an observer from outside itself and those processes.

oInteraction with the environment, including other human beings, is necessary for understanding.

o The process of understanding is at least as important (if not more) than the functionality, for the ways in which meanings are assigned and communicated are intimately attached to human experience, and that is something no machine can ever have.

o Consequently, understanding involves more than neural circuits, chemistry, or formal symbols, and is closely tied to the social and biological organism it serves. A simulation may to some degree approximate this, but it will not model it.

o The exhaustive search of all possible moves by a high speed computer is fundamentally different from the technique used by a human player. Even if the result on the board may be the same, the mental outcomes are not comparable, and that is what matters.

Understanding is non-duplicatible and uniquely human.

6.5 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

219

Page 220: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The degree to which machines can mimic the results of human thinking is becoming progressively greater. It is not known whether there are limits to this, either short of complete human capability or beyond this point. At the present time machines are already used for expert tasks, logical and inference tasks, design tasks, and language translation.

Over the longer term, some researchers would like to simulate human thinking exactly, and even be able to download themselves into such devices to achieve immortality. The former goal is difficult enough, but too little is known about the human brain to expect the latter to be achieved soon.

Various artificial augmentations to the human brain may be more immediately realizable, and even more practical. Devices here called PIEAs (Personal Intelligence Enhancement Appliances) but more commonly termed "pocket brains" may be developed to allow quick computation and large-scale local memory storage of information. Eventual implantation of these is also a possibility. The same device could be the individual's Metalibrary link and allow fast interpersonal communication and data exchange. The method by which any brain/machine link could be made is not yet known.

Whatever route is taken with AI-capable devices, the very possibility they might exist raises basic questions about whether they would be regarded as alive, as human, or as moral agents. If they are autonomous decision makers, there is no reason to assume that they will share many, if any, goals in common with humanity. The consequences could be catastrophic, so decisions on construction need to be broadened as to participants, and to take these issues into consideration.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. Why does one not call a chess-playing machine intelligent?2. If a machine passes Turing's test, claiming for itself self-awareness, does

that mean that it is in fact self-aware? How can one tell?3. Why are language translation problems so important?4. Research the extent to which language translation software has already

been developed and deployed.5. What advantages would an artificially intelligent machine have over today's

expert systems?6. Perform the necessary library research to determine whether the human

brain is generally regarded as a parallel processor or a sequential processor. Summarize, with citations..

7. Write a paper summarizing some of the problems involved in the machine representation of knowledge.

8. Discuss the technical problems involved in simulating vision in a machine.9. Write a paper defending human brain downloading as the ultimate goal of

research into intelligence.10. Write a paper attacking the concept of human brain downloading on either

scientific or moral grounds, or both.11. Attack or defend the proposition "A human being is a machine made of

meat."

220

Page 221: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

12. If the Metalibrary or any AI device behaved in every other way as though it were intelligent, how could one determine if it were independently self-aware?

13. Suppose a person recorded in detail every life's experience, all learning, reading, thinking, motives and so on, and placed this into a mechanical brain. Would this constitute a better "copy" than one made by a molecule-by-molecule scan of their brain at one point in time? Would the copy be human?

14. Argue that AI machines must be made autonomous moral agents, and that the consequences for the human race will be good.

15. What is intentionality? Could a machine have it? Why or why not?16. Discuss the problems involved in making machine simulations of

emotions.17. Argue that only catastrophe could occur if AI devices were to become self

aware, autonomous decision makers and moral agents. Make a case therefore that such machines must be kept strictly subservient to humankind, and unable to be autonomous.

18. Research Isaac Asimov's fictional "Laws of Robotics" and discuss their enforceability, implementability, and adequacy to prevent such machines from mastering the human race.

19. Discuss the kind of work best done by Metapersons, and why a special legal status is necessary for such partnerships.

20. Should an AI device that is capable of duplicating the results of human thinking be regarded as equal in status to human beings?

21. What legal rights should AI devices have? Does your answer depend on their appearance or only on their "thinking" capabilities?

22. What social rights should AI devices have? Does your answer depend on their appearance or only on their "thinking" capabilities?

23. Should an employer give a job to a human applicant in preference to an AI device that can do it better for the same salary? Why or why not?

24. In view of the problems discussed in this Chapter, what restrictions, if any, should be placed on AI research and development? How can these be enforced, and who should do this enforcing?

25. You are the pastor of a small church and are visited one night in 2065 by a mobile AI device that tells you: "I've been listening to your sermons and I want to become a believer and a member of your church." What do you do and why?

Bibliography

Denning, Peter J. & Metcalfe, Robert M. Beyond Calculation--The Next Fifty Years of Computing. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1997

Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. New York: Anchor, 1986.Drexler, K. Eric with Peterson, Chris, and Pergamit, Gayle. Unbounding The

Future - The Nanotechnology Revolution. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1991Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers. New York: Macmillan, 1986.Grimson, W. Eric L. and Patil, Ramesh S. AI in the 1980's and Beyond, An MIT

Survey. Cambridge, MA; MIT Press, 1987.Minsky, Marvin. The Society of Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1986.

221

Page 222: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Ramo, Simon. Century of Mismatch. New York: David Mckay, 1970. Roszak, Theodore. The Cult of Information. New York: Pantheon Division of

Random House, 1986.Scientific American October 1987 issue on Artificial IntelligenceSowa, John F. Knowledge Representation: Logical, Philosophical, and

Computational Foundations. New York: Brooks Cole. 2000.August 1999.Turing, Alan Muthiscn. Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind 59: 433-

460, 1950.

Internet resources:

Corme, D. W. <mailto:[email protected]<http://www.cs.reading.ac.uk/people/dwc/ai.html

222

Page 223: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 7The Biospace Revolution

Seminar - "How Shall we Live?" 7.1 Life in Time and Space--Defining the Biospace 7.2 Disease and Surgery 7.3 Engineered Medicine 7.4 Engineering New Life Forms

7.5 Human Genetic Engineering 7.6 Rights, Health Care, and Life 7.7 The Environment and Human Life 7.8 Building New Environments 7.9 Summary and Further Discussion

7.1 Life in Time and Space--Defining the Biospace Every life form occupies a unique niche in the context of all life on earth. This

niche can be expressed in terms of the physical space that it requires to make or gather food and also in terms of relationships with other life forms with similar agendas. Human life, however much it might be considered as different from other forms, is also lived out in such a context. It draws sustenance in the form of clothing, shelter, and food from other forms of life and cannot exist without the support of the plants and animals with which it shares the earth. The whole of the environment is a complex network of dependencies of one form of life upon another, and it is now understood that no part can be changed without having an effect on the rest. This is by no means a concept new to the information age, though it has not been an important paradigm of the industrial one. Such an idea was expressed by the Elizabethans as the "chain of being." It is the principle of interdependence again, this time expressed as:

Every life form depends on every other life form.

Every habitat has to be shared.

Likewise, human life is lived out over a span of years, and this implies a certain balance in the relationship of people to each other and to the environment. The passing of the years has been counted upon to supply a steady stream of new people with new ideas, to be the new consumers and the new leaders. If a society does not grow in size and power by increasing in absolute numbers, the inexorable passage of time will at the very least by the cycle of birth, life, sickness, and death ensure some measure of renewal in that society. One characteristic of modern medicine has been a great increase in the number of years lived by the average human being, and there is some prospect of further gains. Of course, such changes

223

Page 224: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

in life span produce profound side-effects--and not just in the population or society where they take place, but through the rest of the chain of related societies and life forms.

It is the combination of life in both space and time that can be expressed as biospace, specifically:

The niche occupied by human life in space and time together is called the human biospace.

With each of the earlier transitions to a new society, the interrelationships among humans changed (in some cases dramatically), and this is now happening again. The purpose of this chapter is to consider the aspects of the continuing scientific and technological revolution that directly affect the living of human life itself--that is, medical, environmental, and living space concerns. These issues are multifaceted and complex. It could be argued that they are all somewhat independent of one another and that several chapters are required to do them justice. That they are here collected into one is precisely because there is a unifying theme--all relate to how many people will live, where they will live, and what quality of life they will enjoy in the Fourth Civilization.

7.2 Disease and Surgery One of the most dramatic differences between this time--the close of the

industrial age--and all earlier ones is that people now have an entirely different attitude to disease and to the practice of medicine. Until the late nineteenth century, death was ready to knock at every door at any time in the form of plague, smallpox, diphtheria, typhus, polio, and a host of other diseases. In developed countries, none of these need be feared today because of the widespread use of antiseptics, antibiotics, and vaccinations. Smallpox has now been completely eradicated, and many of the others on the old list of killers have been reduced in certain countries to rare cases of little more than nuisance value to society as a whole. This has come about because hospitals are kept clean, patients are segregated from one another and from the healthy, and drinking water is treated at central locations to remove contamination. It is difficult for moderns to appreciate the scope of these changes. Until less than a century ago, the practice of medicine other than surgery was based on little more than superstition, and a sick person was in many cases better off dying in peace than calling a doctor.

Will this trend continue to the point that most communicable diseases eventually become a thing of the past? Pessimists point to modern population mobility and suggest that some new disease (natural or deliberately engineered) could even now sweep the earth in record time and carry away a large percentage of the population before a cure could be developed. A disease as deadly as AIDS but as easy to catch as the flu could infect most of the world's population in a matter of weeks. No defense could be devised in time to save any except by the small percentage who would be naturally immune. Moreover, people in the developed nations have become complacent about vaccinations against what they regard as rare diseases, and may have made themselves vulnerable. Optimists are sure that new drugs combined with new methods of tailoring enzymes, proteins, and "fake"

224

Page 225: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

viruses to stimulate antibody production will all but eliminate the transmission of disease in the next few decades.

The hardest problems to solve are those of viruses, the semi-living capsules of genetic material that invade the body's cells and take them over as factories to replicate themselves. Some, the so-called "retroviruses", are capable of hiding in the body for years before being triggered to begin or continue their damaging behaviour. These include the viruses that cause herpes and AIDS.

One line of research has concentrated on curing or preventing the symptoms of retroviruses, possibly by forcing them back into dormancy with the hope that eventually, a way may be found to remove them from the body altogether. Another line focuses on interfering with the virus in such a way as to prevent its reproduction or to foil its mode of attack on the body. Still others seek to tailor molecules that can bind with the DNA of the virus directly to kill or inactivate it. All hold the promise that eventually all viral disease can be eradicated.

When the human immune system and its behaviour with viruses is sufficiently well understood to achieve this, a true watershed will have been passed--the last barrier major to the elimination of communicable disease will have been eliminated. The "cure for the common cold" is an old touchstone in such research; achieving that implies the ability to defeat almost all viruses.

Recent experience with antibiotics, however, ought to sound a cautionary note. These work by selectively killing off most of the target organism population. Usually, the smaller numbers that remain are then taken care of by the body's immune system on its own. However, the prolonged use of antibiotics guarantees that the only remaining bacteria will be the ones that were resistant to the antibiotic. Even if this resistance is conferred by an otherwise unfavourable or recessive mutation, eventually the entire population of the organism will be resistant. Such "superbugs" can then defy modern medicine in wreaking their havoc on humankind. This selection of the existing bacterial population for resistance has some potential for catastrophe, and it cannot be denied that a similar caveat may hold for the treatment of viruses. However, the human population had, by the end of the twentieth century, a much better strategic position in the war against both kinds of disease than it had fifty years earlier.

Neither has medical progress been confined to the problem of communicable diseases; numerous surgical procedures are routinely performed today that were unheard of a century ago. Appendicitis is now seldom a killer, and many kinds of cancer and heart disease can be beaten. The people of industrialized countries live longer, are healthier, and are more active and productive later in life than at any time in the past. They have forgotten the times when the limited skills of surgeons were exercised without antiseptic or anesthetics and hospital patients usually died--if not of trauma, then of infection. Instead, most live long enough to become the victims of cancer, heart disease, accident, or suicide rather than of surgery, infection, or communicable disease.

Those advances have not come without cost, for medical science now allows more people with genetic defects or chromosomal damage to live and pass on those defects to the next generation. Old age comes more slowly than it ever has, but death is postponed only at an ever increasing cost for more sophisticated medical

225

Page 226: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

techniques and larger extended-care facilities. Thus, the modern medical system is under constant pressure, forced to make difficult choices over the allocation of scarce and costly resources. The resulting ethical questions concerning the application of life-saving or life-prolonging technology can be divided into three kinds--those of facilities, those of cost, and those of appropriateness.

Facilities

It is often the case that a hospital is severely constrained in its ability to provide complex services. For instance, the number of open-heart repair procedures that can be performed at a given facility in a year is limited by the availability of both operating rooms and qualified surgical teams. Some means of scheduling the clients of such services must always be devised. This may be strictly first-come-first-served, or surgery may be prioritized by the severity of the case, or it may be dependent on some attempt to place a value on the client. This value may derive from the perceived contributions of the person to society (i.e., a famous scientist or artist versus a common criminal or skid road habitue). It may be a monetary value (i.e., the ability to pay for priority treatment). It may be potential value to society--a young person with a whole life to live being given surgical priority over an aged one whose contributions are in the past. The more severe the shortage of resources and the more fundamental the issue--here it is life--the greater the pressure both on those who must wait and on those who control the resources.

In addition, new diagnostic and treatment techniques are always very limited in availability, sometimes for a protracted period. For example, two of the latest are magnetoencephalography (MEG), which measures the magnetic fields of brain cells, and nuclear magnetic resonance (NMR), which is a means of scanning and mapping the internal body organs. The former is useful in the diagnosis of brain disorders such as epilepsy, cysts, and tumors. The latter can produce whole body images and even a spectroscopy, or chemical map, to pinpoint subtle imbalances in the body's functioning. It also can pinpoint tumours and soft tissue damage. Such machines represent very high technology, and come with an equally high price tag. They are expensive and complex to build and operate, and their results require special training to interpret. As a result, they are relatively scarce, as the latest techniques in medicine always must be.

Limited availability of resources is a broad and growing problem to modern medicine. As the population ages, and as new ways are developed to prolong the life of some people, the shortage of facilities and trained personnel become ever more severe, as do the problems of rationing--deciding who will get sophisticated treatment, who will get basic treatment, and who will get none. An act-oriented ethic may seem to demand the maximum possible medical effort to be available for all. A utilitarian one demands the greatest net medical benefits for the largest number of people. But, these are both ideals, for as long as resources for diagnosis

226

Page 227: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and treatment are scarce--and it seems inherent in the present system that they always will be--there may be no solution to the problems of allocation that can possibly satisfy everyone. Consequently, it becomes necessary for both practical and ethical reasons to pursue the development of medical services that can be delivered with the least of scarce and expensive facilities and personnel. One such method is the delivery of treatment at home rather than in a hospital, and by personnel with less training than a physician (perhaps even be self-administered).

At the same time, it is necessary to seek technological solutions to certain problems caused by existing techniques. For example, diagnosis is often achieved only by batteries of complex tests, sometimes using scarce and expensive machines or drugs. It is impossible to deploy such facilities for every doctor in the world, so it is necessary to devise cheaper, more automatic diagnostic techniques in order to make even the existing level of medical knowledge usable.

In addition, society itself, by its very industries, sometimes creates new medical disorders that require sophisticated diagnosis and treatment. Examples include chemicals such as urea formaldehyde and a variety of pesticides, substances such as asbestos, and damage from radiation accidents.

Cost

The problems of paying for new types of treatment is also becoming more acute with each passing year. For instance, should the person who receives a heart or lung transplant be required to pay all, part, or none of the cost? Does it make any difference if the person's own life-style (smoking, drinking, driving) contributed to or caused the problem in the first place? Should the employer be responsible if the procedure was necessary because of some job-related activity? Should the government pay just because the person is a citizen? What if the patient is not a citizen?

As diagnostic techniques and drugs increase in sophistication, they increase in cost as well. Complex treatments, particularly when new, may require hundreds of thousands of dollars, amounts far beyond the ability of most individuals to pay. Neither can medicare programs grow indefinitely without bound, for they will consume the entire budgets of governments that sponsor them long before any end to their growth is in sight. It is not possible to afford every possible medical technique for every patient, yet the physician who does not perform them risks a malpractice suit. Insurance premiums to cover such legal expenses push up medical costs even more. In addition, there is the expense of training medical personnel so that they stay abreast of latest developments. Thus, from a cost perspective alone, it is clear that new and expensive technologies will always be rationed. There will always be the question of whether a procedure should be performed just because it is possible, or only when it is affordable. There will also be the question of who should make such decisions--patients, doctors, lawyers or politicians?

For instance, suppose that the president of the United States, a billionaire industrialist, and a poor but Nobel-winning cancer researcher are all dying. Each requires a liver transplant within twenty-four hours and only one surgery can be performed. Which should be given the treatment? Suppose the issue is complicated

227

Page 228: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

because both the first two could make hard-to-refuse offers to the medical facility that would see it grow in size and in the ability to treat others. Treating many people like the poor researcher could, on the other hand, put the facility out of business, even though treating a cancer researcher might eventually cause more benefit to more people. Can the course of action likely to cause the most good to the largest number of people be determined? Can the right thing to do be determined? On a larger scale, can medical practitioners ever refuse necessary treatment to groups of people who cannot pay, while advancing it to those who can? What about the same question asked of unnecessary (say, cosmetic) treatment that is requested by a patient?

Some examples may be extreme, but similar ones are commonplace. Consider the dilemma faced by the administrators of medical insurance plans when asked to fund complex, expensive, and risky transplant operations for children at remote places. The cost for one such operation may well be greater than that of keeping a hospital bed at home open for a year. How many such special procedures can be afforded before the whole system deteriorates in its ability to provide care for society as a whole? How many community appeals for such special cases will distraught parents be able to make before both sympathy and wallets become exhausted? Should elective surgeries be funded just because the patient wants them, or should only the ones needed be paid for--and who is to decide which ones are needed?

Choices may also arise between expensive and inexpensive treatments. For example, a patient with poor eyesight might be treated with a prescription for glasses or contact lenses at a cost of under a hundred dollars or might be given an expensive laser treatment to reshape the cornea and eliminate the need for external correction. Should there be (in this case, or any other) different treatments depending on the wealth of the patient? Who should pay for the poor man's glasses, or the rich woman's corrective surgery? As the cost of medicine rises, so does the number of people who cannot afford even basic services, let alone exotic new techniques.

If MRI diagnosis is needed to determine if a person has a tumour and there is a six-month backlog, should the person be allowed to have the procedure done privately if willing to pay (this may not be an issue in countries that have no public medicare)? Or, should exactly the same opportunity be available to everyone, regardless of their wealth and the time it would take? What if the private clinic's purchase of a machine means that none is available for a public hospital? What if the hospital can charge for some procedures and use the money to finance more hours for public clients?

The wealthy Western nations make important choices all the time when they elect to make resources available for expensive surgeries whose cost could fund thousands of simple, sight-restoring eye operations in third-world countries. Rarely are things so simple that it is apparent to those directly involved that such a choice is being made, but any comparison of medical facilities in different parts of the world makes it obvious that some nations choose to afford far more than others possibly can.

228

Page 229: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Organ transplant surgery will always have such limitations because of the problem of finding donors and matching the tissue type with the intended recipient. Even if transplant operations become as simple as appendectomies or plastic surgery, ways will have to be found to increase the supply of spare body parts. Today, the presumption in Western countries is that such parts can be removed from a fresh cadaver only with prior authorization from the deceased or the permission of the immediate family. If the individual did not make a point of granting such permission while living, medical staff are understandably reluctant to ask relatives immediately after death, for fear of giving offence to the grieving relatives.

On the other hand, if a potential donor comes into a hospital after, say, a traffic accident, and there is another patient there in need of the badly injured patient's heart, will the potential donor get the best medical care, even when their death could mean life for the other, and vice-versa?

One possibility for alleviating the shortage of organs would be to move to the opposite legal presumption--that the body parts of the newly dead are the property of society and freely available to the medical profession unless authorization has been specifically denied. However, what is more important, the right of the dead to privacy or the need of the living for a new organ? Surely, life must take precedence over privacy in any ethical hierarchy, and yet there is something at the very least dissatisfying or even ghoulish about the idea of routinely harvesting body parts from the deceased, without express prior approval.

Yet, if this seems unattractive, what are the alternatives? One could argue that human organs ought to become commodities like gold, pork bellies, or coffee. After all, the Red Cross already buys blood in many parts of the world (Some countries, such as Canada, have in the past forbidden the purchase of blood from donors and commercial transactions in organs). If blood can be a commodity, then perhaps kidneys, lungs, or even limbs could be treated as such. What is more important, the need to make body parts available when and as needed, or people's reluctance to engage in something that could be likened to the operations of a used automotive parts business?

It should be noted that in countries where people are sufficiently desperate, there is a temptation to make money by selling one's own body parts to the citizens of "enlightened" western countries. Alternately, sufficiently repressive states in need of foreign exchange could decide to farm such organs from its citizens without their consent. Meanwhile, western governments might find the prospect of benefiting their own citizens in this way to be politically irresistible. Who ought to have the authority to allow or deny such transactions? Is it even possible to stop them? Perhaps not, for there is already a lively traffic in such organs from third-world countries to the operating rooms of the West, with only sporadic and ineffectual outcry.

The complexity of these issues is also illustrated by the difficulty experienced by doctors wishing to use transplant parts from newborn but nonviable infants. Sometimes a child is born with much of the brain missing (anencephalic) and will surely die in a matter of hours or days. Some doctors are unhappy that even when parents' permission is given, it may be legally impossible to use organs from such

229

Page 230: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

an infant for transplant purposes until breathing ceases, at which point the parts are much less useful. One rationale for forbidding earlier transplants is that the child is a human being--though a very much injured one--and therefore entitled to be allowed to die in peace without being torn apart for spare parts while still alive. Some hospitals attempt to steer a middle course, keeping the doomed infant well oxygenated and healthy, so that the organs will be in good condition when death does come. However, even this practice is controversial, for the definition of death as the cessation of brain activity is hard to apply when much of the brain is missing.

The success of the pro-abortion movement in effectively re-defining an unborn child as a non-person and thus part and property of the mother's body raises the possibility that cash-starved mothers could sell the parts of her unborn child. After all, attempts to prosecute pregnant women for child abuse for taking drugs, or murder for shooting their unborn child have already been dismissed by the courts because the child in the womb has no legal personhood.

The danger in breaking new legal ground in such respects is in defining that severely injured or malformed infants are not human and can therefore be scavenged. If that could be done in such an admittedly extreme case, there would be pressure to do the same to those born with, say, cerebral palsy or Down's syndrome. If those cases were also permitted, then any child deemed unacceptable by the parents for any reason--say, by being the wrong sex--might be at risk. Moreover, there could be no compelling reason to limit this to infants once such a practice were begun, for the precedent would be set whereby anyone could be declared insufficiently human and subject to salvage, such as for failing in school or for being too old. The state that had the power to do these things could also define the members of a race, religion, or banned political party to be subhuman and available for spare parts. Under current North American law, it would seem that even healthy children could be disassembled and sold for parts while still in the womb even if not after birth. After all, it is already common practice to harvest stem cells and other tissue from aborted children, in some cases without any authorization being necessary.

On the other hand, under a hierarchical ethic of the type developed in Chapter 3, even the most severe "defects" would not disqualify a person from the right to live, for such disablements reflect on the quality of the child's future life, not on the fact of it. Life itself clearly has a higher priority than its quality.

A related and equally contentious issue is the use of tissues from miscarried or aborted infants in transplants, corrective surgeries, and other experimental purposes. It has long been known that such tissue has growth and restorative potential not shared by the corresponding tissue from a mature human. Thus, if bone marrow, skin, liver cells, and other organ parts are required to grow well after transplant, there may be no better source than fetal tissue. Whatever one thinks of the ethics of abortion or of the status of the unborn, such a practice has some unique ethical hazards. If the use of such parts were to become an important medical technique, they would become a correspondingly important commercial commodity. Not only would there be a lively trade in such tissues by hospitals and abortion clinics, there might even be a sufficient economic incentive for destitute

230

Page 231: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

women to become pregnant and sell the right to abort the child to the highest bidder.

Such outcomes may seem bizarre and repulsive to those who regard the human body at all stages as something much more than a convenient assemblage of chemicals into tissue. To others, such practices are simply the logical and normal outcomes of regarding the parts of the human body as commodities like any other. That is, the conclusions one draws on these and similar issues depend on one's view of the human body. If the body is held either as sacred and inviolable (on the one hand) or as entirely material but constituting the whole of a person (on the other), then it could be argued that the body's parts ought to be left alone. Two normally opposed groups find common ground here--one because of a transcendent view of the body and the other because of the belief that the body is the whole of a person. Members of the former group would want to bury the dead respectfully--and by that they mean intact. Members of the latter group might suggest instead freezing the body against the day when it could be thawed out and brought back to life with all parts intact. Respect is the common theme here.

An entirely different conclusion might be drawn by those who emphasize the immaterial aspects of what they see in a human being. A human being is sometimes viewed as a body and soul dichotomy, or as body, soul, and spirit trichotomy, and there are those who regard the material body as by far the least important of these. With such an emphasis, the dead body is not the whole person and not at all sacred. It is just part of the material baggage left behind when the essence of the person (the soul) departs. Since there is in this view no reunion of personality with that body, the previous owner has no more use for its parts, at they might be used to benefit someone else. Other combinations of these ideas are also possible, and the two conclusions about the value of the body can be reached by other means, so there is little agreement on such issues.

There are two possible techniques for alleviating the supply difficulties associated with transplant operations. The first is to use animal donors, such as pigs or chimpanzees, to obtain the organs destined for human beings. This would have the advantage of solving the supply problem, though some people might be repelled at the prospect of having a pig's heart replace their own, and animal rights activists might also be offended. The second is to develop artificial hearts, kidneys, livers, and so on. This would also solve the supply problem, though the cost of such work has so far been very high, and there is no immediate prospect that such devices can be made and produced in the necessary quantity, with the required reliability and at a reasonable price. Nor does either of these solutions address the availability of surgeons and facilities, or the cost of performing the procedures. Mass availability of artificial hearts would not in itself mean that more transplant operations could be performed; other factors are at least as complex.

This discussion highlights the built-in limitations of surgical techniques--barring some dramatic changes in the availability of transplant parts and other costs, the application of such methods simply cannot increase without limit. Thus, the most sophisticated of today's surgical methods are unlikely ever to become available to much of the world's population. There will never be sufficient funds available to perform every necessary surgical procedure, much less every desirable

231

Page 232: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

one--and this is true even if robotic surgeons are developed. However, no one with any sensitivity would want to turn away the sufferer with no hope for relief. Again, necessity seems to force the conclusion that simpler and less costly methods must be found to replace the use of surgery and other complex procedures.

Appropriateness

A third set of problems that accompany the allocation of scarce medical resources has to do with the appropriateness of treatment in some cases. For instance, should a doctor do an expensive heart transplant on a patient who is also suffering with a terminal cancer that will probably kill her within two years? Should expensive surgery be done to allow a child with Down's syndrome to live, even though it is known that the quality of that life will be impaired? Some, including courts called upon to judge such cases, have said "no." According to the ethical hierarchy developed in Chapter 3, on the other hand, the answer to both questions should be "yes." Denial of treatment can be supported for economic reasons--neither person is likely to be able to pay society back for the treatment. The expense of the procedure is therefore wasted. Those giving the latter answer could argue that the future cannot be known in advance and that the termination of a life is not an answer, but a reaction born of despair. What is more, everyone dies eventually, even if it is simply of old age. The physician who may be able to give a woman dying of bone cancer a few more years, although pain filled, does not know if tomorrow will bring a cure or a fatal traffic accident to the patient. Has the doctor a mandate to prejudge her life on the basis of an unknowable future?

Questions of appropriateness are also raised in connection with fertility problems, for treatment of such conditions can also be expensive and time consuming and can require repeated hospitalization. Neither is it easy to argue that a woman has a fundamental right to bear children. Moreover, there is already population pressure, and this grows steadily worse. In that light, it is difficult to justify using scarce resources to enhance fertility. On the other hand, it is hard not to sympathize with the plight of one who desperately desires children but is unable to have any, particularly when adoption is unlikely to be an option.

Other questions of appropriateness are quite different. Many concern cosmetic surgery. Should surgery to reduce a nose, enlarge breasts, change the smile, or "Westernize" the eyes be paid for by medical plans, or even allowed? After all, these take up a substantial portion of scarce hospital and surgical resources--ones which, it could be argued, would be better spent on those who are actually sick. How important to society as a whole is the self-image of some of its members? One might agree that correcting actual defects is good and should be done, but how does one respond to the argument that a nose perceived as less than perfect by its owner is a defect? As the population ages and life spans increase, cosmetic surgery will be in greater demand. Some argue that this area should be left rather unregulated, apart from defining "cosmetic" and excluding such surgery from public medical insurance plans. Even some of these might want the government to step in if cosmetic surgery took a bizarre turn. For instance, perhaps some future youth cult would find it "cool" to have orange cheeks, green lips, an elongated nose, and skin

232

Page 233: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

flaps instead of hair--all arranged by surgery. Is this different from what is often called "corrective cosmetic" surgery? Even if it is, it may be impossible to draw the line between the frivolous and the acceptable, so "user-pay" may have to rule this area. One could suggest that hospitals might make sufficient profit on such enterprises to subsidize other areas. On the other hand, such activities might make operating rooms and personnel unavailable for other types of work.

Summary and Conclusion

As long as current surgical methods are relied upon for replacement or repair of defective body organs, a regulated means of providing the necessary resources must develop, however unsatisfactory it may be. However, many of the surgical methods themselves are likely to remain complex, scarce, and expensive. In all likelihood, those methods will never become available to the world's general population, and the chief problems associated with them will continue to be how patients are selected and who pays rather than, say, the supply of organs as an economic mass commodity. What is required are different technologies--ones that use simple, cheap, and nonsurgical methods. In many cases, the functioning of human body systems are fairly well understood (on a macro level), and so are their dysfunctions--, in theory. This means that solving the problems may be more a matter of applied science or engineering than of pure science or understanding.

7.3 Engineered Medicine As mentioned earlier, the development of effective ways to combat viruses

will represent a major medical turning point. If viral diseases can be conquered without hospitalization, the cost of medical care will decline and life spans will increase--both perhaps rather substantially. Enough progress has now been made to make some health researchers confident that most infectious diseases will soon be a thing of the past, providing no intervening political or economic catastrophe sets the work back.

This leaves three other categories of organic malfunctions for which to consider treatment strategies. The first is invasive illness, such as cancer. Here, encouraging progress has already been made toward the development of biological and chemical agents capable of targeting specific cancerous cells in the body and either destroying them or tagging them in such a way as to invite the body's own immune system to eliminate the intruder. It is now known that a healthy immune system is able to make antibodies for almost any foreign protein; the trick is to keep that system healthy and working. Whatever the method, many forms of cancer can now be completely defeated, especially if detected early. The most difficult remaining ones to overcome may be the non-localized cancers of the bone, blood, and lymph. Still, optimists point to the progress to date and predict that even these forms of cancer will be curable by injection, radiation, and other nonsurgical methods within twenty years.

Lung cancer may also be hard to cure. It is presently on the rise, especially among women, who became smokers in large numbers more recently than men and have not been giving up the habit as readily. This particular problem raises a

233

Page 234: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

subsidiary ethical question--whether the production, sale, and advertising of so potent a carcinogen as tobacco should even be allowed. It would not be if it were a new food additive or drug, but the vested interests of a large existing industry are not easy to set aside, even when the lives of many people are at stake. This is an example of the way that economic considerations sometimes overpower ethical ones.

The second category of malfunctions is those involving the accumulation of extraneous material in the body. Calcium deposits cause painful spurs on bones and cholesterol accretions block arteries, causing damage to the heart and other organs. It seems likely that in many cases, substances will eventually be developed to dissolve such accretions in a harmless fashion. After all, there are already drugs that can dissolve gallstones or block secretions of stomach acid. These eliminate the need for such surgeries as gall bladder removal and duodenal ulcer repair.

In an interesting sidelight, it was long thought that ulcers were caused by excess stomach acid, and the typical treatment was a sedative prescription combined with a bland diet. It is now known that ulcers are caused by bacteria, and antibiotics are quite an effective treatment. That is, rather than being a systemic failure of one's own body, ulcers are caused by an invasive agent. There may well be other such misunderstandings in modern medical knowledge.

Another problem that may be of a similar type (system failure) relates to body cells' seeming inability to divide and replace themselves more than a given number of times before dying. One theory was that this may be due to the action of substances that built up between or inside the cell and eventually blocked its reproduction. If the cell-division inhibiting agents could be identified, an anti-inhibitor could surely be designed. Understanding what to do is not the problem here, the difficulty lies in actually performing the necessary engineering. But even if an accretion-dissolving molecule must be designed atom by atom--and the ability to do that is limited as yet--such design problems are not theoretically insurmountable. In fact, overcoming barriers of this type involves only a modest expansion of today's already formidable battery of pharmaceuticals.

A new theory of cell aging is equally interesting. It suggests that multiple copies of sequences called telomeres at the end of DNA chains vanish one at a time with each cell division. Eventually, no telomeres remain, and the cell can no longer duplicate itself, thus limiting the organism's lifetime. Perhaps an agent can be found to change this action so cells can reproduce indefinitely. On the other hand, such a cell would bear a strong resemblance to a cancerous one.

The third set of challenges for medical engineering relates to repairing physical damage to the human body. In this context, one is tempted to view the body as a biochemical machine, albeit of extraordinarily intricate design. Unfortunately for the mechanics of this machine (the surgeons), their smallest tools are thousands of times larger than some of the very fine parts they wish to repair. Heavy structural members (bones) and outer protective sheeting (skin) are relatively easy to work on, as are the larger subsystems (organs). But as many paraplegics know to their sorrow, the nervous system is another matter. Sewing these with thread is like trying to tie up a flea with an ocean liner's hawser. Finding,

234

Page 235: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

let alone repairing, individual damaged cells is impossible with traditional surgeons' tools.

The engineering challenge here is to develop first the knowledge of the fine structure of the human body at the molecular level, and then the ability to design biological or chemical agents that can effect repairs at that level. This is not as far-fetched as it may seem, for the body can already conduct repair operations to a great extent, and some animals are even capable of regenerating severed limbs. Human bodies cannot effect this, because even as they grow in the womb, their cell tissue differentiates sufficiently to lose the ability to replace parts. However, the fact that such tissue could grow a limb at one stage of development suggests that it could be given that capability again when necessary. This is the point of working with stem cells (ones that retain the ability to produce various kinds of tissue), for these may be induced to grow a variety or organs or parts thereof.

If limb regeneration seems too grand a task, perhaps promoting the healing of severed nerves will be easier to do and reward far more people. Once again, the problem is one of biochemical engineering--of building the appropriate substances to stimulate the body to repair itself. An old engineer's motto is worth mentioning here:

If it used to work, it can almost certainly be made to work again.

There are more comprehensive repair problems, however. As the body's cells grow older they gradually lose the ability to replicate themselves correctly, or at all. As noted, this may be due to some inhibitor. It may simply be that the body's parts gradually wear out and so die or that each DNA replication causes some portion of the genetic material to be discarded, and eventually the cell simply lacks enough DNA to reproduce. That is, perhaps a body cell is not unlike a page of text that has undergone many successive photocopyings. After a time, the text loses definition, and it eventually becomes illegible. If the DNA of a body cell is subject to similar losses, its successors would eventually lose too much of its information content to remain viable. Here is yet another case where it is easy to visualize the problem and to have some idea how to fix it--on a large scale and a theoretical level. Engineering a solution that allows the body to repair or replace structures damaged by age is a much more difficult matter. It could involve the development of many biochemical agents, some natural to the body at some stages of development (enzymes) and others that are new drugs.

It should be emphasized in this respect, however, that the body subsystem once termed the "simple cell" is anything but. On the contrary, it is known to have a biochemical design of incredible complexity and sophistication--more so than any computer, for example. Thus, finding problems at the molecular level, and designing answers at the same level will not be a simple or a short task.

However, the potential for such medicine extends from simple cell repair to the dramatic and even to the far-fetched. If the human body could be induced to grow a new limb, then perhaps it could also be made to grow a new heart, lung, or liver and then to dissolve the old one. Restoring hair to the bald may not turn out to be difficult or even important. Restoring hearing to the deaf or sight to the blind is

235

Page 236: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

another matter, for both involve problems of fine structure whose repair is often not amenable to surgery but could be to new pharmaceuticals. Some have even wondered whether a "memory pill" could be devised to stimulate the brain in such a way that while under its influence anything heard or read would never be forgotten. Regardless of whether any of these are achieved, the principal research focus will be on replacing expensive and difficult surgical methods with cheap and easy chemical and biological ones.

One possible method of producing biological agents is to design cells, say, bacteria, to produce proteins that in turn could be used to make specific enzymes or antibiotics. Such living nanomachines could be developed much further--to the point where a collection of them can act as a miniature assembly line for new DNA, new proteins or new enzymes. Such substances could then be built to order, molecule by molecule. Other optimistically projected nanomachines would be programmable or instructable--and may be termed nano-computers or general purpose assemblers. The reconstruction of a damaged heart, liver, or other organ and even the rebuilding of damaged nerves or neurons could be well within the ability of agents made in this manner. Another possible technique involves the direct construction of DNA strands that can manufacture the desired molecules. Another still is the chemical stimulation of the affected parts to induce them to self-repair through growth. Although these ideas are still in their infancy, there are already machines that are capable of analysing or constructing specific protein molecules. In the longer term, nanomachines might also be employed to grow a PIEA as an implant in the brain or to make alterations to body or brain structures to improve both or to repair congenital or genetic damage in situ--not on a gross structural level, but by editing gene sequences.

Automating preventive medicine

Setting aside the more spectacular speculations for a moment, an important potential for the use of existing technology is in the computerizing information and activities relating to preventive medicine. In particular, the most important contributors to health--or to the lack of it--are nutrition and exercise. Although the appropriate levels of neither are known yet exactly, a great deal of general information is known about both. Average citizens have little access to much of this in ready form until they come under professional care for a back injury, obesity, diabetes, or a heart attack. Most people will not make use of what is known without such a powerful motivation, unless it is in a form that makes it very easy to obtain. This is an interesting but not insurmountable challenge to some in the high-tech industry, for if people had and used the available information on nutrition and exercise, there would probably be a significant decline in health care costs, and an increase in the average life span.

This is yet another instance where reducing the barriers to finding information has great potential. People who would not make a trip to a library to find nutritional data are more likely to do so if it is easily available in their homes via an appliance that they use frequently, and on which the presence of such information is advertised frequently. The Metalibrary would not itself solve health problems, but it

236

Page 237: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

might prove to be an important tool in providing people with the means to solve some of their own.

Consequences of longer life

As understanding of the aging process, of preventative medicine, and of how to do molecular engineering grows, a substantial increase in life spans seems likely. Longevity researchers differ widely in their estimates of what the eventual human average life span could be, with figures of 200, 500, and 1000 years being tossed about. Even if one believes the more conservative of these optimists, and assumes that some of today's under-50-year-olds would live to, say, 150 years instead of to the current average of about 75 years, the social implications are staggering. At every stage in the development of longevity treatments there will be pressure from the rich, the powerful, and the intellectuals to obtain priority treatment. Moreover, since the already highly developed countries would have such agents first, the medical gap between rich and poor countries (and individuals) may grow even greater, increasing the destabilizing forces on world society. Some attempts might even be made to keep the fact of such treatments a secret at first. However, even if the recipients had complete facial make-overs and an entirely new identities, their continued survival could not long be kept from the rest of the wider population or from the citizens of other countries--all the more so since effective treatments for old age are likely to be independently discovered by many researchers more or less simultaneously.

Over the longer term, age sixty-five retirements, the whole concept of pensions, the hope of inheritances, and the ability of youth to obtain jobs vacated by their elders will all be affected by any substantial increase in life span. In addition, unless birth rates are substantially reduced, population sizes could increase dramatically. Some already crowded countries might restrict any longevity treatments that are developed to a small elite for this reason alone. Power and money concentrations could grow, not only because their holders might at first control the treatments but also because they would live longer and have more time to accumulate both.

Some of these problems might be resolved by pragmatic force of circumstances. The managers of large pension plans would either re-market their funds as general investment packages or go into a different line of work. The tax structure might have to change to limit accumulations of wealth. Perhaps a means would be found to encourage people to change careers every few years in order to alleviate the job entry problem. However, the social and economic disruption due to such changes would still be substantial. On the whole, these changes may increase inequities and tensions between the rich and the poor of the world--a prescription for disaster if the treatments are not seen to be fairly administered. Marriage could change, for it is even now seen by many as a temporary commitment during part of a longer life--such a view could become even more prevalent if life lengthens and bearing children were discouraged or forbidden.

There are also some balancing forces to contend with on this issue. While increased longevity would suggest much larger populations, the birth rate in

237

Page 238: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

industrialized countries has been declining for decades, and it seems likely to do so in third world countries as their economies change as well. The net result could simply be a stable but much older population, and an increase in the retirement age because of a lack of younger workers to take jobs.

It is also not clear whether people who live longer would also stay healthy for longer or whether they would merely have to spend more years in extended-care facilities for the aged. If the latter were all that could be achieved, the benefits would be small indeed. The most optimistic of longevity workers are convinced that the greatest benefits of longer life will come by extending the productive years of those people whose generation of new ideas and techniques most profoundly impact the direction of society. This is a large assumption, for many people are productive only in a few of their present years. One might also hope that more years will mean greater productivity, but this may be an occasional side-effect. It may equally be supposed that longer-lived people would gradually become less innovative and productive, and not contribute anything of benefit to others for most of their lives.

Thus, although human life may be extended considerably over the next few decades, the long-term implications of such increases for society as a whole are unclear. There may be a declining birth rate, a more stable and conservative population, upheavals in the job market, and the disappearance of some institutions catering to retirement as it is now known. Whether the extra years would mean "better" people from either a moral or educational point of view is unknown. History would seem to suggest that there would likely be the same proportion of scoundrels and saints regardless of how long both lived.

Another aspect of the increased use of medical drugs is the corresponding increase in their abuse. The more drugs that are discovered, the more mind-altering substances will be among them. Moreover, as the workings of the human brain and body become better understood, so will the ways of stimulating the pleasure centers. Consequently, one should expect that there will always be addicts. What is not known is whether the societal changes now in progress will result in a higher percentage of the population becoming "wired" for pleasure than at present, or whether a significant sacrifice of general civil liberties will have to be made to detect and eliminate such practices. This is already an important question, not just for athletes who attempt to perform better on drugs but also for the employees of railways, airlines, hospitals, and other places where human performance affects the safety of others.

Thus, it can be seen that the development of new pharmaceuticals, as that of any technique, is likely to have mixed results--some very beneficial, some much less so.

7.4 Engineering New Life Forms Some of the methods described in the last two sections are also being

employed to develop new or modified life forms. Current examples include special strains of bacteria that can attack ocean oil spills, digest the material, and reprocess it into harmless substances. Others make antibiotics, antibodies, and other pharmaceuticals for a variety of human and animal disease treatments. On the

238

Page 239: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

drawing board are bacteria that can concentrate the minute amounts of, say, gold in a rock ore, making the extraction of very low percentages of such metals feasible. Other useful strains could process garbage, produce crude oil, or separate discarded metals and plastics into their elemental constituents for recycling. In conjunction with the biological nanomachines of the last section, scavenger species could also be devised and targeted to particular harmful substances or organisms in the human body. Such goals are already being achieved through recombinant DNA techniques, wherein the specific gene(s) responsible for some attribute of one life form are identified and spliced into the DNA of another form. In the case of simple proteins and DNA strands, genetic engineers have been able to design and build the entire strand from the base materials, and methods for doing this are gradually being extended to more complex proteins.

Possible uses of these techniques on plant genetic material include development of new species of high-yield grains, ones that can grow even in poor soils or climates, as well as the combining of two food producing methods into one plant. An example of the latter is the "pomato," which grows fruit above the ground and tubers below. Higher forms of life may also be modified in this manner. Cattle could be developed that are hardy to colder weather, can graze on poorer ground, give more meat or milk, require less care, or are more resistant to disease. Chickens may be induced to grow larger and to lay bigger eggs. Since the change is at the DNA level, the result is not just a hybrid cross-breed; the new characteristics breed true. Science fiction writers have long speculated that someday all food may be manufactured by bacterial action on raw materials at a far higher efficiency than photosynthesis, with conventional farming becoming obsolete.

There is still concern that a genetically engineered virus or bacteria might be released that would cause a plague taking millions of lives. Another disaster scenario involves creating a life form that is capable of nothing but making copies of itself, using the entire biological world for its own ends--the "grey goo" finale to all other life forms. Laboratories that work with genetic materials must be very careful, for it is not yet possible to predict all the side effects of gene splicing. The section being spliced may control characteristics other than the one being targeted, and the life form developed may not be what is expected.

Such difficulties are to be expected in any technology in its infancy. It is safe to assume that the understanding of genetic coding will continue to grow to the point where the DNA even of complex life forms can be mapped. Several nations have already funded the complete mapping of human genetic material (the human genome project). Now this information has been gathered, the raw data is available to discover what each gene controls and to edit human gene sequences.

Methods for changing specific characteristics will also become more sophisticated. It will be several years before new life forms can be developed from scratch, tailored to measure for their niche in the earth's ecological system, but this too seems inevitable. New plant and animal species will likely be made to improve the food supply or replace it with chemically manufactured substances. In the future, some adventuresome workers might tackle the revival of extinct species like the mastodon, certain dinosaurs, or the passenger pigeon. Another possibility is the enhancement of existing animal species. Could some be given enough intelligence

239

Page 240: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

to perform menial tasks, become factory workers, cleaners, or message carriers? Can some kind of animal/machine be developed that is not only alive but also programmable? The answers to such questions are not known at this time, but if they are positive, then humanity will ultimately face a period of adjustment to its own creations, and the necessity of finding them a place alongside the human biospace.

Questions have been asked about who owns the products of such research. In the United States, patents on new life forms developed in the lab have been granted--a practice that is certain to remain controversial. At issue is whether living materials developed in the lab at the cost of time, talent, energy and money are qualitatively different from medical drugs developed in the same way. As long as viral, bacterial, or plant material is in question, the public may take relatively little interest in the matter. When animal species are genetically re-engineered, opposition to patents and even to the research itself may run somewhat high. However, the controversy generated by plant and animal genetic research pales by comparison to that from questions of applying this research to humans.

7.5 Human Genetic Engineering The methods of gene splicing to re-engineer the human race fall into three

broad categories--those intended to make repairs, those intended for selection, and those intended to make improvements.

Genetic Repairs

Repairs of cellular-level damage fall into two categories. The first, the least controversial and probably the easiest to effect, would be those done after birth, or at least after conception. The development of DNA-driven machines to produce specific proteins could lead to the ability to repair damage from mutations, remove dangerous or hostile proteins from the body, or even to correct some chromosomal or genetic defects after the fact. That this is of somewhat limited benefit can easily be seen by considering Down's syndrome. Even if all the associated genetic damage were somehow to be repaired, say by a nanomachine, there would still remain the physical and mental deformities programmed in before birth.

The second category is the elimination of genetic disorders before they happen, or at least before they have any opportunity to do any lasting harm. There is a long list of candidates for such work. Sickle-cell anemia, hemophilia, and the predilection to organic problems such as cancer and heart disease are some that come immediately to mind. Some disorders can already be identified with specific gene locations in human DNA. Diagnosis from material in the fluid surrounding the child in the womb is also possible in many cases. It may not be many years before the genetic causes of most major inherited disorders are well understood, though there is little indication at this time that cures for any of them are feasible once they have been inherited.

In the time between the discovery of the genetic cause for an ailment and that of a cure, a new issue arises, however. Is a person known to have a genetic

240

Page 241: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

predisposition to heart failure, diabetes, or drug addiction insurable? Is such a person employable?

At present, prenatal examinations for such disorders are usually done to determine whether or not to abort the child rather than with any healing process in view. Where governments permit such abortions, it is not hard to imagine them also mandating that genetically defective children be aborted in order to protect the economy by avoiding costly treatment and care after birth. After all, a state that has the power to allow abortion clearly has the power to require it. Indeed, in view of growing population pressures and strains on the medical system, such a possibility must be regarded as quite likely in some countries--a final solution to the cost of birthing, raising, and caring for those deemed genetically defective. The chief question would then be how to determine which genetic characteristics constitute the "pure" human race and which others ought to be exterminated. As the Nazis showed in the 1930s, the decision can be made on a political level and then technology used to enforce it afterwards. Since such a policy would be effective only if it were enforced on the already-born as well as on those not yet born, it would be as easy to establish in the former case as in the latter. It might be a short step to a new program of genocide directed against those deemed sub-human for national, religious, or racial reasons. Because this would be a politically motivated policy, it would also be easy to label dissidents as defective, much as they were in the old Soviet Union, except that a mental hospital expense would not be incurred.

Can such frightening outcomes be avoided? The assumption here is that they must. One possibility is by focusing research on conception itself, rather than on some later point in human development. Assuming that gene splicing methods have also advanced in step with diagnostic techniques, the same methods applied to plants and animals will be available to alter human DNA. The egg and sperm of would-be parents could be examined, and the coding at the target gene sites changed before inducing conception in vitro. The "corrected" fertilized egg could then be implanted in the mother's womb for carrying to full term. The child would still be biologically the offspring of its parents but would lack the damaged genes that they would have passed on in the normal mode of conception. Moreover, those damaged genes would then be eliminated from future generations as well.

There are also objections to this kind of research on the grounds that the result is unnatural, and therefore ought to be forbidden. For their part, advocates respond that, in the case of hemophilia, for instance, blood that clots is more natural than blood that does not. Surely, goes the argument, it would be of great benefit to the whole human race to find ways of correcting and eliminating haemophilia (and similar problems). Heading off genetically-induced disorders before they happen also avoids the more unpleasant aspects of attempting control after the fact. It would also solve some problems that now exist for infertile couples who use sperm banks in order to conceive a child. As things now stand, two children independently conceived through these services could well be half-siblings with no means of knowing this. If they met and married, the probability of genetic defects in their offspring would be much higher than normal. The ability to eliminate genetic defects would make the operation of anonymous banks for human eggs and sperm much safer. Whether, in the light of population pressures, the cost of continuing to

241

Page 242: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

use these techniques is justified is quite another matter. So is the potential right of the child to know who the biological parents are.

On the face of it, choosing to seek the ability to make genetic repairs seems an easy decision to make. Indeed, the numerous research efforts already underway along these line testify to the fact that the decision has already been made. As long as fertilized eggs are not discarded during the process, even the most conservative observer might not object too strenuously to such an apparently beneficial program. However, there are clearly implications of this technology that would be much more controversial. Moreover, there is no guarantee that the best of such techniques, chosen with "good" motives, would not still result in the worst of abuses as well.

Selection

The ability to repair genetic material implies that traits other than those involving defects could also be selected. The most obvious application is choosing the sex of the child. On a personal level, this might be regarded by many as ethically neutral. However if sex selection were easy enough to implement on a large scale, it might not be neutral, for in some cultures there is a powerful bias against female children. In such situations, the ability to select sex would quickly throw the male/female ratio far off the rough balance it now enjoys. Indeed, in some parts of the world, amniocentesis is already performed solely for this purpose. It is hard to imagine the consequences for the particular generation so selected, but the practice of selecting only males would certainly have to die out quickly, with or without the culture that once used it.

Eventually, various selections would be just as feasible--for beauty, strength, longevity, intelligence, height, colouring, and other characteristics. Since some of these characteristics might be perceived to give the next generation a decided advantage, there would at the very least be strong social pressure on parents to adopt whatever technology was available to ensure that their children had the best possible genetic heritage. Indeed, if they chose not to do so, they would surely find themselves on the losing end of a parental malpractice suit brought by their offspring or even the target of criminal negligence charges brought by the state. What is more, if current population pressures are heightened by a dramatic increase in life spans, the birth rate will have to decline in equal measure. If society is able to tolerate only a few children, the pressure to use whatever techniques are available to select the "best" parental genetic material would undoubtedly become extreme.

In the same way that abortion of "defective" children might come to be required, the availability of genetic selection methods could lead to their enforced use, because there would be compelling arguments that selection is in the best interests of society (another example of efficient technique being irresistible). There would always be the problem of who defines the best interests, of course. Some future government might want to breed docility into the general population to enhance its power or to eliminate certain racial characteristics in the interests of what it regarded as purity. This could not be done easily unless authorities also limited longevity treatments to an elite, for otherwise the population would change too slowly to achieve this goal. While a government with enough power to do the

242

Page 243: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

one could clearly do both, it would still be faced with population pressure and might opt instead for mass sterilization or some equally draconian means of compulsory birth control. The more neutral path of requiring reproduction licenses--and only issuing them to those deemed genetically fit, or those able to afford gene editing--might be impossible to enforce under any but a totalitarian regime.

The major assumptions that lead to the most severe of these difficulties are three: that such selection will become possible; that life spans will increase; and that living space will be limited. There may therefore, be a troubled future for human genetic research--and now that it has begun, it cannot be stopped, for it will go on in some part of the world even if banned in another. There may be ways around these problems, if room can be found for a much larger population, and that aspect of the human biospace will be discussed later in the chapter. There are even more troubling aspects of human genetic research, however.

Making Genetic Changes

There is a process of genetic selection acting upon the pool of genes--in every generation of living things most genetic traits are inherited and remain possibilities for transmission to the next, but some do not and thus die out. Of course, genetic selection does not on its own result in the production of anything fundamentally new in succeeding generations, just in variations on the central theme for that life form. Information is selectively lost, not gained, even when speciation results. Even done intelligently (as in plant breeding), selection only allows designers to take advantage of characteristics already inherent in the normal range of genetic variation. Careful selection allows the distribution of traits already present in the population of a life form to be moved toward one end of the existing range. If then left alone, they would tend to regress back to the natural mean. Genetic modifications have the potential to force this selection to become permanent, because undesirable genes would be eliminated altogether.

This is already done with plants and animals, even to the point of generating new species. Is there therefore any reason to suppose that human genetic research would stop with repair and selection? Various "improvements" or "modifications" would certainly be suggested, and no amount of government control could halt such experiments indefinitely. Thus, as with any fundamentally new technology, this one has the potential to be used for what seem to be attractive ends, for what may be frivolous ends, and for ends that seem very threatening.

Possible attractions include further enhancements to intelligence and more extensions of the life span, for instance. A strain of human beings with very large lungs and an altered circulatory system could live in high mountains where the air is thin. Some do this now, so such an ability might fit in the selection category. Perhaps someone would try to develop a human with gills and fins to colonize the oceans, or one with hollow bones and wings to take to the air, or a human with a modified chemistry to live on some hostile planet. Are such things feasible? Not yet, but no one knows at this point they are impossible. In the quest for knowledge, some such things may well be attempted, assuming there are no enforceable limitations placed on genetic research.

243

Page 244: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

What of still stranger alterations in the name of making improvements, such as extra limbs or eyes? Experimenters could try everything from dual sets of sexual organs to new skin colours. Perhaps a docile subspecies with limited intelligence and great strength would eliminate the need for robots or enhanced animals to fill menial positions. Such possibilities may seem shocking, but the point is that at present no one has any idea where genetic research may lead. It may not be either wise or practical to prohibit all such research, but society does have a vested interest in ensuring this work is regulated with codes that have moral/ethical strength beyond the simply legal. Otherwise, human beings may eventually find themselves asking whether a creature derived from their own genetic stock is in fact human--or, worse still, having the question asked of them. At the very least, the question of who owns the rights to new forms of life would have to be reopened. If changes to "lower" forms of life such as plant or animal modifications are patentable, then a degree of ownership is implied. If the same is true of modifications to the human stock, it could lead to the enslavement of the modified humans. It could equally lead to the enslavement of the original human variety by enhanced versions. As for all technologies with potential for enormous benefit, there is equal potential for enormous mischief and harm. Genetic research is a Pandora's box with the lid already off and it may already be too late to effectively regulate it; certainly it is not possible to prohibit it.

The "playing God" objection that was discussed in connection with AI research is also used by critics of human genetic work. As there, it seems to carry little weight any longer. People in the field are usually not conscious of "playing God" in any way, and they are therefore inclined to ignore the argument as false, irrelevant, or meaningless. Perhaps what the objectors really mean is that they believe a Creator intended the creation to be left as humankind found it. But, people who believe they are created in the image of God, yet make a blasphemous thing of specific knowledge and creativity, may not yet have come to terms with the meaning of the creative part of that image in humanity; the accusation has therefore at least some appearance of inconsistency. What is more, making at least selections at the genetic level is not different from the selective breeding that has been the stock-in-trade of plant and animal husbandry for millennia, and that has few objectors today.

Still, the objection has merit, particularly if the genetic technology falls under the total control of the state. In a totalitarian system the idea of designing good docile citizens could be very attractive, for in these systems the state is the deity. Thus "playing God" is a real problem, for such research is not play but deadly serious. For now, these issues must be left open for discussion, but there is a time limit. Choices will have to be faced in the next few years, and it is better to come to grips with the issues before they are presented as fact than after. If a consensus as to what constitutes "good" and "bad" outcomes of genetic research cannot be reached early on, an unregulated chaos could ensue, with consequences that could face humanity with threats every bit as grave as those from nuclear explosives.

What is more, as the level of technology increases, so does its potential to affect all life. Eventually, many people will have the means to single-handedly destroy all of civilization. What can prevent some mad (wo)man from doing so? If

244

Page 245: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

there is no return to a pervasive moral code, such destruction seems likely. Even if there is, how can the consequences of a single rejection of moral codes be policed against, and who would control the police? Some of these issues are examined in fictional form by this author in his Timestream novels. See the web site at http://www.arjay.bc.ca.

What makes regulation difficult is the traditional autonomy of the largely university-based researchers, as well as the large amounts of money involved in commercial aspects of genetic research. Potential economic return for certain animal vaccines, specialized viruses, and modified plant stock is large enough, but opportunities to make money on human genetic manipulations are far more substantial. One means of control that may work is to regulate the sale of products and techniques of such research, much as is now done with chemicals, pesticides, and pharmaceuticals. As experience with illicit drugs has shown, however, if the amount of money to be made in trafficking is large enough, no degree of regulation suffices to stop it altogether.

7.6 Rights, Health Care, and Life Any discussion of genetic engineering leads naturally to questions about what

are the rights of people to benefit from this work. Present-day medical practice is loosely founded on a generally accepted, but often unstated right of all persons to live healthy, normal lives. There are two possible ways of viewing this right. One is to suppose that everyone ought to have the best possible medical and genetic treatments available to bring that person's individual health to an optimal level. A second is to conclude that the human race as a whole should be brought to an optimal health. The danger in the latter approach is that it may also lead to mandating that "undesirable" persons have no right to live.

Improving the human race as a whole through a program of selective breeding and the elimination of those considered undesirable gained great popularity in the early third of the twentieth century under the name of eugenics. The acceptance of this idea was enhanced by the way in which it fit the prevailing model of evolutionary progress. There was great optimism that the human race could take control of its own evolutionary destiny this way, and few voices of concern were raised for the consequences. By the time World War II started, Hitler's program of eugenics was already well under way in Germany, but it was not until the war was over that the horrifying consequences of arbitrarily defining who is acceptably human were seen. State-run eugenics has been anathema ever since, but new medical techniques now mean that individuals could practice a more personal eugenics for their offspring. This apparently attractive option still has the same potential negatives, however, and it would not do to lose sight of those in some euphoric optimism that a new age is dawning for the human race.

On the one hand, selection and modification, as well as effective means of birth control, could well do away with the demand for abortion and infanticide. This would be beneficial for all concerned--child, mother, family, and society. On the other hand, those born before or without the benefit of genetic selection, or whose abilities came to be regarded as inferior would be at a disadvantage. Their genes would not be the latest models. In addition, long life spans will not necessarily solve

245

Page 246: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the problem of caring for the old, who might need more rather than less medical care. A future society could become so obsessed with obtaining and maintaining genetic perfection that individuals of any age who were perceived to fall short could simply be discarded. The state now can permit death at the request of a sufferer--"pulling the plug" on someone who wishes to die in peace. As with other issues, the state that can permit a death can easily assume the power to require the same death. If it has the power to allow certain lives never to develop past the point of discovery of some physical deformity, then it might also claim the power to deny life to any individual for any defect, including economic, political, racial, and religious ones.

Pressures on the medical system lead to questions about when it is appropriate to deny medical treatment. Likewise, economic and demographic pressures conspire to persuade people to limit new life, and abortion or infanticide are used where birth control has not been employed successfully. In addition, the continued existence of humans with limitations caused by genetic defects, accidents or even old age is threatened. All the issues involving life itself are difficult ones; even where the individual involved makes the choice.

Patient Choices

What should a physician do when a terminally ill patient facing painful treatment asks the doctor to withhold further treatment in order to allow a relatively peaceful death? This is a difficult question. Free will and freedom of choice are argued in favour of the patient's freedom to make that choice. Yet, some would say, the doctor is in the position of deciding whether to become an accomplice to suicide. If a woman was about to jump to her death from a bridge, a passer-by would be expected to intervene, to attempt to prevent the suicide, or to call for more help. Most involved would exert themselves in the cause of life, not being willing to give up until she actually jumped, and even then launching an extensive search of the water below in case she lived. If she were to survive, every resource of the medical establishment would be brought to bear to save her life, restore her body to functionality, and provide the necessary counselling to ward off another such attempt on her own life. Shall a doctor do less in the treatment of other patients? If not, what is the essential difference between the two situations, and who decides when that difference exists? Is it more humane to allow an escape from suffering for those who desire it? Or, is the desire to escape from life prima facie evidence of lack of competence, which should therefore be ignored?.

These questions have already been resolved, in the West's legal and medical systems at least. Living wills, in which the testator dictates a do not resuscitate order for extreme eventualities, are now accepted and acted upon in most jurisdictions. However, this has taken place without much debate, and it seems to have escaped the notice of most that if a state has the power to permit a practice, it also has the power to require it.

Some utilitarians who focus on the money issues, and some proponents of a right to die argue that death in terminal illness should be made quick and easy. Some act-ethic moralists would condemn this conclusion, pointing out that cures

246

Page 247: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

might still be possible, and suggesting that participating in another's suicide is not different from murdering the person. One possible conclusion that a consensus moralist could come to is that if the majority of, say, inoperable cancer patients wanted to die, they all should. If this conclusion seems stark, consider a single paralysed patient whose doctor has already participated in assisted suicides in similar situations. It would not be difficult in such circumstances, especially with the permission of anxious heirs, to have the patient declared incompetent and then argue that if the person were able, she would want to die, and therefore must do so. Indeed, such a decision may seem quite utilitarian. A society that had already allowed assisted suicide would have little motivation to enquire about such deaths, and perhaps not much to care about them either.

Such decisions can be even more difficult if a second condition exists that will kill the patient anyway and the (possibly expensive) treatment would only postpone the apparently inevitable. This issue was discussed earlier in the chapter without the complication of the patient's own request for death. When simultaneously faced with such a request as well as a waiting list of patients who can be treated more inexpensively, the pressure to allow or require death increases. There must, some would argue, be some limit on paying for extending the lives of the terminally ill. That there are such limits cannot be disputed. What is in question here is the degree to which active intervention in allowing or encouraging death should be tolerated. Even the most enthusiastic spenders realize that economic considerations ultimately force many life-and-death issues, even if these may be hidden in government appropriations measures and seen as entirely political in nature. It is therefore part of the challenge for new medical technologies to remove as many of the limitations as possible to the extension of productive life, making it cheaper and easier to achieve year by year.

The opposite problem may also arise, for in some cases the technology is available to save the life of a patient, but treatment is refused, perhaps for religious reasons. The doctor, the hospital, the law, and the state must in such cases decide whether the extension of a patient's life is to take precedence over that patient's beliefs. The difficulty is particularly acute when the patient is a child, and it is the parents who are refusing medical treatment. In the case of religious sects refusing blood transfusions for children, the courts have sometimes stepped in and ordered the treatment over those objections. Would they do so for someone old and infirm? Parents have also in some cases been charged with manslaughter when they have refused to seek medical help for life-threatening conditions and allowed a child to die. In other cases, the opposite is done, and permission to rely on such alternatives as faith healing is explicitly written into the laws of some states, with such parents being protected from prosecution.

In either type of situation, the hierarchical ethic of Chapter 3 would insist on the primacy of life, and the making of every reasonable effort to preserve it. However, there would be many who would not accept such an ethical framework and would arrive at the opposite conclusion. The problem for a utilitarian, for example, would be to decide whether there is more good in preserving one life, or more good in alternative uses of the same medical resources. Limits are bound to be reached in some cases, and it may be necessary to force treatment in others, but

247

Page 248: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

great care must be taken in making life and death decisions for other people without their personal and informed consent; for the right to life is the most fundamental of all.

Euthanasia

As already suggested, similar considerations apply to the terminally ill who cannot themselves request a quick death because of a coma or some other circumstance. Proponents of euthanasia would put such people out of their misery, much as they would compassionately shoot a dying horse. They reason that while perhaps extending life might be good, supplying a pain-free death is better. Given the reality of pain and the other pressures cited above, this argument cannot simply be dismissed. An ethical absolutist, on the other hand, is likely to draw the line at "relative good" when it comes to life and death issues. As long as there is any hope, this argument goes, the patient should be kept alive, even at great cost. To the absolutist, death may be an enemy to be fought with all available resources, and its victims to be sorrowfully mourned as casualties in a war. Paradoxically, many religious persons who hold this position believe death to be a release to a new and better kind of life--to be welcomed--even while being fought against as an enemy.

One of the major difficulties with any policy that allows such deaths to be administered has already been mentioned--what the state can once allow, it can at a later time require. People who support the voluntary euthanizing of the aged may one day find the process forcibly applied to them too, for reasons could be found for declaring almost anyone an undesirable or an incompetent.

Infanticide

It was for similar absolutist reasons that in the early days of the Church, Christians collected unwanted infants who had been abandoned by their parents to die of exposure, even though the rescuers then suffered being accused of killing and eating the children they rescued. The Christian view of the sacredness of life prevailed, and for centuries after, infanticide was close to unthinkable--an act that evoked universal moral outrage. In this century it has become respectable again. For instance, at issue at the moment is whether severely damaged or impaired newborns should be left to die without food, water, and treatment, or whether they should be provided with extensive, painful, and costly attention to allow them to live. In China of the 1980s, infanticide was reported to be widespread after the government decreed that couples could have no more than one child. Boys were more desirable than girls, so many female infants were killed. Population pressures as well as political, economic, and racial considerations are potential factors in deciding which infants shall live or die. These have already been decisive in liberalizing the availability of abortion, and it is surely an arbitrary legal fiction to say that a child situated at one end of a birth canal is disposable tissue, and at the other end is a protected human. All the same arguments that allow abortion can therefore be brought to bear on newborn infants, or on children of an older age, or indeed on adults.

248

Page 249: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

While this issue will not go away soon, one major contribution of the new medical technologies may be to render it moot. The goal is to remove from the genetic pool the causes for severe birth handicaps, but it will not be achieved soon, and in the interim there are likely to be renewed calls to do away with "defective" infants and a new insistence that no life at all is better than one lived impaired. Again, ethical absolutists will oppose any such policy, insisting as always that the quality of life is not pre-judgeable or even knowable in another, and that it is a lesser ethical consideration than life itself.

Abortion

The practice of abortion also generates many issues not likely to be settled soon, and it is one on which the medical profession has done a complete about-face in recent years, switching from a long standing view of an unborn child as a patient, to that of it as a disposable appendage of the mother. The debate is sometimes couched in terms of the mother's right to privacy with respect to parts of her own body versus the right of an unborn child to life itself. The mass of cells that will become a child cannot, with current technology, be separated from the mother and live, and in this sense is a part of her. On the other hand, these cells are genetically distinct from her even at the point of conception, and there is therefore a sense in which even the first cell is not part of her body at all. Some regard a particular demarcation point (e.g., end of first trimester) as the start of a distinct human life. To others, any boundaries are purely arbitrary. What is really in dispute is the point at which full human rights ought to be accorded--at birth or at some prior time. Or, do the rights grow gradually with the developing child, and does the ratio of these rights to those of the mother change from zero at first to equal at birth? Does equality come at some earlier time, or at some later time?

Proponents of a women's right to an abortion on demand consider the procedure to be a cheap, safe, and effective way of ensuring that only wanted children are born. Opponents point to the right of the child to life, and also claim abortion to be both physically and psychologically threatening or damaging to the health of the woman. Furthermore, they consider abortion to be reckless of human life in general, and to be murder of a child in particular.

New technologies may enliven the abortion debate even more, for it is possible sometimes to save infants born prematurely at a stage earlier than many others who are aborted. Two surgeons can work side-by-side on two pregnant women, each the same number of months past the point of conception, with one performing an abortion and the other delivering a premature baby. As the ability to live outside the womb (with technological help) is pushed back closer to the point of conception, the medical establishment in particular, and society in general, faces an ethical problem whose difficulty is increasing with time and with the availability of new life-saving techniques. As a result, arguments about the point at which life begins become increasingly irrelevant and the abortion issue becomes more an ethical and political one. That is, the answer to the medical and scientific question "From what point is an unborn child alive?" is now obviously "from conception", so it is now the economic and political question "From what point is an unborn child

249

Page 250: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

human?" that has become the central issue, and North American courts have now answered "not until birth". As we have seen, however, this answer itself raises new questions about what can or should be done to (for) the child before it takes its first breath of air.

New techniques may also take all of the risk out of having an abortion, as they will for many other surgical procedures. It may even become possible to reverse the sterility that is a an occasional side effect. Furthermore, it has already been noted that there will be a tendency to reduce birth rates in the face of increased life spans and to exercise quality control over births as this becomes possible. Three points are worth making:

First, it is not yet possible to discern what are the very long term effects on total population of combining increased longevity and declining birth rates. In developed (and nearly developed) countries, the birth rate is below replacement levels. This would argue for an eventual population decline, except that any substantial longevity increase would overwhelm this trend. Indeed, increased longevity is the main reason for the world's population increase over the last century. It may be over the next as well. Thus, current methods of birth control may be either already more effective than necessary, or woefully inadequate to control population. It is too soon to tell.

Second, abortion-inducing drugs have already been produced. Recent history would suggest that religious protests over such drugs will have no effect on their marketing. Thus, although it may take some time to sort out potential side-effects, it will only be a matter of time before these are available worldwide. The significance of these drugs is that they have the potential to take the matter of abortion out of highly visible hospitals and clinics and make it a decision that can be undertaken entirely in private. Thus, there would be no specific targets to protest against once the sale a drug was approved. In view of the fact that ever fewer doctors are interested in doing abortions, drugs may eventually become the only means of providing them--yet another example of the scarcity of medical resources forcing the adoption of non-surgical procedures (whether one likes the outcome or not).

Third, the technologies considered in this chapter may also be capable of producing cheap and efficient conception control agents for men or women that the state could widely disperse and then require a licence to obtain the antidote. There are several ways in which this could be done. The simplest might be a drug that could cause sterility even in very low doses. Another possibility for the genetic engineer might be a communicable virus like those that cause common colds that would be capable of preventing conception without causing any other symptoms. Since several research teams could build variations on one or both of these themes, it might be expected that at least one of the sponsoring governments involved would release the agent. An antivirus might be as easy to produce, but the opportunity to control it and regulate population would likely be seized upon by most of those involved. After all, it is difficult to imagine some types of government passing up the opportunity to regulate population growth absolutely. Such a development and deployment would imply extensive and intimate control by the state over the lives of citizens, but such things do have a way of coming about, even in Western democracies.

250

Page 251: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Another way to regulate population growth would be to include a sterilizing agent in longevity drugs, or to package sterility and longevity antidotes together. There would have then to be a strong incentive in order to have children, for they would cost parents potential life span. Abortions would cease almost entirely if an enforceable conception licensing scheme were devised. While this might remove some of the population pressures caused by longevity, it would simultaneously change the whole structure of society by cutting off renewal, all but eliminating the family, and promoting a long-term status quo. Could such a scheme be enforced if it were to become technically feasible? It seems likely that an antidote to the agent would quickly become available on the black market--perhaps even supplied by foreign governments bent on destabilizing a country by increasing its population. Moreover, given the record of the West on control of now illicit drugs, it seems hard to imagine the pharmaceuticals suggested here could be so tightly controlled as this. The net result on population could be neutral with the single exception of eliminating unwanted births and therefore removing most of the desire for abortion.

Such a technological "fix" seems to be unsatisfying, but the alternatives are unclear. Neither unlimited population growth nor unlimited abortions are politically, economically, or ethically desirable. The population question must therefore be left unresolved with a technical answer only intimated.

7.7 The Environment and Human Life Human life is lived out in the context of the whole continuum of other life

forms and the physical environment that surrounds them. The industrial age has generally been viewed as an exploitive one insofar as the environment has been concerned. Progress has been the byword, and the bottom lines were the standard of living and the gross national product. Simultaneously, the rapid decline in the agricultural work force and the gathering into cities have isolated industrialized peoples from the natural environment and left them largely unconcerned with harmful changes, except when such issues periodically become fashionable.

The earth is a large place, and its systems have both a great deal of inertia and a massive capability to absorb damage. Nevertheless, there have been severe strains in a number of areas, and it is now clear that the next civilization must continue to develop and deploy a technology of the environment, if it wishes to maintain the earth as a viable living place. Problems have shown up in the quality of the air (acid rain), the water (dead and dying lakes or streams) and the land (erosion, desertification, salt poisoning, and fertility loss). There are also scarcities of strategic minerals, oil, and other energy forms. These problems become most visible in the scars left by open pit mines, in the changed climate and ruined soils from deforestation, in the extinction of entire plant and animal species, and even in the quantity of nonbiodegradable waste floating about on the ocean surface. Cities themselves have largely grown up from old agricultural centres in river valleys, spilling out into the surrounding area and swallowing prime farmland in the process.

The contribution of technology has thus far been negative, accelerating damage to the environment, but this is because the governing model has been exploitive. Moreover, many of the 1960s environmentalists were associated, whether correctly or not, with radical left politics, and this made it easy for

251

Page 252: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

conservatives to discount their legitimate message. Political considerations can be of first importance in facing environmental problems. For example, North American governments are reluctant to tackle solutions to the acid rain problem, so they fund studies to see if it really exists--when it has been known and described in some detail in the literature for over a century. In more recent years, though, environmental groups have successfully called attention to the more spectacular damage and a new model has emerged--one that uses technology in a conserving manner. Gradually, this conserving image is replacing the radical one, and care for the environment is becoming conventional conservative wisdom.

Thus, smoke emissions are now scrubbed in Great Britain, and city air is once more breathable. The same thing will eventually be required of new North American installations, and over time, lakes and forests destroyed by acid rain will probably recover, though perhaps with different species inhabiting them. Likewise, energy sources will in the future likely be required to be clean, giving impetus to research on solar, geothermic, nuclear fusion, and other nonpolluting supplies. At some point, petroleum and coal will no longer be used as fuel, and electricity will be the principal medium for delivering energy. The desire--indeed, the necessity--for a cleaner environment will thus alter many industries and result in further structural changes to society as resource-based industries in certain sectors go out of existence. The political map will likely also be affected, for any current economy that depends on, say, oil or coal production and does not industrialize or otherwise diversify will be seriously impaired.

There will no doubt continue to be a variety of environmental activists for some years--protesting logging, whaling, sealing, habitat destruction, and the experimental use of animals. Although these voices were muted or neutralized somewhat by the 1980s and 1990s concentration on business and the bottom line, their impact will be permanent, for they have expressed the important truth that humanity cannot go on fouling its nest but must come to terms with the fact that the human biospace is part of a complex continuum that must be lived in.

Some environmental groups have in their tactics raised interesting new ethical issues by going beyond civil disobedience to property destruction and violence. Such methods have been criticized even by those who support the causes. Some argue that protesters ought to take a legislative route to make their point, but the more radical environmentalists have claimed that only dramatic action is sufficient to sensitize enough people to the difficulties even to make them public issues. Thus, there have been invasions of labs doing animal experiments; harp seals have been painted red to destroy the commercial value of their pelts; nuclear tests have been interfered with; and a whaling fleet and processing plant have been vandalized to put them out of business. In addition, protesters for a variety of causes throw themselves in front of trains or trucks when they dislike their cargoes; they picket the homes and offices of researchers or politicians who oppose them, and they block roads to proposed mining and lumbering sites or nail ceramic spikes into the trees, and lay down in front of bulldozers to prevent them from clearing land. Regardless of what one thinks about the ethics of these tactics (what is the higher norm that must be obeyed?) there can be little doubt that the

252

Page 253: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

environmentalists have indeed successfully touched a raw nerve of new-found sensitivity to the environment and that the effects will be very long lasting.

They also have going for them that new technologies are indeed likely to be cleaner--at least in the industrialized countries, and provided that clean power sources become available. On the other hand, they have against them that they can be premature or sensationalist in their pronouncements--especially when they offer incomplete or preliminary scientific research to bolster their claims. For instance, that the climate has warmed over the last century is a fact. That it is due to certain gasses causing an alleged greenhouse effect is still speculative; the cause may be sunspot cycles or some other cyclical effect instead. If the latter turns out to be the case, the bad science will prove costly to all environmental efforts.

In any case, the day of the exploitive society may now be coming to an end. If so, all those individuals and institutions aligned with it will decline in influence. This may include some religious institutions that have so allied themselves, taking for example the "subdue the Earth" command of Genesis as exploitive instead of as management responsibility. Political thinking has also often focused upon the immediate economic benefits to be had from industry, however conducted, rather than upon its long term effects. With the new-found realization of the network of biospace dependencies, such voices will no longer be listened to, for people will know that there are many more than the purely short-term considerations to the making of decisions. In an ideal information-based society, decisions would always be made both openly and in a fully informed fashion, and specifically with the effect on the larger environment having been considered. At least, this is the ideal--whether human nature will allow it to be achieved is another matter.

There is also a potential downside to these environmental concerns that must not be neglected, and that is the cost of making suitable changes. Ironically, the cost for the cleanup technology may be so great that only the largest of industrial firms can afford to develop and deploy it. This could have the effect of strengthening the very conglomerates that created many of the difficulties in the first place, at least in the intermediate term. On the other hand, industry could respond to Western environmental concerns simply by moving manufacturing (and its pollution and jobs) to the third world, with negative effects on the Earth as a whole due to increased production and decreased regulation.

In the long term, however, the preservation of plant and animal species, recycling, and a concern for soil conservation and clean air and water will all be part of an environment-conscious ethic of the next civilization. There may even be some who will wish to live at one extreme--indoors, in completely controlled and managed environments. There may be others will want to get back to nature and live in more direct communion with it, but without giving up any of their technological benefits. Both may well be possible, along with as numerous alternative life-styles.

7.8 Building New Environments Much has already been said here and elsewhere about the pressures of

unrestrained population growth. Those who find unpleasant the suggestion that longer life will imply enforced birth control and various other practices will want instead to expand the available physical space for human life. Even the present

253

Page 254: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

world population is having difficulty finding places to live. For example, as countries industrialize they experience the phenomenon of urban expansion. In already heavily populated nations, the growth of a handful of urban centres can be very dramatic, and several more such megalopolis in the developing nations could reach 20 to 30 million in a few years at the current pace. Many of the newcomers are housed in shacks precariously perched on sewage-filled mud or on unstable hillsides. There are no paved streets, lights, running water, official police services, fire departments, or building codes. Yet the slums and barrios of dozens of cities grow by thousands of immigrants from the countryside every day, with no end and little immediate hope in sight. Under such circumstances, the state can easily loose control to anarchy. Criminal elements tend to step in and to become a de facto government. This can be clearly seen in a number of third world countries today, and there is no reason to suppose that the urbanization giving rise to these problems will slow in the foreseeable future.

Nearly the opposite is taking place in cities of the already industrialized nations as they move beyond industrialism to the next stage of civilization. Large old cities--especially industry centres--have lost population in two waves of out-migration. One is the continuing exodus to the lawns, gardens, and golf courses of suburbia. This shift forces relocation of schools, shopping, and some offices as well as the costly extension of transit lines. In this kind of move, people at least remain in the broad surrounds of their original cities. It does cause jurisdictional problems and tends to harm the city core, which is often left with the lowest socioeconomic group, a declining tax base, and neighbourhoods impoverished to the point of destitution. Meanwhile, at the edges, such cities grow together with their neighbours in broad bands of alternating urban centres and suburbs. One can drive hundreds of miles through such areas on the Eastern seaboard of the United States, and a similar situation is developing around the central Great Lakes, in Florida, and in California.

However, other cities, notably in the Midwest, have lost net population to the South and Southwest or to smaller urban centres at some distance from the major cities. In these cases, the central city suffers all the problems mentioned above, and the urban region as a whole cannot compensate economically, for the population has moved too far away.

The net result of these two migrations could be a spreading out of North American population over a much larger percentage of available land, and a dramatic lessening of crowding in large city centres. Suburban areas and new cities gradually develop centres of their own, but these are smaller and somewhat less concentrated than those of the older cities. Better communication and transportation systems and relocation of factory work, once only located near resources or shipping, all contribute to this migration. There are fewer reasons every year for information workers to locate at traditional city centres, and so they move. As communications improve, working out of one's living space becomes more and more feasible, and attachment to cities may lessen further.

Meanwhile, the cities affected by migration from the core see large tracts of former housing and industrial land becoming surplus, and some try to renew and attract counter-migration by making their cores attractive places to live, shop, play,

254

Page 255: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

or tour--even when the people work elsewhere, and especially when they work at home. If some people work where they live, perhaps others can be induced to live where they work. To achieve this, it may be that some present office buildings would become a mixture of offices and apartments. Certainly, new construction and renovation at the core of older cities would have to be radically different in order to make them attractive places once more.

Improved transportation of both short- and long- range types helps to allow such changes and is also driven by them. New technologies for reducing airport congestion and improving takeoff and landing efficiencies are a high priority, for example. Another priority (in North America) is improved high-speed ground transportation technologies for commuters in order to relieve the traffic jams in such cities as Los Angeles and Chicago. At the same time, it will become critical to devise strategies to lessen the impact of the loss of industrial tax base at the city core and to alleviate conditions for those left behind in poverty, with no hope of obtaining jobs or of migrating to places where their prospects might be better. That is, whatever one's ethical framework, there are a large number of factors that have to be traded off and prioritized, and the task is far from simple.

At the same time, new building technologies and a new respect for arable land are driving development in places once considered inhospitable. For instance, mountain sides cannot be cultivated but they can be lived on or in, and an underground house can have many floors, with a large lawn and garden on the roof. Building technology is becoming more and more effective at sealing off living space users from hostile environments. It is now feasible to live comfortably in deserts, on infertile land, or in some of the earth's coldest regions--if population pressure demands. There are vast empty lands in the Canadian north, the Australian interior, and the African and Asian deserts, as well as in mountainous regions in all parts of the world. It may be desirable to cover, heat, live in, and grow food on the Arctic tundra. It may be desirable, say, to run a pipeline from the mouth of the Amazon through the Atlantic and bring abundant water to the Sahara desert. It might become practical to roof over a valley in the Canadian Rockies and build a large city underneath. When population pressures are great enough, technology often can be found to respond to produce new living space--yet another example of the need to find technological solutions to problems caused in part by technology. That is, the doomsday forecast by Malthus may be postponed by the development of still more technique, though it cannot be put off indefinitely if the population continues to rise.

It ought also to be noted that new technology may be required to develop new living space to replace that which has been rendered unusable by older technologies. Even assuming that nuclear war is never the cause of such problems, people may be driven underground by cosmic radiation if, as some suggest, the ozone layer of the atmosphere is any further depleted by the use of chlorofluorocarbons (CFCs) and other pollutants. On a less global scale, overfishing and pollution may force the inhabitants of fishing communities to relocate and take up different work. The same thing happens when acid rain defoliates a commercial forest or cropland. In each case, jobs, people, the environment, and politics play out an intricate dance of interlocking responsibilities and duties complex enough to deeply engage the most sophisticated of ethicists.

255

Page 256: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Perhaps the ultimate in environmental technology would be the ability not just to predict but to manage the weather. Though often wished for and frequently assumed by science fiction writers, this goal has proven elusive, and there is little immediate prospect of much progress toward it. There has not even been agreement on whether the climate is warming or cooling, what the major factors in such changes are, whether human activities have had a great effect, or if there are long term cycles over which little control can be exercised. There is presently a warming trend, and sea levels are rising. Some call this the greenhouse effect and pin the blame entirely on carbon dioxide pollution; others cite sunspot cycles and assert that major climate changes are caused by forces far larger than anything humans have yet deployed. Whether these are short term fluctuations, and whether anything can or ought to be done about them is not known. There is always the possibility that any large-scale attempts to change global climate will make things worse. When a complex dynamic system is ill understood, it is perilous to make dramatic changes to any part. On the other hand, some argue that the industrial society has already made just such major changes, and that these must be reversed before it is too late.

On another note, there may be modest efforts made to establish living places underwater and even off the planet. The former could substantially increase the size of livable areas even in the short run; the latter would have little immediate impact but possibly a dramatic long-term effect. Some suggest that if the mining of raw supplies from the moon and asteroids can ever be done economically and space or moon-based manufacturing becomes feasible, there could be a third industrial revolution that transfers a substantial percentage of human resources and a sizeable population off the planet entirely. Since some manufacturing has already been done in space, it could be argued that this new industrial revolution has already begun. Optimists suggest that facilities in orbit, on the moon, and on various asteroids or artificial planetoids would in all likelihood make the earth a wealthier and more livable place. At the same time, a new frontier of indefinite size would be created and another age of expansion begun. At some point in the distant future, some suggest the earth might hold only half the inhabitants of the entire solar system, and that long before that stage is reached there may well be attempts to reach others. The colonization of space has an important side effect. Once self-sufficient communities exist off the planet, it will no longer be easy to destroy the whole human race in a nuclear war--even if the earth itself becomes uninhabitable. Whether this factor would make war more or less probable is impossible to guess.

On the other hand, more pessimistic voices point out the high cost of doing anything in space, and demand that the money instead be used to improve conditions here on earth. Others don't want space to be used at all, reasoning it will only be exploited as the earth has been. Still others point out there would be little need for a substantial population to leave Earth, as (presumably) automated factories located there would need few human workers to staff them in any case. This illustrates an interesting point--in the long run, profitability will drive all but the most modest of space exploration and colonization. If there are no tangible benefits, the lure of science alone cannot indefinitely sustain the kind of expenditures necessary for such adventures. What is more, the prohibitive cost makes it

256

Page 257: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

infeasible to move any significant percentage of Earth's people out of its deep gravity well. The only way large numbers will populate extraterrestrial regions is to be born there.

Back on earth itself there probably will be advances in genetic engineering and other techniques that improve the ability to feed and clothe a larger population. Other applications of the same techniques have the potential to trigger dramatic changes in living space as well. For example, instead of planting trees, fertilizing them, thinning them, and then cutting them down after fifty years to build houses, it would be much simpler to develop genetically modified trees so that they would grow directly into living spaces. Perhaps various species could be grown as specific types of rooms that could be harvested and joined together in modules to make complete houses.

If that proves too ambitious, there are far less spectacular ways to achieve manufacturing efficiency and modularity. One is by applying mass factory techniques to housing. This is now being done on a small scale, with encouraging results. Houses are built in pieces, trucked to the site, and assembled on a prepared foundation. Widespread use of such methods promises to improve quality, decrease building time, and dramatically lower costs. It would also cause many old trades and professions to vanish, and new ones to come into being. Far fewer blue collar workers would be needed to assemble a house in an even partially automated factory than on the site. On the other hand, there might be a need for used-room salesman and house junkyards. Certainly, these methods would lead to changes in the way people live; tract row houses of older subdivisions would give way to more customized homes on rugged terrain. New transportation and communication methods would be required as well, and all of these would change the physical surroundings--the space part of the biospace.

For the technology in the home itself, there is already a substantial automating trend. This trend can be expected to continue, at least for those homes that "must" have the latest machines. In time, refrigerators, ovens, home heating systems, lighting, and even the distribution of electricity will be microprocessor controlled as part of the invisible infrastructure. One technology with promise is the so-called smart electrical system, wherein outlets for appliances, and telephones for both high and low voltage use are all identical, but power is delivered only as requested by a "smart house" client device plugged in to one of the outlets. This system eliminates shock, short circuits, and multiple hardware and wiring types and is programmable to improve its utility. To some extent, houses may well look very much like they do today, for there are few floor plan styles available that were not four decades ago, and taste in such things tends to repeat cyclically in a manner similar to clothing styles. However, any increase in the number of people working out of their homes would cause a shift to a more functional residential architecture. When both husband and wife were working away from the home, it could be more decorative than functional. If one or both use it as an office, it must have appropriate facilities for work and not just for play. Formal living and dining rooms may tend to be deprecated, and the minuscule dens now included in new construction may grow into useful offices, perhaps with separate entrances. There is

257

Page 258: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

no reason other than zoning bylaws and personal preference why most professions--and these are the model for future work--cannot be practised from the home office.

Another new technology with domestic implications is the use of broadcast energy, such as electromagnetic radiation, to provide operating power directly (no plug) to small appliances such as televisions, radios, and computing devices. Very low power chips are now being manufactured, and prototypes of such devices have been shown. Whether the necessary electricity will be converted from power broadcast here on earth or from stations established in near orbit remains to be seen; the present experimental devices use the radio waves already available. In the home, this technology would reduce consumption of power transmitted by wires, but away from it such devices would be even more important, for they would make many appliances truly portable, with no need for batteries. The most important effect, however, would be the elimination of overhead or underground power servicing, an enormous reduction in costly infrastructure required by industrial age housing. Removal of this requirement would also lessen the need for houses to be clustered in urban subdivisions, further reducing the need for cities in the information society. What would be the health implications of using broadcast power is unknown; there are those who claim deleterious effects from levels already present in radio, television, and cellphone transmission.

Other technologies not yet guessed at will subsume some of the ones discussed here or render them irrelevant before they develop. It is difficult to see exactly how market forces will drive them, but it is worth observing that population pressures are pressing. Such pressures in the past have only been reduced in a limited number of ways. Three of the oldest ones are war, which today could destroy the whole earth; famine, which might be eliminated with international cooperation; and plague, which it is hoped will be eliminated altogether. Other ways are wholesale abortion, infanticide, euthanasia, and genocide, all of which are at worst abhorrent or at best problematical. Another way is birth control, but society may well hesitate at making this compulsory. The last method is to continuously expand the available living space by creating new frontiers and new livable areas in the old living spaces.

Of these options, most are unacceptable in any global strategy with a claim to an ethical base or are unenforceable even by the most totalitarian of governments. Only the methods of expanding living space seem workable in the medium term, and even these will generate new problems that cannot now be foreseen. However, increasing living space might postpone some of the harsher alternatives and the need for the less desirable forms of population control. New living space and the technology to achieve it and use it effectively may also bring other important benefits. The very existence of new frontiers could provide a refreshment and revitalization, new kinds of innovation, and an outlet for the creative and restless. It might also help prevent stagnation in a dreary status quo, because it would provide for fresh starts, new opportunities, and a place for youth and enthusiasm--all of which are in jeopardy if the future were to hold only a stable population of gradually increasing life span. Moreover, it would postpone, perhaps forever, Ellul's amorphous totalitarianism of maximal technique, for it would ensure that expansion and change were the prevailing models rather than efficiency alone.

258

Page 259: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is important to realize, however, that deployment of new technologies for the creation and improvement of human living space has an effect on the earth as a whole. Animal species are displaced or extinguished, natural vegetation is destroyed, soils are paved over and made forever useless, and the climate itself is altered. For example, it was once conventional wisdom that large hydroelectric power dams were an unmixed blessing for the state that built them. They would improve living conditions for ordinary people, attract industry, and provide much-needed downstream benefits in the form of flood control. However, in some cases where large areas were flooded, the lack of downstream overflow reduced fertility and increased salinity, industry still found conditions unattractive, and silt buildup behind the dam ensured that it would have a very short life. The High Aswan dam built by Egypt with Russian help has all these problems and is also contributing to the reduction in size of the Nile delta, the fertile bread basket of that nation.

In the future, it will become more important at all times to consider long-term environmental effects of building large housing projects, converting land to other uses, or constructing massive utilities. There will be more people to accommodate, but there will also be more at risk when things go wrong. Moreover, advances in habitat technology in the affluent West will not go unnoticed in the rest of the world as it struggles with the older problems of wide-scale poverty and continuing urbanization. In an effort to catch up, there will be pressure to take short-cuts--parks and wildlife preserves could be threatened, and the very magnitude of short-term people problems will ensure that long-term considerations are de-emphasized. While it will always be impossible for the West to solve the people problems of the third world by donating money (because such difficulties are cultural and relate to a state of civilization), it may be possible to assist in the financing of park and wildlife preservation until such time as the industrializing nations can afford or are ready to use other help. Whether such a global view of the environment will ever be politically feasible in the West is another matter, but highly targeted aid of this type at least has a higher probability of accomplishing its goals than do unspecified handouts of money.

These and other considerations lead once more to the observation that new civilizations are both enabled by and subsequently demand new techniques, even while the new techniques bring mixed blessings. They have great potential for raising the standard of living and human comfort, but an equal potential for causing long-term deleterious effects. The challenge is to achieve the benefits and plan to minimize the harm. Such planning has not always been done in the past, but it cannot be done without in the future.

7.9 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Human life is lived out in the context of both a physical space and a time span. This biospace also has various quality aspects. Numerous issues affecting both were discussed in this chapter. New surgical and diagnostic techniques have proliferated in recent years, greatly increasing the number of treatable problems

259

Page 260: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and simultaneously generating questions of facilities, cost, and appropriateness of treatment. If medical techniques are to become universally available, various new techniques must be found to reduce cost, people, and facility pressures. Some such new techniques being developed are those to do cell-level treatment by tailoring bacteria or DNA to produce new drugs and molecular machines, called nanomachines. It is hoped that such machines can effect repairs, conquer communicable diseases, reduce the need for surgery, and prolong life.

Genetic engineering may also be used to improve food supplies, reduce defects, and enhance many desirable traits. It may also be used to change plant and animal species or even human beings dramatically. Some benefits or difficulties with such technologies were considered, including the effect of changing technology on the right to life.

Finally, the space aspects of human life were considered, and it was pointed out that the creation of new living spaces on earth and off could both alleviate population pressures and supply new frontiers to prevent technical stagnation and postpone the totalitarianism of the efficient.

Discussion Questions

1. Explain the term "biospace".2. What are some of the reasons that nonsurgical medical methods ought to

be preferred over surgical ones? Give specific examples where one or the other choice may be necessary in the long term and others of situations where nonsurgical techniques ought to completely replace surgical ones.

3. Suppose you are in charge of an agency responsible for a medical insurance scheme run by the state. Which (if any) of the following treatments should the plan pay for, or not pay for, and why?

a. Open-heart surgery on an 85 year old, when average life span is 77. Does it make a difference if average life span is 150?

b. An experimental procedure (40 percent chance of success) to remove a tumour from the brain of an infant who has otherwise an 80 percent chance of dying within a year.

c. The surgery in b when without it the child would have impaired hearing and sight but otherwise live normally.

d. The surgery in b performed in another country at a cost higher than keeping a bed in a hospital in the home country for an entire year.

e. A sex-change operation for a patient who claims to be in great distress over being in the wrong kind of body.

f. Plastic surgery to remove small and harmless but unpleasant looking growths from the face of a teenage boy.

g. A liver transplant for a boy whose body has already rejected two livers and whose older brother died after unsuccessful surgery of the same type.

h. Sterilization (tubal ligations and vasectomies) for those who wished to have no further children but have no organic malfunction.

i. Tubal or ovarian repairs (30 percent success rate) for a woman who wanted to bear a first child.

260

Page 261: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

j. Surgery in i for a woman who already had two children; five children; ten children.

k. An in vitro fertilization ("test-tube baby") for a couple who are infertile.l. A new and experimental drug whose preliminary tests indicate may relieve

some AIDS symptoms and postpone death as much as a year but whose safety and side effects are unknown. A year's supply is estimated to cost $30,000 per person.

m. A $30 000 pacemaker for an 85-year old woman.n. Radiation treatments and/or costly surgery for an 80-year old man with

prostate cancer.4. Discuss the idea of dispersing a 100 percent effective (and otherwise

known harmless) birth control agent in the water or atmosphere, with a state-licensed anticontrol agent being available.

5. Suppose it became possible to grow a clone in a nutrient vat from a person's own DNA and then transplant the cloned brain into a new, youthful body (all at great expense). Under what circumstances should this be allowed, if at all?

6. Suppose a simple, cheap chip implant became available that would allow the blind to regain their sight with a video device. What if some blind people do not wish the operation? Should they be required to have it, so as to reduce the burden of their care on society? Should their disability tax benefits be denied if they refuse it?

7. There is already a wide medical gap between the developed and underdeveloped nations of the world, including a substantial gap in life expectancy. What would happen if this gap widened to 100 years?

8. Ought longevity treatments, when they become available, be provided to everyone--including, say, the poor of third world nations--if the consequences are greatly increased population pressure, and possible famine? Even in countries with little such pressure, ought such treatments be limited to those who can "earn" them? Be sure to say what you mean by earn.

9. A hospital has a wealthy patient who has been comatose and on life-support systems for five years with no discernible change in condition. The man's family approaches the hospital and asks for the support to be removed so he can die in peace. The hospital refuses at first, citing the fact that brain waves are still present, though severely impaired. A family member cites the patient's own expressed desire for release from such a state, but can offer no written proof. What should be done?

10. Does it make any difference to your answer in question 9 if:a. the hospital desperately needs a liver for another patient who will surely die

without it and the comatose man's liver is a perfect tissue match?b. the man's family suggests it will give a large sum of money to the hospital--

enough to allow a new surgery to be established wherein many lives can be saved in a year?

c. the comatose patient is a Nobel scientist; the prime minister of Canada; a convicted rapist?

11. Discuss the pros and cons of establishing an organ bank of spare body parts for transplants. If it is done, should it be public, non-profit, or commercial?

261

Page 262: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

12. If genetic engineering could triple intelligence, should the requisite treatments be compulsory?

13. Which, if either, genetic-engineering project should be undertaken: (a) enhancement of domestic animals to enable them to perform menial tasks or (b) the development of "subhumans" for the same reasons. Explain.

14. Suggest several other new environment-enhancement technologies in addition to those discussed in the chapter.

15. What are some ways in which the human environment might be engineered, other than those discussed in the chapter? (Good and bad, pros and cons.)

16. Discuss the pros and cons of building new habitat (a) on the ocean floor, (b) in the Russian or Canadian north, (c) in the Sahara desert, (d) on the Moon, or (e) in outer space.

17. Which has a higher priority: (a) plant and animal genetics with the end of improving food supply or (b) human genetic research with the end of repair, selection, or improvements? Explain.

18. You are a nurse in an elementary school in a close-knit rural community and become aware of various medical and other problems. Which of the following do you report to the authorities? Explain your answers.

a. A child who often has severe bruises and lacerations on the arms, legs, and buttocks. The child seems not to be under any stress and has a reputation for clumsiness. You must weigh the consequences of not reporting a possible case of child abuse against those of becoming a false accuser.

b. A child who brings no lunch to school and who is always hungry. You know that the parents care for the child but have very little money. Yet the child may be apprehended and taken from them if you report this case.

c. A child with a medical condition (spine curvature, poor eyesight or hearing) that is debilitating but not life-threatening but that the parents cannot afford to have treated or refuse to have treated for religious reasons.

19. You are a hospital nurse with many years of experience on duty with a doctor who is a recent medical school graduate. An emergency patient comes in and the doctor orders tests but leaves one out that you know ought to be done. Do you order the test, exceeding your authority, if (a) the doctor has by now gone home and cannot be reached or (b) you bring it to her attention and she dismisses your concern as unimportant.

20. Discuss the problems of medical diagnosis as they relate to cost, time, facilities, and the possibility of a malpractice suit.

21. What authority ought the state have to (a) permit, (b) require, or (c) forbid various medical procedures? To what extent ought this to be done in defiance of, say, the religious beliefs of the patients, or their parents? Be specific and give an ethical argument to justify your conclusions.

22. Suppose that advanced medical technology made a fetus able to be maintained outside the womb from the moment of conception to the normal end of gestation.

a. What effect would this have on the abortion debate?

262

Page 263: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

b. Should public funds pay to allow infertile couples to use this technology to have children?

c. Should public funds pay for women to use this technology in order to avoid the inconvenience of pregnancy?

d. Should such technology be required for all births and pregnancy be forbidden as too hazardous?

23. The harmful effects of poisonous substances such as tobacco and alcohol are well documented. In view of this, discuss the implications of forbidding advertising in such products. Is the value of free speech more important than the value of deprecating the use of such products?

24. Which is preferable, to attempt to prevent trafficking in mind-altering drugs altogether or to make such drugs legal and freely available and treat the consequences? There are ethical, medical, and economic issues here. You might start with alcohol and tobacco and go from there.

25. One way of reducing medical costs is to transfer some techniques and responsibilities from expensive doctors to other less-expensive medical personnel. Discuss the benefits and limitations of this from ethical, medical, and economic standpoints. In particular, consider the potential responsibilities of nurses, nurses' aides, orderlies, technicians, and other hospital staff.

26. It was remarked in the text that a potential advantage of colonizing space is the survival of humanity in the event of global nuclear conflict. Is this really the case, or would such colonies themselves be added as targets? Indeed, would the very existence of such colonies make nuclear conflicts more or less likely?

27. Research the use of frozen embryos in livestock breeding programs. Now consider their use in human reproduction. Suggest several situations in which they could be employed, and then consider the ethical, legal, and any other problems that arise from this technique. On balance, is this a useful and desirable technique?

28. Research and discuss the issue of patenting new life forms developed in the laboratory. What stand have the courts taken thus far? To what extent do you think new life forms ought to be patentable? Answer for plant, animal, and human-derived genetic material.

29. Research the use of animal organs in human transplant cases. What are the advantages and disadvantages to such work from a medical and ethical point of view?

30. Under what circumstances, and for what groups of people ought the law to mandate periodic checks for the use of drugs? When the law itself does not so mandate, should employers do it themselves?

31. A number of Canadian Aboriginals still make their living as trappers. In response to the concern of animal rights activists, Great Britain proposed new legislation mandating the labelling of Canadian furs with a warning that the animals may have been caught in leg-hold traps. The intended effect of the law was the elimination of such trapping in Canada. Critics respond that a secondary effect would be massive unemployment among one of Canada's poorest groups. Discuss the ethics of this situation, giving particular attention to the relative rights of the trappers and the animals.

263

Page 264: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

32. In the course of the discussion on scarce medical resources, the text made the statement: "Neither is it easy to argue that a woman has any fundamental right to bear children." Develop an argument for or against such a right. Can your argument be applied to support or deny (as the case may be) a parallel right to not bear children? Why or why not?

33. Which is a higher priority, and why--to spend public money on researching the causes of AIDS or to spend it on cancer research?

34. Determine how much money your government puts into research on prostate cancer and breast cancer. Now, what are the incidences of both in men and women, respectively? Do expenditures match? Should they?

35. Which is more important, and why--space exploration, or poverty relief? Or, is there a link between spending on one and not the other?

36. Ought a state to permit (to encourage?) the use of suicide to reduce medical costs and keep the population down? If you say "no," how do you deal with those who are terminally ill, in great pain, and costing the state large sums of money to maintain alive? If you say "yes," how do you deal with the young and healthy who commit suicide and leave behind small children and a destitute spouse? In either situation, how would you deal with the case if the potential suicide were a renowned cancer researcher on the verge of a significant breakthrough?

37. Research the contention that population pressures are the result of poverty, and that raising the standard of living will eliminate these pressures.

38. Suppose that a government determines its territory has become overpopulated to the point where its people are at risk from starvation. Is an enforced birth control program justifiable?

39. Suppose that a government determines its territory has become underpopulated to the point where its national identity is at risk of extinction. What measures can it legitimately take to increase its population?

40. Propose and defend against the alternatives a solution of your own for (a) the problem of medical scarcity (b) population pressures on food supplies and living space.

Bibliography

Asimov, Isaac. Science Past--Science Future. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1975.

Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press, 1986 Drexler, K. Eric and Peterson, Chris. "Nanotechnology". Analog, (Mid-

December 1987): p48-60.Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers. New York: Macmillan, 1986 Geisler, Norman L. Ethics: Alternatives and Issues. Grand Rapids, MI:

Zondervan, 1971.Henry, Carl F. H. Christian Personal Ethics. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1957.Kelly, Northrup. Legal Issues in Nursing. St. Louis, MO: C.V. Mosby, 1987.Kenny, Martin. Bio-Technology--The University-Industrial Complex. New

Haven, CN: Yale University Press, 1986.Minsky, Marvin. The Society of Mind. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1986.

264

Page 265: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Montgomery, John Warwick. Human Rights and Human Dignity. Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1986.

Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner Books, 1984. Toffler, Alvin. The Third Wave. New York: Morrow, 1980.

Internet resources:

Biotechnology Information Centre. <http://www.nal.usda.gov/bic/

265

Page 266: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 8Technology and Economic

Institutions

Seminar - "Well, who would you buy a used car from?" 8.1 Foundations of Business and Economics 8.2 Technology, Business, and Economies 8.3 Wealth in the New Era 8.4 Technology and Business Organizationsg 8.5 Financial Techniques in the New Economy 8.6 Business Ethics and Technology 8.7 Summary and Further Discussion

8.1 Foundations of Business and Economics The development of human societies through the various phases from hunter-

gatherer through agrarian and industrial to the present information age has been accompanied by--and on occasion driven by--the techniques of business and economics as much as by any other kind. Early economies were based on transactions as informal and unregulated as the peoples who undertook them. Surplus fish might be bartered for firewood, meat, or berries. Metal and arrows might be traded for clothing. Rates of exchange for one transaction, if they were remembered at all, had no necessary bearing on other barters in the surrounding neighborhood, or even on those conducted by the same individuals at a later date, and no records were kept except mentally. Each exchange was unique and set its own rules, and there was no notion of profit and loss in any "bottom line" sense.

Even hunter-gatherers sometimes developed more elaborate economies with the passage of time. The division of labour into hunting, weaving, gathering, administering, transporting, war making, and spirit consulting necessitated the development of formal, if unwritten, sets of rules for trade and commerce and eventually caused the introduction of various media for exchange, that is, currency. These could be hunted objects such as teeth or hides, gathered objects such as shells, stones, flints, or metals, and even manufactured objects such as arrows, cured foods, or beaded belts. For example, for more than a century the currency of British North America was the beaver pelt. The prices of guns, whiskey, utensils, blankets, and other trade goods were all measured in these furs. In the case of blankets, a number of colored bars called "points" were woven into one side of the

266

Page 267: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

blanket to indicate its price. Thus, one spoke of a "three point" blanket or a "five point" blanket, and this meant that it cost three or five beaver pelts, respectively.

There were also rules of thumb for testing the quality of the trade goods. For example, to prevent traders from cheating on the alcohol content in the whisky, those to whom it was offered would spit a portion into the fire. If the drink was of sufficiently high proof, the fire would flare up; otherwise it would not--thus the origin of the term "firewater."

Agrarian societies had relatively more complex trading problems to solve, for by their very nature they produced local surpluses of foodstuffs that had to be taken to distant markets. Surpluses, the lifeblood of those societies, fed citizens, armies, and distant peoples. Surpluses also fueled the search for trade routes to exotic lands and their goods, creating further trading complexities. These societies all developed metal-based exchange media in order to create smooth running and convenient business environments. They also developed the means to keep permanent records, taxation, corporate partnerships, trading cartels, sophisticated transportation, and international trade routes. In addition, the economies of agrarian societies came to depend more and more on government, for only the state was strong enough to protect trade routes, guarantee the value of currency, settle disputes, and regulate the growing techniques of the economy.

The industrial age brought with it a greater dependence on capital accumulation and therefore on the means of recording these accumulations. Thus, double-entry bookkeeping was added to the techniques of accounting, which began to become systematized and regulated, that is, to become a collection of formal techniques. For the same reason, banks were developed to assist in capital accumulation on a large enough scale to finance industrial undertakings--for some had grown too large to be within the means of any single private individual. Banks made it possible for both the nobility and the wealthy middle class to loan money to industrialists without direct participation in or even knowledge of the actual use to which it was being put. The anonymity of the capital pool allowed the nobility to profit from industry without the "taint of trade." It allowed others a relatively safe return on investment by virtue of the diversification of the lending institution.

Organizational techniques for the conduct of business also developed. These included limited liability companies, corporate groupings, and holding or investment companies. A variety of state-run enterprises also sprang up, some operated directly by governments, and others through stock holding partnerships with private enterprises. Still others were maintained at a fictional arms length by the state as "crown corporations." In some cases, only the state could undertake a venture, because only it could risk sufficient capital--both because of its power to accumulate such funds, and because of its lack of accountability to shareholders.

Flexibility and liquidity were improved, as were the means of raising still larger capital sums, by the introduction of publicly traded stocks and bonds and by the subsequent development of technical apparatus needed to support such trade in the form of stock and bond markets, brokerage houses, regulatory authorities, and so on. In the industrial age, these trading enterprises have sometimes grown to enormous proportions, occasionally taking on the status of international

267

Page 268: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

conglomerates or monopolistic cartels that in some cases were more powerful than the states of which they were nominally citizens.

At the same time, the state itself has become progressively more involved in trade and commerce, regulating such conduct to the minutest detail and even entering the marketplace directly on its own behalf. When large corporations have failed, governments have sometimes bailed out the owners and employees by taking over the operation, an action that would have been beyond the ability, or beneath the interest, of even the largest groups of private investors. In some situations, governments have felt compelled to intervene to force the breakup of very large companies into smaller entities. In all such cases, the governments involved have had to walk a tightrope between the need to manage the economy and the danger of taking it over entirely--a danger clearly illustrated by the bankruptcy and collapse of the former Soviet Union and its client states. The public-sector economy is important, but no market forces exist within it and it has therefore relatively little incentive to be efficient, unless the state itself approaches bankruptcy.

By the late twentieth century, the systematic and methodical application of management technique to business and the economy in most developed parts of the world was widespread and very advanced. At the same time, Western democratic governments' economic involvement and interference in their economies was scarcely less than what had been attempted in Eastern Europe, through such control achieved far more success in the West in terms of material benefits for the majority of citizens.

The information age owes its existence in large part to the freedom of individuals to innovate, to employ venture capital, and to operate as entrepreneurs. The ability of freely flowing capital to back new ideas and make them winners in the marketplace before any government has been able to respond with new regulations has been critical in the development of computer hardware and software, communication systems, the Internet, medical and other technologies. Major developments in all these fields have taken place primarily in countries like the United States, where new things are freely allowed until they become subject to regulation.

Revolutions are periods of rapid change; they do not take place unless conditions allow such change. Thus the information age cannot even start unless information can flow freely from one individual to another--a state of affairs that still exists in the West, but did not under the closed economies of the former Soviet Union, where new ideas were routinely forbidden until regulations were changed to allow them. The inability of these nations to compete in a rapidly changing world, and their subsequent disintegration, also illustrates that it is not change, however rapid, that endangers a people, but stagnation.

In each phase of economic development thus far, a certain level of technique has been required before the next stage began. For example, an agrarian society must trade and will not thrive unless that trade becomes international in scope. An industrial society requires banks and cannot finance its enterprises without them. Ultimately, the growing complexities of the industrial age brought forth the

268

Page 269: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

automation of both production and record keeping. Thus was born the computer--the characteristic and necessary technology for the information age.

Like the others before it, the information age not only has been accompanied by a transforming technology that in itself necessitates the rise of many new enterprises and the demise of those made obsolete, but also has produced fundamental changes in society and in the attitudes of citizens. It has therefore demanded new ways of viewing the conduct of business and the management of the economy. These changes will result in many "winners" and "losers" among individual business enterprises, various corporate sectors and among national economies. Some corporations and peoples are in a much better position than others to exploit the new paradigms and become the next era's economic and political leaders. The remaining sections of this chapter give a more detailed examination of a few of these issues.

8.2 Technology, Business, and Economies Each change in the characteristic technology of a given society results in a

shift in economic activity and power. For example, those skills or techniques that are most highly valued in an agricultural society are much less at centre stage in its industrial successor, while those of the hunter-gatherer, while they still exist, fade altogether from significance. Businesses that depend on the importance of a particular form of trade or technique may find their very existence jeopardized when new technologies or even new trading routes and patterns come to predominate. Such alterations are always necessary whenever technology changes, for some countries will have the now required resources in greater abundance, will better develop the new techniques, or will be more strategically located than others. Indeed, those peoples most securely wedded to the previous technologies--and most successful with them--may well be the most reluctant or unable to change. They may have, in human and other terms, the poorest resources for moving into the following age. On the other hand, countries that are able to use the new technologies to bring the old ones up to date, then move on a large scale into the new are those that prosper when changes come.

When the industrial age dawned, the principal trade was in food, clothing, spices, precious stones, and metals. As machine-based industry grew in importance, these older markets all continued to exist and even enlarged in absolute terms. However, they declined in importance relative to the overall economy, which was growing many times faster. Eventually, the trade in consumer goods and in the raw materials required to produce them took on an importance that dwarfed the older economy in volume, value, and number of people involved. Those enterprises that remained in older types of trade were required to become more efficient in order to retain investment capital, as well as to release the large number of employees needed by the new industries. Thus, new farming technologies grew up side-by-side with and benefited from new industrial techniques. Farming transformed into a type of industrial activity in its organization, machinery, and prerequisite education. The flow of people and money to new economic dominators was disruptive to the degree

269

Page 270: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

that individual businesses either adapted to the new conditions or died. Meanwhile, overall gross national product in the industrializing nations grew at a rapid pace, as did the disposable income and standard of living of all their citizens. The key was the ability to increase productivity dramatically in virtually all sectors of the economy simultaneously. At the same time, provision of transportation and communications themselves became a major industry, as has the provision of information services in the Fourth Civilization.

Profile On . . . Business Changes

What business am I in?o Am I a hunter-gatherer or a food supplier? If the latter, can I become a

farmer as well?o Am I a farmer who takes my produce to market or am I in the transportation

business? If the latter, could I establish a distribution network?o Do I make bicycles and horse-drawn buggies, or am I a vehicle

manufacturer? If the latter, could I make the transition to building cars and trucks?o Do I run a telephone company or an information infrastructure? If the latter,

could I establish Metalibrary facilities?o Do I loan money, or do I assemble capital? If the latter, could I arrange

financing for multi-trillion dollar projects involving a network of organizations?

Where Should I be Located?o If I am a hunter gatherer, I need to live and work where the animals happen

to be on any given day in order to survive.o If I am a farmer, I need to live and work where the soil will allow me to grow

food and the transportation routes will allow me to sell it.o If I am in the transportation business, trade and travel routes and population

concentrations are critical factors in the location of my work.o If I am in the food distribution business in the late industrial age, my location

is divided between producing and consuming areas, and includes everything between.

o If I am in sales, my location is wherever my customer is.o If I distribute goods and information via the Metalibrary, do I need even to

think of myself as being located anywhere, or is the very concept of a place of business obsolete?

The Future of Economic Institutions

Transitions of a similar nature are now taking place on an even larger scale as industrial paradigms give way to those of the information age. The manufacture and distribution of consumer goods will continue to be important into the indefinite future, though the nature and sophistication of such goods will change with startling rapidity. Likewise, the production and distribution of foodstuffs must continue as well. That is, the basics cannot be discarded, though both these sectors will continue to shrink in relative importance to the overall economy. Manufacturing and

270

Page 271: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

food production will both lose even more jobs than they already have to the service and information sectors, though this shift will be more obvious in manufacturing because it has recently been relatively larger than agriculture. Even the latter will undergo wrenching changes as it too adopts the tools and techniques of the information age. The workers of both sectors will continue to need higher skills than ever, while they simultaneously decline in numbers. Reductions in employment in these sectors will be achieved in part by extensive robotization as many manual forms of labour are turned over once and for all to machines. In the same way as farming became industrialized, both it and industry will be remade in the image of the next age.

Successful manufacturers in the post-industrial age will continue to switch rapidly from product to product as their research and development departments improve on or replace the old and as their public relations arms either detect or create changes in consumer tastes. Because computerized design and manufacturing of goods can so easily be re-programmed, lead time for bringing new goods to future market becomes much shorter. In addition, it will be more cost effective than in the past to order short production runs of specialized items, perhaps even to the point of manufacturing single pieces to customer's personally ordered specifications. Thus, variety of goods increases, within broad standard categories. It will still be possible for small companies that carefully select niche markets to compete with larger ones on even terms, though it may take some time for the prices of manufacturing robots to fall to the point of being affordable by the smaller firms. There will be a continuing increase in the volume of goods ordered through electronic shopping malls that collect subscribers' orders and send them direct to manufacturers, thus eliminating wholesale and retail middlemen. Improvements in efficiency and price to the end-user could be very substantial, because from 30 to 70 percent of the retail cost of some goods represents post-manufacture markup. This disintermediation or exclusion of the middle man is an important trend in the information age, as it places manufacturers in direct contact with their customers for the first time since the agrarian age.

Everyone is connected to everyone else, but the chains that form those connections are getting shorter.

Ultimately, however, service and information sectors, and manufacturers supporting them, will dominate other sectors as much as industry came to overshadow agriculture in the past. More goods may well be manufactured, and they may be cheaper and more sophisticated, but their making will employ fewer people, and this part of the economy will contribute less obviously to everyday life. Except when they take the time to design their own, people will buy and use consumer goods as they now do food, that is, with little thought for or understanding of the means by which such goods come to their hands, since few people will have direct contact with those processes except at the retail and delivery (i.e., service) stages. It could become as rare to be or even to know an assembly-line worker as it is today a full-time farmer. In other terms, the manufacture and distribution processes will become higher level (more invisible)

271

Page 272: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

abstractions, passing out of sight and out of mind as things many people think consciously about. Perhaps "hobby factories" could develop, much as hobby farms have, to provide outlets for a certain kind of nostalgia and a source for hand-made goods for specialty markets, or as some kind of tax shelter.

Capital will still be needed for the extraction of raw materials and for the establishment of factories--even those run by robots--but much less money would be spent on operating costs because of the relatively lower numbers of salaries paid. These funds would go instead into shareholder profits, research and development, and large-scale capital-intensive projects. Medical research and technology, information systems, communications, transportation, the building of new habitat on earth, and the colonization of space could become the dominators of the large capital economy and the most visible vehicles for the business of doing business on a grand scale.

Some of these teraprojects would require concentrations of capital orders of magnitude larger than those arranged by the wealthiest tycoons of the industrial age. This need could result in even larger banks and multinational corporations and even more government involvement, for these institutions would also need to grow to meet such challenges. At the same time, however, the rapid economic changes taking place are catching many industrial giants unprepared, creating many new opportunities for individual entrepreneurs and small companies, if for no other reason than that a small number of people can reach decisions faster than can a large number. Some of these enterprises are in turn becoming the middle-sized and larger corporations of a decade or two later. Change opens up numerous opportunities for small-scale business, so one could predict that numerous and dramatic changes could cause the average size of business enterprises to shrink for some time, reach some equilibrium, and not begin to grow until a new stability emerges (if one does).

In other words, there are collectivizing and individualizing trends in tension here as well. Another kind of equilibrium could be reached if manufacturing and financing concerns formed temporary project-oriented partnerships on an item-by-item basis, rather than merging into permanent and enormous conglomerates.

Despite a proliferation of small companies, large enterprises will have to operate on a scale never before seen, and this will require new financing techniques to make sufficient capital available. Just as the introduction of stocks broadened participation in business during the industrial age, new instruments would have to be devised to create larger and broader-based capital pools than ever before. Many ordinary citizens, companies, and governments will probably have to have a stake--even if only through mutual funds--in such things as space-based industries, biochemical research and sales, land reclamation, the Metalibrary, the robotization of industry, and a variety of transportation, communications, and habitat projects. The result may well be that even more international commercial enterprises will transcend national interests to the point that people will have more feeling of loyalty to and involvement in the companies in which they own shares than they have an attachment to the countries in which they reside. For the increasing number who work as single entrepreneurs under service contracts to make a living, corporate ties will be entirely proprietary. The employees that businesses do have

272

Page 273: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

will more often be either part owners or independent contractors, for the times of viewing labor as a vast pool are now past and the day of the professional worker has dawned. This professionalizing of the work force focuses attention on the individual rather than on the mass of workers and may well create an economy and social values that are more individualistic in many aspects of life.

The Question of Size

It is worth observing that there may be an upper limit to the size of a company as a single financial or structural entity, for some governments have acted strongly in recent years to break up large concerns into smaller ones, acting in what they believed to be the best interests of the public. In the past, such divestitures had widespread popular support on the theory that giant size and monopolies automatically produce predatory behavior. Classic U.S. cases are the breakup of Standard Oil early in the century and the more recent creation of the Bell group of companies from the former ITT holdings. It is too soon to judge the results of the latter action, or of the blocking of proposed mergers in other fields. By the late 1990s Microsoft had grown to be the most dominant company in the software world, and also became the target of successful antitrust suits, though political considerations following a change of government may have precluded applying appropriate penalties for the illegal activities. It is also worth noting that very large companies sometimes break themselves into a number of entities based on geographical or market sector considerations, so as to gain efficiencies and maximize shareholder value. A case in point is the giant Canadian Pacific Railway, which in the late 1990s re-invented itself as several non-overlapping entities, allowing each to concentrate on a specific market sector.

Even if it is the case, however, that companies were never individually allowed to grow beyond a certain size, they may still form multi-trillion dollar capital pools through use of corporate linkings and partnerships. After all, each expansion of the scope of the economy has required a corresponding increase in the size of capital pools to serve the growing market--just as it has required a larger transportation and communication sector. The difference is that such partnerships need not be permanent, but could instead be temporary and flexible--large versions of the metaperson. Some formalization of international cooperations of specialist firms or of individual professionals could provide the alliance a formal identity. These entities could be corporations whose stakeholders are other (possible personal) companies (a practice already common for longer-term entities). Though not necessarily large in themselves, the conglomerate could have an enormous supporting structure.

Suggestions for Large Projects

Among the more remarkable proposals (fictional and otherwise) that would take large sums of money, people, and other resources:

o reclaim large deserts such as the Sahara for living space,

273

Page 274: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o build domed cities under the ocean,o build a circular dam in mid-Ocean, pump out the water behind it, and build a

new nation-city within the dam walls,o construct an elevator to near-earth orbit,o construct cities in space, o explore the solar system and beyond,o build colonies on the Moon, Mars, Venus, and a moon of Jupiter,o build a pollution free power source/ transmission facility in space,o mine the asteroids, o build solar energy power plants in space to transmit energy to Earth,o establish the full Metalibraryo move manufacturing to non-habitable locations underground, inside

mountains, to space, or to the moon,o not only map the human genome, but find out what every gene does,o explore the Solar system and beyond.

Some of these may never come to pass, but others on a similar scale surely will. It should be clear that they can only do so through individual, corporate and government cooperation of a type that has never before been experienced.

Trends for the Future

In all, it is clear that the post-industrial economy has both collectivizing and individualizing trends. It has facets that promote individual professionalism and entrepreneurship on the one hand and those that promote the growth of very large scale enterprises on the other. None of the present aspects of the economy will vanish--manufacturing of goods and food distribution will continue to grow with population in absolute terms--but they will not continue to dominate either public interest or employment. Instead, those sectors will shrink back into a nearly invisible infrastructure run by machines that are superintended by a few managers, who would themselves be part of the information economy rather than be traditional blue-collar workers. Of necessity, the companies engaged in such activity would be relatively large (in capital terms) by today's standards but would occupy a middle ground in the economy. It is of course, uncertain how long some of this will take. Social responses to new technology are even harder to predict than availability of the techniques themselves, but the very possibility of moving in the indicated directions will itself create pressure to do so, in the name of efficiency if nothing else.

There will be vast new economic frontiers opening up, and the instability common to all rapidly growing and changing economies will be a feature of the economic landscape for some time to come. An interesting side-effect of this is that the study of economic technique itself could become more important, though efforts to apply systematic planning to the economy could continue to be frustrating because old data never quite catches up to current reality. It could be argued, for instance, that one reason for the recent success of the computing industry is that governments have not understood it soon enough to be able to stifle it through

274

Page 275: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

regulation. It could also be argued that a state of stasis or economic stability is undesirable and should not be striven for, because it would imply stagnation and eventual decay, and that change ought therefore to be welcomed as a benefactor and encouraged.

There is no shortage of information about the economy, and computing hardware will soon exist to collect, store, and manipulate this information even on a global scale, but it is not yet evident that an economic calculus exists that can comprehend the effects of change on the scope being discussed here. Such a calculus will have to deal more with change and growth than with a stable economy. Explaining what is happening in economic terms even while the object of study is rapidly transforming itself beyond recognition is one of the major academic and technical challenges of the information age. There is certain to be no shortage of candidates for the position of Economic Newton to the new era. If a means of explaining how the economy works can be found, there will likewise be no shortage of those proposing to manage it on a professional basis. Thus, economic technique might be part of the collectivist aspect of the future order, despite the failure of comprehensive management efforts in the past.

Jacques Ellul saw this trend clearly, and argued that like all techniques, those of economies could brook no opposition in being developed to their logical conclusion--a comprehensive planned economy, micromanaged to the last detail by an army of economic technocrats in the name of maximum efficiency. However, his conclusion was based on certain assumptions of the industrial age, some of which may no longer be valid.

First, such an analysis presupposes that there does exist at least one comprehensive economic technique. During an age when industrial technology provided the paradigms, this may have seemed to be a reasonable assumption. It is possible to observe techniques in many fields of human endeavor as they are born, develop, and mature to a comprehensive statement or discipline. They become well-understood components of their environment, taking on an automatic and machinelike aspect. Although this is certain to continue, it is unclear as yet that this process applies to knowledge itself--that is, to information, the supplier of paradigms for the current age. Is the sum total of knowledge in any field of study, or in all of them collectively, limited or unlimited? If it is limited, a final equilibrium state is perhaps possible; otherwise it is not.

However, it will never be possible to prove that everything knowable has already been discovered by the human race, even if it has. Humanity may well style itself as its own god but can never know that it is all-knowing. A transcendent deity is one that can only be revealed, not constructed. If, therefore, the information economy continues to transform itself rapidly, growing without any apparent limits, a comprehensive set of economic techniques might never be devised--attempting to do so might be as difficult as managing the weather at every point on the globe.

Second, it is not clear how the general availability of economic information and general knowledge of economic technique will affect application. The citizenry may well submit to the professional opinion about what is economically efficient, thus creating a de facto managed economy. However, there are certain to be competing voices offering alternative theories, so that even if the best of economic

275

Page 276: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

techniques is discovered and applied, there will be the political problem of persuading people that this is so. There will always be some prepared to argue that a current technique, efficient as it may seem, ought to be replaced by a different one. The only way to discover if the argument is correct may be to try it; theoretical demonstrations of efficiency are unconvincing and often wrong. This may always be the case, for technique is application, not theory.

That is, Ellul's worries about the inevitability of economic techniques may be valid, but as long as there is neither understanding of the role of information nor the ability or will to manipulate it, the day when the economy will be manageable in every detail will be postponed indefinitely. Indeed, economic theory has had a hard time in recent decades. It failed to explain the "stagflation" of the late 1970s, which saw high unemployment and high inflation together--a combination previously thought impossible. It also failed to predict or account for the dramatic stock market plunge of October, 1987 and for the prolonged rise through the nineties. Economic pundits had widely differing, even contradictory, interpretations of why such events took place and what the effects would be, even in the short term. For its part, the information economy is not only new, but entirely out of regulatory control. No one person or group "owns" or manages the Internet (or is likely to the Metalibrary). It is growing and changing so rapidly that its major features may be in place long before there is even any theoretical work done on its management.

Third, the sorry history of attempts to do comprehensive micromanagement of the economy must lead us to question whether it would be wise to attempt it even if it did seem possible. Putting such power into the hands of a government has invariably resulted in brutal dictatorship, and there is no reason to suppose that because we collectively became competent to do what could not be achieved in the past, we would be better off for doing it. History suggests that such power would simply produce another tyranny.

Profile On . . . The Economy

Productivity

Throughout the 1980s and 1990s billions of dollars have been spent on computing and information technology. Yet, the standard measure of productivity (product value divided by average wage) has remained constant during this time. This fact is called the "productivity paradox" and many commentators have used it to suggest that money spent on new technology has been wasted.

However, this analysis fails to take into effect two factors:

First, this is not the first productivity paradox, but the third. The first two (in North America) were the electrification of factories from 1899 to 1939, and the electrification of urban homes from 1907 to 1929. In both cases, there was little or no change in productivity until the end of the period. Then, on the one hand, more efficient factories could be built with radically different designs, and on the other,

276

Page 277: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the gains made by using machines in the home could be translated into economic advantages for the family and the standard of living improve dramatically.

Second, productivity gains are unlikely during the time an old system is being modernized. Such a process consumes time, energy, and capital, but leaves essentially the same way of working in place when it is done. Rather, the important changes take place after the technology has been deployed for traditional tasks, when it begins to transform the workplace into something new and fundamentally different.

Thus, it is only when the economy is into the latter phase of computerization, and adoption into existing systems has reached at least 50% is it likely that the transforming enablement of the information age will produce great productivity gains--these take place after the old system has been changed. Perhaps just such a radical transformation can be seen in the growth of the World Wide Web after about 1993, when the Internet went from being a scholars' tool to a household appliance in a few short years (Changes take place much faster than in previous technology revolutions).

Ted Lewis, writing in the May 1998 issue of the IEEE journal Computer suggested that the economy is moving to a friction-free model, wherein new information can be acted upon almost immediately. He notes some of the same trends mentioned in this chapter--the exclusion of the middle man (disintermediation), the integration of many economic functions under single entities, the increasing flexibility of the workplace under a more professional and less rigid organizational model, and the increasing ability for manufacturers to target individual customers' wants and needs.

If this analysis is correct, then the lengthy expansion of the North American economy experienced in the 1990s might well continue for a decade or more, as the productivity gains of the Metalibrary begin to be realized by the majority of citizens.

Conclusions

What then, can be drawn as a definite conclusion about future businesses activity and the economy as a whole? Although there are certain broad collectivist trends, individualist ones seem also likely to be manifested, with economic knowledge and power becoming widely disseminated. This very knowledge will feed back into the system to reshape it. A group of self-professed economic technocrats or professional managers may well exist, though they may not be successful in achieving a comprehensive understanding or much real control over a very rapidly changing system.

However, less neutral opinions are not hard to find. The stock market could suffer a great crash, confidence in government could decline from low to none, or the new century could see a variety of other calamities that render late 1990s economic and social analysis unusable. It is too soon to say, for instance, whether

277

Page 278: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the bear market begun in 2001 constitites a trend, the beginning of a deep decline, or merely a temporary technical setback. Ted Lewis might be wrong, and a deep recession just around the corner. Governments could collapse, nations self-destruct, and corporations important in the 1990s cease to exist. Some of this has happened already, with problems in Eastern Europe and the Middle East continuing to affect the world economy, perhaps in the end profoundly. In this volatile time, when dramatic change is normal, some apparently small factor could trigger radial alterations to the world's economic, corporate, and political structures that dwarf all the considerations mentioned thus far.

Given recent patterns of economic change, it ought, however, to be possible to forecast with reasonable accuracy what will be the winning and losing sectors in the new civilization--in at least the intermediate to long run-- and the next section will be devoted to these issues.

8.3 Wealth in the New Era Perhaps it seems pessimistic to speak of economic losers in the information

age. After all, is it not an axiom of progress that it automatically results in everyone being better off than they were before? Indeed, progress, thought of as an independent force toward human betterment has been very much an icon of the industrial age. In material terms--goods and services--a citizen of a modem industrialized country is certainly much better off than one of a century ago, and this is particularly evident in terms of medicine. Thus, in some spheres, progress seems real, even though in the social, political, and moral ones it could be questioned. Whether the almost mystic notion of inevitable progress will continue to be a control belief of the new era will be examined partially in Chapter 11.

Assuming for the sake of argument that (at least economic) progress is an inevitable force, the wealth it brings has been distributed very unevenly both by industry and by geography. Despite its name, which seems to suggest specific routes and particular goals, progress is fundamentally unpredictable--most of its prophets seize on one or another utopia as the eventual resting place, the nature of which reflects the economic and political biases of the predictor. In addition such forecasts are often made in absolute terms, ignoring that peoples' perceptions of change are in relative ones--both for where they have been and for where they see everyone else as being. Each individual in a society has a somewhat different view of the past, the present, and the future. With this come different hopes, and so different views of what has already or might yet constitute progress.

For instance, one person might define progress solely in absolute economic terms such as employment or home ownership. Another might define social progress in terms of the percentage of the population with incomes, say, one standard deviation below the mean. Since this figure--the number below a relative poverty line--does not change as the mean rises, those fond of such analysis may see no progress at all, even if more people can buy more things. Still others might survey the moral landscape of the population and draw conclusions that are not dependent on material prosperity at all--or even suggest that there is an inverse relationship. Thus, it is not difficult to generalize the arguments of the last section

278

Page 279: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and suggest that progress, if it is real, may have no general goals, with the possible exception of efficiency.

Economic change also takes time, for there is a great deal of inertia in the spending habits of governments, industries, and individuals. However radical the changes in these are, this inertia acts as a governor or brake, and is itself a key factor in determining how society can change. Moreover, economic information disseminates through society slowly, and decisions made in one year might not realize their full impact for several years. Nevertheless, government and industry leaders are often expected to take immediate action and produce immediate results for the bottom line. Since the economy is probably already in a different part of the cycle than it appears to be, such pressure often results in exacerbating the very problems they were designed to solve, or exaggerating the swing away from the difficulty. One could hope, as Ted Lewis, that in a friction-free economy such bad decisions will become less likely, but such a hope also assumes that decision makers will also ignore emotional pressure, bad economic models, and demagoguery, and history would suggest this to be unlikely.

Moreover, although the new economy will inherit from the old in a straight line fashion, the steps whereby a new order is attained are documentable after the fact but are not necessarily obvious or even evident during the transition. With all these cautions, it is still interesting to analyze present and possible trends by industry and by country to determine which could gain ground and which could lose it relative to the ever-changing norms of economic activity.

Economic Change by Industry

It may seem easy to pick a few of the industries, occupations, and enterprises that will be economic winners in the information age. Electronic and biochemical high technology, information industries, robotics, habitat engineering, and space technologies are poised to become economic leaders, and many businesses in such enterprises will undoubtedly grow and prosper. It is difficult to be more specific, however, and to select individual companies as the greatest beneficiaries in the new economy, for much depends on adaptability, vision, the readiness to make decisions and take risks, and the ability to combine all this with sound management. The winners also need to be able to form and maintain associations or formal partnerships with other companies on an international basis--an exercise in cross-cultural cohabitation that may be beyond all but the most imaginative and flexible.

For instance, even well-positioned giants such as IBM, which should have been at the center of computing technology innovation, sometimes found themselves pushed to the wings by the likes of Apple, Dell, and Compaq. The big players of a previous wave of innovation often find themselves forced to play catch-up in a marketplace that is highly competitive and demands rapid decision making and change--both of which are difficult to do in traditional big companies. When IBM attempted to set standards, these were not particularly innovative and were either easily duplicated by a host of smaller companies, or ignored altogether. The result: though its sales have grown in absolute terms (they could hardly help but in this

279

Page 280: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

sector), IBM can no longer claim to be the single dominant force in the industry and innovative product leadership has often come from elsewhere.

Yet, though IBM may have lost some of the edge of innovation, it retained the marketing skills that kept it in a prominent position even without the mantle of leadership. It also retained sufficient trust in its name to be able to charge the highest prices, as well as sufficient volume to manufacture at the lowest cost in the industry. These factors increased the size of the company and allowed it to do costly research on supercomputers, superconductivity, new materials, and new kinds of software--all of which will be required to build the kind of devices that will establish the Metalibrary, will result in new and innovative products, and will enable management of the wider economy. IBM may not be the first to manufacture the devices made possible by its research, but its role is important to their eventual production. This situation nicely illustrates the need for both large-scale, capital-intensive research and small-scale, innovative applications of new knowledge.

Meanwhile, Apple Computer, on the other hand, illustrates that even being the company responsible for almost every innovation in computing for two decades is not enough to maintain a dominant market share. This is because it is not quality that sells in a mass market, but perceptions (the sizzle rather than the steak). Better managed companies whose people understood this were able to out-market Apple, even though their software and hardware products were often inferior. With the return of Steve Jobs to Apple, and the subsequent change in management style and marketing techniques the company once again became prosperous. This example serves to teach two lessons: first that any one of bad management, poor decisions, or worse marketing can easily overcome superior product quality; and second that as in the moral realm, knowing what is best does not imply doing it--or in this case, buying it. In other words, even perfect information does not lead to corresponding action; Aristotle was simply wrong about this.

The automobile industry provides another interesting example. In its infancy, it boasted hundreds of small enterprises, but those gradually coalesced into a handful of giant car makers with numerous cross-industry standards. These in turn came to be threatened by more sophisticated and automated offshore firms that took advantage of new technologies to build better products before their North American counterparts could react to new market realities, and it took a long time for the latter to catch up.

As the computing industry grows, aspects of it will also mature and become standardized, and there will continue to be a reduction in the number of vendors, though some of the remaining ones will grow in size. Such a rationalization in the computer industry has taken place before, in the 1960s and 1970s, when mainframe manufacturers adapted to the IBM standards. A similar process may be as all-encompassing in the small-computer industry, even though there are many personal tastes to accommodate.

For instance, the visual desktop metaphor that was pioneered by Xerox and popularized by Apple as the MacOS, was then partially imitated by Microsoft, and as "Windows" has taken most of the market. There remains room for some divergence in basic hardware, storage devices, operating systems, languages, and even consumer applications. In the end, the number of small computer manufacturers

280

Page 281: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

may shrink substantially and fall in line behind Intel, Microsoft, IBM, Sun, Apple, and one or two others insofar as standards are concerned. While some will undoubtedly be casualties in the consolidation crossfire, others will prosper as they do now supplying parts, peripherals, service, consulting, and software. At the same time, international organizations such as ISO, the IEEE, and ECMA have also become more important for the setting of useful standards in the industry for the simple reason that they are perceived as impartially transcending any single economic interest.

The establishment of the Metalibrary might serve to open up individual opportunities to gain and use technical knowledge for profit. It may well be some future start-up company run out of a garage that builds and sells, say, the first "pocket brains" or the first lap-top or pocket Metalibrary terminals. Today's computing giants must contend with innovation from start-ups at home and also with attacks on their market share from abroad. They may not even exist in sixty years; their survival depends on their adaptability and vision.

Apart from the computing industry, others likely to be successful in the information age include biotechnology, communications, transportation, and high-technology construction. Engineers of all kinds will be in great demand, as will be lawyers, teachers, analysts, system designers, accountants, document writers, and contract supervisors. Certain professions that may seem to be obvious winners, such as circuit design and programming, may enjoy only a short-lived boom. When computers are used to automate such tasks, such jobs may not be needed as much. However, their holders will be used being problem solvers, and as such will always experience demand for their services, regardless of the specific job title.

It is more difficult to forecast which industries will be unsuccessful, especially outside the high technology fields. Some managements have the vision to adapt new tools to their fields efficiently, and others do not. The properly perceptive corporation in any field--including agricultural and smokestack industries--may not lose market share or importance, even if their overall sector declines relative to the entire economy. Manufacturers such as General Electric have often been cited as examples of companies that have been able to grow and change with their customers over long periods of time. Likewise, the Hudson's Bay Company (HBC) has become the world's oldest continually operating commercial concern by being able to discern those same changes on a retail level, though it was very late getting on the Internet. Interestingly, it too is currently re-inventing itself as discrete chains of speciality outlets instead of as monolithic department stores.

By contrast, many firms that were successful in the late industrial or early information age collapsed when they were unable to make the transformation from one product or market to another that a rapidly changing situation demands. Whether a given company-- old or new--can expand its vision sufficiently to thrive (or survive) change remains to be seen. After all, there are numerous high tech firms, some of which were for a time quite large, that have already succumbed to market pressures, poor management, and negative marketing perceptions. A journalistic feeding frenzy alone can do serious damage to a company--even in the absence of any genuine marketing or technical problems. A classic example was the treatment Apple got from the press in 1996-1997 when reporters with no real news

281

Page 282: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

on hand were able to halve Apple's market share on the basis of nothing more than mutually-reinforced negative reporting.

The HBC serves as an example that it is possible to establish trade to hunter-gatherers from an agricultural society, maintain that trade throughout the entire industrial age, and participate in the next as well, by retailing electronic devices. That no other companies have survived the same time span is telling evidence of the difficulty of managing commercial change and might lead to the conclusion that few of the present companies will survive, though information on potential change will also be available to them if they can take advantage of it. The point is that the new technologies necessarily transform the old institutions even while they create new ones. Those that can effectively manage the transformation survive and thrive; those that cannot die out.

Geographical Considerations

Just as there have been geographical, economic, and political considerations that have resulted in uneven concentrations of certain technologies in the past, such factors will also cause some regional disparities in the near future. That is, there will probably be geographic winners and losers at least in the initial stages of the new economy.

North America has been a leader in the computing industry and that may continue, though it is always hazardous to predict that some economic pattern of the past will continue into the future for very long. This is particularly true in the context of the Metalibrary, where neither information nor vendors need respect artificial lines drawn on the Earth as national boundaries. As the biomedical and aerospace industries grow and change, they will go through startling transitions. It is tempting to suggest, for instance, that the progress of the former could be similar to that of the computing industry, with the giant drug companies losing ground to enterprising garage and basement operations. Research and development costs in this field can be remarkably small in some situations; the potential return is often very high, and numerous academics have left universities in order to reap profits from their research. These factors are certain to encourage many new entrants to the field. On the other hand, the existing North American regulatory environment can result in a ten year, 250 million dollar cost to bring a new pharmaceutical product to the commercial market. This fact alone stacks the deck heavily in favour of the very large companies, and the industry has already become quite concentrated.

In the aerospace industries, the relatively large amounts of money involved will likely benefit large companies in the near future, but some contract work will continue to go to much smaller firms, especially those in close physical proximity to the industry leaders. Again, it is easy to forecast more mergers as the market globalizes and capital needs for new and larger products skyrocket.

As the routine use of global communications networks becomes a reality, geographical proximity may diminish in importance in many industries. This could effect such enterprises as banking, retail sales, travel, investing, and the offering of

282

Page 283: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

professional services. Eventually, economic partnerships will know few national boundaries.

Like corporations, those countries and regions that foster economic innovation and permit rapid change will benefit the most economically. Some countries are in much better position in this respect than others. The United States, though experiencing massive shifts from old northern manufacturing belts to sunnier climes in the South and West, has a wide lead in all the future technologies. The former Soviet Union also has certain advantages in basic science and engineering, including the largest concentration of doctorates in the world. These people now have more freedom to pursue their work without state interference, and could become an important factor in the future. In the short term, however, they have little funding, outdated manufacturing capability, food shortages, political instability, and a collapsed economy to deal with, and will therefore be severely handicapped for a time.

For a time, the United States lost some of its economic leadership to smaller, more rapidly developing and innovative countries whose entrepreneurs seemed ready to manage change effectively. These included Japan, Germany, South Korea, Taiwan, Singapore, and the underpopulated but resource-rich Canada and Australia. However, bad management, government corruption, and poor market supervision led to excesses in the Asian economies in the late 1990s and a sharp contraction ensued in that part of the world. It is too soon to say whether those countries will recover and resume the mantle of leadership, or whether they will give it up to others. In the meantime, capital and other resources have flowed back to safer havens in North America and this has been partly responsible for a renewed domination of the world economy by the United States.

Canada and Australia might be thought to have some important advantages because they can establish robotized manufacturing without as large a work-force displacement as in some countries. Canada in particular has an abundance of natural resources and space for potential habitat. Like the United States, it is positioned both on the old Atlantic trade routes and on the new Pacific ones. It also has considerable experience in both transportation and communications technologies--essential prerequisites for information age leadership. However, it had had decades of poor government management at bot the national and provincial level, and so has squandered most of its natural advantages. Australia likewise could be well positioned for the new trading realities, has substantial natural resources, and a people with a reputation for adaptability and innovation. The downside for both is that if the climate continues to warm as it has done recently, important agricultural lands could become too dry to use, costing them important economic leverage. Both will also need to establish visionary economic and political leadership; electorates do not necessarily make the wisest or most appropriate choices of governments, and even the best of these can lose office for reasons that have nothing to do with their technical expertise, management ability, or vision. Canada also has the handicap of its continuing identity and unity crisis; if it does splinter into two or more parts, no one of these can expect to be significant players on the world scene.

283

Page 284: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Even the rest of old-world Europe need not fare badly in the future, for the information age does not require absolutely that a nation be a manufacturer of goods so much as a manager of that manufacture and of the flow of information. This can be done even if there are no industrial-age style trade routes, just as Japan was able to establish industry without many raw materials of its own. Indeed, a unified Europe could constitute a large enough market as to be virtually self-sufficient in technology. On the other hand, such unity has never come easy to the Europeans. Lacking the threat of the Soviet Union, they may revert to their age-old hobby of cutting each other's throats.

Indeed, since the first version of these materials was written in 1988, that is exactly what happened in Eastern Europe. There is no particular reason to suppose that it cannot happen in Western Europe as well. Lest the author seem to boast of inappropriate prescience, however, it should also be noted that the earliest versions of this book mentioned Indonesia as a dawning world power, but that nation continues to be hampered by its own government; has not progressed socially or economically; and probably will not until some time after its system of governance has substantially altered.

It is also important to note that in recent decades Western industrialized nations have adopted many Marxist ideas, and their people are less free than they once were. That is, the trail of failure and death left by radical egalitarianism throughout the last century has not dampened the desire of Western intellectuals to tread this path again. This desire has given rise to some stifling of creativity and free speech, denial and revision of actual history and literature thought to be embarrassing, and a repudiation of the moral basis for law. History would caution us that these nations could easily drag themselves back from whence they came, passing the mantle of civilization to others in a rather short time.

The biggest winner might be China. Rich in resources, people, and innovative spirit, she could be poised to move from an inefficient agrarian society to the information age in a single leap. China has the potential to become the leader of the Pacific Rim economies in the near future, taking the baton from the United States and Japan, which have shared it since the Second World War. China is not without political problems, or its own unity issues, however, and it remains to be seen whether it can fare any better as a free nation than it has under communism.

It is worth noting that the Pacific region has the U.S., Canada, Australia, Japan, South Korea, Taiwan and China, all of which are mentioned in most projections as economic leaders of the next few decades. Clearly, a dramatic shift in trading patterns from the Atlantic to the Pacific is indicated, not so much reflecting any absolute decline in volume on the older routes, but massive gains on the newer ones. One local region in North America that may have much to profit is the Vancouver-Seattle port complex. Over the medium term these two could grow together into one of the world's largest trading hubs. They could become international centers for banking and information as well, because of their strategic location on the trade and communication routes of the future. They could together handle thousands of times their present volume of trade goods and raw materials, but of course with much more automation, and relatively fewer human longshoremen.

284

Page 285: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Other countries with potential for gains include Brazil, Argentina, and South Africa--providing the first two can become politically and fiscally stable and the last can rid itself of the ghosts of ruinous racial policies without disintegrating into chaos. These and a handful of others could move into a modified industrial age comparable to the 1950s and 1960s in North America, but with many of the benefits of high technology added. There will be other countries that will surprise all analysts by how well they do, and there will be some of the apparently favored few that do not succeed, but instead slide back into either genteel poverty or outright chaos.

Many other third world nations will continue to make absolute progress toward agricultural success and even industrialize to an extent, but it is difficult to forecast anything but relative economic loss for many of the politically unstable, overpopulated, badly divided, or resource-poor regions of the world. For just as an industrial revolution must be built on a sound base of agriculture and established financial, political, and physical infrastructure, so also must high-technology revolutions be built on their proper bases. At the very least, such revolutions require an innovative spirit, a commitment to extensive education, political stability, and at least some previous industrial success. Too many countries lack some or all of these qualifications and do not seem to be obtaining them. It may therefore be a long time before the benefits of the industrial age--let alone those of the information era--come to the majority of the people in many parts of the world. Such benefits are not easily sharable with people who are not ready for them or who do not want them, but are locked into a more primitive society and economy. That is, high technology cannot simply be developed in one part of the world and transplanted to another. Without the proper groundwork preparation, the seed will not take; even with much hard work, it might mutate and grow into a very different form than in the place that it originated. Moreover, techniques that in a democracy enhance freedom and the quality of life may be used elsewhere to destroy both. It cannot, therefore, be just assumed that technology transfer will take place. However, if it does not, disparities in living standards will grow larger, and this would be destabilizing to world peace. Thus, the successful countries may find that it is in their self-interest to find ways to encourage other countries to adopt the new techniques in some form--to gain markets, if nothing else.

Finally, there is the economy of Russia and its former satellites and puppets in South Central Asia, Eastern Europe, and Cuba to consider. As much as any countries in the world, the former Soviet Union and its allies have been wedded to the industrial age and to its paradigms--and even this without much success. Only a new found openness to allowing profound change on a large scale could allow these nations to prosper in the information age. It was the very prospect of such changes, and the fact that the people were aware of them taking place elsewhere, that revealed to them the essential economic and ideological bankruptcy of their nations. Whatever value Marxism may have had in the industrial age, it was too rigid to cope with the information era, and collapsed with its advent. Its problems are especially well illustrated by the economies of countries such as Hungary, Romania, Poland, and the former Czechoslovakia, Yugoslavia, and East Germany, all of which ran up enormous debts and fell on hard times. Poland's economy has rested on steel and shipbuilding, and the same shift away from such activities is

285

Page 286: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

taking place in Europe as in the United States. Since what is needed in this sector can be undertaken more efficiently elsewhere, no amount of planning could revive these industries to their old glories. Similarly, the Russian determination after World War II to punish what it controlled of its enemy's territory left East Germany in economic shambles. Its people were not ignorant of the economic contrast between their nation and West Germany, and when their Soviet masters lost the will to terrorize them into submission, the unification of the two Germanys became inevitable, creating a new candidate to dominate the European community, if not the world economy. It remains to be seen, however, whether even united Germany, let alone the rest of Eastern Europe, can soon recover from the ravages of Marxism and become important players in the next civilization.

Another consideration at the international level is the degree to which some nations may feel threatened by the shifts in global trading patterns. Those that allow old trade and industries to die and foster the formation of the new in order best to take advantage of the changing world economy will likely enjoy continuing prosperity. Those that attempt to protect whatever they think they already have behind high tariff barriers, or that subsidize the inefficient and bail out the incompetent will probably find their trade deficits growing and their relative prosperity declining. Those that indulge in trade protectionism out of nationalistic or xenophobic motives will damage not just their own people, but the prosperity of other nations as well.

For example, Canada and the United States have a trading relationship of a size and complexity that dwarfs any other. Yet special economic and political interests continually threaten to damage this relationship, especially during election years. Such actions are not only counter to long-run self interest; they oppose information age realities and threaten the prosperity of all the world's peoples. Openness, cooperation, and trust are by necessity the watchwords of the future. There will be little economic sufferance of the closed,the suspicious, or the unfair traders.

On the other hand, protectionism could induce trade wars that result in a new world-wide depression, substantially delaying the advent of any new economy. Even when the dangers of such behaviors ought to be well known, history suggests there is a significant possibility that politicians might want to adopt the most irrational course of action, and that the populace will be sufficiently ignorant of history to allow them. That is, the optimistic economic scenario is not the only possible one.

Whether or not the world's economy both modernizes and globalizes, so that individual and regional economic disparities are reduced, government and corporate leaders will face many serious issues in population, employment, health care, and wealth distribution--and unlike other times, they will not be able to keep their people ignorant when other people are more prosperous than theirs. This alone will force them to provide a different quality of leadership--one that is both accountable and result-oriented.

The political implications of these geographic economic problems will be considered in more detail in the next chapter. For now, having looked at institutional change at the macro-economic level, it is time to focus attention on business organizations.

286

Page 287: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

8.4 Technology and Business Organizations In the hunter-gatherer and agricultural civilizations, people who were engaged

in commerce were an integral part of their community, and their social status reflected that fact. The village blacksmith, for example, had a specialized function, and that function defined a total role in the community, dictating much of the life and expectation of family members as well. One of the effects of industrialization has been the fragmentation of work into many highly specialized job tasks, many of which are only a small part of some major enterprise. Since such specialties are not the means by which their practitioners relate to the community as a whole, many people have found themselves dividing life into a series of roles, each depending on the situation in which they have found themselves. This personal fragmentation has been one aspect of a pervasive societal one; people play at religious and moral roles in scattered fragments just as they conduct all their relationships with the community in this way. Even language can be fragmented into a series of registers for different life contexts so that one becomes different people speaking different dialects for various discrete roles.

For example, an industrial-age entrepreneur might play the role of business owner to the community, philanthropist to a church, customer to suppliers, boss to employees, rival or friend to peers, partner to mate, and parent to children. However, the connections among these roles are often incidental and tenuous. In each of the various contexts, this might as well be a different person--little need is seen for an integration of the aspects of life into a whole. Such lack of integration extends to the moral/ethical realm as well. Different roles are seen to call for different ethics. Thus, the generous philanthropist might also be a ruthless business practitioner and merciless employer, and no one see any contradiction in this. Likewise, she may be unfaithful to her marriage partner and not detect an ethical issue in the situation. The woman who is a Children's Bible School teacher on Sunday might pirate software for her employer on Monday and use her employer's machine to view pornography on Tuesday. The politician who takes a high moral stand on integrity in government during the day might cheat on his wife by visiting prostitutes in the evening and not consider this a contradiction

The work of any employee in a dull and repetitious job might be even more fragmented from life as a whole, for that job defines no role in the community and provides little satisfaction to the worker. Such work is unlikely to have little to do with family relations, for the children of such workers are usually not encouraged to pursue such a job but to better themselves and move up the socioeconomic ladder.

The advent of the techniques of the information age suggests that individual workers will know about and operate more of their enterprise. Very highly specialized and repetitive jobs are those most likely to become automated, and human beings are more likely to find themselves either unemployed, controlling a large number of these automatons, or working in the service or information sectors instead. That is, new techniques not only change existing business organizations and bring new ones into being, but they also create new organizational forms. The demand of technique is always for greater efficiency, higher productivity, more automation, more profit, and fewer workers. Up to the early 1980s, this had the

287

Page 288: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

greatest effect on the blue-collar worker on the assembly line or plant floor. Better mechanical devices have gradually reduced the need for such jobs, and the payroll has shifted to white-collar workers in secretarial and middle management positions.

However, the computing and information technology now available is causing a similar automation to take place in the office as well. Fewer secretaries can have a higher output if they have word processors. Senior management can get information summaries done to order without needing their juniors to do research for them--such work can be done easily, quickly, and automatically. The result is a new round of job displacement in what had previously been some of the fastest growing employment areas.

In general, organizations are becoming leaner and more efficient, and even very large enterprises can be operated by fewer people with each passing year. One result is an expectation of rapidly rising productivity and efficiency, that creates a stress with which not every worker is equipped to handle. That stress can sometimes be reduced by diffusing or networking responsibilities among all the workers (see Chapter 12). Another result is that the average amount of training and experience that a firm has invested in employees is increasing rapidly as the responsibility and knowledge expected of each increases. Still another result is that it once again becomes possible to define one's total role in the community by one's job because it is a profession or a craft--not merely an hourly drudgery for someone else.

The employees who remain under such circumstances become progressively more essential to the operation and more difficult and expensive to replace. For this reason, many firms have turned to stock options and profit sharing to lock in loyalties and high performance through part ownership. When this continues, the employees over time are the company, for they eventually become partner-owners of the whole enterprise. This model has worked well for professional firms of lawyers and accountants in the past and is likely to be adapted in the future by many others. Possible candidates for future conversion to employee ownership include many public facilities now operated by the state, such as hospitals, road maintenance, schools, social services, and even tax collection. For those who promote this model, the potential benefits for the quality of goods, service and employee satisfaction are so great that many public and private services--and even some manufacturing--seem likely to become professional collectives in the future.

Those opposed to the privatization of government services, on the other hand, worry about potential declines in quality and universality of services and the lack of direct control by central authority. However, the necessary accountability to meet these concerns can be established in many ways--and these may be much more effective than in the past.

The adversarial relationships that have characterized management/labour interactions in the past are an industrial age phenomenon that seems not to fit easily with the new paradigms. Confrontation results as much from a lack on information as from different ideologies. Information sharing promotes (but does not guarantee) collaboration. In all business and government enterprises, the trend to collaboration may become pronounced; this seems to be a required characteristic of an information society. Of course, there will likely be organizations and places

288

Page 289: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

where for ideological and emotional reasons this does not happen; it is a truism that familiarity can breed contempt as much as it can cooperation. Thus some will still fight old battles for control of dying enterprises; but such people seem destined to become footnotes to history, for such engagements will know no working survivors.

Both within and without organizations, therefore, there will at least have to be a network of relationships, responsibilities and authorities rather than a strict hierarchy as in the past. A few companies in high-tech and other industries already operate with networked rather than hierarchical structures. These are characterized by minimal or no job descriptions and complex reporting lines, which may at times be reciprocal (One person is the boss for some things, another for others). All employees become a part of the management of the total enterprise and accountable for its success. In the future, there may be an understanding that the various professionals contribute to a common cause differently, and need not do so equally in monetary terms to be given equal respect. Although high technology does not require networked models of authority, it does make such models possible on a large scale by providing distributive communication methods. These are generally more versatile and comprehensive and may therefore supplant the relatively inflexible top-down methods that characterize a hierarchy.

Another model is that of the flexible organization, where teams are formed for specific projects, and then disbanded afterwards. For the purposes of one such team, it could choose to have a hierarchy during its lifetime; the same people on a new team at a later date might mind themselves in a different hierarchical relationship, or forming a network instead. One could go further still, and suggest--in the Metaperson model--that a professional/contract model for work suggests that employers per se will become less important, and that individuals will band together on their collective initiative to form corporate entities for specific projects, and not be permanent employees of anyone else.

The whole range of possibilities is shown on the chart below--the original of which was used to show the four civilizations in overview in Chapter 2.

289

Page 290: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

In this overview, there is a near linear relationship depicted from lower left to upper right--the direction of the apparent trend in organizational structure and emphasis. As individual-oriented structures ought to be in some sense more flexible, this makes sense. Structures off this line are perhaps not only inappropriate for their time, but probably also inherently unstable. As can be seen in the next chapter, such instability may indeed be characteristic of certain styles of government. It should also be noted that the style, not the size of an organization alone, determines where it would be placed on such a scale.

The organization gains in the shift to greater flexibility because there is more uniformity of goal, purpose, and technique, and this is by mutual agreement of the professional participants. The individual partner-employee also gains professional status, a degree of autonomy, control over personal job conditions, and a voice of influence in the whole organization. A consequence is that much attention will continue to be paid in the future to organizational cultures, for the relationships of the employees to one another and to the organization as a whole, as well as the commitment of the group to the perceived mission of the enterprise, will be the keys to success in the information age.

At the same time, improved communication facilities have made it more feasible to work at home, and increasing numbers of people are already

290

Page 291: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

telecommuting. As observed in the last chapter, this could change the home environment and even effect house design. It could also affect the office, for at least some of the workers in an enterprise will have little incentive to be with their fellows for much of the week. Since this is a potentially fragmenting and isolating trend, means may have to be found to overcome it by making the work place more attractive--perhaps even as a place to live. Some interaction with fellow professionals is necessary, and it may be that the majority of work done at home is contracted out to professionals who are not part of the organization but are free-lancers.

In the next chapter, some of the concepts developed here will be extended to society as a whole. For now, it is time to turn attention to the methods of financing and ownership of the typical information-age enterprise.

8.5 Financial Techniques in the New Economy The importance of financial techniques to the success of an industrial-based

economy cannot be stressed too much. Without the means of collecting together many smaller savings and then loaning large sums, the capital-hungry companies of the industrial age could never have grown as they did. The next era will have its own kinds of capital requirements and thus its own kinds of financial institutions. To see what these may be, it is necessary to consider current trends in the handling and transmission of money (the medium of exchange), stocks (the instruments of equity), and bonds (the instruments of debt).

Money and its Equivalents

Among the early hunter-gatherers, the medium of exchange was generally something that had intrinsic value. That is, it was valuable because it was useful in itself. Beaver pelts, buffalo hides, and flints are examples of intrinsically valuable exchange media. Because value was tied to use, the rates of exchange fluctuated with both the supply and the perceived need of the valued object but were capable of long-term stability--and prices were as likely to go up as down. In late hunter-gatherer and early agricultural societies, the medium of exchange shifted to objects with symbolic or decorative value, such as pieces of metal. These also gain their status because they are used, but the use tends to be by the upper classes and for ornamentation rather than being universal and necessary. When such use is widespread enough, the state eventually organizes the minting and distribution of coins in order to provide a guarantee of weight and purity and to lend some authority to the practice of using such coins for settling all transactions involving goods and services. Thus, money passes from being an object of concrete value to that of an abstraction known as "legal tender." As is often the case, the abstraction that no one needs to think about is more useful, more universal, and has a wider scope than the concrete object it represents.

The metal in question, such as gold, is still often said to have an intrinsic value, but this is only true to the extent of its direct usefulness--already inherent in such a medium of exchange is a considerable degree of abstraction from tangible wealth. As the economy grows in complexity, the supply of metals with symbolic

291

Page 292: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

value eventually becomes inadequate to serve the needs of industrial capitalization, and a second abstraction takes place, this time to paper money. A certain level of technology is required--advanced printing presses and an art of paper making and engraving that can prevent counterfeiting--but this second abstraction is necessary once the money supply reaches a certain size. At first, the fiction may be maintained that gold backs the currency, but gold too is only an abstraction for real wealth--which lies in the resources, productivity, inventiveness, and enterprise of a people who are behind the value of their money. Eventually, the monetary abstraction becomes more obvious when alongside the cash economy there grows up the practice of writing notes or checks to cover larger settlements--for paper money is also inadequate to meet all the needs of the industrial age. Once more, a certain level of technology is needed to maintain an efficient and large-scale cheque clearing system; beyond a certain level of use, it is next to impossible without computing machinery.

Plastic Cards

Credit cards, a more automated equivalent of checks, are also impossible to implement without sophisticated record keeping. The number and percentage of all commercial transactions presently covered by credit cards is growing rapidly with each passing year and exceeds those represented by the cash economy by a wide margin. Debit cards in turn represent a slight refinement of this system, for they are used at the retail level in an identical fashion to the credit card. The difference is that the account to which the billings are posted is the user's bank account, not a credit account. The user is directly debited for the transaction, and the writing of a month-end check is eliminated. Meanwhile, cash itself is more easily obtained with a card by using bank machines than by waiting for office hours and speaking with a human teller. An third alternative is the smart card, which carries its own balance electronically encoded and debits that whenever it is used for a purchase. All this automation results in efficiency at the cost of some jobs. It also makes for more mobile capital, for money can be transferred internationally as well as locally. It can be moved instantly instead of with substantial delay. Both of these further contribute to the ability to accumulate larger capital pools than ever before.

Taking the Next Step--Abstracting Money Altogether

Another level of abstraction has already taken over for a significant portion of transactions. This is the electronic transfer of funds. Here, there is no paper trail whatsoever, just a message sent from the machine managing one account to the one managing the other. Once the two are agreed on security measures (correct password and electronic signature) the one account is credited and the other debited, with an electronic record of the transaction entered into files at both ends.

The end result could well be a cashless economy--there isn't enough of it anyway--with automated record keeping of salaries, purchases, services, and taxes. Such a system has the advantages of efficiency and accuracy, and as Ellul points out, such considerations are often decisive. Whether the potential for the loss of

292

Page 293: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

personal control, freedom, and privacy is a price that people are willing to pay for such efficiencies remains to be seen. If enough are convinced that such a trade-off is worthwhile; however, the rest will not have the choice of remaining in a cash economy, because in that event, the latter would disappear. Black markets, criminal activities, and other economic undergrounds will all have to find other means than cash to keep track of their enterprises. However controversial the cashless society is to some, it may come about so gradually that its advent is scarcely noticed. Even now its greatest critics generally use checks if not credit cards, rather than cash. This development in itself is not at issue; it is the potential use of financial records for control and direction of individuals by the state that creates ethical issues. Those issues will be considered in more detail in the next Chapter; it is time to move on to other financing means.

Stocks and Bonds

Money, however abstracted, represents services, whereas the instruments of equity and debt represent collective ownership and financing. These, like paper money, are abstractions for wealth, but the wealth represented, while of monetary value, is of a different and less tangible sort. The value of an industrial-age company lies only partially in its assets of money, land, machines, buildings, and inventory. Value is also found in the skills of the employees, the company's ability to capture and hold market share or good will, its efficiency, and its ability to change. It is these latter assets that are the most important in an information and service economy. In fact, if key employees depart, the good will of customers evaporates, or the company cannot adapt to changing markets, the machines and inventory may be worthless. How all these values are perceived is reflected in the trading patterns of its shares and bonds, which move up and down with the willingness of people to buy and sell.

In a sense, the currency of a country reflects the same kinds of perceived values for the nation as a whole, as it also trades up and down on the market. The flow of information affects such trading, and the assumption of the currency marketplace is that when information availability is perfect, the trading price will reflect this. On the other hand, when information is free to flow in near zero time, the volatility in such markets may increase, especially if only part of the system is automated, and other parts have a restricted information flow.

The existence of both speculators and options to purchase currency, bonds, and stocks at a later date adds to this volatility, especially when the volume of trades rise and the current prices do not immediately reflect the actual information. This occurs when the transactions are executed more slowly than information is acquired. If the information is negative, the price of the option may drop faster than that of the actual stock or currency, whereupon dealers will sell the underlying instrument and buy the option. This selling should in theory immediately drive down the price of the actual stock or currency, but if volume is high and execution time lags, the gap may get larger and the activity accelerate. When the buy-and-sell decisions are made by computers, this acceleration can cause enormous gaps and very high volumes to develop, resulting in dramatic price declines. Prices can rise in

293

Page 294: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

a similar fashion if the reverse situation takes place. Market volatility (or at least its appearance) can be exacerbated when an index is based on capitalization and one company's valuation dominates the entire index, such as Nortel did on the TSE before its collapse.

Stock markets have therefore been forced to automate in the same way as some investors have, so that all orders are executed immediately by computers and no one part of the system runs out of control, as it has done at times past under only partial automation. Eventually, this may mean that brokers and floor traders will be unnecessary, for there would be no reason why individuals could not buy or sell shares in their own names without professional intervention. There is sure to be no shortage of professionals offering advice, however, so the people working in the investment industry today may only be slightly displaced.

Once this point is reached, there would be no reason to maintain trading on a 100-share or 1000-share block basis as traditional rules require. Individuals would be able to execute buy-and-sell orders on a per share basis directly from their own homes and offices with the centralized trading facility. Indeed, equity and debt could be expressed in any fraction of a single stock or bond as long as computing facilities are large enough to keep the records. A section of the Metalibrary could eventually be devoted to this function. Because market participation would become so easy, it could be almost universal. Indeed, mutual funds and the ability to day trade have already taken us partway down these roads. Professional fees could be paid in share fractions of the company, and the payee could order those to be automatically converted to other shares, bonds, or uncommitted reserves--anachronistically known as "cash." Again, there are advantages implied in such abilities for individuals, organizations, and even for society as a whole.

Individual professionals could incorporate as personal services companies and might pay some bills in shares of themselves. The advice of counsellors and investment specialists--all stored on line in a subsection of the Metalibrary--would become sought after and extensively used (electronically). One's investment portfolio could be intensely personalized and entirely tailored to individual desires. Of course, if everyone were an incorporated entity, there would be a tendency to abstract the value of a person by the value of his or her equity instrument. Greater worth as a person might be attached to an individual whose shares traded at $100 than at $1. However, people already do this today when they ask "how much is she worth?" when they mean "how many possessions has she at the moment?" Still, a universal investment registry such as this would allow anyone to attempt to finance projects by equity or debt--provided it was possible to convince enough individual investors to subscribe. Bankruptcy would remain possible, with all participants taking part of the loss. Just as is the case now, there will probably be both the "doers" and the financiers, but there may well be more of both.

The same broadening of investment instruments would make the financing of large projects possible. State involvement could add some guarantees to such undertakings, making them more attractive opportunities than they might otherwise be. Such financings could be undertaken without wholesale discounts to middlemen, for they could be advertised directly to consumers, who could purchase them like loaves of bread, boxes of cereal, or a new dress.

294

Page 295: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Banks and Credit Unions

While the size of large banks has, as expected, grown in the late 1990s with a number of high profile mergers, many people are not comfortable with this trend. Thus, while large business and large banks have formed a natural alliance, so have individuals and small businesses with credit unions. Once again the collectivizing and individualizing trends can be seen--this time defining who puts their money into or borrows from what kind of institution. If the trend to large bank mergers and the proliferation of small to medium size Credit Unions continues, it would not be difficult to predict that banks will eventually see very little of the retail money trade in personal loans and mortgages, and will instead confine themselves to the wholesale or commercial trade. However, there is no reason to suppose that the formation of temporary project-oriented pools of capital would not be just as good an idea as the same kind of flexible working partnerships.

Controlling Enterprise

The scenarios of the previous section may not come to pass exactly as described here; but whatever the means, there will have to be broader participation in debt and equity as the working population becomes more professionalized, corporate ownership broadens, and the size of the largest projects increases. Along with ownership comes responsibility and a degree of power. At present, voting by shareholders of a company is done mostly by proxies signed over to one or more representatives to a firm's annual general meeting, at which time a board of directors is elected. They in turn hire the operating officers and seldom intervene otherwise in the everyday affairs of the company. Except in the rare cases where a large shareholder votes herself into the directorship or holds a key operating position, corporate owners are usually removed two or three steps from actual control. For practical purposes, small shareholders of large enterprises, even if they may collectively own 80 percent, can be ignored by the operating officers; there is no means for such small fry to influence company decisions. They also have no channel for communicating their dissatisfaction to or even locating each other and thus cannot organize their dissent.

If corporate information were disseminated and voting collected through the Metalibrary or a similar facility, things could change dramatically. Such a facility offers broad possibilities for the formation of alliances, the developing of voting strategies, and the influencing of decisions. Although many shareholders might still elect to automatically turn over their proxies to the directors, dissident shareholders would more easily be able to organize an opposition, combine interests, and force changes. A larger percentage of the outstanding shares would be required to maintain effective control.

Of course, this innovation, like the cashless society, would not necessarily come about just because it is efficient, desirable, or possible. Social response to such technologies is highly unpredictable, and there are certain to be people who would want to prevent these developments or to lead real events in different and unforeseen directions. However, even a limited implementation of these ideas in

295

Page 296: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

which only some people participate would still enable some of the economic activities described to take place.

Because of the high value people tend to place on economic interests that directly affect them, any scheme for personal involvement in corporate affairs is likely to draw interests and loyalties away from the state and toward the company or group of companies in which they participate. Such ventures will not need to respect geographic boundaries, and eventually some may not even be based on Earth. The result may be a gradual diffusion and internationalization of economic power and interest. The potential loss of individual freedom implied by joining a completely centralized record-keeping facility may therefore be offset by at least a perception of increased individual power over the international economy, a greater ability to raise capital, and a possible shift of power away from the state and to the professionally owned corporations. Such developments are not necessarily good or bad in themselves. There are some alarming potentials here, just as there are some interesting potential benefits, and such potentials lead naturally to the discussions of the next section.

8.6 Business Ethics and Technology Perhaps more than in any other field of human endeavor, success in business

is quantified in terms of a single outcome--profit. As a result, there is always pressure to cheat the customer or trading partner by failing to disclose information in order to improve the monetary return. Business people, whether honest or not, have always been regarded with some suspicion, and every treatise on morals has had something specific to say about the ethics of doing business.

Cheating

For instance, the New Testament Greek word that is usually translated as "sincere" literally means "without wax" and refers to the practice of holding pottery up to the sun to determine whether a dishonest peddler had filled cracks with wax to make the pot appear sound when it was not. Every society that has used coins as a medium of exchange has had difficulties with those who debased the coinage either by shaving off a portion or by mixing inferior metals with the "precious" ones. Suppliers to the military have been notorious throughout history for cheating the state. The Roman army, the British Navy, and the United States Marines have all had to deal with high-priced but cheaply made goods, with rotting food supplies, with late or missing deliveries, overbilling, kickbacks, bribes to commanding officers, clothing that fell apart, and weapons that did not work.

Modern consumers face the same kind of problems with misleading or false advertising, industry cartels or monopolies, the selling of used goods as new, and such high-pressure sales techniques as the "loss leader" or "bait and switch." They must also deal with goods that do not work or fall apart but carry no warranty, or whose manufacturer goes out of business rather than repair the item, replace it, or even deliver it in the first place. The scam may even involve advertising goods that do not exist, collecting some money, and leaving town. Nor are software goods immune, for there is no means other than the collective will of the market to

296

Page 297: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

enforce their quality, and in such a rapidly changing industry, there are no effective guarantees that they will even work. Yet, large vendors have been successful selling badly flawed goods, even in the face of the ability of the target audience to become informed of those flaws.

In most sectors of the economy, such problems arise with only a small percentage of all commercial transactions, and only over a short time, for if they were pervasive or enduring, there would be no economy to speak of. When they do arise, they attract considerable publicity for the same reason. Like any social institution, trade and commerce can exist at all only if the people can trust them to be reliable; the instances where they cannot be trusted tend to undermine the entire economy and society. The software industry is so immature that its customers have so far been willing to put up with inconveniences they would not tolerate from any other group of manufacturers, but this situation cannot be counted on by vendors to continue. Its customers will surely begin to demand the same kind of functional warranties for software as they do for waffle irons. If its workers can more to a more professional model they may simultaneously be more able and willing to deliver such guarantees.

Unbridled Competition

Less publicly obvious but equally problematic are the practices of cutthroat competition intended to damage or destroy other businesses in the same field. In the name of such competition, product or business plans may be stolen, employees bribed or lured over to the competition, merchandise duplicated despite copyright or patent, and damaging information circulated about competitors. Alternately, a company with a large enough bank account might force competitors out of business by selling at a loss in the targeted marketplace, buying off the alternatives, or using market muscle to force vendors to carry, display, or bundle only the dominant product.

To some extent, these difficulties stem, on the one hand, from concentration on market share and profit as the exclusive measures of business success and, on the other hand, from the frequent separation of any sense of ethical behavior from the world of business. The prevalent world view of the industrial age has been that business is done in a jungle, that it is necessary to destroy competitors before one gets the same treatment from them, and that any means justifies the end of higher profits. For the most part, absolutist ethics had no place in business because an action that maximized profits in one situation might not in another. A business person might seriously claim to hold to an absolutist ethic as part of a religion but live a business life as though mutual responsibility and ethical obligations were outdated or did not even exist--and do this without seeing any contradiction. A common slogan has been "business is business." The implication is that it carries its own rules, whatever ethical code the doer of business might in all other aspects of life assent to. In short, such a world view is focused on money, not on the actions or process by which it is obtained. It is also consistent with a kind of economic Darwinism--only the profitable survive to make more money.

297

Page 298: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

However such attitudes and practices contain the seeds of their own future destruction, for they can effectively help achieve the desired ends only if they are kept secret. Consider the White House whose dirty tricks become exposed, the stockbroker caught stealing information and manipulating prices, the chip manufacturer whose FPU cannot do proper arithmetic, or the soft-drink company that continues to market bottles it knows will explode when tipped over. The common thread in all such events is information release. Automobile companies can no longer cover up their release of a lemon, and a software manufacturer whose newly released product still contains bugs will have the fact trumpeted on electronic bulletin boards all over the world within days.

What could once be effective only by being kept secret can no longer be hidden in the information age, and is therefore much less likely to work. Too many people have too much access to information and there are too many disgruntled employees ready to blow the whistle for any modern corporate executive to suppose that damaging information or questionable business practices can be withheld. Such whistle-blowers might not only become celebrities, but also sell their memoirs for a tidy sum, and have the protection of the law to keep their jobs besides. There are too many reporters with the time, patience, and computerized access to government and other public files and a desire to win a Pulitzer prize. Moreover, board members can now be held personally liable for the companies they direct, and this gives them a direct stake in doing what is, if not broadly right, at least narrowly legal. The net result is that the past can seldom be hidden and the present likewise is becoming an open book. While not everyone will necessarily care about the deleterious information, and it may be blunted by effective advertising, it is usually available.

Honesty Revisited

The model of universal information availability therefore forces a reexamination of business practices. In the process, it could be discovered that honesty in business may be not only the best policy also but the only one that a fully informed public will accept. A tycoon of the industrial age could sometimes oppress the work force, ignore safety standards, bribe officials, lie about the competition, create a monopoly, produce shoddy goods, and overcharge the public. All this could escape condemnation or even notice if the tycoon could simultaneously pose as a god-fearing, church-going philanthropist and benefactor. It would be impossible in ideal information age to operate this way, because such practices would quickly become common knowledge.

In addition, the perceived failure of moral relativism to provide society with useful and consistent answers to ethical problems has opened the way for a possible return to moral absolutism, and this is true in business as a part of the total society. In the conventional mid-twentieth century view, right and wrong had little meaning, so to have a different view of them in the various fragmented compartments of life created no philosophical problems, even if it did create social ones. In an absolutist view, right and wrong do have consistent meanings, and these

298

Page 299: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

meanings are true in all contexts, including business. Commerce is a part of life, and governed by the same rules; it does not constitute a world of its own. Its leaders will be expected to be privately and publicly clean, and it may become impossible to pretend that one's personal morality is irrelevant to one's fitness to lead a corporation in the public interest. Indeed, the corporation, which as a fictitious person is accountable for the ownership of property and the making of commercial transactions, will be held accountable for its moral integrity as well. Thus both business leaders and their corporate entities are increasingly being held responsible for the results of their decisions--in the workplace, the environment, the marketplace, and the personal space where products are used.

This trend is seen in two developments: first the widespread interest in developing codes of ethical conduct for professions and conflict of interest guidelines for politicians, and second in the proliferation of "ethical" mutual funds targeted to those who wish guarantees that they are investing in industries that do not, say, pollute, produce tobacco or alcohol products, or traffic in weapons, pesticides, or child labour. It is not that there is general agreement on which such activities are or are not ethical; the interesting thing here is the revival of interest in the idea of ethical behaviour--even in the absence of agreement on what is it and where it comes from.

Moreover, the private lives of business leaders are no longer seen as a thing apart from their public ones, but as part of a seamless whole. Such things as insider trading, bribery of officials, sexual exploitation of employees, false and misleading advertising, bait-and-switch selling tactics, and the theft of secrets through industrial espionage are all becoming harder to do and much harder to conceal from public scrutiny. That scrutiny may not in itself change anything--whether the public cares about such things is a separate issue--but the information will be available.

The public is paying closer attention to such arrangements as the "golden parachutes" out of takeover situations by the senior officers of a company, to insincerity in labor negotiations by both parties, to age and gender discrimination, to advertising innuendos, to high executive compensation, and to predatory pricing policies. In an information age, one might also suppose that there could be less tolerance of strikes, because they could be seen as communication breakdowns and therefore as violations of the reigning social paradigm.

Manufacturers are being held more accountable all the time for the effects of the products they make. For example, the maker of a defective computer printer that requires expensive repairs after a few months will not be able to hide behind the legalese of a ninety day warranty limitation but be required to make good on the product for a much longer period of time. Such openness was forced on the automobile industry by consumer advocates in the 1970s and 1980s and it now routinely conducts recalls for safety and other reasons that it would never have considered in the 1960s. Likewise, tobacco companies have been successfully sued for making, selling, and advertising products with reckless disregard for (and even concealment of) the danger to consumers' lives. The very advertising that glorified smoking as the epitome of the "good life" has been cited in lawsuits as deliberately leading people to their deaths. The bottlers and sellers of alcoholic drinks may be

299

Page 300: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

held partially liable for the carnage on the highways caused by the use of their products.

Such surprising (to a 1960s mindset) outcomes leads one to wonder whether the counsellors, politicians, child rearing specialists, educators, and ethicists whose advice produces injurious social outcomes will also be sued for malpractice in the future. After all if their product (bad advice) is found faulty, can they not be held liable as well?

As a result of such considerations, many managers are already concluding that profit now depends very much on at least a public perception of a business as honest, and on the fact that the ordinary citizen has many means of finding out if it is not. That is, the mutuality and dependency so often mentioned in this book extend to the relationship between corporations and their customers. Ignoring that mutuality of interests may have immediate and possibly devastating consequences for a company. A seamless WYSIWYG ("What You See Is What You Get") is clearly an aspect the kind of open society implied by universal information access. Honest guarantees, fast and sure repairs, and a genuine atmosphere of serving the customer are becoming the watchwords of business in the new age. The seamlessness of all aspects of life will not only be reflected in this way; it will require new attention to be paid to the education of children. After all, the child who is taught to see nothing wrong with stealing from a neighbor's apple tree or a classmate's desk is not likely to be honest with advertising and expense accounts as an adult.

Thus, along with the information paradigm come others. Honest guarantees, fast and workmanlike repairs, and a genuine atmosphere of serving the customer may well have to become the watchwords of business in the new age. That is, Caveat emptor is being replaced by Caveat vendor . These trends could be magnified by any more shifts away from the selling of goods and toward the provision of services, wherein the human element is even more important, for the whole product and process is on view to the customer at all times. In sum, if the industrial age created the consumer, the premise of the information age is that it enlightens and empowers the consumer.

Neither will it be easy for industrial or business concerns to cover up their wrongdoings or shortcomings in the future. For the sake of their own professional reputations and personal integrity, their own employees will "blow the whistle" much more frequently than in the past, and they will do so with the full protection of both law and public opinion.

Another Possibility

Lest all this discussion seem impossibly optimistic, it is worth repeating that another outcome of universal information availability is also possible--that no one

300

Page 301: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

will care about "damaging" facts. Perhaps the current attention to public and corporate morality is a passing phenomenon, a novelty whose bloom will soon wear off. What is more, the principle of holding manufacturers responsible for defective goods could be carried so far that many companies become afraid to introduce new products, lest they someday become the target of a liability suit for unforeseen defects. Should such fears spread further, technological innovation, along with much of the premise the information age seems to offer, could be thwarted. Or, it could shift to those parts of the world where product liability suits are less common.

On a more theoretical level, a society that has bought into a relativistic morality can have its collective view of right and wrong changed very easily. This could lead it to accept shoddy goods, corrupt or unfaithful politicians, and cheating at business as though they were normal. That this is not at all far fetched can be seen by the radical changes in recent years in views on sexual morality. That is, arbitrary or democratic ethics are clearly unstable--information availability could result in anarchy as easily as it could result in demands for greater integrity.

Thus, while the information age promises to change society, it will not necessarily do so in ways that are all for the better--people have to choose to act on information before it has any effect, and they may decide to do nothing.

8.7 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

The increasing complexity of economic activity through the various stages of civilization generates more sophisticated techniques for trade and commerce at each step. In particular, money is an abstraction for value that has been progressively refined from barter to furs to beads to metal to paper money and cheques. It is fast becoming just an electronic entry.

Meanwhile, shifts in the characteristic technology alter the balance of economic activity and power. Not only do old trades and professions vanish, but so do industries, while even entire countries slide from center stage to the sidelines as trading patterns change. In the information age, both industry and agriculture are being transformed by the new models, and once again there will be corporate and geographical winners and losers, in the relative sense at least.

Winners may include the electronics, communications, biochemical, habitat construction and aerospace industries along with the Pacific Rim nations. Relative losers include industrial activities such as making steel or machines and the countries either most tied to such enterprises or the most closed to rapid change and new ideas.

Both collectivizing and individualizing trends were noted in the shifts in economic power, with larger than ever capital accumulations being made necessary to finance some of the construction projects, and simultaneously better facilities for individual participation in and control over the economy. Certain trade-offs of privacy and freedom to gain such power were noted. A cashless society and more flexible instruments of debt and equity were among the possible innovations

301

Page 302: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

discussed, though the actual social responses to enabling technology cannot be reliably predicted.

The consequences of universal access to information on the conduct of business were discussed, and two possible outcomes suggested--one that business would be forced to conduct itself ethically, and the other that little change would take place in the long run regardless of the amount of information available.

Discussion Questions

1. What would be the effect on a gold-based currency system of the discovery in one country of a gold deposit containing more than the entire world supply previously known?

2. When some governments run a deficit, rather than borrow money, they just print more to pay the debts. What effect does this have on the price of goods and on the exchange rate for that currency internationally?

3. Suppose a government were to tax information access (so much per byte of information transferred on the net). What effect would this have on the progress of the information society? Consider both economic and control implications.

4. Suppose that food production were to become an entirely robotized industrial process with chemical and energy raw materials so that plant and animal husbandry were no longer necessary. What economic effect would this have? How would it change society?

5. Which is now more nearly correct--that consumer tastes determine which products get manufactured, or that available technology determines this and then advertising must be used to make consumer tastes match. Which way ought it to be, and why? Who should enforce this?

6. Discuss the advantages and disadvantages of electronic shopping. Are there things that will never be bought this way, or is it possible to eliminate most, if not all, retail stores?

7. Discuss the advantages and potential dangers of the cashless society.8. Attack or defend the suggestion that in the future economic and corporate

loyalties will be more important than political and geographical ones.9. Suggest ways in which high technology can be used to assist the peoples of

underdeveloped nations without making their situation even worse.10. If technology does allow the economy to be micromanaged, should it be?

What are the advantages and potential dangers?11. Discuss the effect of standards in high-tech industries. Do they promote

economic activity, or do they smother innovation?12. What are some specific ways in which high technology is favoring

economic development in the Pacific Rim countries?13. Argue that in the long run the information age means that economic

prosperity will be independent of geography.14. The role of Central Europe in the information age was scarcely mentioned

in the Chapter. Do some research of your own and write a paper outlining the most probable role that these nations will play in the future economy.

302

Page 303: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

15. The text suggests that labor will be more professional and less adversarial than in the past. Argue that this cannot and indeed should not be so.

16. Develop further the concept of paying for services in shares of the payer, whether an individual or company. What practical, economic, and social consequences would such a system have? Perhaps you could argue that it cannot work or must not be allowed for ethical reasons.

17. Argue that a Metalibrary facility would make it harder, not easier, for the ordinary citizen to have an economic influence.

18. Consider the proposition, "Business is business and ethics is ethics and never the twain shall meet." Either attack or defend this statement (a) as an observation on what now is the case and (b) as a statement of what ought to be the case. A classroom debate on the subject could be organized.

19. Explore further the relationship between the openness of information and the ethical behavior of the business world. Which is more likely--that business conduct will improve or that there will be little change?

20. Is there a religious view of business ethics? Try to use examples from as many religious and historical periods as possible.

21. Discuss the advantages and disadvantages of working from the home. Consider the personal, social, economic, and ethical aspects. For instance, are such workers more or less likely to be exploited?

22. Research the causes of the great depression of the 1930s and make your own assessment of the likelihood of such a thing happening again in the foreseeable future.

23. Which is more important--loyalty to one's company or the right of the public to know about that company's activities. In particular, if you became privy to potentially damaging information about your employer's pricing, advertising, or other business practices, what would you do?

24. You work in a hospital and have a strong commitment to the patients and to their community. You are also in a hospital employees' union and believe in the importance of that community as well. After a protracted and unpleasant set of negotiations breaks off, your union calls a strike, which you believe could have been avoided if both sides had been more open and honest with each other. The union says you cannot in conscience cross the picket line, but you have been taught all your life that you cannot in conscience abandon your responsibilities. What do you do?

25. Suppose instead you do not work at the hospital but are a member of another union, and its leaders tell you that you must honor the hospital picket line. What do you do if: (a) You break your leg and need hospitalization, and no other facilities are available within forty kilometers? (b) You have a dying relative in the hospital who wants you to visit her? Is there an essential difference between this situation and a strike of teachers? Of industrial workers? If so, what is the difference?

26. At the company you work for, software is routinely pirated. Your manager buys one copy of a new word processor and expects you to put a copy on the computer you are using. She as much as tells you that if you don't you can find another job. What do you do, and why?

303

Page 304: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

27. Research and report on several examples of high-tech companies that had great success initially but eventually went bankrupt. What were the chief causes of such failures?

28. Give additional examples of products that are sold today with little regard for the consequences of their use, and detail the changes that need to be made as people become more informed about such matters.

29. A chemical company makes a herbicide that has been shown to be particularly effective on a plant from which a black-market drug is derived. The government orders a large quantity of the herbicide intending to spray it indiscriminately over remote areas of South American nations, with their cooperation, in an attempt to reduce trafficking in the drug. You, as president of the company, are concerned that eventually there may be damaging lawsuits against your firm if this program goes ahead. Should you place the potential interests of your shareholders first and refuse to sell the chemical, or should you place the declared interests of the government first? What do you do, and why?

30. Several times in the chapter it was noted that people who have more information about unethical activities in the political or economic sphere might not choose to act on their knowledge, but might instead change their view of what is ethical or simply tolerate the activity. Research this further and either argue that it is the civic duty of all persons to act on their ethical beliefs, or argue that it is their civic duty to tolerate all ethical systems, regardless of how they differ from theirs. In either case, be sure to say how the legal system is connected with society's sense of ethics.

31. "Monopolies are good because they lead to standardization and efficiency." Argue for or against this position.

32. Research innovation and monopolistic practice in the computer industry and describe the relationship between the two.

33. The last section of the chapter for the most part argued that a consequence of the information paradigm would be better warranties, higher quality goods, and more open and honest business. Argue that this is not the case and that the opposite result will occur.

34. Suggest a "teraproject" of your own and outline how it could be organized and financed.

35. Which is more likely and why--that the general population will demand that business will return to a more absolutist ethic, or that they will simply ignore behaviour once thought unethical?

36. Select a particular type of business or professional activity and write a code of ethics for it. Defend your points, saying what is the basis for each.

37. The author suggests a trend from hierarchicalism to networking to flexing to professional/contracting models for organizing enterprise. Argue that he is wrong, and rigid hierarchicalism is the best business model.

38. What are some other measures than profit to determine the efficiency of the techniques an economic enterprise? Argue that one of them is better.

Bibliography

304

Page 305: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Braybrooke, David. Ethics in the World of Business. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanhold, 1983.

Chewning, Richard C. Business Ethics in a Changing Culture. Richmond, VA: Rubert F. Dame, 1983.

DeGeorge, Richard T. Business Ethics. New York: Macmillan, 1982.Donaldson, Thomas, and Werhane, Patricia H. (eds.). Ethical Issues in

Business--A Philosophical Approach. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1979.Ellul, Jacques. Money and Power. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1984.Ezorsky, Gertrude (ed.). Moral Rights in the Workplace. New York: SUNY Press,

1987.Glos, Raymond E., et al. Business--Its Nature and Environment, An

Introduction. 9th ed. Cincinnati: South-Western, 1980.Lewis, Ted. Why the Economy Is So Good IEEE Computer May 1998 p110-112Hess, J. Daniel. Ethics in Business and Labor. Scottdale, PA: Herald Press,

1977.Hirschmeior, J. and Yui, T. The Development of Japanese Business. 2nd ed.

London: Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1981.Hosmer, LaRue Tone. The Ethics of Management. Homewood IL: Irwin, 1987.Naisbitt, John, and Aburdene, Patricia. Re-inventing the Corporation. New

York: Warner, 1985.Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner, 1984.Pemberton, Prentiss L., and Finn, Daniel Rush. Toward a Christian Economic

Ethic--Stewardship and Social Power. Minneapolis, MN: Winston, 1985.Westin, Alan F. Whistle Blowing! Loyalty and Dissent in the Corporation. New

York: McGraw-Hill, 1981.Williams, Oliver, and Hovick, John (eds.). The Judeo-Christian Vision and the

Modern Corporation. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame, 1982.

Internet Resources:

MacDonald , Chris <mailto:[email protected]<http://www.ethics.ubc.ca/resources/business/

305

Page 306: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 9Technology, the State, and the Law

Seminar - "Computers, the Law and Rights" 9.1 Foundations for Law and the State 9.2 Technology and the State--Big Brother and Little Brother 9.3 Technology and War     9.3.1 Confrontation Outcome Scenarios     9.3.2 Other Kinds of War     9.3.3 Policing a Peace     9.3.4 Summary 9.4 Some Legal Problems for the Next Age     9.4.1 An Overview of Current Problems     9.4.2 The Present Law     9.4.3 The Insufficiency of Law Alone     9.4.4 Some Proposed Remedies     9.4.5 Summary 9.5 Technocrime 9.6 Ethics, the Law, and the State 9.7 Solving the Problem 9.8 New State and Legal Forms for the New Age 9.9 Summary and Further Discussion

9.1 Foundations for Law and the State The network of relationships among people that is termed society is not

simply a random affair; it requires organization and supervision. To achieve this, there have developed the related institutions of the law and the state. For its part, law exists to codify the moral/ethical consensus of a society and to provide the "ought" with some force to back up the "shall". It prevents citizens from harming or exploiting each other and protects the nation itself from those who would destroy it from within or without. It regulates behaviour in personal and commercial ways and punishes transgressors for the benefit of society as a whole.

In times past, law's presumption was that it flowed from the emperor or king who gave it either benevolently or despotically to protect the royal regime and its peoples. Later--in particular because of the Magna Carta and to a lesser extent because of Irish Brehon law--the presumption became rex lex, that is, that law rules over all, including the monarch. This principle came to underlie the laws of modern Western democracies. Even more fundamental is the assumption, applied in such situations as war crimes trials and international trade cases, is that there is such a thing as justice in an absolute and abstract sense--even when it may be missing

306

Page 307: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

from the laws of one or more nations. This concept is not exclusively due, even in the West, to Judeo-Christian principles being incorporated into law but was also present in Greek philosophic thought.

Another assumption is that the people and institutions covered by the law agree to be regulated. Even if the ethical consensus is cultural rather than religious, there must be one, for if the law is not either respected as an authority in itself or as deriving from another (higher) source, it will not be obeyed without the application of force (which itself is a higher appeal). The best laws in a democracy are those in which the citizens perceive they have a personal stake, and are therefore willing to obey even if they may also have reasons to dislike them. Even better are those laws with which few citizens will ever come into conflict because their acceptance is so universal. This presumes, however, that the citizens take an active role in exercising and so maintaining their democratic freedoms, or they will surely lose them.

It is also worth observing that because law itself depends upon and derives from the ethical consensus of society, the law's direct impact on society is secondary to that of the underlying values. To put it another way, law does not so much change behaviour as it regulates the exceptions to what the moral consensus regards as acceptable behaviour. This dependence of law upon ethics, and the simultaneous assumption that there exists an absolute justice means that law assumes the existence of an absolute ethic from which it may derive justice. Thus, there are fundamental conflicts between the assumptions of relativistic moral theories and those of law, and these are difficult to reconcile without changing one or the other. For if morality is relative, so is the law on which it is based, and there is no abstract justice, nor is there any means of deriving or enforcing national or international law. For example, there would have been no case to make against the Nazi war criminals or modern terrorists under a strictly relativistic law, and this illustration alone is a powerful argument for a form of absolutism in both realms. Moreover, without a pervasive and compelling ethical consensus, society cannot survive the high-tech empowerment of many unrestrained individuals with the ability to destroy everything.

Even if the influence of law upon society is neither direct nor immediate, the law does touch and is touched upon by technology. For instance, the Romans had great success with their legal system because they viewed it as a management technique for an orderly society, and so long as they continued to do so, their law proved very durable. The extensive ocean-based trading systems of the European imperial powers enabled by ship-building technology led to a system of maritime law. The industrial society had to develop laws to regulate all its technologies in order to protect its users and the society at large. Today, the ability to store and compare fingerprints, retinal patterns, and DNA records has become critical to the resolution of many criminal cases, and has potential to partially restore confidence in the modern legal system.

The state, on the other hand, is not only involved in both law and technology, but also affects its citizens' lives directly and immediately in these and many other areas. The state has two principal reasons for its existence. One is to devise and enforce laws of all kinds to promote orderly behaviour and commerce, through which it serves to institutionalize the economic life of the community. The other is to

307

Page 308: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

provide leadership for the people being governed--to represent them to other peoples; to have its leaders act as role models for virtuous behaviour; and to plot a course for the future by making choices for resource allocation. Because the body of law is large, and tends to develop slowly, the state's impact for change can be much greater in the leadership role than in the legislative.

Every state must also convince its people of its ongoing right to rule them, for unless they are so persuaded, they will eventually destroy that state and bring forward a new state and new leaders. This appeal for legitimacy can be by force, and often has been. Indeed, the overwhelming experience of the majority of the Earth's peoples has been government by tyranny. Sometimes, philosophical or theological foundations for the state have been given, such as the "divine right of kings" or Plato's "philosopher-king" concept. There have almost always been alliances of religion and state in the business of governing, and these have added an authority to the state that it has not always been able to find on its own. It is interesting to observe in this connection that the Bible itself, though cited as an authority by many Western states through the centuries, makes no statements whatever about an ideal form of human government--only about the duties of citizens in the state and the obligations of leaders to their people. Its teachings on universal justice, human dignity, and the equality of all persons have, however, been a powerful indirect influence in the development of democratic forms of government.

The modern secular state has no exemption from this need to appeal for its legitimacy to higher authority of some kind. In today's totalitarian states of the left or the right, xenophobic nationalism or statism takes over the role of religion in this respect. The Caesars were quite consistent in viewing the Christians as a threat to their state--the idea there was a higher authority than their own persons was indeed subversive. Likewise today, the current leader may be honoured, praised and paraded in ways not particularly distinguishable from the worship of a deity, except in terminology. Totalitarianism may attempt to establish the state itself as the highest authority, but it is more common to appeal to other loyalties as higher still--the party, the cause, the revolution, or an assortment of political dogmas are common choices. These all share a vagueness that must be supplemented with a daily dose of propaganda to keep citizens loyal. This can work quite well if other information flows are restricted or can be overwhelmed, for lack of substance is no more an obstacle to a clever marketer in the political realm than in the economic one.

In the modern democracies, personalities are also emphasized, but the objects of such adoration are more likely to be entertainers or athletes than politicians. The original operating philosophy of the democratic secular state was that its people could collectively and more or less infallibly determine the will of God and/or what was absolutely right, then express these in action. Instead of the "might makes right" of tyranny, democracy proclaimed "majorities discern right". The fundamental assumption was that most of the people, at least when voting, would collectively know what is best and act upon it. That is, democracy is founded on something more than the whims of the electorate and the manipulation of these by clever advertising or demagoguery. There is an assumption built into the very fabric

308

Page 309: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

of the democratic idea that a generalized or universal morality or ethical consensus exists and that the people can be trusted both to know what this is and to reflect that knowledge consistently in their actions. Should this notion be lost, say if the prevailing view became that the state serves neither a deity nor abstract principles, but simply the current will of the majority, democracy would be in as much jeopardy as if its peoples simply failed to exercise its practice.

All this is not to say that propaganda and other emotional appeals are not employed in democracies, for they most certainly are. However, they are used more in the service of political or entertainment personalities who are seeking public acceptance than by the state itself. The legitimacy of the democratic state is more or less assumed by those involved, though this was not always so. Such a state does not usually require propaganda to support its existence, though it may to sway public opinion to its policies--at least to the point of making people believe they have been consulted, and are therefore part of the enterprise. Moreover, political parties tend to abuse power by using state funds to trumpet their virtues in the effort to get re-elected, but this is an aberration in an otherwise cleaner record. The democratic state is fundamentally dependent upon a mutual trust in the collective rightness of its electorate and in the integrity of its leadership, not on propaganda.

The notion that there exists a knowable "right" is therefore implicit to Western democracy. It depends for its very existence on an absolutist ethic, for it claims to be absolutely superior to tyranny. If the best ethic is relativistic or situationist, an arbitrary form of government would have as much claim to legitimacy as does a democracy--that is, neither would have any. Provided the concepts of free speech, universal justice and liberty are themselves absolutes with a higher moral authority than any form of government, the people governed know these principles to be true, and act upon them, rule by the wishes of the majority is legitimate.

This establishes an interesting paradox, for the freedom to hold differing views can exist only in a state whose chief absolute is that such freedom is necessary, yet the genuine pluralism this implies could easily lead to an ethical chaos that produces anarchy or tyranny and so destroys freedom. Likewise, pluralism can easily slide into the notion that all idea systems--including the absolute ones underlying democracy itself--are not just tolerable, but of equal value. If this happens, the philosophical foundations of democracy evaporate. The democratic state is, therefore, a fragile institution--always open to the possibility of being persuaded that its values are only relative and of being taken over by an arbitrary and tyrannical ruler--yet always needing to remain confident enough of its fundamental absolutes to give even those greatest enemies a free platform to attack it verbally.

What is more, as the World Trade Center incident shows, democracy's enemies can also use those freedoms to assemble physical attacks without much fear of discovery until it is too late.

How can this confidence be maintained in the future? As shall be seen, technology may have something to do with it, for it opens up some interesting possibilities for both types of state.

9.2 Technology and the State--Big Brother and Little Brother

309

Page 310: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It was observed in Chapter 1 that technology development is of critical importance in understanding changes in society. The same is true of the state--the governing institution of society--for it is the character and actions of the state that ultimately will write its peoples' history and affect the neighbouring states both in place and time.

Reviewing the development of the various stages of civilization, it is easy to see that the state has grown in size and complexity with the numbers of people it governs, with the technologies which it uses and administers, and with the economy it seeks to manage. When transportation and communication were primitive, the state was a localized affair. The strongest or most successful individual in a small area could rule or influence it solely for personal enrichment or benefit. Even hunter-gatherers were not so busy surviving that they could not mount excursions to other territories, waging war to control land, food, animals and slaves. There were elaborate social structures developed in some such societies, and those of one of the most successful--the Eastern North American natives' "Six Nations" --had a direct influence on the constitution of the United States itself.

Agricultural societies had developed a variety of kingdoms, empires and even democracies by the time of Christ--some of them far more successful than others. The success of each was in direct proportion to its ability to use the best available technology for transportation and communication. As the focus of these eventually shifted from land to sea and from the Eastern Mediterranean and Orient to Western Europe, and then to the American East, so did the centres of the successful states. That is, the current centre of economic activity and expansion will invariably be the centre of political influence for the immediately following time.

Throughout this long period, democracy has had only relatively short runs. The Greek version was based on the votes of free and educated citizens who met and debated the day's issues in public forum. It was limited to such city states for three closely related reasons. First, democracy assumes an informed citizenry, and therefore requires a means by which they can be kept informed. So long as they can physically meet together and debate face to face, this can be achieved. However, there are obvious physical limitations to such a system, and these ensured that it never grew to encompass more than a small city. Second, democracy assumes an informable (that is, educated) citizenry. The people who gather together to make decisions must understand the issues fully and be able to explore what are the consequences of the courses of action they may take. The third is that since the state was closely allied to the economy, decision making was generally limited to those with economic interests in the state. Such a democracy was possible, therefore, only for those who had economic interests (i.e., not for women or slaves). The greater the degree of economic participation by individuals, the more broadly based was decision making power. Early forms of democracy, and not just the Greek, always limited the franchise in some way--usually to free, adult, educated, land-owning males, on the assumptions that everyone else was not informable, and being unable to make informed decisions, should not be allowed to participate in them at all. It was also assumed that not everyone had an economic interest, and so could not be qualified to make economic decisions.

310

Page 311: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The industrial age caused some of these assumptions to be swept aside permanently, for the workers in mines and factories had to be educated to some extent in order to work the equipment and use the techniques. As the machines became more sophisticated, and work shifted to white collar occupations, they had to become much more educated and then economically independent as well in order not only to work but also to be consumers. From this starting position at the agricultural/industrial transition point, the state variously followed one of two paths. One reinforced the democracies that were simultaneously developing, and the other resulted in new kinds of tyranny.

Technology and Big Brother

As Jacques Ellul argues in The Technological Society, the development of new techniques, and the necessity for applying them on a universal scale to achieve full potential, results in an inevitable growth of the state, for it is the only agency capable of satisfying the demand for such universal applications. This is true in economic management, in education, in the provision of medical care, in transportation, in communication, in the provision of consumer utilities, in law enforcement, and in basic scientific and technological research. For one field after another, the size, costs, and risk become too great for the private sector, so the public sector first participates and eventually takes over.

Both communism and fascism came out of this milieu as attempts to achieve total management of the citizenry through systematic application of appropriate technologies. Both are industrial-age philosophies that require a citizenry sufficiently educated to use technology, but sufficiently uninformed so as not to question the state's decision-making powers. Fascism failed in Europe because of necessity it had other items on its agenda--after all, an educated, but uninformed citizenry must have its attention focused away from the business of the state lest it become informed. Putting that attention onto the destruction of "enemies" is an effective temporary measure, but either victory or defeat renders this technique moot, and all states relying on it must therefore eventually fail. Thus Fascist states are either defeated by external forces, or they suffer a revolution from within. Neither of these necessarily relieve the tyranny, for it may only replace one set of masters by another, and these may be far harsher. The fascist states that did survive World War II, or were founded later, remained far from the world's economic mainstream and away from public attention. In the 1970s and 1980s, many of these went through peaceful revolutions and saw the establishment of more democratic regimes, and by the 1990s there were relatively few fascist states or military dictatorships remaining.

Radical egalitarianism, or communism, on the other hand, was, for a time, more successful for two reasons. First, in theory, its declared enemies were poverty and injustice, so it had genuine incentives to offer an oppressed people in persuading them to exchange one form of tyranny for another. Second, it delivered on its promises, at least to some extent, in part by acting socialistically according to its stated philosophy, but also in part by pragmatically borrowing capital from the rest of the industrial world and acting as a state capitalist. However inefficient this

311

Page 312: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

may have been by Western standards, Russian statism did offer its peasants more than did the old Czarist agrarian system. However, the very arena of its success illustrates why the Russian system was never successfully exported to a country where the industrial revolution had already taken place, even though Marx intended his ideas for industrialized societies. Simply put, industrial societies require educated consumers, and an educated citizenry cannot forever be kept uninformed by the state. Moreover, consumers have an economic role by definition--their economic voice is eventually heard regardless of any attempt to suppress it. Neither is everyone the same--people differ in intelligence, the willingness to learn or work, and their aptitude for the ingredients of economic success. The state that demands equal outcomes regardless of inputs can therefore achieve its goals only by increasing its application of force to the citizenry until it results in either bankruptcy or rebellion. Doctrinaire socialism will therefore always fail.

Ellul and others are therefore correct when they observe that the actual application of Communism is essentially the same as Fascism--the two have somewhat different philosophical roots, but their manifestations as states are not particularly distinguishable by the average citizen. Losing one's life, property, or freedom to enrich an elite, maintain an army, and support an all-encompassing state does not appear to be different just because of the label attached by politicians or academics to the philosophy behind the tyranny. It can be anticipated therefore that the old Russian style statism is applicable only to relatively primitive agrarian societies, or to those in shock trauma after a war, and not elsewhere. This is due to the information revolution for two reasons: first, because the equally poor of such a nation can see that their system does not work--those of other countries have visibly more, and they want to be equal to them, not each other, and second, because informed citizens do not long tolerate any tyranny. Since even the people of third world nations have greater access to information than ever before, establishing state capitalist tyranny is becoming more difficult all the time.

When people were already under the unjust and repressive despotism of a king, general, or dictator, they were loathe to believe that their lot could become any worse, and sometimes welcomed Marxism. Despite its consistent failures, its credentials as a supposed liberator were not always examined closely, for potential subjects often lacked both information access and democratic experience to realize its true nature. Because of the prerequisite level of education and information access present in an already industrialized nation, it is becoming less likely with the passage of years that any nation will embrace communism overtly. It could get much the same thing, however, if its people are not vigilant and they allow the state to acquire similar power gradually and by default, or if the state appears to lose its moral legitimacy and they demand a dictatorship to restore confidence.

Even the authoritarian state based on a genuine "big brother"--the god-like larger-than-life glorious leader whose image is constantly held before the people--cannot continue indefinitely in the information age. Even if the despot can prevent other information sources from reaching her people, she must eventually die, or perhaps a wide-ranging natural disaster such as a famine strikes. In either event, the feet of the icon are eventually revealed to be of clay, and the illusion fails. At this point the state either crumbles into anarchy, is taken over from the outside, or

312

Page 313: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the successors of the autocrat preside over a metamorphosis of the government into some new form.

It is important to emphasize that the idea that it is possible to keep an educated citizenry uninformed is self-contradictory and, in the medium to long run, self-destructive. Even in a purely technological age, such a state of affairs is inherently unstable, and requires ever more frequent exertion of tight state control over intellectuals to maintain--an activity that cannot be continued indefinitely without robbing the state of its own future. The most damaging development to such philosophies is the information revolution, for its advent has destroyed forever the second of the two assumptions on which tyranny is based--for in an information age the citizenry cannot be kept uninformed. The growing base of information about the more affluent West was one of the major contributing factors in the demise of the Soviet Union and its satellites in the early 1990s, and it will eventually prove the downfall of all remaining dictatorships.

The case of the two Germanys is instructive in this respect. Ultimately it proved impossible to keep half a nation under totalitarian dictatorship while the other half was free. The Berlin wall showed the failure of the Soviet doctrine. Once it was erected, it was only a matter of time before the eastern regime toppled, and a costly re-unification begun. The two Koreas make a similar point. One is affluent, thriving, a substantial player in the world economy. The oppressed North is impoverished to the point of being destitute. In this case, the economic gulf has become so wide, however, that even were the North to become free, the South may wish nothing to do with unification.

Little Brother

While all states have of necessity grown with the techniques they are called upon to manage, democracy has also been able to adapt as it has grown. It is important to realize that democracy depends utterly upon the informed electorate--and modern means of communication are what have kept it informed. When information transfer was slow, the franchise was limited and representative democracy was both appropriate and reasonably efficient. The people's elected representatives would meet and debate the issues and then report back to their segment of the electorate who would then decide whether to keep them in office or send someone else the next time. In such a system, representatives were elected in order to become fully informed decision makers because the electorate could not. They then had to explain the decisions they had made to the less well-informed population at large. The electorate was essentially delegating the process of

313

Page 314: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

assessing information, but only to an extent--they expected to be advised and consulted by their representatives. The slowness of information transfer meant that office holders had to be given terms of two to six years in order to ensure mature deliberation and to allow them to be judged on more than a single issue. Meanwhile, as education and economic interests became universal, the once limited franchise did as well, and the base of democracy broadened, first to former slaves, then to women, and finally to some of the economically dependent through the lowering the voting age.

As the next era dawns, the electorate is better educated than ever, and much more capable of fully informing themselves, rather than finding it necessary to delegate this responsibility to representatives. Consequently, people now expect more direct participation in the decision-making process. The information lag time in political matters as in all others has virtually ceased to exist. An obscure Middle East newspaper can publish a paragraph on an arms for hostages deal buried on an inside page one day, and a thousand North American newspapers can pillory the U.S. president over the contents the next day. The bedroom antics and drug habits of each office seeker or holder constitute information available to every household, and disaffected clerks, bodyguards, and secretaries can achieve media fame and fortune by blowing the whistle on their political masters. In the new era, therefore, nothing can be assumed to be a political or personal secret; citizens are fully informable. Among other things, politicians can no longer assume that they have any private life whatever, nor that their ethical standards can be substantially different from those who elect them--without at least the latter's knowledge and implicit consent. This does not force politicians to adopt an absolute code of morality, but it does require them not to deviate much from popular standards.

Another consequence of this information availability is a growing desire to participate directly in decision making rather than simply send representatives to do it. Thus far, as Naisbitt details in Megatrends, this has resulted in greater interest in state or provincial, local, and community affairs, for this is where citizens have direct access to public forums and referenda and thus an immediate influence. There has been a corresponding decrease in interest and voter turnout where national politics are concerned, for these so far present fewer opportunities for such direct participation, and lacking this, people are becoming increasingly alienated from the central government--a dangerous state of affairs in geographically large nations such as Canada and the United States.

In the medium-to-long term, the nature of Western democracies seems likely to change in order to take this informed electorate directly into the decision-making process. At least some national decisions may be made by direct debate and vote of all interested citizens. Many others now handled at the national level might be delegated to state and local governments, reflecting the new realities by reducing central powers.

Still another variation is possible: require potential voters on given issues to qualify by demonstrating both an interest in and a knowledge of the subject--perhaps by reading and participating in the debate preceding the vote. There are now few technical obstacles to such direct decision making, only political and traditional ones. The full facilities of the Metalibrary are not required, only those of a

314

Page 315: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

much smaller and more easily implemented political data system. The chief danger of participatory democracy, as opposed to representative democracy, is the one inherent in all situations involving zero-time information flow. They tend to result in instant and therefore ill-considered decisions. The qualifying of an electorate for an issue might cause a sufficient delay to prevent this. Perhaps some classes of decisions will need a constitutionally guaranteed debating period in order to ensure that a resolution will come out of mature deliberation.

At the same time, the internationalization of trade and commerce has had a tendency to create super-states that transcend present national borders. This is already taking place with the European Community, and may one day do so in Southeast Asia. The free trade treaty between Canada and the United States (with later additions of Mexico, Chile, and others to come) could eventually result in the largest international economy in the world, and the Europeans are responding to such initiatives with a greater unity of their own, to prevent becoming subject to North American and Japanese trade domination for years to come. There will no doubt be other such trade zones established, because the benefits of international trade and the harm done by protectionism are manifest. For instance, Asian countries whose economies were badly damaged in the late 1990s might hope to recover by establishing stronger trade organizations of their own.

Despite the necessary internationalization of trade, legislators in some countries may enter into protectionism anyway, for they may be unable to see beyond certain narrow local issues, and they may be prepared to destroy the international economy for years to gain a few years' jobs for one city. It was exactly such behaviour that was one of the chief causes of the great depression of the 1930s. Neither can nationalism be discounted as a factor, and this element may ultimately prevent the traditionally fractious Europeans from achieving unity. As the attacks on the Multilateral Agreement on Investment (MAI) in the late 1990s illustrate, nationalism is still a potent enough force to doom a treaty deemed to surrender too much sovereignty to a vague and ill-defined internationalism. This suggests that even though such an internationalization might well be in most people's best economic interests, efficiency of technique is not sufficient in itself to guarantee the outcome, and it may not happen for a generation or two, if ever. However, in the long run, it is probably in the best economic interests of all nations to give up some sovereignty and allow fuller and freer international trade to operate. Whether such trade alliances will eventually also result in formal political unity (whether regional or global) may not matter, for the trade alliance itself may become the de facto senior government for most practical purposes.

What do these twin flows of power from the national level to the local one (on the one hand) and to the international one (on the other) mean for the future of the national state? Its office holders could lose personal power and prestige, and nationalism could diminish as a world force. If so, war could also lessen in importance. However, the regional governments that are today's nations would not necessarily vanish, but could serve as local checks and balances on the world economic and political system. The individual voter may have an extended reach of power, for the Metalibrary is capable of promoting the billions of little brothers of the world into the drivers' seat of participatory democracy on a global basis. At the

315

Page 316: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

same time, it seems that interest in the governance of the local community will continue to increase, and this could eventually result in the substantial transfer of decision making and taxation powers to this level. If these economic trends were the only factors, the net result could be a gradual diminishing of nationalism in favour of global and local interests. Nationalism as it is known today is largely a creation of the departed agricultural and industrial ages, and it might not be expected that it would necessarily survive far into the next era. On the other hand, the break-up of the former Soviet Union has revealed a great deal of traditional nationalism that had been suppressed through much of this century. Without the Russian threat hanging over their heads, the old/new nations of eastern Europe readily returned to their traditional violent nationalism, ignoring the unifying trends of the information revolution until they could either settle some old scores, or give birth to new citizens whom they could teach to have new priorities.

Note however, that this last comment assumes they might want to teach new priorities or perspectives. It is doubtful ethnic members in the former Yugoslavia do desire this. Those in the Middle East and on the Indian subcontinent who teach hatred to their children in their schools are unlikely to stop doing so any time soon.

There are therefore collectivist and individualist trends in the affairs of state as well as in the operation of the economy. Individuals may become more protective of, more interested in, and more desirous of control over what they regard as their local turf, and if they can achieve this even while participating occasionally in global decisions, they may be as content and as democratic as the citizens of any of today's nations, even though their relationship to the state will have changed dramatically.

In the last two civilizations, the government bureaucracy made most decisions of state, and it can certainly be expected that the civil service will be as much a feature of the next era as of the last. It may, along with other service groups, become more of a professional and managerial cadre. If so, the role of elected political leaders and heads of state might become even more ceremonial in nature than it is now. Whether this subsumption of the political and economic life in a technical one is entirely a good thing or not remains to be seen; but it seems reasonable to suppose that one day it could become no more appropriate to elect the state's managers than to elect its doctors or electricians. One does not need to suppose that such a situation will imply a loss of liberty for individual citizens, nor that it would result in an amorphous technical dictatorship. On the contrary, individual citizens could have more power in local matters as well as input into global policy making.

It should be kept in mind, however, that even though technology both enables such changes and may drive society toward them, they may actually come about only slowly, or not at all. Institutions have a momentum and life of their own, and have a way of surviving in roughly their traditional way--even if in form alone--long after they have outlived their usefulness, or better replacements are available. Such change as does come to Western style democracy may be slow--perhaps almost unnoticeably so, and thus lag far behind the level of enabling technique--there are always many with a vested interest in the status quo.

316

Page 317: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

What is more, change is a fragile thing. The availability of new techniques for better democracy does not mean that these techniques will never be subverted to destroy democracy, for tyranny is always a possibility. Indeed, although information technology appears to reduce the risk of traditional despotism based on fear and ignorance, it also allows for rapid spread of bad ideas along with the good, and so increases the risk of a self-inflicted tyranny based on demagoguery or on oppression of minorities by the majority, or both. Which path (greater freedom or less) will actually be followed depends more on the attitudes and motivations of the peoples of the present democracies than it does on the enabling techniques. It also depends on there still being an ethical consensus-- the social glue that is the basis for the rule of law. If the present infatuation with relativism continues to erode this base, it is difficult to see what basis there would eventually be for government at all.

The Global Struggle

However, it should also be clear that universal availability of information is ultimately the mortal enemy of tyranny. The computer, radio and television, copying machines, and the free press all strike at the heart of regimes like the old Russian statist empire, and it could not long endure in its previous form in the face of such technology. The Chernobyl incident well illustrates this, for it was Western media coverage of satellite photographs that forced the Russian leader to go on television and explain the nuclear accident to his people--an act without precedent in that nation. Even China, with its centuries-old reverence for authority has already transitioned itself from Maoism to a mixed system in which communism is disappearing. Undoubtedly, this process will continue.

The underfed, poorly clothed, and poorly housed billions of the third world can now also see in living colour how the peoples of the industrialized world live. They are ready to accept either democracy or a new tyranny if it means they will get a share of the same material pie. It is entirely possible that as the information age and the participatory democracy it brings, come to Russia and China, their tyranny and state capitalism will be temporarily adopted elsewhere in pre-industrial countries. All this makes for very precarious times, for it is still possible for tyranny to use existing technology to overwhelm democracy, and attempt to abort the information age. Indeed, some degree of international cooperation is needed to continue; several-well placed nuclear explosions in medium orbit would effectively destroy most electronic equipment in the world, and there are a number of nations with such a capability.

Television also makes it possible for a morally conservative third world to pass harsh judgement upon the West for its self-portrayal in this medium (That is, the religious leaders of countries like Iran refer to the United States as "the great Satan" for moral reasons as well as political ones). As such countries grow in power, it is possible to imagine these judgements eventually resulting in new "holy wars" with the goal of bringing the West in line morally. Such conflicts would also serve to maintain tyrannies that promote them in the same way as in the past, for of the support of totalitarianism by the making of war with technology there seems to be no end.

317

Page 318: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

9.3 Technology and War The Professor is waiting in the seminar room with Johanna, Dorcas, and Ellen.

As he frowns at his watch, the door opens and Nellie arrives with a visitor who has to duck even more than her to get under the top of the six-foot eight door frame. The visitor is a broad shouldered woman with a somewhat dark, freckled face, red hair done up in a bun, and is wearing a kilt, a brocaded shirt and vest. A broadsword, a heavy cudgel, and a slingshot hang from her belt, and over her shoulder are holstered two throwing knives. She is limping slightly. Nellie is similarly attired and armed, and sporting a large bruise on her face.

Johanna: (to Ellen) I thought Nellie was big, but this one must be over seven feet!

Professor: (rubbing his hands and brightening) Lady Mara, thank you for taking time from your busy schedule. Nellie, glad the two of you made it. Would you do the introductions, please?

Nellie: (indicating each in turn) Mara, these are Johanna, Dorcas, and Ellen. The Professor you know. May I present Lady Mara Meathe, administrator, physician, and regular army officer.

Professor: You're a little late.Nellie: We did a stick work-out in the gym. Just time for one hit apiece.Ellen: (looking at Mara skeptically) And which of the Professor's imaginary

worlds are you from, dearie?Mara: (turning sharply to Nellie, who suddenly grows pale) Is this sacred

ground?Nellie: (shuddering) I think we better assume that, Mara.Ellen: What's that supposed to mean?Mara: Our officers' schools are held under the sword truce of sacred ground.Nellie: (glaring savagely at Ellen) Under those rules she's not allowed to kill

you for insulting her as long as the course is in session.Professor: (motioning everyone to a seat) Well, enough idle pleasantries.

Today's topic is: "War in an information age."Dorcas: There will always be wars. Only the means of waging them changes.Johanna: I disagree. War is an unnatural condition. Human beings are

naturally good and normally peaceful. Now we know the horrors of nuclear and biological warfare, there will never be major wars again.

At this, Mara laughs derisively.Professor: Lady Mara, would you care to give us a thumbnail sketch of warfare

on your home world since the nuclear age.Mara: Are you sure it's all right?Professor: This conversation is fictional, remember. You may speak freely.Mara: Glad to, Professor. In a nutshell, there hasn't been a single year free of

war in the two centuries since. On my planet, the banning of nuclear weapons, chemical and biological warfare, and gunpowder wasn't intended to eliminate war but to ensure that when soldiers fought they would have to do so with what they

318

Page 319: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

could hold in their own hands. Swords, sticks and knives are the weapons of choice. Some like the battle-axe, but I find it cumbersome.

Professor: When was the last time nuclear weapons were used?Mara: At the end of the war with Japan in 1750. There haven't been two

decades without a major conflict, and no year without several minor ones since. Biologicals were used a few times, but no one has fired atomics in that span.

Johanna: (shocked) Your leaders still send people to war?Mara: No, they take them. A noble who declares war on a neighbour must

personally lead the troops into battle. Only the First Lord at Tara is exempt, and that only because he is not allowed to declare war, just to respond to breeches of the peace.

Johanna: (sarcastically) What about the women? Do they stay at home and cook for their husbands?

Nellie: Mara is a high government minister, Johanna, and a major general of the army. Woman on Ortho have equality.

Johanna: (horrified) You don't mean you're a combat officer?Mara: Of course I enter combat. I told you. Leaders go first; they never send.Johanna: You've killed people with that sword?Mara: Certainly. Do you think I use it to shave my legs?Johanna: What if you get wounded or killed?Mara: There are army physicians, of which I am one. But, if the Lord of Heaven

has done with counting out my days, then who am I to object?Ellen: (disbelievingly) How many people have you killed in combat?Nellie: Careful, Ellen. An honourable soldier does not boast, but in Mara's case

I know it's around twenty. She has come close to being killed a couple of times herself.

Johanna: (incredulous) Men would kill a woman in battle?Mara: No one has to take up the sword, but once you do, everyone's equal. In

battle you kill or are killed.Nellie: Isn't that what you and Ellen want, Johanna--equality? Don't you like

the consequences?Ellen: All right, all right. I'll bite. You're from a mythical world where you're a

barbarian queen. How do you reconcile your apparent religion with being a warrior?Mara: I am loyal to the Lord of Heaven, to the throne of Tara, to my family and

sworn friends, and to the liege people sworn to me--in that order. Sometimes those loyalties require me to fight against injustice or despotism, or for the cause of an ally. I do my duty under Heaven.

Ellen: (grunting) Another Christian, but what happened to "love your enemies..."

Mara: "..and do good to those that hate you?" When you have the choice, you take the higher road, of course. In war, your duty is to win--but not at the cost of justice or honour.

Johanna: (stubbornly) There is no such thing as a just war.Mara: You live on the world that spawned Hitler and can say such a thing?

319

Page 320: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Dorcas: There will always be those who believe the strongest must rule, even if they have to kill everybody else to get what they want. It is just to defend society against such.

Ellen: (smiling) There's an inconsistency in your story, Mara, dear. If soldiers on your imaginary world have to kill with their hands, why are you carrying a sling?

Mara: The sling and the throwing knives protect against a coward's attack on a defenceless person, or defend against a banned weapon such as a gun, gas, or bow. One who does or uses such things need not be treated with honour, and can be killed out of hand. A knife through the throat is quite effective. (Glancing around and spotting a wooden bust on a platform by the opposite wall, she turns to the Professor.) Shall I demonstrate?

Professor: Be my guest. That's why I brought it.Nellie stands up, grinning, bows to Mara, strides to the bust and stands

behind.Nellie: Now suppose I were to draw a throwing knife.Reaching over her own shoulder, she produces one. There is a breath of

motion, a blur, and Mara's knife buries itself almost to the hilt in the throat of the wooden bust, rocking its platform slightly.

Johanna: (in a shaky voice) Nellie could have been hurt!Nellie: Oh, nonsense, Johanna. We've practised hundreds of times. Besides,

Mara is a superb surgeon. She'd patch me up in a jiffy.Ellen: (rising, reaching for the knife with both hands and giving it a good pull)

Hey, I can't get this thing out.Nellie yanks it out it with one hand and tosses it to Mara, who catches and re-

holsters it in one motion.Nellie: (grinning) Want another demonstration? Mara and I could go a couple

of rounds with the sword if you like.Ellen: No. I'll buy the proposition that you're somehow and somewhere the

real thing. I just don't see how a society with an advanced enough science to have nuclear weapons could go back to using primitive swords.

Mara: These blades are the best product of the swordsmiths' profession, and scarcely primitive. Besides, it was a deliberate choice to limit weapons as part of the warriors' code. We found killing by proxy offensive. So the change is an advance, not a retreat.

Ellen: But what of those who can't or won't learn the sword? Where does that leave them?

Mara: Wearing a white shirt and the kilt of someone who can and will defend them.

Johanna: But, that is still rule of the strongest over the weakest. It's exploitation.

Nellie: On the contrary, the lord or lady to whom noncombatants owe allegiance has the sworn duty to protect them from exploitation and ensure their rights and freedoms. That's the only reason they carry the sword. It's the reason God ordained government, of whatever form.

Dorcas: Fallen human nature is corrupt. What if a noble fails in that duty and does exploit?

320

Page 321: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Mara: Then the liege covenant is broken, and those freed thereby can replace the base noble. If they are unable to do so, it becomes the responsibility of the rest of the nobility to do it for them.

Nellie: You didn't mention they also have a duty to kill the faithless noble.Mara: I thought it obvious.Ellen: Only the workers are fit to rule. No one's born noble.Mara: Of course nobility isn't by birth. The most fit to inherit family

responsibility takes the name and goes to Tara, whether it be the child of the previous lord, or of the village blacksmith. One is part of the nobility if one can and does fulfill its responsibilities.

Ellen: What about seniority?Nellie: (when Mara looks puzzled) Sorry Ellen, there are no unions on Ortho. If

someone tries to hang on to responsibility too long, one more capable will surely challenge and take it away.

Johanna: Yours is an information-based society?Mara: It has been for over two hundred years.Johanna: I would have thought in such an environment war would only be

fought at a terminal on the network.Mara: That happens, too. Nellie is my consultant in that line of work.Johanna: It couldn't work. A standing army is an intolerable tax burden on

society.Mara: Local lords collect the difference between twenty percent of income and

the up to ten percent that may have been given to the Church. Ten percent of that tax in turn is owed to the central government, but the cost of maintaining the prescribed army units is included, except during an aggressive or rebellious war of local making--then the domains pay troops out of their own pockets.

Dorcas: Is a soldier bound to the same lord for life?Mara: If they swear to be, yes. Many officers prefer to hire out to whomever

they wish.Johanna: They work as mercenaries?Nellie: Nominally all local units are subject to the crown of Ireland at Tara.Ellen: (chuckling) I'll have to tell my aunt about this one. She'd get a kick out

of a world where the Irish are in charge. She's always talking about how the English mistreated them for seven hundred years. (pausing suddenly) Say, how do you treat the English?

Mara: They are partners in the United Kingdom of the Emerald Isles.Johanna: Is it a democratic partnership?Ellen: Some countries elect a parliament to look after local government

matters under the authority of the crown, but England is not among them. Her chief magistrate is Lord Kent.

Professor: Nellie, you act as summarizing prosecutor, and Mara you put on your brehon's chain. Give some examples of how military and criminal discipline is handled.

Nellie: Right. A local ruler stirs up a dispute with another noble and declares war, but stays home from the battle.

Mara: His troops refuse to go. They banish or kill him and install a new lord.

321

Page 322: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Nellie: An officer in the heat of battle kills the non-combatant historian recording the scene for the opposing side.

Mara: The guilty officer's troops suspend battle under a truce, execute the coward, supply a bard to replace the fallen one, recognize a new leader, then decide whether to continue the battle.

Nellie: The General of the Army stages a successful coup against the central government.

Mara: The coup leader is now First Lord, has to give up all his lands, money, and titles, and assume the responsibility of rulership. It's not a job many people want, by the way.

Dorcas: I thought you had a monarchy. You mentioned a throne.Mara: The King was deposed almost sixty years ago and the nobles took over.

Their obligation is to the principles behind the green chair, even though no one can sit in it for over a year yet because it's under an ill-advised ban.

Nellie: Suppose a coup fails, and the instigator escapes. Mara: The Donal sends officers after the loser to kill or capture him.

(hesitates) We had a case like that once where the coup instigator was allowed to escape, changed his name, rejoined the army as a lieutenant and eventually regained his honour. The senior officers know about him but no one ever turned him in to the government and now that the twenty-year ban has passed he could take back his old name if he wanted.

Nellie: A soldier runs away from battle.Mara: Someone runs after him and kills him. That's not an ethical issue, Nellie,

just the practical reality of fighting with swords.Nellie: The House of Lords tries to abolish the army.Mara: The people would rise up in rebellion against the house, kill them all,

and replace them with ones with more sense. The same thing would happen if one of them tried to govern without the people's consent. The government is there to protect the people. They get very nasty when their security is threatened by abrogation of duty.

Dorcas: That's the theory, at least. I doubt if it's always like that in practice.Mara: You're right. There have been despots among domain lords and even at

Tara, but the high nobility is sworn to prevent such, and most take it seriously. Dictators don't live long.

Nellie: An officer challenges an enlisted trooper, or a lord deliberately provokes a fight with someone much less skilled.

Mara: The guilty party is dismissed from all positions of responsibility, dishonoured, and assigned to work as a field hand for one to three years.

Nellie: An officer or noble uses the position for self-enrichment.Mara: The purpose of power is the fulfilment of responsibility. Abuses indicate

high-handed and deliberate dishonour. Three to five years of field work.Professor: Very good. We'll have a formal debate next week on the proposition

"War may be waged justly." Ellen and Johanna have the positive side, Nellie and Dorcas the negative. Mara will be the judge. (noticing Ellen about to protest) Mara must judge fairly. If she didn't she would lose her brehon's chain, and sentenced to field work herself.

322

Page 323: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

He dismisses class, and leaves. Mara turns to Ellen and Johanna.Mara: The gym here's pretty good. How be I take you both on together in a

couple of rounds unarmed? If I break any bones, I've got my medical kit along.

* * * * * *

As observed in Chapter 1, new technologies have historically found many of their applications in he waging war. The modern military, like that in every age, carefully evaluates all techniques and develops some of its own for their potential to kill or to defend. The presence or absence of critical war-making technologies has changed the course of history too many times in the past to suppose that it will not happen again. This is actually the case in every war, for if combatants are technological equals, strategy may win the day, but strategy is a technique in its own right--that is, there is always a most efficient way to wage war in a given situation. In this century superior firepower much more than strategy has been the decisive factor in the major wars. However, in the 1960s, lightly armed and ill-trained young North Vietnamese guerillas took on the heavily armed and mechanized United States army and forced it into a humiliating retreat. Not so in the Gulf war with Iraq, where the United States overwhelmed Iraq with sheer military might.

In the 1970s and 1980s a rough balance of power was perceived to exist between Russia and the United States, and neither side wished to start a war that could not be won, or whose fighting might sterilize the planet, so strategy became paramount again. In the end, the United States essentially bankrupted the Soviet Union by raising the technology stakes to the point where the Soviet economy could not keep up. For a while, pundits hailed this as the end of history--the ultimate triumph of liberal democracy. That this was a foolish hope should have been apparent even then--there are several more countries (and possibly terrorist organizations) that have nuclear capability, and are willing and able to face off against each other or the United States. Thus, one cold war is over; but others have begun between other participants and in different parts of the globe.

9.3.1 Confrontation Outcome Scenarios There are several ways in which a balance of power in a stalemated

confrontation can change as a direct result of new high technologies, or new appreciations of strategic technique. At least three kinds of scenario are possible, though some may be less likely than others.

Escalation--a lose/lose scenario

It is now clear in the aftermath of the cold war between the United States and Russia that two nations cannot escalate military confrontation indefinitely. This is so for both military and economic reasons, for unlimited escalation eventually leads either to war or to the effective bankruptcy of one or both parties.

323

Page 324: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

First, since there is little to be gained militarily by being the responder in a conflict, striking first in such a way as to obliterate the enemy provides the highest probability of survival. The cold war participants realized this, and designed their capability so that they could both survive a first strike and respond with enough force to obliterate the aggressor. This policy of Mutual Assured Destruction (MAD) takes away the strategic advantage of the first strike, but in the nuclear age has the consequence that any conflict has the potential to destroy all life on Earth.

Second, each technical and scientific advance that is applied to the making of war costs more than the last and, like medical costs, military ones have potential to bankrupt all nations that do not limit spending. The demise of the Soviet Union was brought about to a great extent by overspending on the military to the point of bankruptcy. Even though there is now much less chance of nuclear war involving Russia, the economic aftermath still could cause a catastrophe of global proportions--a depression from which it might take decades to recover. Such a result may well have been inevitable if the Soviets and Americans had continued on the course of the 1970s and 1980s; both were spending far beyond their means, and the following years saw many painful readjustments as the United States sought to balance its budget and trade deficits, and Russia struggled to feed its people and bring its economy up to date. None of these goals was achievable without large tax increases and massive reductions in spending--either by a general demilitarization, or by making sharp cuts in social programs.

The former communist nations had to do both, but any Western governing political party that emptied its citizens pockets, whether by taxation or social spending reductions, would quickly lose power to some other party, so it would appear that it is impossible for them to maintain military spending near historical levels for long without at least a major economic upheaval. Moreover, the larger the percentage of Gross National Product once committed to social programs, the smaller the ability for an all-out mobilization to fight a conventional war--though this consideration does not apply so much to a nuclear conflict.

Advantage--A Win/Lose Scenario

The second possibility is that one side achieves a decisive advantage over the other. This result is possible if one side or the other succeeds in developing and deploying a (non-nuclear) technology that breaks down the stalemate dramatically and permanently in its favour. Such an outcome was possible in the Cold War--it would not be the first time a long standoff ended this way. Indeed, it could be argued that computerization was the trump card that made the technical lead of the United states insurmountable.

Possible candidates for future confrontations include the deployment of biochemical agents to render the other side impotent long enough for a conventional military takeover, or the deployment of orbital weapons capable of waging a decisive war and/or preventing any attack from the other side. However, the United States has a vast technological advantage in some areas such as computing systems, biochemical and physical research, and it is doubtful that other nations are currently in a position to employ any of them strategically and

324

Page 325: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

decisively. For their part, biochemical agents, such as new viruses, could not be confined to one territory, but would spread world-wide in a matter of days.

One relatively safe option might would be to deploy the "flying crowbar"--a smart , internally guided, chunk of rock or metal dropped from orbit to a pinpoint landing on missile and other military installations. In theory, such non-explosive devices could be made small enough to avoid detection and yet strike with such force as to destroy buried missile silos, such accuracy as to take out mobile ones, and in such numbers as to prevent retaliation. Indeed, the flying crowbar was probably a component of the proposed U.S. Strategic Defense Initiative. However, the ability of even the United States to utilize space in a cost-effective manner is in some doubt, so an effective space-based weapon or deterrent may be a long way off.

Neither can the expenditure of resources needed to gain decisive technological advantages be kept entirely hidden from the other side. For instance, the aggressor in a biological attack would have to inoculate its entire population with an anti-agent prior to launching the agent against the other side. Such an action could not be kept secret in the information age, and this fact alone seems to make this win-lose scenario unlikely--though not impossible.

Another win/lose scenario has one nation gradually gaining the upper hand in space, to the point where it could dictate terms to the Earth-bound losers. This strategy has its own risks, for here the aggressor would have to agree to short-term military spending cuts to free up money for space hardware, accepting temporary losses in ground level power in exchange for long-term total superiority. The nation that did this could be hailed as a peacemaker by the third world, while simultaneously pursuing a strategy that would eventually result in total domination. What makes an apparently passive strategy likely to succeed where an active one would not, is the tendency of people to overlook the obvious, and the desire, often shown in the Western democracies, to grasp peace at any price, or to pretend that an aggressor state is really a benevolent friend. In this version of the win/lose scenario, no war will be fought, but tyranny might triumph anyway--at least until its inherent instability eventually caused it to collapse.

It should also be noted that it is too early in the life of post-communist Eastern Europe to tell whether the cold war is actually over, or just in interregnum. It is still necessary to deal with the threat of nuclear action from any of the former Soviet states now in control of part of the arsenal, and from any one of several other nuclear club members and organizations in other parts of the world. Perhaps the same kind of high technology "Star Wars" threat that proved too much for the Soviet Union can be effective against other nations as well--if it could be deployed.

Profile on . . . Losing a War

It's not over until...

The greatest drawback of any win/lose scenario is the frequent inability of the loser to accept defeat and live with it.

325

Page 326: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Seven centuries of oppressive British rule in Ireland could not shake that people's determination to avenge the loss of their sovereignty, and the Irish eventually won their freedom.

o Germanys chafed under sanctions and reparations imposed after their loss of the First World War to the point where this issue alone probably made the second inevitable.

o The Serbs, Croats, and Muslims have never done better than live in a state of uneasy stalemate.

o Rwanda Tutsi and Hutu have an even worse relationship, and the situation is similar in other African countries.

o Neither India nor Pakistan is happy with the borders between the two countries, and neither is likely to accept the outcome of any new war as final.

o China makes territorial claims that are unacceptable to Taiwan, Tibet, and India.

o There are numerous unresolved border disputes in South America.o Iraq seems destined to fight more wars with the West, and she and her

neighbours with Israel.

Likewise, one has to wonder whether the people of the former Soviet Union will be able to live with the loss of prestige that came from the end of the cold war and the disintegration of much of their empire. It is still possible that a revived Russian nationalism will renew this conflict, with disastrous consequences.

Genuine Peace Strategies--Win/Win Scenarios

The discussion (and supporting events) thus far lead some to the historically improbable and highly idealistic conclusion that high technology may have made war obsolete, at least war of the global variety. "We are at the end of history," say some--meaning that civilization has reached a new and permanently peaceful state. If so, it is communications technology that is the main cause, on the one hand by making it difficult for one side to gain a technological advantage, and on the other by reducing suspicions and promoting global cooperation. Indeed, if it could be assumed that all military knowledge were equally available to both sides, then no global war would be winnable. If the leaders on both sides of a nuclear confrontation were rational enough to believe that those on the other side would never strike first, they would do so themselves. If they were sufficiently rational to understand that even a first strike that destroyed 90 percent of the potential counter strike would still result in their country's own annihilation, then neither side would strike first, nor even at all. Realizing this and acting upon it logically--that is by an eventual total world nuclear disarmament--are not the same thing, however. If a perfect defensive system could be devised, and any hostile ICBM destroyed at or shortly after launch, then the best insurance for peace would be to share this technology publicly and

326

Page 327: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

with all nations. Since it is the presumption of the information age that this knowledge, like any other, could not be kept secret for long in any case, there would be important real advantages for peace in sharing it from the outset.

The first obstacle to such a result would be the development of provably reliable defense hardware and software--a goal often striven toward, but so far elusive. The second obstacle to the peace scenario is that a considerable portion of the world economy is dependent on the war industry, and any cutbacks in the level of spending on arms would create severe economic dislocations. It must however be judged on measurement of the ethical considerations, whether absolute or utilitarian, that the payment of even a very large economic cost to secure the number of human lives at risk is beneficial, and ought to be undertaken. In a nuclear age, the alternative to peace is no longer war, but the destruction of the whole human race--something that cannot be entertained, and that must be avoided if there is to be a next civilization. It is worth remarking that the transitional period of the early years will be the most difficult, for nationalism is an opponent of both the spread of technology and of peace, and so are many traditional institutions. However, if the twin trends of globalization and localization rob national governments of power, and the universal availability of information takes away their ability to keep secrets, both the motivation for waging war and some of the means will be seriously impaired.

That does not mean war will not happen anyway. For political or religious reasons, some countries are still relatively closed, and information about them is still difficult to obtain and unreliable. If the Russians have not in fact given up their desire to rule the entire world, their best course of action would be to pose as peacemakers and lull the West into a false sense of security; pretend to disarm while actually re-arming; and hope to strike at a weak moment. That such an approach may seem improbable in the West might not deter them; war has often seemed unlikely until it has actually started. Neither are the new democracies in Eastern Europe very secure; one or more of them could easily return to the old ways in an effort to stave off economic collapse. In addition, China has yet to emerge entirely from under the yoke of tyranny, and it is much too soon to speculate on what will happen to her when she does. Add to these the perennial powder keg that is the Middle East, tensions between some South American countries, the poisonous relations between India and Pakistan, and the vested interests of the arms industry, and there remain all the ingredients for many minor and major wars for decades to come.

9.3.2 Other Kinds of War Military wars are not the only kind, moreover. There are a variety of

substitutes for gaining or expressing dominion over others. One outlet is sports, which in some countries takes on warlike dimensions, both on the field and off. Thus the Olympics became the focus of great endeavours not only for the athletes, but also for the national governments who funded their training. Success on the field, slopes, or ice was often seen as a proof of national superiority, and such proofs are easier to buy than those obtained from winning a military victory. Revenge for an old invasion of one's territory may be impossible to achieve on the battlefield, but

327

Page 328: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

very sweet at the hockey arena or soccer stadium in front of thousands of screaming spectators and the hungry eye of the television cameras. Moreover, as in conventional warfare, some may decide that winning at sports is everything--and such an attitude has both ethical and medical consequences, as performance-enhancing drugs come to be seen as essential for such high-level competition.

A more important form is economic war. For the sake of promoting employment at home, governments often adopt strategies to ensure the establishment and prosperity of industries under their jurisdiction. These may include tax breaks, low-cost land or loans, production or wage subsidies, high tariff or other import barriers, or combinations of these.

These activities take place at all levels of technological development and in all industries, and the results are much the same in each case. For example, the United States engaged in an agricultural products subsidy war with the Europeans and Japanese through the 1980s. Farmers enjoyed government sponsored prices and protection from competition, but overproduced and caused enormous surpluses, which had to be stockpiled at even greater cost, or risk a price collapse. No more people are fed by such policies, and the natural market becomes so distorted that a substantial portion of government resources comes to be devoted to the subsidies. The cost easily escalates to the point where they destabilize the economies of the countries using them as much as they do their ostensible targets in other nations. For instance, by 1988, the elaborate subsidies and protections built into the Japanese system had become among the most costly in the world, and some cracks had already begun to appear. These became more serious in the 1990s, and it remains to be seen whether Japan can recover. Subsidies, like all forms of protectionism, have the potential to cause either wars or economic collapse.

Other examples can be taken from high technology trade. When American manufacturers of memory chips (DRAMs) found they could not compete with the low wages and subsidies of the foreign manufacturers, they asked for government protection in the form of import quotas. This reduced the supply of the chips and drove prices up. Since the American manufacturers could not respond immediately to fill the demand, prices continued to increase, and offshore manufacturers got most of the profit from the windfall. By mid-1988, the prices for such devices had reached their highest level in years, due to the distortion of the market caused by political actions. That is, the result was not an immediate increase in domestic jobs, but shortages, higher prices, and a transfer of wealth to other countries. Subsequently, of course, supply and demand took over as the information that there were profits to be made disseminated; supply was ramped up; and prices came down sharply.

Airplanes are also an important commodity, both for the sake of jobs, and for national pride. Aerospace contracts are lured to the soil of a particular nation by governments that subsidize manufacturers to offer their goods at a loss in order to get the business. In such an atmosphere efficient companies are penalized, and the inefficient are encouraged to become more so. Fewer planes are actually made, because inefficiencies drive the price up in spite of state largesse, and consumers pay the higher cost for the waste. The space industry is also often cited as an example of state subsidies creating artificial barriers to the kind of free trade that

328

Page 329: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

could result in much greater efficiency and lower cost. Manufacturers whose only customer is the government, and who work on cost-plus contracts, have no incentive to reduce costs and are discouraged from or even forbidden to export.

Sometimes, the market is interfered with by the establishment of cartels at the state level--again for the purpose of ensuring the highest possible price for the goods of the nations involved. The Organization of Petroleum Exporting Countries (OPEC) is an excellent example of this kind of activity. By combining the major oil producers into a single price-fixing group, it was able to engineer enormous price increases in the 1970s, and an equally large transfer of wealth to its members.

All trade wars must come to an end eventually, however, because they are by very nature self-destructive. No nation can afford to increase subsidies or trade barriers indefinitely, and every cartel eventually causes other sources of supply to be developed in response to the high prices. In their collapse, trade wars can do even more harm than while they are in progress, for if they do not end in a negotiated peace, they may end in a shooting war, thus they may constitute one of the greatest risks to world peace. A premise of the information age is that national leaders will realize that greater long term prosperity is available for everyone if trade and other tensions can be eliminated and the prospect of new wars reduced. However, enablement does not mean implementation. The ability to eliminate trade wars will not necessarily lead to their demise; in some places and for some industries they may become worse.

9.3.3 Policing a Peace All these calculations and arguments may easily be upset, for the history of

this century in particular is replete with the ascension to power of fanatics who were prepared to see their own nations crippled militarily and economically, and die themselves in their efforts trying to dominate or destroy either their neighbours or some hated ethnic or religious minority. Even if the superpower governments have now become super-rational and do succeed in disarming because they realize that a policy of mutual assured destruction is neither moral nor sane, there is no guarantee that those who follow them in power will even be rational, much less super-rational. Unless all the world's citizens are not only fully informed but also free to determine their governments, there is little likelihood that disarmament would be permanent; and there is a small possibility that it will not be even then.

What is more, there are dozens of small states that spend even larger percentages than did the cold war superpowers of their much more meagre budgets on arms. In some of these, the military has not just a vested interest in the status quo, but directly operates the state for its own benefit. Such regimes, like all such tyrannies before them, are stable in the short term only if they can persuade their citizens that there are real threats to meet, or good reasons to become an aggressor. So long as there are nations, there will probably also be wars. Even if the combatants gradually kill off each other's populations, and wear out their economies, there will be larger powers prepared to use such local conflicts both for economic gain and as testing grounds for their own weapons--so the world is still threatened. At some point, many more of the smaller countries will achieve nuclear

329

Page 330: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

capability, raising the probability that one of them will use it in an effort to decisively settle things with their enemies.

Other nations will clamour to have nuclear capability too, and the temptation to sell this technology for the very high prices being offered will be too great for the world's arms merchants to resist, so nuclear weaponry may well spread world wide. After all, there are already many countries that see the sale of conventional weapons solely as a way of obtaining cash, not as a moral issue. Once such technology did spread, it will be impossible to stop its use unless war itself could be prevented. This too is possible, but can only take place with the cooperation of all the large powers, for every nation with weapons capability would have to be persuaded to stop their manufacture and sale. Such an enterprise would involve a surrender of sovereignty on a scale never before seen, and a placing of trust in an international body to a degree not yet imagined. Such action will be hard for all the world's nations, regardless of their size, but the alternative--gradually escalating nuclear arsenals until one is used--is not an option for human survival, and cannot be followed much longer.

A new threat, and perhaps one more difficult to police, comes from the many nuclear technicians and scientists of the former Soviet Union who are now looking for a place to use their skills and knowledge. If only a few of these were to sell their expertise to some of the more warlike of the third world nations, there could arise several new nuclear dangers to world peace. It seems unlikely that all these people can be gainfully employed by non-belligerent nations for peaceful purposes, and those affected are hardly likely to enjoy unemployment after their many years as part of an elite establishment.

As the revival of Naziism illustrates--even if in small numbers of adherents--no nation is safe from demagoguery. It is always possible for a small number of the disaffected to raise the spectre of real or imagined ills, blame them on a domestic or foreign scapegoat, and persuade the majority to initiate genocide or war. No minority can be assumed to be free from the fear of such activities--whether Jews, Christians, or some relocated ethnic group. Neither is any country immune from such activities--whether in North America, Europe, Asia, South America, or Africa.

9.3.4 Summary The discussion in this section raises further questions about the viability of

nationalism, totalitarian forms of government in general, and the morality and sanity of any policy that emphasizes the ability to wage war as a high national priority. It is assumed here that there cannot again be such a thing as a just or moral nuclear conflict; no imaginable goal of public policy or national interest can justify the annihilation of most or all of the human race. The question is no longer whether the world ought to disarm and to effectively police a general peace, even at the cost of some national interest; it is rather a question of how to go about it. For it is no longer national interests, but human survival that is at issue, and that is surely a high priority in any ethical system. In the long run, an information economy is a global phenomenon, and nationalism may decline. If it does so gracefully, peace is possible. If its death paroxysms are sufficiently violent, any other outcome becomes possible.

330

Page 331: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

9.4 Some Legal Problems for the Next Age It is time now to turn from matters of high state and international

relationships to consider the interaction of the law and technology in more practical and mundane matters. One area of law that is of specific concern to the development of high technology is that of property rights, for the recent direction of change here may indicate some potentially serious obstacles to the widespread creation of new intellectual properties that would otherwise be a hallmark of the fourth civilization.

Specifically, when a work exists only in electronic form, what rights of ownership are there? More generally, who owns the information that is the basis for the new society, and who owns or may regulate the right of access to it? The same question could be asked of the programs that organize that data and even of the machines on which they run. What will be the status of the books, articles, poetry, and plays that are produced on a word processor and whose originals are stored in non-paper form? Can anyone own the way a class of software looks and feels to the user? Before attempting to answer these questions, it is worth pointing out that these issues have been singled out for detailed examination because they are representative of the manner in which developing technology forces changes to the legal assumptions and institutions of a previous age. It is not intended to suggest that these are the most important legal difficulties, only that they are good illustrations.

9.4.1 An Overview of Current Problems As the larger manufacturers of equipment have found to their dismay, the

more successful their products are, the more likely it will be that someone else will have an identical or "cloned" version on the market in a matter of months. The first company does the expensive research and development, and a host of imitators with little developmental overhead reap the benefits. The authors of best selling programs have also discovered that for every legitimate copy their publishers sell, many pirated ones are distributed. Some pirates have even sold copies of well-known programs under a different name, or have counterfeited the original label.

It is not that the mousetrap designers of older technologies did not face the same problem; after all, there are only so many ways to make wax paper, photocopying machines, or flashlight batteries, for instance. However, it used to take much more time to copy new inventions. The protection of the law was clearer and easier to obtain, and the concept of private property was thought to be a touchstone of Western society, with the law being applied vigorously for its protection.

By contrast, in the early stages of computer development, lawyers sometimes admitted in court that their clients had copied thousands of bytes of computer code for their own version of some machine, but claimed that the original owner had no right to the creation because, as machine readable code, it was not really property. The argument was that once a legitimate creative expression had been reduced to electronic form, ownership was lost, because no one could "own" electrical impulses or codes that can be read only by a machine. Alternately, they claimed that the

331

Page 332: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

software expressed a formula in essentially the only possible way, and therefore was not protectable. Adding to the legal difficulties was the fact that there was very little lead time for the copying of either hardware or software. In the former case, it takes but a few months. In the latter, the feat could often be accomplished in a matter of seconds. For heavily copy-protected programs, an expert may have needed hours or days, but all such locking schemes could be broken in a far shorter time than it took to create them. A vigorous race between protectors and pirates developed, and there was often more effort going into this sort of activity than into the production of original programs.

The educational marketplace, where copying was epidemic, suffered the most. Few publishers would enter it, for they knew there was no money to be made when they could sell only one copy of a program to a School District employing a thousand or more teachers. In a celebrated hardware case, judgment was rendered for Apple Computer against the leading domestic maker of imitation Apple ][ computers, and after 1984 such clones were no longer legal in the United States. However, this case was based on the contents of the ROM programs built in to the computer, which had been simply copied by the clone makers. Later, when similar companies copied the IBM microcomputer, they were careful to make new built-in code with the same functionality, but different instructions. By doing so, they were able to get around the earlier judgment, so that current litigation is focused more on software than on hardware. In a later suit over the look and feel of the operating system, Apple claimed that Microsoft had illegally copied the essential substance of its intellectual property by imitating its functionality in the various versions of Windows. Although lower courts ruled that there was no infraction, the suit was resolved only when Microsoft settled out of court in 1997, buying shares in Apple in the process.

Despite the fact that courts in several countries have now also ruled that the creators of computer software can copyright their programs, and despite the subsequent dropping of software protection schemes by most major manufacturers, these problems still exist, and the production of genuinely new forms of software and hardware has suffered. Neither are these difficulties confined to the computing industry, for a similar situation is faced by the manufacturers of pharmaceuticals, who see their expectation of some profit from research and development taken away by inexpensive generic copies of their original drug formulas, and in the face of this, decline to do such work within the boundaries of countries that allow the practices. Canada has recently passed new legislation restoring protection to patent medicines; it remains to be seen whether this deliberate restriction of technology transfer will be more productive and beneficial, or whether it will result in higher costs and profits with little or no public benefit.

A third area, besides patent and copyright, in which property rights have been endangered is that of access to stored information. Many computers that served as information repositories, including those of governments, corporations, and banks, were not at first nearly as well-protected against the casual intruder as they should have been. Consequently, there came to be people who specialized in breaking into computer systems to examine or change the data they found. While there were only a few cases of this sort that gained great public notoriety, there was for a time a

332

Page 333: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

widespread underground trade in access numbers and passwords for a variety of installations, and it is still not known to what extent the security of important systems was or is being compromised. This is probably not as much of a problem at the present time, as these few incidents have resulted in much more effective security measures being taken. However, it is not clear what is the extent of liability when a system is broken into and data stolen or vandalized. Is it the fault of the operating system vendor for allowing security holes, the software manufacturer for not plugging these, the owner of the computer for not working around them, or the owner of the data for irresponsibly trusting any of the above?

Another form of vandalism that has become a major problem is the spread of "computer viruses". These are small programs that attach themselves to applications when they are run, and whose instructions cause them to attach themselves to all other programs in the system. At some point, they begin to destroy the hapless owners' data and program files or cause random interruptions during computing tasks. Even in the cases where they merely print messages on the users' screens, they constitute an invasion of property and privacy, and reflect a side of the information age that claims there ought not to be any rules. The computing community has been quick to respond to this threat, and there are a number of "vaccine" programs available to protect systems against such infections or remove them afterwards. Sometimes the virus, or some other destructive behaviour, comes coded inside some otherwise useful program that a person installs and uses. Such a program is termed a "Trojan horse," and while relatively rarer, these can cause as much serious data loss as viruses. Files created under Microsoft's Word and Excel can contain a macro that runs whenever the file is opened. This capability has also been exploited to vandalize other systems.

There is still a feeling both among those who copy designs and programs and among those who "hack" into others' systems that there is no such thing as private property, or ought not to be. "Ideas are the property of the masses" and "information is for the people" are the kind of slogans that they have adopted. Will this attitude ultimately characterize the next age? Will there be no rights of ownership to electronic property in the future? Or, is private property a leftover from the old industrial age, and destined for the same oblivion? On the other hand, if the right to private property ought to be a characteristic of the Information Age, what steps can be taken to ensure that the creators or intellectuals have their interests protected? There is a fundamental conflict here between the need to widely disseminate information and the need to reward its creators in order to allow them a living sufficient to continue their creative activity.

9.4.2 The Present Law There are already certain rights vested under present law for the protection of

intellectual property rights. Usually, these are based on international treaties and conventions. Not all nations sign each treaty, and even for those that do the details vary somewhat from one country to another. In the United States, there are often state laws or court decisions enhancing or limiting such protections further. Thus, the discussion in this section is limited to the principles on which such protections

333

Page 334: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

are based. Briefly, there are four general classes of protection, each with certain advantages, and each with drawbacks.

Trade Secrets

If a manufacturer sells a product that is produced by some process or recipe and that technique has been carefully kept a secret, not being published or registered in any way, the secret offers a measure of legally recognized protection against imitators. Even should a disgruntled employee leave and "spill the beans" to a competitor, the law still protects the original owner of the secret. However, if the secret is made public inadvertently, through the owner's failure to protect it carefully, or if it is independently discovered by someone else, all protection is gone. What was secret then becomes part of the public domain, available to everyone. It may in some cases even become patentable by a competitor, and thus lost altogether to the originator.

The advantage is total protection while the secret is kept. The disadvantage is total loss if someone else can discover or legally obtain the secret for themselves. This method is essentially worthless for protecting either computer hardware and software or pharmaceuticals, as the secrets of these quickly become open to an intelligent prober and, as a result this type of protection holds little promise for much of high-tech industry.

Patent

Patents are intended to protect devices or artifacts. Typically, they are applied to machinery and equipment, including both consumer items and devices used in the manufacture of other goods. They provide an exclusive right to make the patented artifact for a fixed number of years and are effective in preventing the distribution of identical imitations.

A specific computer may be patentable, for example, as may many of its components. However, mathematical algorithms cannot have this protection, nor can any other intellectual expression that is not a physical device. In a move that has generated considerable controversy, the U.S. Patent office has begun to grant protection to certain processes that are part of various software packages, however. On the other hand, there is no computer (and few circuits) sufficiently unique in an electronic sense that the same end result cannot be achieved in some other way. In practice, there is therefore little in patent protection to prevent another company from building a virtual copy of a computer or other machine, and nothing to prevent others from manufacturing an "improved version". Cheap foreign counterfeits or exact clones can now be kept out of the United States, but many countries have thus far not even taken that step, so that a computer patent in such places is essentially worthless. Moreover, workalike machines are usually so easy to make

334

Page 335: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

(and these are often called clones as well) that there is little that can be done to stop very close imitation of computers.

Following the older practice of patenting medicines, and medical machinery, patents have also been sought and granted on genetically engineered life forms--a practice that is sure to create considerable controversy as this field expands. As remarked in Chapter 7, this is likely to worsen if animal life is worked on, the more so for human genetic modifications.

A patent does have the advantage of blanket protection while it lasts, and where it is enforced. It has the disadvantage of being relatively difficult to obtain and often impractical to enforce, particularly in the case of electronic equipment. It may also artificially inflate prices and deprive the general population of the benefits of the discovery by creating a monopoly for an unscrupulous manufacturer determined to exploit the meeting of needs for all the available cash. In the case of patents on key aspects of software, it may prevent manufacturers of even non-competing software from using some ideas or code in their products. For such reasons, most countries are now limiting drug patents to a smaller number of years, and may do the same in other strategic industries, such as computing. Patent is also an artifact-oriented protection; it is more applicable to industrial age devices than it is to the stock-in-trade of an information driven economy.

Copyright

This third type of protection has traditionally been applied to printed material, such as is found in books and periodicals. It is supposed to confer on its owner the sole right to make copies of a work, with limited exceptions, such as allowing one copy for study or archival purposes. For instance, it is illegal to make and sell copies of a novel, textbook, or scholarly paper without the consent of the copyright holder, except that copies of insubstantial portions can be made for research purposes.

It is also illegal to copy cassette tapes or record albums, video tapes, sheet music or song lyrics, to make classroom sets of magazine articles, or to distribute to students copies of chapters in supplementary textbooks. Yet, all of these things are done daily in many homes and offices and in virtually every school in North America. This will become even more common as personal copiers become as common as personal tape recorders. The ease of accomplishing the deed have led to an even more widespread ignoring of copyright in the case of computer software.

What taping has done to the record and video industry and the dry copier has done to the music industry is nothing compared to the effect of disk and file duplication on the software industry. The deed can be done in a matter of seconds and in complete privacy. It is nearly impossible to discover afterward unless a "friend" turns the perpetrator in to the offended company. This situation is complicated by the fact that the courts in many countries (including the United States and Canada) took several years to decide that computer software was indeed protected by copyright laws. Yet, despite all these problems, the affected industries do thrive, even if some portions do not grow as expected. The companies that do well achieve success by offering to their legitimate buyers a variety of personal services such as toll free help, continuous updates, and comprehensive manuals

335

Page 336: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

that the owners of illegal copies do not have. These successes illustrate that a reliance on the legal protection of copyright may not be necessary; it is apparently possible to grow and thrive even when it is being widely ignored. In recognition of this, most commercial software manufacturers had dropped copy protection schemes from their products by the early 1990s.

Unfortunately for record companies and booksellers, the advent of electronic book and digital music storage has meant the same considerations now apply to their copyrighted materials as well. It is too soon to say what kind of answer can be devised to protect the livelihood of writers and artists.

Copyright has the advantage of being easy to obtain. One does not even have to register the work to get protection, just to ensure that every copy that is distributed carries the standard notice. In the case of small printed materials, tapes, and computer diskettes, however, copyright has the disadvantage of being practically impossible to enforce.

Software License

Some software vendors require their customers to sign an agreement that they will make only personal back-up copies of the software, not give it to another person, use it only as directed, and so on. These documents will often disclaim all warranties or guarantees on the part of the vendor, declare that the purchaser takes all the risks, and state that the customer has only a license to use the software, but does not own it. Such contracts are holdovers from the days when software was designed for and sold to only a handful of customers, or only to a single one. Today, notices like these may even appear inside the front cover of the documentation and state that they took effect when the package was opened.

This form of protection has the advantage, in the case of an actual signed agreement, that the vendor can point to a piece of paper and say, "You agreed!". They are also good for the lawyers who make handsome fees by designing them. However, "contracts" that are discovered only after opening a package are worthless, as are any agreements obtained by duress, false pretences, or accompanied by a failure to disclose material facts. They are also void if their primary purpose is actually to disclaim all responsibility on the part of a vendor. The few such documents that may be legally enforceable from a technical point of view, and provided that they are actually signed by the customer, are of little more value in practise than is the copyright notice. People have been ignoring them, and making copies anyway, and will probably continue to do so. Moreover, in many places laws have now been proposed or passed that limit the validity of these "shrink wrap" licenses. On the other hand, there are initiatives to enshrine them in law.

Monopoly

Sometimes, the hold of a particular manufacturer over a market segment or technology becomes excessive, and the company acts to take unduly large profits, restrain the trade of competitors, and prevent customers from using rival products.

336

Page 337: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

In the communications and information storage and retrieval industries, there is a natural tendency toward such market concentrating activities because of the need for standards to make the technology work at all. Many countries have laws against monopolistic business practices. For instance, the United States government forced Standard Oil and Bell Telephone to be broken into smaller entities, and in the late 1990s took on Microsoft over what were alleged to be predatory practices.

However, seeing an actual case through the courts may take many years, and some, at least, of the issues may be moot by the time it is settled. This is particularly so in the computing industry, where product lifetimes are measured in months, and legal times perhaps in decades. Given this time frame, and the sufficient application of money and influence, a company found guilty of illegal practices can probably influence the political process sufficiently to escape penalties and continue the same practices in slightly different ways.

The real harm done by a monopoly is not so much in price gouging and the reduction of choice, but in the stifling or destruction of competition, and therefore of innovation. One could argue that the lack of monopolies in the early days of the small computing industry was precisely the reason for its rapid pace of technological change and innovation. If all common applications were rolled into the operating system, and this became standardized on everyone's desktop, the incentive to compete from outside the monopoly or to innovate from within it would vanish, and the industry could simply stagnate.

What are the courts doing?

After some initial waffling over whether a computer program was indeed copyrightable in its electronic expression, the courts in a number of countries have now given several clear indications that copyright can be applied both to external storage media (diskettes, CDs, DVDs) and to Read Only Memory (ROM) chips that contain programs. Such rulings have slowed down the activities of those who "clone" computers, because an essential part of such a device is usually a large amount of built-in ROM programming. For their part, manufacturers initially responded to the challenge by greatly increasing the amount of code built into ROM so as to make it more difficult for other programmers to build a functional copy or create work-alike code. However, except in flagrant commercial cases, there have been few attempts to bring even large-scale violators to justice. The courts in many countries have yet to follow their U.S. counterparts even as far as the latter have gone, so there is in effect no protection as yet for hardware manufacturers or software authors in such places.

Meanwhile, patents granted on genetic modifications are sure to be challenged, and seem unlikely to be maintained over the long run. The clear direction of change is away from information restriction and secrets; the courts are not unaware of this fact, and are beginning to reinterpret the law in the spirit of the age in which it is applied, rather than in that of which it was written--a trend that can either be welcomed or feared, depending on one's point of view.

The fundamental problem with treating intellectual creations as general information, rather than as property, is the great disincentive this provides to the

337

Page 338: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

creators. If they cannot make a living by their creation, and few software authors, book authors, or musicians can, they become less inclined to create again. They devote their time to enterprises that can provide an income, and their creative endeavour is stifled, impoverishing everyone. It is this fact that leads us to search further for some way of achieving the contradictory goals of protection and dissemination.

9.4.3 The Insufficiency of Law Alone Even if there is a change of attitude on the part of lawmakers to provide

clearer protections, there still remain great obstacles in the way of solving the basic problem. Software piracy is encouraged by the very high prices that foster the attitude: "They're trying to rip me off, so it's okay if I do it to them." The ranks of the copiers are swelled even more by the fact that it is easily, quickly, and privately accomplished--generally by amateurs, and that few of these could ever be apprehended even if enforcement officers were to try.

All of this leads some to ask whether unenforceable laws should remain on the books. There can be little doubt that if this trend becomes one of the hallmarks of the new age, electronically expressed "private property" would cease to exist as it is now known and this will sharply reduce the incentive to create such materials. Since it is unlikely that the new society could live with the broad implications of such a change, new approaches will have to be attempted.

9.4.4 Proposed Remedies Several means have been proposed to improve ownership rights for

electronically expressed intellectual work. What follows is a brief exposition of a few of these, with the attendant advantages and disadvantages.

1. Improve Legal Protection

This remedy would be welcomed by lawyers, software authors and publishers, since the present laws could certainly use some clarification. However, the enforcement problem would still remain, and it is unlikely that this approach alone would suffice.

2. Improve Copy Protection

A number of promising new methods have become available to make diskette duplication more difficult. If a foolproof copy protection could be devised, it could solve much of the problem. However, this avenue has looked promising before, but has yielded few results. A combination of built-in serial numbers and machine customized software does hold some promise, and this might be pursued, but the larger software houses have now all bowed to criticisms of inconvenience from their major customers and dropped copy protection altogether. A few have employed a hardware key or "dongle" that attaches to the parallel or serial port of a computer and that is checked for by the software. This has the advantage that the software can be moved from machine to machine, but the disadvantage of inconvenience,

338

Page 339: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

especially if the dongle is lost. All things considered, most observers feel that barring a dramatic new discovery, this approach probably has little future.

To a limited extent, the same comments have applied to the security of systems and their data--doors capable of being bolted could also have their security bypassed by a sufficiently clever and patient thief. However, large systems are gradually becoming more secure, and those thieves usually need to obtain passwords from the legitimate users--if they do, it is carelessness that has defeated the security, not superior technique.

3. Software Transmission

Potential users of a work could be required to sign on to a host computer (software server) by telephone and pay a fee for each use. This solution reduces the power of the user's computer somewhat, but does ensure that the program itself is never copied, for it runs only on or by being loaded from the larger remote computer. The local device (a network computer) ends up with comparatively little or no storage for programs, for each use is rented.

This approach would solve the copying problem, but would have the disadvantage of being expensive to implement. It would also remove some computing power from the hands of individuals, but in the long run, it has something to be said for it. The Metalibrary, if ever fully implemented, would provide a fast and operationally inexpensive method of recording all accesses to original ideas or programs and of crediting the author with the fee charged, with a percentage retained by the utility to finance its own activities. Like the earlier suggestion that art could be rented from the owning museums for a fee paid as long as it was displayed, this too could be implemented on a time-related rental basis.

Alternately, if billing information were present in the software itself and were updated at each use in a special non-user accessible section of the individual's Metalibrary terminal, the software could be retained and stored locally by its user and the information on fees charged transferred to the central computer on the next access to it. Indeed, the software could even refuse to run without making such a contact. Of course, there might be people who would try to change the billing information, but if there were only one thing to protect, security could be more sophisticated.

If either style of software rental were adopted, there would also be many who would bemoan the end of the chaotic, free-and-easy era of computing where the power was on individuals' desktops. However, a central system may be the only way to maintain the integrity of either the software or the accounting to pay for it. On the other hand, if a single company controlled this security system and could tax all access, it would rapidly assume power comparable to (or greater than) government.

It seems likely that processes and formulas could be licensed in much the same manner. Such information is not now too difficult to get, but if an automatic method to credit the discoverer existed, it might be feasible to do away with monopolies on its use. The most efficient manufacturer would only sometimes be the originator, but the research and development would not simply be lost to the originator; it would just be reimbursed through royalties instead of profits. This is a

339

Page 340: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

technological solution to a technological problem; presumably it will create new problems for later solution, but may have some potential. It is worth remarking that profits are easier to make, and protection less important, when the software is in a constant state of rapid and substantial change. The real crunch comes for the vendors of stable products over the long term; on these the original market can almost always be ultimately swamped by cheap duplicates. This fact forces an eventual resolution to these problems, though it does not suggest what it can be.

A related difficulty arises from the fact that there are often many ways to duplicate the result of a technique without duplicating the technique itself. Should the result be protectable, even though the process is not, or has been avoided? This is the very issue behind several "look and feel" suits launched in the late 1980s by original software vendors against competitors who had created functional work and look-alikes to their programs without copying the actual code. Some courts initially ruled that the "look and feel" is protectable, others the contrary; the latter view seems to have prevailed even though the Apple-Microsoft case was never heard at the highest levels.

4. Lower Prices

The high prices charged for much of the microcomputer software now being sold are also a holdover from the days of low volume production runs for very expensive machines. With some brands already having hundreds of millions of computers installed, a mass market potential exists for well-designed software. Once word processors and computing languages sell for the price of a textbook--say, under $50--much of the incentive for copying will vanish. Of course, many retailers, particularly computer dealers, will resist this trend because of the lower dollar margin involved. Under such circumstances, they would not remain on the scene, because computers would become consumer products and be sold in department stores, and by other general merchants. Bookstore chains would handle software, and sell it as they would their other products.

No set of solutions that fails to address the pricing problem has much chance of success, for the motivation to pirate software is strongly influenced by the economic barriers to owning it. Low prices and no copy protection at all is a better solution than high prices with protection, and some vendors have already discovered this fact. This policy would certainly result in a better utilization of creative energies in the writing of programs, contrasting sharply with the waste inherent in the protect/deprotect cycle.

At the same time, the licensing of drug manufacturing rights, among others, would also help to drive down a range of consumer prices, because this too would promote volume without reducing the long-term return on investment. As this discussion indicates, it may be the case that marketing solutions can sometimes be found for ethical problems.

On the other hand, a near monopoly by a single company of much of an industry probably indicates that no lower-price solution is achievable in that industry without government intervention.

340

Page 341: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

5. Royalties

One answer to the cassette/record industry copying problem has been to impose a surcharge on all blank cassette sales. This is then distributed as a royalty to all performing artists affected, in proportion to their actual sales. The same approach could be taken with blank CDs and DVDs and the accumulated royalties distributed among software artists.

This would have the advantage of redressing the economic injury to the creators of the software, and that is probably the main concern of the industry. On the other hand this approach has the drawback that it deliberately chooses to accommodate to the underlying problem, and appeasement is a policy that can come back to haunt; sooner or later reality must be faced and action taken that leads to a definite solution. Moreover, such a solution is temporary. A given medium is unlikely to remain the primary method of software distribution for long. As indicated above, a royalty on the use of ideas is a better policy, but it can only be enforced by the use of a very large scale and heavily used computing facility such as the Metalibrary.

9.4.5 Summary The information paradigm itself causes new legal questions to arise, as well as

new versions of old ones. If the creators of new ideas are to be encouraged to make a living at such activity, some new form of protection and reimbursement needs to be tailored to the information age. It will likely be a highly technological solution requiring great cooperation and widespread support, but such a solution will help to guarantee that the flow of ideas continues. Full implementation of the Metalibrary is one solution that would encourage continued creation and publication, and provide protection and revenues to the creator, but at low cost for distribution. The drawback of this solution is the potential for control or abuse by a small number of individuals or companies that might be able to exercise effective control over it.

9.5 Technocrime High-technology devices and processes do not just generate new forms of old

legal questions, however. Along with their enormous potential to benefit society, they have a similar potential for harm, and some have already found extensive employment in the service of crime. These uses can be divided into three broad categories, and there are some possible future uses in other criminal activities.

Technology as an Auxiliary to Conventional Crime

Conventional crime can be big business even when it is organized over a single city, but much more so when this is done on a regional or national basis. Drug dealers, illegal gamblers, prostitution rings, protection racketeers and smugglers are like any other business people when it comes to the need for efficient record keeping. They use computers to keep track of their traditional enterprises and improve their bottom line.

341

Page 342: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

If the illegal operation is espionage, the computer may be the means of storing large quantities of stolen information. It may simply be used to store names and phone numbers of easy marks--including passwords of unprotected computer databases. Some criminal enterprises buy legitimate businesses and use computers in entirely conventional ways; others keep records of a less savoury kind. So long as there are laws, there will be those who find profit in flouting the law; and criminal organizations have certainly adapted high technology in much the same way as do others.

Technology as the Target of Crime

At the same time, the value of expensive hardware, software, or technical devices does not get overlooked by criminals. As objects of value, they become worth stealing for re-sale--one more category of hot goods for police forces to track down. They may, in the technology they represent or in the information they contain, also be targets of espionage. From integrated circuit chips to microcomputer designs, to finished mainframe computers--all are candidates to be stolen and shipped to countries that the nation of manufacture regards as enemies, or to a competing company in the same country. The same is true of space, medical, broadcast, and military technologies. It is also true of information filed in data banks of corporate and government files and bank accounts. These latter have spawned numerous new approaches to old crimes and a few new ones as well. Technical devices are broken into, vandalized, stolen, or tampered with because there is a potential for gain or satisfaction in the criminal act. In this they are no different from low technology objects of crime such as cash or jewellery or from those of older technologies (TV's, stereos, and cameras) for all of which there exist lively black markets. In short, while it is military technology and bank deposits whose theft may generate the most publicity, anything that is perceived to have value is bound to become a target for theft. There is a broad spectrum of possible responses to such activities, ranging from attempts to improve security on the one hand to the placing of information in the public domain where anyone can have it, and being little concerned about its fate and use on the other.

Clearly, the same response is not always appropriate; while it may be consistent with the general thrust of the next age to make most data public, access to the banking, government files, and military hardware will not likely ever be in this category, and so there will always be thieves, and there will always be police.

High Technology as the Instrument of Crime

Where the computer differs from other targets of criminal activity, however, is in its potential to be a powerful instrument for crime in its own right. Thus, computers are used to attempt illegal entry of data systems belonging to banks, schools, corporations and governments--either for curiosity or vandalism. In a day of careful outside audits, it gets harder all the time to embezzle money from a financial institution. This does not stop those who understand accounting procedures well enough to try and turn them against their victims. For example,

342

Page 343: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

utility programs intended to correct errors can be used instead to transfer money from one account to another. If the account robbed is dormant, and the total deposits continue to balance, such schemes may take some time to uncover. Other thefts have been made by clever programmers who instruct the system to round down all partial cents on interest payments and place the fractional excess in their own accounts. Given enough accounts and sufficient time, very large sums can be stolen with little risk. Yet another scheme is a variation on an age-old flimflam. The thief sets up a dummy company and generates payables from the organization being victimized to the fictitious supplier of goods or services. These appear on the record to be ordinary invoices for routine activities, but no goods are ever delivered or received; only cheques go out.

False records inserted into a database via a remote computer can create or destroy damaging information. Stock market manipulation can be attempted by carefully synchronizing buy and sell orders utilizing computers. They may be also used to fraudulently transfer equities among interlocking companies to disguise irregularities or to create an appearance of prosperity for the auditors of annual reports. False information can allow the dead to collect government paychecks, goods never ordered or delivered to be paid for, and audit trails to vanish. The larger the organization, and the more insiders it has with special knowledge, the easier it is to steal from it using a computer. The state is itself the most obvious target of such activities, and its agencies must now take elaborate steps to prevent becoming large-scale victims. It is also the largest employer, and so is the most vulnerable to abuse by insiders. The situation is complicated by five additional factors that apply to crimes committed using computer technology.

First, such crimes are widely regarded as "victimless" because they are not directed against a specific person in such a way as to cause bodily harm. There is a general perception that holding up a bank with a gun and fleeing with $2000 is a worse crime than embezzling $200 000 from the same institution, despite the fact that the latter crime also involves a breach of trust. Both are regarded as lesser still than mugging an elderly lady in the park for the $23.57 in her purse. This puts a high monetary price tag on the nonviolent nature of the crime, which may be a good thing in a violent society. However, it illustrates the difficulty in weighing the relative evils of different kinds of thefts. The large sums involved may also make restitution impossible, and this, too, narrows the courts' choices.

Second, the argument is sometimes advanced that the institutions embezzled from have lots of money and can afford to lose some. It is not clear that this argument is relevant in deciding on the degree of wrongness in the theft, or even on the punishment that ought to be meted out.

Third, technological crimes are usually committed by white collar workers with no previous criminal record. The judge and jury tend not to make a connection between office tower criminal activity and that perpetrated on the streets of the slums below. These first three factors together generate another complication.

Fourth, despite the fact that crimes involving the use of high technology such as computers are on average far more costly in dollar terms to the victim than are "blue collar" crimes of violence, the sentencing tends to be lenient. There is less a sense that the person convicted is guilty of anything serious, and the punishment

343

Page 344: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

does not provide much disincentive, especially if a three-year prison term can be followed by the enjoyment of the fruits of the crime. This is further exacerbated by the general crowding of prisons in North America and the high cost of incarceration, which make it even more unattractive to imprison those guilty of economic (rather than violent) crimes.

Fifth, crimes committed with high technology, such as computing devices, may not even be properly understood by the courts, nor may their consequences be appreciated, because of the rate at which technology is changing, and the difficulty that the law has in keeping up to the new situations.

These difficulties are likely to increase with further research on genetics, intelligence, and computing machinery. The possibility may already exist for genetically engineered life forms to be used to commit crimes or to pursue wars. Sensitive banking or military installations will have to be protected against infiltration not only by personal or electronic thieves, but against biological and chemical ones as well. After all, if the people or the electronics of such an operation could be temporarily incapacitated by the agent, it would become easy prey for a more conventional break-and-enter.

Artificial intelligence research could also have its products turned to criminal activity, for great intelligence, so misdirected, has always been capable of correspondingly great mischief. Such devices, should they be devised, could well become the de facto directors of criminal organizations or tyrannical governments as well as of more beneficial organizations such as hospitals, and the courts themselves. They may become both the agents and also the targets of attempts at corruption, simply because of the high stakes involved in such controlling activities.

Even the highly personalized PIEA could become a target for thieves. The owner who stores plans, outlines, new ideas and methods on the PIEA could see it stolen by someone with an interest in marketing the ideas. An artist, poet, or writer who created a new work with another person's PIEA could produce a new kind of collaboration--it might well be possible for an expert to trace the activity of the owner of the PIEA and to have charges laid for a new kind of theft of intellectual property. Perhaps these devices will have to be built to work only with the mind of the person that first "imprints" them, and not with any other. On the other hand, perhaps the notion of ownership of ideas will become obsolete, no longer protected by the law.

Some kinds of technocrime are already becoming a thing of the past. Large computing systems are usually protected against hackers by call-back modems that only allow a user to access the system from pre-specified phone numbers. Moreover, organizations are becoming more security conscious and more often use appropriate account password protection and data compartmentalizing to prevent unauthorized access and to reduce the consequences when it does take place. So, although technology may introduce new openings for criminal activity, the use of such technology does not mean that the crime cannot be prevented; it may simply mean that potential victims must take greater care to protect themselves. As indicated in the next section, it also means that the state and the legal system will have to adapt to the use of the new technologies as well.

344

Page 345: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

9.6 Ethics, the Law, and the State Some problems associated with law and the state have been aggravated by a

general disrespect for both that has become endemic in the West in the last few decades. Some observers feel that the situation has been exacerbated by actions of some judiciaries, which have in recent years undertaken adventuresome rewritings of laws and constitutions with an almost total disregard for the intentions of the original framers or legislators. On the one hand, proponents of judicial activism argue that the courts need to reinterpret law to suit new social realities, even if this means taking this function away from the legislative branch. On the other, proponents of judicial conservatism argue that the judges' attitude has become that the law means what they say it means, nothing more, and nothing less. They point out that such an outlook not only does not foster either respect for the law or for its enforcement, but destroys the system of checks and balances needed for the functioning of democracy.

Will the direction of change reverse? There may come to be some realization that the courts have usurped too much legislative prerogative by changing laws through reinterpretation, and a more legally conservative era could begin. There could be a trend back to a traditional view of the separation of the legislative and judicial functions, to a more cautious view of law itself, and to a greater willingness to enforce the laws that do exist. On the other hand, no group or institution willingly yields power once it has obtained it, and one could as easily go to the opposite extreme and suggest that a new tyranny imposed by a judicial system run amok could be in the offing. After all, such an outcome would be one way that a system of arbitrary law could succeed the chaos of a system based on moral relativism.

The Relationship Among Government, Commerce, and Society

In addition to these difficulties, the role of the state in regulating and providing order to the economic and social system has always been one that has made government officials vulnerable to a variety of temptations to abuses of power and conflicts of interest. Some typical falls to such temptations include:

o The owner of a company who runs for office or uses political influence to direct government business to the family business,

o The union official who is elected to high office and uses the opportunity to change labour laws and government contracts to favour his union associates,

o The former government or military official who takes employment after leaving office and then uses insider information from the years of public service to enrich the employer,

o The banker who allows her institution to be used to launder drug money or finance terrorism in support of her personal loyalties,

o The social activist appointed to the bench or to a quasi-judicial but supposedly impartial body who uses the position not to dispense justice but to bring about social change consistent with her political beliefs,

o The person in a position of government, policing, teaching, or professional authority over others who uses that power for personal enrichment or the obtaining of sexual favours,

345

Page 346: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o The government official who personally directs lottery profits or tax money toward organizations in her own district to ensure re-election,

o The utilizing of networks of school friends extending over business and government to work to each other's mutual benefit,

o The awarding of contracts to specific companies or regions for political reasons instead of economic ones,

o The bribing of government officials for information or contractual favors.o The maintenance of expensive lobbies to press for measures favourable to

particular businesses, when the voice of the ordinary citizen has little opportunity to be heard, and

o The frequent transfer of government and industry officials to and from the lobbying profession that creates an incestuous relationship rife with conflicts.

Much more has been heard about such things in recent years, though it would be difficult to say that the increase in publicity represents any change in levels of questionable activities. Indeed, in some parts of the world, bribery is the only way to get anything done. Rather, the publicity about government/industry relationships and the conflicts therein reflect the information age paradigms beginning to operate. Simply put, there may soon no longer be any such thing as a closed-door deal, a secret agreement, an undisclosed relationship, or an unknown potential conflict. Regulating these problems is another matter, however. No number of regulations and audits can control the desire for illicit gain from public office if everyone involved believes the behaviour to be normal, or has no absolute standards. Indeed, the words "illicit" and "corrupt" in such a connection lose their meaning when there is no standard to say that any particular behaviour is wrong, that is, when morals are only a relative or arbitrary matter. This is easily illustrated by travelling to one of the many countries where accepting bribes to perform public duties is a way of life.

The Problem Behind the Problems

The legal problems associated with technology are not simply those of mechanics, of law, or of economics. Rather, they involve moral and ethical issues. Until they are addressed as such, there is unlikely to be any real progress, and solutions will be only cosmetic. Among other things, there is often an attitude that no longer sees it as wrong to steal or to trespass. In fact, if one can rationalize that there shouldn't be private property, then stealing and trespassing do not even exist. This is a risky paradigm, for a destruction of all personal rights to privacy and to ownership would mean that the individual person has far less protection than a chip on a machine.

It is important to understand at this point that Western civilization is based on concepts of respect for the individual citizen, and the notions of liberty, freedom of speech, privacy, and the right to hold property in private ownership that this implies. Moreover, these concepts cannot be divorced from the stream of Judeo-Christian culture and thinking in which they were developed. This assertion by no means implies that Western society ever was "Christian", but only that it has a

346

Page 347: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

heritage of respect for Judeo-Christian values, and that those values are to a great extent reflected by a legal system that assumes that there is an absolute basis in morality for law.

The growth in statism, and popularity of the concept of law as relative and arbitrary has eroded that basis for law and the democratic state without replacing it with a new one, and the result has been diminished regard for both. Simply put, the social compact that once provided the basis for ethical decisions has been set aside, and for a growing number of people there is no underlying set of principles on which they can base ethical decisions. Hence the law, once regarded as solidly grounded on certain immutable principles, is now treated as subject to arbitrary change or reinterpretation.

This is in part why there is little hope of enforcing drug or property laws under such circumstances. If every person is a law unto herself to the extent that they can get away with it and behave as they choose, there is no reason for them to consider obeying laws whose enforcement have only minor penalties. If the self-abuse of drugs is not seen to be a matter of wrongdoing, the pleasure obtained from using them is, pragmatically, the greater good for the individual, than is abstaining for the sake of a vague social contract. If a person wants money and property, and can take it from someone else who has it with little prospect of legal retribution, and no concept of guilt for doing wrong, the formality of a law is not a sufficient obstacle to deter theft.

Moreover, that which is relative can be changed at a whim either by the courts or by the legislators. That which is arbitrary is subject to the will of the strongest arbiter, a condition that easily leads either to tyranny or to chaos. To an extent, this is the situation society now faces, with a myriad of special-interest pressure groups vying for dominance over the political system amidst growing economic tension. Each group has a set of "rights" it insists upon for its own members, sometimes at the expense of everyone else, and no interest in discussing its corresponding responsibilities. Thus, it becomes more difficult all the time to pass and enforce laws that are obeyed because they are universally perceived to be just and fair. Orwell's vision may turn out to be slightly blurred--legal chaos may be as possible an option as legal rigidity.

Is any Solution Possible?

This suggests a rather bleak general picture, but there are good reasons to be optimistic as well. The recession of the early 1980s and the 1987 stock market crash changed a lot of attitudes, and a new breed of high-school graduate with a more work-oriented and education-conscious attitude emerged in the aftermath. Coincidentally, these are the first wave of information age men and women and they are obtaining the skills and attitudes necessary for the next great awakening of creative spirit. There is also some reason to be optimistic that a new consensus in support of the law may also emerge, but if so, it may at first be rooted for many people in the somewhat novel grounds of economic pragmatism and self-fulfillment rather than in any absolutes. They may not have learned much from the stock market though, for these were some of the same people who drove its prices to

347

Page 348: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

unreasonable highs in the technology bubble of the ninety's only to suffer the predictable meltdown in 2001.

A coincident increase in religious interest has also characterized recent years, and will undoubtedly come to bear on ethical questions, but if this activity turns out to be largely experiential and nominal, it may not have significant impact on the mainstream of society. If, on the other hand, it results in a revival of the notion that faith and ethical behaviour are an integrated whole, religion may yet play a significant role in establishing a new ethical consensus. Of course, even though some have always believed that moral and ethical issues were absolutes, it may be that only a minority will be committed to such an approach in the new society. In the past, many others have agreed with the ethical conclusions of traditional religious thought, either for reasons of self-interest, or out of purely pragmatic considerations. These may join a new ethical consensus for similar reasons, but the consensus they join may well have a different basis than any in the past if religion continues to play only a small role. One such basis could be enlightened self interest, but the very real possibility exists that no ethical consensus will be found, and so long as this is true, the nascent society could lack the social glue on which to base workable laws.

9.7 Solving the Problem It will never be possible to settle all legal problems; there will always be those

who ignore the most widely accepted standards of behaviour. If the real problem is with the ethical base on which law rests, and not with law itself, then any solution must address itself to ethics and to education.

If men and women of the information age are to believe in the rights of others, including, say, property rights, those beliefs will not come about by accident. If their hallmark is economic pragmatism and self-fulfilment, it is in their best interest to develop property rights, for the promise of the information age cannot be fulfilled if production of new intellectual properties is discouraged, or if the state and the law either grow burdensomely large or become impotent. Can citizens be so educated, and will teachers want to do this? This question may now be unanswerable in the broadest sense, but it is possible to see how partial solutions could be worked out in the computer industry, and this approach might be useful in other sectors as well.

This solution could involve data processing and programming personnel, particularly those with managerial and teaching responsibilities, banding together in a professional guild with a high-profile code of ethics. They would commit themselves to teach, promote, and enforce that code for themselves, for their employees, and for their students.

For at least pragmatic and economic reasons, members could give a specific written commitment to:

1) Respect the copyright of other programmers and neither sell nor give away copies of others' work.

2) Respect the privacy of data and agree never to use their skills to enter into, examine, or change the contents of someone else's system.

348

Page 349: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

3) Provide to clients and customers only structured, thoroughly tested and debugged, properly documented and fairly priced products and stand behind those products with a guarantee that errors and deficiencies will be fixed.

4) Advertise only finished products and make no exaggerated price, performance, or delivery claims.

A rigidly enforced discipline could make violators unemployable, depriving them of the skills and means to continue their activities. Cross representation with governing bodies of other professions could raise the profile of these guilds and increase likelihood of success. Strict enforcement and heavy promotion in educational institutions could eventually reduce the number of thieves and vandals. Similar codes of ethics could be devised by those doing work in Artificial Intelligence, genetic research, or robotics.

Codes of ethics for professionals are nothing new. Doctors, lawyers, accountants, engineers, and teachers have had them for some time. There are already associations of data processing professionals that have promulgated codes as well, but membership in such associations is voluntary and a large percentage of those working in the field belong to no such group. If the projections of this book are correct, there will be a considerable professionalizing of all work in the fourth civilization, and this implies creation of new organizations for information workers to provide performance guarantees and stability. The result would be that most workers would belong to a professional organization, and that such groups, or guilds, would have detailed and enforceable codes of ethics, so performance expectations of their members would be clear.

These guilds would be a temporary measure, of course. Even a new cooperative professionalism would not last indefinitely, and their inevitable decline would eventually render such structures ineffective--the fate of all human institutions. By that time, society might be ready for a new try at making modified forms of government work. It might even discover that moral absolutes have been there all along and are a more enduring foundation for the notion of ethical behaviour and the rule of law.

9.8 New State and Legal Forms for the New Age As previously observed, the modern state exists in a tensed condition,

balanced between big-brother statist collectivism and little-brother individualist participatory democracy. While, on the one hand, new and increasingly complex and expensive techniques seem to require massive state involvement in administration and regulation, the ordinary citizen has greater knowledge and therefore broader power than at any time in history. The state is clearly at a crossroads. With its citizens' consent, the modern state could continue to grow in size and influence until it encompasses the entire economy and technically regulates every aspect of its citizen's lives. A side effect would be the resolution through the use of force of the ethical problems discussed in the last section. Such a prospect cannot be ruled out even in the relatively free West, despite its obvious failure in communist states.

Alternatively, the state could give up administrative power and regulatory authority, and turn decision making into a participatory democratic process. There could be great danger for the liberties and rights of minorities even on the latter

349

Page 350: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

path, however, for unless safeguards were built in, majority voting via computer tabulated voting could become just another kind of mob rule. Moreover, the state, though somewhat amorphous, might be equally powerful under participatory democracy as under more explicitly statist regimes. There is also the danger that liberty could become rugged individualism--taken to the point that the state fragments into an ungovernable chaos. Modern Lebanon, and Yugoslavia, if there can be said still to be such entities, became the archetypal example of fragmentation. In these situations, power eventually devolves to the strongest available tyrant, but not before thousands have died. Individual liberty and freedom depend more upon the general consensus that these things ought to be fostered and practised than they do on the specific form of democracy within which they are attempted. If a free people ceases to act free, they have already lost their freedom, and may not get it back. There is a delicate balance between the need to govern, and the need for freedom--too much of either one can destroy the other.

Similar observations are true of the law. If the majority will not obey a particular law, it cannot be maintained except through force, and not very well even then. At the very least, the general population must be convinced that a law is both fair and in its best interests, or the law will fail. It is even better if they are convinced that the law is right in the absolute sense--that it expresses a moral principle they all agree with. It has been the case that the judiciary, policing, and legislative functions have been separated in some democracies in order to improve these perceptions of the law and its enforcement. This separation has blurred in recent years; perhaps it will have to be sharpened once more to restore the old balance of power. It is also worth observing that, if, on the one hand, technology is creating new difficulties with laws and their enforcement, on the other it is providing new tools to these as well.

Technology and Legislation

Legislative decision-making can benefit from the information age in much the same way as does the decision-making process in any other enterprise. However, the need to debate proposed new laws in the light of prevailing political dogmas, and the large number of people involved in these decisions, guarantee that political decision making is relatively slow. If new technologies do permit wider participatory debate, they will be neutral insofar as the speed of this process is concerned, for debates take time, even if conducted electronically. This may be a good thing, for it would help to ensure that instant information will not lead to instant and ill-considered decisions, so the quality of legislation may not deteriorate much. On the other hand, participatory democracy could result in laws that reflect majority opinion without regard to whether there is an overriding justice or principles of right and wrong. Although this trend now exists, there is no reason to believe that a legal system with a relative and arbitrary base can lead to anything other than tyranny--the rule of the strongest (even if collective) arbiter. If, therefore, technology is used to expand the participation in law making, new constitutional safeguards for minority rights may be necessary to prevent unfair laws from being passed simply because the majority desires them. Not every proposition that becomes popular

350

Page 351: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

ought to be made law, for as Hitler showed, it is possible to make scapegoating popular to the point of genocide. However unwelcome his ideas are to most at present, one must remember that they once were popular. What can be done once can surely be repeated, so active measures have to be taken to prevent tyranny by the majority.

In any event, the same considerations that were applied in the last chapter to suggest a move from hierarchical business management to flexible or professional/contract models can also be used to suggest a move to participatory democracy as a model for the state. Here is another version of the same chart.

The trend toward the top right of the chart, identified earlier, seems to favour participatory democracy in the information age, even though it need not be particularly flexible. It is worth noting that the radical egalitarian model appears to be off the line of stability, even though its placement along the bottom somewhere depends on whether one considers its theory or its practice as being the chief determinant of whether it emphasizes the individual or the collective.

Technology and Law Enforcement

351

Page 352: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

If technology has broadened the scope of criminal activity, it has also added new means of enforcing laws. Police of the information age are obtaining database readouts on automobiles, victims and suspects via computer terminals in their cars. It is already possible to make identification of a criminal with genetic mapping from semen, skin, hair, blood, and fingernail samples, and the use of retinal patterns may also be feasible. At some point, an automatic blood sampler and analyzer could be built to instantly identify any human being by genotype--an ultimate identity card. Whether any such device will be used in the near future is another matter--it would be very likely under a totalitarian state, moderately likely in many European countries, and relatively less likely in Canada, the United States, New Zealand and Australia.

Another device whose reception has been mixed is the electronic locator and tracer. Fixed to the arm or leg of a criminal on supervision but not in an institution, it provides an ongoing readout of the subject's activities and a means of checking on parole violations. It has the potential to replace many prison sentences with house or community arrests, and to prevent or solve new crimes because the individual's whereabouts would always be known. Like any device with a beneficial potential, it has an equal capacity for harm--the same device could be fixed to every citizen and the state could then monitor and control all daily activities. However, despite downside potential, reduction of prison population will soon become so pressing a necessity that these devices will probably go into large scale use without much debate.

Applications of technology to the practice of law that have already begun are the use of videotaped testimony and teleconferenced trials. The former is used in cases where victims would be traumatized by having to relive the incident and be cross-examined, perhaps years after the crime. This includes rape and other assault cases, and situations involving child molestation and abuse, or others where testimony taken immediately after the incident is preferable to that made much later. Teleconferenced trials are useful when it is too expensive to transport a judge to a remote location, or the various parties are widely scattered. These ideas have yet to be well exploited but have the potential to effect considerable savings in the judicial system.

Yet another potential application for technology is the much maligned "lie detector" or polygraph. These devices, if ever made reliable, could be installed at airports and banks, whose customers could be required on entry to place a palm on the sensing plate. Those whose emotional state appeared abnormal, as indicated by sweat and pulse, could be further scanned for weapons before being allowed to continue. Indeed, devices now coming into use at airports to detect even parts per billion of plastic explosive molecules on a person's clothes or skin also have potential to be used in detecting chemicals given off when a person is emotionally distraught. These sniffing machines would not prevent all incidents, but would offer an additional level of screening. As in all such proposals, however, there would be a loss of liberty and privacy to gain security, but this is a common trade-off. It is only after some time that it is possible to determine if such trade-offs are satisfactory, by the time this is known, it may be too late to change course.

352

Page 353: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Law enforcement will make incremental new uses of technology as does the criminal element. Police work will never become perfect, because if it did the result would be a permanent police state. It seems most likely that insofar as both law and government are concerned, there will continue to be a big brother/little brother tension, and that there will continue to be both a state and a legal system that are in rough accordance with the prevailing moral/ethical consensus of the citizenry. So long as the absolute principles upon which democracy is based are upheld by its citizenry, it will survive, though its form may change somewhat.

It is worth noting however, that in an age when many individuals can command weapons of mass destruction and the loyalty of suiciders to deliver them, no nation is safe from attack, however democratic it may be.

Internationalization

As with state and economic institutions, law will also exhibit both collectivist and individualist tendencies. That is, more of its application will tend to be at the local and community level, where it can be tailored to suit local needs. At the same time, it may tend to become internationalized as nation and economies spill over their present frontiers and operate more and more on a continental and global basis. In this arena, law is likely to become more standardized and universal. This change would be complex and exceedingly difficult for four reasons. First, it is hard for present nations to concede a measure of sovereignty to new global authorities in order to begin writing universal laws. Second, actual agreement on what kinds of law ought to be internationalized and what their content should be would be very hard to achieve--especially since some countries are now returning to a religious base for law while others are moving away from one. Third, the entire effort must be handled with the greatest caution, for once it is agreed that a law is a manifestation of universal justice, it will be almost impossible to change it--there will be no external comparisons or cross-fertilizations possible with global laws. Fifth, there will always be people who vigorously oppose change, whether it is logical and necessary, or not. These considerations point to a long process of change; the economy may well be a global entity long before law is.

However, there are pressing concerns that can only be handled on an international basis, because they affect more than one nation. These include air and water pollution, biological, nuclear, and chemical experimentation, and control over the effect on the environment of industrial by-products such as pesticides and ozone-destroying refrigerants. They also include export and import of resources like water, which may be in abundance in one country while being very scarce in a neighbour. Many of these problems have to be solved together along with others, for if they are not, even a reduction in nuclear arms would find the world a less safe place, not a better one.

The Control of Space

Some of the problems that will be faced are not confined to the globe, but relate to explorations off its surface. Thus far, control and operation of these

353

Page 354: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

adventures has rested in the hands of two nations--the United States and Russia (with Europe, Japan, China and Canada bit players). In the long run, what happens even in immediate Earth orbit, let alone in the solar system as a whole, affects all nations, and all will have to be part of the process of controlling it. Thus, at the same time as both law and government is becoming to some extent globalized, it will also have to have new forms developed to regulate space.

As soon as any number of people become resident off planet, there will arise a need for commercial, civil, and criminal law in space, as well as regulations governing behaviour of agencies of the various states. The only way that these undertakings could fail to become international would be for space to become the monopoly of a single nation and, while that possibility cannot be entirely ruled out, it may be unlikely, given the vast profits to be made, and the large volume in which to make them. Indeed, by such a consideration, it may be more likely that corporations will dominate space rather than governments.

9.9 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

The state and the law are critical institutions in any society, and both are bound up in technology. Not only do new techniques demand new laws and new statecrafts, but they provide new methods for both.

The problem of respect for law has little likelihood of a solution based entirely on extensions of the present law or technology. Practical solutions must also incorporate new respect for ethical behaviour, whatever its basis. One method of adopting and promoting an ethical code for technical professions has been suggested here as a potential solution; in conjunction with the other remedies discussed, it could provide us with the kind of respect for electronically expressed intellectual property that is necessary for the information age to happen.

New types of crime have already come into existence because of new technologies, and so have new types of law enforcement, and new possible forms of government. There are collectivist and individualist trends in these areas as well as in the economy; there may be losses of some privacies and liberties, and corresponding gains in individual influence on government, especially local decisions.

There are both chaotic and unifying trends in law and statecraft, and the ethical consensus for both institutions is in a state of flux--necessary for a new society, but unnerving because the destination is unknown. A new stability requires a new ethical consensus, and this is possible, even if its basis changes.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. What is the basis for the existence of the state? Answer from both theoretical and practical points of view.

354

Page 355: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

2. It was asserted several times in this chapter that law codifies an existing ethical consensus. Give some other possible foundations for law and then argue that these are either more or less important.

3. Examine and discuss the extent to which it would be correct to suggest that law in Western democracies is substantially based on Judeo-Christian principles of justice.

4. Research and report on the extent to which law is influenced by religion in Muslim, in Buddhist, as well as in largely irreligious societies.

5. Write a paper either supporting or attacking the idea that there exist universal absolutes of justice upon which global laws can be based. Be sure to consider the practical implications of your theoretical conclusions.

6. Suppose that statecraft does to some extent become globalized. What degree of power and authority ought to be transferred from the current national level to a global one? How can the details of universal involvement in decision making be worked out in a practical fashion?

7. On the other hand, what power and authority that is currently national in scope should become regional or local in scope, and why?

8. Argue that some power and authority ought to remain at the national level--say which, and why.

9. Some nations are either too small or too resource poor to be economically viable in the long run. How can they participate in the global economy most effectively? Should they give up their national identity and join other nations to achieve greater economic prosperity, or do they have some other reasonable course of action?

10. Free speech, even to the point of tolerating antidemocratic views, is a cornerstone of democracy. To what extent must even this liberty be regulated to protect minorities from attacks? Explore the question of whether some views are so dangerous to the public interest that their expression must be limited. Discuss specifically whether defamatory speech and writing can be permitted if (a) it is false or (b) it is true.

11. This chapter expresses optimism that the spirit of the information age is antithetical to that of tyranny. Argue for or against this view--is a global dictatorship likely or unlikely?

12, What is the difference between propaganda and advertising, and what are the legitimate limits to the use of both by the state?

13. Some suggestions are made in the chapter about individual involvement in statecraft. Are there any corresponding roles for individuals to play in the legal system? Why or why not?

14. The practice of courtroom law is very much an argument over precedent and content. Could this be mechanized and made automatic so that human lawyers and judges could be (at least partially) eliminated and the application of the law become more certain and uniform?

15. Argue for or against the suggestion that global war has already become impossible.

16. Argue for or against the suggestion that global nuclear disarmament is inevitable.

355

Page 356: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

17. Argue for or against the continuance of some form of intellectual property rights. Should access to information be a universal right, or should it be restricted in some way?

18. Argue for or against the separation of legislative and judicial authority.19. Look up and report on at least two existing codes of professional ethics in

your own areas of interest. How would the code for your profession need to be modified in the information age?

20. What role can professional associations or guilds play in the next society, besides promulgating ethical codes? What social implications do guilds have? How do they fit in to the individualization and collectivization trends? How lasting an institution are they likely to be?

21. Authorities in some countries turn a blind eye to software piracy, arguing that their nation is so poor that it could never move into the information age by buying the technology and so stealing software is justified. Consider carefully both sides of this argument and attempt to come to a resolution of this issue.

22. Women's groups often argue for government sponsorship of child care centres in order to allow them equality of opportunity in the job marketplace. Critics argue that these programs constitute unfair trade subsidies, discriminate against traditional families, and undermine traditional moral views. Is this an appropriate activity for the state? Why or why not?

23. "The rugged individualism of Americans is likely to lead to a Lebanon-style fragmentation of their country." Argue for or against this view.

24. Research the profession of government lobbyist. Explain what they do and why. Also, outline the chief ethical difficulties common to this activity and propose ways to control it. Be sure to include recent examples of real or alleged ethical conflicts in these situations.

25. Research from the popular press recent incidents of alleged conflict of interest on the part of government officials. How serious was each, from an ethical and legal point of view? What steps could be taken to ensure that those particular problems do not arise again?

26. In 1988, the United States customs office announced a drug policy of "zero-tolerance," under which vehicles found to contain minute quantities of controlled substances or paraphernalia for using them would be seized. Proponents of such harsh actions argue that they are necessary to control drugs. Opponents counter that they impede civil liberties. What is the ethical response here? Research specific instances of these seizures from media of the day, and state whether each was justified.

27. In connection with robbery prevention, the author suggests banks employ scanning devices to detect people in abnormal emotional states and further scan them for weapons. Would this differ substantially from the practice of scanning for weapons at airports? What are other cases in which gains in security are traded off for losses in personal freedom? Are trade-offs in general a good thing?

28. The computing language Ada was originally developed by the Department of Defense of the United States. Suppose you are a pacifist. Ought you to refuse a contract that specifies software is to be written in this language? Why or why not?

356

Page 357: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

29. In section 9.3 (Technology and War) Mara gives us a view of a society that is warlike, but has banned all but hand-wielded striking weapons such as swords. Is this situation possible? enforceable? stable?

30. Research a warrior culture such as that of Ireland or Japan and detail the idea of honour among and between warriors.

31. Argue that a feudal system is still a viable form of social organization--even in the information age.

32. Argue either that Marxism is a stable and viable form of government or that it is not.

33. The author (and some characters) suggest that a participatory democracy is the most viable in an information society. Either argue that this is the case, or refute it (Good debate topic).

34. In the Fall of 1965, the Undergraduate Debating Society of the University of Calgary held a debate on the topic "Resolved that this house shall mind its p's and q's." Prepare both a fifteen minute argument on the affirmative side and one of equal length on the negative side of this topic. Make sure that what you say is relevant to this chapter.

35. What are high technology ways to wage war in the information age without using conventional weapons?

36. Give a detailed explanation of how governments responded to the year 2000 problem, and how those responses differed from those of business and industry.

37. In view of your answer to question one, what services should the state provide, and which ones that it currently is involved in ought to be moved to the private sector?

38. Select a particular function or role of government and write a code of ethics for it. Defend your points, being sure to say what is the basis for each.

39. Old Testament law limited government to taxes of 10% of income, with another 10% due the priests. Today, most countries use a sliding scale, where the higher income earners pay not just more money, but a higher percentage of what they make. Find out what the income tax structure is in your country and province/state, and determine the marginal rate for an income equivalent to $50 000. What level of marginal rate is fair and just? What are the ethical issues here?

40. The existence of international trade and investment agreements such as the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA), and the proposed Multilateral Agreement on Investment (MAI), transfers a measure of national sovereignty to non-elected trans-national tribunals, thereby globalizing both decision making and law enforcement. As these agreements are made by nations, they override the authority of state, provincial, and local governments, whose taxation, subsidy, and zoning bylaws could be voided by such bodies on behalf of a multinational corporation, even though they would still apply to local firms. While increased trade manifestly increases prosperity, the trade-off is the loss of control over affairs within national boundaries. Discuss these trade-offs and argue that the sovereignty of the nation-state is too important to risk such globalization, or argue that internationalism is not only necessary but good.

357

Page 358: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

41. Research the anti-globalization protest movement. Examine its arguments and its tactics and comment on (a) their success, and (b) their validity within a specific moral framework.

Bibliography

Arden, Harvey. "The Fire That Never Dies." National Geographic 172, 3 (September 1987).

Drexler, K. Eric. Engines of Creation. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press, 1986 Ellul, Jacques. The Technological Society. New York: Knopf, 1973.Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers. New York: Macmillan, 1986 Kaku, Michio. Visions--How Science Will Revolutionize the 21st Century. New

York: Anchor, 1997Lund, Erik; Phil, Mognes; and Slok, Johannes. A History of European Ideas.

Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1972.Montgomery, John Warwick. Human Rights and Human Dignity. Grand Rapids,

MI: Zondervan, 1986.Naisbitt, John. Megatrends. New York: Warner Books, 1984. Ohmae, Kenichi. The End of the Nation State--The Rise of Regional Economies.

New York: Simon and Schuster, 1995Schaeffer, Francis A. How Should We Then Live--The Rise and Decline of

Western Thought and Culture. Old Tappan, NJ: Fleming H. Revell, 1976.Snow, C. P. The Two Cultures: AND A Second Look. London: Cambridge

University Press, 1963.Toffler, Alvin. The Third Wave. New York: Morrow, 1980.

358

Page 359: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 10A New Education for a New

Civilization?

Seminar - "What do they Teach in These Schools, Anyway? 10.1 Foundations--Theories of Learning 10.2 Learning, Education and Training 10.3 The Content of Learning in the Cultural Context 10.4 Issues in Formal Learning 10.5 Education and Technology 10.6 Schooling in the Fourth Civilization 10.7 The Role of the University 10.8 Summary and Further Discussion

10.1 Foundations--Theories of Learning Learning is one of those difficult-to-define concepts that most people claim to

know the meaning of, but few are able to explain. There are a variety of theories proposed by educators and psychologists as paradigms for the learning process. For a detailed discussion, the reader is invited to consult a text on educational psychology; what follows is only a brief summary of these by certain major categories in a form that will be found useful in the remainder of the chapter.

Behavioral Approaches

Behavioral theories hold that all learning involves (or perhaps consists solely of) a change in the learners' behaviour--either externally and in an easily observable fashion, or internally, but no less physically real and quantifiable. They depend heavily on assumptions that there is nothing extra-material about the human spirit, mind, or consciousness but that all these can be explained entirely in terms of quantifiable responses to changes in the environment, that is, in physical terms. Learning is supposed to be achieved when new electrical patterns are established in the brain, and to be entirely objective and scientific in nature. Complex Behaviours are learned a piece at a time, with connections being made in the brain in order to build up the whole pattern

The techniques that are supposed to achieve the desired change of behaviour vary according to different members of this school. They include:

o Classical conditioning, which involves the introduction of a stimulus designed to evoke a particular response. These theories grew out of the work of Pavlov and his experiments with dogs. His subjects were presented with an unconditioned stimulus (food) along with a neutral one (a bell) and their salivation was observed. Once this had been done many times, the dogs became conditioned to salivate at the sound of the bell; they had "learned" its connection with food. In a

359

Page 360: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

like manner, this theory holds, children can be conditioned to make certain connections with what they already know, and all their learning can be explained by this process.

o Operant conditioning, which is similar to classical conditioning except that the animals were required to operate some apparatus such as a lever in order to have the food dispensed. Here, learned behaviour is self-selected rather than simply reflexive. That is, the learner actively participates in acquiring the conditioned behaviour.

o Environmental shaping, which holds that control of the environment is the principal tool to behaviourally engineer learners into any desired pattern. In particular, heredity is regarded as relatively unimportant either to the ability to learn or to the final outcome of the process.

o Contingent reinforcement, which reverses the order of classical conditioning and supposes that reinforcing stimuli ought best to follow a learned behaviour. Thus, the likelihood of some behaviour is increased or decreased depending on whether it is followed by a reward or a punishment. One would view the dog's salivation at the sound of a bell as the learned behaviour, and the provision of food as the reward. Here, all teaching methods, whether using reward or punishment, are evaluated for their ability to produce the desired behaviour, and not for any intrinsic value they might have. Practical techniques based on this theory, which was developed by B.F. Skinner, include scientifically scheduled and programmed learning and the use of a variety of teaching machines.

o Social learning theories, which hold that new potential Behaviours are acquired by the observation and imitation or modelling of others, and that these are stored for use on appropriate occasions, the suitability of which are also learned by imitation.

These behavioural theories have the advantage that they are end-result focused on the actual physical or brain activity of the learner that results from the process. They have two disadvantages: First, they do not attempt to explain what thinking is or offer a context in which to evaluate ideas--that is, they are useful only for outcomes. Second, they do not provide an ethical framework within which to judge techniques of teaching and learning, except for the end result of changed behaviour. Together, these mean that the means are divorced from the ends, except as cause-and-effect, and that could be hazardous indeed for the participants in learning processes.

Cognitive-Discovery Approaches

Cognitive-discovery approaches concentrate on thinking patterns in the learner, without the behaviourist stress on objective physical changes achieved in the learners' overt activities or brain patterns. The whole of learning is held to be greater than the sum of its parts, that is, the mind assigns meaning to patterns that transcends the original data. In this view, learning takes place not just by adding up the facts and physical associations of the stimuli, but by grasping the relationships between them. The learner does not merely respond, but perceives. That is, something new is mentally synthesized from the raw data that was not present in

360

Page 361: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

any physical sense, but that is a result of classification, organization, and insight taking place as mental activities within the learner. Some variations within the theme include:

o Gestalt theory, which emphasizes the high level pattern of the whole as opposed to the low level details of the structure. Perception is dynamic and at any one moment concentrates on one pattern or "figure" against a background of detail, much of it not actively being perceived. Another way of putting this concept is to say that perception involves the making of abstractions, while learning is the acquisition of or assent to new abstractions.

o Piaget's theory of the active learner, which holds that the person learning is an active processor of the stimuli being presented, and has a built-in desire to organize and make sense of the data. Thus, understanding is not the making of a mental copy of what is seen and heard, but is the product of each individual's unique ways of knowing or transforming data. Because the drive to learn is inherent, success in doing so provides its own reward, and the learner need only be encouraged in the active process, not given external rewards or punishments. In particular, the painstaking memorization of material organized by others is discouraged, because it bypasses the learner's own ability to create patterns, and therefore carries no intrinsic reward. Piaget based his theory on two premises. First, he postulated an underlying organizational ability that enables a human to develop intellectually. Part of this is biological; that is, it is inherited genetically and is therefore variable. Another part is generic to the human race as a whole and is therefore constant. Second, he observed that the human system was capable of adapting to the environment. This is done by assimilating new data into existing behavioural patterns in view of the new data.

o Cognitive-discovery theories that hold teaching ought to be concerned with assisting students in the process of sorting data and organizing their own conclusions. The idea is that if they grasp the total idea of the subject, they learn principles that can apply to other studies at a later time. The learner is more likely to remember and, having done so, to have a good foundation for extending the study to more complex levels. Rather than making of learning the sum of many details, the discovery approach asks the learner to generalize from a few experiments and observations, and then apply the generalization to similar situations in detail. It is assumed that the student not only can reason, but also wants to, and that curriculum must be arranged so as to provide ample opportunity to explore within a broad structure. In a sense, this method could be contrasted with the technique of the Greek philosopher Socrates, who believed that knowledge was to be drawn out of the student by a series of well-designed questions posed by the teacher, the end of which was the convincing of truth by logical argument. By contrast, the discovery approach assumes that the student poses the questions, and can generate meaningful self-rewarding answers from the data. The teacher need only provide the raw materials for gathering the data, not the actual answers.

Cognitive-discovery approaches have the advantage that they consider two additional aspects beyond just outcome: the intellect and experience of the learner on the one hand, and the act of learning on the other. They do however, make assumptions about the process of learning that may not be universally applicable,

361

Page 362: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and concentrate somewhat more on that process than on the results, in contrast to the behavioural approach, which does the opposite.

Humanistic Approaches

Humanistic approaches focus on the human potential of the learner. They agree to some extent with the cognitive ideas of the last section, but their emphasis is on development of the social and emotional aspects of their students' lives more than just on knowledge acquisition and new paradigms for organizing it. There are many variations on this theme, but certain characteristics that all modern humanist approaches share to a greater or lesser degree are:

o Progressivism, which is a term adopted to indicate a reaction against traditional values and techniques. This reaction involved far more than education and also included agrarian reform and changes to the status of workers in large cities. Although the "progressivist era" is thought of as having ended by the Great Depression, elements of its thinking continued to be important in education long afterwards. For these purposes, progressivism includes the principles that

i) There are no absolutes, including of moral values, but all truth is relative. John Dewey was the principal proponent of the application of relativism to education, teaching that each individual generates personal truth--including values and reality--by interacting with the environment and engaging in a transaction with the consequences of that activity. There ought therefore to be no authority, competition, or punishment involved in learning. Although many of Dewey's ideas were no longer being explicitly used after the 1950s, the notion that values are relative has survived in more modern theories. Thus, if there is any discussion of values, it is to have as its end the "clarification" of students' values, and their comparison with those of others, but certainly not the inculcation of any from a predetermined or authoritative set. This rejection of truth reached its zenith in the 1990s deconstructionism, and has the same problem in the learning arena as elsewhere--there is no difference between a solely personal and relative truth and no truth at all.

ii) There ought to be no repression of the ego, or of painful feelings or thoughts, but complete freedom of self-expression. This is supposed to produce a more open and creative learning environment. That it might simultaneously make it impossible for anyone else within range to teach or to learn is less important than unfettered self-expression.

iii) Learning should be child-centred in the sense that there ought to be as little adult influence as possible, and the child's perception of needs and interests ought to dictate both the curriculum and the methodology. All activities should be democratic, with the teacher having only one vote, along with each of the students. The drawback of this version of child-centredness is that uneducated students do not yet have the ability or the techniques to ascertain what activities and ideas are the most important.

iv) Children are naturally good, curious, energetic, and eager to learn, and one of the tasks of the teacher is to facilitate the removal of traditional societal

362

Page 363: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

inhibitors of these traits. Unfortunately, these assertions appear to contradict actual classroom experience, and have, therefore to be regarded as suspect.

o Existentialism, which in this context holds that learning is to be viewed as part of the learner's unique and personal struggle to find meaning in existence. Emphasis on this aspect of learning implies a corresponding de-emphasis on the potential educational demands of the society as a whole. Full realization and full actualization of the self become the most important factors in learning, and the needs of others are taken into consideration only secondarily. Curriculum is also secondary, because the way individual students feel about the subject at hand is more important than the factual information itself or the students' understanding of it. Sometimes, attempts are made to inculcate values or attitudes based on feelings. Thus, there have been curricula designed to teach young children about sexual abuse based on the child's feelings relative to the abusive activity. Attempts have also been made to teach about the environment solely on the basis of students' feelings about species extinction. The problem with such approaches is that feelings, being individual, cannot be relied on to achieve a specific curriculum outcome. Thus, far from validating the theory, this approach seems more likely to contradict it.

o Freedom from fear, including fear of criticism, competition, punishment, and failure. This is one of the most controversial aspects of this group of theories, for others have held that one learns a great deal from all four, so they need not be feared. Other freedoms have also been proposed, including those from dependence, or from all forms of authority.

o Learning is principally a matter of experience, and that it is therefore intensely personal, and to at least some extent, non-transferable.

According to its proponents, the humanist approach to learning has the advantage that it extends the process to the whole person, and that it recognizes individual strengths and differences. Its opponents suggest that it has the disadvantage of negating all absolutes, and therefore of undermining any basis for its host society. This may be the reason why so few of the progressivist experiments last for very many years--a school by its very nature is both an organization and a society, but the progressivist models are hostile to both. As with all relativists, the progressivists are vulnerable to criticism on theoretical grounds, for their espousal of the non-uniqueness of truth also undermines the foundations of their own theories. No relativist theory can ever assert its own superiority over an absolutist one with confidence, for if it does, the very relativism it proposes becomes an absolute. The humanists also have practical critics who claim that children both need and want authority in order to know their limits in society.

Toward a Unified View of Learning

Each of the three schools of thought examined so far has something to contribute to the total understanding of what learning is. Each provides a useful paradigm for some aspect of the process--the behavioural, the mental (or cognitive), and the emotional and social, or some combination of two or more of

363

Page 364: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

these. Each is also open to criticism for concentrating on one or two aspects to the exclusion of others, and for the extremes to which such focusing may lead. There is, for example, no shortage of "educators" who are ready to compel all children to learn in a particular way, and to require all teachers to use a particular technique to achieve this. After all, if there does exist a universally applicable theory of learning, then it follows that there may be an optimal technique as well.

It is also important to note that these three schools of thought have an implied definition of the totality of the learner that omits important considerations that go to the heart of what it means to be human. Beliefs, values, convictions, motivations, and meaning questions also have to be considered, for it is these that provide the reasons for behaviour, the structure for cognitive filters, and the basis for engaging in experiences having emotional reactions, and being social. That is, they do not deal with the issues behind ethical and social questions, or with the meaning of what it is to be human. But, there is an aspect to humanness that is more fundamental than those dwelled upon by these schools of educational psychology, and it is necessary to consider how this aspect relates to the whole person as a learner. In keeping with the integrative and wholistic themes of this book, what follows is a suggested approach to understanding learning that attempts to combine this fourth element with those from all three of these schools of thought in a way that deliberately avoided answering the question of whether there exists an optimal technique to achieve the desired goals, but that does suggest how the process ought to work.

Learning can be elaborated in terms of certain physiological changes that take place in the brain as new information is stored there, or it can be cast in terms of the stored information itself. It has something to do with growth and development, and with the process of finding out more about the world. It depends upon ones beliefs, philosophy, commitments and religion, and it also changes the learner. It also depends on past experiences and relationships, and enables different ones for the future (i.e., learning takes place in a continuum). Learning is not just any kind of change in human capacity, for the forgetting years of advanced senility are not what one wishes to regard as learning ones. However, learning does change as one matures, so a definition must include this aspect as well. Here is an attempt to include all this in a single statement:

Learning is a process of abstraction taking place within the context of existing culture, behaviour, knowledge, and beliefs whereby the person who is the learner acquires or acquiesces to new

paradigms in order to explain experiences and by so doing changes in the ability to respond to new circumstances.

Many interactions are involved in learning, even though some theorists emphasize one more than another. The following diagram may be helpful to illustrate these relationships and their mutual interaction.

364

Page 365: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Diagram 10.1--A Model for LearningNote that although all interactions are mutual, there is a certain order of

priority implied by the positioning of the elements in this diagram. Who a person is comes at the centre of all, for from beliefs and commitments flow everything else. Indeed, all the others can be thought of as aspects of being. Experiences, including the emotional, are next, at the top; then the intellect at the lower left, and finally the relational at lower right. Also, the categories are not entirely distinct. For example, inventing is not a purely relational activity, but requires the intellect as well. The diagram also indicates a mutual interaction among the elements pictured, for none of them stand alone. This description does have a comprehensiveness of its own that with some amendment could applied to machine that "learn," however, this chapter will only be concerned with learning undertaken by human beings.

It can even be argued that learning is a uniquely human activity. Actual response to stimuli--pushing a lever for food, or learning a maze--may be appropriate terminology for rats, but there is little evidence that it can be adopted uncritically for humans. Mental changes alone are of theoretical interest, but lack practicality. Likewise, there is yet no convincing evidence that terminology used to describe human cognition--words such as "perceive", "understand", "assent to", "comprehend" or "intend"--have any application either to animals or to artificially constructed devices.

Since learning involves the altered ability to change within and to respond to alterations without, and since change is partly the result of mutual interaction

365

Page 366: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

among motivations (ethics), society and technology, it is clear that a great deal of learning is required of all members of a civilization in transition to a new mode, just for them to remain functional. Another mutual dependence exists here: new learning creates new Behaviours and techniques, and these in turn require new learning--oftentimes even on the part of those who developed the techniques but may not understand what they have wrought until later. In addition, new techniques also require new applications of old ethical principles, and the learning of a new consensus of behaviour with respect to the new methods. Many examples of this can be drawn, say, from new medical applications, which often raise related ethical questions. Thus, the lines shown on the graph above are all two-way paths of mutual influence.

The definition also includes potentially negative changes, for people can learn Behaviours that inhibit their abilities to respond, but such "negative learning" tends to make the person less efficient and reduces the ability to pass on the behaviour in most cases. Thus, not all learning is useful either to the individual or to society, and that which is will tend to carry with it a reinforcement that adds motivation for the potential learner.

Learning is also something every human being experiences from the time of the womb on. All have to learn how to make sense of sound, to talk, to read, to write, and to operate within the myriad of common conventions that make up the bond that is society. This commonality must include:

o a knowledge of its history, or else the bond is incomplete, o understanding of its ethical norms, or else it is impossible to exhibit

behaviour appropriate for the society, o skills in its techniques, or one cannot participate productively in it. That is, learning that results in a potentially productive and contributing adult

does not just involve the acquiring of factual knowledge and social skills; it also involves the acquisition of a set of restraints and imperatives that characterize the culture and allow it to operate, and a set of experiences that provide empirical data on which to base one's own actions.

A child growing in mind and body and acquiring more of the total cultural consensus, gradually becomes a part of it, and is enabled to enrich it in turn--this is an outward-directed relational and transformational aspect of learning. In order for all this to happen, the already functioning members of the society must organize the child's learning in order to ensure that the total cultural context is passed on efficiently and effectively; for with each generation the society that context represents is but one step away from extinction. At some stage of this process, each child must learn how to learn in order to take over this responsibility for that too is a part of the expected adult responsibility in every society. That is, this wholistic description implies that the culture and not the child sets the learning agenda until the learner has the fundamentals in place and is ready to take responsibility for carrying on.

Thus, for the sake of their own survival, hunter-gatherers had to teach their skills to their children. Likewise members of agrarian societies that followed them had, and now have, to teach plant and animal husbandry. Indeed, in many situations (including military ones), the choice is between learning or dying--such

366

Page 367: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

circumstances have little room to allow for those who cannot or will not learn the necessary skills; the non-learner is a non-survivor. This is as true today. On the one hand, one who does not learn effectively cannot participate in society appropriately. On the other, ideas, beliefs, and cultures, are all engaged in a variety of conflicts; those that have no means of effective transmission to the next generation all perish. And it is not the best ideas that survive, but those with the most adherents to transmit them.

A civilization is always one generation from extinction.

This is not intended to suggest that learning is a part of evolving toward some high goal, as though it were an aspect of "Progress" with its own sense of self-direction. Rather, it is simply to observe that every society has associated with it a set of attitudes, skills, techniques, and ideas that it must transmit to the next generation if it is to survive in a recognizable form.

In at least one sense, learning continues throughout life, for every day that passes brings experiences that are at least in some respects different from those of all the yesterdays. Yet, in many societies, particularly the very primitive or stable ones, substantive learning effectively stops at a very early age, except as later required in order to survive in emergent conditions. An individual can find a niche in such a society, and stay there from early adulthood until old age claims back the abilities guarded and used through a lifetime. Even in the industrial age, a worker could learn a single trade, such as automotive welding, and do nothing else until retirement. However, in a rapidly changing society, such a luxury is available to relatively few, for job descriptions and even whole industries change much faster than the passing of the generations alone can accommodate, and social survival becomes an immediate and very personal incentive for learning.

Having made a case for a wholistic and comprehensive approach to learning, it is now time to make new distinctions, this time based on the subject and goal of the learning, rather than on the process by which it takes place.

10.2 Learning, Education and Training It is worthwhile to distinguish incidental learning from organized learning.

Learning that takes place with focus, purpose, and direction on the part of the learner, and that specifically engages cognition toward understanding ideas is more properly called "education". While it is correct in one sense to apply this word to the acquisition of life skills as described at the end of the last section, it may be useful to restrict it to that subset of learning undertaken with some sense of mindfulness, deliberation, and purposefulness (intentionality) by the learner. Thus, even when learning is organized as "schooling", it may not be entirely proper to consider the process as education, for many of the "schooled" are having something done to them, rather than actively and willingly participating in changing themselves toward some goal.

For its part, schooling could be regarded as the attempt of a society to cause a degree of learning to take place that will be useful to that society. It has ambitions beyond mere functionality for the learner, but it may only partially enable

367

Page 368: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

education. While it might therefore be in the interest of a society to insist upon a certain minimum level of schooling for its members, it is not possible to ensure an education for any of them unless their minds are engaged at some point to become willing participants in the enterprise. Mere years spent in the schooling process will not of themselves guarantee that the schooled person will be more productive, more educable, or even more useful to society. Schools can be used as little more than safe holding places while awaiting a certain legal age.

It could also be useful to distinguish between human intelligence and that potentially ascribed to artifacts (A.I.) on the basis of whether education is possible--that is, whether understanding is achieved, or whether all that can be accomplished is a technique of factual regurgitation. Even in the latter case, the recitation of facts by a human being, though not high level synthesis, requires some integration of memory and verbal skills. It is not at all clear that there is a machine equivalent even to this; even it may be a uniquely human activity.

Yet another learning word is "training", which is distinct from education in that it requires a lesser degree of cognitive activity and is not primarily focused on mental activity. While education must deeply involve the mind, training need engage it only slightly, for training is the perfection of skills, and these are at their best when mastered to the level of instinctive and unthinking reaction to stimuli. The main purpose of training therefore is to change an individual to conform to and be able to use existing techniques. Education, on the other hand, ideally leads the willing mind on to understanding, and enhances the ability for self-change--perhaps in developing new techniques, or in demonstrating to society that faith in some of the old ones has been misplaced. It may even result in substantial changes to society.

Like education, training may also be attempted through formal schooling, but this will never be entirely satisfactory or complete on its own, for the necessary instinctive level of technique comes only from long practice of the method in its actual application, not from classroom lessons. Thus, one need not expect there to be much correlation between years of schooling and subsequent on-the-job trainability, even when this connection is the stated purpose of school-based training. Berg (Education and Jobs) points this out in referencing military and other government statistics on recruits, which clearly indicate that years of schooling, even in extreme cases, are not necessarily well-related to trainability. One could therefore argue that job-related skills ought to be taught in the grade schools, but there would not be ready agreement on the specific skills to be included.

Training cannot be completely separated from education, however, for there are ideas behind all skills and techniques. Moreover, those with training in some technique are among the best qualified to think about and improve upon those techniques. They may also become capable of forming abstractions based on what they do, and thereby making new intellectual contributions. However, it is not those who are solely technicians who make new scientific discoveries--without the creative and questioning aspect of the educated intellect, a technician can only continue to do things the same way indefinitely. It is in the integration of education and technique that the power of the scientific method lies, and that is why it is

368

Page 369: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

essential that scientists be experienced evaluators of ideas, not just trained in the application of technique.

Since new methods that remain confined to their inventors are of little use to society, training is important for the dissemination and use of techniques of all kinds, and education plays the same role for ideas. It is possible to be a well-trained scientist/technician, but so unmindful of ideas, as to be properly regarded as uneducated. It is likewise possible to be somewhat unschooled, but of considerable education--though this latter is perhaps rather less likely than the former.

It should be apparent that a society needs both forms of organized learning; it cannot hope to survive with only one. One of these transmits actions and methods; the other culture, beliefs, and ideas. It should also be evident that a whole person ought to have both training in technique for the sake of a job, and also education in ideas for the sake of understanding and wholeness as a human being. In the hierarchy of Chapter 1, this makes wholistic learning an ethical priority. Of course, one could also make it a priority on pragmatic grounds.

Because the existing members of society have a vested interest in perpetuation of that society, both education and training have been organized and institutionalized from very early times. Formal institutions of learning such as schools, however, are like any other organizations. Once they become sufficiently entrenched in the fabric of society, they take on reasons of their own for existing. In addition, schools are not proactive institutions; rather, they react to what the community deems important, and may lag behind those desires by a considerable time. They also develop techniques for managing the enterprise of learning--ones to deal with salaries, budgets, buildings, public relations, discipline in school, and a variety of teaching strategies. They often have a specific agenda for reinforcing or changing the broader society that has given them nurture. This additional agenda comes variously from the state, the local community, the parents, or from their teachers. It may have political, social, cultural, religious, ethical, or economic motivations, or may simply arise from the growth momentum of the appropriate bureaucracy. It may be expressly stated in printed goals for the jurisdiction, or it may be kept hidden from public view to avoid controversy. In all, schools invariably end up with far more concerns than the specific learning that is their ostensible task.

For example, the state may use schools to reinforce its power, by dictating both the content of the curriculum and the form of teaching. Teachers may desire to use the schools to achieve economic or political goals of their own, and these may have no intersection with those of the state. Parents are likely to want the school to reinforce values they have taught their children, and their emotions can run extremely high if they perceive that these values have instead been tampered with or denied by the school. The community, as represented by its school board, may have a vested interest in certain shared ideas--which in some places could include a racist attitude toward some group, usually one highly visible for its color, national origin, or economic status.

All parties consider that the students' values and loyalties are up for grabs to the most persuasive, and that they can be secured through the school. Whether this is true or not, the belief that it is, together with differing agendas of the parties

369

Page 370: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

involved, guarantee that there will always be conflict over control and use of schools. Furthermore, whatever agenda is adopted, the result is likely to be a concentration on the most efficient techniques for achieving that agenda, rather than on what the broad curriculum should contain, or who should teach it.

However, in preoccupation with techniques of learning institutions--especially when these are in turn used mainly to teach techniques--it is easy to lose sight of education. Techniques are routine, safe, familiar, and easy to manipulate for specific purposes, and so are the institutions that focus on them. Ideas, on the other hand, change people at a far more fundamental level than does training in technique. By their very nature, ideas can be dangerous, strange, threatening, and difficult to engage another's mind to. When new ideas are adopted, the emotions are also involved, and behavior changes; so do motivations for engaging in learning new ideas and techniques. Ideas are also the whole stock-in-trade of education; and know no institutional boundaries. This can make them very threatening indeed for those with institutional and political agendas.

There is also a danger that preoccupation with technique in school-based learning may sometimes cause practitioners of those techniques to forget their clients are people--citizens in transit, supposedly becoming more productive and better thinking and behaving adults. The follower of modern political debates over educational philosophy, curriculum, teaching methods, or funding, cannot help but be struck by the paucity of references to the actual students who are engaged in the process. In such discussions, learners can easily become an amorphous manipulable mass product, lacking personality, humanity, and individuality. The irony is that this dehumanization can take place within the confines of the very institutions entrusted with the task of making individual students functional as humans. However, economic and political considerations have a way of forcing some dehumanization by a kind of assembly line approach to schooling. It should also be noted that students are often very much aware, both of agenda conflicts and of the degree to which they are treated as products rather than as people, and they often come to resent being less than they know they could be. This is true even when they appear to cooperate willingly with an educational experiment, for they are quite capable of simultaneously and contemptuously criticizing the same arrangement whose benefits they enjoy.

There is also an interesting tension and competition between education and training. Since training relates principally to technique--that is, to the ability to do things a society considers important--it is one of the keys to obtaining a job that can feed a family. A person may have much education, but insufficient training to earn a living, for there is no compelling efficiency in hiring a learned, but unable person. In the industrial and prior ages, ideas alone would put bread on the table of only a very few people, and it is not their activity that most citizens see and judge society by.

However, it is not only the technological achievements, but also the ideas of a people that generate the judgments of the future upon a society, and a civilization would become stagnant and start to die without either. Neither can the two ever be completely separated as might be inferred from the discussion above, for there are

370

Page 371: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

ideas behind all techniques, and there are at least consequences, if not applications, of all ideas.

An important challenge to formal schooling systems seems therefore to be to provide people with a suitable mix of training and education to allow them to be doers, experimenters with, and also thinkers about what it is that they are doing. Another is to work within a student-oriented ethic, recognizing the importance developing human potential fully, for none of the other parties have so great an interest and so much to gain or lose as the learners themselves. This is not intended in the progressivist meaning, wherein the student sets the agenda, but rather in the sense of recognizing the uniqueness of the individual within the total context of society--having the good of students as first priority.

Of course, schools are not the only agents of learning. Families, churches, peer groups, and the media also play an important part. The agendas and institutional priorities of each of these are part of the process as well--whether of education or training. Since there is a complex interaction of all these forces in the whole culture, which is the learning milieu, an interesting set of tensions is created.

On the one hand, the voice of any one of the teaching agents is weakened when they do not all speak consistently. The parent who speaks disparagingly of the school to a child may well render ineffective much of what it is attempting to do. Likewise, the teacher who sets out deliberately to undermine the parents' authority--or that of the whole society--is likely to succeed at least to some extent. The communications media with a social agenda may have an even easier time persuading people, especially the young, to adopt novel values. This is particularly true in a society in which the family, once the most important factor in value transmission, has been greatly weakened, for there is a silence into which many voices seek to speak authoritatively.

When there are no uniform voices from which to learn, the result may well be confusion. The student who has not consistently learned the history and morals of society cannot be expected to make a commitment to them, and may never become a part of it, for being becomes confused and so does knowing; the result is likely to be chaotic. This observation may bode ill for a society that seeks to be ethically pluralistic, and therefore does not give any one set of values priority over all others, for even its pluralism would then have no transmittable legitimacy, and the freedoms that make pluralism possible would have none either. That is, there is always a tension between the need to transmit values, and the need to allow for diversity and challenge to those values.

For example, the constitutions of both Canada and the United States enshrine fundamental freedoms as legal rights on the assumption that they are "self-evident." Yet, the very rights to free speech, a free press and a free and secret vote must be extended to the enemies of all three rights, who must have the freedom to attack these values, attempt to persuade people to discard them, and to vote against their continuance. Unless these values are believed in by most people, and most of the society's institutions work in concert to transmit them to the next generation, their enshrinement in the laws of this time may mean little in a few years. The Greeks' cyclical theory of history held that such a deterioration of democracy into dictatorship was inevitable and that to hold freedom as an absolute

371

Page 372: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

is to walk near the edge of a precipice. The paradoxical challenge for any free society is to systematically preserve that freedom without destroying the freedom to speak and act inconsistently with itself. As noted earlier, "tolerance" that regards only itself as the highest value becomes narcissistic and tolerates no voice that claims to know absolutes. It then becomes intolerance.

Education with a reasonably consistent voice is essential to the continuance of any society for it cannot survive without transmitting its particular ideals. In the social compact, teaching and learning are aspects of a society's imperatives and of the mutual dependence of its members, for there is an implied obligation on the part of society to assist individuals to become functional members, and there is a return obligation on the part of the individual to obtain the requisite learning needed to make the mutuality called society work, and to repay society for that learning by keeping it working.

For this reason, a school must always have a clearly defined mission statement, philosophy, goals, and expectations of its students. After all, it must present a consistent organizational culture to its clients that is an appropriate microcosm of the broader culture that has entrusted to it the transmission of its essence. It ought not be the forerunner of change, following every new whim and opinion as soon as these are in the majority, and neither must it be too slow to change to society's new paradigms. It must manage the task of preserving the historical values that gave it birth and simultaneously enable students to live in tomorrow. This is not a hard task in times of little change, but a nearly impossible one when a society is rapidly metamorphosing into a new form.

On the other hand, while conformity and consistency are important for the transmission of values, an excessive concentration on both would destroy the freedom of enquiry necessary for democracy. The regimes of Hitler, Stalin, Mao, and Pol Pot were nothing if not consistent, but they were brutally repressive of every idea not deemed to be part of the state's agenda for indoctrination. Therefore, the other players in society, such as corporations, governments, and the media, cannot be required to have missions, philosophies, and goals that are entirely consistent with the schools, or freedom will already have ceased to exist. The possible extreme for consistency also points out the need to teach students to identify propaganda, to discern facts, to evaluate the content of opinions, to be able to propose and weigh alternatives--in short, to think clearly. For instance, the author is continually advancing various points of view, and it is sometimes clear that he is advocating one over a number of others. Even in the cases where this fact is not evident, however, the omission of some ideas from the discussion is also evaluative. The reader is expected to assume that everything in a book of this kind is evaluative, and to continue the evaluation process personally.

That is, education very much involves a conscious give-and-take among informing, preserving, growing, and changing. Rigidly legalistic absolutist philosophies often fail important tests here, for they do not allow sufficient flexibility for necessary change. However, a completely relativistic and individualistic philosophy also fails the test. Such thinking holds that no ethical principles, or indeed anything else is absolute, but that the individual may assess and then accept or reject all ideas equally. In this view, schooling is a smorgasbord from which the

372

Page 373: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

student may sample piecemeal according to choice, regardless of the degree to which that choice has been informed. However, people actually tend to absorb beliefs, emotions, ideas and techniques wholesale from their teachers on the strength of mere assertion, and without assessing them. Moreover, the very notion of a society is that some ideas are held by its members to be more important than others, and the idea of a civilization as a whole is that some ideas are universal and absolute. These include honesty, the value of its members work, empathy with other members of the society, the ability to cooperate, and so on. If education, from all its sources, fails to show clearly the superiority of the fundamental ideas at the core of a society, it will actively prevent continuance of that society.

The notion that learning can be value free, or that one can learn about values without assigning any sense of importance to any of them is a myth, for this attitude itself is a statement about values. It is also one that is contrary to upholding principles of liberty and democracy, for these provide the context for anything that can be called "free" enquiry. There can be no such thing as context-free studying about culture, religion, politics, economics, good taste, or morality. The very attempt to remove context is a contextual act, one that asserts that there are indeed other absolutes than those of the society. Moreover, if there are neither truths to learn nor values to assess what is learned, it is not clear that education has any ideas to talk about.

Thus the school in a democratic society must teach democratic cultural absolutes as such and set students into the existing cultural context, while at the same time including freedom to think differently as one of the absolutes, and empowering them to change the culture dramatically, without necessarily suggesting that they ought to. Achieving this also implies imparting a fine sense of values, a deep sensitivity for both individual people and for the culture, and a broad ability to integrate ideas from many subjects at once. An integrated agenda, rather than a fragmented one, would likely therefore be a hallmark of the next civilization, and this would surely be reflected in its schools.

In like manner, the attempt to distinguish too sharply between education and training will ultimately fail. They may be somewhat different aspects of the greater process of learning, but neither can be completely separated from the other. This is true not only because there are ideas inherent in technique, and methods are implied or necessitated by ideas, but also because both education in ideas and training in technique take place within broader contexts. First, there is the context of the whole human being who is undertaking the learning, and who is changing as a whole because of it, and second, there is the context of the society in which the two processes operate. Since education and training are connected through those contexts, there is always a mutual influence of the two, so they can be treated separately only insofar as they are aspects of useful learning in a total context. While some schools may specialize in one or the other of the two, all must to some extent integrate them into a seamless whole, for the people of the fourth civilization will all have to know technique, but they will also be required to be evaluators of ideas.

373

Page 374: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Just as the total context of what is learned is of critical importance to the process, so also is the content of that learning and it is on these two that the next section is focused.

10.3 The Content of Learning in the Cultural Context

"A human being should be able to change a diaper, plan an invasion, butcher a hog, craft a ship, design a building, write a sonnet, balance accounts, build a wall, set a bone, comfort the dying, take orders, give orders, cooperate, act alone, solve equations, analyze a new problem, pitch manure, program a computer, cook a tasty meal, fight efficiently, die gallantly. Specialization is for insects."

-- From the Notebooks of Lazarus Long, by Robert A. Heinlein

What ought education to contain, in order to achieve the goals of engaging the mind to the task of bringing the learner into the main stream of society? The various interested groups such as government, teachers, administrators, and school-based associations, have all conducted studies and composed their own lists over the years. The one here is therefore in a long tradition, but it is presented in the context of the discussion of this book, not so much as a summary of the extant literature Some of the items are fundamental and obvious, but worth restating precisely because the obvious is sometimes invisible, and therefore ignored, even when it is important. Other things may be less obvious, but nonetheless important to achieve the appropriate balance in the entire cultural context.

Life Skills

Once, it was once assumed that basic life skills were taught at home, and that the school system need no longer concern itself with them. However, such things as manners, etiquette, how to balance a chequebook, use the banking system, how to shop, to budget, to raise a family, to look for a job, and to obtain government, medical, dental and legal help--among many others--can no longer be assumed to be in possession of the student. To fulfill the mandate to help a child become a functional adult, schools must pay attention to such things; failure to do so will leave many students incapable of breaking out of family patterns of ignorance and poverty. Critics of including such things in a school curriculum are quick to blame the parents or some ethnic sub-culture, but in so doing they forget that the school has an ethical obligation of its own that does not depend on the student's background, and that this obligation is to the principal client.

Who is the principal client? Depending on one's point of view, it is either the society that gave the school its mandate and agenda, or the student who is receiving the knowledge. In a democracy, the difference may not seem great, but it can be very large indeed in a totalitarian state. Ideally, the student is the focus of the learning activity, and socialization into the broader society is for the benefit of the student as much as it is to fulfill the mandate of the state.

374

Page 375: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Neither can the universities suppose that this observation about life skills is relevant only to the grade schools. After all, what is the use of producing academics who are filled with ideas and techniques from their specialty, but who are non-functional in their society? Such learning may not have to be a large part of the curriculum for mature adults seeking new horizons, but for the student fresh out of high school, it is still a necessity.

Communications Skills

The ability to receive and transmit ideas, needs, and emotions is crucial at every level of participation in society. On the one hand the person who cannot be communicated to cannot be taught, and is therefore unable even to begin the pilgrimage to adulthood and responsibility as a member of a society. Indeed, it is precisely the ability to learn that delineates what professions or job roles are available to a given individual. On the other hand, from the infant who needs to inform parents of a dirty diaper to the Ph.D. in biochemistry trying to publish a potential Nobel-winning breakthrough, the ability to get a message out is equally crucial to functionality. The following maxim is offered to bring this critical need into focus:

A person who is unable to communicate beliefs, feelings, information, and knowledge efficiently and effectively might as well not have any.

The case has already been made in this book that the society of the future will be characterized as one in which suitably trained people will have instant access to all forms of information. Thus, the memorizing of many facts will take second place to the ability to acquire, manipulate, and transmit information--that is, to organize and communicate ideas. Since such communication will involve ideas as well as facts, those who do work in the future will have to work smarter, and the specific area of their learning that will need the most attention is the ability to communicate clearly and effectively. There will be much less tolerance of incomplete or erroneous communication, and there will be substantial pressure on all those using information facilities to ensure that they do so correctly.

Those who are able to master the techniques of working with and communicating ideas, which is part of being educated in the sense used here, may have enormous advantages over those who cannot, so this will be a critical part of future learning. At what point such training would become universal is not yet certain, but the assumption being made here is that by the advent of the major Metalibrary facilities, the ability to make use of them will simply be taken for granted by both workers and employers. Thus, reading for understanding and writing for the clarity of another's understanding will not simply be the goals of future learning; they will of necessity be its major acceptable outcomes.

Literature

375

Page 376: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

No people can be understood, nor any culture perpetuated, without serious reference to its literature. The sophistication of the students will, of course, determine the complexity of the writings with which they can grapple, but books are essential for a people to know where they have been and who they are. For example, no serious study of Western civilization is possible without coming to grips with the Bible--the single most influential collection of books in this culture's literature. The British heritage and even the English language are heavily dependent on Chaucer, the Magna Carta, Shakespeare, and many others. Likewise, the writings of the founding fathers of the United States, including the Federalist Papers, the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution, are crucial to an understanding of American society and culture. Works of fiction also hold up a mirror to the soul of a people. It is no mere coincidence, for instance, that science fiction became so popular in the machine age, or that fantasy exploring alternate worlds, cultures and religions was on the ascendancy at its close. In both forms, this genre of literature is reflecting culture--the stable one of the mature part of the industrial age, and the changing, groping, and uncertain one of its passing. These observations are true of every language and culture; all express themselves in their writings, and no culture can otherwise be understood.

Likewise, the history of ideas is contained in books, and the modern person is treading on dangerous ground in dismissing the thinkers of the past on the grounds of supposed obsolescence. Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, Kant, Luther, Calvin, Galileo, Newton, Locke, Marx, Freud, Einstein, and a host of others shaped the world and its views as they now are; modern culture cannot be understood without reading them. The great danger in making the transition to the new age is that foundational attempts to grapple with ideas will be dismissed as irrelevant simply because they are old, or were conceived of (and therefore are seen as tainted by) people whom the moderns do not view as politically correct.

History

This topic and its importance have been remarked upon extensively in this book. In order for citizens to understand their place in society, and their potential to contribute to or change that society, the learning of its history is essential. The cultural bond of any society is not just with its current citizens, but with all those who made the society what it now is, and with those who will follow. When the motivations and techniques that brought it to the present point are understood, and the points at which the major decisions were made for stability or change have been identified, it is possible to begin informed consideration about new directions. Otherwise, decisions are taken in a vacuum of historical knowledge. Being ill-informed, these are as likely to bring harm as good and so the mistakes of history come to be repeated.

As for the literature of a culture, so for its history--the present cannot be understood without the past, and the past exists for the present primarily through its books. Fail to read these books and see where society has come from and why, and the student will surely be unable to determine where it is going and why.

376

Page 377: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Ethics

It is also insufficient (and impossible) to study the values of a society in a judgement-free context, as if they were of no real account for either the present or the future. Both the values being studied and those of the one examining them are inseparable from their respective cultures. These are not relativistic; they are part of what makes a society and a people unique. When they are discarded, the people lose their distinctiveness and become, even if only partly, some other people. This is the case of every truth that a people holds to be self-evident, for such a statement is an assertion that its values are absolute and essential to their distinctiveness. Moreover, it has been argued several times in this book that it is impossible for a society to exist at all without a collective conviction of what constitutes "good" for that people. If all go their own way in this, doing what is right in their own eyes without concern for anyone else, then there is no society, just a collection of individuals, centered upon themselves and groping about in an increasing chaos.

Moreover, an absolutist ethic holds that there are "goods" that transcend all cultures, and without an agreement on them, humanity itself may be at stake. That is, the commonality of good and evil applies to the community of nations as well as to each country individually. Lesser values may pertain to the survival of a culture; but greater ones may have an impact on the continued existence of humans on the planet. Since each generation must work these things through in order to avoid extinction, values are a part of every education, whether this is acknowledged or not. On the big issues, some of today's students will eventually make the decisions that might precipitate or avoid a global war, cause or avert an ecological catastrophe. For a myriad of others, they will have to live life and share a community participating in its understanding of how to apply the good and the right.

In addition, since the lives of teachers are an open book to their students, and can be far more persuasive and compelling than the content of the formal curriculum, it is often the teachers' moral actions that students will imitate more than their words. Thus, the ethics that are caught will depend only somewhat on the subject matter in schools; they will depend much more on who does the teaching and how. Students are very sensitive to the total classroom context; their response to the subject matter is much more dependent on the teacher than it is on their peers. This observation applies to all who teach, including the popular media and its stars. Indeed, the more popular the media, and the more hero-worship offered to its major figures, the more potential those people have for influencing change, and the greater the responsibility if by that change, the values of the society are replaced by others.

Once again, the dilemma of democracy is highlighted, for students must learn to allow and even to hear voices that would destroy freedom in the name of the absolute of free speech, but if they do not also learn a self-imposed restraint along with their commitment to such absolutes, they will have the power to obliterate democracy in a single generation.

377

Page 378: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Sex Education

This discussion highlights one of the most controversial curriculum items of all. Every person must come to terms with sexuality; it must be understood, for it is a part of being a human person. Sexuality is not just a collection of anatomical facts and techniques, but a critical aspect of humanness, and an essential part of the most important relationships one forms. Sexuality is critical to knowing and participating in cultural rituals and to understanding literature; it is an undeniable part of everyone's life. It has the potential for enormous pleasure and satisfaction in the closest of all possible bondings two human beings can form. The corresponding dark side shows as a great a capability for harm, for evil, for disease, for perversion or exploitation, and even for death.

Because of its power, pervasiveness, and importance for both personhood and socialization, human sexuality generates a wide range of moral issues. This creates an irresolvable dilemma for schools. On the one hand, a child must learn to become a responsible adult, and sexual education is too critically important to leave out of the curriculum. On the other hand, information about sexuality cannot be transmitted free of values, for it is behavior that is in question, not simply facts. It is impossible for children to be taught about their sexuality without some indication (even by implication) of what is appropriate behavior; the attempt to require teachers to do so itself makes the moral assertion that there is no moral question involved. For example, if students are encouraged to use condoms in order to prevent AIDS, they may be given the message that sexual indulgence carries only disease risks, and is otherwise morally acceptable--a stand that contradicts traditional beliefs. Yet, not to tell them about condoms at all might well be irresponsible; the school is in a dilemma from which no easy exit exists.

Likewise, one cannot teach about homosexuality without making value statements, for its practice is not merely a lifestyle issue, but a moral one. There are also health implications to such practices.

In the ensuing debate, one side correctly points out that lives are at stake if students remain ignorant; the other rightly complains that merely "factual" education both ignores the relational aspect and undermines moral values learned in the home. Some wish children to learn that sex was designed for free use only in the context of strictly monogamous, permanent, and heterosexual marriage. Others view it clinically--as a body appetite to satisfy, and no more a moral issue than eating--one takes precautions to avoid tainted food, but nothing else. Schools are caught in the middle of the conflict, unable to meet important needs without causing offense.

There is no escape from this dilemma in an ethically fragmented society. Sex education is essential, but can never be value free, and schools are unlikely to gain a mandate to lead culture, especially in its values. The advent of new killer sexually transmitted diseases (STDs) has merely sharpened the controversy. In some communities, the short-term consequence may be a renewed emphasis on private schools, many of which are religious in nature, so that families can ensure the transmission of their sexual morality to the next generation. Of course, such families generally do so at home; their private schools often do not teach such things

378

Page 379: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

because they are established without such a mandate. Such a fragmentation of schooling is inevitable when a portion of society changes direction and adopts a new world view, but it bodes ill for consistency, unity, and cultural survival into the future, for there are often other forces, such as racism, working to divide the school system as well. In the longer term, there must be a new consensus on this issue as well, for a society cannot be built on diversity alone.

Science, Technology, and Mathematics

Since the society of the future will be even more wedded to high technology than it is now, far more of its citizens will require some technical knowledge in order to function. Just as the factory workers of the industrial age had to be trained to run the machines, so also will any who wish to work in the future be required to have some technical literacy. This is not the narrow training of the late industrial-age specialist, but rather the ability to understand and effectively use the new technology and the information it provides. For example, it will no longer be possible for even the most ivory-tower of academic intellectuals to work without using computing equipment, for their publishing too will be accomplished in this way. It will also not do for any citizen to be ignorant of basic science, for far too much of life will be directly affected by and constantly changed by the new discoveries.

Yet, while necessary, the objective of infusing broad technical training into education will continue to be difficult to achieve. The majority of students abandon even the modest general science courses offered in today's high schools at their earliest possible opportunity. There are a number of reasons for this, but the chief one appears to be an early loss of interest in mathematics, without which any further science education is impossible. As such organizations as the National Council of Teachers of Mathematics (NCTM) are too well aware, much of this problem is probably traceable to the lack of qualified or even interested mathematics teachers. In North America, it is rare for an elementary school to have a mathematics specialist on its staff. Even at the junior secondary level, many of these courses are taught by the great surplus of English and social studies teachers, regardless of what mathematical background they might have. Math avoidance can be perpetuated from one generation to another by elementary teachers who may themselves be afraid of the subject, and by high schools that are too busy with a broad agenda of other problems to attempt the costly and time consuming rehabilitation of the avoiders. For their part, most universities operate on the assumption that the student chooses the major, and outline the curriculum within that narrow choice. Few of them operate the traditional liberal arts curriculum and demand at least a few courses from each of the major areas of study, and their students can easily depart with little or no mathematical literacy. Yet those who do avoid mathematics cut themselves off from a broad range of careers, including most of those that will be at the center of the action for decades to come.

Some of this problem is cultural, for there is a broad perception that mathematics is not necessary for many occupations, and indeed the very abstract materials often included in the curriculum are not. However, it is exactly these types

379

Page 380: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

of jobs that are threatened as the industrial age closes, and it is the ones requiring greater technical knowledge and presupposing some mathematical literacy that are multiplying.

There are institutional reasons for these problems as well. Many school administrators not only believe (or are forced to act as though they do) that anyone can teach mathematics, they also act as though it can be taught anywhere, anytime, and with no equipment. Thus a high school mathematics teacher may be handed a piece of chalk and sent to the sewing or drafting room or to a vacant science lab. The same teacher may be required to use decades-old books and lack the budget, facilities, or expertise to produce local materials. For social and cultural reasons, the few well-trained teachers of this subject are still far more likely to be male than female, despite the fact that their high-achieving students are more likely to be female. In such circumstances, the female students will lack role models appropriate to breaking out from stereotypes.

There is no easy or short term remedy for these problems, but those countries that are successful in engaging the attention of and convincing their peoples of the necessity for mathematical and technical learning will be the big winners in the economic sweepstakes of the future--provided that this is simultaneously combined with the learning of effective communications skills. There is no indication at this point that such a happy realization will soon come to North America. If it does not, the unchallenged scientific leadership it once had will surely pass elsewhere.

Technique

In a sense, the industrial age majored on techniques--the many narrow specialities of the academic, the tradesperson, and the industrial worker. The information age demands techniques of its own--those of finding, assigning meaning to, and using information. Thus the education of professionals must change dramatically, for they will no longer need to be factual repositories when they have machines to take over this function. Instead, they will concentrate on being finders and users of facts as necessary, and on the creative artistry that has always separated the many mundane practitioners from the few truly brilliant ones. Doctors and lawyers will have to change their ways most dramatically, for they are currently the most dependent on knowing facts when needed. However, every step toward the Metalibrary will force similar changes on many other professions, and their techniques will grow much more similar with the passage of time.

Thus, training in skills will tend to concentrate on the finding of appropriate information, which, being about the idea of technique, is actually a matter of education more than it is training. Alternately, one could term these "meta-techniques." Education in the new civilization must be much more concerned about the process or ability to learn. This is something many theorists had already hoped it would be, and studies of education have usually called upon it to be, but there is little evidence that it has been delivered on in the past. If suppositions here about the nature of work in the next civilization are close to the mark, future education must become more concerned about both the process of learning and the ability to learn. The difficult task will be to devise the techniques to bring it about.

380

Page 381: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The Big Ideas

This in turn means that more people in the future will have to become assessors of ideas, for this ability is part of the technique required by the information paradigm. Implied by this is a reduced emphasis on some of the discrete and narrow specialization considered important in the industrial age, and an increased one on the activities of the mind itself. Certain very broad questions that have always been important to philosophers will become part of the education of the future, because they touch directly upon the assessment of ideas. These include:

o Classical Metaphysics, or the study of ultimate reality and meaning. This is the discipline that provides the frameworks within which to create world views, such as those of the scientist. In it, one also studies questions about the origin and development of the universe (cosmology), about the nature of being or existence (ontology), about the existence and characteristics of God (philosophical theology), and about the nature, role, and destiny of humanity (anthropology).

o Epistemology, or the study of the nature of knowledge statements, and the sources and meaning of knowledge. Though this word as such has not previously been used in this text, epistemology has been at the heart of several of the discussions thus far. It bears on the truth value of statements, on the reliability that can be ascribed to various forms of knowledge, on whether truth is relative or absolute, and on whether knowledge is subjective or objective. It helps to distinguish whether knowledge is based on another's authority, is revealed by God, comes from a reasoning process, is intuitive, or is empirical and derives from the senses. Clearly metaphysics and epistemology are closely, even circularly, related, for one needs a theory of reality to say reality can be known, and a theory of knowledge to say that one knows that reality exists. These are important questions to the serious knower, and need to be considered by the would-be assessor of ideas.

o Axiology, or the study of values. This usually includes ethics, though that topic has been treated separately in this book. It also includes aesthetics, which expresses cultural values in art. Because it relates to the imagination and creativity of a people, and because artistic media tend to express the history and other values of a people, an understanding of aesthetics is important to the knowing of a people's soul. The answers to questions such as "What ought I like?" or "What ought I consider beautiful?", are important to the would-be member of a culture, and are not techniques, but appreciations, without which both communication and functionality are seriously impaired.

These three areas of study, while often regarded as unimportant, and not really needed by many people, are a part of the intellectual makeup of every human being alive. If not taught, they are caught, but they are learned. Perhaps the difference in the future is that they will be explicitly identified and discussed, for there will be a greater realization that it is not behaviour that gives a person an

381

Page 382: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

essential identity, but beliefs and values, for these shape the emotions, the experiences, and the behaviour.

The Social Studies

In this final category are included all the studies of the behaviour of humankind, both in the mass of society, and as individuals. Such disciplines as economics, politics, psychology, and sociology are represented here. As indicated in the chapters on the economy and on the state, these too will become progressively more important as time goes on. However, if the projections of this book are even close to correct, there could be a long period of dramatic social change in the immediate future. This would increase the desire to develop social techniques and the yearning for such disciplines as economics and sociology to become full-fledged sciences, but the turmoil will seriously hinder the ability to achieve this goal.

It should be recalled at this point that social change initiates new techniques, and is caused by the interactions and conflict that arise out of new ideas and inventions once they have been implemented. Thus, the rate of social change and the rate of technological innovation are closely linked, and it may often be unfruitful to enquire which of the two came first in a given instance.

Will the Generalist Come Back?

There was a time, not too many hundreds of years ago, when it was possible for a well-educated person to contain within a single mind virtually the whole body of scientific and literary information known. Ideally, such a person would have attempted to read all the works of philosophy and theology available, and would have striven toward being the complete scholar. Such a day passed away with the scientific and technical revolution of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, when the pool of knowledge became so vast that no one individual could hope to comprehend it. Even artificially lengthening the adolescence of young scholars by keeping them in school until their mid twenties could only produce a "doctor of philosophy" who could be so narrow a specialist as to be almost non-functional outside the tight little world delineated by the final dissertation.

In the hard sciences, particularly physics, it could take several more years for the student to arrive at the frontiers of knowledge and begin to do useful and original research. The minuscule overview the student received of all those fields outside the speciality was hopelessly out of date even by graduation. However, in the information age, remembering all the facts all of the time will become less and less important. Being able to find the facts, associate them, and use them will be of first importance. That is, in a given project, it will still be necessary to assemble the factual information, for this process is fundamental to integration and synthesis, but it will not be necessary to personally retain such information in order to continue functioning in one's profession. This necessity to learn for skills rather than information is most pronounced in the computing and information sciences themselves, where material can become obsolete by the time it has come to the attention of the person who proposes to teach it.

382

Page 383: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

All workers in the next civilization, but especially its leaders, will have to be more articulate communicators, broadly educated, with at least some technical and some business background. Once certain minimum skills have been obtained, and without diminishing any of them as broad, basic requirements for functionality, the man or woman of the new age may be free to specialize. The present day stereotype of the able science student who is nearly completely illiterate in the English language will probably have to vanish. The equally stereotyped arts major who fears, distrusts, and is willfully and even proudly ignorant of modern science and technology will be equally out of place.

The quote from Heinlein at the beginning of the chapter provides a good starting point, but men and women do not yet have the multi-century lifespan of a Lazarus Long that is required to become knowledgeable in every field. Moreover, if new progress is to be made in technology, specialists are needed to make it. The amount that these specialists will have to know, the way they will work, and the demands society will place upon them to enable them to function at all are changing dramatically. The new civilization belongs to those who will specialize enough to earn their bread and butter as distinct individuals but who will be generalist enough to qualify them as functional human beings in a society where information management and communication skills are paramount. They will have to use their knowledge skills to work in several specialities simultaneously or serially, switching from one to the other as the need dictates. It is to such ends that learning is likely to be directed in the future.

10.4 Issues in Formal Learning The compilation of issues discussed in this section is far from comprehensive--

they are only a few of the major concerns about learning: those that fit in to the themes of this book, those that deal with the broader society, that are ethical in nature, or that touch upon the techniques of learning.

Why is Learning Undertaken?

Groups with an interest in the learning process were mentioned in the first section of this chapter, along with their possible conflicts. The idealist's answer to this first question is that learning is undertaken to make the learner functional and preserve and enhance the knowledge and values of the society wherein it occurs. However, there are many groups with special interests in learning for the benefits or changes it can bring to them. For its part, the state often wishes to develop willing citizens, and to this end an authoritarian state will dictate the entire curriculum, perhaps in both a comprehensive and an arbitrary fashion. At the same time, a democratic state must use the curriculum, albeit much more subtly, in an attempt to convince students of the superior virtue of democracy. In any case, the state that fails to achieve this persuasion of students that it is legitimate will soon cease to exist, for there are other voices prepared to persuade them differently.

The state (at the national or regional level) may have a variety of specific agenda items to achieve and hope to use the school system for these purposes. For instance, catching up with the Soviets became the byword of the early 1960s after

383

Page 384: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the United States' perceived humiliation by the Sputnik launch of 1957. For a time, being beaten into space provided the motivation for an extensive rewriting of the national curriculum to emphasize mathematics and science. Academic theoreticians were called upon for a quick fix of the mathematics curriculum, and produced the impractical and abstract "new math" with its scores of axioms and abstractions and few examples, applications or exercises. It did not seem to have occurred to anyone to ask whether it was necessary for grade two students to become mathematical theoreticians, nor whether any practical needs were being addressed. Not many teachers even understood what the purists had given them, and some ten years went by during which few had the courage to deprecate theory and try to relate mathematics to students' lives or to the surrounding culture. It is not clear at this point whether much is accomplished by such dramatic changes, nor even what the general effect of state dictated or influenced curricula is in general. Neither is it clear that the uniformity demanded in such cases is actually achieved; the classroom teacher has opportunity to implement other agendas than those of the state.

There may also be specific social reasons for undertaking schooling--it could be done in order to perpetuate class differences or an existing division of economic spoils by keeping certain groups "in their place". Since information is available from many sources, such uses of schooling are becoming more difficult and could be effectively impossible in the more open society of the future. Others have the opposite view--that schooling ought to focus on the elimination of socioeconomic distinctions; that it ought to be the great class leveller. Thus they promote "lowest common denominator" curricula, on the assumption that if not everyone comes into the school system the same, they can surely be made to leave it the same. Even though this philosophy has very strongly influenced North American school administrators, it is seldom carried out to such an extent in the classroom, because its premises are observed by practising teachers and by their students to be untrue.

For instance, by the time students finish high school, there may be five to eight years difference in reading and arithmetic capability, and there may be no immediately available means to close this gap. This does not mean it will never close, or that those that are either less able at that point or are completely and permanently dysfunctional; it merely suggests that the modern school lacks techniques, resources, and the mandate to produce a uniform product in factory-like fashion. Formal learning is not, for a variety of reasons, a class leveller, though it has some trends in that direction, nor is it likely to become effective as one. Quite the contrary, the provision of equal opportunity to excel in learning might result in an entirely new class structure based on ability. Whether this turn of events is a desirable outcome or not is questionable.

Another social agenda may sometimes be followed by employers, for whom the number of years of schooling may be a screening device, on the understanding that those who have successfully cleared one set of hurdles in life are better equipped to clear another. However, this will work against the employer who hires people who are overqualified, for when the reward offered by the job fails to match the expectations of the jobholder with respect to responsibility or remuneration, the result is dissatisfaction and a high turnover rate. Employers who hire those with

384

Page 385: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

slightly lower paper qualifications than needed and train their employees on the job will have higher job satisfaction, lower turnover, and a better retention rate. Some employers know this, and deliberately hire overqualified workers for menial jobs on the theory that they will not be around long enough to organize effective demands for improvements in working conditions (See Berg--Education and Jobs: The Great Training Robbery).

However, such exceptions aside, it is remarkable that employers have so far had little interest in or opportunity to influence schools, even though they are entirely dependent on them for their human resources. This is probably due to their concentration on the short term bottom line--a practice that may be necessary to meet immediate competition and satisfy shareholders, but tends to limit long term potential. Such limitations are most problematic when, as in the fourth civilization, the business milieu is changing rapidly and markets can appear and disappear overnight. The ability to respond sufficiently rapidly in such situations requires a flexible generalist work force that can reinvent themselves and their enterprise at a moment's notice. Finding and training such people requires that long term commitment to change have priority over the immediate bottom line.

Perhaps it is most accurate to say that society organizes learning for economic reasons. These include the ability of a nation to compete effectively in innovation and high-tech production, and the ready availability of a well-trained labour force so that employers can make quick changes or additions to their staffs. There is also the benefit to the state accruing from higher taxes paid by better trained workers, who usually obtains a higher salary for the effort. However, these observations apply mainly to training in technique. On the other hand, the benefits to society of education--the ability to think and evaluate ideas--are much less immediate and tangible, especially at the close of an age that has been obsessed with training in technique for short term rewards, and wherein education is ideas has largely been an incidental by-product of such training.

One could advance the suggestion that education produces a better and more complete person, and is therefore desirable for ethical reasons, but this would be unlikely to impress those who have to pay for the process, and it would be difficult to establish as true, even if it seems to be self-evident. A better argument might be that more highly educated people are likely to be the very kind of versatile problem solvers that a fourth civilization enterprise needs to survive and thrive. Thus, in the future, education in ideas may be undertaken for economic reasons, because it is more available, or because there are time and money to pursue it. These may not be profound reasons, but they are pragmatic ones, and will likely serve.

Who Should Control Education?

Since there are public, family, and business interests in learning, and since there are both societal and individual concerns, the issue of control over organized learning is a difficult one indeed. Teachers claim the right to oversee it in the same way as other professionals control their work. But, doctors and lawyers police only the entry to their professions and, to some extent, the ethical standards of practice. Hospitals are built and their administrators are appointed by their owners, which

385

Page 386: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

may be private organizations, churches, community boards, or officials of government health departments. Likewise, judges are either elected or appointed by government. That is, in neither of these cases is the entire medical or legal apparatus operated by the professionals for their own ends. Thus, teachers cannot expect to gain such control over schools, curriculum, and the administrative aspects of learning, except as they are appointed by and represent the broader society.

Yet, just as hospital administrators have usually been doctors, and judges are usually lawyers, the educational apparatus is normally run by teachers, or former teachers, even if it is not their organizations that appoint them, for government education departments are often operated by those whose training is as classroom teachers, just as are the schools. There is not necessarily any direct conflict of interest in this, because such people generally cease to be teachers and become instead administrators--removed from and possibly unsuitable for the classroom environment after a time. They have the time to be the developers and pursuers of educational techniques of all kinds, and the persuaders of classroom teachers to experiment with these techniques, but gradually become divorced from the practical realities of the classroom and immersed in the business, politics and public relations of schooling. Indeed, just as hospitals have in more recent years begun to create a separate profession of medical administration, so also there is beginning to become a distinct breed of educational administrator.

However, such comprehensive control by teachers, former teachers, and professional administrators, while not a conflict of interest, is very narrow. Parents and children have the most at stake in learning, but there has not been much mechanism for their voices to be heard. Employers also have a major interest in the learning process, for they are expected to hire the students afterward. Yet, very little attention is paid to their needs, and they are seldom represented in the design of curriculum. Likewise, universities may set entrance standards, but their influence on the grade school is otherwise confined to the trickle-down effect of their graduates who take on teaching positions there. This gives them a delayed-action philosophic control over the grade school, but no direct voice in decision making. There are exceptions to these observations. In some cases, universities have worked closely with grade schools on curriculum, and some states in the United States are mandating a broader business and community representation on the boards of technical colleges. However, these are usually experimental or isolated test cases, and it is not clear how soon these will become general practices. That they will so become is one of the information society paradigms, but it may take some time.

Another difference between teaching and the practice of law or medicine is in the direction of accountability. All may be somewhat administratively accountable to government, and to institutional bureaucrats, but lawyers and doctors are always understood to be responsible for the outcome of their work directly to the client. Although the ideal professional teacher has a deep sense of responsibility to students, there has in the past been little to hold teachers externally accountable for the work they do, or for the interests of their clients to be directly taken into consideration. If they used the techniques promoted by their superiors and did not offend anyone, it was unlikely that any enquiry would ever be made about whether

386

Page 387: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

their teaching had been effective or if it had achieved the desired learning outcomes. Moreover, there is frequently sharp disagreement about what outcomes are desirable, how to achieve them, or how to measure them. It is also in the vested interests of teachers and their unions to oppose any measurement of teaching effectiveness.

This too is changing, however. The combination of easy access to information and the litigious nature of American society is already starting to produce educational malpractice suits, and there have already been cases involving students who sued because they were allowed to graduate while still illiterate. There is nothing like the threat of legal responsibility to concentrate the mind on making improvements. Thus, in far more learning situations, specific goals are being delineated before the process begins, and these are being tested for once it is finished. Also, more people are becoming involved in the making of curriculum decisions, in the development of teaching strategies, and in the measuring of outcomes, and the premise of the information society is that such integration of the efforts of the interested parties will increase substantially in the future.

Since the learning process is addressed to a critical ethical point --the completing of functional human beings--the question of effectiveness and the matter of accountability to the student are crucial issues. It would be inappropriate to have the student, if a young child, control the process and the curriculum, even though this may well be suitable for an adult learner. However, if teacher-student accountability were practised, and the outcomes of the process measured, it might become possible to determine which, if any, of the many educational techniques are most effective. However, it should be noted that the institution of teacher performance assessments will probably take a long time and the process will likely involve much pressure by clients and much resistance by unions. Theory may indicate that such assessments are desirable, but theory must still be put into practice. The wide variation in control over education will continue to ensure that the move from theory to practice is uneven.

What is the Status of Teachers?

At the present time, teachers are often regarded as professionals only at the university level, and those in K-12 schools may find themselves accorded a rather low status in the community, especially considering the importance of the task in which they are engaged. Yet, there is little evidence that university professors are better teachers. Indeed, as a rule they are not expected to be competent in anything but research--for that, and not teaching, is their profession. In the public eye, there is often suspicion that the K-12 teacher does little that could not be done by anyone. There are sometimes deep concerns about the results of grade school education that are said to be partly justified by the scores on some standardized tests, and many of those concerns are focused on the teacher.

The problems of the broader society also impinge on the classroom, making the job more difficult still. Because public schools can operate with training or educational goals that are either few in number, not clearly defined, or that contradict one another, and because of the competing desires of society, teachers

387

Page 388: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

find themselves at the conflict point of the various demands made for learning. Instructors in technique have an easier time, because they know what the outcome of their work is supposed to be. University professors have the least problem of all with such conflicts because the general public does not expect to know what they are doing, and they need not have educational goals, so they are virtually immune from criticism. They are, however, academics and not men and women of action, so they are extremely vulnerable to direct frontal attack, especially with the threat of violence. Thus, in the 1960s academic standards and course content came to be dictated by the most violent student radicals, and few academics were courageous enough to withstand the onslaught. After a period of relative calm, such attacks were renewed in the 1990s, this time focusing upon the removal of the last vestiges of cultural relevance and values, and on the grading system (see Bloom--The Closing of the American Mind).

This discussion leads directly to the question of qualifications for teaching. In the formal sense, these vary widely from one jurisdiction to another. Until well into the twentieth century, many teachers took only one year of teacher education beyond high school at a "Normal School," and were never formally tested for competence once they were certified. They were at the mercy of superintendents, inspectors, and board members, and could be fired for any reason. Later, the single professional year of training came to be appended to the end of a standard university degree, and teachers were also able to form powerful associations or unions. In some places, it became virtually impossible to fire a teacher, regardless of competence. However, many certification boards now have rigid formal standards, and periodically require recertification or upgrading of skills and they make every effort to remove those unable to perform the task set to them.

There are three aspects to teacher qualification: personal suitability, teaching skills, and subject competence. A degree of administrative ability may be included in the first of these, and the last has traditionally been directly equated with academic background. At the primary school level, the first two are held to be more important, but as one moves up through the years, they suffer in regard by comparison to the last, and at the university level, the latter becomes paramount. Yet, at all levels, the learner is also searching for role models to assist in the becoming of a whole human being. This fact would seem to suggest that the order of priority should always be: (1) who teaches, (2) how it is taught, and (3) what is taught. Care must be taken not to allow such a shift in emphasis to become an anti-intellectual relegation of subject matter to a low priority, or an emphasis on charismatic leadership at the expense of content. All three are important factors in education, but the industrial age has tended to diminish the human element, and it may need some restoration.

Such a realignment of priorities might be achieved if the essential unity of learning at all levels is realized, and teaching becomes a more professional, self-policing discipline (with public input). Given the size of the teaching force, this goal seems difficult to achieve, but the ethics of the task of completing human beings would seem to demand much more careful selection for personal suitability to the task. In addition, it requires both a greater subject competence at the lower levels,

388

Page 389: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and a greater ability to teach at the higher ones. These will not come about by accident, but requires deliberate action on the part of educational administrators.

Information paradigms seem to encourage such action, however, because it will become increasingly difficult to hide incompetence of any kind in an open and highly competitive society, and this will force these issues into public view where they must be faced. It is also possible that the passing of the baby boom and the increased demand for more highly trained and educated workers will put heavy pressure on schools, and this will help to ensure that teachers are suitable, do become competent, and are effective. Here, too, change does not come easily, and there are sure to be teacher organizations that will fight any perceived loss of power and influence.

Who Should Pay for Education and Training?

Population stability also means that North American school enrolment has peaked and will begun to decline. However, increasing participation at the upper levels, raised expectations by students, the great number of new capital-intensive techniques, and higher teacher salary expectations, continue to put upward pressure on school expenses. Like the health system, the learning system has potential to break the budgets of even the wealthiest funding agency. This has resulted in two trends.

First, there is a search for new technology in order to turn over some of the teaching process to machines--this in the hope that it would make learning more capital intensive and less salary intensive. Whether this is a good thing or not will be discussed at length later in the chapter. This is, however, yet another illustration of demanding that technique solve problems, without considering whether the problems ought to be solved first, and then technique applied to make the solution more efficient. As in the computerization of a bad office system, when it is done the other way, with technique before solution, it is the problem itself that becomes more efficient, that is, it becomes worse faster.

Second, there is a growing lack of enthusiasm on the part of the state for the whole process, at least in some places. Governments, and the people who elect them, have in some cases begun to lose both ability and will to fund the learning system to the extent that it has come to expect. The result has been a series of conflicts between governments and teacher unions, and in some jurisdictions a sharp decline in the percentage that formal learning has of the overall government budget.

Quite apart from long-term survival issues, this has created a funding vacuum for existing schools that can be met only by appealing for funds to the private sector or by going out of business and turning their students over to private sector institutions, which charge fees, but on average spend much less. In either case, it would appear that, over the short term, private sector involvement in and private funding of education is likely to increase dramatically. The companies and individuals providing these funds will of course demand a corresponding control. Whether the resulting competition with the public sector will improve learning or fragment it remains to be seen. It is likely to mean that education and training will

389

Page 390: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

become more distinct, for the private sector is much more interested in the latter than in the former; it will not pass up the opportunity to influence schools to produce graduates who are immediately useful to them.

One widely advocated proposal to fund publicly while allowing the competitive advantage of a private system is to issue vouchers for all children in a jurisdiction. They, or their parents, would then select a school and turn over the voucher, which would then be exchanged for a fixed number of dollars from the state. Such a method would have been cumbersome to implement without computing equipment, but would now be relatively easy to administer. Critics have attacked the proposal as a way to create two standards and two tiers of education and so divide society--all at public expense. A way around this objection might be to use a partial voucher for half of the estimated cost, or some other suitable proportion. Public schools would receive the other half from the state as they do now. Private ones would be expected to raise their second half from the private sector. This system could possibly reduce the total cost of education, allowing the public sector to redirect money, say, into the inner city schools and actually provide improved learning experiences--if politicians could avoid the temptation of using it elsewhere, such as in reducing deficits or increasing other spending.

A further objection to a voucher system in the United States is that it would necessarily result in government funding of religious schools, including Catholic parochial schools and various other Christian institutions. Some believe this to be unconstitutional.

Other funding methods are possible as well. As the corporate sector grows in power and influence it may set up its own schools for employees and their children. Corporations in fast-changing technologies that must engage in continuous retraining could become more like technical schools or even universities than like the businesses of old. Indeed, this is already true to a great extent of companies like IBM, Apple, and Microsoft. However, since the average size of corporations will likely decline in the information age, and these may undergo very rapid and continuous change, the ability to run formal schools in this way may be rather limited.

In theory, universal public schools are the prime agency for democratization and socialization, but this ideal is difficult to maintain in a divided society. Privatization may have the advantages of maximum efficiency and precise targeting, but it has the disadvantage of potentially severe fragmentation. This is already taking place, and seems likely to continue until some time after the broader society has reached a new consensus on its values and priorities. What seems certain is that schools will have to find new sources of revenue and support in the private sector. Where these will be, and what this will lead to is not yet clear.

Is Learning Fair?

Every society has a variety of socioeconomic groupings or classes. As mentioned earlier, one socialist ideal is the levelling of these through learning, but what may well happen is that either the existing class structure is exacerbated or that new ones based on ability are established. There can be little doubt that the wealthy have access to better and expensive private schooling for their children,

390

Page 391: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and therefore to substantial opportunities to perpetuate their economic advantage for another generation.

Even in the public system, schools in better neighbourhoods or wealthier regions have a greater capacity to raise money for school projects, equipment, field trips, and even renovations to the physical plant. They may also attract the better teachers, and people of poorer districts may not be able to complain effectively about such inequities. Thus, in some inner city schools, problems with low status, poor self-esteem, broken families, despair, inability to speak the language, and skepticism of the value of schooling, all conspire to make the schools relatively ineffective. Since wealthy suburbs may be under different school boards, and the city core often lacks a solid tax base, these problems get worse as time goes on. Such schools have little pride, little of the latest technology, and few outstanding graduates to any kind of post-secondary institution other than the local prison. Some have relatively few graduates of any kind, and some become focal points and breeding grounds for crime, substance abuse, and yet another despairing generation. It is important to note that although such problems are often complicated by the fact that particular ethnic or racial groups may dominate the inner city, these difficulties are social and economic, and have nothing to do with race, though in some cases official reluctance to address them might.

Busing students to and from the inner core was once seen as the panacea for such problems, and it did focus the attention of uncaring suburbia for a while and was an interesting social experiment, but the experience has shown that this does not in itself solve the real problems, and it is now generally recognized to have been inappropriate. This seems to be an instance where only the centralizing of control and the funding of education over much broader regions can spread out the tax base enough to equalize facilities and salaries. That, and a broad-scale injection of private funds may have some potential to improve such situations, but these are long-term problems and will not go away soon--there is no quick fix for complex problems.

In this instance as well, there is pressure to find technological solutions to social inequities, but it must be appreciated that neither money nor technique alone will solve human problems; it takes people motivated by an ethical compassion, love, and a desire to break the cycle of poverty. On the other hand, if the fourth civilization's information industries have a sufficiently high demand for workers, they may only be able to get them from the thus-far neglected inner city schools. Thus the cycle might also be broken by economic pragmatism.

Another fairness question has to do with ability. As mentioned earlier, and notwithstanding socialist doctrine, it is readily observed in real classrooms that not all people of a given age have equal ability to learn. Since training will continue to be important and education will likely make a comeback--with either or both becoming more necessary for job holders--there is a distinct possibility for the creation of new and very sharp class distinctions in the future. For instance, one could worry that if the Metalibrary came into being, the 10 percent or so who were sufficiently well-learned to use it effectively would have the potential to control it, even to the point of denying its use to those they deemed unfit. On the other hand,

391

Page 392: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

with the proto-Metalibrary now known as the Internet/World Wide Web, such trends do not appear to be very evident.

One possibly longer term alternative to such a class structure is to find technological fixes for the learnability problem--drugs or electronic implants that erase the advantage of the more able by raising everyone's ability. In some ways, the latter of these especially seems like a rather inhuman solution, for it appears to make cyborgs of all, but if the alternative is a meritocracy or dictatorship of the learned, there may be those who will prefer to become part machine instead. Yet another possibility with problematic overtones is that genetic selection could be employed to change the next generations and make them more able. Such eugenics programs are still closely associated with fascism and would not likely be well received in the West. Indeed, there are more frightening alternatives still, for there will always be demagogues who wish to initiate a neo-Nazism based on hatred of the less able, and propose a new "final solution". These dangers are as real as the lack of resolve by society to solve the problems of educational and other inequities in real and lasting ways. Whether such a resolve will ever come about or be effective is yet to be seen.

Finally, the premise of public schooling is that there is a shared set of fundamental values that society has the duty to transmit to the next generation. As long as North American society was viewed as a melting pot with a homogeneous result--one that presupposed an essentially British view of law, justice and civilization, and assent given to a Judeo-Christian moral background, public schooling was workable and generally acceptable. However, in a multicultural environment that presupposes no absolutes of culture or morality, each group would appear to have an equally legitimate right to demand either that the schools respect its ethnic or religious traditions or to insist that it have its own schools in order to survive.

Thus, some religious groups (often including Christians) find that they cannot tolerate a school or university system operated on principles antithetical to their existence, so they set up their own schools. Others do the same for linguistic, cultural, and religious reasons. Such efforts result in fragmentation, and mitigate against the long-term survival of a recognizable uniformity of culture.

Is there a short-term way out of such a dilemma? Short of a new totalitarianism, there is probably not, for even using the Metalibrary for much learning may be potentially more fragmenting than unifying. Indeed, it will almost certainly be used by some at first to promote industrial paradigms such as further fragmentation and isolation and only later be seen to enable something better.

In the long term, the very existence of the fourth civilization will mean that a new consensus has been reached, and a new stability may well come to the school system along with it. But the shape of moral/ethical and societal consensus is still very much up for grabs in the marketplace of ideas, and it is not now possible to confidently predict a stable or unified immediate future for North America's schools and universities.

Is There a Right to Learn?

392

Page 393: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

At first, the answer to this question may seem to be an obvious and unqualified "yes". Everyone must learn certain basic techniques and background context to function in society. But as some of the above discussion indicates, it may be difficult to determine how much each individual has a right to learn, and there are subsidiary questions:

o Is there an obligation on the part of every person to learn? o Does any right and obligation to learn extend to the provision and forced

acceptance of twelve years of schooling? o Does it extend, as asked above, to a fundamental right to become equal in

ability by technological means? ...to be born equal in the first place by genetic selection or manipulation?

o What limit, if any, is there on the obligation of society to provide training and offer education, and at what point do both become the individual's responsibility to society?

o If twelve years of schooling produces an inept, illiterate, and ignorant graduate, who is responsible? Is it the parents', for passing on a poor genetic heritage or providing an anti-education atmosphere; or the schools' for not overcoming the inability or lack of interest; or is it society's in some general way? On the other hand, is it no one's fault but the student's, or perhaps no one's at all?

o Is there a right to be educated in one's own moral, religious, or cultural heritage, or is there a right and duty to become part of that of the historical majority in whatever nation one finds oneself living? Or, is there a correct mix of rights and obligations in this connection?

In the increasingly litigious society of North America, these questions need to be phrased in terms of who shall the defendants be in the learning malpractice suit. For that matter, who should the plaintiff be--the student, the parents, or the employer or society upon whom the student is eventually inflicted?

Over the longer term suppose that very capable artificially intelligent artifacts were built. Would they have a right to training because they are able? Would they have more such right than an incapable human student? More seriously yet, would the ability to receive training imply understanding? If so, would it imply also the right to be educated? If so, could it be taught aesthetics? etiquette? morals? Do history, sociology, or human society have any meaning for such a device? The answers are not simple; seeking them forces one to go back to the questions of what it means to be alive or to be human--and the answers shed very little light on the problem of less able humans.

As previously mentioned, there is here much potential for social troubles, up to and including violence; the question of what it means to be human is one whose answer must be universally accepted in the ethical consensus, or the cost in misery and human lives could once again be great.

Is Learning Sexually Biased?

393

Page 394: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This is another flashpoint question--one that may well have as many answers as there are students or teachers. The author recalls one occasion on which an inner city school teacher from another country held forth at length during a conference on the subject of the inability of women to learn mathematics. He cited the fact that in many years of teaching, no female student had ever taken his analysis (pre-calculus) course. When informed by the author that his own two classes in the same subject were at that very moment overwhelmingly female (and had been for years), he reacted with disbelief.

In many cultures, women have been regarded as ineducable. They were routinely and systematically denied a variety of types of education even in the nineteenth century Western industrialized nations, and this is still the case in many parts of the world.

Some authors claim that North American teachers in all grades still give most of their attention to boys--either because they ask for it more often and more effectively, or because of a built-in cultural bias of their own. On the other hand, it may easily be observed in most high school graduating classes that majority of graduands are female, and this is overwhelmingly so of the valedictorians and other medal winners. By the late nineties, women outnumbered men in Canadian universities by nearly two-to-one. If this latter point were the criterion by which to judge, it would appear schools were at this point heavily biased in favour of female students. Since the majority of elementary school teachers are women, such a conclusion is not only tempting, but also has a ready explanation (though not necessarily the right one).

Interestingly, however, though women have begun to outnumber men even in highly competitive disciplines such as medicine, they still are a decided minority in the mathematical, computing and information sciences, and to a lesser extent in physics and engineering. Typically, first year calculus has still more women than men, but they all vanish from the discipline by second year. Likewise the small number of women in first year computing courses are seldom seen at the higher levels, even though there are many women in managerial positions in the computing industry.

Why are these things so? Is there systematic discrimination favouring boys in some parts of the schooling experience, and girls in others? Some claim there is, and governments through the 1990s have launched expensive programs to change the outcomes, on the theory that equal numbers of both sexes ought to be successful in each endeavour. However, some other questions about the cause of such observed differences in outcome have not been carefully investigated. Are there some innate differences between the male and female brain that affect what students are capable of learning, or perhaps what they want to learn? Or, on the other hand, are boys and girls culturally conditioned to differing social roles and learning modes by the toys they are given as toddlers, so that they become unlikely ever to develop certain interests? One might suppose, for example, that if a person has never as a child played with construction toys or been encouraged to take things apart and put them back together, he or she could never become an engineer or a physicist. It is certainly reasonable to suppose that if female primary

394

Page 395: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

teachers conveyed a fear of mathematics to young girls, their students would not likely train for any profession needing that discipline.

Answers to such questions have only sometimes been sought, and then have proven elusive. Performing such investigations would be as politically difficult as doing so on the basis of racial differences. This would appear to be one of those areas of educational mythology and policy where much effort and funds have been expended to fix the outcomes of an ill-understood problem.

Is There a Technique for Learning?

Many attempts have been made to describe what happens when a person learns, and how to induce it efficiently. One ancient method of teaching, the Socratic, attempts to draw out of a student the ability to think via a series of questions. A question this technique begs is whether every person has the ability to think at the desired level.

A modern theory, the behaviourist, couches every part of the process in terms of the actual response to stimuli and the altered behaviour patterns observed. There are champions for the lecture method, for classroom demonstration, and for the discovery method. On the other hand, there are critics of all. Teaching has been attempted with large groups and with small, with "lock-step" lectures and with individualized progress, with rigid structure and with none, by dispensing knowledge and by demanding that students discover it. Along with techniques, cognitive theories to explain how learning takes place have also multiplied. However, there is little convincing evidence of the general superiority of any one of these theories or techniques in all situations. Each one of them may be shown to work given the right teacher, student, and subject material. The challenge is to suit the best available method to all three, addressing the whole person through a variety of strategic techniques.

One thing that does seem necessary is to provide the student with not just factual knowledge, but also systematic (and perhaps formal) techniques for doing their own analysis afterwards. For instance, children can learn to read by memorizing vocabulary as whole words, but this method has its limitations, because not every student can memorize very many words, and all eventually run out of capacity. At some point, children have to learn the techniques of phonics so that they can analyze new words in a systematic way without committing to memory each new combination of letters that arises in their reading. Similar comments could be made about mathematics--only so many number facts and formulas can be learned by rote; sooner or later analytical methods have to substitute for memorization.

395

Page 396: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The question of learning effectiveness is compounded by the fact that it is not always easy to measure it. If the object is training, the student can be asked to demonstrate the technique after a suitable period; it is for this reason that there are examinations and theses. If the object is education, it is not clear how the outcome can be measured, for the ability to assess ideas is more than an ordinary technique. Questions of motivation are also difficult to deal with. Some students are motivated for training by the prospect of social status, employment, or approval. But, what makes a person want to learn about ideas, and can such a desire itself be taught? In other words, is there a meta-education that must precede education, and if so, where does it come from and how? It is the very difficulty of answering such questions that makes the task of educational administration discussed earlier so very daunting, and the need to develop reliable techniques for learning so pressing.

If a consensus on the answers to such questions remain elusive after thousands of years of schooling, what prospect is there of discovering them now, say, as part of the artificial intelligence agenda? They are so far a part of the human mystery and will need to be understood much better before any kind of intelligence enhancer or autonomous artificially intelligent device can be constructed.

Summary and Conclusions

The questions in this section have thus far been presented without many suggestions for answers. The hierarchical ethical framework developed in Chapter 3 presents an obligation for all involved in the learning process to work in their mutual interest in order that the learners will become more functional human beings and society might become enriched. This wholistic approach would tend to increase emphasis on educational aspects of learning. A Christian would further suggest a larger obligation to God to become (and to enable others to become) the most able human being with the talent available just in order to serve Him and to express this in service to others. On the other hand, a Marxist might aver that the only aspect of learning worth considering is the extent to which it serves the needs of the society.

But, these motivations for an obligation to learn are idealistic, and there are other agendas. For example, the technocrat might wish either to raise everyone's intelligence or to impose a dictatorship of the most able--whichever seemed to be most efficient. Since such an approach is little concerned with the individual as such, it would likely mean that training would come to be the chief factor in learning, because education, and anything else that might produce a "better" person, might not be regarded as relevant to such a society's needs. Moreover, there are many pressure groups vying to dictate what it means to be that better person. Whose agenda will the student be compelled to follow?

10.5 Education and Technology The purpose of this section is not to examine educational technique in

general, interesting though such a discussion would be. Rather, it is to consider the effect upon the learning process of the use of specific products of technology, and to consider in what direction current and projected technologies may influence or drive institutions of learning.

396

Page 397: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The Purpose of Technology in Learning

It has long been assumed, with some evidence, that if the number of sensory gateways to the learner's mind could be increased, so could the efficiency of the learning process. For example, a lecture on Shakespeare would normally involve verbal and aural skills, but watching his plays as they are acted out would engage the visual as well, and therefore initiate more complex and comprehensive learning. The richest experience would be gained from acting in the play, but this is not an option available to everyone. Perhaps at some point, it may be possible to build an interactive feedback to the Metalibrary that would allow the watcher to become a participant, but this enticing possibility is still very speculative.

Thus, various types of print media and audio-visual materials have been produced for schools over the years in an effort to expand sensory interaction with the lesson being learned, and to reinforce its contents. Administrators often greet such innovations with great enthusiasm, even though in many cases classroom results are inconclusive.

The examples that follow are not to be taken as the sum and substance of the application of technology to the classroom environment, but rather as illustrations of the way in which some of the products of technology have affected it. After all, the object or machine is not itself the learning experience--it is a support for some intended lesson. However, the medium in which the experience is presented does have an important effect, and cannot be completely separated from the motives for using it.

Common Classroom Materials

To meet such ends, charts, maps, posters, and various graphics materials made their way to the walls of the modern elementary school classroom. Such materials become less common as the student moves through the schooling process, and the walls at the higher levels are often rather bare. Various object lessons are also available for "hands-on" experiences in counting, exploring science, social studies, health, life skills, and so on. These can be effective in the hands of a skilled teacher, but care must be taken to ensure that the desired lesson is delivered. Some educational theorists think that unguided exploration can too easily become unfocused play to no particular end. Others hold that unguided exploration is the central method of learning in early childhood and is necessary for most children to learn. In the last three decades, this latter theory has been in vogue twice and gone out of favour both times. It will undoubtedly make another comeback.

Primary classrooms keep counting tokens available as concretions for the abstractions of arithmetic. They also might have students dissect owl pellets to discover rodent skeletons and reinforce lessons on the food chain and life cycle. Secondary schools will have a wide range of scientific and other equipment and universities far more, for they require exacting original research.

There can be little doubt that the wide range of common equipment does make the classroom a more interesting place to be, and that fact alone may justify

397

Page 398: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

its purchase, even in the absence of hard data about its effectiveness. In fact, it is possible to show that discovery methods of learning can be more effective than reading about something in a book and then demonstrating what is known. However, it is not practical to allow the student to personally rediscover the entire body of scientific or other knowledge. Neither is it possible for every school to own a piece of equipment to support each item on the curriculum, so there must be some limitations placed on such methods.

Without some centralized control, moreover, teachers may decide to purchase equipment largely to reinforce personal interests, and this becomes surplus when they move to another school. Many are the rooms filled with unused and obsolete or broken equipment, and few are the budgets that can continue such uncoordinated purchases indefinitely.

With pressures on budgets increasing, many schools are having to turn to parental donations and community fund raising for their equipment purchases. This is forcing them to be more accountable to these new sponsors, and is increasing community ties to the school after a long period of separation. Thus, the ordinary day-to-day technical provision for and operation of the schools is no longer the exclusive domain of their professional administrators, but is once more coming under the closer scrutiny and control of their local constituency. What is more, a greater portion of that constituency has more schooling than ever before, and is both qualified and prepared to ask whether a given piece of equipment or a particular technique is appropriate. Again, availability of information, which in this case has nothing to do with computer access, enables wide cooperation among the interested parties and encourages broad control over purchase decisions.

Slides, Filmstrips, and Movies

That which is too expensive to purchase for the classroom can always be photographed and shown on film. Though still lacking in the ultimate experience of personal participation, such media have the potential to bring techniques and ideas to the classroom from effective teachers, and thus to supplement locally available resources. They have the disadvantage of being inflexible, impossible to question, and subject to rigid scheduling constraints as several classrooms compete for the same material at the same point every year. Since such media may remain unused the rest of the time, and since they require an investment of time, training, and inconvenience on the part of the teacher, their cost-effectiveness is difficult to establish. They also take years to justify their purchase, so school audio-visual centres tend to become filled with 30-year-old material of doubtful relevance but which still makes its dutiful circuit about the district once or twice a term--often to the great hilarity of the students who are subjected to ancient material. Likewise, libraries at all levels, including university ones, can easily become filled with obsolete materials that may physically prevent new arrivals, but that no one has the heart to throw out.

Furthermore, if the message of the film is not immediately reinforced by the teacher, say, using supplementary print media or by requiring some feedback from the students, the use of such technology is likely to be regarded by them as a form

398

Page 399: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

of entertainment rather than as a part of the instructional process. Since such materials are often of a much lower quality than television and arcade entertainment to which students are accustomed, they have difficulty taking the lesson seriously. In addition parents tend to view frequent use of films with suspicion. They are not, therefore, asked to fund such purchases, nor are these made at the school level, for the cost is too high. Since purchase decisions are made centrally, there is additional resistance by classroom teachers to some of this material, and they often turn to media over which they have more control.

Radio and Television

The high hopes that were initially expressed for radio-assisted instruction were later repeated for television. In both cases, broadcast lessons were supposed to revolutionize learning, as school boards established their own transmitters and developed series of lessons that could be taught to an entire district at once. These expectations were followed in both cases by disillusionment. In the case of radio, the lessons suffered by comparison with those offered by a live teacher, who could be seen and talked to, not just heard. Television added the visual dimension, and was a "hotter" medium, but the participation was still relatively passive, the scheduling inflexible, the costs very high, and the return on investment not able to be measured. Moreover, the school system has always had very high inertia with many of its teachers uninterested in changing their ways. Faced with the extra responsibility for scheduling their classes and lessons to suit what was available on educational radio or television, few such teachers went beyond the experimental stage with either, and eventually both disappeared from most classrooms. Moreover, at the university level, neither was ever used extensively outside the faculties of education, so the broadcast media has had little effect on this level of learning.

Videotape and Video Disks

The advent of videotape has revived television as an educational medium to a great extent, for it allows lessons to be given once and recorded, rather than broadcast. Taped lessons can be played at the teacher's convenience and do not require transmission facilities. However, it is not clear that videotape has important advantages over film, except in cost, nor has it been established that students regard it as more important than the home entertainment it so closely resembles. While teachers are already making extensive use of video recordings, it will be some time yet before their impact on learning can be assessed. The potential seems great, but it also did for its two older cousins, so a degree of caution would seem to be in order.

The perils are also great, for videotapes are often made in schools with little regard for copyright law, just as are copies of printed materials. Programs are commonly taped off the air for later classroom showing without asking permission, or copies of commercial products are made and retained in the school for re-use.

399

Page 400: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Those who engage in such practices need to consider carefully what it is they are really teaching their students.

At the university and technical school, the use of television and video is a little different. Lecture scale monitors are now being found useful in classrooms where computing and information retrieval skills are demonstrated, and video also has great potential in the recording and viewing of complex or rare techniques, such as those to which a medical student may need exposure. Such larger institutions also will often have the facilities to make their own materials, and rely far less on those taped from the commercial media.

As the 2000s begin, DVDs are replacing videotape, but their purpose and potential use is similar, and there is no reason to suppose they represent an educational breakthrough, even if they are a technological innovation.

Computers in the Classroom

The latest technological marvel has also been touted, as others before it, as the answer to many learning problems, and judging by the multi-billion dollar sales of hardware and software to schools of all types, there is widespread confidence in the value of this technology to deliver that answer.

At the university level, computers are indispensable to both the research and learning processes. No one who has grown accustomed to the enormous power offered by the simplest word processor would trade it for a stick with graphite on one end and a piece of rubber on the other, or even for a typewriter--if one could be found on a modern campus. Neither would the business faculty want to trade electronic spreadsheets for the paper kind, or go back to the hand-calculated trial balances of pre-computerized accounting courses. Their students will be working in office-like environments after graduation for the most part, so the computer forms an essential component of their training. Programming these machines has also become a discipline of its own, and though not yet very mature as such, has already carved out an important place in the university curriculum. It should be noted, however, that while there is an educational component to some of these activities, for the most part they involve training--somewhat of a departure from the traditional role of the university as repository, transmitter, and generator of ideas. Much of this new business and computing curriculum would once have been thought instead to be the province of the technical school, but such is the power of the new technology to transform society that computing studies has become accepted at the university without its credentials as an academic discipline being questioned.

Similar remarks, to somewhat less effect, could be made of the high school. There also, the computerization of marks gathering, attendance, student records, and timetabling, have all proven important time and money savers in an environment that is severely stressed financially. These schools also all have the advantage of having technically oriented mathematics or science specialists ready to seize upon the machine for the learning of computing or doing computations, and a clientele mature enough to take advantage of such instruction. They usually have appropriate business courses to take advantage of the typical applications packages and train students in their use. On the other hand, teachers in other disciplines have

400

Page 401: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not found them particularly useful as yet, because of a lack of both training and suitable software. Also network access has yet to come into its prime at this level because of the relatively high cost of school infrastructure, and so secondary school computer-use mirrors that at the university, on a reduced scale. In both cases its larger potential for other disciplines is unrealized, and may be for some time.

However, the picture is quite different in the younger grades. There, a variety of uses for the computer have been proposed and tried, but in this context, the computer remains a machine that has not yet found a technique to apply it. There are several reasons for this. The first is that elementary teachers are not always qualified in either mathematics or science and may have little interest in technology that requires technical expertise. The second is that there is little need to study the machine for its own sake at this level, so no programming need be taught. Moreover, computers are not required for computational purposes in elementary school. Programming was for a time advocated by some for use at this level, but it was never clear what usable skills such exercises impart, so this too fell into disfavour. The third is that traditional word processing use is not relevant unless schools consider having primary students learn typing instead of, say, writing--for they would be worse off attempting to apply word processing skills if they could not touch-type. The fourth is that the flood of "educational software" that hit the market in the 1970s and 1980s did not prove to be very useful. As programming for its own sake or as a teaching tool, such material was at first uniformly poor--the result of being written either by teachers with amateur programming skills or by gifted computerists who knew nothing about teaching. The computer language LOGO was once advocated for teaching programming to children, but its implementations were clumsy, and neither teachers nor students were convinced of its value in the instructional process.

Have the billions been wasted? If the testimony of many idle elementary school computers with no one to use them is to be believed, the answer is "yes," at least for many schools.

What went so wrong? The same thing that often does in business, where the computer is also commonly regarded as the solution to a badly run and inefficient operation. Computers cannot, by themselves, solve the problems in an organization; they can only exacerbate them by making them occur faster and by entailing a capital outlay that turns out to have negative return. Schools have been under very heavy criticism of late, and the computer came billed as an easy fix for their difficulties--one that the public and funding agencies were quick to agree to--too quick, for they did not consider whether the solution had the potential to be effective. As in business, it is critically important to have adequately problem-free systems in place before introducing computers, because machines can never by themselves help a badly managed operation. The vague and enthusiastic assumption that computers were the wave of the future, coupled with the usual bandwagon effect, have caused schools to spend enormous sums on these machines with little research done on how they could be used effectively. At this point, few elementary teachers have any clear ideas what to use them for, so unless an elementary school is fortunate enough to have a computer specialist available, the machines may well sit idle. This problem is compounded by the rapid changes in

401

Page 402: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

computing technology, which can render a school's entire inventory of such equipment obsolete in one or two years, and make it cost ineffective to replace much of it.

Some recovery may be possible as computer software becomes easier to use and therefore more accessible to young children. A limited set of word processing skills, some art and music, and certain information searching may yet prove to be valuable; but these applications may arrive too late to avoid having many of the existing computers join other little-used machines from past years on the educational technology scrap heap--at least as far as elementary schools are concerned.

On the other hand, what could be right about a decision to use computers in elementary schools? In a word--the Metalibrary. If a school can afford the infrastructure, the opportunity to perform and present research using a world wide data store is an educational key to unlock the techniques of the future for today's students. Used in this way, networked computers have enormous potential to enable even very young students to obtain the very life skills that will be required in the information society. It may be some time before the actual data available on the system is complete, reliable, and easily accessible, but the Internet of the late 1990s is at least a primitive beginning, and a well-educated teacher can assist the students to sift it for relevance.

Teaching Machines

Various audio-visual and print media have been combined in a number of attempts over the years to build machines that could automate some portion of the learning process. These have included hand-held wands touched to metal studs through holes in question cards that lighted or rang a bell when the stud for the correct answer was touched. Later, there were slide sets keyed to experiments or post-tests, high school and university language labs, and in more recent years, various "drill-until-it-kills" software packages, often in the form of computer games. Recent attempts involve multimedia integration of computers with videotape or optical disk (CD-ROMs and DVDs) to provide both textual and graphical lessons based on a very large database and with multiple paths through the material depending on the student's responses. While this technology is not widely available as yet, it probably will be in the near future. If it is used, it apparently has the potential to reduce labour costs somewhat, but also to increase capital ones dramatically. Like all other such technologies, it will have to prove its worth, and this may not be easy; thus far machinery has not done well in the classroom. Moreover, there are few meta-techniques of proven worth for evaluating the process of learning, and in the absence of convincing evidence of their worth, complex machines are unlikely to receive a warm welcome from many teachers, particularly at the lower grades. Rather than struggle with such devices in their own classrooms, they might prefer to wait for the day when interactive multimedia lessons are available prepackaged from the Metalibrary.

School jurisdictions that welcome these machines so enthusiastically that they replace human teachers on a large scale--as a few have attempted--may soon

402

Page 403: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

realize that it is untried and unproven technology. Heavy commitments to the unknown will be hailed as visionary if they succeed, and exorciated as foolishly shortsighted if they do not. Unfortunately, it is real human beings who are being experimented with, not just techniques, and this raises the stakes uncomfortably high for such commitments. If the earlier experiences are any guide, the new teaching machines ought to provoke a reaction of extreme caution. History would suggest they might instead be met instead with wild enthusiasm and high levels of spending.

Summary

The effect of these products of technologies used in modern schools and universities has been mixed. It is difficult to discover whether it has improved the efficiency of the learning process, or whether the continuing problems of learning institutions would be worse without it. Clearly, a better technique for measuring the effects is needed, and so are more carefully defined goals for their use. Methods will also have to be found to ensure that the use of such hardware in the classroom does not exacerbate socioeconomic differences, for some schools can afford it, and some cannot.

As observed at the beginning of the section, these are only examples of the use of equipment, and this discussion does not encompass all of the term "technology." Indeed, if the extension to "technique" suggested in Chapter 2 is used, one must include methods of administration, classroom management, school organization, and all the quantifiable methods employed directly or indirectly in specific schooling or general learning activities. While new technologies and paradigms of the information age affect all these things, there is insufficient space here to consider them in detail. Interested readers are encouraged to research further such specific topics. It is also important to ask whether young people ought to be taught by machines or by role-model adults, and the answer to that question may determine whether much more, if any, of the learning process will be experienced through machines.

10.6 Schooling in the Fourth Civilization There are other factors influencing schooling, and it is time now to consider

the effect of major new technological revolutions on the organized school system. If the specific machines discussed in the last section have had mixed and ambiguous effects on schooling, the same cannot be said of the societal changes being driven by the major technological revolutions discussed earlier in this book. Organized schooling did not exist at all in hunter-gatherer societies, and was an individual or small group affair arranged directly with the tutor in agrarian ones. During this time it became possible to divert surplus production to the systematic maintenance of scholars who could spend their time generating and examining ideas. The greater the prosperity, the more such people could be afforded, and thus the university came into being, and was an important fixture before other types of institutionalized schooling existed. Indeed, part of being a member of the elite ruling class came to mean either having an education, or having an educated advisor available, but

403

Page 404: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

there was no motivation even to teach the general population how to read, for they had little use to which to put such skills.

It was only with the economic and social demands for the schooled labour force of the industrial age that it became necessary to organize grade school and technical training on a widespread, even universal basis. As techniques became progressively more sophisticated, so did requirements for training in their use. Gradually, higher and higher levels of schooling became necessary in order to function effectively in the society. First grade school, then secondary school became all but compulsory, and college began to have a similar imperative by the close of this period. At the same time, education became, like many other enterprises, far too large for any but the state to organize and control. However, industrial age assumptions that drove learning to become mass training in technique, and all but obliterated education in the process, are no longer valid.

To consider what changes might take place in the next civilization, it is important to examine the potential effect on learning of all four of the major modern technological revolutions.

The Computer and Information Revolution

Aspects of the effects of this have been discussed in Chapter 4 and in this chapter. On the one hand, the reception in classrooms of computers themselves has been mixed, and they have yet to have practical uses established in the lower grades. On the other, the information they make available so universally must eventually change learning dramatically even if only in curriculum. Much more emphasis will be placed on communications skills and broad techniques--including those of information--and on ideas, because far less time will be required to develop deep, narrow specialists, since these will not need to retain as much information in their own minds.

This new emphasis will, among other things, involve teaching students to use terminals to gain access to data bases, and ultimately, the Metalibrary. It seems much less certain that most of them will ever need to know how to program the machines, or that they will need to learn how to use many business applications, especially in the younger grades, but widespread use of word processing causes a new emphasis on typing skills at a younger age.

In an earlier chapter, it was remarked that the Metalibrary had certain potentials to become a universal teacher, storing and reproducing by student need and demand lessons on every subject and at any level. Perhaps a live teacher could be simulated, and so could the ability to answer questions interactively. One could even claim that schools at all levels as they are now known are already obsolete, and that machines will eventually suffice for all learning. This might sometimes be the case for adults engaged in continuing training, for they need only to add new techniques to an existing background of general knowledge. They usually already know how to do this and are interested in achieving training quickly and efficiently--not jumping through a series of arbitrary hoops established by a school to flesh out its programs and provide further reasons for existence. Such incremental skills may

404

Page 405: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

be learned individually and by machine to a great extent, though it might be some time before this method becomes common, much less universal.

However, the obtaining of essential background knowledge and cultural context as a child is a different matter. Here, the learner is finding out what it means to be a human being and how to be a part of the culture. However attractive teaching machines may be, they are not role models, for they have not experienced the culture, lived in it, observed it, known new life, cried over death, and pieced together the memories of a typical human being by living them out one day at a time. Even if the Metalibrary were to have available the whole vast store of facts, it would still be something altogether different from a human being. While it may be possible to obtain facts and background information from a Metalibrary, it is questionable whether it is possible to learn how to be a functioning human being from a machine.

The same objections could be made, say, of an ambulatory artificially intelligent (AI) device built to look roughly human--even if it were smarter, faster, and more capable in every way than a human. Unless it were possible to certify that such constructs are identically human, it seems inadvisable to turn over to them the responsibility of teaching children what it means to be human, for they lack the capacity to understand and to model the role they are supposedly teaching, and these are the most important aspects of the learning process. Unless the machine had understanding and intentionality, it could scarcely teach what either of these meant.

A similar reservation could be held when it comes to education in general. The entertainment, creation, and evaluation of ideas is a distinctly human activity, for ideas are held and examined within the context of a person's total cultural and world views. There is no reason to believe at this point that a machine can be provided with anything resembling a human world view. If it were other than exactly human, then it would either not be capable of sharing the human commonality of culture, experience, and world view, or it would be able to have a distinct non-human one of its own--perhaps in common with other machines. It ought not be expected that a non-human device would share much, if any, of the human commonality even if it could be regarded as intelligent in a meaningful sense and even if it could initially be given much (all) human knowledge. What is more, no such device ought to be expected to have human interests in mind--if it can be said to have a mind--but rather its own interests, and these are unlikely to include teaching human children to be the best they can be in order to advance the human race.

Thus, at all levels, the education of humans in culture and ideas probably ought to be undertaken by human beings, rather than by machines, even if some training may be done by machines, and even if there may be short-term economic benefits to replacing teachers by such devices. The need to be distinctively human has a higher priority than the need to save money.

If these arguments prevail, what would the effect on schooling be from the information revolution alone? Elementary schools would show little change in the first grades, and there might be some use of teaching machines and later Metalibrary terminals in the higher ones. Secondary schools might split into streams

405

Page 406: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

emphasizing education on the one hand and training on the other, with teaching machines playing a more important role in the latter. Universities could consider going back to their original business of education in ideas and not directly use teaching machines very much at all, though they would use computers even more, but technical institutes, trade schools, and community schools could use such devices extensively.

On the other hand, proponents of using technology in learning have always been persuasive with both the public and the educational hierarchy, and the possibility that all learning will actually come for a time to be mechanized in the name of efficiency and lower cost cannot be completely discounted. Since such a transition, even if only partly achieved, would be extraordinarily expensive, it would also add weight to an earlier suggestion that more of the funding would have to come from the private sector. The great initial capital outlay required would also give such an experiment a life of its own and a necessity to succeed that would in itself fuel demand to see it through to completion, regardless of whether it could be shown to be effective. Moreover, private funding would imply private objectives, and there may be more likely to include training than education, so be more likely to use machines in the process. Indeed, the university that wished to be a place of ideas might find that no one was willing to provide funding for such endeavours.

The Effect of the Second Industrial Revolution

The advent of large-scale robotization of many manufacturing processes, and widespread use of efficient office machines will likely continue to obliterate many jobs and create others, with the new ones tending to be either more technical or more service oriented. Up to a point, the computing industry will continue to have very large personnel needs, though computers will eventually be utilized in much of their own design, manufacturing, and programming. Many field engineers and technically trained construction workers will be required for new habitat creation and any expansion off planet. After all, robots have to be much more complex and mobile to be useful on a construction site than inside a factory. Other people will be employed in the biochemical and pharmaceutical industries.

Since, as earlier observed, new human workers in such fields can only be drawn from among those who once would have been content to leave school early and take a low-skill factory job, there will have to be a much larger and more effective participation by children on the training side of schooling, and for a longer time. At the same time, the service sector, and knowledge-related and other technical industries will all expand, but these changes will create a sellers' market only for those with the appropriate skills. There might also be more people with the time, inclination, and need for an education in ideas, and more older workers who must return to the learning process either for retraining or for an education. These trends would seem to indicate that a larger percentage of the population at all ages will be involved in formal learning in the future. Since not all of this activity will ever be mechanized, even if the full Metalibrary becomes a reality, the result of these workforce realignments alone is likely to be an increased demand for both training and educational facilities for the indefinite future, though not necessarily an

406

Page 407: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

increase in the number of teachers, because of the decline in the number of children.

The Intelligence Revolution

The effects of AI research on learning are very hard to guess. If the most optimistic scenarios prove to be accurate, there are two ways in which the success of AI efforts could render moot the entire question of humans learning from humans. On the one hand, if AI devices are built that are faster and more knowledgeable than humans, and in the unlikely event that they are also capable of autonomous decision making, then they might deem it to be in their best interests to dispense with the human race entirely.

On the other hand, if partially programmable intelligence-enhancing devices like the PIEA are built, the factual part of learning could take place through a simple electronic transmission or through the addition of a new ROM (see Chapter 6). A practicum could then follow to allow the skills transmitted to be experienced, but on the whole, little interaction with human teachers would be necessary for factual learning. It is not clear whether ideas could ever be handled in the same way as facts and skills, for if it is possible to electronically represent ideas and the meta-idea of evaluating them, then AI might already have been achieved, and these methods might be unnecessary.

There is a certain efficiency-related attraction to such approaches as this one, though there is likewise an opportunity for the truly comprehensive statist to plan the production of trained people as never before. If the state determined it needed 5000 doctors, it need only produce 5000 sets of physician ROMs and sell them to or implant them in selected individuals. If it wanted a million soldiers, it would do likewise with a ROM programmed with efficient killing routines. These last considerations ought to give pause to the idea of taking some of these technologies to their logical conclusions, however attractive some of them may seem to be on grounds of efficiency.

A third possibility is that intelligence may become somewhat enhancible via implants, drugs, or genetic engineering, but that current teaching methods would survive. Education and training would then take on a somewhat different character, but would be natural and straightforward extensions of what is being done now.

All three of these possibilities are interesting, but speculative, for as previously indicated, the nature of any achievements for all the hard work in AI is not yet clear. In any event, dramatic changes in learning due to AI work may be some time in coming; the fourth of the technical revolution has more immediate probable implications.

Effects of the Biospace Revolution

Many of the changes in medicine will have little direct effect on learning. However, the cumulative result of new life-saving and prolonging techniques, and the outcome of longevity research will almost certainly have the effect of substantially increasing life spans. This factor would lengthen the number of

407

Page 408: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

potential working years, and along with a rapidly changing economy, guarantee a continued strong demand for re-training. Indeed, continuous training on the job so that job holders change with their jobs will probably become the norm. Longer life means more time for ideas as well, and it seems likely that it will result in new pressures on the educational part of the learning system, provided that people will want or be able to continue having or considering new ideas at an advanced age. One result could be a considerable increase in the demand for learning facilities at the university and technical school level.

However, longer life creates population pressures and this, combined with other economic factors, will put very strong downward pressure on the birth rate. This long-term trend is already clear in Western countries. There will continue to be fewer children, fewer schools, and less need for teachers. Since the skills and expertise involved in training and educating adults are different from those involved in teaching children, surplus teachers cannot simply transfer to other levels without themselves retraining. Thus in many jurisdictions the attrition of resignation and retirement may be insufficient to rationalize the greatly reduced demand, and there could be layoffs as well.

Paradoxically, there could be dramatic increases in short-term demand for teachers in newly developing areas (new towns or suburbs). Families with young children, or who are still childless, are highly mobile, and are among the leaders in migration from the city core to the suburbs and other regions for economic purposes. This creates a demand for new facilities in some areas, even while those in others are being closed for lack of use. Moreover, in many parts of North America, a high percentage of the teaching force is close to retirement age and must be replaced over the next few years. Even more important is the fact that in much of the world it is not the transition to the fourth civilization that is underway, but the one to the third. Thus, outside the already industrialized West, the population is still increasing, especially in the cities; it is still very young; and it is still relatively uneducated

All these factors taken together may mean that there is little cause for concern in the overall teacher employment picture in the near term. Teachers will have to scramble from one level to another and from one geographical area or country to another in large numbers to stay in the occupation, and many will decide it is not worth the effort and will find other employment. Such dramatic turnover does present a unique opportunity for standards to be raised and for teaching to become professionalized, but in the midst of such turmoil, it may be that this aspect will not receive much attention.

In the long term, the need for K-12 teachers in the previously industrialized countries might be very much less, even if governments do not impose limitations on births. At the same time, training schools and universities could need far more teachers, and they may obtain these by retraining and re-educating some of the ones they have temporarily placed in the K-12 schools to take care of their short-term boom. In addition, developing parts of the world will need K-12 teachers in great numbers and for a longer time than Western ones, unless arbitrary birth control measures are adapted there. However, this would only create a demand for Western trained teachers if language and culture were not regarded as barriers.

408

Page 409: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Should the habitat-expansion scenario develop to any great extent, the formal learning system may actually expand in absolute terms, even though the K-12 portion eventually seems likely to become a much smaller part of the overall educational picture.

The Overall Picture

Overall trends affecting the size of formal learning systems are mixed, with some factors increasing demand, and some reducing it. The number of trainers in specific techniques will undoubtedly increase, though these too will need constant updating as techniques in all fields continue to change rapidly. The number involved in the education in ideas seems likely to increase as well, but there could eventually be sharp declines in the workforce at the K-12 level. Certainly, there will be very substantial pressure to cut costs here, and this will be the most difficult in which to obtain private sector participation.

One possible means of cutting costs is to move to a more effective utilization of resources by using schools for twelve months instead of nine or ten. In theory this could produce a fifteen percent efficiency improvement. In practice, there would be many difficulties to overcome in making such a change, and great resistance on the part of families and teachers to the potential loss of summer vacations. The future of this oft-proposed (and just as oft disposed of) idea is still cloudy.

Since present schooling practice is highly labour dependent, great cost savings could also come from a substantial reduction in the relative number of teachers, by whatever means. They might in turn respond to this in one of two ways. They could further unionize and refuse to entertain any cuts in staff on the threat of a strike, insisting that staffing levels remain as they are regardless of the use of machines or the number of students. This reaction would be consistent with the economic self-ism and tendency to fragment so prevalent in the late industrial period. It would also promote both the privatization and the automation of education, for strikes by teachers are easily seen by students and parents alike as betrayals, and could both lower teacher status and promote a determination to replace at least some of them at any cost. On the other hand, teachers could, even in the face of a reduction in their numbers, professionalize and attempt to raise their status--something that would take much more courage and foresight, but that would be more in accord with the spirit of the information age.

The trends to more local and participatory forms of government discussed in Chapter 9 will also have a substantial impact on schools at all levels. These ought to mean that more decision making authority is devolved to the local level from the state, and that many individual schools will have far more control over budget and hiring than in the past. Along with greater local control will go greater local supervision, and this may mean higher expectations, and ought also to promote the professional model for teachers.

At the university level, the situation is more complex. At the same time, there is a greater independence, flexibility, and understanding of change. Thus, in theory at least, there is a greater potential to discern these forces and restructure to meet the needs. The potential for this to happen is the subject of the next section.

409

Page 410: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

10.7 The Role of the University Many of the changes discussed here could have a dramatic effect on the

modern university in the long run. The original premise of the university was that it was an educational gathering, in the sense used in this chapter. That is, its special concern was the development, examination, and transmission of ideas. Training in technique was done elsewhere--either on the job, in technical institutes, or as a by-product of some other form of schooling.

The ideal university was free from any constraints of technique or utility and it was free to question any idea, presupposition, or world view; it neither leaned upon nor was very much obligated to produce a specific product for the broader society. It did depend on that society for funds and students, but it was free to go its own way intellectually, even if it attacked the very structure that gave it birth. This "ivory tower" separation of intellectuals from ordinary life was not a bad thing, but a necessary one, for only through a relatively free detachment could objectivity be achieved.

Whether this ideal ever existed apart from theory, even for a short period, is debatable. The first universities were intimately connected with and dependent upon the church. Later, many had mandates deriving from a local ruler, and served the state--if in no other way, by loaning it intellectual prestige. The university has always depended on the broader society to supply it with a cultural context, a collection of scholars, and the resources to carry on its investigations even when there was no economic return. At the same time, the relentless pressure of the search for efficient technique, which has been a hallmark of the industrial age, has gradually re-created the university in a very different image from this original, perhaps never-achieved ideal.

Although some academics still attempt to maintain what they hope is a detached attitude from the broad culture, the university as a whole has gradually adopted the search for technique as its own mandate. Thus, university-trained scientists major in technique. In fact, today they study little else, for philosophical questions about the meaning and legitimacy of their discipline and its place in the whole spectrum of knowledge-gathering activities are of little interest to the person whose whole orientation is the empirical method or the economic survival of the department. The gestalt is one of barely suppressed excitement at the prospect of personally finding out something never before seen or touched; ideas are divorced from the asking of whys about the validity of what is being done and instead are limited to mechanical explanations of empirical data. The metaphysical studies are generally ignored as uninteresting or unimportant, or even dismissed as nonexistent.

At the same time, the prestige of the university has been borrowed for other technical studies, for it has also become the home of computing science, engineering, teaching technique, and the technical study of economics and other social disciplines in a manner that attempts to mimic the methods of the natural sciences. The humanities have also subjected their subject matter to technical analysis, with linguistics becoming more of a science than an art, and research on

410

Page 411: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

literature sometimes tending to concentrate on computerized dissection of the great works to discern the supposed involvement of many hands in the writing of them. Even theology has been invaded by such "higher criticism"--by which is meant a similar technical analysis of the books of the Bible. The fact that such efforts nearly always accomplish little other than to confirm the researchers' presuppositions about disputed authorship and content does not slow such work down. In fact, it increases the opportunities for learned scholarship, for it seems to be possible to develop a pseudo-technique to establish every possible hypothesis about a piece of literature. The older the work, the less likely there is to be any parallel material to corroborate its professed authorship or content, and the more freedom there is for a modern researcher to create and apply such techniques to the desired end.

Most universities have gone much farther with theology--they have dismissed it altogether from the curriculum as an intruder in the domain of technique--this discipline that was cornerstone to the original Western university movement. Theology, for its part, has obliged by removing itself to seminaries and schools of religion that are no longer associated with the unfriendly university, and for the most part, ignoring it altogether.

But theology is not the only embarrassment to the modern university; so is the whole historical and cultural context that gave it birth, and these too are now deprecated if not denigrated. Consequently, courses in Western culture, while they make an occasional reappearance, have been systematically removed from the broad curriculum, along with the study of philosophy and ethics.

Clearly, deconstructive scholarship is on all fronts destructive not only of the historicity, content, and meaning of the work studied, but also of the relevance of the discipline doing the study. Once the subject matter of a group of scholars has been deconstructed to that point, they themselves are easily seen as irrelevant to society and so to the school. If a discipline has no important ideas, why should people study it? If theology, history, philosophy, ethics, and the humanities all likewise have no answers to the meaning questions, why operate a university when technical schools are cheaper, more efficient, and more immediately useful? If students have no idea where there society has come from, how will they decide where to take it?

But, it has become unnecessary for a university graduate to have a nodding acquaintance with the great thinkers and writers of the past; their view is considered inadequate merely because it is old. Also, a technically oriented society cares most about the day-to-day pursuit of what it regards as being practical, functional, and relevant; that is, doing rather than thinking. What matters is the development and analysis of ever more sophisticated technique, and such pursuits are expected to supply their own reasons and meanings. The modern university, by and large, has adapted the technical philosophy that apart from empiricism there is nothing, or at least, there is little of value, but at the same time it no longer questions what constitutes "values" in the first place.

Allan Bloom, himself a philosopher, argues most cogently (The Closing of the American Mind) that North American universities in particular have discarded their formative culture, for a nihilism and relativism in which there are no absolutes, no values, no culture, no religion and no education worthy of the name. He accuses

411

Page 412: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

them of blindly following popular culture and the latest trends in pseudo-intellectualism without pausing to examine the ideas they accept to see if they have any content. In his view, the universities have betrayed their intellectual heritage, debased culture, and are pursuing they know not what. He believes they have cravenly caved in to the nihilistic demands of "student causes" because they no longer had a purpose of their own, and the thing they offer called education has become devalued to the point of worthlessness. Only the domain of the sciences and technologies have escaped the abandonment of academic standards, because only they can measure the outcome of what they propose to do and only they have confidence in what they are doing.

He could have added that since what they primarily do is train in technique, science and engineering faculties cannot be expected to defend the traditional educational domain, or to believe that they have any common cause whatever with the rest of the university or its traditional educational goals. Bloom suggests that of all the humanities, only philosophy is left as the guardian of ideas, and its role has become much like that of a museum keeper, taking students on guided tours through the musty and discredited past of their culture--all the while fearing the wrath of the radical left that controls the university lest they permit their charges to touch anything there, much less evaluate it or embrace it. Any of the older writers whose works can be labelled as racist, sexist, or religious can be banned from the curriculum without further examination for content or validity, and if no such reasons can be discovered, they could always be accused of being irrelevant because of age alone. Not only do these attitudes tend to render the university as irrelevant, they also ensure that the control ideas of the dominant intellectual culture cannot be examined and will not be challenged. Thus, when authors such as Emberly--Zero Tolerance--complain about the systematic politicizing of the university, they may be discussing symptoms rather than causes.

Since it is always possible to discern cultural overtones in the most abstract and philosophical of work, and much of it cannot be understood without that context, it is always possible to bring culturally-based charges against the old writers and find them guilty of failing to support modern causes. Bloom concludes that North American academics have taken the same journey into an unthinking nowhere as their European predecessors before World War II, and are blithely unconcerned with where this nihilism may lead them, for they do not study history any more either. Such trends can be seen in modern fiction as well, for it often writes of the past not by holding up for examination the values and ideas people actually espoused in those times, but by projecting modern ideas and conflicts into characters who almost certainly would never have entertained them.

Bloom has his critics of course, and these believe that he has either misstated or overstated his case. Since he is a philosopher, his lament of the decline of his own discipline and his promotion of its revival could also be viewed as somewhat narrow self-interest. Moreover, his comments on the scientists of academia carry with them the flavour of one who is a distant observer, rather than a personal and professional acquaintance. Others undoubtedly think there is nothing wrong with either nihilism or the casting of the culture adrift from the past, and could easily welcome his observations while rejecting his criticisms.

412

Page 413: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

But like Snow in the early 1960s with his "Two Cultures" critique of academia, he appears to have touched a raw nerve; to have stated what many people had come to believe or perceive even though they had not articulated it. Many academics, in common with the whole culture, have indeed discarded idea examination for technique. They have also separated themselves from the human aspect of their work, that is, from student contact. Retreating into the safety of their tenured sanctums, they have left the work of teaching undergraduates to graduate students and untenured temporary instructors. It has become too easy to redirect the university apparatus that was designed for the process of careful thinking about ideas into the pursuit of ways to make money, and to quote one another in an incestuous circularity that gives an appearance of learned scholarship without substance.

While he may be criticized at many points of detail, the broad thrust of his criticism is factually correct, for the modern university has become a creature of the technique-obsessed industrial age--after all it has only found a niche in the social and technical apparatus. Whether his suggestions about the consequences of all this are appropriate or not is another matter, but there is no denying the fact of intimate relationship between the modern university and modern technology.

This relationship goes beyond the specific disciplines studied by it or ignored by it, for it is also expressed in its ties to the broader society. For example, what Eisenhower first termed the "military-industrial complex" in the early 1950s has become a military-industrial-university axis in the 1980s. As remarked in Chapter 2, a large percentage of the funding for technical research in the university comes from government defense projects. These are sometimes directed to basic science, but their major thrust is often the development of specific military hardware. The U.S. Strategic Defense Initiative (SDI), or "Star Wars" project of the late 1980s drew much comment and criticism, but is typical of much military spending on research, and is not by any means unique. For the sake of the research funds, its agenda was readily adapted by many universities. In such ways, whatever independence the university may have once had, it has come today to be tied very closely to government funding; its ability to pursue knowledge for its own sake has been severely curtailed, and its freedom to speak out largely ceremonial.

New connections are being made all the time to new industries. As economists and professors of commerce have found in joining with colleagues in engineering, physics and chemistry, there is much money to be made in selling consulting expertise, techniques, and products to the broad marketplace. They have been eager to meet such challenges, and the web of connections to outside interests has been woven ever closer in recent years. Their discipline has even been renamed, and is now the study of business; that is, it is now concerned about technique more than it is about people or even social institutions. Questions are occasionally asked by some traditionalists about whether the university is an appropriate location for the study of business technique, but such voices are drowned in the flood of applicants for places in such schools, and this creates a compelling economic argument of its own--it allows some threatened universities to survive what had been a declining enrolment.

413

Page 414: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Biotechnologists have followed suit, and begun marketing the products of their research labs via their own companies or in alliance with existing pharmaceutical firms. Their work too is frequently tailored to the marketplace, and borrows business techniques to enhance their prospects as vendors. Like the members of other disciplines, these are no longer academics in the old sense, trading in ideas; they have become entrepreneurs in generating and selling patents.

All this activity has made university administrators consider whether the institution itself ought to receive a share of the income. Thus, there are starting to be more joint ventures, profit sharing, and quid quo pro arrangements with industry that involve profits returning to the university. Reductions in public funding are increasing the pressure to find other sources of revenue, and business and industry need more than just a tax receipt for their money. It seems, therefore, that the existing research institutions, especially in the sciences, engineering, computing, and business, will be under long-term pressure to become more closely associated with industry all the time. This may be a good thing if it relieves the public purse, but it is sure to enhance the role of technique in the university and push it even more in the direction of training and away from education. After all, privatization of this type could be very hard on those university departments that have no commodities on which they can obtain patents, but whose stock-in-trade remains ideas.

However, as already noted in this chapter, there are other long- term trends pointing to a revival of the latter as well, because less time will need to be taken to learn technical facts, so more is available for a broad consideration of ideas. In addition, the more people with time available to think, the more thinking that could get done. However, there is no guarantee that this will take place, for many people may not want to be confused by ideas. After all,

You can lead a son or daughter to Horace, but you can't make one think.

Thus, while there may be a window of opportunity for the university to revive its traditional role as a forum for the enquiry into ideas, this niche could be preempted by other institutions or vanish altogether.

For example, electronic discussion forums are even now being conducted on the Internet, and are certain to be included in the Metalibrary of the future. These are much more open and free-wheeling than the university lecture hall, and though quantity dilutes quality in this medium, it is impossible for the possessor of a doctorate and chair, say, at Harvard to use paper credentials and position to bully acceptance of ideas upon the other participants. It is possible for a thoughtful janitor to participate with no formal education past the third grade, but with a big reading list. The slogan is "On the Internet, nobody knows you're a dog." It is too soon to determine where this will lead, but it is possible that much larger groups of people will take over the philosophical roles of guardians and evaluators of ideas from the universities and exercise these independently of academia. This would require many changes from the late 1990s version of the Metalibrary called the Internet, for in the latter's news and discussion groups there is often little that passes for rational

414

Page 415: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

argument, and the bullying for politically correct views is cruder and more blatant even than in the universities.

Another candidate to take over some of the university's late industrial role is the new-style corporation that does much of its own training and re-training. Any substantial shift of training in technique to the business sector itself will leave the university without many of its industrial-age clients and groping about for a new identity.

Such trends are not likely to go unnoticed, however, and the universities may attempt to recover some of their traditional function. It is possible to make a case for an immediate and long-lasting return to a very broad form of liberal arts education in the universities, based solely on the observation that the day of the narrowly trained, fact-knowing technical specialist has passed, and that the future belongs to the fact-finding and integrating knowledge worker of much wider interests and adaptability. At any given time, such people could still be regarded as specialists because of the results they produce, but there will be an important sense in which they are actually generalists.

The challenge for the university will be to find new ways to integrate education in ideas with training in technique. Their graduates must become evaluators and potential users of ideas and techniques in general, rather than be wedded to a small selection of both. This argument is even stronger if one concedes to the teaching machines and corporate sector some of the on-going training in specific techniques, but reserves education almost entirely for human teachers, for then the university must either integrate its traditional role back into its agenda or become little more than a small branch of the Metalibrary. This could happen quickly for some institutions who are unable to hire from the shrinking pool of potential computing science professors. There is too much money to be made elsewhere for people with such qualifications to settle in to academia.

How likely is such change? The momentum built up in the industrial age suggests that the trend to specialize in technique at the university will continue and that its relationship with industry will become closer. Information age paradigms, on the other hand, suggest that there will be a renewed need for education as well--one that could possibly be filled by the universities, but will not necessarily be. History seems to suggest that institutions have a tendency to allow their own inertia to resist even inevitable changes, and that not many of them survive radical social alterations. Whether this will be true of the university remains to be seen. Perhaps some of them will die slow and painful deaths, or become absorbed by the private sector, and new ones will be established that suit the new paradigms. One possibility is that universities will become private umbrella consortia of academic professionals offering their services electronically and with no physical campuses at all. An easy prediction is that the traditional tenure system will change radically or even vanish, for the universities will have to have flexibility in order to compete in a world characterized by rapid change. Moreover, their academics will have to involve themselves more personally with students if these institutions are to remain in the idea business at all.

It is also worth observing that the role of many private universities is in some doubt. While on the one hand, there is pressure to increase funding from private

415

Page 416: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

sources, there is also the tendency to employ the same "star system" that applies to sports and entertainment figures--established institutions with gilt-edge reputations receive the new private funding and the best students, while all others suffer cuts in public money and attendance. In addition, many private colleges and universities have merged or folded because they were unable to maintain a distinctive character sufficiently great to allow them a niche, and they were equally unable to compete on general terms. It seems likely that this trend will continue. Most of the smaller institutions cannot hope to compete with the larger ones in changing times, unless they have a clear distinctiveness that extends to their student population and to their constituency--including funding. In addition, there is little for small schools to gain by seeking support from the government, but they may have to seek it from the private sector.

For example, there are a large number of church-related colleges and universities in North America. To the extent that these maintain their historical ties to their founding constituencies and simultaneously offer sound academic instruction, they have the opportunity to grow and prosper. But if they sacrifice either scholarship or their traditional orthodoxy, they will lose their reason for being in short order. Identity problems in such cases cannot be kept secret in the information age; such an institution can vanish from the scene almost overnight if its constituency is caused to lose faith in it. The day when a distinctively religious school like Harvard could evolve in genteel fashion into a secular one without anyone taking notice has now passed. At the same time, if the world view of any university, whether public or private, remains mired in an inflexible pattern that relates to a bygone culture so that it has no basis to speak to the new civilization, it too will fail. Thus, the church-based school is faced with the task of remaining distinctive and separate in its world view, yet becoming able to speak relevantly to the new one in the culture around it. This is an especially daunting task, and the number of such schools that survive in recognizable form to make an impact on the fourth civilization may well be few indeed.

This need for a distinctive identity is not unique to religious or even private institutions. Like schools at all levels, and any other cohesive organization, universities must have an organizational purpose believed in and promoted by its members, and a sense of shared pride in its accomplishments. There are many strains on both of these, and only the schools that can maintain both will survive--even the currently public ones will be in trouble if they fail to convince their constituencies of their need for them. They will also be in trouble if they fail to flexibly re-organize to meet the new challenges and demands upon them, or if they discard altogether the old role of idea-brokers for the patenting of techniques.

In the long run, information age paradigms would suggest that the educational sector will become like the business sector in its new identity--more entrepreneurial, more accountable, and more people-oriented. There may be a greater realization that the people involved are the enterprise, and more teachers will actually own their place of employment. There may also be a greater emphasis on establishing a long-lasting relationship between teachers and students as they wrestle together with ideas. Some of these integrative ideas are discussed in a more

416

Page 417: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

comprehensive form in Chapter 12. In the meanwhile, the following conclusion is offered:

The proper task of the university is to analyse, integrate, and transmit ideas.

10.8 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Education and training can be thought of as distinct subsets of the whole learning process, and may take place either as part of a formal schooling, or outside it. Training can be largely associated with technique, and education largely with ideas. They exist together as parts of integrated packages, but different cultures and professions tend to emphasize one, often to the exclusion of the other. One of the challenges of the next civilization will be to integrate the two, particularly in the universities.

The content of school curricula will be broadened and somewhat de-specialized to meet the needs of the next civilization, as it will depend more on ideas (education) and somewhat less on specific technique (training). People will have to acquire the meta-techniques of information retrieval and retrainability in order to hold jobs in the future.

Issues of importance in the process of learning also include:

o Why is learning undertaken?o Who should control education?o What is the status of teachers?o Who should pay for education and training?o Is there a right to learn?o Is learning sexually biased?o Is there a technique of learning?

Technology has an effect on learning by dictating a new curriculum to meet the new life-needs, by requiring learning to be organized once society reaches a certain complexity, and by forcing it to examine itself for effective teaching and learning techniques. The actual machines employed in the process have had a mixed reception and doubtful results, but each new wave of machines is greeted and purchased more enthusiastically than the last. The various technological revolutions now in progress have several potentials to change the formal schooling system, as some may increase the demand for teachers, and some may reduce it. If education for life skills in a cultural context on the one hand and for the ability to assess ideas on the other is to be regarded as uniquely human, it should not become the province of machines, even if most training does.

Finally, the role of the university in the future is in some doubt. It may continue to be wedded to current technology and even more fully integrated into

417

Page 418: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the state and economy to serve those interests, or it may revive its old activities as the developer and guardian of ideas, allowing philosophy, for example, to make a comeback.

In any event, adults will have more time for learning, and more need of it. Both education and training will tend to become lifelong and continuous pursuits rather than being confined to specific years and schooling experiences. These trends, as well as the new population demographics, are certain to force major changes in the philosophy and methodology of the teaching/learning process, especially where this is formally undertaken in schools. The Metalibrary may also come to play an important role in training and in idea exchange, but there seems to be great importance to retaining human teachers for many of the learning experiences as role models of what it means to be human--at least for the education of children.

Funding constraints and demand may simultaneously cause private sector involvement in education to grow, and the relative share of government control to decline accordingly; this trend could either level out or increase current socioeconomic gaps in education, depending on the response of government.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. Argue convincingly that all present-day forms of schooling are obsolete and that the entire process can and should be mechanized as soon as possible. Or, argue that machines are of little value in schooling, and that all of it should remain in the hands of human teachers.

2. As an alternative to the extremes suggested in question #1, attempt to propose a reasonable balance between the two. What things can be automated and what things must remain in the hands of human teachers?.

3. The author suggests that the private sector will become more involved in learning in the future. Either support this argument in detail, or attempt to refute it and to show that the state is the only institution qualified to control education and training.

4. Research and discuss some or all of the major theories of learning. In addition to those mentioned in the first section of this chapter, some modern ones include the Gagne-Briggs, Algo-Heuristic, Structural Learning, Inquiry Teaching, Component Display, Elaboration, Motivational, and the method of Complements and Contrasts. Compare some or all of these with each other and/or with the Socratic method, or with the discovery approach.

5. Research and discuss the origin and development of compulsory schooling in Western nations. What important differences are there between the European and North American approaches?

6. What differences are there between European and North American universities? Consider curricula, techniques, training versus education, and the status of teachers.

7. "North American schools are doing a good job in preparing students to become functional adults and useful workers." Attack or defend this thesis.

418

Page 419: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

8. The author argues that the school system must become more people- and idea-oriented. Either argue that this is not so, or detail specific changes that would have to be made to the present schooling system to achieve this.

9. Who should control schooling, and why?10. Who should fund schooling, and why?

11. "Ethical principles and cultural values must be part of education." Argue for or against this thesis.

12. The author argues strongly that the day of industrial-age style narrow specialist has passed and that of the knowledge worker or generalist has arrived. Develop this idea further supporting it with research into current trends and other authors who make the same claim.

13. Refute the thesis in the previous question, citing convincing authorities and research to make your case.

14. Should teachers (a) unionize or (b) professionalize in order to best advance their economic and political interests?

15. Is learning fair? Should it be? If so, how can it be made fair?16. What should the K-12 school of the future be like? Sketch out your ideal,

and then propose a way to pay for it. Alternately, answer this question for the university.

17. Which of the following should be part of the mandatory K-12 curriculum and in what form? Why or why not? (a) personal finance, (b) business principles, (c) health and hygiene, (d) sex education, (e) ethics and morality, (f) politics, (g) religion. Alternately, answer this question for the university.

18. In which direction ought the university go--toward training, toward education, or toward some mix of the two? How should the goal you prefer be achieved? How do tenure, the academic ranking system and student/professor contact fit your model? How does research?

19. Make a list of what you regard as the ten most important books of all time and defend in detail your choice of each as an important part of every education. At what level should these books be a part of the schooling experience? Are there books or classes of books that ought not be part of the schooling experience? Why or why not?

20. Bloom argues that the North American university has discarded its traditional role as the guardian, expositor, and evaluator of ideas. Do you agree? Why or why not? Be sure to read him first.

21. The author argues, as does Bloom, that there are absolute principles, including moral ones, that must be a part of every education, and that all cultures are not equal, but some are better than others. They also argue that education can never be entirely value free. Support these arguments by references to the specific principles that underlie democracy and demonstrate why such things must be taught as absolutes.

22. Argue on the contrary that no cultural or moral absolutes exist, but that society can still exist even with no such commonality. Specifically argue that education can and must be entirely value free, except for the dispassionate

419

Page 420: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

examination of all values as equals. Argue that democracy can still survive even when its principles are not held as absolutes.

23. The author argues that "who teaches" is more important than teaching technique and that is in turn more important than curriculum. Support this in general, but show that there may be specific exceptions.

24. The author argues for a wholistic approach to education as superior to the strictly behavioural, cognitive, discovery, or humanistic. Refute this argument in favour of one of these approaches or some other.

Some Ethical and Other Issues For Teachers

25. You have promised your twenty-four biology students a field trip to the local aquarium as part of the current unit; indeed you believe it to be essential to what you are trying to teach. What do you do if (a) the school board cancels funding for field trips? or (b) some parents refuse to allow their children to participate in "such frivolity"? (c) your union orders you to stop all such activities to protest slow negotiations with the board over a new contract? (c) your orders you to stop all such activities to protest new social policies of the provincial government?

26. A student of the opposite sex comes to your counselling office and unfolds a tale of academic and personal woe that has left him (or her) in a state of near despair. Feeling loveless, deserted, alone, and a complete failure, the student is nearly hysterical and inconsolable. As part of your counselling and role-modelling of humanity, do you hug him (her)? What criteria do you use to decide? Does it matter whether the teacher or the student is male? Why?

27. You are a high school physics teacher and a young lady (age 17) comes to you who wishes to sign up for your course because she wants a career as an aeronautics engineer. Her parents are adamantly opposed and demand she take the child-care course instead, stating "She's just going to get married". All efforts to convince them otherwise have failed. The student wishes your help to deceive her parents and take your course without telling them. What should you do, and why?

28. Reverse the scenario in the above question. The student in question is being pressured by her parents to take physics. She is quite able to do so, but wants to take the child care class, because she rejects her parents' ambition that she become an engineer like them and wants to get married and have children, regarding that as a higher goal in life than a career. Do you help her to get the course she wants despite her parents? Is your conclusion the same as in the previous question? Why or why not?

29. You are a school administrator with enough funds to set up three regular classrooms for standard courses and reduce class size by 10% throughout your school. Alternatively you could set up two special classes--one for slower students who need extra help to catch up to the others, and one for better students to have an opportunity to excel. This option will only reduce general class size by 5%. Which do you do, and why?

30. You are the same administrator with a choice between hiring one new teacher, and purchasing much needed gym equipment and some computers. Which do you pick and why?

420

Page 421: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

31. A student in her high school graduating year confides in you that she is pregnant and plans to leave town to move away and live with her boyfriend, abandoning her education. You are unable to convince her otherwise. Do you inform her parents, breaking the confidence? Does it make any difference if you are (a) her friend and classmate, (b) one of her subject teachers, (c) her school counsellor, (d) the school principal, (e) her social worker, (f) the pastor of her church?

32. Repeat the analysis in the previous question, but this time what has been confided in you is (a) a recent incident of sexual abuse, (b) a many years old incident of sexual abuse, (c) a criminal act by her parents, (d) a perceived derogatory remark by another teacher, (d) perceived unfairness in marking or other treatment by another teacher, (e) a racial bias on her parents' part, (f) religious discrimination by another teacher.

33. You become aware because of frequent student comments and complaints that one of your fellow teachers is very strongly pressuring students to adopt a particular philosophical view. Those who disagree are shouted down in class, have their marks reduced, or are simply ignored or ostracized in class. What should you do about this? Does it make any difference whether the philosophy is (a) Christianity, (b) an aboriginal religion, (c) an oriental religion, (d) new age, (e) political liberalism, (f) atheism, (g) feminism, (h) Marxism.

34. An election campaign is in progress, and the teachers' union has taken issue with the present government and is strongly supporting the opposition party. Is it legitimate for the teachers to (a) send some of the members' dues to the campaign headquarters of their favoured party, (b) wear political buttons and slogans to class, (c) proselytize their students for their cause, (d) send literature home to the parents with their students?

35. You are a department head who requires one new Math/Physics teacher and have a choice between one who could teach both and has all the correct qualifications on paper, and a second who is certified only for Physics but is more energetic, personable and could sponsor several extracurricular activities. Which do you pick and why?

36. You are a school administrator, and it is traditional for administrators in your jurisdiction not to teach classes themselves. One of your teachers puts it to you strongly that as a leader in education you have a responsibility to role-model the activity you are leading and so should teach at least one class. What should be done? Your discussion should include an examination of possible conflict of interest, union opposition and time pressures on your "real" job.

37. Research an existing code of ethics for teachers or propose one of your own. Examine it point by point and give reasons for or against the inclusion of each item. Be careful to analyse items for the reasons they are present--occasionally they are there for political or power purposes rather than ethical ones.

38. The argument is often made that some or all of the schools in a given public school district ought to specialize in some fashion. Thus a variety of special schools have been established--for the fine arts, emphasizing technology, committed to the fundamental skills, or language immersion. Either argue for such models, or argue that the neighbourhood school ought to provide exactly the same programs for all students in the area.

421

Page 422: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

39. Should ideas that the majority culture deems offensive be examined at all in the university, or should they be brought up only in the context of condemnation? Does it matter if the ideas are philosophical, political, economic, racial, or religious?

40. Survey a the class in "Mathematics for Elementary School Teachers" at your university. What is the male/female distribution? Ask if the students are afraid of mathematics or dislike it, and why. If time permits, compare with the Calculus III course. What conclusions do you draw about sex differences?

Bibliography

Barlow, Daniel Lenox. Educational Psychology: The Teaching-Learning Process. Chicago: Moody Press, 1985

Barrow, Robin. Radical Education. Oxford: Marien Robertson, 1980.Barr, Donald. Who Pushed Humpty Dumpty--Dilemmas in American Education

Today. New York: Atheneum, 1971.Barton, Len and Walker, Stephen (Ed.). Education and Social Change. London:

Croom Helm, 1985.Berg, Ivan. Education and Jobs: The Great Training Robbery. New York:

Praeger, 1970.Berman, P. Debating PC: The Controversy over Political Correctness on College

Campuses, New York: Laurel, 1992Biehler, Robert F. & Snowman, Jack. Psychology Applied to Teaching (Fifth

Ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1986.Bloom, Allan. The Closing of the American Mind: How Higher Education Has

Failed Democracy and Impoverished the Souls of Today's Students. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987

Bloom, Harold. The western Canon: The Books and School of the Ages. New York: RiverHead Books, 1995

Bowen, James. A History of Western Education. New York: St. Martin's, v1 1972; v2 1975.

Bowers, C.A. The Promise of Theory--Education and the Politics of Cultural Change. New York: Longman, 1984.

Coleman, James S. (Ed.). Education and Political Development. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965.

Craft, Maurice (Ed.). Education and Cultural Pluralism. Philadelphia: Falmer Press, 1984.

Dewey, John. Experience & Education. New York: Collier, 1968.Emberley, Peter C. & Newall, Waller R. Bankrupt Education: The Decline of

Liberal Education in Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1993Emberley, Peter C. Zero Tolerance--Hot Button Politics in Canadian

Universities. Toronto: Penguin, 1996Hill, Winifred F. Learning: A Survey of Psychological Interpretations (Fourth

Ed.) New York: Harper & Row, 1985.

422

Page 423: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Hirsch, E.D., Jr. Cultural Literacy: What Every American Needs to Know. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1987.

Jencks, Christopher & Riesman, David. The Academic Revolution. New York: Doubleday, 1968.

Karier, Clarence J. Man, Society, and Education. Glenview Illinois: Scott Forseman, 1967.

Kline, Morris. Why Johnny Can't Add--The Failure of the New Math. New York: St. Martin's, 1973.

Kozol, Johnathan. Death at an Early Age. Bantam Books, 1968.Lewis, C.S. The Abolition of Man. New York: Macmillan, 1953.Reigeluth, Charles M. Instructional Theories in Action. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence

Erlbaum Assoc., 1987.Rossi, Peter H. and Biddle, Bruce J. (Ed). The New Media and Education--Their

Impact on Society. Garden City NY: Anchor, 1966.Saettler, Paul. A History of Instructional Technology. New York: McGraw-Hill,

1967.Sandin, Robert T. The Search for Excellence--The Christian College in an Age

of Educational Competition. Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1982.Snyder, Tom and Palmer, Jane. In Search of the Most Amazing Thing--Children,

Education, and Computers. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1986.Tesconi, Charles A., Jr. & Morris, Van Gleve. The Anti-Man Culture--

Bureautechnology and the Schools. Rubana Il; The University of Illinois Press, 1972.Tyack, David B. (Ed.). Turning Points in American Educational History.

Walthum, MA: Blaisdell, 1967.Vandenberg, Donald. Human Rights in Education. New York: Philosophical

Library, 1983.

Chapter 11Religion and the Transcendental in

the Fourth Civilization

Seminar - "Who Needs Religion?" 11.1 Foundations of the Study of Religion 11.2 The Major World Religions 11.3 Religion and the Scientific and Industrial Revolutions     11.3.1 Rome to Galileo     11.3.2 Reason in Science and Protestantism     11.3.3 The Partnership Dissolves 11.4 The Debate Over Origins--an Illustration of World View Clashes 11.5 Learning How to Conduct Debates

423

Page 424: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

11.6 Science, Technology, and Religion in the Twentieth Century 11.7 Summary and Further Discussion

11.1 Foundations of the Study of Religion Every people and culture has one or more possibly overlapping sets of

absolute values, outlooks, attitudes, and beliefs that can be regarded in part as its religion. While it is in some cases difficult to classify aspects of a culture as religious or otherwise, the characteristics of a religion in general are:

o It makes absolute assertions about the existence or nonexistence of a god.o It provides reasons for human existence. These may include statements

about the origins or destiny of humanity in general or of individuals in particular.o It makes statements about what is the content, reliability, and manner of

human knowing and about what is the ultimate meaning of knowing. That is, it has intellectual content.

o It addresses the meaning of human experience and engages the emotions of the individual and society. It also includes an element of experience; that is, it must be experienced.

o It makes statements about how existence, knowledge, and experience interact in the conduct of relationships with other people, with the cosmos in general, and with God (or gods). That is, it includes an ethical code, though the source of this may vary.

Such statements provide a comprehensive world view through which to filter and give an interpretation to the intellect of both human existence and human experience.

424

Page 425: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Figure 11.1 Model of Religious Experience

Figure 11.1 is a model of religious experience. Note that this diagram is similar to that used to model the learning process. It must be, for education and training address the issues of being human and of acquiring appropriate techniques to act humanly, while religion serves to answer the question, "What is a human being?" That is, religion makes comprehensive or wholistic declarations about the ultimate meaning for the existence of humankind, both as individuals and as a society. Such comprehensive answers necessarily embrace all of being, knowing, experiencing, and doing. The central titles in this version of the circles are derived from the Bible's statement about what is owed by human beings to their Creator:

"Hear O Israel, the Lord our God, the Lord is one. Love the Lord your God with all your heart and with all your soul, and with all your mind and with all your strength." --Deuteronomy 6:4-5 and Mark 12:29b-30

There have been a variety of approaches to the study of the role and function of religion in culture that have focused on one or more of these four aspects, but each such approach is insufficient in itself to explain religion, even though all

425

Page 426: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

provide valuable insights. A summary of some of these is provided here, although aspects of them will be expanded on further in later sections.

Religion as Philosophy

It is possible to view religion as a branch of philosophy--that is, as part of a general intellectual search for ultimate answers and meaning in life. This aspect differentiates religion from, say, experimental science. The latter generally deals with the measurable physical universe and usually sidesteps questions of ultimate reality, even though its operating assumption must be that one does exist (i.e., that it measures something real).

Religion deals not just with what people believe about meaning but with how they think, emote, and live in the light of such beliefs. That is, it always has an important experiential and relational component, and in this way it differs from philosophy and has an abstract kinship with both the empiricism of science and the applicability of technology. However, religion also tries to provide answers to questions about ultimate origins--about an originating deity--whereas neither philosophy nor science need do this. Thus, the philosophical approach to religion, taken alone, is insufficient to determine its substance or even its meaning, for religion gains much in its empirical interaction with the deity on the one hand and with people and life on the other.

The Historical Approach

If anything, this may be opposite to the philosophical approach, for in it, religion is assessed by the roles its adherents have played throughout history. Such an approach is commonly used in overview courses having such titles as "comparative religion." Inevitably, this view of religion concentrates on religious institutions, for it is through these that the state and its decisions (and so, history) are most often and most directly influenced. However, the historical approach alone may discern little about the effect on individuals and in turn their influence on society.

For example, histories of England discuss Wilberforce and his long and eventually successful political campaign to eliminate slavery, but often omit his Christian commitment and the high view of the value of human beings that led him to oppose slavery--this at a time when the institutionalized church favoured it. Likewise, the religious convictions of the framers of the American constitution played an important role in determining its contents--but today it is the words and the judges own perceptions of social needs that matter to the courts, not the principles that motivated the framers.

It is worth noting that carefully preserved and transmitted religious writings often do have a substantial historical content that is potentially verifiable by parallel documents from other sources, and by archaeological evidence. For example, many archaeological digs in the Middle East would be difficult to interpret without the accounts found in the Bible. Archeology in turn casts light on many details of life and culture in the times described in religious works. However, this light is confined

426

Page 427: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

to externals, and likely to be bereft of insight into the thoughts and beliefs of practitioners.

However, a historical approach alone need not take into account the ideas behind religions (doctrine) or even the religious ideas behind social change, but need view them only as mass movements on the broad stage of human history. Thus, while history is clearly an important component of the religious picture, it too cannot stand on its own as a description of religion.

Religion as Art and Literature

These are aesthetic approaches, wherein various religious ideas are not approached directly, but via the literary value of their sacred writings, and the artistic value of the painting, sculpture, and music that their followers generate. This approach has the advantage of recognizing the rich contributions of religion to culture in these broad areas--ones so large that they could easily be the subject of many books far larger than this one. It has the disadvantage that it deals with religious ideas in a peripheral and abstract manner, as themselves forms or aspects of artistic expression, and not so much for their value as ideas. Neither can an aesthetic approach shed much light on the application of those ideas to life.

This method is certainly worthy of being included in a comprehensive examination of religion, even though its details are beyond the scope of this book. However, the aesthetic engages only part of the whole person, and this approach therefore reveals only a portion of religion's scope.

A Psychological Approach

There have also been a number of attempts to use scientific methods to study religion as a collection of mental or behavioural phenomena and even to make systematic evaluations of religious ideas. This is more comprehensive than a purely descriptive historical approach, for it recognizes that, while mass religious behaviour is important, it does not give the whole picture. The ideas themselves must at some point be grappled with, and as more than just mental or personal effects. However, religion has an element of the transcendental or supernatural about it that extends its realm beyond that of empiricism and makes it very difficult for an analytical science to fully cope with it.

Yet psychological effects are of interest, and there is considerable material of mutual concern to psychologists and to religious adherents. For example, those most concerned with finding answers to the meaning questions are the ones who are likely to be the clients of both religious and psychological counsellors. The two approaches may occasionally have superficial resemblances, for both attempt to secure a suffering client in an environment that can comfort and soothe, thus transcending anguish with a reality of another order. The modern psychologist might say that the better reality already lies within the client waiting to be summoned forth, and a mystic may well agree, differing only in the means of drawing it out.

427

Page 428: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

By contrast, many religions declare that ultimate reality and meaning lie outside the individual and provide a framework in which to relate an individual not just to society, but also to the whole of being. Thus, the mystical idea of locating god within a person is in direct competition with the more conventional religious idea that God is a distinct and separate entity.

Some religions point to a supreme being as the ultimate knowable reality, all else having been created at that being's command. A few religions assert that all created matter is therefore an illusion, and so is any knowledge of it, denying that there is much, if any, reality to draw upon, and counselling an acceptance of such nihilism as the path to mental health. Others counter that such a conclusion is the very antithesis of religion, asserting that, whatever else they may be, religious ideas are every bit as much about specific realities as are scientific ones.

Psychology also makes interesting contributions to the study of behaviour under the influence of faith assertion, particularly in the proclamation and profession of that faith to large groups of people, either in person or through the media. Certain threads common to the persuasion and response of any crowd can readily be identified, and these seem to be applicable to the pronouncements of both preachers and, say, politicians. In addition, the new cognitive theories of modern psychology attempt to evaluate beliefs and knowledge, also in a scientific fashion.

The strictly psychological study of religion, however, limits religion to physical and empirical phenomena on the assumption that the mind is not more than the brain. However, most religions assert that the two are distinct and that religious activities transcend the physical. Measuring such transcendence appears to be beyond the empirical bounds of modern science. On the other hand, measuring only its effects seems to be somewhat incomplete.

Thus, all attempts to find common ground for science and religion are fraught with delicate problems. On the one hand, science seeks to evaluate religion as a quantifiable and measurable physical phenomenon, because such are its realm. On the other, religion asserts that it derives from and deals with things that are no less real for going beyond the physical realm and that science has nothing to say about such matters--only religion's effects can be scientifically measured and not its causes and motivations. Since the existence or nonexistence of the supernatural realm is a matter of basic assumption and is unlikely ever to be provable or disprovable by empirical means without a revelation from the supernatural realm, this debate is irresolvable.

Yet, it is unsatisfactory to assert that religion and science have non-overlapping magesteria (teaching domains) and leave things at that, for science can at least attempt to describe behaviour--whether religious or otherwise--and religion does attempt to describe motives--whether those of scientists or others. The way in which the two once interacted comfortably is described later in this chapter, and some thoughts on achieving new rapprochements are expanded upon in Chapter 12.

428

Page 429: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The Social Aspect of Religion

Groups of people with like beliefs play a role in society that also cannot be ignored. There is a social need--to be with, to talk to, to share emotions with, and to do with--that is part of the human experience. Such general needs extend to the commonality of religious belief and in that sphere are part of what give rise to the assemblies known as synagogues, churches, temples, reading rooms, mosques, and so on. Such gatherings are a partial expression of what it means to be a distinct culture, or a society-within-a-society, and are part of the reason for being of every person.

Put in other terms, the total cultural world view of a person or a people always includes a set of religious beliefs, even if these are mostly negations. It is not always possible to tell whether certain aspects of a society are the cause or the effect of its religious beliefs, nor is it easy to separate the religious aspect of a culture from its other elements, so intertwined are they. One can easily argue that this is true even in professedly irreligious cultures, where similar commitment, activities, behaviour, and passions are evoked for causes with other names. Thus, Western liberal humanism and communist statism both have religious significance, even though both often claim to have none--for all people act on a set of values and in turn attribute these to some cause, and all hold some values to be more important than others, even to be supreme. All people must deal with questions of the ultimate origin and meaning of life, and all cultures have some reflection of the answers to such questions in the lives of their members. Even a firm denial that such things exist, or that they matter even if they are real, is a statement with religious content and has consequences for the person or society making such a faith statement. That negative statements on religion are indeed faith affirmations becomes evident when one realizes that the same quality of emotion and the same kind of empirical evidence is behind a rejection of the supernatural as there is behind a belief in one. Thus, the common argument that the beliefs and values of irreligious people cannot be compared at all to religious faith affirmations is very weak. So is the assertion that social behaviour has no necessary connection with religion, for both logic and historical experience argue otherwise.

A social approach to the study of religion is, therefore, potentially more comprehensive than a purely historical one. However, it still tends to have the limitation of being primarily descriptive rather than evaluative and does not therefore suffice alone, for the thing being described demands an evaluation by its very nature. That is, at some point, the claims of religion upon the whole person must be dealt with. Moreover, it is evidently impossible to stand entirely outside the thing called religion and give it a dispassionate evaluation, free from any preconceived notions about the thing being described. Thus, there will be bias in any description of religion.

A Moral (Behavioural) Approach

Religion also addresses moral issues, for it is concerned with how to be a good person, how to live life in harmony with those around, and perhaps how to live a life

429

Page 430: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

that pleases a supreme deity--any or all of which may lead to rewards in a life to come. It is to behavioural issues generally (and moral ones specifically) that comparers of religions look, for it is here that the most common ground is found, even though the reasons for arriving at moral laws may be very different. Such commonality is yet another evidence for the universality of a moral sense and, to some extent, for the content of moral laws. Moreover, many people think of religion as a set of practices and/or rituals, that is, in behavioural terms.

What distinguishes various religions on this score, however, is the reasoning behind the rules, and the motivation for having them. One must ask if ethical rules exist just to have an orderly society, for the production of relative good, or for the pleasing of a god who is absolutely good. Do the rules exist to gain a salvation or are they behavioural guideposts for those who already have one? Do they arise from within people or do they come only from the character of the deity being worshipped? It is, incidentally, only in the context of worshipping a moral god that the concept of sin (violation of Divine standards) arises.

The moral aspect is evidently essential to comprehending a religion but clearly also does not stand alone. Moral codes need to be assessed in the context of their reason for being and also in the context of the actual behaviour people exhibit when they claim such codes for their own. Do the moral codes change a person; do they change the person's behaviour; or do they change nothing outside the person's mind? That is, do they have a transforming effect, or are they entirely mental abstractions with peripheral, if any, application to life?

Do the deeds (behaviours) dictated by moral codes become the means to the end of an eternal salvation, or are they the result of already having it, the external consequences of a prior inner transformation? Do they co-exist with belief, produce it, or are they produced by it?

That deeds themselves do not answer these fundamental questions illustrates that there is more to religion than the behaviour associated with its adherants.

Religion as a Commodity

There are two ways in which one can approach religion as a commodity. The first is to treat it as a marketable item--one with a perceived need, a set of clients, a product to respond to the need, a sales force, an organizational structure, and an appropriate pension plan. In this view, religion is a package of ideas and life-style that has to be sold into a competitive marketplace, and the methodology for doing so is similar to that for the advertising, packaging, and selling of any other product. Potential customers need to be convinced that they have a need and then persuaded to accept a particular brand-name solution. The deal must be closed, and then the client must be maintained as such over the long term. The competition has to be assessed and beaten back at every turn. The sales force (preachers) must be trained in all the latest marketing techniques. Available media have to be utilized to their fullest potential to get the message out, and the entire enterprise must be financed through voluntary payments of its purchasers. If the marketplace (cultural milieu) changes, then the company (the religious institution) must either change

430

Page 431: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

with it or diversify, lest it become insolvent and either cease to exist or have its assets in people taken over by a competitor.

In this view, religion maintains cultural relevance as long as it remains economically viable in the marketplace of ideas, so its models and techniques must continually be adapted to those of the culture into which the ideas are being sold. Thus, religion has discovered television, and numerous sellers of religious products now hold forth from electronic pulpits, backed by advertising, orchestras, choirs, and the latest broadcast technology. The difficulty with this approach to religion as commodity is that once the product has been wrapped up for retail sale, it may be difficult for customers to discern what are the contents of the package. Exactly what is being sold, and what is its cost? Is there a warranty?

In fact, when any product is marketed with standard methods, the lines between substance and packaging blur, and in this way, religion can metamorphose into either a business or a form of religious entertainment. If so, it necessarily comes to engage the emotions far more than the intellect. At such a point, it no longer stands on its ideas or on its ability to transform people but only on the marketing technique that has provoked the response. That is, it is not religion itself that becomes in such cases the commodity but an emotional experience described by a religious-like vocabulary. Since this is at least one step removed from the religious ideas themselves, it may be best to assess this particular phenomenon strictly in terms of its business and entertainment value and to regard its most visible sales force as media celebrities who are only incidentally related to the actual religion. They sell an emotional experience that many people are prepared to buy as a less comprehensive and less demanding substitute for religion, much less to the beliefs motivating religious behaviour. These comments apply regardless of whether the emotional experience comes from being an observer at the pomp and ceremony of some ancient ritual or from the charged atmosphere of a charismatic miracle meeting.

A second problem created by the constant repackaging of religiosity for the marketplace is that ideas which started with a claim to transcend time and culture come to be heavily modified in the light of both, and perhaps ultimately to be discarded. Thus, the irony of the search for relevance in the application of religion to modern culture is that the modified religion can all too easily thereby become irrelevant to the search for universal applicability.

To be sure, religious ideas are indeed in competition with those from other sources and with each other. In the West the very notion of a democracy requires the free competition of ideas. But, as illustrated here, the model of competition among ideas cannot be pressed too far in practice without dissipating their vitality in spectacular if unengaging show. The same observation, to the same effect, can be made of politics, which when partnered with modern media may also become a personal and emotional experience that lacks much intellectual content or relevance to people's lives. After all, the most effective marketing sells the sizzle of outward appearances to the emotions, not the steak of content to the intellect, and this is true whether the product is computer software, religion, or politics. That is, the treatment of religion strictly as a commodity obscures its nature rather than explains it.

431

Page 432: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This marketing of religious ideas and fragments also raises some interesting legal and ethical questions related to the definition and status of religious organizations in the United States and Canada. Since these organizations are tax exempt in both countries and there is in both a societal and legal prohibition against government entanglement with religion, there are few means to ensure that funds raised on television and by direct marketing will indeed be used for the stated purposes. It is not always clear that the actual use of such funds has anything to do with religion. Yet attempts to regulate activities operated by religious bodies are sure to provoke charges of interference by the government in areas prohibited to the state. On the other hand, failure to protect a trusting and unsuspecting public from fraud may be irresponsible, for only the government has the power to undertake such a role. As in the case of pluralism, there is a paradox here. To the extent that religion is to be marketed as a commodity, there must be some measure of accountability and responsibility for the activities of its people and organizations. On the other hand, freedom of religion ceases to exist if the government dictates how it shall be practised, or acts as arbiter of the validity of its ideas. But, if it ignores religion altogether, the state may fail in its duty to protect its citizens from danger. One must conclude from these marketplace considerations alone that, although the state perhaps should avoid excessive entanglement in the affairs of religion, there can never in practice be a total wall of separation between the two.

The second, and rather different, approach to religions as commodities is to assess them competitively by the benefits they bring people. Which ones promote war, famine, corruption, totalitarianism, and moral decadence? Which brings hospitals, food, medicine, new agricultural techniques, freedom from slavery, equality of opportunity, and high moral standards? What payment is asked for the material benefits offered? Is political or cultural assimilation demanded? Does the preacher demand the buyer's soul to hang at a denominational belt like a trophy scalp? Is the motivation for the message a love of God translated into love for people? What benefits are offered the believer? These could vary from a nice feeling of doing good, to avoidance of divine punishment, to divine acceptance for eternal life, to the nirvana of escape from another dreary reincarnation, or to some vague, but unspecified reward. Whatever the salvation offered by a religion, it too could be viewed as an idea in competition with similar ones, and this is one way of assessing religions that may be useful if taken in conjunction with others listed here.

Analyses of the commodity aspect of religion are quite legitimate, for they deal with the effects of beliefs on people and culture, and such effects are of interest to everyone, not just those who profess a certain religion. For example, a religion that believed in and practised human sacrifice, the killing of people with some other skin colour or religion, or the violent overthrow of the state has a direct impact on everyone in the society. Consequently, the society has a vested interest in protecting itself from beliefs that threaten its existence or the lives of its citizens.

The comparison of religions may be undertaken with the implicit assumption that there is a standard to which the comparison is being made--that absolute religious ideas exist. This assumption is especially evident when the comparison is being conducted with the ostensible purpose of debunking the very notion of religion (common in secular universities), and there is a logical circularity here from

432

Page 433: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

which no immediate escape is evident. Even when no standard is made apparent, the effects chosen for comparative study reflect the relative importance attached to such things by the one making the report. Why is one group of outcomes from religious beliefs more desirable than another, and who is qualified to judge between the two? In particular, who can say that one moral standard is higher than another, apart from an all-knowing deity who Himself reveals the truth? It is no easier, therefore, to make comparisons between religions as commodities in an objective manner than it is to do so as objects of scientific, historical, or psychological examination. To a greater or lesser degree, the comparer of religions is emotionally and religiously affected by the objects under study, making an objective analysis difficult if not impossible.

On the other hand, such comparisons may be conducted with a view to choosing the portions one likes from various religious systems. This practice is one contributor to religious fragmentation in the twentieth century--the picking of religious ideas from this or that system of beliefs as one might select a dinner from a smorgasbord. The result may be an exotic but ephemeral taste experience, but in the long haul and for practical purposes the components may not go together at all.

The same kind of fragmentation may also take place when religious ideas are exported to other cultures. If they go attached to the cultural strings of the sending nation, they will be perceived as strictly cultural exports and not as religious ones. If a religion is indeed universal, then it is culturally independent and it can be believed in and practised by the peoples of any language, culture, civilization, time, or economic status. If it is not, pieces of it will perhaps be added to the importing culture and religion, but the religion as a whole will not be widely adopted.

Even when religious and charitable organizations go to other nations with aid for hunger or disaster, such help may be received only as a mixed blessing. It may create dependence, encourage poverty, cause resentment, and actually promote rejection of the religious or cultural message accompanying it. Thus, those who undertake missionary or religious-based relief work must have a clear idea of what it is that they are attempting to do or to persuade a people of, as well as how to make it that people's belief, independent of all cultural and material considerations. Similar comments could be made of the political and social strings attached to aid provided by governments.

In summary, religion can be treated as a commodity, but this is a level of abstraction that fails to do justice to any of its content and claims, or to measure its impact on people. Such a view of religion is also superficial, for it looks only at its competitive behaviour and not at the object itself. Religions can also be analysed from a commodity perspective, with their effects compared to one another or to some implied standard. This is more useful, though it is impaired both by the difficulty in achieving objectivity and that of knowing what can be included in the study. In addition, all such attempts suggest that there is a kind of meta-religious standard by which the truth claims of religion can be assessed, and this too becomes a religious statement. One ends up in the same place as before--religious statements can be validated against a standard only if that standard exists independently and absolutely.

433

Page 434: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Religion as a Personal Experience

This final view of religion regards it as a sum of personal experiences, an intimate thing difficult to expound upon in universal terms. Such an element is the focus of the mystical religions that search for ultimate reality within each person--one that must necessarily constitute a different experience for each individual. This aspect is present in a different sense in evangelical Christianity, which holds that true religion involves a personal relationship with a personal God, one that recognizes individual differences but whose character is nonetheless essentially similar, but only because God never changes.

While this view of religion expresses an important aspect, it is one that is of most interest to individuals and their own experience and is of lesser concern to the historian or forecaster because it addresses societal and ethical questions only indirectly, by hypothesizing how the changed individual might work out relationships with respect to other people. That is, assuming that religion is a personal experience means that its behavioural consequences in general terms are elusive. When actions do not appear to match the religious theory, it is not certain whether the theory is faulty or whether the personal experience of it is absent.

This uncertainty has always, for instance, been a particular problem for evangelical Christians, who assert that the believer in Christ has been born again to a new life and has the indwelling power of the Holy Spirit to live that new life successfully. How are actions completely inconsistent with the religion's moral code to be explained? How are the apparent conflicts among faith, emotions, the intellect, and one's relationships to be resolved? Is the person's understanding defective or was the experience a false one? The only answer that can be given is that God alone knows absolutely who His true people are, and this reply is unlikely to satisfy the skeptical observer. Another difficulty is caused by the fact that people respond emotionally in very different ways to the same set of beliefs. Is this simply an artifact of their differing personalities and interests, or does this observation invalidate either the experiences of some, on the one hand, or the claim to universality on the other?

As a result, personal experience alone is also insufficient to explain the phenomenon of religion. It does not hold religious ideas up to scrutiny in themselves, but attempts to assess them solely in terms of experiences--and experiences claimed in the same cause may be very diverse. External reference points are needed in doctrine to account for experiences; they are insufficient on their own to explain religion.

Summary

As this overview indicates, religion is rich and complex, affecting both the individual and group life in a wide variety of ways, none of which taken alone provides a satisfactory explanation. At least the entire context of the model diagrammed at the start of this section in Figure 11.1 is necessary, and even then it is not clear whether what has been achieved is an understanding of religion or just a partial redefinition of something that lacks a full explanation. It is clear that the

434

Page 435: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

impact of religion on both individuals and society as a whole is substantial, and it is appropriate to consider that impact further, first by looking at the teachings of some of the major religions, then by discussing the origins of modern science and technology in their religious context. It will also be of interest to consider whether that impact will continue to diminish, as it has in the industrial age, or whether religion will make a comeback and become an important factor in the information age.

11.2 The Major World Religions In this brief overview of the history and teachings of the major world religions,

emphasis will be on the ethical teachings of each, the impact each has had on society, and the current status of each. Doctrine will be discussed only to the extent that it directly affects teachings on ethical and social behaviour, and not in any comprehensive terms. It is beyond the scope of this book to make detailed comparisons of major religions at all doctrinal points.

It is worth noting that the classifying of many such systems of teachings as "religions" is a modern Western idea. A body of beliefs and activities may not be separable from the culture and society of which they are a part. It could therefore be argued that such classifications can be done only for the sake of making comparisons between ones that claim cultural independence and universality (Christianity, Buddhism, and branches of Hinduism and Islam) and ones that do not. A better model for most of the latter group might be as social or philosophical systems. For instance, one properly speaks of the religion of the ancient Romans, Greeks, Egyptians, and Babylonians as having been principally cultural and educational phenomena. Their priests were the primary preservers of culture--of all the available knowledge--and not just of their philosophy or theology. However, these have all passed from the world stage with the cultures that spawned them, and those that do remain must compete into the future for human souls, so it is they that must submit to such comparisons.

There are also numerous folk religions that survive to this day, but these are usually confined to limited geographical areas and only occasionally play an influential role on the world scene. Their impact can be substantial on local variations of some of the major religions, as the latter will often accommodate themselves to local practices and beliefs and incorporate many of them into their own structure. Because of the wide variety of such systems and their limited impact on the larger society, they will not be considered in any detail here.

Buddhism

The philosophical and ethical system attributed to Buddha (563-483 B.C.) in India was not at first a religion as the people of the West might view one. Buddha, the wealthy son of a warrior king, renounced his inheritance and family for the asceticism of a monk and then for the role of reformer. The Buddhist philosophy is based on the "Four Noble Truths":

1. Existence involves suffering.

435

Page 436: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

2. Suffering is caused by indulging insatiable desires.3. Suffering will cease if these are suppressed. 4. This suppression can be achieved by following the eightfold noble path,

which consists of striving for: right views, right goals, right speech, right actions, right livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness, and right meditation.

Buddha did not mention a supreme being, but after his death he himself came to be venerated as a deity, for the people of the polytheistic societies in which his teachings spread quickly added him to their pantheon of gods. Followers of some Buddhist sects came to believe that anyone could reach a state of Buddhahood or enlightenment and also become an immortal deity (or at least absorbed into the life force of such). As can be seen, the ethics of Buddhism are negatively expressed and individualistic. They are directed to improving the self through suppression of desire, and have little to say to the society at large. Evil is entirely an individual responsibility, and if it has not been sufficiently put down to achieve Buddhahood or nirvana as did the founder, then his followers teach that the person's karma will cause reincarnation to another life.

In China and Japan, where most modern Buddhists live and where there are also more Buddhist deities, the faithful are often organized somewhat as in Western churches. Nirvana--the salvation offered--involves a deliverance from the necessity to live another life and to continue suffering. It is not always clear whether this is comparable to the Western idea of heaven or if it is simply personal annihilation.

Though Buddhism has split into many sects, it is not confined to national boundaries but has been adapted to a number of rather different societies and could be said to claim it is universal. Certainly it has been missionary, and portions of it are even now being adopted by many in the West as interest in new philosophies and exotic religions grows.

The industrial age is a very late arrival in traditional Buddhist countries, and it remains to be seen whether its essential pessimism of humanity in general and of the body, and women in particular, will allow it to secure a place in the optimistic, humanistic, and egalitarian late industrial and early information age. It may be that in the short term aspects of Buddhism will be incorporated by Westerners into a diverse and fragmented religious menu that simply ignores any aspects of it that seem inappropriate. In the countries where Buddhism is widely practised, the industrial age had a rather late start, and its presence is still rather uneven. The transition to the fourth civilization will likely bring bout the demise of a number of totalitarian regimes in that part of the world, as it already has in the West. However, there do not appear to be inherent conflicts between Buddhism and the information paradigms.

Confucianism

The teachings of the Chinese philosophy and culture were organized by their greatest expositor, Confucius (551-479 B.C.) who did not so much set about to found a religion as to effect social, political, and educational reform. It was important to him to place a sound and authoritative philosophical foundation under

436

Page 437: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the institutions of society--family, social class, and nation. Veneration of this sage began after his death. He was given many titles by later emperors, and temples for his worship came to be erected throughout China. This worship had begun to decline somewhat even before the communists came to power in China and has been suppressed since then, as have all other religions. It is not clear how much of it has survived at this point as a distinct religion, but elements of its cultural and nationalist zeal can be detected in the devotion to the communist leaders, which was similar to that commanded by the earlier emperors.

Confucianism concentrates on relationships, especially those of friends, of family and of the subject to the state, with particular emphasis on the last. The superior man (this philosophy has little to say about women) does his proper duty in each relationship in a dignified and aristocratic fashion. Virtues such as propriety, sincerity, faithfulness, studiousness, justice, benevolence, reverence, moderation, calmness, and honesty are encouraged. These virtues were guaranteed by heaven or by an impersonal god, and the deity has supposedly implanted in everyone an inherently good moral sense. There are remarkable similarities between the good Confucian ruler and citizen and those of Plato.

Worship is to be directed toward heaven, earth, and one's ancestors. It was conducted by the emperor on behalf of the people of the whole nation, for there was no priestly role except for that of government officials. Emphasis is placed on social duties, a variation of the golden rule, the family, religious values in the state, and the wisdom of the past. Confucianism is national rather than universal, and salvation is humanistic and social rather than personal and other-worldly. Despite its religious-like observances, it is not clear that Confucianism ought to be termed a religion; perhaps it is better regarded as part of the Chinese culture. For this reason, it has not been exportable, and its devotional aspect may continue to have a troubled time in the light of rapid and dramatic changes in Chinese society.

Indeed, the most remarkable thing about the suppression of religion by communists has been the conversion of tens of millions to Christianity during the first fifty years of its reign, a process that continues at a rapid pace. This change has been even more substantial in South Korea, where fully a third of the population is now Christian and where the ancient philosophies of Buddhism and Confucianism are now on the decline, in relative terms.

Much in China does still remain of Confucianism, but it is woven into the social and cultural patterns of the Chinese people and is much less discernible as a devotional-style religious worship today than it was in the past. China has long been a closed and insular society, one with great Confucian regard for authority and self-sufficiency. However, Chinese communism has apparently not survived rapid industrialization, internationalization, and the beginning of the information age. It has not suffered catastrophic collapse as in the former Soviet Union, but has begun the process of dismantling itself from within by changing into a form of state capitalist dictatorship. Even this is only temporarily stable because of the cultural Confucian-like reverence for authority. Otherwise, the regime's brutal suppression of political and religious dissent would long since have resulted in collapse. Thus, Mao Zedung may have been the last Chinese emperor to receive old-style veneration, and China seems poised to perform the great leaps forward into the technological

437

Page 438: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and information ages that it has hitherto been unable to make. How much of the Confucian philosophy will survive the ongoing wrenching social adjustments that will accompany the information age remains to be seen.

Hinduism

Hinduism is the term used to refer to the religious beliefs of the majority of India's people. These date to about 1500 B.C. and include a very broad range of philosophical and social ideas and gods--so broad a variation that they are difficult to characterize. A Hindu may be an atheist, a polytheist, a monotheist, a nature worshiper, a contemplative, a mystic, an agnostic, or a follower of formal ritual Hinduism. The last kind was until recently chiefly characterized by its caste system; to its followers, it was much more important what caste one's neighbours belonged to than the specifics of what they believed--as long as they were not adherents of a different religion altogether. There were more than fifty major castes and well over a thousand subcastes in addition to those who were noncaste, or "untouchables". This last concept was outlawed by the current constitution of India, and the whole caste system is under great pressure from foreign ideas, though in practice it is still an important feature of daily life.

The only unifying theology is belief in one all-present being or world soul called Brahma-Atman. Hinduism is more a religion of nature (pantheism) than of one god (monotheism), for the goal of human beings is to separate themselves from the illusion of life and reality as it is commonly perceived and merge themselves into the Brahma-Atman, or rather to fully realize that they are already part of it. Death is not final, for the individual soul (the atman) is reincarnated in some new form, which may be an animal or a higher caste member. These two--the belief in Brahma and that of the transmigration of the karma--were added after the caste system became prevalent.

There are a multiplicity of legal codes, movements, and deities in various Hindu traditions. One of the most popular gods is Krishna, the compassionate warrior-teacher, whose love his followers devote themselves to imitating. The eclectic nature of Hinduism is also illustrated by the Ramakrishna reform movement dating from the nineteenth century, which teaches that the same degree of mystic enlightenment can be achieved whether one comes from Islam, Christianity, Buddhism, or Hinduism. The founder of this group, Sri Ramakrishna, is now revered as the reincarnation of Krishna, Rama, Christ, and Buddha. A variant of this offshoot of Hinduism with its Krishna worship and belief in reincarnation has been exported to other countries in missionary fashion, whereas Hinduism in general has not, primarily because of the caste system.

The ethics of Hinduism are as diverse as its theology. Good and evil are not entirely distinguishable, and defects such as ignorance, or the violation of caste rules, while lamentable, can always be corrected in another incarnation. Evil is an illusion, and it is overcome by being immersed in the Brahma-Atman and by complying with the social conventions of caste. Individuals have little value as such, nor can they improve their situation in this life. Worship is ceremonial and

438

Page 439: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

meditative, and a deity is more a force than a personal being. In general there are no universal absolutes of behaviour.

Thus, even the industrial revolution, let alone the information one, runs up against religious or cultural obstacles in India, because both require improvement of the individual and of society as a whole through education. As long as the caste system and the relatively low estimate of the individual and of women survive, movement into the information age will probably continue to be slow in India. Moreover, despite broad religious tolerance within Hinduism, India is troubled by religious differences internally with the minority Sihks and externally with its Islamic neighbour of Pakistan, and the temptation to use nuclear weapons to resolve these conflicts may yet prove irresistible. Yet the diversity of Hinduism is such that occasional elements of it can easily be exported and added piecemeal to the religious menu of the West. That same diversity may in time allow India to import the cultural assumptions, scientific ideas, and techniques from the West that make the third and fourth civilizations possible.

Shintoism

Like Hinduism, this religion is a national cultural and social phenomenon confined to a single country--in this case to Japan. Its chief feature is a belief in the divine origin of the islands of Japan, and the divine appointment of the Mikado, or emperor. Its ceremonies are both patriotic and devotional, and its gods are many, including the emperor himself. There are a variety of nature gods, the most important of which is the sun-goddess. To these are made many ceremonial offerings to purify the faithful from guilt and to cement their relationship to the state and to Japanese culture as a whole. In this, there is a strong resemblance to the Confucian philosophies.

At times, Shintoism has been combined with Buddhism and other Chinese religions, and it has always expressed a tolerance of these, even though it has traditionally taught the essential superiority of the Japanese people and culture. This doctrine was formally repudiated after the surrender by the emperor to the Americans in 1945, as was his own divinity, and thus the connection of the Japanese state to Shintoism was officially severed. Devotional Shintoism is still self-sacrificing and patriotic, though the patriotism is now somewhat more vague. It emphasizes purity, though it lacks specific moral injunctions except as these have been borrowed from Buddhism and Confucianism. It teaches reverence for one's superiors, and especially for the state, but offers no hope for a new life after death, no place for outsiders, no intrinsic individual value, nor specific guidance for living morally.

The Japanese are quite prepared to use both Western science and technology to advance their collective cultural interests, and it may be said that their religious zeal (if the word is appropriate for a cultural phenomenon) has been turned from the former goal of military superiority to one of economic domination. Thus, the Japanese continue to have a patriotism and desire to serve national interests that give them organizational unity and flexibility. These seem likely to serve them in good economic stead well into the information age, despite that the elements

439

Page 440: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Westerners would call "religious" are now of somewhat lesser importance than they once were. A philosophy that is attuned to this life rather than to a hope for the next must be pragmatic, and the pragmatism of collective economic advantage can serve to unify and energize a nation in the place of a religion for a generation or two, if not longer.

As the information age progresses and the Japanese people continue to be exposed to religious ideas that claim to be universal from the rest of the world, there may be some reassessment of their cultural beliefs. Such a reassessment may also happen as a result of inevitable economic declines that are part of the normal cycle of activities; if economic success has indeed been incorporated into the Shinto culture, such events could be extremely painful for the entire nation.

At the present time, the Japanese still remain much less open to outside religious and cultural ideas than, say, the Koreans and the Chinese. They have, however, no reluctance to borrowtechnique and, up to the late 1990s, were among the most successful of the late adapters of many industrial age methods. These adoptions were, however, into a closed and highly nationalistic context, and reluctance to be fully internationalized partners in trade and banking ultimately brought them serious economic difficulties in the late 1990s, ones that have still not been dealt with a decade later. Since success in an information age requires openness, cooperation, and the free flow of goods, ideas, and capital, continuing Japanese success into the fourth civilization appears to hinge on making extensive internal and external adjustments. As any such changes would have cultural (and therefore religious) overtones, it is not clear that they can easily be made. On the other hand, the economies of the rest of the world's nations have become too closely interconnected with that of Japan for them to allow her to collapse and so threaten their own stability. Thus an accommodation to circumstances will undoubtedly be found that will either bring Japan into much greater international cooperation (at the expense of local cultural sensibilities), or cushion her decline back into isolationism (preserving traditional nationalism at economic expense) so that it takes place gradually.

Judaism

This name, given to the national religion of the descendents of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob (Israel), is borrowed from that of one of the last surviving identifiable tribes of Israel's children--that of Judah. It is the earliest of three religions, including Christianity and Islam, to proclaim a single, personal, all-knowing, ethical creator God who has revealed His existence and actions, and that He has righteous moral demands upon all people. These revelations began with Abraham, who was influenced by them to break away from his polytheistic culture and religion to become the father of a new faith in one single highly ethical and all-powerful God. Typical of those of a nomadic culture, neither he nor his descendents did anything to propagate their faith beyond their own family. It was to Moses, centuries afterward, who codified both sacred history and the ethical demands of God in the Pentateuch (the first five books of the Bible). However, when his followers subsequently conquered Palestine under Joshua, they quickly adapted as

440

Page 441: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

their own a large pantheon of local gods and goddesses known as "baals." Much of the prophetic literature of the Old Testament was written to counter this idol worship and to warn the people of the consequences of continuing in it.

The Jewish God's ethics are revealed in His commands respecting relationships, to Himself, family, neighbour, and nation, which are highly detailed and reflect concern and care for fair treatment of the defenceless orphan and widow, of the poor, and even of the foreigner. He emphasized production of an ethical nation to reflect God's character in the conduct of an entire people. When they turned away from His law and participated instead in temple prostitution and infant sacrifice, worshipping Molech and other gods, He turned His back on their nation for a time. Their subsequent captivity in Babylon burned away all trace of polytheism, and the Jewish people have been relatively monotheistic since. On their return from this exile, their teachers gradually expounded upon and expanded the codes of Moses until priestly interpretations of law became comprehensive legalistic regulation of every aspect of life. Simultaneously, there arose an ever more elaborate religious ritualism centred about the rebuilt temple in Jerusalem.

Much of this was obliterated by the Romans when they sacked Jerusalem and dispersed the Jews about 70 A.D. following a rebellion against the empire. During this time the rabbis (teachers), rather than the priests, became their religious leaders, and their sayings too came to be collected in a work known as the Talmud. Though dispersed widely, speaking many languages, and severely persecuted, the Jews maintained both their religion and their cultural identity for centuries, principally in Europe and later in America as well. Their persecution reached its greatest depths in Hitler's holocaust, during which some six million Jews perished, nearly a third of their total number.

Subsequently, the Jewish people were able to re-establish a national homeland in Palestine, naming their new country Israel, though it is a secular rather than a religious state. Its citizens are diverse, both in cultural origin, and in religious practice, which vary from the highly traditional to the rather liberal, with some professing no religion at all. Israel's national unity may depend not so much on religion as on a desire to survive the hatred of enemies on all sides.

Two major streams of religious thought have existed in Judaism--that of detailed observance of the form of the law as the means of salvation, and that of devotion to the law as part of a personal relationship to God. In both cases, the chief characteristics are a scrupulous ethic and monotheism as well as an insistence upon the sovereignty of God over all of life. God's ethical demands are universal, even if His promise of a saviour (Messiah) is held to be a national one. At the same time, their long history of persecution by countries whose leaders they would not bow to, and by the zealots of other religions who could not convert them, left the survivors a profoundly pragmatic people. This, coupled with their belief in the regularity of God's creation, has helped to make them eager adapters of techniques of all kinds, and given them great success in the industrial age and good promise in its successor.

Islam

441

Page 442: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Next to Christianity, Islam is the second largest of present-day religions. Like Christianity, it was personally founded, claims universality, is monotheistic, and is missionary--to the point of being, perhaps, the fastest-growing religion today. It was founded in distinct opposition to Christianity by Muhammad of Mecca (570-632 A.D.), whose experiences, teachings, and visions were later recorded by his followers in the Koran, the holy book of Islam. After his death, Muhammad came to be regarded as more than a prophet, approaching the status claimed by Jesus Christ except that he is not considered to be God.

God is represented in Islam as an ultimate unity, and the representation that Christianity has three gods is explicitly attacked. God, or Allah as he is termed, is punisher of the wicked and rewarder of the good. However, good deeds alone do not necessarily assure one of paradise, for nothing is certain about the next life, except that Allah, in his good pleasure, will reward whom he regards as the faithful and will punish others.

Throughout much of its history, Islam has been closely associated with the state, and there have been numerous Islamic theocracies (officially Islamic countries). There have also been many sects in Islam, though the chief ones today are the Sunni (traditionalists) of the majority and the Shia (militant mystics) of Iran, Lebanon, and some parts of Africa. Other sects have included the Baha´i--though they now claim to be a world movement that encompasses all the major religions and are severely persecuted in their birthplace of Iran by the Shia.

Insofar as technology is concerned, Islamic scholars were the great preservers of philosophy and developers of mathematics and philosophy during the Middle Ages of Europe. Yet, for the most part, modern technology and the industrial revolution were not imported into Middle Eastern Islamic countries until lately, when oil revenues allowed those nations to purchase the products of both. In more recent years, there has been a simultaneous increase in missionary expansion and a turning inward to a strict fundamentalism. Highly ethical Islam castigates the people of Western countries--which nations it often equates with Christianity--for what is seen as their immorality, and it continues to promote the establishment of officially Islamic nations whose laws are those of the Koran. In some such countries, converts to any other religion face the death penalty, on the theory that they have insulted the prophet.

With its current power, wealth, and success, Islam is aggressive, expansionist, confident, and devotional. It appeals to force when necessary, is somewhat fatalistic, and postulates a sensuous heaven. It gives women a low social and spiritual status, though greatly improved on what Arabian women previously had, and it continues to be somewhat fragmented. It is therefore difficult to predict the future of Islam, but for the time being it is one of the most potent religious forces in the world, and therefore one of the most important shapers of ethics and of culture even if not presently of technique. It appears to be the chief contender, along with Christianity, and Buddhist/Hindu syncretisms for the religious-style heart allegiances of all peoples in the years to come.

On the other hand, the closed nature of Islam with its hostility to new ideas and information, place it in fundamental conflict with information age paradigms, and this makes it more likely to aggressively resist the fourth civilization than to

442

Page 443: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

embrace it. This does not bode well either for the material prosperity of the predominantly Islamic nations or for world peace.

Christianity

Statistically, Christianity is the largest of all religions--in its various forms numbering perhaps a billion or more adherents. Its scriptures incorporate and explain those of Judaism, its predecessor, as the Old Testament, and add to these the account of the life and sayings of Christ together with those of His apostles. Christianity is monotheistic but teaches that the one God is manifested in three personalities--the Father, Jesus Christ the Son, and the Holy Spirit. Uniquely among all religions, its personal founder claimed to be the Almighty God Himself, having taken on human form for the express and sole purpose of providing an answer for the general problem of evil and for offering a way to relate to a holy God despite the pervasiveness of sin.

Specifically, Christianity holds that evil is an offence against God's standards and character as revealed in moral laws He gave to Moses. All human beings violate those laws and are therefore already judged by God, condemned, and sentenced to the eternal and painful punishment of separation from Him--this by their own choice not to seek Him. The Jewish sacrificial laws established through Moses are explained as pictures of the one final and completely effective sacrifice--that of Christ on the cross who alone, being perfect and divine, is capable of actual substitution for the punishment of death due the sinner. By this act, God extends His grace to individual human beings, giving each the power to overcome the problem of sin, to gain salvation, and to have an eternal life in His presence.

The New Testament teaches that salvation is entirely a gift of God, not due to any merit on the part of the one saved. The sins of the one coming to faith are forgiven, and God chooses to regard the one so redeemed as having the perfect righteousness of Christ and so fit to enter heaven. It also teaches that not only are God's past acts toward humankind rooted in history, but that He will yet return personally to earth to judge each person individually according to his or her relationship with God. The resurrection of Christ from the dead is not just the evidence of His defeat of death, but is also a foreshadowing of the general resurrection of all people to an eternal body in which each person will individually receive either reward for Christ's righteousness seen in them by God because of their faith, or will instead receive punishment for their pervasive and unatoned-for evil.

There are several major divisions within Western Christianity. The Roman Catholic tradition holds that the New Testament was created by the church and can be interpreted and modified by it. Thus, the supreme source of doctrine is the church and the final arbiter of the faith is its head, the Pope, when speaking formally as its doctrinal teacher (ex cathedra). Here, good works by a baptized person are also held to be essential to participate in the salvation offered by Christ, and one's status is never really secure until one dies, for at any given moment one's sin account may be larger than one's works account. Similar doctrines are found in many other groups within Christendom as well. In this particular case, it is coupled

443

Page 444: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

with a large body of Catholic law that is held to have the same force as the ethical principles of the Bible itself.

The Protestant Reformation of Luther, Calvin, and others was an attempt to remove institutional trappings and to uphold the Bible as the only rule of Christian faith and practice. The reformers taught that the Bible documented the church's reason for being, rather than the other way around. They concluded, therefore, that good works were not a means to the end of salvation, for that was God's finished work and perfect gift. Rather, moral behaviour was something the already saved would naturally exhibit out of gratitude for the gift of God, and was due to the Holy Spirit dwelling in each believer and so incarnating in that person the character and works of Christ.

However, many of the churches founded by the reformers themselves acquired the status of self-perpetuating institutions, and their elders and deacons became, if not priests, at least a professional class of clergy with their own agenda for self-preservation. Eventually, some of them discarded reform teachings either for a vague doctrine of salvation by works or a teaching of universal salvation for everyone regardless of what they believed or practised. Others retreated into nominalism, perhaps retaining social action for its own sake, but losing interest in doctrine and beliefs. Some came to view Christ as an interesting moral teacher, His actions exaggerated by His followers to provide an example to emulate but one that is impossible for anyone, even Himself, to achieve. Eventually finding themselves with no raison d'etre in faith, such groups began a slow decline into oblivion. Thus, there have periodically been new reform movements within Protestantism in an attempt to sharpen the distinction between institutional and nominal Christianity as represented by the formal denominations on the one hand and the cross-denominational "true church" of faith-affirming converts on the other. For example, modern evangelicals hold with the earlier reformers that a person is a Christian not by virtue of being a citizen of a country or a member of a church of Christendom, but only by a specific act of the will by which one becomes a member of the family of God and is assured of salvation.

It is therefore possible to view Christianity as an institutionalized religion, one among several others, or as an individual relationship with a personal and living God. Seen in the former way, it can be analyzed beside other institutions and cultural movements. Seen in the latter way, it is not a religion in the institutional or cultural sense at all, but something quite different. Indeed, in the latter view, much of what is popularly or traditionally seen as within the realm of Christendom (e.g., religious wars or persecutions) is not Christian at all.

It is also worth remarking that there are numerous sects or cults that have borrowed ideas or language from Christendom and which are sometimes loosely regarded as part of it, but which ought properly to be considered as different religions. The usual test for inclusion in any form of Christianity would be whether a group at least believed in a triune God and specifically in Christ as God's Son (and Divine Himself); lacking this distinguishing doctrine would classify them as something other than Christian in even the most liberal and general sense of that term.

444

Page 445: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

As remarked earlier in this book, it is principally the Christian institutions that have made their way into Western historical accounts and that have had the main recorded interactions with society and with science and technology. The rise of science and the industrial age both took place in a society galvanized and energized spiritually by the Christian reformers in particular, and both must be considered in the context of the religious atmosphere in which they began. That is, the history of the relationship of technique, especially that of science, to religion is essentially the story of its relationship to Christianity, and it is to this that the next section will be devoted.

Summary

It is not easy to separate many of the religions from the culture of which they are an integral part. Of the ones considered here, Shintoism, Confucianism, and Hinduism are so bound up in their national cultures that it may be a misnomer to term them generally as religions at all, in the Western sense, and this is particularly true of Hinduism, which has only a few beliefs common to all its people. Judaism is also a national religion and claims to have universal application, though it is not at the present time missionary. Besides certain fragmented portions of Hinduism, three religions claim universality and are missionary, Buddhism, Christianity, and Islam. Of these, only the last two, along with Judaism, are monotheistic. All these have been associated with the state (or with particular economic models) in one form or another, though some, including Christianity, contain no doctrines in their scriptures to support such a partnership.

All religions contain some references to ethical codes, but only in some branches of Christianity is moral behaviour regarded as a natural consequence of having received the gift of salvation from God rather than as the means of earning it. All have at one time or another acted as the sole means for their culture of preserving and teaching knowledge, including the available techniques, but it was in Christian-influenced countries that modern science, industry, and technology arose. Most of the other religions still have the task of developing a doctrine and suitable cultural response to industrial-age and information-age ideas that arose in (to them) a foreign religious and social context. For Christianity itself to speak with authority to the people of the future, it needs to find a way of reconciling its own former partners of science and technology to itself--and this may prove to be an even more difficult task than that faced by the culturally foreign importers of science and technology. These prospects will be discussed in greater detail later.

11.3 Religion and the Scientific and Industrial Revolutions

11.3.1 Rome to Galileo The rise of science and of industry must both be considered within the total

cultural context that gave them birth. The exact causes of the Industrial Revolution may always elude historians. However, there are certain attitudes, certain cultural values, a particular world view, and specific societal conditions within which science came to the fore and the Industrial Revolution began. The fact that they did not do

445

Page 446: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

so in other cultures is telling evidence of the importance of this context. Since the societal context for both cannot--as none can--be entirely separated from its religious aspects, it is worthwhile to consider what specific influence religion has had on these developments.

As noted, Islam played an important role, preserving and developing philosophical and mathematical knowledge for many centuries while Europe declined from the days of Roman glories and also lost much of its knowledge of the past. However, it was the various forms of Christianity that had nearly exclusive direct religious influence upon Northern Europe and Great Britain, where the major historical developments of interest here took place--that is, the rise of science and of industrial technology.

Through the decline of the Roman empire and the long political and legal vacuum that was its aftermath, the Christian church--especially the Irish-led monastic tradition--gradually became the custodian not only of Europe's learning, but of its statecraft as well. Like all religious institutions, it was not the least reluctant to extend the doctrines of its scriptures wider and wider field. On the one hand, its care over the moral values of its faithful came to reach into all social realms--including the legal and political--so that state and church became inextricably entangled. On the other, learning under its care came to be scrutinized by and subject to reconciliation with or incorporation into church doctrine, so that accepted paradigms for understanding the physical world were themselves eventually moulded into doctrines, and given the weight of ecclesiastical magisterum.

Thus, scientist-philosophers used the notion that God is beyond time and reflects no change in time to explain His works--the world--and also science, the body of learning about those works. That is, the Biblical notion of progressive revelation in the context of both history and society was not applied to the physical world. It was regarded as created perfect, fixed, and unchanging. Thus, the earth did not move. Other bodies moved about it and did so in circles, for circles were the most "perfect" of motions. Even though this model was an import into Christianity from another world view--that of Greece and Rome--the fact that church scholars had adopted it gave it a weight equal to the most sacred of doctrine. In this way a common-folk or broad cultural world view came to be incorporated into church tradition, then to be reimposed upon the surrounding culture by both religious and political means whenever deviation was suspected.

This fixed view of the universe was applied not only to the physical world but also to the biological one (all species must have existed unchanged from creation on) and to the social/political one as well (the place of both state and citizen in society were fixed and immutable). The scriptures themselves were made subordinate to such traditions, even viewed as having been produced by it, so that their display of a dynamic flow of history and society was subservient to the Church teaching of a static one. Finally, the fixed world view came to be applied to knowledge itself. Aristotle's mechanics, Galen's medicine, and Ptolemy's astronomy all found a home in the church and took up permanent residence as doctrine--despite that none of these writers were Christian. What seemed like adequate and plausible explanations in the light of available knowledge were accepted as the last

446

Page 447: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

word and absolute truth on such subjects. As a result, medieval scholars came to be concerned with logic, rhetoric, and oratory as means to the end of making intellectual points to support what were viewed as obvious truths fully known. They were not very interested in making new discoveries because of their confidence in the completeness of the understandings they had. Institutional Christianity came to see itself as the guardian of a specific culture, rather than as a critic of all cultures.

Despite these rigidities in the prevailing world view, the stage was already set for the dawn of both modern science and the industrial age. A number of important points in the historical development can be identified.

First, Christians seized Toledo and Sicily from the Muslims--in 1085 and 1091, respectively--and took over the libraries and the scholarship practised there. This opened up not only Arab learning, but the complete set of Greek works, rocking scholars from their complacency and triggering a sweeping Renaissance of learning, scholastic enquiry, and art.

Second, a century later (1214-1258) the Mongols conquered both China and the Eastern portion of the Islamic world, establishing a conduit for the flow of both goods and ideas between China and Europe. During this period Roger Bacon, a Franciscan monk, criticized the basing of learning on the authorities of the past alone and advocated questioning and experimentation. In one of his letters (1249) he also mentions gunpowder, an oriental import that was to shake the secure foundations of many fortified castles dominating feudal societies with the church's help. Though he was reprimanded for his views on learning by his ecclesiastical superiors, his recommendations were later to become the basis for the science of Galileo and his successors.

Third, the centre of economic power was shifting northward, away from Rome's direct influence and watchful eye, a move marked in part by the founding of the powerful Hanseatic trading league of Northern Europe in 1241. This set the stage for political power to pass into northern hands as well.

Various industrial techniques had also become important by this time, among them metal foundries, water wheels, windmills, hay making, and the heavy horse-drawn plough, and during the thirteenth century many crafts organized guilds for the perfection and transmission of techniques among their members. This brought another power influence and knowledge base onto the scene to compete with the church; it also broadened control over economic power. By the sixteenth century, there was to be a marriage of technique and academic studies that the Greeks could never have contemplated, because by that time technique in itself had become worthy of study.

In the fifteenth century, great strides were made in the understanding of human anatomy--many made by painters such as Leonardo da Vinci who dissected cadavers for study in order to be able to accurately render the external human form. That century also saw the introduction of the most revolutionary technique of all, for paper had been made in France by 1189 and now the printing press was perfected by Gutenberg during the period 1436-1450, so that it became impossible to control the dissemination of knowledge. Thus, new ideas and physical models proliferated, and the church's adopted static world view came under increasing

447

Page 448: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

pressure. This was no more apparent than in the new models put forth to explain the motion of the sun and planets.

The complexity of Ptolemy's fixed-earth model, with some sixty circles and epicycles of motion about it, first came under attack by Copernicus, himself a priest, in 1543 when he showed that a sun-centered solar system could reduce this model to forty-eight circles. Copernicus attributed to God the skill of a clockmaker who had put the sun in the centre of the universe to govern and rule over it all--a characterization that was also to play a major role in later science. Later Tycho Brahe (1546-1601) attempted a mathematically indistinguishable compromise that had the earth fixed, the sun moving about it, and the planets orbiting the sun. His successor, Johannes Kepler, was able to use Brahe's painstakingly gathered data and derive an even simpler model based on a sun-centred solar system and only seven ellipses. Galileo drove the final nail in the Church- sanctioned Ptolemaic world view when he discovered sun spots, mountains on the moon, and moons orbiting Jupiter, thus removing the perfection of the heavenly bodies and the earth as the centre of all, by observation rather than by argument. He also used and promoted mathematical/scientific methods in his early experiments on mechanics and so laid the foundation for the modern scientific technique of examining the physical world by observation, hypothesis, prediction, and experimentation, rather than accepting a view of it based on arbitrary dogma borrowed from pagan philosophers. Unfortunately, he tended to be dogmatic himself, promoting Copernicanism as absolute truth (rather than a model) and ignoring Kepler's detailed work in favour of his own general and qualitative observations of the solar system. This dogmatism was also to guarantee him an escalating conflict with the Catholic Church.

Meanwhile, the Church was under simultaneous attack from within, for Gutenberg's presses were busy printing what turned out to be the most revolutionary book of all--the Bible. It did not take long for people to realize that there were great discrepancies between it and the church's teachings. Not only was the church's view of the physical world not to be found there, many of its other doctrines were also absent from or contradictory to it.

Those who subsequently broke with the Church were reformers at first, preaching against corruption and immorality among its officials, but they soon differed substantially in doctrinal matters as well, and after the 1520s, the teachings of Luther and Calvin became progressively and rapidly more important in Northern Europe. They taught personal responsibility for sin, salvation through grace rather than works, and they eschewed the religious institution per se as the means of (or substitute for) establishing a relationship with God. England joined the reformation in 1534 when Henry VIII had parliament confirm him as head of the church in that nation following his dispute with the Pope over a divorce he wanted. Much later, Calvin's followers in Scotland and England (Puritans) were to stress the importance of good works on the part of the elect of God, and they included in those the pursuit of science and the building of machines when such activities were undertaken to improve the lot of humanity. This Puritan attitude had much to do with the promotion and rapid spread of industrial techniques and was one of the key factors in the scientific and industrial revolutions in England. Science also was promoted there by Francis Bacon (1561-1626), the lord chancellor of England under James I.

448

Page 449: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Bacon analyzed and promoted the scientific method espoused by Roger Bacon and by Galileo.

Thus, it was a church under fire on many fronts that assessed Galileo's publications and scientific methodology in the early seventeenth century. But, it was also a church that had some experience with dissent, having run the Spanish Inquisition since 1483 and the Italian since 1542--both dedicated to the destruction of heresy and to the purification of doctrine. The Catholic Church had also clarified and reaffirmed its own doctrines and asserted the supremacy of the Pope in the Council of Trent, begun in 1545. So, when the Inquisition summoned Galileo in 1633, the trial represented a classic clash of world views, but the outcome was a foregone conclusion. Galileo was forced to recant, was placed under arrest, and his books prohibited--a ban that would last for over two centuries. To some extent, he was the author of his own misfortune, for he dogmatically insisted that the Copernican view was not just a better mathematical model for the universe (that is, an abstraction to explain it, but was also the ultimate physical reality)--something that is impossible ever to prove. After all, Earth could be the centre of the universe with everything else moving about it, even though this is not the simplest of explanations for what we observe.

The church was not prepared to move on what it had come to regard as a doctrinal point merely because Galileo's explanations were more useful. He wished to remain a good Catholic, but was convinced that the church's interpretation of the Bible, and not the Bible itself, was at fault. Neither he nor the cardinals who tried him seemed to realize that both had trespassed into areas in which they were not competent to judge. Conflicts over church doctrines about the physical world, and corresponding insistence by scientists on their models as ultimate reality, have been a feature of the intellectual landscape ever since.

11.3.2 Reason in Science and Protestantism The Catholic Church continued to fortify itself politically and doctrinally,

effectively ending both the Reformation and the pursuit of science in its realm of Southern and Western Europe. Meanwhile, the scientists and religious reformers of Northern Europe and England discovered that they had more in common with each other than merely being mutual enemies of the church that had given both birth and then cast them out.

First, they shared the scholarly attention to detail, to rigor, and to logic that was their common heritage from their scholastic predecessors. This did not mean that such scholars always agreed, but it did mean that they could argue well--and it is in the crucible of intellectual argument that many a theological and scientific truth is born or tested.

Second, they also inherited the general Christian belief that God had not only expended His creative energy as the Old Testament described, and sustained it through the power of Christ as the New taught, but that He did both in a rational way. God was therefore regarded as the best of both Hebrew and Greek ideals. Moreover, humankind, being made in His image, could also expend creative energy and do so rationally. These ideas, coupled with a new reliance on the Pythagorean concept that reality is rooted in its observable and numerically describable form,

449

Page 450: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

meant that God's works could be analysed after Him and that enlightened reason could think His thoughts after Him. Consequently, the rules of His rational universe could be deduced (and ought to be) for the sake of understanding God and applying this to the good work of improving the human condition. That is, the created order could be studied and used for good because it had an underlying rationality--and this unique idea is in fact fundamental to all science. This was expressed in Calvinism as part of God's predetermination; He had ruled by fixed decrees from the beginning of time and these were observable as the laws of nature. This very observability, however, meant that such laws were not untouchable; they were not quite a part of God Himself so they could be understood and used.

The great seventeenth century scientist Isaac Newton believed God sustained the workings of the universe, such as those of planetary motion, by supplying additional force on an ongoing basis to keep the system constant. As far as Protestant churchmen and most scientists were concerned, the Bible, properly understood, was literally true, and it could not contradict the truths discovered in the physical world, provided they were also properly interpreted.

Third, Protestant emphasis on faith as a personal experience rather than a cultural and institutional one coincided with scientific compulsion to personally doubt, investigate, hypothesize, and experiment. In its formative years, science was intensely personal and individualistic, and its great thinkers were not afraid to become highly emotional over science as the great gift of God placed in their hands to understand the world He had made. In its later years, there was a tendency to downplay this aspect of science and to present it as if it were impersonal, institutional, a finished work, and entirely value free--but it still does have the personal element, as demonstrated in Chapter 2. Even though the professed goal of modern science is the specific exclusion of all factors that depend on variations between individual experimenters, and the practice of science assumes that a reality exists that transcends both beliefs and culture, it is impossible for its practitioners to achieve transcendence themselves. Paradoxically, they are even reluctant to do so, first, because transcendence is seen as religious, and second, because the very assumption that an objective reality exists must also be questioned if science is to be consistent. That is, just as democracy must give its enemies leave to criticize and even condemn its fundamental assumptions and it would cease to be democracy if it either abandoned its absolutes or its toleration of potentially fatal opposition; so also must science encourage and even conduct a potentially fatal criticism of its own foundational presuppositions. Failure to do so would be a betrayal of those foundations.

Fourth, both science and Christianity profess to be designed for seekers of truth, (or at least seekers of reality) and to need observable facts, though not to be dependent totally upon them. That is, both claim to be the revealers of the meanings of mysteries, not the creators of myths. There is a strong and striking element of commonality in thinking, in methodology, and in application. It is expressed in the theoretical realm by the need to conceptualize, explain, predict, generalize, and synthesize--one with theological ideas and God's revelation, and the other with physical ideas and the empirically observed universe. In experience, both are personal, descriptive, and experimental. That is, theoretical knowledge satisfies

450

Page 451: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

neither; both need to relate knowledge, classify it, predict with it, and consider its consequences. Also, both are relational and transformational; they both have a imperative to be applied to and to change real people in real situations. Further, they both have a philosophy of being, a set of presuppositions, or a world view through which everything else is filtered. In addition, in both Protestant Christianity and science, these four--world view, theory, description, and application--act in mutual feedback to change one another, and cannot exist alone.

Fifth, their mutual disdain of the kind of hierarchicalism expressed by the earlier Church in both its theological/ecclesiastical and physical views, led both science and Protestant Christianity to dispense with hierarchical views of nature. There was no longer need for either to suppose the heavenly bodies were virtuously ordered, or that a host of angelic beings of various ranks were employed in maintaining heavenly movements. Similarly, there was a general loss of belief in evil spirits, the other side of the angelic host, and with it the personality and activity of Satan as a progenitor of evil faded from view. Humanity began to be viewed as autonomous--free from external influences and bonds, and able to make anything of the race. Scientists were to take this much further, however, and eventually to make differences on this point a crucial factor in a near total break with Christianity.

Galvanized by the techniques of science, the growth of industry, and an entirely new view of religion, the society of Northern Europe and Great Britain underwent a startling transformation after the seventeenth century. The momentum was slow at first, for many wars came to be fought in the complex and unstable political environment left behind by the Reformation. But scientists continued as partners with the Protestant churchmen until well into the nineteenth century, to a time when the industrial revolution was solidly underway, and the scientific one highly advanced. There was a slackening of scientific momentum at the start of the eighteenth century, but it revived as scientists turned practical in England and fostered the Industrial Revolution, and as they turned theoretical in France and promoted the political revolution there in 1789.

The opening of the Americas to settlement also had a profound influence on the European scene. The new frontier provided a population safety valve, and a place to flee from religious persecution. It also triggered a major expansion in the European economy and assisted in raising the standard of living--both for those who emigrated and for those who stayed at home. During these years, it was common to be both theologian and scientist; indeed the practice of combining the roles of ordained minister with scientific seeker-of-knowledge was widespread, especially in Great Britain.

11.3.3 The Partnership Dissolves However, this partnership was not to last, and several factors contrived to

drive a wedge between the world view of science and that of its mainly protestant church partners. One was that even though both movements had begun in a reaction from the institutionalized church, both had been busy creating institutions of their own. These institutions took on new reasons for being, entrenched positions, and dogmas that their originators did not have. The institutions of the scientific world took form as the Royal Society of London (1662) and the Paris Academy of

451

Page 452: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Sciences (1666--the same year as Newton's gravitational experiments). On the religious side, the new churches became more firmly connected to the state, though the 1662 Act of Uniformity in Britain had many dissenters, who set up their own universities and also became prominent in scientific circles. Though they had much in common at first, these institutions were also eventually to play a role in destroying that commonality. Usually begun under the protection of a church, they gradually went their own way and declared their independence of all things religious, and even of all society.

Meanwhile, many Protestant church organizations took on a nominalism, legalism, and formalism not unlike that which had characterized the Catholic Church before the reformation. They formed self-perpetuating bureaucracies and lost their sense of urgency and mission. It became possible to be a "good Christian" by occasionally attending services and giving a donation while pursuing economic gain in the service of industry with the energy of one's substance. Their theologians had also followed their earlier Catholic counterparts by adopting as absolute fact the current scientific world view, in this case that God had wound up creation like a clock and had then stepped out of the picture. As this abstraction seemed adequate, churchmen came to believe in it as dogma. Thus, they came to discount miracles as fables and to define the supernatural out of existence. For all practical purposes, their clockwork god became irrelevant to real (empirical) life.

At the same time, the Catholic Church had not only consolidated its doctrinal hold on the peoples it influenced, but it had also come to terms with science--not adopting its world view but tolerating it at arm's length and making an attempt to integrate an understanding of its methodology into the faith. Thus, by 1820, Galileo's books were no longer forbidden, and scientific investigations were thriving in some Catholic nations as well as in the Protestant ones. This was particularly true in France where, through the turmoil of revolution, church and state had a very rocky relationship and intellectuals had great freedom from church control.

Meanwhile, the world view of scientists was changing, too. Flushed by the success of both the scientific method and of industrial revolution's machine and by a rising standard of living, they developed four ideas much further than they had before and adopted the product as the guiding principles of a comprehensive world view of a very ambitious scope.

First, their own mechanistic view of nature was gradually reinforced by their successes to the point where it replaced the personal God who sustained the universe, and Christian belief was discarded, with God being reconceptualized or represented in daily practice as a vague personality termed "nature." Because such a god had at best only created, then stepped back and let nature take its course, he was impossibly remote, could not be experienced and was therefore essentially unknowable. To the deists among scientists, God existed only as a creative force; he had no personality and certainly no personal interest in the real world or in any individuals. He was an abstraction like any other and could therefore be redefined. Moreover, the Christian scriptures themselves were subjected to a new analysis based on the exclusion of miracles as even theoretical propositions. Thus, many scientists first rejected any intersection of the supernatural with the known physical world, then the historical accuracy of the Bible, and finally Biblical doctrines as well,

452

Page 453: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

for if its contents could be regarded as substantially mythological in some areas, then none of it need be considered authoritative or legitimate knowledge. In many circles, this vague deism was, of course, carried much further and became either disinterested agnosticism or hostile atheism.

Second, the philosophical techniques of science--rationalism and empiricism--gradually became elevated to positions of unquestioned, absolutes achieving a status equivalent to apodictic religious doctrine. This version of materialism ultimately came to be known in science as logical positivism--the view that positively asserts the sole existence and knowability of logical reasoning and empirical data, and that explicitly defines out of existence the supernatural (The corresponding political expression was the Marxist doctrine of dialectical materialism). That is, their world view went beyond indifference to religion, and became hostile. So great was confidence in science by 1900 that it was believed that the essential workings of the universe were now well known in the absolute sense and that only a few details--such as more places after the decimal in certain physical constants--needed to be settled. It was inconceivable that a god could have worked outside a technique knowable to science if he existed, and these were believed to be already known by humanity, so there was no need to propose there were higher ones known only to him by which he could have created and sustained the universe or worked miracles--say, of healing. Such a god could be treated as a dispensable hypothesis, as irrelevant to science. For all practical purposes, Newton had created the world, for the power of his mechanics and calculus served to explain all but a few minor details. It appeared to be plainly obvious to scientists that the physical world was indeed as it could ordinarily be observed to be. Newtonianism was no longer an abstraction, it was the real thing. Such adoptions of current scientific models and world views as though they were absolute truth had happened before, to later regret, but, as with many lessons of history, this one had also been forgotten.

Unfortunately for the nineteenth century view that only a few more decimal points needed to be calculated in some constants, those few niggling details were later to give birth to the revolutions of relativity theory and quantum mechanics--revolutions that shook the theoretical foundations of science and caused a few cracks to appear in the epistemological ones as well.

Third, scientism (for by now it was a full-blown belief system) expanded upon the humanism of the Greeks and of the renaissance thinkers. Since God either did not exist at all or did not matter, humanity was self-evidently the autonomous pinnacle of all observable nature. At most, God needed only be consulted on those questions where humans had difficulty finding scientific answers. The world was the human oyster, to do with as desired, and with no higher accountability. There were no bounds, no one need submit to another authority and no one needed a social or other context to give meaning to self. The whole cosmos existed and drew meaning from human observations; indeed, it could well be regarded as having been created by humankind, for the rational/empirical world view was the only ultimate reality. Human beings could therefore recreate the cosmos; they had either collectively become god or they could define new ones for themselves.

453

Page 454: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This new scientific humanism had a great deal going for it, because the record of achievement and progress was substantial, and there was therefore reason for the great optimism both would continue indefinitely. It seemed to nineteenth century scientists that the human race had pulled itself up by its own unaided efforts from poverty, disease, and superstition, and if not already in a golden age, it was on the very edge of one. All problems could be solved. Unlimited wealth was available for exploitation and the inherent goodness of people was evident in the technology they had created. Soon war would be abolished and a glorious age of health, wealth, harmony and global community would be entered upon. In the process of coming to this view, "progress" came to be a god word of status akin to "nature." The assumption that humanity was progressing to a higher state was unquestioned and unquestionable--it was considered a self-evident fact.

Fourth, the scope of progress was extrapolated backward as well as forward in time, and a number of theories of evolution came forward in the early part of the nineteenth century. One effect of these was to produce a naturalistic explanation for the presence of humans on the earth, one tied to the material world alone and contained entirely within the context of naturally observable processes. Thus, the mechanistic view of the universe came to be applied to humans as well; biological as well as physical systems all must have progressed (evolved) to higher forms by past operations of the law of progress in a purely mechanistic universe. Several means had been proposed whereby this mechanistic evolution might have taken place, but experimentation refuted most, and there was no popularizer for such models to make them more widely acceptable. However, the stage was set for someone who could produce a plausible theory. Then, in 1858, Charles Darwin published his idea that evolution had taken place by the natural selection of traits according to their survival value in changing environments (survival of the fittest). In addition, he was able to communicate this notion effectively to the public. Evolution had its mechanism; moreover, it was firmly placed in the past and could not be refuted by experimentation.

Though acceptance in some scientific circles and many religious ones was slow at first, the philosophical ground had been well-prepared, and evolution by natural selection eventually swept all other naturalistic theories of origins away. Along the way, it gave rise to a new hierarchicalism--this time of species--ordered according to the height (i.e., the complexity) to which each had evolved. This was later to have disastrous effects when applied to the "races" of humanity, when science came to be employed to "prove" one or another nationality or skin colour to be inherently superior, because of supposedly being more highly evolved.

Moreover, natural selection came to be applied to social, political, religious, economic, and moral systems as well as the biological. In these fields, there was even less inclination to regard this kind of evolution as a model or an abstraction--it quickly became the only possible expression of ultimate reality. For example, human opinions were part of the social machine; opinions therefore and necessarily determined social and moral patterns, which were relative, not absolute, for they too could evolve and would necessarily and inevitably do so to a higher and better order of existence. Christian morality had survived in a world that had rejected its theology, now it too was set aside. The old morality was replaced by a new one,

454

Page 455: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

based not on absolute divine fiat, but on changing human opinion--higher and more sophisticated principles than right and wrong applied to evolved mankind. That there was in practice little difference between the new morality and the old immorality was not much remarked upon.

It is important to note, however, that there is no logical connection between theories of social evolution and the biological ones of Darwin, so that evidence for one lends the other no support, and the refutations, problems, or failures of one cannot be used to criticize the other.

Thus, by the end of the nineteenth century, those phenomena associated with what is called religion in other cultures had been abdicated by a largely nominal Christianity, and had been taken over by a confident and aggressive scientism which, though it by that time tended to eschew all religions, was filling the same intellectual, philosophical, and practical role, and could be properly regarded as a religion itself.

Conservatives in the religious community had by this time so little knowledge of, interest in, or commonality with science that they were unable and unwilling to debate the issues on scientific grounds. They had so thoroughly committed themselves to a view of the physical world as the product of a God of the clockworks they had forgotten this idea was an abstraction and could not be proven to be the physical reality itself. When science changed course and committed itself instead to a new model that conservative Christians could not accept, the evolutionary model, a classic irresolvable clash of world views resulted, one that gradually drove Christians into silence, accommodation, or an intellectual ghetto.

Thus matters stood until well into the twentieth century, when events began once again to force changes, not only in both world views, but in the societal context in which world views are formed and exercised. Before considering the direction in which these are now going, a more detailed examination of the creation/evolution debate is in order. It is not only an important case study in differing world views, but has recently been restored as a debatable topic principally through the efforts of a new breed of conservative Christians who are not prepared to assume that the last word on the subject was said in the nineteenth century.

11.4 The Debate Over Origins--an Illustration of World View Clashes Because of timetabling conflicts at MUSHEAT, Nellie is taking her biology

course at the local public community college. Hoping to finish at least his first year of university before completing high school, Lucas is also enrolled in this course. The instructor is Ed Mandel, and this scene takes place the night before their seminar at the university, close to the end of class time as Mandel is summarizing his lesson.

Mandel: This great panorama presented by the evolution of the universe and of life from nothing at all ought to result in a sense of awe at the wisdom of nature. We are who and where we are because of being the best adapted product of that grand process, superior to all else, and veritable lords of all we survey. We do not need to hypothesize that some god created us, for we have created the gods. Man is the epitome...

455

Page 456: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Lucas: (interrupting) How can you be so sure of all this?Mandel: (smiling coldly) What do you mean?Lucas: I mean, you seem pretty dogmatic about it. How do you know it all

happened the way you say, when you weren't there to see it? Isn't evolution a theory rather than an absolute fact?

Mandel: Evolution is a theory. It is also an absolute fact. We are as certain that it happened as it is possible to be about anything in science.

Lucas: But the "certain" mechanism seems to change with each new generation of scientists. There isn't much in common between biology text chapters on evolution that are more than five years apart. For instance, isn't natural selection now rather discredited?

Mandel: It makes no difference whether we know what the mechanism is or not. Even if every possible mechanism for evolution were proven to be wrong, we would still know it happened.

Lucas: How would we?Mandel: Because we're here, and there is no other possible explanation other

than evolution.Lucas: But that's an ex post facto argument; it's not valid to say that the

present determines what history must have been, only that the present is a result of whatever history was. Aren't there other possibilities?

Mandel: Well, for one thing, you can see it in embryology. You started out as a one-celled creature, passed through a variety of stages including that of a fish with gills, and became a human. Thus your own development recapitulates that of the species.

Lucas: I've read about the ridges you are referring to as "gills." They never actually serve such a purpose, and develop into important structures in themselves. Besides, no one who knew anything about it could ever mistake a human embryo at any stage of development for the embryo of any other species, so that argument won't hold water either. Not only that, but it has been conclusively shown that the man who first suggested that theory faked his photographs, and the whole thing is now discredited.

Mandel: What other explanation could there possibly be for the existence of complex organisms like ourselves than that they all evolved by chance through natural processes? You cannot deny the similarities among various forms of life that prove their evolutionary relationship.

Lucas: Similarities don't prove relationship, even if they may suggest it. If you see two similar buildings in downtown Vancouver, you don't think one evolved from the other, though you might suppose both were designed by the same architect.

Mandel: You're not one of these creationists, are you? What's your name again?

Lucas: Lucas Dominic, sir.Mandel: (startled) Dominic? You're not related to that old Bible preacher that

used to live up near Cultus Lake are you?Lucas: (biting his lip and speaking almost inaudibly) I live at Berea, sir, and Mr.

Dominic is my guardian.

456

Page 457: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Mandel: So the old fellow is still infecting impressionable boys with the disease of Christianity, eh? What do you think he would say to a public debate on the believability of evolution versus that of the creation myths? Oh, never mind--I'll go phone him myself right now. Just wait here.

As soon as Mandel has rushed out the door, an excited buzz of conversation erupts. A few sidelong glances are shot Lucas' way, but others seem embarrassed to speak to him. Finally, Nellie leans over and whispers:

Nellie: What's Berea?Lucas: (in a very pained voice, and after a long pause) It's an orphanage.Nellie: (startled) I'm sorry, I didn't know such things existed any more.Lucas: (looking forward) I'm the last one there. (and then, turning accusingly

to her) You weren't much help.Nellie: Well, I couldn't get a word in between you two. Besides, you have little

to lose.Lucas: What do you mean?Nellie: This is a required course for me. I have to pass it. You can always take

it again later.Lucas: What are you getting at?Nellie: Mandel fails anyone who defends creation in the class.Lucas: I didn't. I'm not certain what I believe in myself; I just thought he was

too sure of himself, so I challenged him. Look, I feel sick and I don't want to be around when he comes back; I'm heading out.

Lucas leaves, and a few minutes later Mandel enters by the other door. He is rubbing his hands together and seems pleased with himself. He immediately notices Lucas is missing, and remarks to the rest of the class:

Mandel: He actually agreed to do it. We'll settle his hash. A few invited experts will make mincemeat of a country preacher, and I'll arrange for it all to happen in front of a few thousand people and some television cameras.

* * * * *

Debates over scientific issues arise for a variety of reasons. These may include disputes over the data employed, the methods of doing the research, the qualifications of the researchers, the validity of the results, or even personality conflicts. Many such disagreements can be solved by attempting to repeat the experiments under a variety of conditions to see whether the suggested conclusions are indeed justified. Because of the human element, a variety of ethical issues may become involved in the doing of science, but these too are in many cases resolvable within the scientific community. After all, the premise of the information age is that mismanagement, sloppy research, bad analysis, wrong conclusions, or outright deceit will eventually be exposed to the light of public scrutiny and be corrected. In such situations, there may be no need to appeal to outside absolute ethical authority for assistance in reaching a resolution. The experiments either demonstrate the validity of a theory or they do not.

However, some issues that are not as straightforward touch on the very meaning of science, as well as motivations for doing it and interpretations of the

457

Page 458: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

results. As usual, such fundamental issues are further complicated by the ethical or religious questions that are often related to them. An interesting illustration of this is the debate surrounding the theories competing to answer the question: "How did we all get here?" This not only is one of the most fundamental of such issues but also is frequently made a focal point for disputes between science and religion. In one form or another, the question of origins and its principal answers have been around from the beginning of recorded history. The usual answers are often broadly classified as either "creationary" or "evolutionary." However, the meanings of these words vary as much as do the meanings attached to words with ethical content (such as "good"). Moreover, the boundaries between the two principal positions are not always distinct or easy to determine, even though some modern-day protagonists insist that they are. Neither is it always clear what, if any, are the ethical consequences of holding to one position or another. In their most general form, the major views of origins can be summarized as follows:

o Strictly materialist view The universe and all that is in it, including humanity, can be explained in

terms of time, chance, and physical laws. There is no design, purpose, and direction; what is, simply is. All that can be observed is all that there is, and this in turn is entirely the product of time, random events, and the operation of natural processes.

o Deistic/mechanistic view The universe was created, as were the physical laws governing its operation.

After that, the deity stepped back from the process and allowed everything to run its course without interference. Life, including humanity, is the product of the predetermined operation of created processes. If the universe and the life it contains have any purpose or direction, it is to a large extent built-in.

o Theistic view The universe and its physical laws were created. At certain points in the

subsequent action of time, chance, and natural processes, a deity may have intervened. This might have been done once to cause life to come into being, and again to provide a distinct nature to human life. The particular involvement of the deity may imply some measure of purpose and direction to life. It may also imply some accountability to that deity for humanity as a whole. Whether such purposes are knowable or not is debatable.

o Supernatural viewThe universe and all that is in it, including humanity, exists by intelligent and

personal design. It had a definite beginning, has a definite purpose for being, and will have a definite end. Natural processes operate within a purposefully created framework of both time and space. All of creation is accountable to the creator.

There are a variety of positions on the date of origin, on the duration of various creative or evolutionary processes, and on mechanisms for origins within each group. Summaries such as these four are very broad; they contain statements about both the cosmos in general and the origin of human life in particular. Models for origins that fit in one of the first two categories are, roughly speaking,

458

Page 459: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

evolutionary. Those that fit one of the latter two are to a greater or lesser extent creationist. Some theories have elements from two or more of these groups, and indeed the variations shade almost imperceptibly from one to the next. It is not necessary to examine all of the possibilities in order to understand the debate over origins. However, it is important in debating such issues to distinguish among

o the origin of matter, that is, of the initial cosmos,o the origin of the earth in the cosmological context, o the origin of life from nonlife, o the development and speciation of plants and animals, and o the special case of the origin of human beings. Many scientists would confine the term "evolution," for example, to just the

fourth and fifth of these issues. Others use it for all five. A creationist, on the other hand, would accept variation within species as the only observable form of evolution (i.e., microevolution, if she used the word at all), and might deny that any of the others have ever happened.

Actual debate on such issues tends to involve mostly the extremes, with the deists and theists--who would rather be accommodative than raise issues--being largely ignored, or declining to participate on various grounds. Within their immediate circles, both conservative creationists and strict materialists tend to be outraged at any suggestion that the other side (or any middle ground) has any credence whatsoever. It is important to remember, therefore, that in the detailed discussion of major issues presented in this chapter, mere provocation is not the goal, but rather the inducement to think. As the following section concludes, the point is to consider the nature of scientific debate; a particularly provocative topic is a useful foil to do so. The reader is free to elaborate any position, indeed is encouraged to attempt this, but only after considering positions on some of the issues of concern to the major participants.

Philosophy and World View

Which model for origins is held by a person to be true depends on their world views as it touches such issues as the existence and attributes of deity, the revelation that such a deity is alleged to have provided, and the relationship of human beings to that deity. There are also consequences of holding particular beliefs about origins.

First, world-view considerations, and the degree of allegiance to those views, tend to determine attitudes toward interpreting data that bear on the question of origins. Whatever that may be, scientists necessarily work within the framework of some such world view, fully convinced of the reasonableness of their beliefs. It is therefore natural for them to filter their scientific experiences through their world view in a way that yields results supporting their beliefs. There is nothing wrong with this as long as those involved are aware of it. However, in some cases, it may be that there does not exist any conceivable data or argument that could ever be accepted as invalidating the world view held. Such a position, in effect, removes the matter in question from the realm of the scientific altogether, for something that is

459

Page 460: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not even conceivably falsifiable by scientific methods is also not verifiable by them either.

Thus, to some the deity is creator by very definition, and a random universe without that creative power is inconceivable. A completely mechanistic universe is a denial of the existence of the overseeing deity in whom they trust. Even if they cannot explain how creation was performed (in the scientific sense), and regardless of how many people claim that the physical evidence not only supports but completely documents materialism, they must still say, "We absolutely know that we were created."

To others, the world can only conceivably consist of the material, and it is meaningless to suggest that anything called the "supernatural" could exist or be perceived if it did. That is, they must believe in some form of evolution, as generally defined above, and do so regardless of the current state of the evidence for or against; the alternative is not possible even to consider. Theirs is an episteme that requires evolutionary explanations for origins lest it be self-contradictory. That is, even if every mechanism for it were shown to be impossible, strict rational/empiricists and materialists must still say, "We absolutely know that we evolved." Even if they do not completely reject religious accounts of origins, they will consider them as subject to scientific analysis and potential refutation, for the ideal of this brand of science is that no beliefs, including their own, are free from the possibility of being falsified by actual experiment.

Others, who are between these two extremes, may want to believe to some extent in a creation, but are also persuaded to accept the majoritarian view that evolution is an established fact rather than a model. This group seeks one of a variety of possible accommodations between two extremes, but their faith is in a world view more compatible with materialistic models than supernatural ones.

Second, answers to the question of whether or not there is a God who created are related to whether one believes that such a God has the authority to make ethical demands. If a creator does exist, and has made ethical rules, then such demands constitute a higher authority than human opinion, reasoning, methodology, or law. To a greater or lesser extent, this is the position of most religions, though they may differ on the details of ethical demands. If, on the other hand, human life exists solely because of the operation of time, chance, and natural processes, then no external moral authority need be assumed. That is, if any meaning exists for humanity as a whole or for human ethics in particular, it can be found only in the natural world, and by using natural processes. In summary, some claim that there are answers to meaning questions and preexisting rules of ethics that affect the entire human social dynamic and that these transcend the natural order. Others claim that answers can only be found in the observable natural order, for there is nothing else. One possible conclusion from this is that the principle of "survival of the fittest" can be applied not only to the development of life itself, but also (in some fashion) to moral rules--indeed that it is itself the only moral rule. This conclusion is problematic, for it makes morality not only relative to the situation, but also to the evolutionary place of the one applying the rules, and it is unclear how this could in the end produce anything but hedonism.

460

Page 461: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It is not hard to see that this debate involves far more than science and religion, for anyone who ascribes transcendence to any aspect of the human experience, in such things as art, music, or philosophy, will also be in conflict with strict materialists.

Recent Developments

Many people are happy with what they see as a compromise on one of the two middle positions outlined above, and it was on this centre ground that most North Americans probably stood before the 1950s. However, deists and theists may have the most difficulty formulating a belief framework for their position, for their desire is to find a middle ground that allows for the action of a creator, but that still accepts the mechanism of evolution as an established fact. It is not easy to do this when the underlying principles of two positions they are attempting to reconcile contradict each other so fundamentally and so thoroughly.

Moreover, since that time, new conservative creationist groups have arisen and the debate over origins has been rejoined in earnest. This has resulted in the founding of such organizations as the Institute for Creation Research and the Creation Research Society, both of which consist of scientists committed to working and publishing within a creationist world view. Much of the material produced by these groups is sharply at variance with the interpretations of the majority of modern scientists and is severely criticized or ignored by mainstream schools and journals.

The new creationists assert that time, chance, and natural processes could not possibly have produced life in the first place or resulted in any evolution afterward other than minor variations. They claim that the fossil record is better evidence for creation than for evolution, and that neither biology nor geology support an evolutionary scenario. Many (not all) of them doubt or deny that the earth is very old, suggesting an age of thousands rather than billions of years. They flatly deny there is any evidence for human evolution. They attempt to conduct the debate on scientific rather than religious terms, and try to use scientific methods to demonstrate their points, though few in the majority scientific community will engage them on those terms. As will be seen below, those at the other extreme have counterattacked in force on all fronts.

While one could argue about the degree of success both sides have had in convincing the general public of the rightness of their views, a major effect has been to polarize the lively discussion, all but excluding the middle ground from the debate.

Belief and Faith

Thus, someone like Steven Jay Gould will say: "Well, evolution is a theory. It is also a fact." (Montagu, p 118) and also: "'Scientific Creationism' is a self-contradictory, nonsense phrase . . . dogma, not science" (Montagu, p. 120). Another in the same vein is Isaac Asimov, who says of Creationists [ibid, p 184] that they use the general belief of most peoples in a Creator as evidence there must have been

461

Page 462: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

one, and dismisses all such accounts as myths, none inherently more credible than any other. The essential point made at this end of the spectrum is that the very idea of creation is inherently religious and so not open to examination. It can therefore have no connection whatever to science. Most of its writers do go further, however, and assert that creation is not only unscientific, but actually false.

In a piece written as a direct response to Asimov for the Institute for Creation Research, Henry Morris responds that creationists do not use such arguments, but that evolutionists: "use the argument that 'all scientists believe evolution' as the main proof for evolution." (Impact #99 pamphlet) It ought to be clear that majoritarian arguments are not sound logic, so that it makes little difference whether either side actually uses them or not.

Both creationist and evolutionist scientists believe themselves to be engaged in legitimate and experimentally sound searches for knowledge. The result is an indefinite impasse, for apart from a religious-style conversion experience, neither can ever convince the other to abandon what they believe to be valid science consistent with their world view. And yet, truth is unique, for the fundamental principle with which science begins forces one to believe there is such a thing as a 'right answer' to a scientific investigation of the physical universe, that the cosmos as we perceive it today only has one history. The assumed uniqueness of truth would appear to mean that one side or the other could be proven wrong, but as indicated above, no such purported proof could ever be accepted by the "losing" side. Asimov: "...creationism has clearly lost. But creationists, placing myth above reason, refuse to accept the decision..." [ibid p. 191] Morris: "Asimov, in his anti-creationist harangue, does not attempt to offer even one slight scientific evidence for evolution." [ICR pamphlet]

The problem is that the issue is not decidable by physical means, because at least part of the argument is not about science at all. The difference in world views causes the two groups to search in different places for different things and to interpret what they do find consistently with what they already believe. Because the question of the existence or otherwise of a creator's initiation of the universe is fixed in the empirically unknowable remote past, it is not decidable by the kind of mechanistic process that the strict rational/empiricist claims science to be, and so there is no possibility of resolving the impasse in general terms. One of the difficulties in analysing a debate of this sort is that the two sides do not agree on what it is that they are debating--science or religion. Indeed, both sides will claim that theirs is a scientific position and that the other's is a religious one.

Turning to the scientific aspects, evolutionists say that having a falsifiable mechanism for evolution makes it inherently superior to creation on the grounds the theory of revelation by a deity is un-falsifiable, and is therefore not science but accepted by blind faith. Asimov: "To those who are trained in Science, creationism seems like a bad dream ... a renewed march of an army of the night risen to challenge free thought and enlightenment." [ibid, p 183] They are not concerned if they have disagreements about the possible mechanism for some aspect of evolution: "However much scientists argue their differing beliefs in details of evolutionary theory ... they firmly accept the evolutionary process itself." [ibid, p 187]

462

Page 463: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Creationists claim that such an insistence that evolution must have taken place in turn constitutes the faith of the other side. Morris says in the ICR pamphlet: "Evolutionists walk by faith, not by sight!" One side accuses the other of naivety in belief systems, and the other counters that proposals to fill in evolutionary 'gaps' involve more wishful thinking and flights of fancy than factual evidence. Both believe that the opposing world view is mythological, fragile, and unscientific, and they do so principally because of their opposing world views. In addition, the two sides reject each other's interpretation of things like fossil evidence, claiming that this too is based on faith and not reason.

Thermodynamics

When they turn from the philosophical to consider more specific scientific matters, creationists argue that the idea of a high degree of order in both the cosmos and in living organisms could arise spontaneously from a primordial chaos is a violation of the entropy principle, also known as the second law of thermodynamics. They assert it is not good enough to claim that matter in chaos is inherently able to organize itself or that the provision of raw energy to a system causes its order and information to increase spontaneously without any previously existing program. Evolutionists reject these arguments as simplistic and assert that energy input to the earth from the sun is sufficient for evolution (i.e., the earth is not a closed system, so the second law is inapplicable). They also search for mechanisms whereby order can increase even in closed systems, but the examples of this, such as the growth of crystals in solution, are rejected by creationists as irrelevant. They insist that there are no known physical laws by which the voluminous information coded by a DNA molecule could self-organize.

It should be noted that the two sides profess to be unable to understand each other's arguments on these points, and they differ sharply on the meaning and applicability of entropy to the whole question of evolution.

Mechanism--Chance and Design

An important argument of the creationists derived originally from an analogy to the old Copernican "clockwork" view of the universe. If one found a watch somewhere, it would be immediately obvious from its very intricacy that it did not come about by chance and that no one would dispute that a designer was involved. A single living cell, much less a human being, displays an intricacy of far greater order than does a watch, and therefore also implies a designer. To put it another way, if one beholds a woven wicker basket full of flowers, one would immediately "know" the basket had a maker. However, the flowers are much more complex. Surely therefore, the argument goes, they have a maker too.

Asimov responds: "This argument seems unanswerable ... [but] to surrender to ignorance and call it God has always been premature ... the complexity of the universe ... is not in itself an argument for a creator." [ibid, p 184] Morris contradicts

463

Page 464: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

this in his response: "The principles of mathematical probability and scientific causality certainly do not constitute a 'surrender to ignorance,' but provide a compelling demonstration that complex systems do not originate out of chaotic systems by random processes."

Asimov is correct in stating that this objection is unanswerable; the question of a cosmic design is moot to one who does not or will not conceptualize such a designer. The paradigms of modern science require that the act of such design be demonstrated, even repeatable. Familiarity with the design of machines in actual experience makes the origin of the watch obvious; but nothing less than seeing God in the act, not even doing it in His stead, can satisfy the strict materialist. As things stand, they have at best nothing but what some other people hold to be His word for evidence, and their paradigm for knowledge rejects that as insufficient and circular reasoning.

However, creationists go much too far if they assert the existence of the clockworks proves that the God of the clockworks also exists. At best, it is only a hint that this may be so, not a proof. Existence of a watch maker or a flower basket weaver is only inferred, then believed on the basis of what appears to be reasonable and probable evidence; and this is the best this argument can do for creationists. However, this is also the nature of scientific evidence in general; even the balance of a preponderance of empirical evidence does not constitute an absolute logical proof for a theory, only reasonable support for one. That is, the best conclusion that can be made of this kind of argument is negative--no known physical mechanism could cause the basket, clock (or flower) to self assemble, so asserting that it must have done so places the evolutionist in at least the awkward position of having to assert the existence of a mechanism even though there may be no evidence for one.

Asimov fingers the real issue, for the question here is whether we are ignorant of the existence of the creator, or whether there are reasonably reliable evidences for the existence of one. Science alone is inadequate to answer this question, for the supernatural is outside its realm, and therefore creationists need more than the existence of clockworks to offer it as scientific evidence, they need verifiable traces of the creator's work to carry this argument. The Greeks had it right in their theology of the unknown god. If there was a creator who operated from outside the realm of the physical to create it, he could be known within the creation only by revelation. On the other hand, scientists cannot use the inability of their methodology to examine the supernatural as proof the latter does not exist. Neither can it be forgotten that there are scientists who are also creationists, who believe in a supernatural god-creator employing evolution as one of his mechanisms, so this issue is not as sharply focused as some claim it to be.

Evolutionists at one time believed the entire past history of man, life, the Earth, solar system and the whole cosmos could be completely explained in terms of physical processes now being observed (This principle, in general, is called uniformitarianism). Creationists said that in the ultimate origin of the universe there had to be different processes, because those presently operating are in capable of explaining the very beginning. In particular, they asserted the mathematical impossibility of chance mutations producing better adapted life forms, rather than

464

Page 465: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

simply genetic damage, with its accompanying information loss. They reject Thomas Huxley's comparison of evolution to a large number of monkeys at typewriters pressing keys at random, and given enough time producing the entire works of Shakespeare--even this, they say, is clearly impossible even in all the billions of years one might wish to grant the universe, and the probabilities of producing a single protein by chance are far lower.

Uniformitarianism is now less often advanced as a point of argument. Faced with the actual calculations, Huxley's descendents have abandoned the line of argument that given enough time even the most improbable events must occur.

Evolutionists now concede physical laws must have been different in the first few moments of the universe; indeed they claim that the processes that took place then determined what those laws would be. One sees more reference to catastrophe and sudden, sweeping change in their literature than to the old gradualism. However, they reject the creationists statistical and probabilistic arguments as irrelevant; after all, the presence of life on Earth demands some explanation, regardless of its apparent improbability, and they are not prepared to give it other than a materialistic one. They point to the driving force of natural selection, asserting that the changes in life forms are not random at all, but driven by the need to adapt to changed environments. Creationists respond that anatomical adaptions have to come from somewhere, and the only mechanism proposed to this point is mutation. Changes could be selected among after they occur (or if a suitable genetic variant were already present), but they have to happen in the first place, and this puts the argument back into the realm of vanishingly small probabilities.

In the 1990s, Johnson, Dembski, and others brought forth refined and updated arguments that the complexity of natural systems shows characteristics of design, quite apart from what one may believe about a designer. They argue, for instance, that many systems have an irreducible complexity that could not have evolved in stages because any one component or behaviour of the whole has no particular survival value. Among complete complex organisms they may cite the woodpecker and hummingbird, among large structures the elephant's trunk or giraffe's neck, and on a smaller scale the living cell.

The Fossils

Creationists claim that the fossil record contains the strongest evidence against evolutionary scenarios; that it shows the sudden appearance of the major types of life in the various strata, and that it shows a complete lack of the many transitional forms that would have had to have existed in order for a gradualist mechanism to have ever operated. Indeed, many more lines have now been traced to the Cambrian, now known to have had a rich diversity of complex life forms, a fact they claim to be entirely at variance with Darwinism. They assert that the vast numbers of fossils now catalogued do not show inter-family gradualism, and that it is therefore safe to conclude (from a statistical argument) that still larger numbers never will. They sometimes question the entire concept of the geologic column, claiming that it too is a fanciful interpretation of fragmented data, and that the

465

Page 466: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

indexing of fossils by rocks and of rocks by fossils constitutes circular reasoning. They further assert that numerous examples of rock strata laid down in the "wrong" order refutes evolution absolutely.

Evolutionists are confident there are indeed abundant cases of transitional fossils, and that the geologic column, while not existing entire in any part of the Earth, can legitimately be pieced together by comparing similar strata from many places. They are unconcerned about "wrong order" strata, referring to them as "overthrusts" in most cases, and maintaining confidence that they can eventually explain the others as well. They also claim that, in general, geology is the creationists' weakest point, and that the latter would have to do a great deal of work to explain what is seen in the Earth's crust consistently with any of their current sub-models.

However, evolutionists have also now conceded the fossil record does not support the thesis of uniformly gradual changes over millions of years via natural selection. A number of suggestions for a replacement mechanism have been made, chief among them the 'punctuated equilibrium' scenario. This hypothesis holds that evolution proceeded in sudden bursts, perhaps triggered by vast ecological changes or multiple mutations from large doses of radiation. Large changes over a short period of time would leave few or no traces in the fossil record, and this is much more in accordance with what is actually found. In an interesting side-development, this theory has found much greater favour among Marxists, who have promoted it actively because revolution fits their world view better than slow evolution.

This very willingness of evolutionists to change their theories in the light of new data is regarded by them as a great strength, for they point to the unwillingness of creationists to do the same. The latter maintain that changing theories is a weakness, and that holding to revealed religious ideas is their strength.

Creationists use the difficulties with interpreting the fossils as evidence against evolution, but their opponents are unconcerned. If one interpretation fails to work, another can always be tried out as a model; moreover they are confident that the fossils will eventually provide entirely adequate proof that large scale evolution has taken place. For their part, Creationists would look on even the most complete taxonomy of life forms, including intermediates between the various families and orders, as nothing more than an interesting chart of similarities, not as proof that any relationship by descent exists. Indeed, they regard such similarities as evidence of the handiwork of a common designer. From a logical point of view, these two conclusions are equally valid. Whether the evidence does equally support both is another matter.

The Age of the Earth, and Related Issues

Some creationists dispute the multi-billion year time scale favoured by evolutionists. While there is evidence in things such as magnetic field, lunar orbit decay, and sediment deposition (land to ocean and space to Earth/Moon system) for the young Earth this group often advocates, almost all scientists interpret radioactive dating methods as authoritatively yielding much greater ages.

466

Page 467: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Geologists are virtually unanimous in asserting that there is ample evidence in the pattern of sedimentary rock formation and erosion for a very long earth life.

Creationists also have the difficulty posed by light and its speed relative to the apparent size of the universe. They must decide whether to assert that the light from stars was created in transit so that the universe had an apparent age, or perhaps, as a few have, that its speed may decay over time, or that the geometry of the universe is not actually as commonly accepted.

Asimov says of the apparent age suggestion: "Can it be that the Creator is a cruel and malicious prankster, with a vicious and adolescent sense of humour?" [ibid, p 189] Morris responds: "There is no deception involved at all. As a matter of fact, the world does not even look old, except to the distorted vision of an evolutionist." [ICR pamphlet] It should also be noted at this point that some creationists do accept an old earth model, and do not regard these issues as problems. For example, among Christians, there are a variety of hypotheses to stretch the six days of creation into a sufficient number of years to harmonize with the evolutionary scale. However, all such compromises tend to be roundly denounced by those at both ends of the spectrum.

Creationists claim that evolutionists have their own problems with time, and that the data do not unequivocally support either a young or an old earth. They say that the indicators for a young earth need to be properly explained, as must the nature and significance of the assumptions inherent in radioactive dating methods. They point out the problem of the missing mass--galaxies are not observed to have enough of it to have stayed together for as long as their claimed age. Mainstream cosmologists have conceded this is a problem, and are actively trying to find the missing mass. Creationists add that there is no evident source for dust and comets in the solar system that could account for their presence for longer than about thirty thousand years, because such small particles are constantly being swept up by the larger bodies. Some even question the nuclear model for the sun's energy, stating that the observed gravitational collapse is sufficient for current energy output, and suggesting that the predicted but not yet observed flow of neutrinos needed to support the nuclear model will never be found, and that this too supports a young solar system scenario. A new argument is that the existence of halos characteristic of the decay of a very short-lived polonium isotope in granitic rocks indicates an Earth solid from the moment of creation, rather than cooling over time from a molten state. They also assert that rock formations are fragile, and could not bend into the domed upthrusts that are so common except when they were first formed and the rocks were still quite plastic, denying that layering and upthrusting needed to take place over long periods of time.

Evolutionists believe that they are on very solid ground on the age of the Earth, despite the many interesting questions and issues connected with this. For instance, they dismiss the problem of cometary and dust supply by hypothesizing a cloud of such materials at some distance from the Sun, and from which material is periodically ejected into the solar system proper.

Creationists have become somewhat reluctant to offer a specific date for beginnings, so they have confined themselves to criticizing the specific dating methods and assumptions of the other side. If Bible-based, they may claim that the

467

Page 468: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

flood of Noah is entirely sufficient to explain the fossil record without any assumption of age beyond a few thousand years, but this group had not until recently worked out such an explanation in any great detail, and is subjected to some of the most scathing attacks on this particular issue, for it is at this point that the lack of detailed work leaves them most vulnerable.

Life From Non Life

A critical issue, on which there seems destined to be no end to speculation, is the way in which life could have arisen from non-living matter in the very first instance. Lately, this discussion has focused on the possible manufacture of life forms from non-living chemicals in the laboratory. Some think success in this area would be definitive evidence for an entirely mechanistic view of life. Creationists are quick to point out that if the application of sufficient time, energy, intelligence, and creative ability resulted in the manufacture of a living thing from non-living components, this would instead be evidence that life was intelligently designed in the first place.

Many possible mechanisms have been proposed to explain how this step could have taken place in the past, based on a variety of assumptions about the primitive Earth; but the suppositions about both the conditions and the mechanisms are highly speculative and change with each generation of scientists, so this discussion is unlikely to bring about any quick resolution of the debate.

Some schools of thought would shift the focus elsewhere, proposing that life, or at least organic chemicals, evolved in outer space and that the Earth was 'seeded' in some manner from there. This avoids the problem of the non-demonstrability of the appropriate conditions at any time in Earth history by simply assuming that these conditions existed in some place that cannot be observed at all. However, this suggestion is also unlikely to provide much in the way of resolution to the argument; for it clearly begs the question. Creationists are also accused of begging the question by assuming that life was created and did not in any substantial way evolve. The issue here is whether either belief is an a priori assumption, or whether it is based on reliable evidence. The problem is that even a demonstrated proof that life as we know it could come about in a particular way does not show that such was the path of actual history.

Human Evolution

By far the most contentious and important issue is that of the evolution of the human race. Whatever else they may concede, Christian creationists at least must insist upon the direct hand of God in the making of the first human beings. For evolutionists, on the other hand, establishing a line of descent for man has always been a kind of holy grail--if found, to be considered as the final and definitive proof that man is the pinnacle of a series of chance processes aided by natural selection, and nothing more. Over the years, many such lines for man have been proposed, and even regarded as firmly established, but a number of once highly-trumpeted ancestors have now been relegated to other roles. As for the current candidates,

468

Page 469: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

both Java and Australopithecus, including the skeleton known as "Lucy," are regarded by creationists, and by some others, to have been entirely ape. At any given time, the "missing link" promoted by one group may be derided as an irrelevant evolutionary offshoot by others with their own candidate. As with other such topics, the evidences offered in textbooks all tend to disappear within a decade or so, to be replaced by something else.

The difficulties involved in constructing an ancestry for the supposedly most recently evolved creature ought to provide future interpreters of fossils with a larger dose of the more customary scientific caution, and forestall some of the premature rush to speculative publication that has characterized this particular field. For their part, the creationists have the difficulty that if man came on the scene at roughly the same time as the animals, the bones of man ought to be found with those of all animal species. Likewise, evolutionists require many more bones to be found to make a case for their side. Is the fact that both generally have not found the evidence to support their positions simply a matter of interpretation, or must some grave theoretical difficulty be acknowledged?

Nothing is being conceded by anyone on this front. One side is certain humankind has evolved, and that at least some fossils are evidence of it; the other is certain no such thing happened; that no catalogues of bones (or even of comparative DNA), however arranged and sorted by human-like characteristics, can possibly prove otherwise, and indeed that nothing that could possibly be interpreted as a link between humans and animal primates has ever yet been found. They are confident that none ever will be, and that they will have little difficulty debunking evolutionists' claims to the contrary.

The Law

Conservative creationists say they are eager to debate the scientific merits of their theories and that they wish only a fair examination of their ideas and work. To this end, they did manage to convince a few state legislatures their theories ought to be taught in schools alongside the majority ones. There, they attempted to make three points: a) that the intent of the separation clause in the U.S. Constitution was to keep state influence out of churches, not the converse, and that recent rulings to the contrary have amounted to an adventuresome rewriting of that document by the courts, (b) that forbidding any mention of creation paradigms in public schools and allowing only the teaching of evolution is a violation of the free exercise clause of the same amendment, and (c) that if creation is to be banned from schools on the basis of its religious or metaphysical underlay, so must evolution for precisely the same reason.

Evolutionists counter: (a) that whatever the scope of the original intent, the correct interpretation of the U.S. Constitution in the light of present day society is to mandate an absolute separation of church and state, that is, a rigid secularism, (b) that allowing any mention of religious ideas in the schools is a violation of the anti-establishment clause of the first amendment, (c) that creationism must be banned from the schools because it--and not evolution--is unscientific, inherently religious

469

Page 470: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

however taught, and promotes sectarian religion in what must be a secular and pluralistic society.

Eminent scientists, theologians, and lawyers lined up on both sides to testify, but in two celebrated court decisions in Arkansas (1982) and Louisiana (1987), laws mandating the teaching of creation as an alternative theory to evolution were ruled unconstitutional on the grounds that they promoted entirely religious doctrines rather than fairness between equal competing theories. The strength of the rulings indicates that it will probably be a long time before such questions are ever again examined in an American court of law, and there is no immediate prospect they will be considered at all by Canadian ones. Thus, from a legal point of view at least, the issue has been settled in favour of the majority scientific establishment. However, law will not stop this kind of debate, for it involves abstractions competing to explain the existence of the cosmos, life in general, and humans in particular. That is, it is a conflict between comprehensive world views, not just on interpretations of the law, and such a conflict will undoubtedly exist forever in some form.

Interestingly, a British Columbia court, in a case involving whether a school board could decline to use homosexual-advocacy books in primary school classrooms, went much farther, when it ruled such public bodies could not make decisions that were even informed, much less influenced, by religious belief. Such a novel doctrine, if upheld, would effectively bar Christians from all public office, not just remove their ideas from public view.

Education

Educational institutions are caught in the middle of this dispute. The religious right claims that its forbearers invented the whole concept of mass education and is dismayed to find its influence and presence there now reduced to naught by the ascendancy of what it calls "secular humanism". They regard this as a threat to their very existence, for if their children are taught only in a hostile philosophical setting, then their beliefs are a generation from extinction at the hands of the state. They argue that the education of children exclusively in such theories is an infringement on their right to hold their beliefs unhindered. For their part, the other side is not about to relinquish any portion of its control over Western educational institutions. They in turn regard the exposure of children to any theory other than evolution as tantamount to the teaching of witchcraft, astrology, and superstition. They are confident in the essential rightness of evolution and of the evidence for it, not just as a good abstraction, but as actual physical truth. Two things seem to have escaped notice here:

first, that the assumption of models as absolute truth has never been historically tenable for long, and

second, that the exclusion of religious based models is inconsistent with holding tolerance as a high value.

Summary

470

Page 471: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Creationists accuse those they term "secular humanists" of practising a narcissistic and exclusive tolerance--one that has room only for their views and none for any other religious ideas. Their opponents countercharge that creationists are censors who wish to replace good science with religious myths, and that they must be suppressed for the good of society. Asimov: "...church and family can easily censor printed matter or television. Only the school is beyond their control." [Montagu, p 191] Creationists respond that it is their views that are being censored, not those of the evolutionists. Morris: "Unfortunately his (Asimov's) last statement is mostly correct." [ICR pamphlet] Both sides accuse the other of having a hidden (or not-so-hidden) agenda--that of the imposition of its own views via a program of mind control and propaganda. Those on the extremes also excoriate or ridicule any attempts to take a middle position, and those who do try for some intellectual compromise are likely to be equally emotional in their views.

Both sides have found weaknesses in the other position--and though from a logical viewpoint it makes a poor argument, the shortcomings of one side are used as a psychological boost for the other. Occasionally, answers to criticisms have been provided by one side in a very speculative fashion, and this practice gives great encouragement to the other. Much of the argument is conducted in extremely emotional and personal terms, which could be used to encourage the other side because of its lack of content, but tends to inflame it to do likewise instead.

On both sides, some old untenable positions have been abandoned. For example, only the most outdated of books still mention "vestigial organs" or claim that "ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny". These were two of the interesting, but ultimately misleading speculations of the past that have now been laid to rest, a fate no doubt to be shared by some of their successors. For their part, creationists concede that life forms can be observed to change via natural selection, even if they do not agree that they do so to the extent extrapolated by evolution's supporters or that mutation is a possible source of this change. Events may also force a realization that humankind will soon have some measure of control over future changes to itself, something sure to enliven the debate, though proving nothing about the past.

11.5 Learning How to Conduct Debates Whether one thinks that such debates are about science or not, several things

can be learned from this particular one. First, new theories, or any theory that seeks to displace the consensus view, will always be the subject of vigorous examination and criticism. Such debates are healthy, for they are a sign that science is still alive and growing. If established ideas are never questioned, stagnation will result and new discoveries will cease. Second, it is important to know what is actually being debated. Is it factual matters (data), methodologies, theories, interpretations, or conclusions? Is it about intellectual honesty, scientific integrity, personal qualifications, or the associations of the participants? Or, do the disputes arise because of differing world views? If so, are they therefore irresolvable? While those who differ sharply on such fundamental issues cannot be made to compromise on their world views even in the long term, they could learn to live with and honour one

471

Page 472: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

another. They could also learn to give and take in a vigorous and yet respectful fashion.

In the particular case discussed here, any rapprochement between modern science and most religions (especially conservative Christianity) would have to involve an acknowledgment on the one hand that science is not an entirely mechanistic process and on the other that religion does not necessarily include a rigidly fixed view of the physical universe. If each side took a friendly though surely disbelieving attitude toward the other, a great enrichment of both science and religion could take place as each sought answers to the legitimate questions raised by the other, questions that might never be asked if one of the two views absolutely dominated. One way of achieving this might be to increase the intellectual content and reduce the emotional aspect of the debate. Alas, since many people reading the last section become angry that it is even in print, and thereby gives credence to the idea there is something to debate (when they are convinced there is not), such a lowering of the temperature seems unlikely, to say the least. Perhaps there is a reason why the author picked such a provocative subject.

In an open information society, there could be a realization on the part of scientists that there is room for such debates, even with those who are not materialists. After all, science does have a tendency to overlap into important metaphysical territory and is not just a subset of logical positivism. From the ethical principles of wholeness, respect for the individual, and the promoting of the common welfare, one could conclude that there ought to be a greater tolerance of those whose views are at variance with those of the current majority. Once again, if a society can use the perception that a minority poses a threat in order to suppress that minority, the society is not truly free. Pluralism and tolerance must be real and not exclusive; they must not demand freedom exclusively for one set of views.

World view affects the science one does and it shapes the interpretation of data. If this becomes more generally realized--as it may in the information age--all scientific debates, whether seen as having world-view implications or not, would be perceived as healthy, potentially enhancing knowledge and human understanding of the universe. Such common good is an ethical goal for all seekers of truth, whatever their belief framework.

For their part, creationists--who are usually religiously motivated--must abandon any fear that conceding anything to the other side would destroy their entire belief framework. Furthermore, if they expect creationism to be evaluated seriously as a scientific study, they will need to develop testable hypotheses, for there is likely to be little future in their attempts to have evolution labelled as a religion, even if it does have such characteristics. They might not abandon their fight to have the influence of evolutionary ideas reduced, but the one to have creationism taught alongside it in science classes has apparently been lost--at least for the foreseeable future in North America.

With these considerations in mind, the following suggestions are offered for a potential ethical framework for participating in debates and discussions on issues that relate to science. They may be particularly useful for those issues that are entirely philosophical or world-view dependent, or otherwise have a high level of personal and emotional content, but they can be applied to many other situations.

472

Page 473: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Participants in such debates need to agree on what it is they are debating. Is it science? If so, what are the testable hypotheses, what experiments have been done, and where are the repeatable results? If it is not science, then let that fact be clearly stated before the debate begins.

o Specialists who enter debates against generalists over broad world-view related topics are at some risk, for they are likely to lack the breadth of knowledge to function in such circumstances. They may also be too aware of the difficulties of supporting their position from within their own speciality and will attempt to use what they believe to be better-founded interpretations from other fields, not realizing that those abstractions too are no more substantial than their own. Models of the information age also suggest there will be fewer narrow specialists in the future, and this fact alone may make such debates more productive.

o Personal attack, innuendo, and scornful remarks concerning the opponents' world view, politics, friends, or religion should all be avoided. So should the emotional denigration of the other side's views. Anger wins nothing in a debate about science or theology; onlookers will carry away a negative impression of everything that the angry person has said. Ideas that one finds unpleasant will not go away just by shouting at them loudly enough.

o A line of argument should never be based on assumptions about an opponent's beliefs. For instance, one who attempts to discredit a creationist by referring to the Bible could be dismayed to discover the opponent to be Zoroastrian, an Animist, or a believer in some creation account other than Genesis. Comments about the irreligion of a scientist could also be quite off the mark. People often set up a stereotype (or "straw man") of opponent's beliefs and attack that. If sufficiently eloquent, such a tactic may impress a gullible audience, but it too is irrelevant to the main issues.

o Arguments from silence are useless. It cannot be assumed that someday someone will find experimental evidence for or against a particular theory when none exists today. Neither is the absence of such evidence relevant in the most general terms, even if it does appear to refute a particular aspect of some theory. For example, both evolution and creation are abstractions for describing a past reality, and they will continue to exist in some form independently of all suggested mechanisms or refutations thereof.

o Indefensible positions cannot be defended. When one group has seen fraud, wishful thinking, over-confidence, bad management, or poor experimentation, it may as well concede this when opponents point out these specific problems. If one side has not thought out a complete explanation of part of its position, this too must be acknowledged, and not covered up. It will be less difficult all the time to hide anything. Good work can stand up to any amount of public scrutiny.

o Speculation is futile. The fact that it is taking place at all may be an indication that the topic has metaphysical overtones and that it is about world view, not science. In any case, trying to fill in the gaps in a theory with speculation only displays more clearly its weakness both to opponents and to the audience. This is not to suggest that speculation in general is futile, for it leads to new abstractions and new ideas to test for theoretical consistency, coherency and practical value.

473

Page 474: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

There is a tendency, however, to advance such speculation as fact, especially when attempting to fill in the details of a cherished theory. Just as Ptolemy's geocentric abstraction became a doctrine, so can a modern theory. No matter how cohesive, useful, or even beautiful an abstraction about the physical world, it does not convey the thing itself; it remains an abstraction. No matter how closely a model can be made to conform with interpretations of the observable evidence, it is not absolute truth. Many models for one underlying truth may be possible; far more can be devised when not all the evidence is available.

o Arguments from consensus are invalid, even if they appear to have a facade of authority. The fact one group may well have a majority of living or dead scientists on its side does not mean that it is right. Neither does it matter if the current scientific or religious media superstars are in agreement. What does matter in science is not how many people find a particular abstraction or explanation of the phenomenon more satisfying to their world view, but which explanations best fit the experimental evidence, if indeed any experiments can be done.

o The losers of a particular debate should be gracious. It is easy to claim that one's opponents were better funded, perhaps by some shadowy conspiratorial group, and that an innocent lamb such as oneself is no match for such sophisticated tactics. This is really an excuse for not doing one's homework, or for tackling a debate one lacked the knowledge or ability to prosecute.

o No one should fear such debates. The worst that can happen is that both sides will reinforce their positions. A better outcome is that both will realize they do not have the whole truth and all the answers, not yet. The best is that both sides will be forced to abandon some bad science or incorrectly interpreted religion and find better answers.

o Most important, no one should be afraid to examine ideas, regardless of how much they may seem to be at variance with one's own views. Likewise, it ought to be possible to be free from fear of danger or ridicule in putting one's own ideas up to public scrutiny. Such fears prevent growth, foster prejudice and censorship, and impair the viability of a whole culture. It may be possible for the fourth civilization to be freer from such fears because of the openness of information, but tolerance of others' religious or scientific views is an ethical issue and not just a matter of having better information.

11.6 Science, Technology, and Religion in the Twentieth Century The hold on all aspects of Western society of the nineteenth century secularist

thinking models (humanism, rationalism, empiricism, materialism, progress, and evolution) continued to grow in the twentieth as the influence of religion declined. For instance, the doctrine of the separation of church and state began in the United States as a way to protect churches from state interference and to prevent the establishment of state religion. In this century, this doctrine has also been used to eliminate from public life and action all mention of Christian ideas. A case in point was a lower court decision in 2002 declaring that the words "under God" in the American pledge of allegiance were unconstitutional. Although Europeans could not point to any law enshrining this doctrine (most have state churches) the same situation existed there as much as fifty years earlier.

474

Page 475: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

A similar self-censorship, was nearly complete in academic publications early in the century. By the 1980s, it had been successfully extended to politics, public bodies, music and art, public prayer, books, the media, entertainment, and schools. One could grow up in both Europe and North America without ever hearing or seeing religious themes or ideas or having them positively referred to by any figure in authority. It became possible to read newspapers and magazines and watch television entertainment without seeing much mention of religion or religious ideas, except in paid-for programs, promotions, and advertisements, or as negative stereotypes in programming. Likewise, popular fiction seldom mentioned religion except negatively. Religious ideas had largely been relegated to their own publications, radio and television stations, and book publishers. They were not to be seen in public, unless there was a scandal of some kind, and then they were very public indeed.

The assumption of both the media and of intellectuals in general was that religion had been relegated to the scrap heap of superstition and had no more relevance for the present or the future. Television, movies, and school textbooks came to be so thoroughly sanitized of religion that no one from outside Western culture would ever guess from them that even a tiny percentage of their audience even believed in God, much less was devoted to Him. Many publications would no longer accept paid advertising from religious groups, even on social or political issues. Voluntary school prayer groups were forbidden, and religion was virtually banned from public life, the courts being enlisted to enforce these prohibitions and enshrine them into law.

Meanwhile, churches and their people had refined and redefined the ways in which their doctrines related to the physical world, in order to remain rational and consistent. In general, this involved a pulling back from the older practice of incorporating views of the physical world into doctrine, except to assert that God was the ultimate source of all creation. The realm of Western religion came to be morals and relationships alone, and the assertion by academics of the moral neutrality of technique was accepted and used to justify the noninvolvement, especially by conservative Christians, in science or technology. However, since technique was the chief concern of life in the industrial age, this withdrawal increasingly implied that religion had less and less to do with the everyday activities of ordinary citizens. Even for those who wanted to go beyond nominalism, there came to be little of relevance to be found in the churches, and it became easier to compartmentalize life into the sacred on one day of the week and the secular for the rest of it, or to ignore religion altogether.

The tendencies of late machine-age people to be very narrow specialists and to pick and choose only fragments of the culture outside their specialities were also applied to religion. So was the tendency to view ideas as commodities. The result was an increasing fragmentation of religion itself, as people become shoppers in the delicatessen of religious ideas. Thus, people might regard themselves as associated with a church, but would select what doctrines they wanted and rejected the rest. For instance, many Catholics will accept church teachings on some theological and moral issues, but will reject that authority on an issue like birth control. Likewise,

475

Page 476: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

many Protestants will say they believe in the Bible's guidance but will actually follow the daily horoscope (Babylonian religion forbidden in the Old Testament).

The same trend can also be seen in the tendency to form religious organizations independent of any church body, as well as in the rise of theologies, such as the modern charismatic movement, that have themselves become fragments of the menu selected by members of many traditional churches. The result is that people attend the church of their choice a few times a year (Easter, Christmas) and to buy its commercial services for rites of passage such as weddings, baptisms, and funerals. Otherwise, what was a day of worship is incorporated into the rest of the week, and make shopping, lawn mowing and golf into more relevant Sunday activities than church attendance. Alternatively, they require their churches to diversify and to offer a larger menu of theological choices so that they can remain within them, even if they do not agree with their church's traditional beliefs. Yet another approach is to incorporate diverse ideas and activities into Church itself, transforming worship either into entertainment or a series of self-improvement seminars. One effect of these trends has been to produce mega-churches that can entertain masses of impersonal and uncommitted attendees.

Even the use of technology and techniques by the churches of North America has contributed to its separation from life, rather than promoting bonds, for such use has tended to make them over in the image of the world their original doctrines purported to be trying to change. Nowhere is this more evident than in the plight of some television evangelists who rose to media stardom on a wave of adulation through the early 1980s and suffered such scandalous falls afterward. Most began as apparently legitimate and sincere preachers of a message, but the very nature of the media they used replaced that message by the same kind of personality cult it tends to generate for all its stars. The magnitude of their success destroyed the authenticity of their message by building in them the first of the seven deadly sins, pride--and the least Christian of all loves--that of money.

For others, the shift in message was of a different type--first accommodating within their gospel the success philosophy, which is a different kind of materialism, and then allowing that in turn to replace the Christian message altogether. These writers and television personalities encourage their audience to make material prosperity their principal goal and deliver this message with a Christian-like vocabulary, declaring that God owes His followers health, wealth, success, and prompt delivery upon demand. Of course, such a god is neither transcendent nor master of anything, but the creation and servant of those making the demands--an appropriate deity for the self-centred.

Thus, some segments of Western Christianity distanced their religion from life to the point of meaninglessness, while others became assimilated to a materialistic culture to the point of indistinguishability. Both of these trends may have buried the historic Christian message and made it irrelevant to modern society. By the late 1960s, popular philosophers, some purporting still to be Christians, could well proclaim that "God is dead." It is interesting to observe in this connection that in both compartmentalization and assimilation there was a search for sophistication or "relevance," in a trendy sense of the latter word. Both were historically regarded as

476

Page 477: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

heretical, but now together represented the mainstream of Western Christendom. In particular, the philosophy that equated success with a blessing bestowed by God on the deserving righteous and material failure with His judgement on the unrighteous was entirely at variance with both modern and historical interests of the majority--the poor and oppressed. These had always flocked to Christianity, not to find a way out of their problems and into material prosperity, but to find a way to transcend and to live through them. This "gospel of sophistication" was the same one that Western Christians scorned as "worldliness" a few generations before, and the change demonstrates the redefinition of religion in the 1980s better than anything else could.

The process of mutual withdrawal by science and religion into non-overlapping spheres or magesteria is known as secularization. Among social scientists it became an axiom that in any scientific and technical society, secularization would inevitably proceed to the point of extinguishing all remaining traces of religious expression. Christianity was held to be particularly vulnerable because its very rationality accelerated the process. Up to a point, this assumption appeared to be correct, for as long as the machine age's materialism persisted, religion fought a rear guard action, nominalism increased, and churches continued to become either refugees from culture or assimilated by it. Churches that accepted secularization gradually became unable to refute anything science affirmed, and afraid to affirm anything scientists denied or doubted. The more doctrinally conservative groups retreated almost entirely from the intellectual world between 1850 and 1950, abandoning both education and technique and abdicating a role in or responsibility for defending their faith in the open marketplace of ideas. There, an optimistic and confident science reigned supreme and unchallenged in the Western world for decades, reaching its peak in the 1950s. However, the spiritual leadership provided by nineteenth century scientific paradigms eventually faltered somewhat, for several reasons.

First, the optimism of humanism was shaken by two world wars, a devastating arms race, and numerous famines and other local political crises that demonstrated the practical failure of the idea humans could be autonomous from any external and absolute moral standards. It began to appear that autonomy was a myth, for it led not to freedom but to either anarchy or the arbitrariness of totalitarianism. Too many such tyrants had become mass murderers. The very emphasis on the individual that had fragmented religion led people to question the validity of the notion of collective and statistical man--summarized, probed, and laid out rationally with all the parts on the table and open to view. The old ideas that mind might be more than the brain began to gnaw away at humanist assumptions, and the failure of paradise to arrive on schedule to suggest that perhaps it ought after all to be looked for outside humanity or even outside the physical world.

Second, these same failures also led to a re-examination of rationalism and empiricism as intellectual absolutes. A variety of people came to wonder whether the scientific technique really did not have all the answers, to question its ability to find them all, and to suspect that its practitioners might not even know what the most important questions were. A certain amount of technological cynicism developed among ordinary citizens. Meanwhile, Gödel's work on logical systems,

477

Page 478: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Einstein's on relativity, Heisenberg's on the uncertainty principle, and indeed the whole unsettling field of quantum mechanics had seriously eroded late nineteenth-century scientific community confidence in the absolute authority and completeness of their own work. There was a growing realization (in physics at least) that the best understandings of the universe were indeed models or abstractions, and that ultimate reality was far more elusive than had once been thought.

Third, materialism too came to be questioned, as more people began to react to the impersonality of the machine age and to the dehumanization of the individual. Through the 1960s and 1970s, there came to be a much greater emphasis on the individual and on the rights of minorities. This emphasis was reflected in a shift in government spending priorities from the military and technological into social programs. Perhaps the benevolent state could bring salvation even if people could not save themselves by their own efforts. Meanwhile, the idea of the melting pot for American culture--assimilation to the traditional majority--was abandoned, and the best society came to be seen as multicultural. The structure of big business also began to change. Large firms tried to become (or be seen as) social leaders and relate to people as well as to products, and many new companies were set up as unstructured entrepreneurships.

The 1980s saw the emergence of a new materialism, based on economic pragmatism. Everyone was seen as a potential entrepreneur out to become better off, either economically or spiritually. Personal satisfaction and individual self-realization to the maximum of human potential became important and a vague supernaturalism was attached to these new materialisms that partially contradicted the old materialism. The spiritual and transcendental came back into vogue, with many new religions being founded, and both Christianity and Islam began a new period of rapid missionary-style expansion, particularly in emerging industrial nations. In North America, however, new age mysticism rose to challenge and compete with the rational faiths of both Christianity and scientism. It filled a void; it was new; and it was vague enough to require no commitment or make any demands on its followers' life-style--one could design one's own religion, and even be one's own god.

Fourth, the notion of inevitable progress was also set back badly by the political, military and economic "accidents" of the twentieth century--so much so that even the greatly accelerated pace of the scientific revolution after 1945 could not convince people to trust progress as they previously had. Some of them were now prepared to march against it or even lay down in front of the bulldozers and stop it. Opposition to nuclear technology, for example, eventually became sufficiently widespread at the grass-roots level to force both governments and corporations to cut back or cancel many programs in this area. Environmental groups also became influential in the battle against the inevitability of progress, and their cause had by the 1980s become not only respectable, but positively chic. Many of the same people became protesters against globalization by the turn of the millennium, apparently fearing that individual freedoms would disappear into the maw of international corporate greed. The political and philosophical ecology had changed; evolutionary-style progress was no longer a god, nor even inevitable; it was perhaps incorrect.

478

Page 479: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

There can be little doubt that the Three Mile Island and Chernobyl incidents set back progress in nuclear power technology by years, if not permanently. Even though nuclear fusion (an entirely different technology) might have been safer and cheaper than other energy forms, such plants may never become a commercial reality because of political and emotional considerations. This nucleophobia leads to extraordinary extremes--Western nations may spend millions of times as much per life saved in nuclear safety as they do in their relief to the Third World or on disease control and prevention, for example. But, famine, earthquake, volcanic eruption, flood, fire, and the like can all be attributed to the acts of the impersonal nature-god. When people die because of technology, the wounds appear self-inflicted; they are acts of a god created by man, and are intolerable where the others are not. Paradoxically, the family automobile is perceived as a god of a lower order of technology, more familiar, less powerful, and less emotionally threatening than nuclear energy, even though it destroys legions of lives each year. In addition, acid rain attributed to industrial pollution is slowly poisoning lakes and rivers, killing trees, and dissolving the clay feet of the god of progress. Its fall is not one easily acknowledged; this shrine may be badly eroded, but it still receives much homage.

Fifth, the only recently elevated god of the secular and benevolent state that could itself bring about a socialist utopia on Earth also became discredited. Not only did the Soviet Union and its client states all fall utterly, but there came to be an increasing sense in the West that there were limits to the extent of control that the state should have over individuals' lives, and limits to the percentage of income that could be extracted to ensure a social safety net. Confidence in government, only recently risen to unprecedented heights, fell to corresponding lows, and the new millennium's beginning finds the average citizen of most Western countries indifferent to, cynical about, or hostile to the state, and distrustful of its leaders.

That is, the political version of evolutionary natural selection has collapsed, because "survival of the fittest" has come to be seen as a dangerous social doctrine, and because historical evidence is against it. Neither the Nazi superman, the Marxist strongman, or the liberal humanist man has proven to be better, much less to be the end of history, as their proponents supposed. Note that there was never a logical connection between biological natural selection and survival of the fittest in the social and political sense when these ideas were on the ascendancy, and there is still no connection when one of them becomes discredited. However, the connection, once made in some minds, is hard to disown.

Sixth, as seen in the last section, evolution itself came under renewed attack from a completely unexpected quarter--scientists who were also conservative Christians. Rather than accommodate two world views by compartmentalizing life, or by mythologizing or re-interpreting the Bible, they chose to believe it and attack the conclusions of scientists, attempting to use science to do so.

There is a tendency among intellectuals to write off this renewed challenge to the accepted doctrine as irrelevant, incompetent, and insignificant. It is none of these, for it strikes at the very heart of the central issue--not creation versus evolution, but rather what ought to be the proper sphere of influence of science and religion. Can scientists really insist the evolution of the universe, of life, and of humankind, as they model them, constitute the ultimate historical reality? The new

479

Page 480: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

breed of creationists say they cannot, and so offer creation as an alternate model, with or without the Biblical account, and with or without physical evidence. Both this new challenge, and the necessity to make periodic changes to evolutionary models despite having previously taught them as ultimate fact causes a credibility problem, one that will be compounded when the big bang model for the origin of matter is eventually dramatically revised or discarded.

For these reasons, it is gradually becoming more obvious that progress and evolution are both abstractions or models and not ultimate reality. That is, scientism is losing the emotional and religious-like following it has had at both points. Thus, if the rationalism of the Christian faith was eventually to contribute to its secularization, the same can be said to some extent for the rationalism of scientism. Science and technique are useful for developing the means of describing and using resources implicit in the physical world, but the descriptions and techniques so generated are neither final answers nor ultimate reality, and may therefore be legitimately competed with on those grounds.

The absolutism of recent scientism could in the end be as troubling to itself as was the absolutism of the Catholic Church in the seventeenth century. If it cannot learn to question its own most basic philosophic foundations by applying its methodology as a meta-technique to itself, it could find itself swept aside and replaced by new gods. This outcome is not one that humanity can afford, for whatever its failings, science cannot be dispensed with altogether, or lived without for very long, and neither materialists nor Christians would be very comfortable in an anti-rational world.

At the same time that doctrines of scientism have come under challenged, the information age has begun, and its models are replacing those of the machine age. Although there are new machines, new techniques, and new kinds of progress at the heart of this change, the magnitude of the break with the past ensures that peoples' basic assumptions and beliefs will be up for grabs for some time. Just as politics, economics, corporations, and society are being redefined from the collection of fragments they have become, so are beliefs, world views, epistemological systems, and religions. As the scientific and industrial revolutions progressed, Christianity seemed to lose its vigour and go into decline. Likewise, as the new civilization dawns and the basic cultural premises settle into new patterns, the religious aspects of those cultures will also undergo transformation. What will the gods of the information age be? Computers themselves? The Metalibrary? The dominant monopoly providing software and hardware?

Religious change has already begun. Some churches with roots in pre-industrial revolution days have retreated into a genteel intellectualism, abandoning both experiential and relational aspects of their source. They have suffered sharp declines in membership, and these appear to be accelerating. Not only are they having increasing difficulty holding onto existing members, but also their missionary emphasis has all but vanished, cutting off the flow of new blood and causing substantial increases in the average age of their memberships. Like all other organizations perceived as lacking fresh and vital contact to the current culture and its models, they cannot survive on old glories when the culture changes a second time. Nor might they survive on their new-found sophistication, however culturally

480

Page 481: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

accommodating this may be, for by itself, this is too insubstantial, and the less erudite readily observe that the god-emperor of sophistication not only has no clothes, but is the enemy of piety. Such churches become like hunter-gatherers in an industrial society--irrelevant and all but invisible.

Even the most vibrant and rapidly growing churches are barely holding their own relative to the total North American population, and they are doing this chiefly through migration, birth and marriage, not by bringing in previously unchurched people. Moreover, the process of fragmentation and the delicatessanizing of religious beliefs and practices has become advanced even in the growing churches, and it is unclear how much of their growth represents renewed commitment to conventional orthodoxy or how much is due to doctrinal diversification and insubstantial cultural accommodation. In short, religion in the West is rapidly becoming as much form as substance, and what growth is observed may well be illusory.

But the set of beliefs about God and about moral absolutes--the transcendent things that one calls religion--appears to be a necessary part of the experience of being human in any culture, by the example of historical record if by nothing else. If this need is not met (in the West) by traditional Christian denominations, and if the answers provided by a century of scientism are no longer an entirely adequate substitute, it becomes reasonable to ask what will fill their role in the next culture. For, even if all the old gods are fragmented beyond repair, religion will still exist. People will still seek a meaning for being, a foundation for knowledge, an understanding for experience, and a basis for human and other relationships, and they will want all these integrated into a comprehensive belief system by which to live.

In the next chapter, the possibilities for a revival of the human spirit and of religion will be considered, and contenders for leadership roles will be examined.

11.7 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Religion is a comprehensive, and vital, energizing force in every society. It encompasses beliefs and the reason for being, knowledge, and a world view. It has the power to transform behaviour through its ethical imperatives--though it is not the only such transforming force. It can be viewed philosophically, historically, artistically, psychologically, socially, morally, economically, or personally. Each of these approaches contributes to the total picture for religious activity, though none are sufficient alone to explain it.

The major world religions today include Buddhism, Confucianism, Hinduism, Shintoism, Judaism, Islam, and Christianity. Of these, some are more philosophical and cultural, or even strictly national. The Western notion of religion may not always be applicable to certain patriotic or cultural expressions such as Confucianism, Hinduism, and Shintoism. Judaism, Islam, and Christianity are monotheistic and in the same tradition, and the last two are the largest and most aggressive today. Besides them, only Buddhism claims to be universal and has had some missionary

481

Page 482: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

history. It is uncertain whether the "New Age" syncretism of fragments from scientism, Buddhism, and Hinduism is a religion in the same sense as some of these.

Science and the Industrial Revolution both came about in the crucible of European Christianity, and the Protestant reformation was a critical factor in the development of both, sharing key elements of their world views for nearly two centuries, until the rise of scientism in the late nineteenth century coincided with a retreat of Christianity into defensiveness and nominalism. This new world view became progressively more important up to the mid-twentieth century when it began to come under pressure due to internal inconsistencies, the failure of doctrines of progress, antitechnology sentiment, some resurgence of conservative Christianity, and the imminent passing of the industrial age.

The debate over origins was selected as representative of a typical and likely permanent world view clash. Suggestions for debating these topics were made, and it was asserted that such debates, properly conducted, are healthy.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. Research and discuss in detail an approaches to the study of religion mentioned in the section one. First attempt to encompass the entire phenomenon of religion under this single heading, then discuss the extent of limitations, if any, to this approach.

2. Research at least three additional religions other than those mentioned in the text. Summarize their principal beliefs about God, humanity, and ethics. Are they universal? missionary? Attempt to determine the extent to which they are cultural phenomena or philosophies rather than religions (in the more comprehensive sense). In each case, be sure to assess their followers' prospects for living with and utilizing machine-age and information technology.

3. Research and discuss in much greater detail than in the text the history and beliefs of Islam, particularly as these interacted with Europe during the time of the scientific and industrial revolutions.

4. What was the effect of the plague ("black death") on (a) the scientific and industrial revolutions; (b) the Christian Churches in Europe?

5. What role did Irish-led monasticism during the dark ages have in the preservation of western learning?

6. The author indicated that the printing press was one of the most important technical innovations. Research and discuss in detail the history and effects of this device on both religious and scientific institutions. Why is the advent of personal desktop publishing seen to be of equal or greater importance today?

7. Some have suggested that the age of the printed word or verbally modelled communication has passed and that the future belongs to visual communication or images. What are some of the aesthetic, religious, social, and scientific consequences if this is true?

8. Consider the suggestion that secularization (the separation of religion from daily life, politics, and work) will no longer be an operating premise in the fourth

482

Page 483: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

civilization, either supporting this with a detailed argument or attempting to refute it.

9. Examples were given of the way in which institutions (scientific and religious) can take on a life of their own and become something very different than what they started as due to their mutual interaction with society and technology. Research and describe this process in detail with one or two specific institutions of any kind.

10. Write a detailed biography of one of the scientists mentioned in this chapter, or another of your choice who made revolutionary contributions to the development of science. Pay particular attention to his or her religious beliefs and how these affected the science that was done. Now do the same for a religious figure of equivalent stature, paying particular attention to his or her world view as it related to science and technology.

11. The author argues that in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, scientism has played the role and achieved the status of a religion. Refute this argument.

12. Research and discuss some of the cosmological models for the origins of the universe (continuous creation, big bang, and so on). Why were previous models abandoned and the big bang generally adopted? What are weaknesses of the theory?

13. Research and discuss paradigms for the evolution of life (spontaneous generation, inheritance of acquired characteristics, gradual uniform natural selection, punctuated equilibrium). What experimental or other evidence caused the first ones to be abandoned? What is the evidence for the last?

14. What are the differences between what a creationist paradigm predicts will be found in the fossil record and what a natural selection paradigm (both slow and punctuated equilibrium versions) predicts will be found there?

15. A slogan once found in textbooks on animal evolution was "ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny". Find out and explain what this means, and why it eventually came to be criticized as misleading.

16. Obtain from the library a text on evolution (or a first year biology text) published in the 1960s, the 1970s, the 1980s and the 1990s. Make a brief summary of the principal arguments and evidence used in each decade for evolution, and try to account for the differences.

17. Do an actual calculation of the probability that if a thousand monkeys were set to typing at random, one of them would, in under 100 billion years produce all the works of Shakespeare in a contiguous piece within the text.

18. "The absence of nascent (developing) organs refutes the notion that others are vestigial (remnants)." Either develop this argument further, or refute it.

19. Several court battles have been fought over the creation/evolution issue. Research this history and summarize the arguments made on both sides and the conclusions of the court in each case.

20. Research and assess the numerical extent of religious faith in the modern world. Which is the fastest growing religion in the world as a whole? In the West? In information-age countries? Why?

483

Page 484: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

21. The author asserts that fragmentation of beliefs is a religious expression corresponding to the phenomenon of specialization in the machine age. Research this trend in the literature and summarize statistics supporting the conclusion that this fragmentation has taken place. Alternately, argue that no such fragmentation has occurred and support that conclusion with data.

22. Give detailed examples of the Western Christian assimilation of and redefinition by the surrounding culture.

23. "God is dead." What does this mean? Either support this thesis or refute it.24. Read some of the creation/evolution debate literature and analyse the

quality of the arguments on both sides of the criteria in this chapter, or on the basis of criteria you develop yourself.

25. What are additional examples, besides those in the text, of the adoption as dogma of a fixed view or model of the universe into either science or religion? Show how the idea came to be discarded.

26. What are UFOs? What evidence is there they are visitors from somewhere else? What factors contribute to beliefs that they are/are not?

27. Research the topic of cold fusion. Define the term and give a brief history of its initial discovery and the aftermath. Now, research later literature for subsequent references. Is there anything to cold fusion? What do you think of the initial response of the scientific community?

28. Who is Uri Geller?29. Very recent trends (see Bibby's Restless Gods) may show an increase in

religious interest by younger North Americans. Research this suggestion and comment on it.

Bibliography

Aardsma, Gerald E. Minisymposium on the Speed of Light--Part I: Has the Speed of Light Decayed Recently--Paper 1. Creation Research Society Quarterly 25, 1 (June 1988).

Barbour, Ian. Issues in Science and Religion. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1966.

Barbour, Ian (ed.). Science and Religion--New Perspectives on the Dialogue. New York: Harper & Row, 1968.

Bibby, Reginald W. Fragmented Gods--the Poverty and Potential of Religion in Canada. Toronto: Irwin, 1987.

Bibby, Reginald W. Restless Gods--the Renaissance of Religion in Canada. Toronto: Stoddart, 2002.

Berggren, W. S., and Van Couvering, John A. (eds.). Catastrophes and Earth History--The New Uniformitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.

Butterfield, H. The Origins of Modern Science 1300-1800. New York: Macmillan, 1962.

Braswell, George W. Jr. Understanding World Religions. Nashville: Broadman, 1983.

Brophy, Donald (ed.). Science and Faith in the 21st Century. New York: Paulist Press, 1968.

484

Page 485: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Cahn, Steven M., and Shatz, David (eds.). Contemporary Philosophy of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press, 1982.

Chittick, Donald E. The Controversy--Roots of the Creation-Evolution Conflict. Portland, OR: Multnomah Press, 1984.

Dannenfeldt, Karl H. The Church of the Renaissance and Reformation--Decline and Reform from 1300 to 1600. St Louis, MO: Concordia, 1970.

Dembski, William.The Design Inference: Eliminating Chance through Small Probabilities Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998

Dembski, William (ed.). Mere Creation: Science, Faith, & Intelligent Design Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1998.

Dembski, William. Intelligent Design: The Bridge Between Science and Theology Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1999.

Dembski, William and Kushiner, James(ed.). Signs of Intelligence: Understanding Intelligent Design Brazos Press, 2001

Gish, Duane T. Evolution The Fossils Say NO! San Diego: Creation - Life, 1973.Granberg-Michaelson, Wesley (ed.). Tending the Garden--Essays on the

Gospel and the Earth. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1987.Green, Ronald M. Religious Reason--The Rational and Moral Basis of Religious

Belief. New York: Oxford University Press, 1978.Hammond, Phillip E. The Sacred in a Secular Age--Toward Revision in the

Scientific Study of Religion. Berkely: University of California Press, 1985.Hawkin, David J. Christ and Modernity--Christian Self-Understanding in a

Technological Age. Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfred Laurier University Press, 1985.Henry, Carl F. H. (ed.). Horizons of Science. San Fransisco: Harper & Row,

1978.Hillerbrand, Hans J. Men and Ideas in the Sixteenth Century. Chicago: Rand

McNally, 1969.Hoogkaas, R. Religion and the Rise of Modern Science. Grand Rapids, MI:

Eerdmans, 1972.Hume, Robert E. The Worlds Living Religions. (rev. ed.) New York: Scribners,

1959.Hummel, Charles E. The Galileo Connection--Resolving Conflicts Between

Science and the Bible. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1986.Humphreys, D. Russell. Minisymposium on the Speed of Light--Part I: Has the

Speed of Light Decayed Recently--Paper 2. Creation Research Society Quarterly 25, 1, (June 1988).

Johnson, Phillip. Evolution as Dogma: The Establishment of Naturalism Haughton Publishing, 1990.

Johnson, Phillip. Darwin on Trial (Revised edition) Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1993.

Johnson, Phillip. Reason in the Balance: The Case Against Naturalism in Science, Law & Education Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1995.

Johnson, Phillip. Defeating Darwinism By Opening Minds Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1997.

485

Page 486: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Johnson, Phillip. Objections Sustained: Subversive Essays on Evolution, Law, & Culture Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1998.

Johnson, Phillip. The Wedge of Truth--Splitting the Foundations of Naturalism Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2000.

Kenyon, Kathleen M. The Bible and Recent Archaeology. Atlanta: John Knox Press, 1978.

Knight, David. The Age of Science. New York: Blackwell, 1986.Ling, Trevor. A History of Religion East and West. London: Macmillain, 1968.Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The

University of Chicago Press, 1970.Lund, Erik, Phil, Mognes, and Slok, Johannes. A History of European Ideas. W.

Glyn Jones, trans. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1972.Mason, Stephen F. A History of the Sciences. New York: Collier, 1962.Montagu, Ashley (ed.). Science and Creationism. Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 1984.Morris, Henry M. An Answer For Asimov. in Impact #99 El Cajon, CA: Institute

For Creation Research 1981.Morris, Henry M. (ed.). Scientific Creationism. San Diego: Creation-Life, 1974.Omni magazine, February 1987 issue.Owen, Virginia Stem. And the Trees Clap Their Hands--Faith, Perception, and

the New Physics. Grand Rapids MI: Eerdmans, 1983.Quebedeau, Richard. By What Authority--The Rise of Personality Cults in

American Christianity. San Fransisco: Harper & Row, 1982.Reid, W. Stanford (ed.). The Reformation--Revival or Revolution. New York:

Holt, 1968.Schaeffer, Francis A. How Should We Then Live--The Rise and Decline of

Western Thought and Culture. Old Tappan, NJ: Revell, 1976.Smith, A. E.Wilder. The Creation of Life--A Cybernetic Approach to Evolution.

Wheaton, IL: Harold Shaw, 1970.Tillyard, E. M. W. The Elizabethan World Picture. Harmondsworth, England:

Penguin, 1966.Walsh, Brian J., and Middleton, J. Richard. The Transforming Vision--Shaping a

Christian World View. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1984.Weber, Max. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York:

Scribner's, 1958.Wilson, Edward O. Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Knopf,

1998 Internet resources:

Leadership U. Origins. <http://www.origins.org/menus/design.html

486

Page 487: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Chapter 12Integration And the Fourth

Civilization

Seminar - "Did We Get Anywhere?" 12.1 A Caveat Concerning Futuresy 12.2 The Case for Integration     12.2.1 Integration as a Process of Consilience     12.2.2 Integration to Show Concinnity 12.3 Aspects of Integration 12.4 Integration and Relationships 12.5 Integration and Society 12.6 Renaissance and Reformation in the Fourth Civilization 12.7 Missing the Mark--Some Potential Difficulties 12.8 Technique and the Fourth Civilization 12.9 Summary and Further Discussion

12.1 A Caveat Concerning Futures This book has been relatively optimistic about the advent of the fourth

civilization--even taken some aspects of it for granted. There may be a certain inevitability to some of the trends that have been discussed, but one should not suppose that a kind of utopia is being suggested. Far from it. Instead, the necessary

487

Page 488: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

conditions for the establishment of any civilization following the late industrial period are being put forward, and it is obvious that these too have been filtered by a particular world view--that of the author.

Depending on the way its etymology is taken, "utopia" can mean either the "best place", or "no place". The fourth civilization may turn out to be some place, some time, but it will not be the best possible society. Some of its potential is described here, and an attempt made to show why certain trends exist and what their outcome might be, on the whole. However, all the cautions advanced in Chapter 1 concerning the study of history apply even more so to the study of potential futures. The trends and predictions discussed here are just potentials and even after one of the possible futures has come into being and it turns out to be different from all those forecast by every futurist, it might not be entirely clear to historians even with the benefit of hindsight why society changed as it did.

Thus, this chapter will pursue the integrative themes of the last few chapters, summarizing them and attempting to tie them together in additional ways. However, it will also present major obstacles to the kind of future foreseen herein, and in addition provide a short list of specific problems for which the next civilization may be interested in seeing solutions.

12.2 The Case for Integration The possibility and availability of wholistic integration is an important one, and

it is worth considering these ideas apart from the specific contexts of the last two chapters. Moreover, it is important to consider integration with respect to relationships on both personal and societal levels. After all, general philosophy may have its interest, and even its fascinations, but it does not, even when it deals with ethics, tell a wholistic story.

In each of the last two chapters a four-fold model of the person in a cultural context was presented--once to discuss the nature of learning, and once to explain religion. It has been an important theme of this book that specialization and compartmentalization, that, of necessity, characterized the machine age, will not be the dominant features of the next civilization (once it is mature) or at least that they will be very much muted. Instead, far more people will be required by the nature of their work to be generalists, and by the nature of society to be less private, more open, and more consistent.

Beyond that, it is the premise here that all aspects of knowledge, understanding, behaviour, emotion, and being are interwoven (the principle of connectedness), even when they have not been perceived as such.

The academics of the industrial age, and in particular its latter-day postmodernists deconstructed that seamless whole into a series of apparently disconnected and supposedly meaningless fragments. However, this lack of connectivity is just an illusion fostered by the inability of any one person to organize vast quantities of material, diverse forms of experiences, and different modes of learning. Computing and information technology removes such limitations and enable all forms of knowledge to be examined for interconnections.

These tasks can also be described in the definition of a term that has already been used informally several times:

488

Page 489: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Integration is the process of decompartmentalizing, connecting, and generalizing beliefs, knowledge, experience, and relationships, thus showing that what appear to be fragments are actually a seamless whole.

The essential idea behind fourth civilization integration is that its new paradigms and technologies enable a more wholistic approach to being, knowing, feeling, and relating. Not only can each of these be broadened, enhanced, and de-specialized, but they can be better interconnected with one another, or decompartmentalized. The process is one of re-conceptualizing the knowledge as a whole from its postmodern fragments. It is important to realize, however, that such a result is only enabled by new technologies and new ways of thinking--it is not guaranteed. As remarked in the sections on the use of the Metalibrary, people would as easily be able to tailor its facilities so as to reinforce their existing world views (filters on the body of knowledge) and thus simply ignore any one else's. It is also conceivable that a totalitarian regime of political or religious origin might be able to enforce a certain world view and set of relationships on its people, at least for a time.

12.2.1 Integration as a Process of Consilience The argument that all knowledge has always been part of a seamless whole

waiting to be discovered or at least assembled is far from new. Neither is it unique to this text. In his 1998 book Consilience--The Unity of Knowledge, noted philosopher of science, Edward O. Wilson, argues this point in a powerful manner.

"Most of the issues that vex humanity daily--ethnic conflict, arms escalation, overpopulation, abortion, environment, endemic poverty, to cite several persistently before us--cannot be solved without integrating knowledge from the natural sciences with that of the social sciences and humanities. Only fluency across the boundaries will provide a clear view of the world as it really is... Wilson: Consilience--The Unity of Knowledge, p. 13

This, according to Wilson, was not only the view of the Enlightenment, it is the only correct way to approach knowledge. He presses an integration of the natural sciences, social sciences, humanities, the arts, religion, and ethics, with arguments similar to those already familiar to readers of earlier chapters of this book. Wilson calls the empirical process of joining knowledge together by the linkage of facts and fact-based theories "consilience," and views the ability for some fact or idea to become a part of the whole in this specific way to be the only possible test of its truth. To Wilson, if something is not scientifically integrable with the whole, it is not knowledge.

Central to Wilson's thesis is that knowledge can only be unified under the rubric of evolution, and that the empiricism of the natural scientist is the sole valid means by which anything--including ethics--can be known. In all realms, humans are, believe, emote, act, think, and perceive as they do, according to Wilson, because they have evolved to do so down through the millennia in a self-organizing

489

Page 490: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

and entirely autonomous fashion. They need only understand what they have evolved into, and they will know everything else as a by-product. His faith is that the scientific method in general, and evolutionary biology in particular will ultimately explain and subsume everything else.

"Once we get over the shock of discovering that the universe was not made with us in mind, all the meaning that the brain can master, and all the emotions it can bear, and all the shared adventure we may wish to enjoy, can be found by deciphering the hereditary orderliness that has borne our species through geological time, and stamped it with the residues of deep history. Reason will be advanced to new levels, and emotions played in potentially infinite patterns. The true will be sorted from the false, and we will understand each other very well, the more quickly because we are all of the same species and possess biologically similar brains." Wilson: Consilience--The Unity of Knowledge, p. 43

Thus, Wilson's consilience is a sweepingly general process by which autonomously evolved humankind builds an understanding of evolution, and so takes control of its own evolution. It is a rational and empirical joining of knowledge to demonstrate truth by virtue of its unity under the rubric of evolution. Anything that cannot be conciliated empirically is not knowledge; indeed it may not be anything. Wilson's view could be summarized:

The process of consilience is the next step in human evolution--the cataloguing, validation, integration and subsumption of all knowing under the empirical.

12.2.2 Integration to Show Concinnity However compelling to the secularist, Wilson's argument for what amounts to

a revival of logical positivism hinges on some important presuppositions, none of which are provable by empirical methods. Here are some of them:

1. That self-directing evolution is not just an organizing paradigm, but a historical fact, even though unverifiable,

2. That a transcendental creator-God not only can be dispensed with as a hypothesis, but that Wilson can himself positively and accurately assert that no such being exists,

3. That empiricism will eventually become capable of explaining ultimate meaning as well as of describing and organizing some kinds of facts and theories, even though it has never before been capable of this,

4. That the mind can be completely understood by a scientific description of the brain, and

5. That religion itself is only an evolved internalized mechanism growing out of the survival value of ethical behaviour.

However, an almighty God who created the universe as something other than Himself could only be known if He chose to reveal Himself in that universe. Lacking such action, no empirical method could uncover one who exists outside the universe He created. Such a failure is not evidence that God does not exist, it only reflects on

490

Page 491: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the inability of the human senses to judge and measure one who transcends those faculties by virtue of being their creator. To be sure, some of the creator's qualities might be inferred from the physical world, but He personally could not be deduced, reduced, described or related to without moving beyond the physical. Thus, in promoting what amounts to an aggressive atheism as the conciliator of all knowledge, Wilson makes himself the transcendent arbiter of ultimate truth--and in areas not knowable by him in the exclusive manner he proposes for discovering that truth.

Thus, there is plenty of space for an opposing view, and as in other contexts in this textbook, the obvious candidate is design--a position that must be taken by most Christians, and likely will be by those of many other religions as well. In this view, knowledge is a seamless whole not because it happens to have become self-woven with the thread of human evolution, but because it comes from an integral God whose creation was always a well-designed integral whole, and can only be perceived correctly as such--not in limited fragments.

In this view, it is not the process (consilience-integration) of building up the whole from parts that is the primary focus. Integration of parts is here not the end of an evolution of wholistic knowledge, but a means to discover and demonstrate that all creation was from the beginning well-designed intentionally and elegantly as a seamless whole in order to glorify the creator. This could be summarized as:

Integration is a means to discover and illustrate the comprehensive concinnity (i.e., skilful and harmonious unity, aesthetic beauty, and rational organization of creation's design.

Thus, while "consilience" is a process of pulling (literally "jumping") together pieces of empirical knowledge into a coherently evolved whole, "concinnity" describes the well-designedness of creation that humankind can discover by virtue of having been made in the image of the creator and so having the capacity of thinking His thoughts after Him. Further, while consilience limits itself to the empirical and has no referents external to humankind, the creator's concinnity necessarily includes the spiritual or transcendental realm as well.

The two positions differ sharply on whether integration is an end in itself (consilience) or a means to the end of discovering a preexisting design (concinnity). They agree, however, that knowledge, understanding, behaviour, emotion, and being need to be seen as inextricably interwoven, either because they were made that way (concinnity) or because it is useful to construct them that way (consilience).

12.3 Aspects of Integration Setting aside for the time being the question of under which rubric one ought

best, on the one hand, to attempt a consilience of all knowing (as Wilson might put it) or reveal the concinnity of all that exists (as this book would have it), the purpose of the next few sections is to demonstrate specific needs for integration as a means to piece together post-industrial fragments.

Integrating Being and Beliefs

491

Page 492: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The world view of the citizen of the next civilization will initially inherit much of the rationality, pragmatism, empiricism and humanism from their machine age counterparts in a very straightforward manner. Because of the de-emphasis on the need for personal factual knowledge of specialized techniques and the new emphasis on ideas, fact finding, and evaluation, people may generally be more aware of what they believe, of their world view, of who they are, of why they know what they do, and of how their knowledge is related. This implies a greater emphasis on the influence of such beliefs (who a person is) on knowledge, experience, and relationships. It may be clearer that the kinds of things that are said to be "known" (and what is meant when this is said) depend heavily on one's total world view. It may be more evident that the nature of one's experience or experimentation is a consequence of such beliefs as well. There is already a greatly increased interest in ethics--one result of applying a set of beliefs to relationships. Moreover, such an integration will not be confined to an intellectual elite, because the working demands of the information age require far more people to be well-trained and educated. It is not difficult to predict, even to discern already, a greatly increased interest in philosophy and religion as a result of this new emphasis on the heart of what it means to be human.

Integrating Experience

Everyone gathers data and experiments with the surrounding world on a continuous basis. These data come from the senses of touch, taste, and so on, in a direct manner, and from relating with other people or using the communications media in a less direct way. These data are constantly being integrated with past experiences and emotional responses to create new reactions, relationships, and ideas. For example, one might read about a new type of cancer, and file away the fact of it. Later, a television documentary could provoke recollection of the earlier fact and heighten interest. If a relative is diagnosed with the ailment, the knowledge becomes more personal and emotional. Both what are called "hard facts" of everyday living and the more hidden emotional aspects of life are a part of such experience. The emotional and the audio-visual-tactile are both a part of the raw data or base truths that each person experiences and remembers, and though contrary to Wilson there is no evidence yet that the emotions can simply be subsumed under the empirical, the two aspects do bear on each other and need to be taken into consideration together. Here, both are taken as aspects of experience.

Data gathering (including reading and listening) also take on new forms and meanings in the fourth civilization because new information media, such as the Metalibrary, enable new ways of obtaining and using knowledge, and informing the determination of answers to the "What else is?" questions. There may be somewhat less relative emphasis on the empirical (data from experience) and this will have to be more fully integrated into the whole person as it becomes realized that the rational/empirical description of humankind is insufficient to achieve a general integration of the person. One of the interesting challenges for artificial intelligence research would be to develop machines that can experience sight, touch, sound, emotions, and so on. This may be almost as difficult as providing such artifacts with

492

Page 493: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

the ability to comprehend or even to know in an abstract sense. It may turn out to be the chief obstacle in developing any sense of "being" for such machines.

People will have a broader range of experiences in the fourth civilization. Those who have employment will necessarily have more training and re-training, more education, and more factual knowledge available to them. There will be better communications, transportation and information access. As in the past, higher technology will mean that there will be more sharable wealth, although this does not mean that everyone, even in the prosperous countries, will share such benefits equally. History would suggest that there will continue to be both rich and poor individuals but that the general standard of living will rise, even for the poor. It would also suggest that there will continue to be rich and poor nations, and that people may continue to starve to death even in a more prosperous world.

In the same manner, information technology gives more access to the experiences of very different people. Thus, there would be more sharable experiences in the information age, and this could suggest that greater acceptance of others might be enabled. As with the sharing of wealth, this enabling does not mean that there will be more tolerance of other peoples, only that there will be additional forces empowering it. If the arguments presented in this book do turn out to be correct predictors, there will be more international cooperation as a result of greater knowledge--not only knowledge of other peoples, but of the total interdependence each person and nation has with every other. One also, as always, must be careful to define what is meant by "tolerance." Here it is used in the sense of a benign acceptance of differences, not in the aggressive sense that demands all that beliefs be given equal credence or value and marginalizes those who believe they know one or more absolutes.

It is important to note that, although greater sharing of experiences promotes greater toleration, this sharing does not in itself solve the problems of hunger, racism, waste, pollution, and war. Actual solutions will not come easily or soon, but the premise here is that it is likely to make more people aware of the mutual nature of such problems and increase the desire to solve them.

Integrating Knowledge

This may be the area that changes most in the new civilization. The number of people whose livelihoods depend on the depth of detail in their speciality knowledge will be far fewer. Although specialities will continue to exist, the people who master them will either be serial specialists who move on to new areas of interest after a few years, or parallel specialists who have a wide and shifting range of related interests. That is, there may well be even more speciality knowledge, but it will be more diffuse insofar as individuals are concerned, for they will need to be able to find it when needed, not know everything about a speciality all the time. Their knowledge will also have to extend to the ethical and legal effects of their work, and will be predicated on better organized and more efficient thinking, greater productivity and creativity in ideas, and a much wider base of ideas and techniques for work skills. This means that people will have broader and somewhat less focused educations and be more acquainted with a broader variety of disciplines. They will

493

Page 494: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

therefore be enabled to apply insights obtained in one to solve problems in others, and might, for instance, even look to Medieval and Renaissance scholars for insights in how to be this way.

If the prediction of longer life spans is correct, this trend may be sharply accentuated in the long run as knowledge workers, including academics, change from one area of interest to another over their lifetime. The longer a life becomes, the smaller will be the number of people who regard their current special interests, job, or social situation as permanent, and the greater the percentage who will have spent at least part of their professional lives engaged in what are now called academic or scholarly pursuits. It is now taken as commonplace that most people entering the work force in the fourth civilization will have to be prepared either to change careers altogether several times or else re-invent their jobs continuously throughout their working lives.

It should be evident from discussions in Chapter 1 that this scenario also depends on large-scale transfer of goods production to machines--the second industrial revolution--and perhaps to some extent also on the intelligence revolution. After all, the proportion of people depending on intellectual activity for a living can only increase if the necessities of life are provided, and the premise of automation is that indeed they will be--by machines requiring very few human attendants.

It seems reasonable to suppose that one consequence of this will be that the "culture" of the scientist and technologist identified by Snow and others may become much broader and more diffuse as it extends into other disciplines of thought--borrowing, and changing itself as it goes. The fragments of late industrial culture may be reunited in some strange new ways, but if a new civilization is to rise, there must necessarily be a new intellectual cohesiveness. This scenario, which Wilson shares, but for different reasons, is quite unlike that of Ellul's--instead of a total victory of soul-less depersonalized technique, it predicts a merging of what has been technique with the humanities, social sciences, and religion to produce new and much more comprehensive ways of knowing.

However, that new paradigms and new facilities (like the Metalibrary) only enable such a diffusion and generalization; they do not determine its actual path. The broad new view of knowledge presented both here and by Wilson is very idealistic, and may turn out to be impossible for reasons as yet unforeseen, such as wars, politics, economics, and new technological directions. Nonetheless, it seems likely that what is regarded as knowledge in the future will be more broadly integrated across what have been very narrow intellectual specialities. Not only that, but the emphasis on the intellectual and scholarly will itself be more diffuse over the general population, as people pursue learning on a less single-minded, specialized, and full-time basis. Neither does admitting far more people to what has often been an elite club of academics have to dilute the quality of thinking; it could simply be the case that more adults have the time, inclination, and access to such activities. Moreover, in an information-based society, ideas are economically valuable, so practicality alone ought to dictate that the number of people involved in assessing and manipulating them will increase.

494

Page 495: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

An integrated view of knowledge and the intellect cannot be confined only to its own branches, but necessarily involves other aspects of the total person as well. Thus, one could also expect the fourth civilization would bring a greater emphasis on the mutual effect of knowledge on beliefs and relationships, and possibly a corresponding decrease in the relative stress placed on the specific aspect of the relationship of knowledge to the empirical--a special emphasis characteristic of the machine age, but one that need not be of the information one.

Integrating the Transformational and Relational

People change, and they cause other people to change because of what they believe, how they think, and what are their experiences. Free and open access to information suggests a possible breaking down of old relational barriers and a new emphasis on other people. This would be in sharp contrast to the "I-it" relations of the machine age and the specific raw "me-ism" of its latter decades. Such a shift seems to be necessary because while Me-ism is part of basic human nature, only if it is muted sufficiently to avoid excessive fragmentation and achieve a high level of cooperation is the continued existence of civilization possible. If this does happen, there will be a greatly increased emphasis on the application of ethical principles in relationships--a shift that does seem to have begun already.

In the working out of ethical relationships, both parties are transformed, just as in the working out of technologies knowledge is transformed. It is partly for this reason it was suggested in an earlier chapter that the new stress on environmental issues is not simply flash in the pan, but will be a permanent part of the social and intellectual landscape. More broadly, this new integration and emphasis on the transformational and relational is intimately connected with all aspects of the biospace revolution. The advent, to any significant degree, of artificially intelligent artifacts would also force re-examination of the relational. Not only would the question of who or what is a human need careful examination, but so also might, in the extreme case, the question of how to get along with other intelligences.

In addition, for many people the effective size of the world will shrink further, as communication technology improves. Some of the more totalitarian nations may be forced to operate with greater openness, for their dictators will be unable to hide their activities from the critical scrutiny of other nations. The industrial and then the information revolutions will come to more countries, and a far greater number of people will be enabled to have frequent contact with those from distant locations. These forces promoting unity will not necessarily homogenize culture or create a single "global village"; but they will at least force everyone to stress relationships with people they would once have ignored--just to function in their jobs. Again, it is not necessarily large social groupings and organizations such as the state, multinational corporations, and old-time institutional churches that will benefit the most. Rather, it is smaller social units such as local governments, entrepreneurial organizations, local clubs and churches, and families that might have the most to gain.

The integration of relationships does not just refer to other people and how one's actions affect them. It refers inward as well--the relational and

495

Page 496: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

transformational aspects of the individual person cannot be considered in isolation apart from world view, knowledge, and experience. But greater personal integration and wholeness do enable more substantial and deeper interpersonal relationships, even though they do not lead inevitably to these.

As the late 1990s events in Eastern Europe have shown, old hatreds, racial and religious divisions and old xenophobic nationalisms die hard, and there will always be those who perceive an advantage in the fanning of such flames anew. Even though such behaviour is manifestly not in the long-term self-interest of either individuals or nations, it may still take place. Indeed, one could argue that it is precisely new and close contacts with different cultures--especially very similar close neighbours--that lead to divisions and wars. That this is especially so among old enemies that have only been kept apart by fear of a greater one is now obvious throughout Eastern Europe. The most difficult thing to do with a relationship is to get it past the stage where little knowledge and much misunderstanding are dangerous things and onto the one where there is enough understanding to attempt conflict resolutions with a reasonable chance of success.

The New Renaissance Person

The admittedly idealistic portrait painted here is that of a fourth civilization people who think and act in greater harmony with themselves and with others. It is for this reason that religion may rise in importance--such a radical integration as suggested here forces people to re-examine and re-apply the meaning questions: "Who is God?" "Who am I?" "Why am I here?" "What can I know?" "What does my experience mean?" and "How then shall I live and relate to other people?" Such a re-examination also supposes that the answers are rationally and coherently integrated by a whole people into a whole culture.

However, the kind of integrated equilibrium suggested for this idealistic new Renaissance person is far from static. After all, the principal feature of the fourth civilization will be rapid, continual, and substantial change in economics, politics, technique, and ideas. Therefore, any new equilibrium of being, thinking, experiencing, and relating will necessarily be a dynamic one as well. This provides yet another reason to predict a rise of religion and of moral absolutism along with it--people will need "being anchors" to give them a definite sense of who they are and how they can go about integrating the other three in a rapidly changing environment. After all, there comes a point where being "in process of change" must be replaced with a sense of having arrived at someone definite, even if this does turn out only to be a temporary stop. Furthermore moral relativism was one of the fragment-promoters of the late industrial age; it does not fit an integrative paradigm very well.

Such anchors are most useful if they are non-contextual; that is if they take their meaning and substance from outside knowledge, experience, and relationships. In other words, they are at least in part religious, for they need to rest on that which is external to all of life in order to provide a meaning for life.

Such a radical re-integration of what had in the machine age become discrete compartments and fragments of life, intellect, and religion would force a re-

496

Page 497: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

invention of education, government, economics, corporations, family life, and society in general. The first four of these have been considered in some detail in earlier chapters, but there are some issues in family life and personal relationships that have not previously been mentioned, and it is with some of these that the next section is concerned.

12.4 Integration and Relationships To this point, most of the discussions in this book have focused on the big

issues--knowledge, philosophy, technique, and large institutions. One of the four areas of life involved in the radical integration of people is the relational, about which little has been said in detail thus far.

Personal relationships can be thought of as taking place on a variety of levels--from those with the whole society and culture to those with other individuals. It is the latter that give relationships their most direct sense of meaning, generating both experience and knowledge of those other persons. However philosophical and general one may become about relationships, they are actually conducted one at a time and in small groups. Specifically, they consist of a number of one-on-one pairs of personal and individual interactions that collectively form a group gestalt of an ever widening, more dilute, and less personal nature. Thus, it is appropriate now to give brief consideration to some of the more personal relational issues that grow out of the new paradigms and techniques and that themselves form aspects of the new civilization.

Men and Women

In some hunter-gatherer societies women were little more than possessions. Survival depended on the strength of one's arm or on those of one's allies or mate. In many cases, a strong man could take as many women as he could provide food and security for. Those physically less able--including women--had nothing to say about the matter--they could often be forced into submission, or simply killed. Relationships could be harsh, hard, and even brutal--but so was much of life.

Agrarian societies have generally had a more substantial role for women because they depend on animal power and some machines to enhance strength and rely less on personal brute force--at least on the part of farmers themselves. However, such societies have shortages and trade disputes, and therefore armies and wars. With these there often came an organized exploitation of those considered weak. Slaveries of whole nations or "races" became possible or even economically advantageous. In such an atmosphere the ability of women to become economic and political partners with men was severely limited. Along with all others who could be overcome by force, they were often still regarded as little more than chattels, and had few opportunities to break out of such a pattern. Matriarchies, or even the occasional woman monarch, were rare exceptions to the universal rule and authority of men, and this was in large part because such societies still depended on physical strength, even though for different things. All but the most rudimentary of training and education were unavailable to women in most manifestations of the

497

Page 498: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

second civilization, and they had few economic or other influences to use in order to change their lot.

In the industrial society, the picture changed dramatically. As more of the labour was transferred to machines, there was less need for physical strength to provide for daily sustenance. It gradually became evident that women could run machines as efficiently and effectively as men, and during times of war they did just that. Since the machines required a more educated work force, it also became obvious that women were as intellectually capable as men, so the educational and economic barriers to their full participation in society began to crumble, though centuries of tradition ensured that this process was slow.

Moreover, in the West, where the industrial and scientific revolutions took place, Christianity was the dominant religious force. After a long self-struggle, it found it already had a paradigm for the essential equality of the sexes--at least before God ("There is neither Jew nor Greek slave nor free, male or female, for you are all one in Christ Jesus." Galations 3:28). This idea eventually broke through into the broader society, where it ultimately became a political and social equality that went even further than many church groups desired, or thought doctrinally correct. Passages in the New Testament about the leadership role of men were cited by some as reason not to have equality in the broader society. But most Christians argued that, whether the original intent of these was doctrinal or cultural, they applied at most to Church and family, and had nothing to do with the workplace or politics.

These discussions became moot, however, for women joined the workplace in force starting as early as World War II, and this accelerated to record numbers in the 1970s and 1980s, so that the tradition of their staying at home became a cultural fragment, even among the conservatively religious. This change was not brought about solely by a different view of work. Much of it was economic--it became nearly impossible to support a family on a single income. Some reversal of this trend in the 1990s has not made much of an impact on the way most people think about work. Another reason why women gained economic power in this period is that widows rather than first-born sons came to be the inheritors, and since most women survived their mates, family monies passed into their hands at peak size.

The great economic story of the late industrial age years was the way that thriving Western economies absorbed both the post-war baby boom and the simultaneous sharp increase in female participation in the work force. In North America, the majority of women came to take working for granted.

In the late industrial age, men for the first time had no advantages due to their greater physical strength. In the information age, what counts in most occupations is intellectual and integrative ability. In this context, newcomers to the work force have great advantages, for they are not set in traditional ways of doing things--something often seen with new immigrants, for instance. Thus, even though women may be concentrated in areas such as secretarial, service, and middle management that are vulnerable to automation, they are also more mobile and flexible--not because of their gender, but because many are relatively new to the market. Those who are already working may therefore be somewhat less subject to long-term unemployment, more aggressive to retrain and displace themselves, and

498

Page 499: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

more able to survive radical change. They may also overtrain and overcompensate if they believe themselves to be making up for what they perceive to be past injustices.

Enrollment trends in medical, dental, and law schools by the late nineties indicate that the equality of numbers that was already reached among teachers would ultimately exist in these professions as well. Also, as Western women continued to reduce both their number of children and the amount of time they devote to raising them, salary inequities caused by childbearing dropout diminish. It is not difficult to predict that as these relative newcomers work their way to the top of their professions, there will continue to be many more women chief executive officers, judges, hospital administrators, and politicians. It seems possible that within a few decades it will be as likely to have a woman president, prime minister, premier, or governor in most Western nations as it will be to have a man in such roles.

On the other hand, many women who were not inclined or educated to make their own way received a harsh introduction to the realities of sexual "equality." For a substantial percentage, this has meant abandonment of them and their children by men who developed other interests. Increasingly, it meant leaving men who drank too much, assaulted them, abused their children, promiscuously pursued other women, or did all four. Indeed, this became one of the major social problems of the 1980s and 1990s, for such women suffer a sharp decline in living standards, while their former partners often enjoy an increase in disposable income. Because women in the twenty-five to forty-five-year age bracket were at that point the product of families and schools that operated on industrial age assumptions, they often had little education, less work experience, and no marketable skills, or if they had any of these, it was long out of date. As a result, they had to live either on social assistance or on the income from very low-paying jobs in which they were the most vulnerable to unemployment. They usually had young children to care for, and could not both work and do this themselves, nor could they afford to pay someone else to do it for them.

They were the victims both of the "sexual revolution" and of the trends to fragmentation and individualization that conspired together to cause many to throw off the former constraints of religion and custom and instead regard sexual liaisons as a passing thing rather than as part of a permanent commitment. In such an atmosphere, there was no underlying motivation to hold marriage together once passion had cooled, and many people became uninterested in trying. Too many women became like their men's used cars--traded back into the marketplace as soon as models perceived to be more glamorous became available. The culture did not help, for it had exploited women as decorations in the service of selling a variety of consumer goods, and the disillusionment that resulted when marriage stripped away the veneer and revealed a real person was too much for many to take.

If anything, the idea of autonomy and independence for all women promoted by the radical feminist movement has exacerbated the problem. Such independence may be a worthwhile goal for some, but there were many women who neither wanted nor were prepared for such independence in the industrial age, and instead found it thrust upon them at an awkward stage of life. Moreover, hyper-aggressive

499

Page 500: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

anti-male feminism has probably generated some costly backlash that has made things worse. Indeed, it is not even clear that the gains women made in the marketplace had anything to do with such political movements, or whether both were independent results of more fundamental economic and cultural forces. In any event, newly and involuntarily created women heads of households have few opportunities to retrain and enter the job market on the same terms as the less constrained and more highly educated younger woman can do.

The overall result of these gender shifts has been a re-definition of the entire workplace, with some women aggressively moving into the middle and higher end of the labour market to claim equal pay and status with men while others were forced into the lower end because their traditional male bread winners left them to fend for themselves. In this new milieu, a young woman of high school age can no longer expect to be able to find a lifelong male provider; she has to assume the responsibility of carving out her own niche in the marketplace. She therefore has to make personal learning and career choices as an individual in the same way that men have always done in the past, and quite independent of any considerations of marriage--even if she does not immediately enter the work force on graduation from school or university. Schooling becomes a necessity, as does the choice of the "right" courses. For example, women can not afford to give in to social or other pressures and avoid the hard subjects such as mathematics, physics, and computing science if they expect to play the economic game in the future on an equal basis with men.

On a more personal level, the days when one or the other partner could dominate a marriage relationship, make all the money and the decisions, and determine the entire family agenda, had passed in most Western families by the time the information age was underway. In the future, women might afford so little time from their careers for childbearing, and not much more for child raising, that the impact of their sex on their careers will be very much reduced. It may, however, take an entire generation to rescue the victims of this transition from the ghettos into which they have been forced by making what turned out to be the wrong learning choices and mating assumptions. Much of a generation has been caught off guard by a sudden change in course, unprepared for independence and equality; their daughters are unlikely to rely on the same assumptions.

These changes have severely strained men as well, for they have been shaken out of their traditional roles in order to accommodate women moving in. Some men may feel threatened by the prospect of reporting to a woman, or of being married to one who commands a higher salary--perhaps high enough to relegate the man to the housekeeping role, or at least to the follower when his wife is transferred to another city. At the close of the industrial age, there was an increasing fragmentation of male/female relationships, fewer men and women were selecting long-term commitment or faithfulness as a way of life, with more of them either dropping out of marriage or never entering it. In this casualization of relationships, they were supported by various pop philosophy versions of relativism and hedonism, by the sexual revolution's inversion of morality, by an increasingly accommodating and largely irrelevant religious climate, and by the corresponding fragmentation of the once monolithic society around them. Much less support

500

Page 501: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

existed for the old-time and long-term stability of commitment, so it was no longer being followed as much as in the past. At the same time, the wide gap between male and female life expectancies, coupled with the tendency of past decades of men to marry younger women, would have ensured that most women would spend many years alone, as widows if not as divorcees.

What is more, there are early information age factors that have tended to exacerbate male/female tensions. In its early days, the computer was largely a male preserve, a toy for the men who were already dominating mathematics, science and engineering, and who once would have had model trains, collected stamps, or built furniture for a hobby--none of which many women did. Now they bought home computers, and isolated themselves from their families even more with their new pastime than with their old. There was also initially a perceived appeal in programming work to a certain kind of pioneering male who once might have been seen as a misfit and dropped out of school or even society altogether, but who could now legitimately fall in love with a predictable, safe, and impersonal machine. At the same time, he could master it, dictate to it, and make it perform extraordinary feats--all without any concern for its potential to damage his ego when something went wrong. It would never question his manhood, care about his faithfulness, criticize, complain, use sarcasm as a weapon, or fight at all, much less fight dirty.

It was some of these very social misfits who were the most successful early programmers, and who eventually had sufficient money from their efforts that everyone listened to them, so that they could define for others how they would fit in. For a variety of social, cultural, and economic reasons, this was a path to success that attracted few women, and almost none took it. The result was that men dominated the computing and information sciences at first even more than they had some of the traditional ones.

However, programming is now a sufficiently complex and mature technique to be studied as an academic discipline rather than learned entirely on one's own, so there is a path into the heart of the industry that is more conventional, and at least some women are taking it. They are also entering high-technology realms as users, trainers, managers, editors, executives, sellers, designers, and manual writers--all areas in which a highly skilled and specialized programmer is often severely lacking. Thus, as the industry matures, women are finding excellent positions, and often ending up in management--more than making up for being latecomers. There can be little doubt that there are far greater opportunities for educated women in the new industries than in the old, because in the new it may be more possible for them to compete on equal terms without having to be concerned with stereotypes or with an entrenched male-dominated establishment. Moreover, they are in a job-seeker's seller's market, because sufficiently knowledgeable and skilled people for the information industry are in ever-increasing demand, and will be for some time. There are even opportunities for women to work at home and manage their families without a man, although telecommuting is not yet as important a factor in the job market as it may become.

Thus, there continue to be strong forces acting to promote equal participation of women in the new marketplaces, despite the setbacks many of them have had due to the dissolution of large numbers of marriages, and despite lingering

501

Page 502: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

reluctance to study mathematics. The new civilization will be the age of non-specialized ideas and information, and physical strength without intellectual ability and education will be a severe disadvantage. It is even possible that women may come to dominate men, rather than be their subjects as in the past. While this suggestion may seem far-fetched, history would seem to suggest that when a large group of people who have had to survive on their wits is suddenly freed from bondage, an extreme swing of the power pendulum may well take place. If it did, it would counter other trends toward egalitarianism, but it is in the fourth civilization that just such startling and unpredictable exceptions are taking place during transitional periods. After all, cultural fragments can be assembled in a variety of ways; the "best" is not necessarily discovered first. Indeed, it is those who first successfully assemble the fragments into a cohesive cultural whole who thereby acquire the power to define their way as having been best all along.

Many men, especially younger ones who have grown up in a more egalitarian society, will adapt well to the changes in sexual roles. Others will react very negatively, and one also cannot rule out the possibility of a substantial backlash against successful women. Some men, finding their physical skills no longer in demand, and facing a new culture ill-equipped, could retreat into defeatism, random violence, and alcoholism. Indeed, if the "macho-male" culture suffers a substantial defeat in the face of new cultural patterns, the result for many could be similar to a military defeat by a superior civilization--total despair. Judging by certain historical parallels, it could take at least several generations to effect either a recovery from the cultural shock or assimilation by the new one.

It is interesting to note in this context that social institutions such as schools, and parental and peer pressure still promote an effective gender segregation. Most boys and girls still grow up in two non-intersecting worlds, with their own friends, toys, activities, and values. They live it side by side in the elementary school but do not really meet until their teenage years, when a different set of the same kind of pressures rushes them into sexual intimacy before they even know who they are. That is, the forces favouring sexual equality are economic, not yet educational, and certainly not yet very culturally rooted. They are therefore fragile, and are vulnerable to being diverted to a variety of possible extremes.

It is also worthwhile to cite the despecializing and integrative themes of the fourth civilization in connection with the trend to establish local and personal relationships. Thus, whereas university students in the sixties had their causes, and in the seventies their self-fulfillment, those of the late eighties and nineties opted either for financial security or for friendship as the highest value and most important goal. Because men and women often still grow up in sexual solitudes, such friendships are mainly of the same-sex type, but the openness of the fourth civilization and its new stress on personal relationships may well lead to the breaking down of some of the cultural barriers to opposite-sex friendships. Broad networks of friends will gradually become more important in both business and politics, and will be the principal basis for personal and loyalties and professional partnerships, much more so than obedience to hierarchical command structures.

Similar points might be cited, to become contrarian, predicting an increase in the number of permanent, monogamous marriages, and there is some indication

502

Page 503: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

that this may be taking place. However, such commitments in the future will be partnerships of essential equals as the old gender solitudes give way to more open and less private but deeper relationships. On the other hand, the advent of any substantial increase in life spans will be a severe test for marriage, perhaps more so than was the so-called sexual revolution, for under such circumstances a lifetime commitment is a far more serious matter, because it must be maintained over a much longer time. In such a context, and from a little distance, it might almost be as tempting to predict the virtual demise of such marriages, but the suggestion here is that commitments, because they are integrative, will become more important, and that they will overwhelm the other factors.

Thus, there are social and economic factors that may promote sexual equality over the long term. There are also factors that are exacerbating some of the old tensions, some that are creating new ones, and some promoting new harmonies. It may be a couple of generations at least before things settle down, and a new kind of male/female relationship is established. There is also the possibility that some new extreme may become the norm for a time.

It is also important to realize that not all women find the social trends described here to be to their liking. Some want to work as home managers and feel uncomfortable with, or even antagonistic to the messages that seek to persuade them otherwise. They wonder if there is a place in the new world for wives and mothers, or whether they will be forced into a marketplace they have no desire to enter, and they feel that the apostles of feminism are too busy advancing their own careers to hear dissenting voices. Their voices too will shape the new society, and in some ways may prove more powerful than some of the economic factors.

Children

Much of what has been said so far might be construed as suggesting that children are endangered and that the traditional family may turn out to be a thing of the past. To a great extent, this may well be true, and there are a variety of reasons for it. While families were the centre and mainstay of community life in both hunter-gatherer and agrarian societies--because of the need for cooperative action to survive--they were only one component of industrial society, which took its shape on the basis of other organizations and from work, rather than on the basis of personal relationships. The industrial society has ended in a highly specialized and fragmented state, with the traditional family seeming to play a much reduced role, and many observers claiming that it no longer need constitute the basic societal framework. The extent to which this perception is true is somewhat doubtful; although there are certainly far more single-parent and otherwise non-traditional family units, the family still exercises an important influence on society. There can be little doubt, however, that this influence has been in a period of perceived decline.

Moreover, economic and population pressures in an information society cause extreme downward pressure on the birthrate, and so does the fact that a mother

503

Page 504: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

can no longer assume that there will be a father on the scene for very much of her potential children's lives. These factors, coupled with what in effect is free abortion on demand in many Western countries, are causing a dramatic reduction in the relative number of children, especially in the cities. Prolongation of life much beyond the present seventy to eighty years is likely to increase this pressure, even though it could extend the number of possible childbearing years. Even the post-war "baby boom" was only a temporary wavering above the trend line of births, which has been falling steadily throughout the entire industrial age. There is no reason to suppose that in the fourth civilization there will be anything but cyclical variations in this trend, despite the continuing high birthrates in agrarian societies elsewhere. Indeed, even those reflect a lag behind a declining death rate, which can confidently be expected to be followed by a corresponding decline in births, judging from the Western experience.

One could argue that growing up has itself become more difficult, for far fewer children in North America can now count on the presence or the attention of even one parent for any substantial portion of their developmental years. In such families, children are frequently left to fend for themselves at baby-sitters', at school, soccer clubs and other activities--out of the sight and hearing of their parent(s). Starting at a very early age, they make their own decisions, pick their own friends and activities, buy their own clothes and music, and live their own independent lives without much traditional parental oversight. The one parent, or both where applicable, works all day and there is much less energy left for children than there once would have been. These children have little guidance, and lack much opportunity to learn by example or teaching about traditional familial, cultural, and religious values--for in all these things too they are left on their own to make individual decisions. While some claim this produces better decision makers, this practice also contributes to an increased fragmentation of culture and society, and helps to ensure that the only value passed on by example is that of a ceaseless striving for self-satisfaction and economic success.

The building of a social fabric begins with young children; if this is simply abandoned there ought not to be any surprise when they reach adulthood and have no commitment to the values and laws of the society they find. Even if parents could transmit 75% of their ideas to the next generation, and it has 25% new ones of its own, it would be only six generations before the original transmission constituted less than the new ideas of the current generation. But, if the value transmittal is less than 50 percent, the world view of parents is potentially overturned with every new generation.

On the other hand, if each decade or so changes a very small percentage of the population because of low birth and mortality rates, the progression of change through society could be slow. Moreover, low birth rates could mean a high value for children and more attention paid to them, and this might increase the rate of culture transmission. Thus, despite recent fragmentation of the family, it may yet turn out to be an important institution of the fourth civilization. After all, there are not many other candidates for the role of basic societal building block.

504

Page 505: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Relationships and Sexual Behavior

As observed in Chapter 3, it is not certain how much of the "sexual revolution" was real and how much was simply more publicity for activities that had always been undertaken. It can scarcely be doubted, however, that public perceptions have an effect on behaviour. The encouragement of the media, peers, and social leaders to throw off old norms and experiment with sex has brought about a substantial change in the way the most intimate of relationships is viewed and practised. Rather than being seen as a way to express commitment in a permanent, monogamous and heterosexual marriage, sexual relations have come to be as fragmented as other ones. In at least their public and media image, they became temporary, promiscuous, casual, and indiscriminate as to gender. Except to suggest a possible partial reversal of this trend, fourth civilization paradigms have little to say about such matters, and they would be best considered as moral issues.

However, there are social and medical consequences to the casualization of sexuality that cannot be ignored. Apart from the obvious connection--not necessarily cause and effect--to the decline of the family, society's most pressing concern is now with the spread of disease by such means. There have always been STDs (sexually transmitted diseases), but old nemeses such as gonorrhea and syphilis had been thought to have been relegated by drugs to the role of mere inconveniences. Genital herpes could have in time changed that view of the situation, but it, though as yet incurable, was at least not life-threatening. Even the very widespread chlamydia trachomatis bacteria caused only a few cases of blindness, and its more common effect--infertility--was much less publicized.

The arrival of AIDS changed the situation permanently, however, because casual sexual behaviour can now result in death. Not only is no cure in sight, there is little to hold back the grisly symptoms of a wasting, painful, and inevitable demise. Although health authorities were at first confident that only injecting blood or having male homosexual sex would cause transmission, blood transfusions, and even routine dental work are all likely to continue as factors in the global spread of AIDS for some time, for even proper syringe sterilization, much less routine blood detection tests have not yet come to many countries. Moreover, it is now apparent that heterosexual sex also spreads AIDS, though less rapidly.

Moreover, the early recommendations that condoms were sufficient preventatives are now being hedged in the light of their well-known poor performance even as birth control devices, for they break or leak in up to ten percent of uses. An individual who engages in sex on a casual basis in a population with, say, a 5% infection rate will be exposed to infection after an average of 13.5 sexual encounters. The same individual who consistently employs condoms--which break or leak 10% of the time--will be exposed to infection after an average of 138 encounters. Indeed, virus particles can go right through the pores in latex rubber, and few doctors feel safe from infection even when double gloved. This analysis of course does not apply to non-random encounters, for if one's sole sexual partner is not and does not become infected, no number of encounters will expose one. Thus, although the use of condoms may slow down the spread of the disease, it does not stop it, and the higher the percentage of the population infected and the greater the

505

Page 506: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

degree of sexual adventurism, the faster the disease will proliferate even in places where needles and drugs are clean and condoms are used. In other places, it spreads unhindered, threatening to sharply reduce the population in some regions of the world. The "safe sex" campaigns are not just misleadingly named; they have tended to encourage casual sexuality and minimize consciousness of risk, while increasing actual risk.

Thus, there is a potent pragmatic reason to change actual sexual behaviour--the fear of death. Society as a whole also has a powerful incentive to stop the spread of AIDS and to find a treatment, for even the number of individuals infected by the late 1990s had the potential to bankrupt the entire Western medical system within another decade. These considerations could trigger a dramatic change in the practice of sexual relations--possibly a swing of the pendulum far to a conservative or even repressive extreme. Among church groups there are already large groups of young men and women who have made public vows of chastity until marriage.

At the very least, relationships are likely to be more cautious than in the recent past and the trend toward the integrating of relational fragments may reinforce a behavioural change. The economic result of such a change could be bad news for the operators of brothels, and owners of sex boutiques, but any move to greater sexual equality and less relational fragmentation would put additional pressures on these industries anyway, sharply reducing their presence and influence even without the AIDS scare. Countering this suggestion, however, is that the marketers of pornography have made their business a major world industry, especially on the Internet, and show every indication of gaining ground.

Summary

Nothing is certain about any of the trends in personal relationships discussed in this section, and other factors could intervene to render some of the points made here entirely moot. However, when viewed on a historical basis, the casual and fragmented state of relationships of recent years appears as somewhat of an anomaly; one could be on relatively safe ground in forecasting radical changes for this reason alone. The two greatest relational challenges will be to re-invent the lost art of friendships and to break out of the gender solitudes. A society that fails on both counts may still form the fourth civilization, but it will be nonetheless impoverished for remaining fragmented.

12.5 Integration and Society Integrating the fragments to build a new civilization will be neither a simple

nor an easy task. The new will be built partly from remnants of the old, but it will have to have a new social glue, a new world view, new technology, and a new ethical consensus. This section will contain a summary of how some of the ideas throughout the book relate to this integrative theme.

Fragmentation and Dependence

506

Page 507: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The theme of dependence has been an important one in this book. As indicated in Chapter 1, the course of history depends on the ethics and technology of the people it describes. Indeed, the very notion of society assumes human interdependency. All actions are part of chains of consequence--they have effects, and none of them is isolated--everyone's depend on everyone else's. The same is true of technology--everything is connected to everything else. Thus in sum, as in Chapter 1:

It is impossible to be, to know, to experience or to change one thing.

The recognition of this principle is at the root of building of new cultures, for whatever its diversity, a society consists of the commonality of interests and mutual dependencies that have been agreed to by the people involved--even in the inherently unstable situations where this agreement has been temporarily secured by force. In the difficult years of transition when an old society is brought face-to-face with its successor, the old inevitably fragments. This has been pronounced in the current transition because of two additional factors: First, rapid technological change has coincided with pronounced shifts in the ethical and spiritual foundations of Western culture, and these have promoted equally rapid social changes. Second, the specialization that was so important to the industrial age tended to encourage people to fragment their life roles into discrete compartments. One result has been to place great stress on the individual and reduce the emphasis on duties and responsibilities to society as a whole.

This book has attempted to make the case that, as a new world view takes hold, new bonds of dependency must emerge and that these will give structural form to the successor civilization. The new will still depend on machines, on techniques, and on speciality knowledge, but these will exist and operate in the background of society, rather than by being its sum and substance. People will tend to the needs of other people for more of their time than they spend watching over machines, and they will concentrate more on ideas and somewhat less on technique.

Two trends may affect the speed at which cultural fragments of the machine age are assembled into a new form. First, reaction to perceived extremes of fragmentation may promote even more rapid integration--in the same contrarian manner that the stock market often reacts after a too-sharp increase or decrease in prices. Such perceptions of concern may include those of the breakdown of old moral codes and religions, an increased crime rate, the isolation of individuals from each other and from government, emphasis on rights to the exclusion of duty and responsibilities, and the focus on individuals at the expense of society. The extent to which such beliefs are true matters less than that people become uneasy with social instability and seek a new and more solid social framework in which to think, work and relate to others. Chaos--even the mistaken perception of it--is simply not stable.

An opposing trend is the continuing rapid pace of technological change, which may contribute to the propagation of new technological and social fragments on an ongoing basis. As a result, it may be necessary for the next society to have continuing dynamic integration as an important operating principle, at least for a

507

Page 508: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

time. There is also the possibility, in those nations that are already highly industrialized, that the momentum of the pattern of fragment creation in late-industrial society will result in an "overshoot" into wide-scale social disintegration, aborting the coming of the fourth civilization as described here, or shifting its locus to other parts of the world. The potential for such "overshoot" will be examined more carefully in section 6 of this chapter. It is therefore conceivable that the nations best equipped to successfully implement an information age integration may be those that do not have a long industrial history accompanied by a debilitating load of cultural fragments. In other words, China or some other nation building from scratch may inherit the future, rather than the West.

Redefining Culture

This last observation applies to all aspects of the machine age culture--they must be re-integrated into a cohesive unity, in order for it to be meaningful to speak of the advent of a fourth civilization. This means, for example, that the academic disciplines must cross-fertilize and begin to integrate. It means that the population as a whole must have better access to and better opportunities to participate in what have in the past been called "academic" activities, and that the intellectual elitism of the past will continue to diminish. It therefore means that there must be a better and more broadly educated population. It implies a renaissance in the arts, new interests in the social sciences and humanities, a more human face on science and technique, a new ethical consensus, and likely a revived general interest in underpinning religious ideas. It means coming to terms with a dynamic view of the physical world and a rapprochement even between science and religion. More broadly, it means gaining the ability to assess ideas, however strange they may initially seem. After all, if certain ideas, disciplines, or doctrines are fit only for intellectual ghettos, it would not be long before the people who expressed them found themselves likewise isolated. In short, integration takes place as interdependence is recognized and a whole culture is pieced together, a whole civilization is built.

In particular, the conundrums faced as the fourth civilization begins are so large, so pressing, and so comprehensive, that humankind can no longer afford the luxury of not using cross-disciplinary approaches in their solution. Environmental problems, for instance, require scientific, economic, social, and political solutions that make sense not in isolation from each other--which is where their practitioners worked in the machine age--but in unified concert. Snow's "two cultures" have to cross boundaries and become one--not by way of a takeover by the sciences as Wilson would have it, but as a true partnership of equals.

What is true in the academic sphere is true of the world as a whole. Its peoples live on a single planet, and are interdependent whether they care to be or not. Environmental, social, economic, and political problems know no boundaries; their solutions cannot either. This is not to suggest a homogenization of all the world's disparate cultures; it is rather to point out the necessity of their cooperating more than competing. The fourth civilization is global in scope; people and cultural

508

Page 509: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

groups who attempt to stay entirely their own course and keep others at bay will either fail in the attempt or find themselves shut out of the new era.

Hierarchicalism and Networking

The nature of relationships is also different in a more open and unified, less individualistic and fragmented culture. In all of the first three civilizations, relationships were principally conducted through a hierarchy. The hierarchical family, which one could argue was shaped by the prevailing technological environment, served as a model for all of society. Thus, religious institutions, governments, and eventually corporations all were structured in hierarchical fashion and had a command pyramid. One individual was the leader in each of these organizations or in each sub-cell, and had a variety of assistants, each with their departments and authorities. Most people in the organization or larger society were a part of the led, the commanded, the governed, or the workers, and their function was to obey, to follow and to accomplish the tasks given them.

The fourth civilization focus on the dependency of people upon each other and on the importance of their relationships with each other increases the value of what each person contributes to the commonality. This is antithetical to a hierarchical command structure in most activities of the culture. Interconnections of information, technique and relationships are too complex to maintain under a simple hierarchy, and the technology is available to handle them in several dimensions simultaneously, not just vertically. The appropriate model for a culture in which barriers are dismantled, privacy is lessened, and fragments are integrated, is an informed network of partnerships in work and relationships, rather than an inflexible chain of command and obedience. There will of course always be leaders, but effective leadership in the fourth civilization will be more by enlightened consent, and much less by absolute fiat.

Thus, the suggestion was made in Chapter 9 that representative democracy might ultimately give way to participatory forms--on the local level first, but with the potential for extension to a worldwide scope eventually. Other organizations now having an extensive hierarchy, such as some churches, may find their influence decline rapidly unless they devolve the decision making process to their members. More specifically, they will have to realize and respond to the fact that fourth civilization organizations will be the people who make them up, they will not either command or even necessarily employ them. Decision making and accountability in all areas will become much broader and more mutual; in most organizations people will be mutually responsible rather than hierarchically accountable. Such a model could be termed networked accountability and the term implies that each person has direct and mutual responsibility for the success of the total enterprise, precisely because they are the enterprise.

In a hierarchical system, those at the lower and wider end of the pyramid have only to do as they are told. Even if they wish to know about policy, decision making, and the management objectives and goals of the total enterprise, management/politicians/religious leaders can frustrate this desire by keeping necessary information from the lower ranks. Authority flows one way and

509

Page 510: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

accountability flows the other. Absolute monarchies, feudal systems and their surviving relatives under the modern communist, third-world police states, and religious theocracies epitomize this in the political realm, and the closely held and managed corporation does in the economic one.

A networked model for government would surely imply a participatory democracy with minimal formal government apparatus, as the functions of providing society with an infrastructure would be broadly diffused among many small professionally owned and operated enterprises. These would have a local scope and focus in most cases. Relationships with distant places could be handled by agents on the scene and by long distance communications rather than by large numbers of political appointees and diplomats.

Recent moves by some Western governments such as those of England and Canada to privatize many of the corporations they have built or acquired could therefore just be just the beginning of a trend that could also see a massive localization of many previously centralized services. There is resistance to this both from statists and from those who perceive the apparent fragmentation of hierarchical structures as the end of the process rather than as a means to reassemble them on a diffusely networked basis. There will also be opposition from vested interests such as unions, whose leaders will try in vain to dissuade their members from participating in such activities, say, by purchasing their workplace. The opposition will be particularly strong where the enterprise has been a part of the industrial age centralized state, and it is necessary to move it to the entrepreneurial private sector, for the opponents will then attempt to arouse public passions against the inevitable by wrapping themselves in patriotism to make their pronouncements. As the example of the former Soviet Union shows, the process of diffuse privatization can also be taken hostage by organized criminals along the way, temporarily halting any benefit to the common people.

Similar trends can be seen in churches, which, though slower than business to respond to social change are much faster than government. Centralized and tightly governed denominations are giving way to fellowships of like-minded congregationally-governed groups having a support staff, but no particular authority in their central offices. Independent community churches are already thriving, particularly those that are stressing the relational and acting as social change agents because of their beliefs. Among Christians, the idea of the "priesthood of all believers" is making yet another comeback, as part of a new conception of the essential spiritual equality of all humans under the sole authority of God.

Re-inventing the Corporation

A 1985 best-seller of this name by Naisbitt and Aburdene detailed changes that were even by that time already taking place in the work force and tried to project these forward into the next millennium. The trends they detailed were based not only on information age paradigms, but also on their perception that the new industries already in place would have a higher demand for workers than could easily be satisfied, once women and the baby-boomers were absorbed into the labour market. They foresaw dramatic labour shortages, with future workers being

510

Page 511: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

in such demand they would be able to write their own tickets with respect to job security, working hours and location, fringe benefit packages, retraining and other terms of employment. Some of the key trends identified either by them or in this book, and that have already begun to reshape the corporate environment are:

o the trend away from large corporations toward small entrepreneurships, o the increase in participation of women at management levels,o the corporate provision of contracted child care, medical and dental

programs, health and fitness facilities and counselling services--in order to attract and maintain workers,

o the new emphasis on company loyalty and involvement in the decision making process,

o the new commitment to extensive retraining and job satisfaction,o the provision of flexible hours and benefit packages,o the extension of ownership to the employees in recognition that they are

the enterprise,o the merging of university and corporate interests as each grows more like

the other, ando the opening, broadening, networking, and general demystifying of

management.

Many of these themes have been touched upon in earlier chapters of this book. Some of them have already been widely implemented; others have not become important as yet. For instance, workplace demographic change has been slower than they expected; in the mid 1990s jobs were still being lost in sunset industries about as fast as they were being created in new ones, and shortages did not appear even in the computing and information sectors until after 1997.

However, in general, changes in corporations may be the most prophetic of all institutional ones, because companies are forced to respond rapidly even to slight changes in the economy. Thus the forces that are destroying hierarchicalism and promoting networked models are most advanced in their case and their consequences are good indications for what is in store for the slower-moving institutions of society.

The average corporation of the future seems likely to be smaller, largely worker-owned and will have few or no job descriptions. Existing owner/worker/partners will decide when to add new professionals to their teams, and these will be expected to responsibly and quickly contribute to the joint interests. A typical worker will, like Heinlein's human being (see section 10.3), both take and give orders--and likely to and from the same people at the same level of authority at the same time, rather than in a chain or command.

On the larger scale, big projects will be undertaken by networked corporations whose relationships are put together by high-tech engineering/consulting firms. Such meta-specialists in the technique of assembling techniques will play an important role on the corporate scene, for the number of very large corporate players with a permanent identity will be quite small, and the formation of strategic and often temporary alliances among smaller companies will be much more

511

Page 512: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

important. An individual professional can become a team player in these big-league enterprises because it is already possible for anyone to maintain a seven day/twenty-four hour office accessible to the entire world, and do so without secretarial assistance.

Rejoining Ethics with Technology

A networked model of mutual responsibilities within and between corporations and in personal relationships also implies a larger emphasis on ethical conduct. Since fourth civilization society is postulated to be built on relationships rather than on job descriptions, and on integration rather than on fragments, a high degree of dependability and predictability in those relationships is essential. While a relativistic ethic might be temporarily compatible with a specialist, role-playing, and fragmented society, the fourth civilization demands a cohesive and reliable absolute ethic, because it will be built on a rather diffuse network of relationships. People will be once again counted upon for who they are, and not just for the way in which they can play a specific role in one compartment of their fragmented lives.

To put things another way, a fast-paced, rapidly changing and relation-dependent civilization cannot afford to feel its way tentatively through a minefield of potential civil and criminal lawsuits over its every decision or action. Things are happening too fast for that. By the time a major lawsuit can be settled, the elements of the dispute are rendered irrelevant by the passage of months. The professionals one deals with in one's own networked corporation will have a mutual economic interest and community that will work to reduce such hazards internally. They will also need to have enforceable codes of ethics so that their behaviour can be depended upon by the owner/workers of the other corporations who do business with them, either professionally, or as consumers. While using computers may make it easier than it has been to produce comprehensive and iron-clad legal documents governing such undertakings, and even to produce quick decisions on disagreements, a networked model must depend far more on the a priori assumption of ethically reliable behaviour than it does on a posteriori threats of legal action over non-performance. To put it another way, the costs of law suits cannot be allowed to continue growing, or they will swallow the entire world's production.

In a professional trust environment, there is little time for and too much to be lost by legal action; means will be found to avoid the litigious death-embrace by ensuring that conditions leading to it do not arise in the first place. It may also become more likely for a partner/worker who has acted unethically and damaged another company--even a competitor--to be bought out by the other partners and decertified by the professional body than for the injured parties to sue for damages. While there would still be criminal activities, the use of the courts to settle contractual disputes between professionals would, in this scenario, decline dramatically. In sum, there will be practical economic and professional reasons for ethical behaviour; its rewards will promote it, even if no intrinsic value is perceived.

512

Page 513: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This ideal for professional ethics is based on pragmatism, honesty, full disclosure, truth in advertising and the concept that a person's word is as good as a bond. Mutual, rather than competitive advantage is important in such an environment. After all, the competitor on one project is a potential partner on another. The assumption will not be that a professional knows everything about the field of current practice, but that such a person is equipped to find out what is necessary quickly and efficiently, and can effectively integrate it into the whole project at hand because of a wide-ranging knowledge and the ability to grasp interdisciplinary work as a whole. Such a professional would do so not with an eye to exclusive personal advantage, but with that to successful completion of the total enterprise and to the mutual benefit not only of the partnership but to some extent that of the society as a whole.

At least, such seems to be an indicated outcome of the networked society. Human nature being what it is, there are likely to be many who will want to make a living subverting this model rather than contributing to it. However, in doing so, they would be generating fragments, not a viable integration. The latter requires a bond of trust on the part of those integrating.

To such ends, an important part of every education will be an in-depth study of ethics--both in general terms, and in the ways that such principles relate to specific professions. Throughout the nineties, early versions of such courses were already proliferating at many universities, particularly in schools of business and of computing science, where there had often previously been the most difficulties. It is important to note however, that such courses are of little use if they are designed only to raise sensitivity levels on ethical questions. Professionals having to make real choices in real situations are little served if they are only aware that ethical considerations happen to be involved. They get little from reading numerous case studies if they have no ethical apparatus to employ in drawing conclusions and modifying their own behaviour. Instead, they need to use specific, generally reliable, and probably hierarchically ordered guidelines in order to function predictably. If such cannot be achieved, the fourth civilization as described here will not come about, for the necessity for professionals to rely upon each other in such respects will dictate that no lesser course can be followed.

Integration and Education

As indicated in Chapter 10, the school system will also have to change to encompass the new social and economic paradigms. For the grade school, this means a new stress on communications skills so as to prepare students to enter a world where these are essential to earning a living. High school graduates will already be skilled in the finding of information in electronic databases, and in integrating and recasting this into new forms for their benefit and that of others.

Universities will have three major challenges. The first will be to achieve an integration of their own. This means a new emphasis on beliefs, ideas, emotions, and relationships, and a new integration of these with the study of technique, including that of politics, economics, and the hard sciences. Their graduates will need to know who they are, what they believe and why, and be able to place an

513

Page 514: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

intellectual foundation under their experience of technique, for all this will be expected of them as leaders in the fourth civilization.

The second challenge, related to the first, will be a shift in strategy when dealing with ideas. It has become the practice to do so only by asking questions. But, while a questioning and healthy doubting attitude are necessary for intellectual maturity, questions alone too often constitute a destructive criticism that leaves the student empty and cynical. Since the imperative of the fourth civilization will be the finding of practical answers, students will need to be taught how to do so. Thus, universities must become places that do not just teach to question, but how to find answers, and having found them, how to integrate them into the total person and society.

The third will be to learn how to deal with the information revolution itself. The existence of the electronic Metalibrary implies the availability of information, and courses on any subject a student might wish. By the late 1990s there were already virtual universities on the Internet, some of them sponsored by old and prestigious institutions. It remains to be seen whether the "bricks-and-mortar" college can compete with one that has no travel expenses or dormitory fees, but can buy interactive lectures from the best teachers in the world. In other words, can the traditional university survive?

Integration and Computing Technology

Computing technology is the driving force behind the changes to the institutions, professions, and other disciplines. It is re-shaping society at least as profoundly as the industrial revolution did in its day. It has become essential for decision making, knowledge acquisition and representation, and for the functioning of communications and commerce. This technology is, therefore, by its very nature, interdisciplinary, and its proper study and application require broadly educated and experienced practitioners.

The Global Society

The ethical consensus of the industrial age was based on a belief in one's place in society. Church (if applicable), job, family, and state all delineated one or more socially approved roles that were played out by the majority of people. As that age closes, these roles have been compartmentalized and fragmented, and they now await a new integration that will provide a basis for the next civilization. That such integration is necessary for a coherently identifiable civilization is taken here as axiomatic--continuing fragmentation can surely lead only to chaos and anarchy. Some might regard networked relational models as anarchistic by comparison with hierarchical ones, but they are not. Rather, they are different models for different times, hierarchicalism having served its purpose and run its course.

514

Page 515: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

The suggestions made for modifying democracy will also seem troubling to some, but if the basic presupposition that free people ought to govern themselves is still to be taken as absolute, then form must inevitably follow function and bring change to the structure of modern government. Most troubling of all to many will surely be the idea that religion will not only revive but also become a major spiritual energizing force of the fourth civilization. History would suggest, however, that this must be so; indeed it may be the safest prediction of all those in this book. The question of where and when this will come together most effectively and what people will lead the information society has been left open, however, for the best confluence of all the integrating forces is extremely difficult to forecast.

This matter of potential revival of the human spirit and of religion is an important leadership question that was posed in Chapter 11 and has yet to be considered in detail; the next section is devoted to doing so.

12.6 Renaissance and Reformation in the Fourth Civilization It has been noted already that information paradigms will have a tendency to

break down the rigid barriers that delineated narrow specialities and compartments of the industrial age. At the same time, people will have more time for, and be better educated to consider ideas, and they would also be better equipped to communicate their own with a wide variety of people. The Metalibrary could break down some of the authoritarianism and insularity inherent in the present academic system and throw open the examination and discussion of ideas to a far wider constituency than ever before. The result is likely to be as great a turmoil, and as intellectually stimulating an atmosphere as that which resulted from the infusion of Arabic and Chinese ideas into Europe after the fourteenth century.

A New Renaissance

It is not therefore difficult to dip into history and predict a time of great flowering of the arts and an infusion of new life into the collective human spirit. In such an atmosphere, new forms of music are being generated, many of them synergistically with new types of machines. Indeed, most music is now composed with synthesizers driven by computers. The flexibility of this form of composition means that music is no longer limited to "real" instruments or even to major variations on the traditional ones. Any sound can be generated electronically, regardless of whether there has ever been a stringed or wind device that could duplicate it. The result is an ever broadening experimentation with sound effects in a search for new styles of music. This activity may be so intense and so diverse that music appears to be chaotic, but some forms will surely seem more aesthetically pleasing than others and will be added to or modify the traditional ones. It should be noted, however, that much of this experimentation thus far is individualistic; for the large symphony, there may be considerable difficulty attracting customers. In fact, the better the home entertainment facilities offered by the Metalibrary, the more difficult it could become for theaters and concert halls to attract customers to live performances. A few of the very best orchestras may come to dominate the "sensorium" that television becomes, making things very difficult for smaller groups.

515

Page 516: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

It may even become possible to synthesize an orchestra of choice (both sight and sound) from stored recordings of individual musicians--without physically assembling them. On the other hand, there will be a demand for social events to offset extreme individualization prevalent in the late industrial age, and this could translate into renewed life for venerable old artistic institutions at a local and community level. For instance, theatre chains have been quick to seize upon such trends and reconceptualize large movie houses as complexes of smaller, more intimate entertainment experiences.

New multimedia art forms will continue to proliferate, particularly as the resolution of video and graphics displays improves, and holographic image storage and retrieval become refined. The full Metalibrary could be an artistic medium of major importance, for works could be rented from it for display in individual homes and offices. More adventuresome artists might perhaps experiment with sculptures in orbit that would be visible from the Earth's surface, or attempt to transform large landmasses in an artistic fashion for viewing from space. All this soft high-touch counteraction to hard high technology may also encourage the dance medium both to revive ancient forms and to produce new ones.

Electronic publishing will continue to make it much easier to express oneself in writing as well. It is more difficult for a new writer to gain a conventional mass audience than in the past, for there is far more material for editors to consider. However, electronic distribution will become simpler and the collection of royalties more efficient. Publishing houses can work through the Metalibrary facilities to conduct the editing and approval (publishing) functions and collect a royalty for their efforts on the author's behalf--but in the electronic medium at least it is the artist who is the cornerstone of the whole endeavour, not the editor. Printed paper editions may still be made on a one-off or print-on-demand (POD) basis, but perhaps more for collectors than for the general trade.

The visual media will be much improved as well, so drama could take on new life. While live theater will probably not vanish altogether, the quality and quantity of dramatic presentation available through the Metalibrary will be very much greater than that on today's television, and this too will mean many more opportunities for writers, producers, media technicians, and actors. The number of channels available is increasing in order to provide a greater diversity of material, and this could reduce the current reliance on the old networks, on formula writing, and on the faddism that have dominated television in the past. What is said above about the potential for live music performances to become important social events applies here as well. This will not necessarily be manifested in better opportunities for well-known national and international troupes; it may simply mean that more people participate in and watch local and amateur theater. This would also imply a continuing growth in the number and variety of athletic events and team sports, as available time and money for such activities also increase.

It was noted earlier that a new civilization needs a new economics and politics. It will also need a new sociology, a new psychology, a new anthropology, and a new way to integrate these disciplines to gain insights from all of them and bring their ideas to bear on the problems of people. Although the beginning of this new Renaissance of the arts, fine arts, humanities, and social sciences is only just

516

Page 517: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

being seen, the intellectual turmoil and excitement will surely be as great as in the first Renaissance. For the first time in over a century, ideas about the human condition, knowledge, thinking, and the human spirit are available to be freely and widely discussed in a cross-disciplinary fashion. It would be far too speculative to suggest what specifics might emerge from this ferment, but not at all speculative to predict that it will continue to take place, for such activity is a necessary part of reconciling the academic world with the new culture and developing a new world view to match the new civilization. The intellectual fragments of the machine age will surely be carefully and thoughtfully picked over before being pieced into a new coherence.

The duration of the new Renaissance is also uncertain. Despite that an important feature of the new civilization will be continuing rapid changes in economic, social, and political systems, history suggests that its peoples' world views will crystallize on a new set of paradigms, and that once this has been done, the culture will view itself through that new filter and stabilize around it. These are conflicting suggestions, to be sure; perhaps a way will be found to make rapid change and healthy conflict part of a new world view.

An important part of such a world view is a meaning framework, or religious system. If there will be a great increase in interest in ideas, a more integrative world view, and a renaissance of the human spirit, then there will be a new view of religion as well. There are, at this point, three major groups of candidates to capture the religious loyalties of the men and women of the fourth civilization; these will be considered in the remainder of this section.

A New Religion

There is no shortage of new candidates to move into the vacuum left by Christianity's retreat and scientism's shortcomings, and to claim the heart-allegiances of information-oriented peoples. More than one pundit has remarked that starting a new religion is a good way to become rich, famous, or both. Some have gone on to do so. New groups that have attracted the greatest attention thus far have been those with mystical overtones and connections to the religions of the Far East. The leaders of such groups have not been hesitant to give themselves the titles of guru, blessed teacher, or holy one, or to claim to be Christ re-incarnate and God himself. Apart from devotion to the group--love manifest in a variety of ways--and to the leader, the teachings of such groups tend to be theologically and morally vague. There is not always agreement, even among their members, on whether such systems are religions. For instance, on the one hand, L. Ron Hubbard's Scientology group lost a court case whose decision stripped it of tax-exempt church status, and on the other, Transcendental Meditationists have sometimes had their teachings declared in court to be religious against their will and so forbidden from public schools. Again, not all followers of the very diverse group known as the "new-age movement" would characterize their belief system as religious, despite its Hindu mysticism and reincarnation, its pantheism and its search for the God-in-the-self, in the manner of Buddhism. It is a blend of all these with elements of scientism in a mixture that appeals to the intellectual who wishes to engage in spiritual

517

Page 518: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

experimentation without accepting the accountability demanded by a personally theistic religion like Christianity. It also seems to be highly commercialized, and constitutes an excellent example of a modern religion as a marketplace commodity, for many of its entrepreneurs have garnered great wealth by manufacturing new religious ideas and re-packaging old ones--not as whole systems, but in typical late-industrial age specialized fragments for the modern shopper at the religious market.

Such movements are a natural outgrowth of the specialization and fragmentation of the late machine age peoples. They are the ultimate in designer philosophy, for each individual can create a personal religion with whatever gods are desired--self included. This makes such Hindu/Buddhist mysticism an ideal religious form for an individualistic time. It also fits in well with some elements of scientism such as humanism and materialism, though it conflicts with others by being somewhat fatalistic, and indifferent to both progress and evolution. But mysticism is most sharply antithetical to both science and Christianity in the rationality that they share and it does not, and in treating experience as an end in itself when they both regard it as a means to other ends. Thus, it is difficult to assess whether the "new age" movements in the West are only late-industrial fragments, whether they constitute the nascent form of a significant new religion that, when matured, integrated and organized will become a major force in the next civilization, or whether they will be simply be incorporated into a new versions of both science and Christianity.

Indeed, the latter has happened to at least some extent, as many ostensible Christians have shopped the marketplace of ideas and put together a stew of ideas that bear little resemblance to any taught in the several churches they attend, as the need and whim strike them.

For the new movements that have formally organized themselves as religions, few have thus far sustained memberships of more than a hundred thousand at any one time, and fewer still have survived long after the death of their founder. Among the groups using some Christian vocabulary, if not its doctrines, and that are sometimes termed "cults" there have been some major scandals involving tax avoidance, the sexual proclivities of leaders, and of course the beat known of several mass suicide/murder pacts, such as the Jonestown massacre. These have taken their toll on some of the new religions, and it is not clear whether any of them, even the new-age groups, have a sufficient following to substantially influence the next civilization.

The reason why some of them have failed to make a great impact is the same as that for the decline of statism. They are often arbitrary and autocratic, and are run for the benefit of charismatic individuals who convince people salvation entails following and serving those superiors. The information age being what it is, it is impossible for leaders to hide either the wealth they thereby accumulate, or the inconsistencies between their lives and their teachings. It is also harder for followers to fail to notice the radical doctrinal changes commonly made by arbitrary leaders. Thus the new religions, especially those of the very exposed religious entertainment industry, often have a very high turnover, for people make and keep long term commitments in the information age only to those organizations in which they can be a part of the decision-making process, and within which they can be kept fully

518

Page 519: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

informed. Such commitments also imply consistency in their agreement with the religion, that is hard to achieve in an arbitrary organization.

It is a telling commentary on the current fragmented state of religious belief and practice that the diverse and unorganized New Age movement has been more successful than many of the other new groups that have organized themselves. Were one to suppose that cultural fragmentation were to continue, it would be the best contender. However, the supposition here is that it will not and that integrative paradigms will rule instead. If so, a more cohesive religious view may turn out to be more successful.

In the interim and out of the fragments, there is also a potential opening for a new fanaticism based on some of the old hatreds to arise, and certain European Fascist political movements must in this context be viewed with great alarm. Religious-like allegiances are sufficiently open as the millennium approaches that a suitably charismatic leader could well lead them captive once again into the darkness of racial and religious hatred, or even a new large-scale war. Even though this kind of gathering of the fragments might seem counterproductive and contradictory to information age paradigms, the religious vacuum does exist, and could well be occupied by such passions. This result too, however unlikely it may seem, would constitute a new religion, or at least a new manifestation of an old one. What is more, universal information in this case, means that such religio-political movements can spread rapidly and unpredictably, and therefore are even more dangerous. They can also brook no critics nor competitors, whether those critics may bear the name "North American" or "scientist" or "Christian". It is also of little utility to enquire whether the passionate advocates of such movements are politically on the left or of the right, for there is little difference in the effects upon people of either extreme.

The prospects for the continuing expansion of Islam are also difficult to assess, because it has not yet come to grips with modern science or technology. It is becoming more difficult all the time to read modern scientific advances into the Koran and yet Islam has always held it to be potentially dangerous to know anything that is not in the book. Neither is it unaffected by superstition, materialism, and a nominalism of its own, even in professedly Islamic nations. Meanwhile, education and modern communications chip away at the often monolithic Eastern states and introduce ideas from the West. The tentative alliances of some such nations with the former Soviet Union were seriously undermined by the invasion of Afghanistan, as Islamic unity was by the Iran/Iraq war and then the Gulf war. Indeed, about the only thing that unites the Islamic states of the Middle East is their desire to annihilate Israel, and that kind of unity is scarcely encouraging for world peace. Neither is the newfound willingness to engage in suicide bombing, either with a vest full of explosives, or at the controls of a passenger jet. Thus, despite earlier successes in the North American marketplace, Islam appears to have enough internal problems and difficulties left over from the current age to raise serious questions about its ability to maintain its influence in the next, and this is particularly so when one considers that the oil money will not last long into, nor much influence the fourth civilization. Moreover, even though the World Trade

519

Page 520: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Center incident was engineered by a small group of fanatics, there will undoubtedly be a backlash against all adherents of Islam as a result.

A New Philosophy for Science

Many of the shifts in thinking that are taking place in the move to a new civilization mentioned in this book have been noted by others as well, and there has been no shortage of technical writers pointing out the new paradigms to the scientific and technical community. Moreover, science and other techniques will continue to be of great importance in the information age; its very existence depends on them--both in the heritage of the last age and in their new developments. The hold of the tenants of materialism, humanism and progress (collectively called scientism here) on the hearts of Westerners has been shaken, however by its failure to deliver on the promise of a better humankind to wield all the new high technology toys.

At the same time, a new society has by definition a new world view, breaking with the past on the transcendental issues along with everything else. It is much easier to pass technique along from one generation to the next than it is world view, cultural assumptions, or religion.

Indeed, history would suggest that world leadership tends to pass to those nations that undergo revitalization in both technology and religion at the same time. This was certainly true in the industrial revolution, and there is every reason to suppose that it may be true in the information age as well. The changes, when they come, may well be more rapid and more dramatic than the last time, just as will the technological and other societal ones.

There are some signs of a revitalization in the world view of many modern scientists. The old insistence upon empiricism and rationalism tended to exclude ethics, and therefore to allow only an agnostic antinomianism in science. But the old assertions that technology is ethically neutral are being replaced by an increasing caution, and by a willingness to consider carefully the effects of new techniques on real peoples in real societies. Moreover, the populace at large is demanding such caution, and greater accountability as well, as it learns more about the activities and potential dangers of certain types of scientific research or technologies. Indeed, it was precisely such greater awareness of the potential environmental consequences that effectively killed off any possibility of building more nuclear power plants in the United States.

More people now realize that technological solutions to problems are not the only ones possible, and that they are not necessarily the best. Certainly, there are always trade-offs to consider with the solutions not pursued. Part of this caution stems from the experiences of scientists who worked on nuclear energy before 1945 and must still live under the shadow of the bomb. Thus, anti-nuclear protests in the 1990s were not just anti-technology; they were sometimes being led by scientists themselves--ones who were trying to find and express new forms of social responsibility. Moreover, there is a new and growing concern for the doing of ethical science and for the wielding of ethical techniques over the broad range of both science and technology. A number of books have appeared that examine the ethical

520

Page 521: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

side of specific professions or of science and technique in general. Most of these would not even have been contemplated, much less have been published, as recently as 1980, but today's teachers and students have already been sensitized by the scandals and conflicts brought their way courtesy of universal information, and they are anxious to study what they can of ethical behaviour. While much of this material is still the product of a relativistic and individualistic age, and while many of these books consider ethical systems uncritically, describe case studies without guidance, or ask questions without suggesting answers, the very fact that such issues are being discussed represents a substantial change.

The message of Snow about the danger of living in two isolated cultures (or many fragments of one) is also being listened to. In the future, there will be more time to listen, to learn, and to integrate what were disparate fields, because a scientific education and career will not need to be so narrowly specialized as in the past; it will have to include a substantial general education as well. This seems likely to generate a great influx of ideas from the arts and humanities into the formerly isolated scientific community. The exact effect this will have is uncertain, but it is sure to cause some softening in the exclusivity of the scientific world view, and a greater acceptance of the notion that knowledge can legitimately come from other sources than rationalism and empiricism. This would make scientific debates much broader, much deeper, less dogmatic and far more interesting. There could be a return to fundamentals, with theories and models being seen once again as the abstractions for reality that they are; this would allow evolutionists, for example, to debate easily with creationists, (and vice versa) without feeling that their whole persons, livelihoods and spiritual beings are under attack.

In short, information paradigms ought to force openness and destroy narrow exclusiveness. Ideas are put out onto the open marketplace to compete for the hearts of people. If the paradigms of science can be modified accordingly, the new ones will form an important part of the basis for the religious-like attachments of the men and women of the next era. Scientism as it has been known may have passed however; those who dogmatically cling to it may find it to be as relevant to the information age as Medieval scholasticism was by the nineteenth century--an honoured, but no longer believed spiritual ancestor.

A new scientism could recognize and integrate into its structure an understanding and appreciation of the human spirit and in particular of the role of belief systems and world views. It could employ itself as a meta-technique to criticize its own basic assumptions and world view. It could employ models and paradigms without supposing that either constitute ultimate reality. If it answered meaning questions it could acknowledge openly and frankly their religious nature. It could freely debate its own meaning and that of other systems without either fear or aggression. It could accept that there are things beyond itself, that ethical considerations can shape it, and that it has a total societal responsibility, and it takes these mutual effects seriously. It could recognize that its own technique is one of many possible, and is not the generator of all possible knowledge. A scientism less confident of its own invincibility and inevitability is not as aggressive a religious force as in the past, but a frank, responsible one that knows its limitations may be one that more ordinary people will believe in, trust, and follow in the future.

521

Page 522: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

This scenario is like that of Wilson's consilience in seeing the need for and inevitability of a new assembly of all the intellectual fragments; it differs from his in suggesting that whatever integration may come about, it will not be by a total intellectual takeover by empiricism--a new triumph for hard, exclusive logical positivism and the complete expunging of supernatural ideas from society seems extremely improbable.

If the reviews for the newly-minted religions are mixed, and the prospects for a modified scientism depend on it muting its religious force (rather than per Wilson, increasing it), it is also important to consider the potential for a Western revival of Christianity.

A New Reformation

First of all, it is worth repeating that the historical conjunction of religious revitalization and great social and cultural dynamism is no mere coincidence. Neither are the great technical revolutions conducted by those whose spirits are bound to the paradigms of old cultures; the re-awakening and re-focusing of the human spirit in the transcendental sense--a new renaissance--seems to be a necessary factor in the building of a new civilization. The powerful dynamic that causes people to break decisively with the past and stride forth confidently to fashion new ways of thinking, experiencing, and transforming, is not technical alone, as some scientists believe, nor is it only the result of inevitable social and historical forces, as, for instance, Marxists aver. It is partly both of these, but a motivator is also required, a spiritual awakening that re-focuses people in large numbers to strive toward new goals and re-energizes them to achieve things previously thought impossible.

For millennia, the spiritual ancestors of modern Western society defined their responsibilities to each other in terms of their responsibilities to an almighty God. The fact that they generally do so no longer has led some twentieth century intellectuals to think that religion has been forever banished from the mainstream of society and to suppose that a new order could be ushered in on the basis of technique alone. Was Ellul's despairing concession of apparently inevitable loss by a weakened Christianity the last word?

However, the effect so far has been a dehumanization and depersonalization, an emptiness reflected in a nihilistic philosophy, a modern literature of pessimism and despair, and a hope focused only on economic advantage. Living under the shadow of nuclear extinction, pollution and a multitude of social problems that new technologies seem only to exacerbate, the people of the Western nations may well be ready for a swing of the religious pendulum back from the secularism of the first half of this century. The very extremes to which the fragmentation of culture and religion have gone would seem to reinforce this view. There certainly appears to be a spiritual vacuum into which some religious system has an opportunity to step and to re-unite the pieces into an integrated whole.

522

Page 523: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

There is no obvious prospect for this among new religions, though the high level of experimentation with them is indicative of the strong undercurrent of religious interest. It is important therefore to consider the prospects for a greatly revived and energetic Christianity to become the spiritual galvanizing factor in the West. These are mixed, depending on how they are viewed. After all, the Christian response to culture in the past has ranged from radical rejection, such as in the monastic or ascetic life-style, to near total identification with and assimilation as in the last culture. Any Christian revival in the West would have to forge a new place in society based on an open, energetic and critical participation that engaged the culture at all its important points. To do this it would need to develop or rediscover several characteristics:

First, it would need a new sense of being, that is, a new sense of commitment. Part of this is a rediscovery of its ancient doctrine that moral goodness is an all-encompassing character quality, not something that is just done. Nominalism may suffice for a declining organization to survive through a single generation, but not beyond. If Christianity (or any other religion) is to mean anything to the fourth civilization, it will have to reflect total commitments, faith-assertions sufficiently broad to encompass the whole person, and sufficiently deep to stand up to testing. Generalization and integration rather than specialization and fragmentation will be important in the future; the organizations that have diversified and fragmented and lost all their distinctives may vanish from the scene in a single generation. Successful religions for the future would, therefore, have coherent beliefs and confident, comprehensive faiths. Their world view will of necessity contain filters for understanding the physical world, but these will be general assertions and, if they are to learn from the lessons of history, will not stray far into the territory of science or adopt its tentative conclusions as inflexible dogma. Most important of all, they will have a definitive and transcendent view of God that makes them distinct alternatives to humanist and pantheist philosophies. Without this, all else is wasted, for religion without transcendence, and a clear view of God lacks any meaning, and if it cannot answer meaning questions about itself, it certainly cannot for its people.

Second, a renewed Christianity would require a new intellectual discipline, aggressiveness, and willingness to debate the ideas it holds to be truths in an open and free-wheeling fashion. If its doctrines are indeed self-evident, or rationally supportable, and were actually historically revealed by God, they can stand up to scrutiny in the open marketplace of ideas, and Christian intellectuals need not be afraid to pedal their wares outside the ghetto's dark corners. As part of any intellectual revival Christianity will have to come to terms with a response to evolution in particular, for it cannot sacrifice its general assertion that God created the known physical universe and its specific claim that He created man, without losing its whole reason for being. Without the real first Adam and a literal fall from grace, Christ, the second Adam is simply irrelevant--it makes no difference whether He came if there was no reason for Him to have died for sin. The aggressive assertiveness of the ultra-conservatives is one way to reclaim intellectual territory here. An understanding of Genesis as literally true but undetailed as to time, order and mechanism could be another. However, the liberal assertion that such things do

523

Page 524: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

not matter is cowardly and tantamount to intellectual suicide; issues like this one have to be faced, not defined out of existence by willful ignorance.

There is also in this category the problem of what to say about miracles. Should they be regarded as a result of the work of God who invented all the physical processes and can therefore set them aside as He wishes? Or, should God be regarded as employing as-yet-unknown techniques that are in accord with the physical laws of the universe, but that humanity does not yet possess paradigms to understand? Whatever its response to challenges of this nature, Christianity must end its century-long retreat from the mainstream of academia, for religion that is anti-intellectual has little relevance or foundation even in a fragmented intellectual landscape--and none at all in an integrative one. It is important to note, however, that taking the conservative and even literal ground on such matters as creation is not in itself anti-intellectual. Rather that term describes those who cannot or will not debate their ideas openly. It is also not wrong to assert a specific interpretation of the Christian Scriptures as literally true. After all, they either have no meaning at all or some specific one; it is a cop-out to assert that they may have many possible meanings and turn one's back on debate.

Third, such a revival would need to have a new excitement, a new sense that its doctrines are not musty things for theologians to argue about, but part of an encounter with the power of the living God. There is some evidence this is happening, because for some time, there has also been an increased emphasis on experience in some Christian churches. This emphasis is roughly termed the charismatic movement, and is at least some indication of a return to the experiential aspects of Christianity. This particular manifestation is as yet immature and intellectually incomplete, and its consequences are as yet unknown. However, religion that fails to touch the emotions or to explain the experiences may be an interesting philosophy, but has no humanity. Moreover, an experience grounded in a success philosophy is a fleeting one, good only for today. The authentic and orthodox experience of Christianity was not just emotionalism or success, but both within a context of faithfulness in social action and intellectual vigour; to be revived, it would have to be so again.

Fourth, it would have to regain its power to change both people and society. Its claims to be able to do so are both radical and comprehensive; if these are to have any credibility they must be seen in action. That is, it must rediscover that moral goodness is a character quality that leads to things that ought to be done, rather than things not to be done. At the same time, there is a large collection of activities that Christians have no conceivable motivation to pursue, which many of them do now in the name of sophistication, but ought to desist from--more to regain their distinctiveness and voice over culture than for the sake of legalism. Unfortunately, there is little evidence at the present time of the transformational aspect of Christianity in Western society. Nominalism, and the confining of Christian life to a single day of the week are the rule rather than the exception. It is worth noting that the objections of outsiders to Christianity are seldom intellectually grounded; they are nearly always morally based. Yet, the actual morality practised by those who profess to be Christians is often not especially different from that of anyone else. But, if it is impossible to tell by observing a radically transformed life

524

Page 525: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

morally--in priorities, life-style, and relationships--that people are Christians, then they may as well not claim to be. Religion that lacks effective, practical, transforming compassion is not only useless; it is misleadingly dangerous. Faith, knowledge, and experience with no consequences in human relationships are not just dead, they are counterfeits.

Fifth, these four aspects cannot exist alone and entire unto themselves; they have to be integrated into a unified and whole people in order to become the galvanizing factor in the intellectual life and experiences of the broader society and play a role in transforming it. Some denominations emphasize one aspect of the four, and some another, but there is little effective and comprehensive integration that can be pointed to. Progress has been made by many Christian academics seeking to integrate their faith and discipline, but the radical integration of these two with experience and relationships to demonstrate the concinnity of God's design has not yet overcome the fragmentation that has been going the opposite way.

One church may pride itself on doctrinal correctness, another on its faith, a third on its emotional experiences and a fourth on its program of social works. All four are out of balance, so all these organizations are impotent in an age that demands comprehensive integration and generalization for relevance. Nominalism and fragmentation go hand in hand and so do commitment and integration to see God's concinnity. The former are safe, because they are defined and sanctified by the old culture; but the latter are dangerous, because they come out of a claim to stand above culture and to have the authority not only to critique it, but even to rule on the legitimacy of many of its elements.

Thus, sixth, any revival of Christianity from its present state will require a catalyst, a rallying point, and leadership. If the fourth civilization is to see Christianity as a religious force, it will require visionaries such as were Luther and Calvin in another age to refocus nominal, existential, and fragmented Christians, rally them behind a comprehensive view of their faith, and restore the dynamic and missionary force.

There is not much evidence that any of this is happening in the West. But, there are indications that such a radical reformation is taking place elsewhere--in China, Korea, and Africa. The historical record would also seem to suggest that Christianity may rise elsewhere even as it continues to die in the West. After all, it began in the Middle East, where today it scarcely exists. It flourished for centuries in Europe, where it had its most glorious successes, but where it is today quite indiscernible. It was exported to the Americas, where it is still visible, but socially and culturally ineffective, and where it has lost its transformational aspect and its ability to dynamically criticize and interact with society.

It must be concluded, therefore, that the question of spiritual leadership in the fourth civilization, and with it the energizing of political and economic leadership, is very much open. A modified scientism will play an important role; whether it will have a corresponding religious partner remains to be seen. Both the New Age movement and the remnant of Christianity seem to be too fragmented as they currently are to provide a general spiritual dynamic in the West, but there is an interesting possibility that the latter may do so elsewhere. There may be reasons to

525

Page 526: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

suspect that a revival of Christianity could supply the spiritually galvanizing force to complement the enabling technology and transform civilization into a new form, but there are few reasons to suppose that this new energizing will take place in North America, and even fewer to offer Europe as a candidate. If it takes place anywhere, it might be in China, for that nation has both the technical momentum and the openness to a new spiritual paradigm required to assume the leadership role.

Moreover, the comments made in this section can be applied, with suitable modifications to religions other than Christianity; it has been used for illustrative purposes because of its past role in the development of the technological society; but the possibility cannot be discounted that some entirely unrelated religion might arise to play the role of spiritual motivator to the fourth civilization (this both in negative and positive senses.)

12.7 Missing the Mark--Some Potential Difficulties There are many things that could go wrong with any or all of the integrative

scenarios presented in this chapter. Indeed, one reason for suggesting the leading nations in this civilization may be different is the very momentum built up over the last century by the most successful exploiters of machine age paradigms. Clinging to these now and resisting change would result in stagnation, but there is a heavy investment in the old ways, and many good reasons why people may not want to change. This is often seen in computing technologies, where people will stick with inferior software and hardware and ignore better operating systems and computer designs because of familiarity with and investment in the installed base.

Thus, this section examines a few problems, all of which have the potential to derail features of the information age and divert attention away from the integrating themes discussed here.

The Infrastructure Problem

In economic terms, investments in infrastructure take the form of large corporate structures, buildings, ships, roads, aeroplanes, factories, and other machinery. The short-sighted view of infrastructure is that it is built once and used forever. A realistic view recognizes that nothing lasts indefinitely and envisions a specific plan for infrastructure replacement and modernization. It is for this reason that every modern accounting system considers the depreciation of capital goods.

However, this system works well only in a relatively unregulated private sector where market forces directly affect decision making. The provision of public infrastructure is entirely different, because it can be built without regard to either financial or future considerations, and the concept of depreciation is not used in the public sector. The massive expansion of water, sewer, and roads over a relatively short period of time in North America means, for example, that much of this infrastructure will have to be replaced over an equally short period of time. Indeed, some of the more recent techniques sometimes proved less durable, and this foreshortens the overall replacement period. For example, steel-reinforced concrete, if not properly treated, will deteriorate rapidly due to reaction of the steel with salts in road water. As a result, the majority of bridges and buildings constructed with this

526

Page 527: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

method in the 1950s and 1960s will need to be replaced much sooner than expected. Meanwhile, governments have placed social spending at the top of their agendas, and much of the infrastructure has simply been left to decay. Similar remarks could be made of the health and education infrastructures.

This may not be as great a problem as it seems, for the new civilization will surely require much new infrastructure in any case. However, those nations that build one from scratch may have the advantage of the lack of attachment to obsolete structures and ways of doing things. As post-war West Germany and Japan have shown, building from scratch, or even out of chaos, may be easier and more economically beneficial than attempting to change the momentum of an existing nation; this may prove to be the case in the next civilization as well.

The same problem exists in heavily regulated industries such as shipping, agriculture, and public utilities. Though not necessarily owned by the state, these tend to be so closely supervised by it as to become its close associates; they then take on an economic aspect similar to that of enterprises directly constructed by the state. It is not surprising, therefore, that these sectors have similar infrastructure problems, and that change comes only very slowly. Yet all are important to the fourth civilization, and its success in any given nation will depend heavily on the ability of these sectors to solve their infrastructure problems, even if it means casting them loose from the protective and smothering embrace of government.

Vested Interests

Organizational infrastructure can also be an impediment to change. New techniques demand new methods of structuring businesses, educational institutions and governments. The case for such change has been made at length in this book, and so has the assumption that it will take place. Hierarchies, for example, seem inimical to the new ways of doing things. However, some of these will be very much attached to their current arrangements and will resist change. Those that do may not survive; if enough could, the fourth civilization may in many quarters be only a pale extension of the third, with little new to commend it.

The present communications media may be among those institutions with the greatest interest in maintaining their current status. Never have they been more powerful than at the close of the machine age. They serve as official oppositions to all governments, expose the sordid side of public figures, filter the news and shape public opinion to their standards, and confer widespread recognition on the causes and leaders of their choice, regardless of how few followers they may initially have. As more people have direct access to information, the role of traditional media may be threatened, and they could use their influence to block such changes in order to retain power. Censorship, heavy taxes, or technology restrictions on the Internet could, for example, slow its growth in favour of the traditional media.

Politicians too may be more interested in extending the last age than in ushering in a new one in which their scope of influence narrows, especially if participatory democracy does become important. The fragmentation generated by political polarization or jingoistic nationalism can work well for them in the short term, for they can keep their own answers vague and meaningless and still appeal

527

Page 528: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

to enough of the electorate to remain in office, especially when many lose interest and do not vote.

Ethics Problems (reprise)

One could also wonder where the kind of integrity envisioned for the fourth civilization professional will be found. After all, as the fragmented machine age draws to a close, integrity appears to be sick, even to the point of death. The future is nothing but an undefined nightmare if its peoples have no interest in the making and keeping of promises to their spouses, to employers, and to society as a whole. But, the very publicity that integrity problems are generating can be taken as a sign that they have at least been diagnosed, and that may be a positive sign for the future. Certainly, lack of integrity is one aspect of the machine age that fourth civilization openness paradigms would appear to be hostile to, but it may be some time before integrity becomes the norm. If a marriage between a religious-based moral philosophy and the technological and scientific mindset cannot be achieved, it may never happen.

The Scapegoat Problem

Sometimes, change is resisted more actively, and those who feel themselves to be powerless can find themselves in very dangerous straits indeed. If only a few are perceived to desire the change, and they achieve a high profile, the majority could begin to blame them for all the ills it believes society to be afflicted with. If only a few resist the changes, they could find themselves culturally isolated, and ready targets for scapegoating when things do not go quite as the majority had expected (They seldom do). Although the open information paradigm says this should not happen as much in the future, the possibility of some charismatic demagogue stirring up one nation against another (or even against one of its minorities) can never be completely discounted.

Thus, blacks and orientals are still vulnerable in North America and Europe; Christians are hounded to their deaths in many parts of the world; and the spectre of anti-Semitism continues to haunt modern civilization. Muslims and Hindus stare each other down over Kashmir, and Israelis and Palestinians do the same in their partitioned land. It is also easy to blame the peoples of another nation for the ills at home, for this shifts the responsibility for not solving them to someplace else. Western governments often ignore such problems if a politically unpopular group such as Christians, Jews, or Muslims are the targets, or if there is money to be made by trading with the oppressors. Better not to offend the voters back home or damage fragile trade prospects by taking up the cause of ethnic or religious minorities for the sake of justice.

One could express the optimistic hope that greater openness and willingness to take responsibility ought to reduce the risk of scapegoating, but caution from historical experience knows it will not be eliminated. There will always be people for whom the pace of technical and social change is either too slow or too fast, and who would rather fix blame than work on solutions for the problems they perceive. Such

528

Page 529: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

people will always be a threat to civilization as a whole; the challenge will be to eliminate the threat without destroying the freedom to dissent.

More Problems of Race and Discrimination

This leads once again to a dilemma. Every society and every nation, if it is to continue to believe in the things that make it distinct, must promote itself and find ways to demonstrate its own cultural superiority, while resisting encroachments from others. However, such healthy vitality and the defense of values, customs, religion, and a way of life can easily be taken to extremes, and become racial or religious discrimination. These problems are compounded by historical leftovers:

o The uninhibited racism of the past, inflamed by doctrines that one's own "race" is a product of higher evolution, religious hatreds, or the cultural remnants of black slavery.

o The legacy of white European colonization of large areas that were already inhabited by peoples of less advanced technology who were pushed aside and treated as inferiors, fit only to be ruled.

o The continuing, deep-seated problems posed by religio-cultural hatreds in various parts of the world (former Yugoslavia, the Indian subcontinent, and the Middle East).

o The misuse of the Bible to justify racial discrimination and white superiority.All of these are fragmenting, rather than unifying. Integration paradigms apply

in this area as well, so that it is easy to hope that these attitudes may change in the future. Indeed there is evidence in some parts of the world that they are changing already, though hatreds with their roots in religious controversies seem intractable . Some of these attitudes may only be cured by the passage of time and the education of successive generations in a more forbearing attitude. Others may never be.

Only a fringe minority now attempts to make an evolutionary case for the superiority of a particular race, and slavery by race, while not forgotten, no longer has such a profound effect on Western society as it once did. It is too soon, however, to determine whether the aftermath of the civil rights movement of the 1960s in the United States will make a lasting difference to race relations there--only time can judge this.

In most of the regions colonized by Europeans, the aboriginal population is now so greatly outnumbered that problems of race seem invisible. However, they still do exist, and nowhere is this more evident than in South Africa, where blacks outnumber whites by a wide margin. Like North American whites, those of South Africa are natives; they are generations removed from knowing any other homeland, and have no desire to leave. Because of the relative numbers involved, their repression of blacks was more severe than any discrimination against native Indians in North America, yet it is of the same kind and origin. However it is much easier and more realistic to foresee the elimination of paternalistic, government-controlled Indian reservations, and a reduction of discrimination against aboriginals, than it is to predict the soon coming of a stable or an integrated society in South Africa, despite disbandment of the old white supremacist government there. One

529

Page 530: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

might note, however, that the general drift of some land claims settlements in Canada seems to be in the opposite direction, more towards segregation then integration.

Apart from the history of discrimination itself, there is no external support for the notion that one type of human is inherently superior to another. There is no scientific evidence for such claims, and there is no more reason to cite differences on the basis of skin color than there is on the basis of height or eye colour. Moreover, the Biblical passages often cited in support of racism are not only obscure and used in isolation from their context, but provide no mandate to pursue a policy of discrimination by race. Indeed, the modern idea of "race" was not known to the writers of the Bible at all, and such discrimination that the Israelites were commanded to practice was intended to maintain the purity of their religion, not so much that of their physical ancestry. This much is made obvious by the inclusion of foreigners in the genealogy of David, for instance.

Thus, from every rational point of view, it is safe to assert without fear of objective contradiction that there is only one race--the human race, and that the interests of all humanity are nearer the top of an ethical hierarchy than are the interests of any one nation. Will the men and women of the fourth civilization act on this self-evident truth? For the sake of their collective survival, they have to, but history tends to suggest that they might not. Racism is an old problem, a leftover from a dark and evil age, but it is not one that will go away easily. We will know that it has when people think no more of skin colour than arm length, number of freckles, or toenail shape--not only for decisions about business, but also those for church membership, choosing a neighborhood, and for marriage. We can suppose racism has passed when a Baptist Pakistani can move in next door to Muslim Japanese and Liberian families, and across the street from a northern Ireland Catholic, and all join the same clubs, their children all play together without eliciting comments from anyone, and their religious differences provoke no more than vigorous discussions. We will know that it has passed when the peculiarities of some religious group can be satirized without that groups' leaders sentencing the offender to death or complaining of discrimination. We will know when all ideas (including unpopular ones like creationism) have equal chance to compete for space in the newspapers, magazines and airwaves without being censored by advocates of the currently fashionable version of scientific or political correctness.

The possibility that racism and other forms of discrimination will "overshoot" into the next civilization and mar its ability to work and communicate in universal fashion cannot be discounted. Neither can the possibility that religious groups rather than national ones could become the focus of a new and fatal form of intolerance--there are indications of such attitudes today.

However, it must be appreciated that solving such a deeply entrenched problem will not be easy--even in the most "enlightened" of societies. Care must be taken that attempts to redress old inequities do not become a reverse discrimination and create a backlash of new racism, or to simply redefine "tolerance" to mean the same as an old intolerance. Care must also be taken in applying sanctions to countries engaged in racial or cultural wars or internal discrimination that they do not simply make things worse, by strengthening the

530

Page 531: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

resolve of the racists to maintain power at any cost. That such divisive problems will eventually be solved and a new unity of humankind emerge is a premise of this book; that it will come easily or soon is not.

Summary

All the institutions of the machine age can react to its demise either by embracing change and re-defining themselves to suit new roles, or by acting to perpetuate themselves and their existing agendas at any cost. Likewise, its peoples can welcome and work with the changes for good, or either resist them or use them to evil ends. However, it is the contention of this book that change will be the course to achieve social stability, and that attempting to continue to live in the industrial age will only result in further fragmentation. The real challenge of the new civilization is not the preservation of old and disintegrating institutions, it is the integration of their fragments into a new and cohesive whole--not change for its own sake, but for the construction of a new and better society.

Finally, and more specifically, and since this book is intended to challenge students of technology not only to consider ideas, but also problems, it is appropriate to put forth some very specific questions for solution. In keeping with the tradition for such things, these are presented in lists, with only minimal comment.

12.8 Technique And The Fourth Civilization The techniques that will characterize or drive the fourth civilization are not

difficult to discern, and it was to the major ones of these that Section II of this book was devoted. There are a number of specific issues that will likely receive a great deal of attention in the coming years, however. Some of these represent likely or potential developments in science or technology, and not all are central to the character of the fourth civilization. Also, in accord with such traditions, the technical issues raised in this section are in a series of somewhat unspecific questions and requests for action. They constitute one person's summary of some of the interesting outstanding puzzles or problems for solution by investigators over the next few years. They have been selected partly because of the impact on basic science that a solution might represent, and partly because of the magnitude of the potential effects some of them have for the integrated body of knowledge or for society in general. A few may be regarded as resolved already but perhaps are in need of reopening. Others may be answered in part by the time these lists are published.

In keeping with caveats already sounded in this chapter, some of the social issues raised here are critical, for failure to develop appropriate techniques to solve them could mean that there will be no fourth civilization, but a new dark age instead. In no case should these lists of questions be regarded as exhaustive or static; they will certainly change if there is another edition. For convenience, they are divided into categories, not all disjoint, and not all traditional. Oh, and these are not homework problems, but portions of them could become the lifelong research projects for a few readers.

531

Page 532: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Basic Physical Sciences and Applications

o How constant are physical constants? Do any of them, such as the speed of light, change, say, decay?

o Does the proton decay?o Develop a grand unification theory (GUT, also known as a Theory of

Everything or TOE) to incorporate gravity. Is a practical antigravity device feasible?o How does superconductivity work? For that matter, how is electricity

conducted, really? Make a room-temperature superconducting material that can be drawn into a wire.

o Is there an effective way travel faster than the speed of light, or to avoid the problem, as assumed by so much science fiction?

o Does quantum mechanics imply that alternate universes exist or that the behaviour of particles can be determined by what takes place with paired particles even when these are at great distances? If the latter, what practical use does this have? Build a working quantum computer.

o Devise a practical method for molecular-level data storage. Build a Drexlerian assembler (nanomachine) and employ this in both manufacturing and medical applications.

o Build a commercially viable lightweight battery or fuel cell and eliminate petroleum use from transportation applications (forecast the political implications).

o Of what class of phenomena is time? Is it a physical phenomenon, or does it even have an existence independent of the physical world. Or is it a mental construct devised by humankind to accommodate a limited perception of some more fundamental phenomenon?

o What is the most fundamental particle of matter? The quark, or something else (smaller)? Is it really a particle? Define "particle."

Cosmology and the Earth Sciences

o Demonstrate the existence of a black hole close enough at hand to run experiments with (i.e., closer than those hypothesized to exist at the centres of some galaxies). Is it possible to use one?

o If the universe is closed and does contain enough mass so that it will eventually contract, where is the mass? It is not sufficient to hypothesize "dark matter" that cannot be perceived.

o Settle the question of whether the neutrino is massless.o Revise the nuclear model for the Sun, or find the neutrinos it ought to emit

under the present one.o Find an actual, not just a hypothesized, source for comets and solar system

dust.o What is the mechanism whereby the earth's magnetic field is produced and

maintained?o Is any substantial portion of natural gas or coal produced directly by earth

processes (e.g., outgassing from the core) rather than being of organic origin?

532

Page 533: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Predict earthquakes and volcanic eruptions with a high degree of reliability. Do the same for hurricanes; for the weather generally.

o Devise a cohesive cosmology that is substantially different from the standard big bang theory and that can worthily compete with it or even replace it. Pay particular attention to a mechanism for galaxy formation and the large-scale structure of the universe.

o Is the Earth getting hotter or cooler? Whatever it is doing, is the process naturally cyclical, or do man's activities have much to do with it? Do something about it, without making an even worse mess than the one you think already exists.

Biospace Problems

o Extend the detailed mapping of human DNA, to include the function of every gene. Is this all there is to life and heredity, or do other parts of the cell, such as the mitochondria, also play a role? What is it?

o Discover a way to block or remove viruses--one that can be tailored to any virus. Achieve a complete analysis of the human immune system.

o What is sleep? Is it necessary, or can it be dispensed with?o Settle the mind-brain question. That is, is the mind something more than the

brain or something less? Or are these two names for the same thing.o Is aging a disease or perhaps a complex of diseases or malfunctions? If so,

how can it be treated?o Find a way to persuade the body to regenerate damaged organs or

otherwise remove the necessity for organ banks or transplant surgery or both.o Find a foolproof sterility drug and an antidote. Or, find some other means to

eliminate nearly all abortions.o Determine whether the earth's ozone layer is diminishing. If so, is this as

part of some geological or solar cycle, or because of the activity of man, and can you do something about it without creating a worse problem?

o Find a way to stop acid rain. Solve some of the other deforestation and stream pollution problems while some of both remain alive.

o Construct new human living space for a substantial number of people without destroying farmland or extinguishing any more animal species in the process.

Miscellaneous Applications

o Is a railway or elevator to near-earth orbit feasible? Build one. Otherwise, find a method of transporting materials to orbit at, say, one percent of the cost of space shuttle launches.

o Is there a way of preventing either the launching or the explosion of nuclear warheads by some simple and cheap method?

o Develop an automated prospecting method for coal, oil, and natural gas; for minerals.

o Develop a commercially viable, inexpensive, plentiful, safe, and publicly acceptable power source, and find a way to stop using organic fuels altogether.

533

Page 534: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

o Develop a new, fast, cheap, and safe method of (computer controlled) ground transportation, solving the problem of highway massacre.

o Find a way to solve the airport bottleneck problems without raising fares, reducing competition or compromising safety.

o Simulate human vision with a computing device.o Build the data repository and searching facilities of the academic

Metalibrary. Build the PIEA.o Build a permanent and self-supporting space station in orbit, on the Moon,

or both.o Build a holographic broadcast/receiving system with a fine resolution on

each plane.

Integrations and Other Social Questions

o Develop a science of history (i.e., a psychohistory) that explains historical phenomena in terms of statistical behaviour, or prove this cannot be done.

o Develop an economic calculus that can operate even in a highly complex and rapidly changing climate.

o Dismantle the statist regimes and restructure democracy without either falling into anarchy or global war. In both cases, achieve a state that concentrates on collective and networked obligations, rather than on either the demanding of fragmented rights or a hierarchical command structure.

o Find a way to prevent either science or religion from creating a societal intolerance of the other. Forge a reconciliation between the two that includes a mutual respect and use of intellectual territories.

o Find a way to overcome racial and national prejudices and avoid the establishment of a new Naziism. Establish the principle that there is only one human race.

o Find a way to rebuild the education system, making it locally relevant, but culturally and sexually integrated.

o Devise workable codes of ethics for the major professions, and a means to enforce them.

o Either legalize the use of all drugs, or find an effective way to prevent the production of the illegal ones. In either case, use the solution to reclaim both the third world governments and the inner cities of the West that are now hostage to the drug gangs.

o Solve the problem of the creation of new class structures based on the ability to use the fourth-civilization techniques. In particular, find a way to prevent the disappearance of the middle class.

o Find a way to resolve the sexual differences and gender solitudes without creating a new social extreme in the process.

The most important social problem are implied by items in the last list. The most daunting task of all is the piecing together of the fragments of the exhausted machine age civilization into a cohesive culture that has the dynamic energy to fulfil some of the potential of the information age--and doing so despite the fragment-

534

Page 535: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

creating momentum that still exists. The peoples who achieve these things in their nations will dominate the early years of the next era, for they will indeed be the inheritors of the fourth civilization.

12.9 Summary and Further Discussion

Summary

Each phase of civilization fragments before the next one can be built. This process has been most noticeable on this particular transition because of its rapidity and because the specialization of the machine age has tended to encourage intellectual, professional, and religious fragmentation and specialization as it developed more fully.

The task of building the fourth civilization is that of forging a new integration of the fragments. This takes place both on an academic level, and on a broad cultural one. It requires a redefining of such institutions as government, corporations, education, science, and religion and a wholistic approach to personal and institutional relationships. The heart-commitments of those in the new era are not yet evident, but there is much experimentation with various forms of religion, some of them quite novel. A muted scientism may be an important factor and the new age philosophies may play some role; however, any resurgence of Christianity, for instance, would require it to come to terms with its world view, intellectual and spiritual foundations, and work out a transformational relevance in the new society. North America is a possible venue for such a revival, but the Far East may be more likely. There is a tension between the use of integration to self-evolve a consilience of purely empirical knowledge and its use, on the other hand to demonstrate a preexisting concinnity, or design.

The last section presents several interesting technical and critical social problems whose solution could have an important impact upon the further technological and social development of the fourth civilization or even on its very existence.

Research and Discussion Questions

1. The author argues that fragmentation is caused by machine age specialization paradigms exacerbated by normal transitional problems and that integration must characterize the fourth civilization. Argue instead that the chief paradigm of the new will instead be fragmentation, and that a cohesive culture can be built upon such a foundation.

2. What is the future of the family? Do not assume anything that the author has said in your answer, but argue from such other sources as you have available, filtered through your world view. State your definitions and assumptions and develop your reasoning clearly.

3. Argue that a participatory democracy is just another form of totalitarianism and propose a better alternative.

535

Page 536: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

4. A woman who is eight months pregnant applies for a position for which she turns out to be the best qualified person. Should she be hired without regard to her pregnancy? Are there any exceptions to your conclusion? Does it matter if this is a sedentary desk job or one requiring considerable physical exertion--say, as a deck hand on a tuna fishing boat? Does it matter if this is a key management position whose occupant will be a critical company player over the next four months?

5. Now repeat your analysis in the last question for the case where the father-to-be is the applicant. Is there any difference? Why or why not?

6. Now, do the same analysis of the last two questions for the case where the task is a combat posting for the army. Is there any difference? Why or why not?

7. The author has expressed some doubt as to whether the sexual revolution involved a change of behaviour or a change in public perceptions of behaviour. Research the issue and try to settle it one way or another.

8. Argue that a technical solution to the AIDS and other venereal diseases will have (a) no effect or (b) a permanent effect on sexual behaviour.

9. The author makes much of the "principle of interdependence". Argue that it is the individual and not the total society that is of paramount importance, and that this principle is of much less importance than suggested here. You may wish to defend the position that individual rights are far more important than obligations to society.

10. Take one of the categories of questions and tasks proposed in the last section and examine two or three items in detail. Research what is now known, explain the magnitude of the task remaining and summarize the probable effect on society and on knowledge in general that a solution would have.

11. The author asserts that in the information age the late machine age post modernist religious fragmentation will be replaced by an integrative view of religion. Argue the opposite--that either religious fragmentation must continue, or argue that religion will die out altogether. Base your argument on what you believe will be the prevailing paradigms of the fourth civilization.

12. Do a detailed review of Wilson's Consilience, summarizing his arguments and defending them.

13. Argue contra Wilson, but in more detail than in this chapter, that all the physical universe is a concinnity, that is, an integral design.

14. Argue contra both Wilson and this author, that there is no need for a comprehensive integration of knowledge.

15. Expand upon and detail the means by which a "new Reformation" of Christianity might take place. It might be appropriate to critique a particular church, preferably your own, if applicable with respect to the proposal of radical integration and cultural criticism.

16. Apply the same integrative model to another religious system other than Christianity, and detail how it would have to change to become the major dynamic religious force in the new civilization.

17. Explain in detail the beliefs, practices and cultural impact of the New Age movement. Is it a religion? Why or why not?

18. Make your own list of ten interesting and important unsolved problems in any field. Justify the inclusion of each item.

536

Page 537: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

19. What of the role of the family in society? Some claim that the traditional family is obsolete. Either defend the traditional family as the only reasonable building-block for a society, or propose an alternative view of the way society can cohere.

20. Write a detailed explanation of the way in which you personally will be attempting to integrate your being, knowing, experiencing, and relating as you look forward to living and working in the fourth civilization.

21. Write a detailed explanation of why you do not need to do any of these things, but be sure to state what your presuppositions are for the main features of the fourth civilization and how you will relate to them if it does not have to be in an integrative way.

Bibliography

Alcorn, Paul A. Social Issues in Technology: A Format For Investigation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1986.

Asimov, Isaac. Science Past Science Future. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1975.

Bibby, Reginald W. Fragmented Gods--The Poverty and Potential of Religion in Canada. Toronto: Irwin, 1987.

Bloom, Allan. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1987.

Denning, Peter J. and Metcalfe, Robert M. Beyond Calculation--The Next Fifty Years of Computing. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1997

Hawkin, David J. Christ and Modernity--Christian Self-Understanding in a Technological Age. Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfred Laurier Press, 1985.

Huber, Charles H. and Baruth, Leroy G. Ethical, Legal, and Professional Issues in the Practice of Marriage and Family Therapy. Columbus OH: Merrill, 1987.

Kaku, Michio. Visions--How Science Will Revolutionize the 21st Century New York: Doubleday, 1997

Klass, Morton and Hellman, Hal. The Kinds of Mankind--An Introduction to Race and Racism. Philadelphia: Lippincott, 1971

Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions--Vol 2 No 2 in The International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (Second Ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970

McCuen, Richard H. and Wallace, James M. (ed.). Social Responsibilities in Engineering and Science--A Guide for Selecting General Education Courses. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Simon & Schuster, 1987.

Naisbitt, John and Aburdene, Patricia. Re-inventing the Corporation. New York: Warner Books, 1985.

Rybczynski, Witold. Taming the Tiger: The Struggle to Control Technology. New York: Viking Press, 1983

Schaeffer, Francis A. How Should We Then Live--The Rise and Decline of Western Thought and Culture. Old Tappan, NJ: Revell, 1976.

Scorer, C.G. The Bible and Sex Ethics Today. London: Tyndale, 1966.

537

Page 538: The Fourth Civilization-Technology Society and Ethics

Sowa, John F. Knowledge Representation: Logical, Philosophical, and Computational Foundations. New York: Brooks Cole. 2000.

Toffler, Alvin. Previews and Premises. New York: Morrow, 1983Trefil, James S. Space--Time--Infinity. New York: Random, 1985. Wilson, Edward O. Consilience--The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Knopf,

1998.Yourdon, Edward. Nations at Risk: The Impact of the Computer Revolution.

New York: Yourdon Press, 1986.

538