30
Self-sufficiency of Law

Self-suf Þ ciency wof La - Springer978-94-007-4298-7/1.pdf · Nelken, Stefano Petrucciani, Geminello Preterossi, Sham Qayyum, Martin Ramstedt, Vincenzo Rosito, Aldo Schiavello,

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Self-suf fi ciency of Law

Law and Philosophy Library

VOLUME 99

Series Editors:

FRANCISCO J. LAPORTA, Department of Law,Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain

FREDERICK SCHAUER, School of Law, University of Virginia, U.S.A.TORBEN SPAAK, Uppsala University, Sweden

Former Series Editors:

AULIS AARNIO, MICHAEL D. BAYLES†, CONRAD D. JOHNSON†,ALAN MABE, ALEKSANDER PECZENIK†

Editorial Advisory Board:

AULIS AARNIO, Secretary General of the Tampere Club, FinlandHUMBERTO ÁVILA, Federal University of South Brazil, Brazil

ZENON BANKOWSKI, Centre for Law and Society, University of Edinburgh,United Kingdom

PAOLO COMANDUCCI, University of Genoa, ItalyHUGH CORDER, University of Cape Town, South Africa

DAVID DYZENHAUS, University of Toronto, CanadaERNESTO GARZÓN VALDÉS, Institut für Politikwissenschaft, Johannes

Gutenberg Universitat, Mainz, GermanyRICCARDO GUASTINI, University of Genoa, Italy

JOHN KLEINIG, Department of Law, Police Science and Criminal JusticeAdministration, John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University of New York,

U.S.A.PATRICIA MINDUS, Uppsala University, Sweden

YASUTOMO MORIGIWA, Nagoya University, JapanGIOVANNI BATTISTA RATTI, Department of Legal Sciences,

University of Genova, Italy and Member of the Chair of Legal Culture at the University of Girona, Spain

WOJCIECH SADURSKI, University of Sydney, Faculty of Law, Sydney, AustraliaHORACIO SPECTOR, Universidad Torcuato Di Tella, Argentina

ROBERT S. SUMMERS, School of Law, Cornell University, U.S.A.MICHEL TROPER, Université de Paris Quest - Nanterre, Institut Universtaire

de France FranceCARL WELLMAN, Department of Philosophy, Washington University, U.S.A.

For further volumes:http://www.springer.com/series/6210

Mariano Croce

Self-suf fi ciency of Law

A Critical-institutional Theory of Social Order

Mariano CroceDepartment of PhilosophySapienza – University of RomeRome, Italy

ISSN 1572-4395ISBN 978-94-007-4297-0 ISBN 978-94-007-4298-7 (eBook)DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-4298-7Springer Dordrecht Heidelberg New York London

Library of Congress Control Number: 2012940229

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, speci fi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on micro fi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. Exempted from this legal reservation are brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis or material supplied speci fi cally for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the Copyright Law of the Publisher’s location, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer. Permissions for use may be obtained through RightsLink at the Copyright Clearance Center. Violations are liable to prosecution under the respective Copyright Law.The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a speci fi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.While the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication, neither the authors nor the editors nor the publisher can accept any legal responsibility for any errors or omissions that may be made. The publisher makes no warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein.

Printed on acid-free paper

Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com)

v

I have acquired many theoretical debts over the years and many people have affected what is contained in this book. My profound thanks are due to Nunzio Allocca, Daniele Archibugi, Laura Bazzicalupo, Ignazio Castellucci, Alfonso Catania, Dimitri D’Andrea, Seán Donlan, Alessandro Ferrara, Lyana Francot, Maurizio Fioravanti, Emmanuel Melissaris, Elena Pulcini, Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, David Nelken, Stefano Petrucciani, Geminello Preterossi, Sham Qayyum, Martin Ramstedt, Vincenzo Rosito, Aldo Schiavello, William Twining, Marco Ventura, Bald de Vries, Gordon Woodman. I owe a special debt to my mentor Virginio Marzocchi and my colleagues at La Sapienza in Rome, Andrea Salvatore and Michele Spanò, who have always supported me and who patiently read and discussed this book and delivered both workable criticisms and useful suggestions. I would like to thank Werner Menski, whose support has been very important, and the guys of his teaching team at the School of Oriental and Africa Studies in London, Taymour Harding, Hanns Kendel, and Alberto Neidhardt. I am very grateful to William Twining, Dennis Patterson, and Werner Menski who have honoured me with their endorse-ments. I thank Neil Olivier and Diana Nijenhuijzen at Springer for professional guidance and a smooth production process. I also thank Francisco Laporta, Frederick Schauer, Torben Spaak, Law and Philosophy Library Series Editors. I am very grateful to the anonymous readers of this book for their gratifying assessment and constructive comments.

I am grateful to my father, who, many years after his death, is so very much present in my memory, my mother, and my brothers along with their families for their continuous and unconditional support over the years; to my friends, who have accompanied me throughout this journey; and last, but not least, to Valeria, for making everything worthwhile. I am very grateful to William Twining, Dennis Patterson, and Werner Menski who have honoured me with their endorsements.

Acknowledgements

vii

Part I Law as a Complex Practice: The Rule-Based Model

1 Legal Theory as a Scientific Discipline and the Variety of Rules ....... 5 1.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 5 1.2 Austin and the Autonomy of Legal Theory ..................................... 6 1.3 Kelsen and the Scientific Amendment of Legal Positivism ............. 10 1.4 Beyond Commands and Imperatives:

The Puzzle of Secondary Rules ....................................................... 13

2 Legal Validity and the Problem of Rule-Acceptance ........................... 19 2.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 19 2.2 Four Notions of Acceptance ............................................................ 21 2.3 The Ambiguities of Acceptance as Observance .............................. 27

3 Reflective Acceptance: Reasons for Action and Criterion-Rules ....... 31 3.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 31 3.2 Internal Point of View and Rule-Government ................................. 33 3.3 Rules as Reasons for Action ............................................................ 36 3.4 Habits, Rules and the Limits of Hart’s Approach ............................ 38 3.5 A Quasi-Wittgensteinian Reading of the Practice Theory ............... 41 3.6 Criterion-Rules and Conditions of Thinkability .............................. 46

4 The Legal Practice and Its (Vanishing) Borders .................................. 49 4.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 49 4.2 The ‘Payne Problem’: Relevant Population and Lay People ........... 50 4.3 Rule-Based Model of What? ............................................................ 54 4.4 Law as a Practice Among Practices ................................................. 60

Contents

viii Contents

Part II Law as a Selective Practice: The Social and the Legal

5 The Pluralist Divide ................................................................................ 67 5.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 67 5.2 The Reasons for Legal Pluralism:

Pragmatic and Conceptual Arguments ............................................. 68 5.3 First Type of Pluralism: Law as Organisation .................................. 71 5.3.1 Eugen Ehrlich: The Living Law of Associations ................. 72 5.3.2 Santi Romano: Institutions as Legal Orders ........................ 76 5.4 Second Type of Pluralism: The Artificial Character of Law ........... 79 5.4.1 Sally Falk Moore: The Dialectic

Spontaneity/Artificiality ....................................................... 79 5.4.2 Marc Galanter: The Historicity of Legal Borders ................ 83 5.5 Third Type of Pluralism: The Dissolution of Legal Pluralism ......... 86 5.5.1 Sally Engle Merry: Law as Frame of Significance .............. 87 5.5.2 Brian Tamanaha: The Praxiological Way-Out ..................... 90 5.6 Legal Pluralism: A Provisional Assessment .................................... 94

6 Legal Pluralism Revised: Law as the Product of Selection ................. 99 6.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 99 6.2 The Root of All Evils: The Malinowski Problem ............................ 99 6.3 Legal Selection and Legitimate Coercion: Hoebel’s View .............. 105 6.4 Towards a Concept of Law as a Selective Practice .......................... 111

7 Classic Institutionalism: Jural Reality and Legal Selection ............... 113 7.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 113 7.2 Institutions, Inner Orders, and Romano’s Dilemma ........................ 114 7.3 Jural Reality and Official Law ......................................................... 119 7.4 Integrating Institutionalism: Thin Functionalism ............................ 125

8 Exploring the Jural Continuum ............................................................ 127 8.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 127 8.2 The Background of Social Practices ................................................ 128 8.3 Criterion-Rules, Instance-Rules, Norm-Rules ................................. 132 8.4 The Jural Continuum: Practices, Institutions, Organisations ........... 139 8.5 Relevant Population and Lay People Reconsidered......................... 144

Part III The Law as a Special Practice: Legal Field and Social Reality

9 Negotiating Reality: Knowledge and Categories in the Legal Field ..................................................................................... 151

9.1 Preliminary ....................................................................................... 151 9.2 Law as a Trans-Sectional Venue ...................................................... 152 9.3 Law and Its Custodians: The Paradigmatic Case

of the Roman ius .............................................................................. 157

ixContents

9.4 The Semiotic Circuit of Law: The Intriguing Case of Mekgwa Le Melao ..................................................................... 162

9.5 Is Productive Circularity Really Distinctive? A Theoretical Objection ........................................................................................ 167

9.6 The Indispensable Self-sufficiency ................................................ 173

10 The Ritual Dimension of Law: Normality, Normativity, and Critique ............................................................................................. 177

10.1 Preliminary ..................................................................................... 177 10.2 Ritual and the ‘Question of Plausibility’ ...................................... 178 10.3 Law’s Nondiscursive Dimension:

Normality and Normative Facts ..................................................... 187 10.4 Law’s Discursive Dimension: The Space for Critique ................... 190

Epilogue ........................................................................................................... 195Defending a Pluralist Critical-Institutional View of Law ............................ 195

Bibliography .................................................................................................... 201

Author Index.................................................................................................... 209

Subject Index ................................................................................................... 213

xi

Point of Departure: The Question of Questions

In the fi elds of jurisprudence, legal sociology, and legal anthropology the nature of law is one of the most debated questions, even though, already at the beginning of the twentieth century, some scholars claimed it to be unsolvable. In 1938, Max Radin made a mockery of those whom, among his colleagues, still showed interest in de fi ning law by saying that “[t]hose of us who have learned humility have given over the attempt to de fi ne law” (Radin 1938, 1045). In effect not only has there been disagreement on how to de fi ne law. There has also been a great deal of disagreement as to the proper target of such an inquiry. Some theorists have almost exclusively focused on rules. Some of them have argued that what characterises law is the fact that legal rules, unlike every other type of rule present in society, are backed by coercion, are enforced by some type of legitimate authority, and are generally meant to secure social order. Others have put emphasis on the institutional character of law so as to argue that the speciality of legal rules rests on their being part of a complex institutionalised practice. Finally, others have stressed the processual side of law, which they see as a specialised machinery meant to settle disputes, channel powers, and accommodate social change. In sum, the label ‘law’ has been employed for covering quite different phenomena, which only bear feeble resemblances to each other.

The theoretical complexity of de fi ning law is one of the main reasons why, as also Brian Tamanaha has recently remarked (2001, xiii), in the last decades few legal thinkers have tried to outline a comprehensive core conception of law. Yet, despite the decline of grand theories, the debates about the nature of this pivotal component of social life are far from decreasing. Indeed, the question of what distinguishes law and the inquiries into the features that make it so special are now returning to the fore in new ways and with new intensity. Actually, the incisive socio-political changes that are impacting upon our global world are progressively tearing into pieces most of the basic tenets of traditional jurisprudential approaches. As I will argue in the following pages, today, more than ever, legal theorists are trying to provide new conceptual devices able to capture the dynamics of a social

Introduction

xii Introduction

reality that is quite different from that in which the foremost thinkers of the twentieth century were situated. Today the legal fi eld is characterised more and more by the rise of alternative normative sources and hybrid regulatory phenomena, which in the past were straightforwardly relegated to the domain of the social, whereas at present they claim to be included in the domain of the legal. The present book can be seen as a contribution to the ongoing attempt at deciphering what these changes are bringing about and how they are reshaping the legal fi eld. At the same time, this book claims to be a vindication of the role of legal theory, which can and should play a crucial role in this wide-ranging enterprise.

The Question of Questions in an Era of Transformations

Needless to say, any theoretical inquiry is rooted in the background of a speci fi c geo-historical context, whose social, political, and cultural conditions inescapably come to affect the set of presuppositions from which theorists move. Accordingly, this in fl uences the way in which such theorists interpret their own conclusions in relation to the limited set of variables and criteria on which they focus. This is a fortiori true as to studies on legal phenomena which are undertaken amidst the epochal changes that are gradually reshaping our social world. Law is undergoing a series of transformations that turn out both to alter its traditional con fi guration and to remould our perception of it. In the 1960s, Herbert L.A. Hart could present the discordances over what law was as an outcome of an academic contraposition over a rather de fi nite reality (the state legal order). In his introduction to The Concept of Law , he simply de fi ned as devoid of mystery the quasi-legal status of non-state laws. In contrast, today such a reality is becoming more and more the matter of an ongoing debate among legal scholars. Nowadays a quite less de fi nite reality (that is, a plethora of normative entities that are prospering below, above, and beyond national states) is challenging most of the theories of law produced in the last couple of centuries and is bringing into question the traditional boundaries separating the legal from the quasi-legal, the non-legal, and even the illegal. As a matter of fact, since the last decades of the twentieth century, the political-legal actor that was deemed to be the legitimate holder of an unquestionable of fi cial lawfulness , that is, the state and its legal order, has increasingly had to face with insidious competitors questioning both its legitimacy and its monopoly on of fi cial lawfulness. Through different pathways and with different trajectories, a great amount of indigenous, informal, sectorial, and functional (both substate and suprastate) laws have started to claim their portion of of fi ciality and to demand an ever-greater autonomy to exert justice through their own means and methods. This is why, as Carol Greenhouse (1998, 63) observes, the chief problem of legal and political theory at present “is the contested nature of states’ claims regarding the legitimacy of of fi cial law”.

The doubts and questions that surround the state’s claims on legitimacy primarily stem from the fact that today its sovereignty seems more and more an empty shell. It is a platitude to recall that the origins of modern law are deeply entrenched with

xiiiIntroduction

the origins of modern national states and their normative supremacy. As I have argued at length elsewhere, 1 modern legal orders – as essentially distinct from medieval legal orderings in methodologies, technologies, and categories –, were made possible by the conquest of the legal fi eld by state governments. States cen-tralising tendencies accelerated the erosion of the common (though multilayered) legal framework that for a long time had allowed several local laws to co-exist. The new central government rendered the medieval integration of ius commune / iura propria into a chaotic overabundance of con fl icting local laws. They employed the uncertainty and instability yielded by this legal particularism as a plausible justi fi cation for the extraordinary revolution by which they turned out to present themselves as the unifying factor for all sub-state social entities located in their jurisdiction: each of these social entities was called upon to rule out the elements that were in con fl ict with the will of the sovereign. In this way, political rulers managed to have the pre-eminence over the legal specialists (be they judges, jurists, or professors of law), who became (especially in the countries of civil law) ‘state of fi cials’. The myth of the monist legal system had been created. The complete takeover of the legal fi eld was crucial to the centralisation of power and competen-cies. The corresponding revolution in legal ideology was at least as important for the creation of modern states as the spread of numeracy for the development of natural and social sciences.

Yet, in the last decades, many factors have gradually contributed to dismantling the image of law that I have just sketched. Among them, two are particularly inter-esting, the fi rst related to the developments in various fi elds of legal study, the second related to the actual changes that have occurred in the global scenario. 2 Firstly, in the second half of the twentieth century, an impressive amount of studies and inqui-ries in many fi elds of legal and political research have cast light on the historical, contingent, hegemonic, and even despotic character of state legal orders. Both historians of Western political organisations and scholars of non-Western and post-colonial countries have argued that state legal orders (be they Western or non-Western) have emerged as arti fi cial products with a patchwork character. They have been able to af fi rm themselves only by downgrading and de-legalising all the pre-existing types of legal orderings and, in this way, have successfully managed to impose a canon of of fi cial lawfulness , which today can no longer be taken for granted. Secondly, at a more pragmatic level, social and economic globalisation is signi fi cantly

1 See Croce (2009). 2 I would like to make it clear from the very outset that my book is not intended to analyse the way legal theory is changing in response to globalisation. I am rather referring to these ongoing trans-formations (both pragmatic and theoretical, as I will explain shortly) insofar as they have contri-buted to bringing to light some of the fl aws of traditional jurisprudential approaches that focus almost exclusively on state law. This is why I will say nothing about the so-called “global legal pluralism” (see e.g. Berman 2009 and Michaels 2009) and will pay scant attention to supra-national, transnational, and international legal phenomena that in the last years have stimulated interest in re-conceptualising state law to fi t these phenomena. For a thoughtful analysis of these emerging theoretical streams, see Twining (2010).

xiv Introduction

impinging upon the role and the shape of state legal orders. Although, contrary to what a recent vulgate has contended, states are not disappearing, they are adapting themselves to the changes that are taking place above and beneath them, to such an extent that they have even served as key channels of socio-political transformation. In this reading, globalisation can be better understood as the accretion of a multifac-eted set of sub-national processes, whose main effect is that of eroding the tradi-tional division (once crucial to there being a state) between what is public and what is private. The collapse of the private-public divide is now favouring the withdrawal of the public domain and the parallel expansion of the private one, which gains power through the absorption of traditional state authorities. In this articulated dynamic, many types of indigenous ordering (from ethnic and religious groups to multinational corporations and nongovernmental organisations) are both entering the ambit of public policy-making and creating new areas of private jurisdiction.

As we can see, in the global scenario that has emerged out of the fall of the Berlin Wall, the state has not only to face the traditional normative sub-state entities, whose autonomy and independency had been harmed by the rise of the modern systems of states. The proliferation of alternative sources of normative power along with sub-state and supra-state regimes of justice is considerably increasing the hybridity of law, which can be no longer considered as a personal property of national states. It is easy to offer a rough sketch of the different instances of law demanding to exert jurisdiction on different geographic areas and/or on speci fi c sets of subjects. There is a global law which is comprised of regulatory systems operating at different lev-els, such as trade, fi nance, environment, nuclear energy, fi shing, agriculture, food, postal services, intellectual property, energy sources. There is an international law in the classic sense of relations among sovereign states integrated by treaties and charters of fundamental rights. There is the regional law of organisations such as the European Union and the African Union. There are transnational laws regulating speci fi c sectors of social reality, such as merchant law, copyright law, internet law, or governing the life (or part of the life) of speci fi c populations, such as Islamic law, Hindu law, Jewish law, Canon law. At the same time, traditional national jurisdictions are more and more fragmented because of the rise of sub-state jurisdictionally-autonomous federal or provincial entities, such as Quebec or Catalonia. Finally, there is an array of non-state laws and folk laws that are being recognised by the state law of many post-colonial countries. 3 This new scenario induces us to see the emerging global legal order as an intertwined web of jurisdictional venues, in which global, international, transnational, state, sub-state, and non-state laws are fated to coexist.

These momentous changes are inevitably affecting how legal theorists think of law and talk about law. This rising trend is epitomised by the book by William Twining, General Jurisprudence , which the author himself depicts “as a plea for a less parochial jurisprudence ” (Twining 2009, xiii). His “central concern is with the development of adequate ways of expressing law and talking about law”, which in his view can only be obtained by elaborating a “wider conception of law that goes

3 For more precise and more detailed taxonomies, see Menski (2006) and Twining (2009).

xvIntroduction

beyond municipal or state law and covers all levels of legal ordering”. Twining’s core concept of law is based on a much “wider range of concepts than traditional analytical jurisprudence” in such a way to include “global, transnational, interna-tional, regional, municipal (including national and subnational), and local non-state” legal orderings ( ibid. , 39). Such an extensive revision of legal theory, according to Twining, should break once and for all with the myopic tendency that has long identi fi ed state legal orders (that is, a particular and transient shape taken by the millennial practice of law) with the broader phenomenon of law.

This fracture with the traditional ways to understand law and its relation to society is full of consequences. In a nutshell, What happens to law when its ties with the state and its monopoly of legitimate violence are being severed? This is what Twining calls the ‘problem of the de fi nitional stop’: “If one opens the door to some examples of non-state law, then we are left with no clear basis for differentiating legal norms from other social norms, legal institutions and practices from other social institutions and practices, legal traditions from religious or other general intellectual traditions and so on” ( ibid. , 369). In the present book I will contend that this question is absolutely central and that yet there can be remarkably different ways to tackle it, which lead to remarkably different conclusions. As I will explain in detail in the book, some scholars deem the distinction between legal rules and other social rules either as an abstractive construal of positivist state-centred theories, or else as a factual consequence of historical political arrangements. Such scholars say that nowadays the growing pluralism of normative orders makes this distinction outdated and exhort legal theorists to dispose once and for all of the fi ctitious idea that law is something separate from ordinary life. In reality, they conclude, the legal and the broader social are so intertwined that no distinctive line among good manners, religious precepts, and positive legal rules can be drawn. In contrast, there are scholars who believe that such a distinctive line, although dif fi cult to fi nd, exists and is constitutive of law’s nature. They claim that the legal practice actually possesses some speci fi c qualities that make its products unique and norma-tively prior to the products of other types of normative orderings, and that legal theory is the proper fi eld in which these qualities must be identi fi ed and examined.

In my opinion, the fi rst stripe of scholars convincingly demonstrate that, whether or not the distinguishing line between the legal and the social domains exists, today the inquiry into the nature of law requires a novel theoretical approach and more adequate tools of analysis, freed from the tacit assumption that law is only what the state wants it to be. At the same time, however, the profound changes that I men-tioned above require legal theorists to take the pragmatic bearings of their concep-tual proposals into due account and thus to pay due heed to what is involved in expanding the domain of the legal. In fact, what is at stake in this quarrel is not a mere clari fi cation of the meaning of law; nor does it merely lead to a better under-standing of a familiar institution. What is at stake here is the stock of symbolic power that is inevitably linked to the term ‘law’ . Enlarging the domain of the legal, as I will argue in this book, always involves a re-allocation of power and legitimacy. De fi ning something as law, and, more in general, de fi ning something as something entails the power to say what must be included and what excluded, what belongs to

xvi Introduction

a genus and what does not, what should be recognised as having certain preroga-tives and prior claims and what should not. This is why de fi ning cannot be merely seen as an analytical job, in that, as Pierre Bourdieu stresses, categories have the

the etymological sense of collective, public imputations ( katègoreisthai originally meant to accuse someone publicly), collectively approved and attested as self-evident and necessary. As such, they contain the magical power to institute frontiers and constitute groups, by performative declarations […] that are invested with all the strength of the group that they help to make (Bourdieu 1990, 170).

As a consequence, the inclusion of religious, business, or nongovernmental normative entities, which once were considered as non-legal, into the realm of the legal, and, even more signi fi cantly, the dissolution of the very idea of the legal as a special fi eld of society, inevitably exerts pragmatic effects on social reality. The quali fi er ‘legal’ bears with itself a claim to independence, autonomy, self-government, which is not necessarily associated to the much more extensive quali fi er ‘normative’. This is the reason why the battle around the use of the term ‘legal’ starts off as partly and necessarily theoretical, but then becomes political more quickly than other conceptual battles.

In this book I cannot discuss these pragmatic effects. 4 Nonetheless, I will try to cast some light on the crucial importance of the question as to what law is and its relation to society while pursuing two different but related aims. On the one hand, I will argue that the pluralist challenge must be taken seriously. I will show that most of the traditional attempts to pin down the speci fi c properties of law have fallen short. This should compel us to recognise that law is a far more articulated and multifaceted phenomenon than the state legal order and that ‘legality’ can be neither considered as the exclusive property of a given social entity (such as the modern state) nor con fi ned to a narrow lapse of time (such as Western modernity). On the other hand, I will claim that the plurality of laws cannot be confused with the plurality of normative entities, and that ‘legality’ is a special subset of the broader fi eld of social (or ‘jural’, as I will call it later) normativity. I will provide the ground for holding that, even though legal entities and normative ones have many traits in com-mon, the legal is a very particular fi eld of society and that it is up to legal theory (appropriately supported by other approaches and methodologies) to identify its distinguishing marks. Yet, as I will argue, this does not imply the conclusion that in a given geo-historical context there can be only one law. As the history of both pre-modern European countries and colonial realities show, there can well be more than one type of law claiming to exert a jurisdictional supremacy on a given territorial area and/or on a given set of subjects. However, it is my contention that this does not mean that every group, association, and/or fi eld, which produces rules of its own, can be straightforwardly considered as legal, despite the in fl uence on of fi cial law they can wield. In brief, the main proposal of this book will be to justify the claim that, albeit we cannot by any means deny the existence of a plurality of legal orders, we cannot simply accept the conclusion that every normative ordering is in itself legal.

4 I deal with this topic in Croce (2011b). More in general, see Roberts (2005) and Heydebrand (2007).

xviiIntroduction

In other words, I will argue that we need a highly pluralistic theoretical approach, which however may be able to help determine what distinguishes the legal from the broader social and, therefore, whether or not something can be de fi ned as legal.

Theoretical Backdrop

In the ten chapters comprising the present book I will tackle four main issues: the nature of law, the nature of normativity, the relation between law and society, the borders between legal and non-legal normativity. Such a far-reaching inquiry will necessitate a multi-sided and interdisciplinary approach. My arguments will draw on studies developed in the fi elds of jurisprudence , legal sociology, legal anthropo-logy, but also social theory, history of law, and history of ideas. Although I do think this conceptual strategy to be indispensable to the achievement of my aim, I cannot omit that each of these fi elds adopts a speci fi c approach and follows a rigorous methodology, which, more often than not, cannot be easily translated into the approach and methodology of the others. This is why I want to clarify the scope, the aims, and the methodology of my work carefully.

In my opinion – and this is one of the main claims of my book – there is no point in accentuating the divide between legal theories that prospered inside the state and those that today are emerging as a reaction to the undeniable legal centralism of the former. Rather, it is important to understand and stress the extraordinary af fi nities among some theoretical paradigms, which at fi rst sight seem to be at odds with each other, whereas in reality reach very similar conclusions about the nature of law. A thoughtful and pondered integration among them can not only show that signi fi cant authors, in spite of their different conceptual argot, have actually dealt with the same problems and have noticeably contributed to elaborating workable solutions; an integration among them can also amend and reinforce such solutions, and can also make sense of some of the puzzles that they have left unsolved. More speci fi cally, I will canvass the proposals of some exponents of three leading schools of thought, or fi elds of study, who have remarkably contributed to a better understanding of legal phenomena. The mentioned schools are legal positivism , legal pluralism , and classic legal institutionalism . Especially in Parts I and II, I will examine what some of their leading exponents have argued about the nature of law and its relation to society. Yet, my objective will not be a detailed exegesis of these scholars. I will rather try to assess and compare their thinking on the nature of law and on the way it affects social reality in order to think with , against , and beyond them.

In Part I, I will mainly consider legal positivism . I will fi rst explain the reason why some of its leading representatives (such as John Austin and Hans Kelsen) have been so preoccupied with defending the idea that law is a set of coercive rules issued by state of fi cials. However, this will be instrumental in the examination of what I deem to be one of the most impressive as well as intriguing attempts to de fi ne the nature of law, that is, Hart’s ‘practice theory’. In my view, Hart’s is the most robust and at once most instructive attempt to produce a positivist conception of law. By

xviii Introduction

exploring his proposal, I will pursue a twofold aim. On the one hand, I will suggest the limits of a positivist understanding of law. On the other hand, I will develop what I will call a ‘rule-based model’, which is a crucial, although not suf fi cient, step towards the de fi nition of the core nature of law. In trying to achieve such a twofold aim, I will show that Hart has provided the ground for a pluralistic understanding of law, although he himself was reluctant to support it.

In Part II, I will focus both on legal pluralism and on legal institutionalism. I will start off by examining the conclusions of Part I so as to understand whether or not the impasse of the rule-based model is a conclusive reason for us to accept that the line distinguishing the legal from the social is a theoretical construct, which has no actual counterpart in reality. This will be a suitable pathway to enter the variegated world of legal pluralism. I will brie fl y examine three kinds of pluralism and the types of reasons they offer to sustain that the law is an intrinsically plural pheno-menon. In particular, I will focus on Eugen Ehrlich and Santi Romano ( fi rst type), Sally Falk Moore and Marc Galanter (second type), Sally Engle Merry and Brian Tamanaha (third type). I will examine how they deal with the dilemma of the de fi nitional stop and the ways they suggest for solving it. In doing so, I will argue that, despite their generally declared anti-positivism, some of these authors precisely arrive at the conclusions reached by Hart and that therefore their proposals are affected by the same problems affecting the rule-based model. As a possible way-out, I will fi rst call attention to the proposals of Adamson Hoebel, who sets forth a view of law that, if properly amended, is fully compatible with legal pluralism and is immune to its main defects. This analysis will allow me to turn to legal institutionalism, some of whose exponents have put forward a sound hypothesis on law, which is able to combine an institutional view with both legal positivism and legal pluralism. I will argue that the cradle of this institutional view was the Italian legal culture of the fi rst half of the twentieth century, of which Santi Romano and Widar Cesarini Sforza were prominent representatives.

The analyses developed in the fi rst two parts of the book will be instrumental in identifying two necessary but insuf fi cient elements for capturing the core nature of law, that is, the formal structure and the selective nature of law, which I will con-cisely address in the next section. To these elements, in Part III I will add a third necessary one. To achieve this, I will draw on very different kinds of analysis: from legal sociology and legal anthropology to the history of law. This wide-ranging approach will allow me to pay due heed to the various aspect of the legal domain. It is worth mentioning that, in Part III, I will mostly look at the processual side of the legal practice. In doing so, I will claim that law is not only a special set of rules, with a given structure and a given function; indeed, the legal fi eld is above all a theatre of interaction and discussion for social subjects to change social reality by applying the rules and categories of the legal fi eld.

To develop this complex strategy, it is vital that legal philosophy, legal sociology, legal anthropology, and legal history may be brought together, so as to appreciate the many aspects of law from very different angles. By way of this multidisciplinary approach, I will be able to provide an image of law as a dynamic space, which retroacts on social reality in a very special manner. I will portray law as a discursive

xixIntroduction

contest, in which social subjects can renegotiate their surroundings and revise wide-spread social meanings. In my opinion, only this wide-ranging view can make sense of the role of law in the construction and maintenance of social order.

At the same time, I believe that in order to develop this view of law and to capture how law affects social reality, one should also concentrate on the much broader phenomenon of social normativity. This is why, although philosophy and other kinds of approach must proceed hand in hand, the role of the former cannot be undervalued. In effect, today there is a widespread tendency to sociologise and historicise the philosophy of law. This tendency can be useful inasmuch as the refer-ence to factual circumstances helps uncover some of the tacit presuppositions of traditional legal philosophy, such as the identity between the law of the state and the law, which too many philosophers in the last two centuries have taken for granted. It is undeniable that the recent experience of modern state – which appears rather brief if compared to the millennial history of law – has moulded the perception of legal phenomena in such a way to establish the mentioned identity. In contrast, as I have already said and as I will explain in more detail in the book, many studies in the fi elds of legal history and legal anthropology have contributed to disproving this biased tenet. Nevertheless, it is my claim that legal philosophy cannot be seen as ancillary; let alone as unnecessary. Among other things, legal philosophy, at least as far as I understand it here, is an essential re fl ection over the conditions that allow to de fi ne something as legal. Legal philosophy is called upon to justify the argumenta-tive conditions allowing to assess certain statements about law as meaningful and others as meaningless. Legal philosophy is the laboratory in which important conceptual tools are produced in order for legal scholars to talk about their subject matters. Such tools serve as an indispensable component of a broader lexicographic apparatus, which all legal scholars employ every time they use terms such as law, legal, legality, legal validity, and so on. It is my opinion that, to account for the composite phenomenon of law, legal scholars cannot merely look at social reality and describe the way it works. In every description of law, and even more pro-foundly, in every description of reality, many conceptual categories are at work, even without legal scholars being aware of that. More in particular, as I will argue in the book, in order to differentiate between legal rules and generally social rules – as well as in order to deny that such a difference exists – one should previously determine what a rule is, which role such rules play in social life, and even how rules are connected to knowledge and interaction. Short of robust conceptual tools, developed in the fi eld of legal philosophy (and philosophy in general), no legal scholar can answer these questions in a convincing manner.

Because of this, I believe that any sound inquiry into the nature of law should be based on very different types of analysis, which may integrate and amend each other. My own inquiry will be devoted to analysing the nature of law by understanding the particular way law shapes social reality. As I will brie fl y explain in the next sec-tion, the fi nal argument of my book will be that law is a special trans-sectional venue, with some speci fi c properties, in which subjects can renegotiate social reality. I will provide a speci fi c image of law, its set of rules, its categories, and its language as functionally instrumental to the construction and maintenance of a special area.

xx Introduction

In this area, social subjects – who inescapably live in a highly fragmented and frac-tured social world – can enjoy an as if , in which they are forced to adopt the same categories and to apply the same rules in order to provide a shared account of social reality. To justify such a hypothesis, I will previously examine the way rules work in social life, the different types of rules, the different types of practices that such types of rules contribute to building, and other relevant topics. This is why I believe this book to be a contribution in the fi eld of legal philosophy, with the fi nal aim of enlarging its horizons and overcoming some of its traditional impasses.

The Book: Structure and Aims

As I have so far argued, I mean this book to contribute to the understanding of what law is and its role in the ordering of society. At the same time, it is also a plea for rethinking legal theory and its role in the analysis of legal phenomena. It is impor-tant to regard these aims as strictly related in order to decipher a contradiction that may seem to be affecting my purpose. In fact, on the one hand, I will support the hypothesis that law is a very special fi eld, whose inner nature is intrinsically con-nected to its being distinct and separate from every other fi eld in the social theatre. On the other hand, I will argue for a pluralistic view of law, or rather, a comprehension of legal phenomena claiming that social reality is characterised by the constant pos-sibility that two or more laws can operate side by side in the same geo-historical context. How can one say at one and the same time that the law is something unique and special and that it can always be plural? My gamble is that we can cast some light on law’s being a plural phenomenon precisely by capturing its special nature. To achieve this, I will focus on social and legal normativity trying to show that distin-guishing them from one another is crucial to a thorough comprehension of both. In this regard, Frederick Schauer (2004) correctly notices that we cannot simply accept as a trivial assumption that law is a “limited domain”. It will be part of my argument in this book that a solid inquiry into the nature of law requires a careful analysis of the difference between social and legal normativity, of what really distinguishes them, and of the degree and value of this distinction (what Schauer calls the ‘how much’). In saying this, I am convinced that “[w]hen we ask whether law is slightly or greatly a limited domain we thus ask a question whose answer takes us far towards understanding what law does and how it does it” (Schauer 2004, 1916). My analysis also aims to investigate whether the distinction between legal and social normativity and the separation between the legal and the social domains are the mere product of some sort of social differentiation and specialisation, or whether, on the contrary, it is a constitutive element of law, which quali fi es the very same nature of law. In the following pages I will address the kind of analysis I will undertake throughout the book and, in doing so, I will also provide a brief synopsis.

The title brings up the two poles of my general argumentation: law and social order . It also reveals my fundamental conviction about the nature of law. Law is self-suf fi cient, although in a particular sense, that will become clearer chapter by

xxiIntroduction

chapter. But I would like to clarify in advance that, in my view, ‘self-suf fi ciency’ is not the same as ‘autonomy’. The two terms may overlap and in effect they tend to be confused both in the everyday language and in the special languages of social sciences. I think it is important to differentiate them inasmuch as we want to under-stand the way in which law relates to social order. As far as I can say, most of the legal thinkers who were interested in law’s being a special sphere of social reality have tried to establish if and how law is autonomous or semi-autonomous from what it is designed to regulate, govern, control, or discipline: in a word, from society . In this reading, studies concerning law’s autonomy have started off by two premises: fi rstly, that law develops according to an inner logic, which is quite independent form the broader logic of social development; secondly, that the set of legal rules is always characterised by a gap in relation to the several non-legal entities populating the social, which produce many kinds of regulations of their own. 5 I reject these premises not so much because they are fl awed, but because in my opinion they do not provide a workable point of departure for understanding the nature of law. I believe that a simple basic divide between law and society is untenable. Such a dyadic view, law/society, is a theoretical construct, a mode of representation. The complex relation between them can hardly be represented by any simple dyad. This is why I refuse any bare contraposition, such as law and culture, law and society, law and morality. Not only is there no single law. But above all there are no single society, culture, and morality. I am committed to, and my book will try to justify, a radically pluralist standpoint seeing human activity and its numerous productions as intrinsically plural and multifaceted. Society is a set of intertwined social practices, institutions, organisations with no single centre from which they radiate. As I will argue at the end of my book, this pluralistic understanding of social reality throws some light on the role of law in the geo-historical context in which it is at work.

My pluralist vantage point, however, does not rule out the possibility that we can fi nd reliable conceptual criteria that may help us understand and assessing the difference (that I believe to exist) between what I will generally label as ‘the social’ and ‘the legal’. Indeed, this is one of the main goals of the present book. This explains why, in Parts I and II, I will mainly concentrate on how the prominent authors I have mentioned above have tried to uncover and conceptualise the line separating these two realms. At the same time, I will pay much heed to the way in which the pursuit of this line has signi fi cantly affected the outcome of their theoretical inquiries. As I said above, mine will not be an exercise in literature reading. In fact, I will interpret their proposals and suggestions (sometimes contrary to their self-interpretation) in such a way as to show that they deal with the same kinds of problems and offer highly compatible solutions, which in my view should be integrated in order to provide a much stronger theoretical account. In Part III I will offer my own view on the problems discussed in the preceding parts. In doing so, I will capitalise on my personal interpretations of these authors and will further elaborate and strengthen the theory emerging out of their integration. But now I can offer a sketch

5 See also Tomlins (2007, 46).

xxii Introduction

of my general argument. I will adopt the problem of autonomy/self-suf fi ciency and the relation between the social and the legal as basic guidelines.

The issue of autonomy has been widely debated in the fi eld of legal theory. For example, in the ambit of jurisprudence , Brian Bix (2003) has provided a concise view on what legal autonomy means and implies. He argues that the idea of legal autonomy is based on the fact that legal reasoning and legal decision-making are self-suf fi cient as compared to other forms of reasoning or decision-making. More in general, Schauer (2004) convincingly claims that legal positivists, and in particular the pioneers of this school of thought, expended signi fi cant efforts in trying to portray law as something distinct from the social. He praises their struggling to understand law as a ‘limited domain’ that has many relationships with morals, politics, religion, and other spheres of social reality, but remains separate from them all. Schauer mentions the works of Hobbes, Bentham, Austin, and Kelsen in order to prove that legal positivism emerged precisely as an attempt to stress law’s being different from seemingly similar domains. I will start off by arguing that this reading is sound. Still, I will devote many pages of Part I to showing that positivists were not only concerned with the independence and autonomy of law, but also with the independence and autonomy of legal theory. Still, in arguing so, I will not provide neither a historical nor a conceptual reconstruction of legal positivism. It will be my purpose to demonstrate that positivism, as a theoretical enterprise, collapsed precisely when one of its leading representatives, Hart, resorted to shortening the distance separating both the legal from the social and (I would say: consequently) conceptual analysis from sociological inquiry.

In Chap. 1 I will argue that Austin and Kelsen, whom I take as basic prototypes of two different ways of elaborating a positivist view of law, were primarily intent on setting the borders of jurisprudence . Austin’s insisting on the fact that the subject matter of jurisprudence must be positive law was instrumental in de fi ning the borders of this new science: he believed that legal theorists are called upon to provide criteria for determining whether something is legal or not. According to Austin, they must simply ascertain if what is under scrutiny is the command of someone who is habitu-ally obeyed by the bulk of the population and which has no habit to obey anybody else. Kelsen thought that this view turned out to render legal theorists into sociolo-gists called upon to scrutinise effectual reality in order to verify if such commands are socially ef fi cacious. He thus proposed a ‘purifying’ amendment to legal positi-vism . Legal theorists must provide a description of law as it is, regardless of whether it is concretely obeyed. It should not surprise us, therefore, that sociologists of law and their tendency to match the social and the legal domains were the main target of Kelsen’s criticisms. In his view, law can only be understood if we think of it as a separate domain and if legal science provides speci fi c conceptual categories that may account for what a legal order is and how it differs from other types of social order-ing. In short, Austin’s drawing the borders of jurisprudence and Kelsen’s defending the pureness of legal theory were crucial steps towards the constitution of an autono-mous discipline and towards an understanding of law as a limited domain.

Of course, such an enterprise could not be totally free of defects. The main fl aws were an high degree of theoretical abstractness and quite a counterintuitive

xxiiiIntroduction

implausibility of some basic tenets. This is the reason why I believe Hart’s thought to be so important. As a respected representative of the positivist school, who how-ever has ever tried to eschew its abstractness, Hart constitutes at one and the same time the apex and the collapse of the positivist enterprise. As I will argue throughout the book, the legal positivist Hart manages to provide one of the most robust theo-ries of legal pluralism. Just in trying to show that law forceful pluralist institutional-ism is a limited domain, 6 Hart proves that law is a plural phenomenon. This is why my concern will not be with Hart’s theory of law per se , but with the lesson we should learn from his struggling to refute many of the paradoxes which several posi-tivists authors incurred. In Chaps. 1 , 2 , 3 , and 4 (comprising Part I) I will seek to show that, in the very same attempt at confuting some conclusions of these thinkers, Hart turns out to jettison legal theory as a separate fi eld of study and, more importantly, to jettison law as a separate sphere of social reality. Part I will be entirely dedicated to examining the striking paradox I am discussing here: one of the soundest justi fi cations of law as a special sphere of reality leads to the conclusion that such a sphere is not special at all. My basic line of argument will be that Hart elaborates a very robust conception of normativity (in particular the conception that emerges out of the original version of The Concept of Law , which I will address as a book highly in fl uenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein’s teaching and by the philosophers of ordinary language). By analysing and, at least to some extent, revising some of the theoreti-cal pillars of Hart’s book, I will argue that his conception of normativity does account for the role that rules play in everyday (not legal) life and that, as a conse-quence, his model of law is by no means a model of law, but a sound analysis of rule-governed contexts in general.

In this kind of inquiry I will take Hart as a basic prototype of all theorists who try to justify the law with no recourse to other elements but law’s own formal structure. In effect, Hart programmatically disposes of coercion and morality as two typical, although opposed, ways of accounting for the nature of law. He purports to demon-strate that law, at least from a conceptual and foundational vantage point, is thoroughly separate from other spheres of reality, such as politics (and its monopoly on coercion) and justice (and its ties with conventional morality). Hart believes that, if we really think of law as separate from other spheres of reality, we must avoid recurring to aspects, such as coercion or moral elements, that belong to non-legal spheres. He is persuaded that what he calls ‘rule of recognition’ is really able to distinguish what belongs to the legal domain and what to the larger domain of the social. In examining Hart’s lines of reasoning, it will be my concern to demonstrate that the relevance of his fascinating attempt at justifying a fully autonomous legal domain is not con fi ned to analytical jurisprudence . Indeed, the vindication of what I will call a ‘rule-based model’ would exert many bene fi cial effects on other fi elds of studies, in which, as I will illustrate, many thinkers have striven to capture the

6 I agree with Schauer when he claims that “[m]uch in Hart’s work might be understood (though perhaps not by Hart) as assuming that law is […] a limited domain” and he believes that “rules of recognition distinguish the norms or sources (or anything else) of the law from the norms and sources available in the larger society” (Schauer 2004, 1917).

xxiv Introduction

properties of the normative entity that we call ‘law’. Yet, just in showing the strength and fruitfulness of the rule-based model of law, I will argue that the strategy to capture law’s being a special sphere of social reality by solely casting light on the characteristics of its formal structure breaks down. Two of the main consequences of this failure are, fi rstly, that the line separating the social from the legal vanishes and, secondly, that also legal theory ends up losing its distinctive properties.

In other words, Part I will be a critical defence of the rule-based model. It will be a defence , in that I will maintain that this model is a convincing analysis of social normativity in general. In Chaps. 2 and 3 I will examine the way in which rules structure and govern social interaction and their pivotal role as epistemic and prag-matic instruments. Hart’s arguments about rules (especially if observed through Wittgensteinian lenses) are compelling. Rules are both guidelines that enable social subjects to plan their actions and standards for assessing and criticising deviant conducts. In addition, one of the core aspects of rules is that, when accepted from an internal point of view, they permit social subjects to provide a common account of what surrounds them. At the same time, my defence will be critical , because in Chap. 4 I will argue that, if we assume Hart’s idea of rules being a good foundation for law, then we must conclude that, paradoxically, law is not a limited domain at all, but a largely widespread phenomenon. In fact, I will explain that the rule-based model of law, justi fi ed by the conceptual tools devised by Hart, depicts law as any sort of practice characterised by two basic features: fi rst, the presence of two distinct types of rules (primary and secondary) which must be systematically intercon-nected; second, the presence of a restricted group of authorised rule-creating and rule-applying of fi cials. If this is so, then every context that exhibits these features can be legitimately deemed to be an instance of the legal phenomenon. As a matter of fact, several social groups, institutions, and organisations are structured that way.

This conclusion explains why, in Part I, I will constantly compare Hart’s theory with the view of a prominent legal anthropologist, Gordon Woodman, who is par-ticularly hostile to the idea that law has a special place within social reality. Woodman denies that we can really fi nd any element in social reality indicating the difference between a genuinely social and a genuinely legal domain. According to him, both theoretical analysis and empirical observation attest to the fact that there is no distinguishing line separating social rules from legal rules. He concludes that, more often than not, the legal and the social are interwoven, if not coextensive. At the same time Woodman argues that, just as the social is not a homogeneous monolith, grounded on the same shared set of rules and made up of one group of people, but is a vast array of practices, groups, and institutions with their own set of rules; so the law is not a homogeneous body of rules, but an unstable, changing, and fl exible accretion of different and overlapping sets of rules. In the light of this comparison, I will claim that (perhaps contrary to his own intents) Hart has remarkably contri-buted to the dissolution of legal theory as a specialised science and to the dissolution of the idea that law has a special place within social reality. I will then argue that, all things considered, the rule-based model represents a robust theoretical foundation for what today is known as ‘legal pluralism’. In addition, as I hope it will become clearer chapter by chapter, this model offers a fi rst basic, although quite insuf fi cient,

xxvIntroduction

element for the de fi nition of law that I will offer in Part III. The element stressed by the rule-based model is that, in order for something to be de fi ned as law, it must possess a formal structure made up of different kinds of rules and inner groups with different roles and functions.

In Part II I will further elaborate the issue of law as a limited domain and that of the separation between the social and the legal by examining the valuable insights of some leading representatives of legal pluralism and classic legal institutionalism. In Chap. 5 I will consider the proposals of some authors (more speci fi cally, Ehrlich, Romano, Moore, Galanter, Merry, and Tamanaha) who, in different ways and with different intents, have provided workable insights into the relation between the legal and the social. In doing this, I will sketch three basic prototypes of legal pluralism. The fi rst type, developed by Ehrlich and Romano, portrays law as the inner order of every organised social body. In this reading, the legal and the social are barely distinguishable. The second type, developed by Moore and Galanter, deems law to be a speci fi c form of ordering which has many elements in common with generally social orderings, although there are some traits that are typical of law. In this read-ing, the legal and the social signi fi cantly overlap, but the legal is characterised by a varying degree of arti fi ciality. The third type, developed by Merry and Tamanaha, is more preoccupied with not confusing the legal with the social and with fi nding genuinely legal elements. In this view, there are entities that can be de fi ned unmis-takably legal and that therefore can be distinguished from non-legal ones. I will stress some weak and strong points of these ways to understand legal pluralism, and will call attention to the need for legal theory to adopt a pluralistic approach. Nonetheless, at the end of the chapter, I will maintain that, however enlightening and open-minded such an approach may be, legal pluralism and the rule-based model of law are somehow two sides of the same coin. My line of argument will be that most legal pluralists (with the exception of those who do not believe that a line between the legal and the social can be found 7 ) fail to explain what the difference is between the multitude of social orderings and genuinely legal orders. They declare that there must be something which confers on some orders a genuinely legal signi fi -cance, but at the end of the day they are incapable of saying what this something is.

In this reading, Chap. 6 will start off by examining the criticisms that Tamanaha conveys to many versions of legal pluralism. In particular I will mull over what he de fi nes as ‘the Malinowski problem’, which plunges into the dif fi culties faced by most legal pluralists while trying to ascertain the differences between the social and the legal. Although Tamanaha’s arguments are worth being considered, I will claim that his criticisms are not well addressed and that legal pluralists have many strings to their bow to rebut them. I will then put forward my own solution to the Malinowski problem by drawing on the proposal of Hoebel. The analysis of his thought will be an occasion to discuss a highly crucial issue, that is, whether or not the difference between the legal and the social can be really found in coercion, as many authors

7 Two vivid examples are Werner Menski and Woodman.

xxvi Introduction

belonging to different fi elds of study contend. I will show that Hoebel provides a thoughtful analysis as regards the way in which law emerges and functions as a selective device meant to serve some speci fi c tasks. On the other hand, I will claim that he wrongly posits that only legitimate coercion can really make the difference.

To corroborate my conclusions, in Chap. 7 , I will argue that, at the beginning of the twentieth century, the school of thought known as ‘legal institutionalism’ (which some interpreter calls ‘classic’ so as to distinguish it from recent institutionalist paradigms) was able to capture almost all of the elements discussed in the preceding chapters. By analysing the thought of the founding fathers of Italian classic institu-tionalism, Romano and Cesarini Sforza, I will show that they provide a convincing analysis of the nature of law with no recourse either to morality or to coercion. Although both support a radical version of legal pluralism, they are persuaded that legal theorists are called upon to discover the differentia speci fi ca of law. The com-parison between their view on legal phenomena will be particularly functional to the main goal of this book. Actually, I will fi rst argue that Romano develops a forceful pluralist institutionalism, which has much in common with Hart’s and Galanter’s view. However, his theory (precisely like the rule-based model and most versions of legal pluralism) incurs what I will call ‘Romano’s dilemma’. I will then argue that this dilemma can be solved by employing Cesarini Sforza’s conceptual tools. It will be my claim that this highly overlooked Italian thinker offers some precious insights into the nature of law, which can help solve many of the puzzles highlighted in the previous chapters. Like Hoebel, Cesarini Sforza claims that law is a selective device ful fi lling some basic social tasks. The latter however offers a sounder description of social normativity and of the way in which it interacts with the legal domain. The integration between Hoebel and Cesarini Sforza will allow me to formulate a new hypothesis that, following Twining (2009), I will de fi ne ‘thin functionalism’. I will fi nally maintain that this particular kind of functionalism offers a second element, that along with the idea of a formal structure of law, helps understand the special nature of the institution of law. Thin functionalism posits that, in order for an order-ing to be de fi ned legal, it must not only possess the formal structure mentioned above. It must also have the capacity to ful fi l some pivotal tasks, such as de fi ning relationships among the members of a collectivity, allocating powers, settling trouble cases, and handling social change.

In Chap. 8 , I will capitalise on the analyses conducted in the previous chapters so as to provide a comprehensive understanding of social normativity. I will contend that social reality is nothing but an array of rule-governed contexts, structured by different kind of rules (criterion-rules, instance-rules, norm-rules). I will explain that these contexts can be differentiated by inspecting some inner features, such as the formality of rules, the specialisation of roles, the type of sanctions that can be exerted therein, the way in which sanctions are in fl icted. In doing so, I will argue that rule-governed contexts can be regarded as components of a normative contin-uum, with fl uid social practices at one end and solid organisations at the opposed end. I will say that what I will call solid organisations do possess a particular formal structure (in terms of inner rules and roles) and ful fi l the social tasks mentioned above. Yet, I will explain that not all of them should be deemed as legal. Based on

xxviiIntroduction

this, I will argue that the ideas of formal structure and thin functionalism, though necessary, are not suf fi cient to identify the core nature of law and to understand what differentiates the legal from the social, in that several social organisations present in society can be described with recourse to these elements.

In Part III I will provide my own solution to this thorny issue. I will contend that the two elements thus far stressed must be integrated by a third one, which has to do precisely with the space separating the broader social from the narrower legal fi eld. In doing so, I will try to cast some light on the relevance of the legal domain for there being such thing as social reality. At the same time, I will claim that the sep-arateness between the legal and the remainder of non-legal rule-governed contexts inheres in the very same nature of law.

In Chap. 9 I will argue that law is so special in that it represents a trans-sectional and insulated venue, neatly separated from everyday life, in which everyday reality can be renegotiated and rephrased by means of its special knowledge (usually mas-tered by legal experts) and a rigid set of conceptual categories. The main variables involved in this de fi nition are: trans-sectionality, professionalisation, separateness from everyday life, insulated knowledge, rigid conceptual categories, and formulaic language. Of course, no single variable is peculiar to law. Physics can be trans-sectional and separated from normal life, a church can be highly professionalized and can adopt formulaic languages, theology or economics are insulated forms of knowledge and deploy special sets of conceptual categories. Yet, I will argue that the conjunction of all or most of these variables makes law unique. It is my claim that my de fi nition singles out some useful criterion which may help both theoretical inquiry and empirical observation determine what law really is. My proposal will contribute to showing that law is not a single basic phenomenon, but a complex set of phenomena that can be subsumed under the same category owing to their sharing the same analytically constructed criteria . Put otherwise, in order for something to be de fi ned as law, it must not only have a given formal structure and be able to perform some vital functions; it must also be founded on a separate and trans-sectional form of knowledge, comprised of a special language and special categories, which is usually (though not always) administered by specialists. Only if it is structured that way can law overcome the fractures that fragment social life and also provide different social subjects, belonging to different rule-governed contexts, with rules and categories that they can all understand and apply. I will argue that many forms of law in most geo-historical contexts exhibit all, or most, of the aspects that I have thus far mentioned.

In Chap. 10 I will reinforce my conclusions on law’s being a special venue by arguing that law has a ritual nature , sparking off two opposite but inseparable dimensions. On the one hand, there is a ‘nondiscursive’ dimension where ‘normative facts’ are produced, which are able to set a criterion of normality for social reality. On the other hand, there is what I will call ‘discursive’ dimension, in which social subjects have the possibility of questioning and revising these very same normative facts. Precisely by doing so, they renegotiate their social surroundings. Thus, these dimensions (the one conservative and the other transformative) are both opposed and deeply intertwined. The nondiscursive dimension allows the establishment of a

xxviii Introduction

shared context of action – the legal fi eld – in which social subjects are compelled to adopt a given stock of knowledge and categories, which cannot be questioned from inside the legal fi eld. This context of action is safeguarded by its own ritual character. Yet, just because of this rigid structure, the discursive dimension of law allows those who employ its knowledge and categories to put into question and then revise the rules of their everyday life, and even to outline new ways of relationships and coexistence. Based on this, I will argue that law is what makes a collectivity exist and subsist as a collectivity, and this explains why law is so crucial to there being a social order.

In other words, the last two chapters of my book are meant to justify what I have called a ‘critical-institutional’ theory of social order, in which the role played by law is presented as central. My theory will be institutional, because I will contend that law triggers and protects a process of institutionalisation, which is indispensable for a collectivity not to be a mere aggregate of isolated individuals or self-interested groups. At the same time, I will stress the critical side of this process, which consists in law’s capacity to favour a constant revision of social rules and meanings. In the light of this, I will fi nally argue that the separation between the social and the legal is instrumental to the existence of both. On the one hand, the legal exists only insofar as it can claim (or pretend) to be self-suf fi cient and to be based on a fully autono-mous body of knowledge and categories. On the other hand, social subjects, by entering the legal fi eld, make use of law as a trans-sectional venue, in which the fragmentation of the social can be temporarily replaced by a shared set of categories and rules (the body of legal knowledge), which are (or at least pretend to be) equally distant from every rule-governed context on which law claims to exert a supreme jurisdiction. Law functioning that way, the legal fi eld operates as an as if , in which people jointly handle and negotiate social divisions by using a given stock of tools. While arguing this, I will duly put stress on the constitutively different roles played by two different groups of people within the legal fi eld. On the one hand, there is the group that I will call ‘relevant population’, consisting of publicly recognised experts (be they elders, wises, chiefs, professors, or judges) who are called upon to select the ‘normative facts’ of a population and to proclaim them as binding in the whole jurisdiction (whether or not this is tied to a territory). On the other hand, there is the group that I will call ‘lay people’, which is very often excluded from the game of the interpreting the legal body of knowledge and rules, because they lack certain indis-pensable requirements. Yet, I will claim that also the role of lay people is constitutive of there being a law. In fact, in order for a law to work as a law, it must serve as a theatre of interaction and discussion (above all) for lay social subjects. They are required to bring into the legal fi eld what is outside it; they are required, under the guidance of the experts, to provide an entirely new description of fact and events; they are required to transport the outcome of the discussions and interaction taking place within the legal fi eld into the broader social domain.

In conclusion, I would like to return brie fl y to the two interlaced aims of my book, that is, justifying the distinctiveness of law and, at the same time, advocating a pluralist approach to law. It should be clear now that my idea of law does not rule out the possibility that more laws coexist in the same geo-historical context. A quick

xxixIntroduction

look at what came before the modern state, the Middle Ages, shows that many types of law (Roman law, Canon law, feudal law, the various customary laws, merchant law, and others) cohabited and often overlapped. They all had their own sources, their own experts, their own courts, although they always interacted within the broader framework of the ius commune . This was a highly fl exible legal order, in which different types of law might balance each other, or even con fl ict. In fact this order was not based on hierarchical levels, fi xed once and for all, but on an always revisable framework, inclined to privilege the plurality of cases to the detriment of the generality of laws. Yet, all the component of the ius commune were laws in the sense I will specify in the present book. In other words, I believe that we can prop-erly account for their nature only if we employ the analytically constructed criteria that I will discuss in the following chapters. And in my view, this applies to many other types of law in other geo-historical contexts. Surely, any context has its own speci fi cities, which can hardly be found in others. Inevitably, law takes different shapes in accordance with these speci fi cities as well as with the particular produc-tions, requirements, and needs of those who employ it for negotiating their own social reality. Nevertheless, I believe that legal philosophy (in collaboration with other disciplines) has both to provide the ground for comparing these different experiences, in order to determine whether or not there is some element which is truly crucial to their subsistence and reproduction, and, at the same time, to explain which features make this element what it is.

As I have underlined at the outset, this kind of analysis is by no means a mere theoretical enterprise. While in the past decades the vexed question of the borderline between the legal and the social could merely be seen as an academic quarrel, today it is increasingly acquiring a pragmatic value. At present many normative regimes, whether at a local or a global level, demand to be legitimately recognised as types of law. But, as many critics observe, an undue overextension of the legal domain may seriously harm the way law functions in social life. In my view, legal theory can signi fi cantly help determine whether or not these regimes, which end up affecting our daily life signi fi cantly, 8 are really suited to play the function that pertains to law. Legal theory has to help determine whether these regimes can really operate as trans-sectional venues where lay subjects can revise, renegotiate, and reframe their social reality; or whether, on the contrary, they are normative repertoires performing self-centred tasks and pursuing private goals, so that it would be meaningless to qualify them as legal.

8 One only has to consider the incidence of certain supra-state sets of rules that regulate speci fi c sectors of reality, such as WTO law, transnational labour law, merchant law, copyright law, or internet law.