7

Click here to load reader

Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Qualitative Inquiry article.

Citation preview

Page 1: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

Qualitative Inquiry18(8) 655 –661© The Author(s) 2012Reprints and permission:sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navDOI: 10.1177/1077800412452856http://qix.sagepub.com

The title of this article is “The Importance of Qualitative Research for Causal Explanation in Education.” It is not “The Importance of Causal Explanation for Qualitative Research in Education.” Much qualitative research provides valuable and trustworthy accounts of educational settings and activities, the contexts in which these are situated, and the meanings that they have for participants, that have noth-ing directly to do with causation. Although I’ll argue that causal explanation is a legitimate and important goal for qualitative research (see Maxwell, 2004a, 2008, 2011a), my main point is a quite different one—that educational research desperately needs qualitative approaches and methods if it is to make valid and useful claims about what works. Although I have focused my argument on educational research, where the dismissal of qualitative research in some quarters has been particularly virulent, this argument applies to the social sciences generally, and in fact, to natural science as well.

This argument draws on a point that I have made else-where (Maxwell, 2004a)—that so-called “scientific research” in education, which assumes that investigations of causation in educational settings must necessarily be quantitative, with randomized controlled trials (RCTs) as the best way to con-duct such investigations,1 is based on a narrow, incomplete, and dated conception of causality. (I address this conception in more detail below.)

But to build my case that qualitative research can make an essential contribution to causal inquiry in education, I need to address the question that motivated this collection

of articles—why many qualitative researchers believe that causation is an inappropriate concept in qualitative research. Despite some notable exceptions (e.g., Coffey & Atkinson, 1996, p. 243; Erickson, 1986, p. 82; Fielding & Fielding, 1986, p. 22; Huberman & Miles, 1985; Schwandt, 1997, p. 14), this rejection of causation has been a widespread and pervasive assumption within the qualitative community; particularly influential statements of this position are those by Lincoln and Guba (1985, p. 141) and Guba and Lincoln (1989, pp. 44, 86). The recently published two-volume Sage Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research (Given, 2008) had no entries for cause or causation, and the only nondismissive mention of causation in the third edition of the Handbook of Qualitative Research (Denzin & Lincoln, 2005a) was in the chapter on qualitative evaluation and social policy (House, 2005), where the issue of causation is almost impossible to avoid. (There are no nondismissive mentions of causation in the fourth edition of the Handbook; Denzin & Lincoln, 2011). The author of one of the finalist dissertations for the qualitative dissertation award given by the Qualitative Research Special Interest Group of the American Educational Research Association in 2011, Brianna Kennedy, confided

452856QIX18810.1177/1077800412452856MaxwellQualitative Inquiry© The Author(s) 2012

Reprints and permission:sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav

1George Mason University, Fairfax, VA, USA

Corresponding Author:Joseph A. Maxwell, PhD, George Mason University, George Mason University 6D2, 4400 University Drive, Fairfax, VA 22030-4444, USA Email: [email protected]

The Importance of Qualitative Research for Causal Explanation in Education

Joseph A. Maxwell1

Abstract

The concept of causation has long been controversial in qualitative research, and many qualitative researchers have rejected causal explanation as incompatible with an interpretivist or constructivist approach. This rejection conflates causation with the positivist theory of causation, and ignores an alternative understanding of causation, variously known as a “generative,” “process,” or “realist” approach, which is influential in philosophy and is becoming widespread in the social sciences and history. This alternative approach to causation is compatible with the practice and “theory-in-use” of many qualitative researchers and enables qualitative researchers to credibly make and support causal claims. It also enables them to defend their work against the dismissal of qualitative methods by proponents of “science-based” research, since the latter assumes a positivist understanding of causation. Adequate causal explanations in the social sciences depend on the in-depth understanding of meanings, contexts, and processes that qualitative research can provide.

Keywords

causation, realism, process, ontology

Special Section on Causality

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 2: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

656 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

to me that she felt that “even uttering the word ‘causal’ in qualitative methodology circles was akin to invoking evil spirits.”

This is particularly puzzling given that most of us accept the concept of causation in our everyday lives. We believe that when our car doesn’t start, a mechanic can discover the cause of this and fix the problem. Most of us also believe that greenhouse gases released by human activity are caus-ing the earth to become warmer, regardless of how many people believe this theory. This acceptance of causation isn’t limited to the physical world; most of us also believe that changing people’s understanding of, and motivation to act on, global warming can cause a reduction in the amount of greenhouse gases we produce. As the philosopher Hilary Putnam has said,

whether causation “really exists” or not, it certainly exists in our “life world.”. . . The world of ordinary language (the world in which we actually live) is full of causes and effects. It is only when we insist that the world of ordinary language . . . is defective . . . and look for a “true” world . . . that we end up feeling forced to choose between the picture of “a physical universe with a built-in structure” and “a physical universe with a structure imposed by the mind.” (1990, p. 89)

So how did we get ourselves into a situation in which we deny in our epistemology and methodology what we accept in our everyday lives? A major reason for—can I say “cause of”?—this rejection of causation by qualitative researchers was the positivist account of causation, which was dominant in philosophy for most of the 20th century and had a power-ful influence on quantitative and experimental research. This account, generally known as the “regularity” or “succession-ist” theory of causation, was derived from David Hume’s analysis of causality (1739/1978), as further developed by J. S. Mill (1843/1988) and Carl Hempel (Hempel & Oppenheim, 1948). It held that we can’t directly perceive causal relationships, only what Hume called the “constant conjunction” of events. Hume denied that we can have any knowledge of causality that goes beyond the observed regu-larities in the association of events and repudiated any refer-ence to unobservable mechanisms. In its current manifestation, it holds that the demonstration of causation is simply a matter of showing that there is a regular, law-like relationship between two variables, so that a change in the first (“indepen-dent”) variable results in a change in the second (“depen-dent”) variable (National Research Council, 2002). This account is the basis for some of the current, most respected quantitative approaches to causal research (e.g., Mulaik, 2009, pp. 63-87; Murnane & Willett, 2010, pp. 26-38).2

Although logical positivism is no longer a viable phi-losophy of science, and the term “positivist” is often used

far too loosely to discredit anyone who is seen as insuffi-ciently “progressive” in their approach to research, the term is in this case an accurate description of this approach. The regularity theory of causation is a genuine living fossil that is consistent with basic logical positivist premises and has survived in virtually unchanged form since the positivist era. This concept of causation fits perfectly with quantita-tive research, which is ideally suited to identifying consis-tent associations between variables, and it is the basis for the claim that quantitative methods are the only way to val-idly establish causal conclusions.

I think that there have been four main reasons that quali-tative researchers rejected the regularity view of causation as valid for qualitative research:

1. They associated it with the positivist commitment to “objective” knowledge of reality, implying that causes could be accurately identified in a theory-neutral way.

2. They saw it as mechanical and deterministic, as ruling out human agency, and as incompatible with an interpretivist understanding of human thought and action.

3. They saw it as denying the importance, not only of the meanings that things had for people, but of the importance of context and the need to take unique circumstances into account in understanding why some event or outcome occurred.

4. Finally, they understood that it dismissed the idea of process, of the possibility of understanding not just whether there was an association between variables, but of how one thing influenced another, a goal that was central to Blumer’s view of sym-bolic interactionism (1956).3

However, in rejecting the regularity understanding of causation, qualitative researchers threw the baby out with the bathwater. For at about the same time that this rejection of causality was gaining force in qualitative research, an alternative concept of causation was being developed, in both philosophy (Bhaskar, 1978, 1989; Salmon, 1984, 1989, 1998) and in social science (Mohr, 1982). This theory, which has variously been termed a “realist,” “generative,” or “process” approach, abandoned the Humean restriction of our understanding of causation to observed regularities and argued for the reality of causal processes. As subse-quently developed in the social sciences and in history, this alternative theory saw causal explanation as fundamentally a matter of identifying the actual processes that resulted in a specific outcome in a particular context (Little, 2010; Pawson & Tilley, 1997; Sayer, 1992; for a more detailed dis-cussion of the relevance of this approach for qualitative research, see Maxwell, 2011a). Little, addressing causation in history, argued that

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 3: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

Maxwell 657

it is very important for historians to arrive at deeper understandings of the metaphysics of social causa-tion. This means, first, understanding the complete inadequacy of the traditional positivist interpretations of causation: “causation is no more than regularity.” This Humean view does not serve the natural sciences well, and it certainly does not help us when it comes to social causation. So it is necessary to explore a dif-ferent model of causation that fits better with what we know about the actual workings of social processes. The model developed above is “causal realism.” (Little, 2010, p. 218)

This theory removes most of the barriers to the accep-tance of causation by qualitative researchers (Maxwell, 2004a, 2004b, 2008, 2011a). First, it identifies process as a necessary and central aspect of causation, a view that is characteristic not only of our everyday understanding of causation but is implicit in the work of many qualitative researchers. It validates not only the idea that causal pro-cesses can in some situations be directly observed (Maxwell, 2004a; Scriven, 2008), but also that they can be established in single cases, without the need for comparison or quantita-tive measurement (Cartwright, 2000; Salmon, 1998, p. 15). Causation is thus fundamentally local rather than general (Cartwright, 1999, 2000, 2007; Huberman & Miles, 1985); causal generalizations are necessarily secondary to particu-lar causal understanding.

Second, it makes context intrinsic to causal explanation. Causal processes always operate within a real context, and this context is inextricably involved in the outcome of that process (Pawson & Tilley, 1997). The causally relevant contexts for understanding some phenomenon include not only the immediate physical and social situation but also broader social and cultural contexts, as argued by Anderson and Scott (2012). These contexts can’t be reduced to a set of “extraneous variables” without misrepresenting the nature of the causal process (Blumer, 1956, 1969).

Third, it extends causal efficacy to beliefs, values, inten-tions, and meanings, not just to physical objects and events (Pawson, 2006, pp. 27-29; Sayer, 1992, pp. 110-112). The view that beliefs and reasons have causal consequences is a position that has repeatedly been defended in philosophy (Davidson, 1980, 1993, 1997; McGinn, 1991; Putnam, 1999; Robb & Heil, 2003) and is generally accepted in both our everyday explanation of people’s behavior and in psy-chology as a science. However, the sharp separation of “meaning” and “cause” explanations by Dilthey (discussed by Donmoyer in his article in this issue), Weber, Winch, and others has been far more influential in qualitative research.4

From the realist perspective presented here, meanings and beliefs are part of the causal processes that operate in human individuals and communities, and any attempt to explain what happens in human groups that ignores the

meanings and intentions of the members of these groups is seriously deficient and unlikely to be productive (Menzel, 1978). The fundamental premise of symbolic interaction-ism “is that people act in accordance with their definitions of situations, so that explanations are dependent on under-standing those definitions” (Hewitt, 1984, p. 269, cited by Goldenberg, 1992, p. 524)

Finally, an ontology that accepts the reality of causation is quite compatible with a constructivist epistemology that holds that our understanding of the world, including our understanding of causation and causal relationships, is neces-sarily our own creation, incomplete and fallible, rather than an “objective” perception of reality (Bhaskar, 1989, p. 185; Campbell, 1988, p. 447; Keller, 1992, pp. 73-74; Lakoff, 1987, p. 265; for a detailed justification of this claim, see Maxwell, 2011a).5

From this perspective, I disagree with Donmoyer’s view (2012) that causality is a “convenient fiction.” The idea that theories about the world are “convenient fictions” is another vestigial holdover from logical positivism. Positivists argued that theoretical terms and concepts were simply logical con-structions based on, and defined by, observational data, “fic-tions” that were useful in making predictions but which had no claim to any “reality” (Norris, 1983; Phillips, 1987, p. 40). This view, generally termed “instrumentalism,” was (and remains) influential in psychology and the social sciences long after it was abandoned in philosophy (Salmon, 1984, pp. 5-7).

Seeing our understanding of causation as a construction does not make it “fictional,” for at least two reasons. First, as a construction, causation points to and captures (although not “reflects”; see Keller, 1992, pp. 73-74) something about real-ity, an aspect of reality that can resist or fail to accommodate to our constructions of it (Blumer, 1969). Second, as a con-cept held by real human beings, this construction is itself real: It influences our actions (e.g., a realist concept of causation played a major causal role in my writing this article).

Accepting the legitimacy of causation in qualitative research does not put us on a slippery slope leading back to positivism or foundationalism. A realist process theory of causation constitutes a rejection of the basic premises of the positivist understanding of causation as well as being incompatible with other aspects of positivism (Maxwell, 2011a, pp. 8-9; Schwandt, 1997, pp. 133-134). The linking of ontological realism and epistemological constructivism that I advocate here is also explicitly antifoundationalist in rejecting any fundamental beliefs or assumptions about reality other than that it exists. Reality is more complex than any belief or theory can fully capture; multiple valid under-standings of any phenomenon are possible (see Maxwell, 2011b), and all beliefs and assumptions are tentative and subject to revision.

This view of causation is compatible with, and in fact supports, the actual methods and interpretive concepts and

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 4: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

658 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

approaches used by many qualitative researchers—what Argyris and Schoen (1992) called the “theory-in-use” of these researchers. It is even explicit in the work of some qualitative researchers; for example, Weiss (1994) argued,

In quantitative interview studies the demonstration of causation rests heavily on the description of a visual-izable sequence of events, each event flowing into the next. . . . Quantitative studies support an assertion of causation by showing a correlation between an earlier event and a subsequent event. An analysis of data collected in a large-scale sample survey might, for example, show that there is a correlation between the level of the wife’s education and the presence of a companionable marriage. In qualitative studies we would look for a process through which the wife’s education or factors associated with her education express themselves in marital interaction. (p. 179)

However, it is not compatible with the espoused theory of some qualitative researchers—a radical constructivist or relativist ontology that denies the reality of causation. What I am arguing is there are good reasons to question this espoused theory, and to try to better understand the theory-in-use that we employ in our work.

This view of causation is also essential to any approach to causation that can be of real use to social and educa-tional researchers. This is most clearly illustrated by mixed-method studies that combined qualitative and quan-titative approaches in ways that respected the value of both approaches and supported a dialog between the two. Good examples of this can be found in the collection of mixed-method studies edited by the ethnographer Tom Weisner, with the title Discovering Successful Pathways in Children’s Development (Weisner, 2005). In these studies, the insights gained by the qualitative researchers were essential to the causal conclusions that emerged from the study, and in one study they not only refocused the quantitative data collection on the outcomes that emerged from the qualitative work, but “led us to develop an overall conceptual framework for thinking about the mechanisms through which changes in outcomes due to moves out of high-poverty areas might occur” (Kling, Liebman, & Katz, 2005, p. 244).

I also believe that incorporating causal inference in qual-itative research supports, rather than undermines, social jus-tice agendas for our work. A particularly good example of this is Dixiane Hallaj’s recent award-winning dissertation Caught by Culture and Conflict: Palestinian Refugee Women’s Perceptions of Illiteracy and Education (2006), which grew out of her work to establish family literacy cen-ters within the refugee camps in the West Bank. Hallaj explicitly identified cultural, environmental, and political causes of these women’s illiteracy and the ways in which

these causes interact, and described ways in which these causes might be alleviated.

A second example is a recent book by Stuart Buck, Acting White: The Ironic Legacy of Desegregation (2011), in which he argued that the perception that academically successful Black students are “acting white” is a real phe-nomenon that causes serious problems in school for Black students, and is itself an unintended consequence of the way desegregation was implemented. It seems to me that if you want to work against injustice and oppression, you need to understand the causes of the particular forms of injustice and oppression you are dealing with, and how to counteract and overcome these causes.

In conclusion, I am making two claims. First, I am argu-ing that qualitative researchers can draw and support causal conclusions—that this is not an inappropriate aspiration. We are able to do this by focusing on the causal processes, mental as well as physical, that result in particular out-comes, rather than by simply demonstrating that a relation-ship exists between particular variables. Not all qualitative researchers aspire to draw such conclusions, and that is legitimate, but there are no good philosophical or method-ological prohibitions against our doing this.

I am not just arguing that we can do this, but that we’re good at it. We have the methods that allow us to both develop and test causal explanations in education. However, we could be better at it. Drawing causal conclusions is challenging even in the best of conditions, and attempting to generalize such conclusions is even more difficult. If we want to credibly make such claims to a wider audience, we need to be system-atic and rigorous in providing evidence that supports these claims and that addresses potential validity threats to these claims; I provide elsewhere a detailed discussion of methods that qualitative researchers can use for this (Maxwell, 2004b, 2011a). However, in doing this, we also need to challenge the positivist assumptions that typically inform “evidence-based” approaches to research (Maxwell, 2009).

Second, I am arguing that educational research, and social research generally, requires such qualitative approaches if it is to credibly identify the actual causes that influence a par-ticular outcome, let alone to make claims about the broader efficacy of any intervention. Pawson (2006) argued,

The nature of causality in social programmes is such that any synthesis of evidence on whether they work will need to investigate how they work. This requires unearth-ing information on mechanisms, contexts, and outcomes. The central quest is to understand the conditions of programme efficacy and this will involve the synthesis in investigating for whom, in what circumstances, and in what respects a family of programmes work. (p. 25)

The idea that randomized experiments or structural equation models can provide valid general conclusions

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 5: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

Maxwell 659

about the effect of an intervention, in the absence of any understanding of the actual causal processes that were operat-ing, the specific contexts in which these processes were situ-ated, or the meaning that the intervention and contexts had for participants, is an illusion. We need qualitative methods and approaches in order to understand “what works” and why.

Declaration of Conflicting Interests

The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Funding

The author(s) received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Notes

1. For a particularly scathing critique of the idea that RCTs (ran-domized controlled trials) are the “gold standard” for causal inference, see Scriven (2008).

2. One statistician who was not committed to the regularity the-ory, and who sought to understand causal processes in particu-lar cases, was David Freedman (2010). The philosopher Nancy Cartwright, whose work (e.g., 2007) represents some of the best thinking about using quantitative methods in causal research, has provided a detailed argument for what she called “causal pluralism,” the view that what causes are and what they do var-ies from case to case. She stated that current approaches “are not alternative, incompatible views about causation; they are rather views that fit different kinds of causal systems” and that “there is no single interesting characterizing feature of causa-tion; hence no off-the-shelf or one-size-fits-all method for finding out about it, no ‘gold standard’ for judging causal rela-tions” (2007, p. 2).

3. The National Research Council Report Scientific Research in Education (2002) acknowledged the value of understanding mechanisms, but made this subordinate to, and dependent on, the quantitative demonstration of a causal relationship between variables, and claimed that even the understanding of mecha-nisms was necessarily a primarily quantitative activity (see Maxwell, 2004a).

4. For example, Howe (2011) has recently presented a different analysis of causality in qualitative research from the one pro-posed here, accepting the validity of this concept, but arguing that causation of intentional phenomena (I-causation) is different in kind from that of natural phenomena (N-causation). Although I endorse his recognition of causation in human interactions, and his position that qualitative and quantitative methods can both be used for intentional and physical phenomena, I think that his analysis in terms of two kinds of phenomena still leaves as mys-terious the interaction between the two, an interaction that is intrinsic to our everyday understanding of causation.In addition, Howe still seems to implicitly rely on a regularity understanding of causality, for both natural and intentional

phenomena. Thus, he describes both types of causation as “establishing and accounting for ordered patterns of human behavior” (p. 166; emphasis added). Although Howe acknowl-edges that for N-causation there is a realist/process alternative to the regularity view, he makes no mention of this in his dis-cussion of intentional causation, and never addresses the pos-sibility of causal explanations of singular events, as opposed to regularities.

5. Smith (2008; Smith & Deemer, 2000) argued that the con-straints of a constructivist epistemology make it impossible for a realist ontology to have any practical value. (This is one manifes-tation of what has been called the “ontological-epistemological collapse,” which sees ontology as simply a reflection of episte-mology, for example, Denzin & Lincoln, 2005b, p. 203.) I have argued elsewhere (Maxwell, 2008, 2011a; Maxwell & Mittapalli, 2010) that this is simply false, and that a realist ontology has important implications for research that are not incompatible with a constructivist epistemology.

References

Anderson, G. L. & Scott, J. (2012). Toward an Intersectional Understanding of Process Causality and Social Context. Qual-itative Inquiry, 18, 674-685.

Argyris, C., & Schoen, D. (1992). Theory in practice: Increasing professional effectiveness. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science (2nd ed.). Brighton, UK: Harvester.

Bhaskar, R. (1989). Reclaiming reality: A critical introduction to contemporary philosophy. London: Verso.

Blumer, H. (1956). Sociological analysis and the “variable.” American Sociological Review, 22, 683-690. Reprinted in H. Blumer, Symbolic interactionism: Perspective and method (pp. 127-139). Berkeley: University of California Press.

Blumer, H. (1969). The methodological position of symbolic interactionism. In H. Blumer, Symbolic interactionism: Per-spective and method (pp. 1-60). Berkeley: University of Cali-fornia Press.

Buck, S. (2011). Acting white: The ironic legacy of desegregation. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Campbell, D. T. (1988). Methodology and epistemology for social science: Selected papers (S. Overman, Ed.). Chicago, IL: Uni-versity of Chicago Press.

Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundar-ies of science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Cartwright, N. (2000). An empiricist defence of singular causes. In R. Teichmann (Ed.), Logic, cause, and action: Essays in honour of Elizabeth Anscombe (pp. 47-58). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them. Cam-bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press

Davidson, D. (1993). Thinking causes. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 3-17). Oxford, UK: Clarendon.

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 6: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

660 Qualitative Inquiry 18(8)

Davidson, D. (1997). Indeterminism and antirealism. In C. B. Kulp (Ed.), Realism/antirealism and epistemology (pp. 109-122). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2005a). Handbook of qualitative research (3rd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (2005b). Paradigmatic controver-sies, contradictions, and emerging confluences. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (3rd ed., pp. 191-216). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2011). Handbook of quali-tative research (4th ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Donmoyer, R. (2012). Can Qualitative Researchers Answer Poli-cymakers’ What-Works Question? Qualitative Inquiry, 18(8), 662-673.

Erickson, F. (1986). Qualitative methods. In M. Wittrock (Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching (pp. 119-161). New York, NY: Macmillan.

Fielding, N. G., & Fielding, J. L. (1986). Linking data. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Freedman, D. (2010). Statistical models and causal inference: A dialogue with the social sciences (D. Collier, J. S. Sekhon, & P. B. Stark, Ed.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Given, L. (Ed.). (2008). The SAGE encyclopedia of qualitative research methods. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Goldenberg, C. (1992). The limits of expectations: A case for case knowledge of teacher expectancy effects. American Educa-tional Research Journal, 29(3), 517-544.

Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1989). Fourth generation evalua-tion. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.

Hallaj, D. (2006). Caught by culture and conflict: Palestinian refugee women’s perceptions of illiteracy and education. PhD dissertation, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA.

Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135-175.

Hewitt, J. (1984). Self and society: A symbolic interactionist social psychology (3rd ed.). Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.

House, E. (2005). Qualitative evaluation and changing social policy. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (3rd ed., pp. 1069-1088). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Howe, K. R. (2011). Mixed methods, mixed causes? Qualitative Inquiry, 17, 166-171.

Huberman, A. M., & Miles, M. B. (1985). Assessing local causal-ity in qualitative research. In D. N. Berg & K. K. Smith (Eds.), Exploring clinical methods for social research (pp. 351-382). Beverly Hills, CA: SAGE.

Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature (Edited, with an analytical index, by L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2nd ed.) Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1739)

Keller, E. F. (1992). Secrets of life, secrets of death: Essays on language, gender, and science. New York, NY: Routledge.

Kling, J. R., Liebman, J. B., & Katz, L. F. (2005). “Bullets don’t got no name”: Consequences of fear in the ghetto. In T. Weisner (Ed.), Discovering successful pathways in children’s develop-ment (pp. 243-282). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What cat-egories reveal about the mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Lincoln, Y. S., & Guba, E. G. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.

Little, D. (2010). New contributions to the philosophy of history. New York, NY: Springer.

Maxwell, J. A. (2004a). Causal explanation, qualitative research, and scientific inquiry in education. Educational Researcher, 33(2), 3-11.

Maxwell, J. (2004b). Using qualitative methods for causal expla-nation. Field Methods, 16, 243-264.

Maxwell, J. A. (2008). The value of a realist understanding of cau-sality for qualitative research. In N. Denzin (Ed.), Qualitative research and the politics of evidence (pp. 163-181). Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.

Maxwell, J. A. (2009). Evidence: A critical realist perspective for qualitative research. In N. K. Denzin & M. D. Giardina (Eds.), Qualitative inquiry and social justice (pp. 108-122). Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.

Maxwell, J. A. (2011a). A realist approach for qualitative research. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Maxwell, J. A. (2011b). Paradigms or toolkits? Philosophical and methodological positions as heuristics for mixed meth-ods research. Mid-Western Educational Researcher, 24(2), 27-30.

Maxwell, J. A., & Mittapalli, K. (2010). Realism as a stance for mixed method research. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral research (2nd ed., pp. 145-167). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

McGinn, C. (1991). Conceptual causation: Some elementary reflections. Mind, 100(4), 573-586. Reprinted in C. McGinn (1999), Knowledge and reality: Selected essays (pp. 152-167). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Pres.

Menzel, H. (1978). Meaning—who needs it? In M. Brenner, P. Marsh, & M. Brenner (Eds.), The social contexts of method (pp. 140-171). New York, NY: St. Martin’s.

Mill, J. S. (1988), A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive (8th ed.). New York, NY: Harper and Brothers. (Original work published 1843)

Mohr, L. B. (1982). Explaining organizational behavior. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

Mulaik, S. (2009). Linear causal modeling with structural equa-tions. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC Press.

Murnane, R. J., & Willett, J. B. (2010). Methods matter: Improving causal inference in educational and social science research. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

National Research Council. (2002). Scientific research in educa-tion. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

Norris, S. P. (1983). The inconsistencies at the foundation of con-struct validation theory. In E. R. House (Ed.), Philosophy of evaluation. New directions for program evaluation (Vol. 19, pp. 53-74). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

Pawson, R. (2006). Evidence-based policy: A realist perspective. London: SAGE.

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 7: Qualitative Inquiry 2012 Maxwell 655 61

Maxwell 661

Pawson, R., & Tilley, N. (1997). Realistic evaluation. London: SAGE.

Phillips, D. C. (1987). Validity in qualitative research: Why the worry about warrant will not wane. Education and Urban Society, 20, 9-24.

Putnam, H. (1990). Realism with a human face (Ed. J. Conant). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, body, and world. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

Robb, D., & Heil, J. (2003). Mental causation. Stanford Encyclo-pedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-causation/

Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 3-219). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Sayer, A. (1992). Method in social science: A realist approach (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

Schwandt, T. A. (1997). Qualitative inquiry: A dictionary of terms. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Scriven, M. (2008). A summative evaluation of RCT methodol-ogy: An alternative approach to causal research. Journal of Multidisciplinary Evaluation, 5(9), 11-24.

Smith, J. K. (2008). Relativism. In L. Given (Ed.), The SAGE encyclopedia of qualitative research methods (pp. 749-753). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Smith, J. K., & Deemer, D. K. (2000). The problem of criteria in the age of relativism. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research (2nd ed., pp. 877-896). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

Weisner, T. S. (Ed.). (2005). Discovering successful pathways in children’s development: Mixed methods in the study of childhood and family life. Chicago, IL: University of Chi-cago Press.

Weiss, R. S. (1994). Learning from strangers: The art and method of qualitative interviewing. New York, NY: Free Press.

Bio

Joseph A. Maxwell is a professor in the College of Education and Human Development at George Mason University, where he teaches courses on qualitative and mixed-method research design and methods. He is the author of Qualitative Research Design: An Interactive Approach (2nd ed., 2005) and A Realist Approach for Qualitative Research (2011). His research and writing include work on research methodology and philosophy, program evaluation, sociocultural theory, Native American societies, and medical education; see http://cehd.gmu.edu/ people/faculty/jmaxwell/. He has a PhD in anthropology from the University of Chicago.

at OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY on March 24, 2015qix.sagepub.comDownloaded from