More-Evans Off Target

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Aristotle's epistemology Commentary ancient philosophy

Citation preview

  • Scots Philosophical AssociationUniversity of St. Andrews

    Evans Off TargetAuthor(s): F. C. T. MooreSource: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 25, No. 98 (Jan., 1975), pp. 58-59Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Scots Philosophical Association and theUniversity of St. AndrewsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2217952 .Accessed: 22/01/2015 09:52

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Oxford University Press, Scots Philosophical Association, University of St. Andrews are collaborating withJSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Quarterly.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:52:27 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • 58

    DISCUSSIONS

    EVANS OFF TARGET

    BY F. C. T. MOORE

    In his recent paper "Aristotle on Relativism", PQ 24 (1974), 193-203, Mr J. D. G. Evans reminds us of the Aristotelian puzzle (Nicomachean Ethics r 4) about whether the object of wishing (of Pou'5X) lS, the faculty concerned with the ultimate grounds for action) is the good (in which case a person who chooses wrongly does not wish what he wishes), or what appears good to each person (in which case, on Evans's account of Aristotle, there would be no way of evaluating different wishes). Aristotle's solution is that in the case of the good man the object of his wish (that which appears good to him) is the same as the unqualified object of wish (that which is good), whereas in other cases these two do not coincide.

    Evans illustrates his comments on Aristotle's solution by the analogy of shooting at targets. To avoid the paradoxes by which unsuccessful shooting would be proved not to be shooting at all (since all shooting is necessarily directed at the target), and all shooting would be proved successful (since all shooting is necessarily directed at its target), Evans claims that we should distinguish for any shot its target (the "qualified target") from the target (the "unqualified target"): only in some cases (namely, cases of successful shooting) do these coincide. But this treatment of unsuccessful shooting is not only implausible, as Evans concedes (p. 201): it is absurd. For an un- successful shot is precisely not one which hits a target (even a "qualified target").

    The distinction between qualified and unqualified targets is not itself absurd: it is the distinction between what a person is aiming at, and what he is to aim at-between what he takes to be the target, and what really is the target. But it is entirely separate from the distinction between success- ful and unsuccessful shots: a successful shot is one that hits the (qualified or unqualified) target, and an unsuccessful shot is one that does not. Mistak- ing the target does not make a man a worse shot, and if he hits what he aims at, he is not unsuccessful in shooting, but unsuccessful in identifying the target.

    In the case of wishing (the Aristotelian pou6X6]7l), the parallels would be as follows: the unqualified target would correspond to the unqualified good (that which is determined as good in some way independently of a particular wisher), and the qualified target to the qualified good (that which is determined as good simply by being the object of a particular man's wish) -while wishes would be "successful" and "unsuccessful" according as the man attained the good or not, or attained his object or not.

    Evans assimilates the (plausible) claim that there is a distinction be- tween successful and unsuccessful wishing which should be preserved by any account of wishing, to the question-begging claim that there is an independent criterion by which a person's ultimate goals (the objects of his wishing) could be judged correct or incorrect (and by which he could there-

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:52:27 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • EVANS OFF TARGET 59

    fore be considered successful or otherwise in his po6X7mcqL); this simply begs the question in favour of the realist.

    We need not quarrel with Evans's claim that Aristotle's own solution to his puzzle is realist, but Aristotle does not beg the question in the way Evans would make him. For Aristotle, the paradox of the relativist position is not that it would preserve no distinction between successful and un- successful wishing, but that by it the good would not be the natural object of desire, but only the apparent good in each case would be the natural object of desire, so that contrary goals could both be the natural object of desire. Aristotle's notion of a natural object of desire (p6asL 3ouX7y6v) may itself be held to be question-begging, but that is another question.

    University of Birmingham

    ALMEDER ON TRUTH AND EVIDENCE

    BY WILLIAM E. HOFFMANN

    In his recent paper "Truth and Evidence", Robert Almeder attacks an assumption that is central to the discussions of the classical definition of knowledge that have been precipitated by the Gettier counter-examples.' This is the assumption that evidence sufficient for knowledge does not entail truth. Almeder correctly argues that this assumption is essential to every analysis of knowledge which begins by accepting counter-examples such as Gettier's, and then argues that this assumption is false. I shall argue that this assumption is true, that Almeder's arguments attacking it are mistaken, and that the rejection of this assumption leads to highly counter-intuitive results.

    To see that the rejection of the assumption that evidence sufficient for knowledge does not entail truth leads to counter-intuitive results, imagine the following two cases. The first case finds Jones sitting in the lobby of the hotel where he resides and focusing his attention on a point a few feet in front of him on the floor. For no particular reason, Jones begins to wonder if the floor at that point will support him, as it has so many times before, or if he will go crashing through the floor if he walks across that point. Having nothing better to do, Jones attempts to answer his query by watching people, many of whom are obviously heavier than he, tread across this point. After several hours without seeing a plank bow or hearing one creak despite heavy traffic, Jones walks over to the point, cautiously tests it by tapping his foot, then confidently walks across it. The second case is exactly like the first in every relevant detail except that it occurs at a different place and time, our man is named Smith, and that when Smith begins to walk across the observed point, owing to some freak accident, the floor caves in. Engineers later attempting to find the cause of the accident are unable to explain the structural failure.

    Putting aside the difficulty of defining knowledge, in the first case Jones clearly knew that the floor would support him; that is, Jones had knowledge

    1The Philosophical Quarterly, 24 (October 1974), 365-8. See also Edmund L. Gettier, "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?", Analysis, 23 (1963).

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Thu, 22 Jan 2015 09:52:27 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    Article Contentsp.58p.59

    Issue Table of ContentsThe Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 25, No. 98 (Jan., 1975), pp. 1-96Front MatterThe Ideas of Power and Substance in Locke's Philosophy [pp.1-27]The Case for Scepticism [pp.28-39]Transcendental Arguments and Moral Principles [pp.40-57]DiscussionsEvans Off Target [pp.58-59]Almeder on Truth and Evidence [pp.59-61]

    Critical StudiesWittgenstein and Ogden [pp.62-68]Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle [pp.68-79]

    Book Reviewsuntitled [pp.80-81]untitled [pp.81-82]untitled [pp.83-84]untitled [pp.84-85]untitled [pp.85-87]untitled [pp.87-89]untitled [pp.89-91]untitled [pp.91-93]untitled [pp.93-94]

    Books Received [pp.95-96]Erratum: The Definition of Prime Facie DutiesBack Matter