Mindscapes and Landscapes: Hayek and Simon on Cognitive Extension

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Hayek’s and Simon’s social externalism runs on a shared presupposition: mind is constrained in its computational capacity to detect, harvest, and assimilate “data” generated by the infinitely fine-grained and perpetually dynamic characteristic of experience in complex social environments. For Hayek, mind and sociality are co-evolved spontaneous orders, allowing little or no prospect of comprehensive explanation, trapped in a hermeneutically sealed, i.e. inescapably context bound, eco-system. For Simon, it is the simplicity of mind that is the bottleneck, overwhelmed by the ambient complexity of the environmental. Since on Simon’s account complexity is unidirectional, Simon is far more ebullient about the prospects of explanation. Hayek’s social externalism functions as a kind of distributed “extra-neural” memory store manifest as dynamic spontaneous orders. Simon’s organizational rule-governed externalism negotiates the “inner” world (the mind) with the “outer” world through a homeostatic interface that offloads the cognitive burden into the environment. Their respective externalisms may differ in detail but not in spirit in that it ameliorates their shared presupposition of cognitive constraint. Even though any “optimization talk” for Hayek and Simon is objectionable, knowledge acquisition can be represented by a contextualized stigmergic swarm optimization algorithm that gives due emphasis to both the individual and the environment. The key insight is that “perfect” knowledge is unnecessary, impracticable and indeed irrelevant if one understands the mechanism at work in complex sociality, a stigmergic sociality that in effect augments or scaffolds cognition.

Citation preview

  • 1 DRAFT: DO NOT CITE

    Mindscapes and Landscapes: Hayek and Simon on Cognitive Extension

    Leslie Marsh Deans Office, Medical School, University of British Columbia

    In Hayek and Behavioural Economics, Palgrave Macmillan, Eds., Roger Frantz and

    Robert Leeson. http://www.palgrave.com/products/title.aspx?pid=509789

    Abstract: Hayeks and Simons social externalism runs on a shared presupposition: mind is constrained in its computational capacity to detect, harvest, and assimilate data generated by the infinitely fine-grained and perpetually dynamic characteristic of experience in complex social environments. For Hayek, mind and sociality are co-evolved spontaneous orders, allowing little or no prospect of comprehensive explanation, trapped in a hermeneutically sealed, i.e. inescapably context bound, eco-system. For Simon, it is the simplicity of mind that is the bottleneck, overwhelmed by the ambient complexity of the environmental. Since on Simons account complexity is unidirectional, Simon is far more ebullient about the prospects of explanation. Hayeks social externalism functions as a kind of distributed extra-neural memory store manifest as dynamic spontaneous orders. Simons organizational rule-governed externalism negotiates the inner world (the mind) with the outer world through a homeostatic interface that offloads the cognitive burden into the environment. Their respective externalisms may differ in detail but not in spirit in that it ameliorates their shared presupposition of cognitive constraint. Even though any optimization talk for Hayek and Simon is objectionable, knowledge acquisition can be represented by a contextualized stigmergic swarm optimization algorithm that gives due emphasis to both the individual and the environment. The key insight is that perfect knowledge is unnecessary, impracticable and indeed irrelevant if one understands the mechanism at work in complex sociality, a stigmergic sociality that in effect augments or scaffolds cognition. Keywords: Friedrich Hayek, Herbert Simon, cognitive closure, bounded rationality, complexity, extended mind, particle swarm optimization, stigmergy.

    I: A Shared Presupposition

    Is complexity primarily an epistemological or an ontological phenomenon? Is there even

    any coherence at all in suggesting the latter ontological variety? Two of the twentieth

    centurys greatest minds did approach this philosophical chestnut Friedrich von Hayek

    and Herbert Simon.1 Hayek and Simon share a key philosophical presupposition: that is,

    mind is constrained in its computational capacity to detect, harvest, and assimilate

    (crunch or process) data data generated by the infinitely fine-grained and perpetually

    dynamic characteristic of experience in complex social environments.2 To ameliorate this

    state of affairs, Hayek and Simon proffer an adaptive externalist theory of mind to spread

  • 2 the cognitive burden. For Hayek the social and artifactual world functions as a kind of

    distributed extra-neural memory store manifest as dynamic traditions, custom and

    practice the sine qua non of acting, thinking, and communicating. For Simon, the

    inner world (i.e. the mind) has a homeostatic interface (a system that regulates its

    internal environment towards equilibrium), with the outer world modulated through the

    artifactual environment, most notably social institutions that give conceptual outline to

    thought and determine action. Both Hayek and Simon rejected the pernicious fiction of

    the unvarnished Cartesian reasoner manifest in the derivative guises of, on the one hand,

    central planning-type rationalism, and on the other hand, homo economicus so favored by

    orthodox economics.

    Complexity is the touchstone for both Hayek and Simon. For Hayek, mind and

    sociality are classic instantiations of mutually reinforcing spontaneous orders. Simon, by

    contrast, takes the view that it is the environment in which complexity abides and not in

    the mind. There are problems with both Hayeks and Simons positions. With Hayek one

    cannot be sure if hes making an epistemological claim or a metaphysical claim. With

    Simon how does one account for the unidirectional account of complexity? That is, if one

    accepts the presupposition of mind being highly adaptive and plastic (as he does) in

    negotiating an ambient complex environmental soup, why then would mind not reflect

    this external complexity? Part of the problem in approaching both Hayek and Simon lies

    in giving some specification to this thing called complexity, a term subject to much

    obfuscation even before it is layered with the agnoseology or the theory of

    unknowability literature (Rescher, 2009, p. ix) that Hayek and Simon partake in.

  • 3 Hayek and Simon are, to use the current argot, well recognized as situated

    theorists and it is from this perspective that they are so fertilely examined. Both sought

    to overcome the notion of abstract Cartesianism on the one hand, and an inflated social

    ontology on the other hand, that paid scant regard to the individual mind. Consider these

    two similar constructivist slogans3:

    Insofar as behavior is a function of learned technique rather than innate characteristics of the human information-processing system, our knowledge of behavior must be regarded as sociological in nature rather than psychological . . . (Simon, 1996, pp. 54, 62, 76). It is probably no more justified to claim that thinking man has created his culture than that culture created his reason (Hayek, 1952/1979, p. 155).

    It is this situated perspective that motivates their social externalism. Broadly speaking,

    externalism is the thesis that an individuals environment has some causal determinant on

    the content of the individual mind. It is social in the sense used here that Hayek and

    Simon are primarily concerned with social institutions. By contrast, Cartesian

    individualism (or internalism) is internal in the sense that knowledge relies solely upon,

    or is fashioned by, the operation of the cognizers mental states without any appeal to

    external considerations. Simon got a boost from David Chalmers and Andy Clarks

    seminal paper The Extended Mind (Chalmers & Clark, 1998) in which they

    acknowledge Herbert Simon as providing some inspiration for their extended mind thesis,

    a species of externalism. Positing the notion of the extended mind forces one to take

    seriously the idea that cognition has an embodied, social, and artifactual dimension;

    indeed, mind exists at the intersection of this trinity.4 Simon in turn credited and endorsed

    Hayek for providing the key philosophical presupposition that underwrites cognitive

    extension (Simon, 1996, p. 34). Hayeks work in the philosophy of mind is now

  • 4 garnering much attention (Feser, 2006; Butos & Koppl, 2007; Butos, 2010; Marsh, 2010;

    Marsh, in press); Simon is of course a grandee within cognitive science circles.

    The discussion unfolds as follows. Section II outlines some of the general issues in

    conceptualizing complexity. Section III examines the cognitive dimension to knowledge

    acquisition referred to variously as the agnoseology or the theory of unknowability

    literature. Sections IV and V explicate Hayeks notion of cognitive closure and

    Simons notion of bounded rationality respectively. The penultimate section recasts

    both Hayek and Simon as proffering a stigmergic variant of cognitive extension. The

    final section offers some concluding thoughts.

    II: Complexity: Some Basic Distinctions

    Whether or not one takes complexity as an epistemological or an ontological thesis,

    complexity-talk is inextricably a cognitive phenomenon: complexity refers to some

    observing system (Biggiero, 2001). Or as Rescher puts it: [C]omplexity . . . pertains in

    the first instance to cognitive artifacts . . . (Rescher, 1998, p. 16).5 Mind and complexity

    are, Janus-like, inextricably linked: to be sure, Hayek and Simon understood this better

    than most. This said, the immediate task at hand is to try and get a handle on the highly

    slippery concept that is complexity.

    As Nicholas Rescher (1998, p. 8) says: There is no agreed upon definition of

    complexity any more than there is one of chair despite the fact that these days

    complexity is all the rage within the academy and the popular imagination. Herein lies

  • 5 the danger: to invoke the concept without much conceptual discrimination empties any

    concept of meaning. Hayek, for one, in Bruce Caldwells words, [b]y the 1960s Hayek

    was seeing complex orders everywhere (Caldwell, 2000, p. 19). Simons definition of

    complexity (Simon, 1962; cf. Rescher, 1998, p. 22, note 14) is woefully inadequate:

    There are some properties common to many complex systems. Complex Systems are those that are made up of a large number of parts that interact in a non-simple way. Given the properties of the parts and the laws of their interaction, it is not a trivial matter to infer the properties of the whole.

    Complexity studies is a veritable smorgasbord of overlapping disciplines and research

    projects for a birds eye view see the diagram below.

  • 6

    Figure 1: Made available courtesy of Hiroki Sayama, Collective Dynamics of Complex Systems Research Group, Binghamton University, State University of New York.

    This diagram sets out in a comprehensive and clear way the various projects and sub-

    fields that comprises complex systems studies. The particular conglomeration that this

    paper is concerned with is collective behavior, specifically particle swarm

    optimization/stigmergy more on this in section VI. In clearing some distinctive

    conceptual space one must test a given concept for:

  • 7 (a) logical independence

    (b) extensional and intensional adequacy

    (c) functionality.

    (a) Logical independence merely means that a given concept shouldnt be analyzable in

    terms that presuppose that very concept. As Neil Johnson (2009, p. 3) rightly says:

    Take a look in many dictionaries, and you will find Complexity defined along the lines of The behavior shown by a Complex System. Then look up Complex System, and you will probably see A system whose behavior exhibits Complexity.

    An example of this can be found in Knauff and Wolf (2010, p. 100) in their introduction

    to a Special Issue on Complex Cognition:

    The crucial characteristic of complex cognition is that it takes place under complex conditions in which a multitude of cognitive processes interact with one another or with other noncognitive processes.

    (b) Extensional and intensional adequacy is philosophical jargon for the idea that a

    concept, say complexity, should enable one to pick out and identify all and only the

    things to which the concept applies.

    (c) The functional adequacy of a given concept cuts across (a) and (b) and asks why

    would we need a given concept what work or role would a given concept have to

    fulfill? (In addition to epistemic and ontological modes of complexity, Rescher

    offers a third mode functional complexity (Rescher, 1998, p. 9)).

    By way of a first pass, Melanie Mitchell (2009, pp. 12-13) suggests that there are three

    properties common to all instantiations of complexity:

  • 8 1. Complex collective behavior i.e. emergent phenomena not reducible to

    individual components

    2. Signaling and information processing there is informational flow within and

    between systems

    3. Adaptation there is an inherent dynamicism manifest as learning or evolutionary

    processes.

    Though 1-3 are perfectly sound typical features can they be viewed as jointly and

    severally characterizing complex systems? If items 1-3 define complex systems then its

    puzzling as to why Mitchell later acknowledges that a single definition of- and

    measurement of- complexity is not forthcoming even at complexitys Mecca, the Santa

    Fe Institute (Mitchell, 2009, pp. 94-95, 301). Specifying necessary and sufficient features

    is bound to defeat most attempts at defining open concepts: Mitchell concedes as much

    (Mitchell, 2009, p. 297). Complex systems are at best a family resemblance concept with

    no single property in common (Wittgenstein, 1953, I.66). This would be the approach to

    counter the philosophically illiterate criticism heaped by science journalist John Horgan

    upon the cogency of the very concept of complexity science as reported by Mitchell

    (2009, pp. 291-292, 299).

    It might be argued that the common denominator and therefore the defining

    feature of complexity is emergence. But again things are not that straightforward. As

    David Chalmers points out, there needs to be a more adequate analysis of the concept of

    emergence (Chalmers, 2006). Chalmers distinguishes between strong emergence and

    weak emergence. The former is the idea that the high-level phenomenon arises from the

    low-level domain, but truths concerning that phenomenon are not deducible even in

  • 9 principle from truths in the low-level domain. The latter is the idea that the high-level

    phenomenon arises from the low-level domain, but truths concerning that phenomenon

    are unexpected given the principles governing the low-level domain. This distinction does

    not seem to be made within the literature: emergence is taken as an undifferentiated

    conflation of weak and strong variants even though novel features might well be a

    function of theoretical impoverishment.6 The greater complexity of social phenomena

    (filled with meaning and significance) renders controlled experimentation

    impracticable and lessens the precision of the social sciences (or so it is usually conceded

    by Hayek and Popper).

    III: Taking Ignorance Seriously

    As already indicated the other component to thinking about complexity resides in the

    realm of epistemology. Epistemology in the Plato-Descartes tradition, besides being

    highly individualistic, i.e. individualistic (or internal) in the sense that knowledge relies

    solely upon the operation of mental states without any appeal to external considerations

    is primarily concerned with justification. It therefore has a distinctly positive concern.

    Ignorance, for want of a better term, by contrast does not play a leading role in

    epistemology.

    The sort of ignorance we are concerned with here is inevitable ignorance

    (Rescher, 2009, p. 2) the idea marking what we cannot know as opposed to culpable

    ignorance what we dont know or what we should know but dont, or as others term it

    deliberate or inadvertent neglect, secrecy or suppression, unquestioned tradition (or

  • 10 avoidable) cultural political selectivity (Proctor, 2008). But neither are we concerned

    with insoluble ignorance (Rescher, 2009, p. 11). Preeminent examples of insolubilia

    typically come from the realm of theology, a domain that cannot be considered a proper

    object of epistemological study.7

    When Hayek delivered his Nobel Prize Lecture entitled The Pretence of Knowledge he

    might well have had Socrates words in the deepest recesses of his mind. Plato in the

    Apology (29a) has Socrates say:

    For this fear of death is indeed the pretence of wisdom, and not real wisdom, being the appearance of knowing the unknown; since no one knows whether death, which they in their fear apprehend to be the greatest evil, may not be the greatest good. Is there not here conceit of knowledge, which is a disgraceful sort of ignorance?

    Well-known epistemologist Susan Haack opened up a recent talk with the following, now

    infamous words, from Donald Rumsfeld:

    . . . as we know, there are known knowns; there are things that we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns the ones we dont know we dont know.

    Despite Rumsfelds awkward phrasing, Haack saw that it brought to light a serious

    epistemological point the idea of the unknown unknowns. Haack elucidates what she

    has previously termed as the Rumsfeld Problem (Haack, 2008) as follows.

    To assess how good the evidence was that, e.g., Saddam Hussein had weapons of mass destruction, U.S. intelligence services needed to know not only where the available evidence [the knowns] pointed, and how secure it was, but also how comprehensive it was; and to do that, they needed to know what relevant evidence there might be that they didnt have [the unknowns]. Unfortunately, though they knew what some of the relevant evidence was that they needed but didnt have [the known unknowns], they didnt realize that other evidence, evidence

  • 11 they also didnt have, was also relevant [the unknown unknowns]. (Haack, 2011).

    At first blush does it make any sense to posit the idea of unknown unknowns? Were

    they to be identified as such then surely wed know something. The idea of unknown

    unknowns is a neglected part of epistemology and cuts across the epistemology of

    complexity in all its guises including the philosophy of sociality and the philosophy of

    mind. Hayek (1967, pp. 22-42) certainly thought that epistemological modesty was vital:

    It is high time, however, that we take our ignorance more seriously. As Popper and others have pointed out, the more we learn about the world, and the deeper our learning, the more conscious, specific, and articulate will be our knowledge of what we do not know, our knowledge of our ignorance.

    Consider the following illustration of the epistemological paradox that lies at the heart of

    positive knowledge:

    Figure 2: If the circumference marks the bounds between what we know and what we dont know, then with the increased body of knowledge at time t ignorance increases!8

    The perpetual limiting condition is what (to borrow a phrase from Colin McGinn, 1989)

    Im terming as cognitive closure. The notion of cognitive closure, though unfashionable

    and controversial, is hardly an eccentric position; it has a long-standing provenance and

    can be found in different guises in recent philosophy of mind (McGinn, 1989 and Stoljar,

    Body of

    knowledge at time t

    Body of knowledge

    at time t

  • 12 2006). Despite the aforementioned paradox, neither Hayek nor Simon are saying that

    scientific or social progress is not possible. What they are saying is that one has to be

    very careful about characterizing progress progress is not a straightforward linear

    phenomenon and that epistemic modesty should be an epistemic virtue. The next two

    sections examine Hayeks and Simons notions of cognitive closure.

    III: Hayeks Double Hermeneutic

    Hayeks cognitive closure position has strong commonalities with philosophers of mind

    such as Thomas Nagel, Frank Jackson, and Colin McGinn, their conclusions collected

    under the rubric of new mysterianism (Flanagan, 1984). Mysterianism connotes the

    idea that while naturalism is true, the human mind is terminally constrained in being able

    to explain itself so whatever we discover about the causal states of consciousness, there

    will still remain an explanatory gap. Though Hayeks tome in philosophical

    psychology (Hayek, 1952/1976) is centrally concerned with the mind-body problem, the

    issue is emblematic of a generalized cognitive and epistemic predicament that was his

    lifelong concern. That is, what is the precise nature of our lack of knowledge: is it

    conceptual, empirical, terminal or surmountable? Eric Dietrich and Valerie Hardcastle

    have an epistemically motivated view that consciousness has an essential property that

    prevents it from ever being explained, philosophically or scientifically (Dietrich & Gray

    Hardcastle, 2004). This amounts to a deflationary view that, on acceptance, does away

    with standard philosophical metaphysical talk. Ostensibly, their distinctive position turns

    on the idea that even if there were scientific progress in matters of consciousness,

  • 13 explanation would still not be forthcoming. Hayeks double hermeneutic turns upon the

    inextricable link between mind and sociality: whatever mind may be, how does it

    apprehend the natural and social world, a world that significantly constitutes the mind?

    The brain is both the object of interpretation as well as the interpreter: therefore the

    brain is itself a hermeneutic device (rdi et al, 2006). For Hayek the idea of the mind

    explaining itself entails a logical contradiction (Hayek, 1952/1976, 8.91; 1952/1979, p.

    380). Hayek is acutely aware that self-referentiality leads to dead ends, the instrument of

    explanation simultaneously being the object of explanation cannot get us anywhere

    (Hayek, 1952/1976, 8.67, 5.91, 8.26, 8.69, 8.80; cf. Rescher, 1998, pp. 151-164 and

    Maturana & Varela, 1980, p. 49).9 Any explanation of consciousness must be condemned

    to a practical dualism (Hayek, 1952/1976, 8.87).

    Three related points need to be made. First, Hayek is not recommending a

    Cartesian dualism, but simply that despite the underlying physical basis of consciousness,

    all we really have to work with and through is a folk psychology that posits two realms

    the sensory order and the physical order. Second, Hayek is through and through a

    naturalist, a position he has consistently held throughout his career. Hayek fully

    acknowledges that consciousness is a natural phenomenon, but determining what the

    precise relation of consciousness is to the physical world is constitutionally beyond

    mankinds ken (Hayek, 1952/1976, 1:11). Third, Hayek is not a naturalistic agnostic,

    that is, the view that science currently cannot offer an explanation of the mindbody

    relationship, but in principle it could. Hayeks pessimism manifest in his discussion of

    cognitive closure and qualia (the felt qualitative aspect to experience) marks a deep

    philosophical issue: that is, the view that science is explanatorily closed (Hayek,

  • 14 1952/1976, 1.88, 8.31). Were Hayek an agnostic he would take the view that the

    ultimate explanations provided by science are in need of supplementation (Hayek,

    1952/1976, 1:13; 8:26; 8:31; Hayek, 1952, x35). Rescher also marks this point by

    saying that there is no cognitively satisfactory basis for maintaining the completeness of

    science in a rationally cogent way (Rescher, 1998, p. 48). Science has failed miserably

    at assimilating the irreducible phenomenal aspect of conscious experience (Hayek,

    1952/1979, p. 36) and will continue to do so. For Hayek it is the capacity of mind as a

    pattern detector that holds out the nave promise that any and all patterns or structures

    can, in principle, be laid bear to analysis whatever the subject domain. It would be fair to

    suggest that this concern lay at the root of his anti-rationalism or critique of scientism in

    the social domain. Despite the shared presupposition of cognitive closure here we find the

    greatest point of divergence between Hayeks ostensible pessimism and Simons psycho-

    ebullience:

    For the first time in its history as a science, psychology may now be in possession of techniques that are commensurate in power with the complexity of the phenomena we seek to understand and explain (Simon, cited in Crowther-Heyck, 2005, p. 257).

    It is difficult to discern what motivates Simons view. Suffice to say, this tension might

    have arisen because Simon may have always harbored a residual optimism of the early

    days of artificial intelligence and was still very much a cognitivist.

    IV: Bounded Rationality

    For Simon complexity is an external phenomenon; it is the intrinsic richness of the social

    and artifactual environment (the former, properly speaking is very much an artifact) that

  • 15 the world apprehends through the senses and the information about the world is stored in

    long-term memory. Social complexity for Hayek and Simon offers both the fabric of

    possibility and of inherent constraint (c.f. Rescher, 1998, p. 191). Epistemic and cognitive

    efficiencies, well beyond the capacity of any one mind, are facilitated through the

    ubiquity of sociocultural trellising and dynamic looping. Human beings:

    can store away in memory a great furniture of information that can be evoked by appropriate stimuli . . . [I] would like to view this information-packed memory less as a part of the organism than as a part of the environment to which it adapts (Simon, 1996, p. 53).

    For Simon, rationality is not bounded by the Humean passions but by the structural

    limitations of the brain as a computational device. Human cognition is constrained by the

    inextricably linked problem of sheer volume of data and computational speed available

    (Conlisk, 2004, p. 193). For Hayek, the mere possibility of thought can exist only within

    a matrix of tradition, custom and practice to dispense with these resources would not

    only be vulgarly rationalistic but irrational. Similarly, for Simon, rationality can only be

    coherently detected and specified within a context a context of social organization

    whether it be the family, the school, the company and so on.10 Social organization

    provides the scaffolding for reason and not (as Crowther-Heyck so elegantly puts it)

    amplifiers of unreason (Crowther-Heyck, 2005, p. 47). On Simons account rationality

    takes place, indeed is really only possible only within an institutional context why else

    would these institutions have arisen? Rationality, therefore, is an adaptive ability in the

    face of complexity. It should be noted that being obfusticated by complexity does not

    entail that an optimal resolution cannot be found but that it cannot be solved without

    some other steep transactional cost e.g. time (Simon, 1972, p. 164). Simons work in

  • 16 administrative theory is the source of his notion of bounded rationality and distinguishes

    administrative science from economics whereas economic man maximizes,

    administrative man satisfices, satisficing being a strategy for operating in complex

    settings with incomplete information because they have not the wits to maximize

    (Simon, 1956, p. 136). Agents, are therefore prone to identify with sub-goals, that is, the

    searching for a good enough action rather than optimal ones.

    Simon rejected, as did Hayek, the pernicious fiction of perfect profit-maximizing

    rationality so characteristic of homo economicus.11

    The capacity of the human mind for formulating and solving complex problems is very small compared with the size of the problems whose solution is required for objectively rational behavior in the real world or even for a reasonable approximation to such objective rationality (Simon, 1957, p. 198).

    The upshot for Simon is that cognitive agents simply do not have sufficient means for

    storing information in memory to enable them to apply the most efficient strategy unless

    the presentation of stimuli is greatly slowed down or the subjects are permitted external

    memory aids or both (Simon, 1996, pp. 61, 99-100).

    A recurrent problem for Simon is if he accepts the plasticity of mind (and he

    does) and its development as a spontaneous order, how does he reconcile this with the

    idea that complexity is merely an external phenomenon? Simon might well respond by

    saying that relatively speaking, the individual mind is simple compared with the

    emergent sociality generated by multitudes of other individual minds. Godfrey-Smiths

    suggestion that there is no necessary link between environmental complexity and organic

    complexity (if there were, a given organic system would be implausibly large and

    cumbersome) could come to Simons rescue (Godfrey-Smith, 1996, p. 59). This would

    explain Simons externalism, i.e. offloading the cognitive burden on the environment.

  • 17 Yet another problem that Simon faces is in his idea of a homeostatic interface between

    mind and environment. Though he doesnt mentioned Simon specifically, Godfrey-Smith

    makes the point that perhaps intelligence is not a genuinely homeostatic phenomenon

    (1996, p. 79).

    VI: The Ant on the Beach

    For Simon, ants (and indeed humans) viewed as behaving systems, are really quite

    simple. The apparent complexity of the ants behavior is largely a reflection of the

    complexity in which it finds itself:

    We watch an ant make his laborious way across a wind- and wave-molded beach. He moves ahead, angles to the right to ease his climb up a steep dune let, detours around a pebble, stops for a moment to exchange information with a compatriot . . . [I]t is a sequence of irregular, angular segments not quite a random walk, for it has an underlying sense of direction, of aiming toward a goal . . . [H]e has a general sense of where home lies, but he cannot foresee all the obstacles between. He must adapt his course repeatedly to the difficulties he encounters and often detour uncrossable barriers. His horizons are very close, so that he deals with each obstacle as he comes to it . . . [V]iewed as a geometric figure, the ants path is irregular, complex, hard to describe. But its complexity is really a complexity in the surface of the beach, not a complexity in the ant (Simon, 1996, p. 51).

    According to Andy Clark, the dean of the extended mind theorists, [M]uch of what goes

    on in the complex world of humans, may thus, somewhat surprisingly, be understood in

    terms of so-called stigmergic algorithms (Clark, 1996, p. 279). Ubiquitous instantiations

    of stigmergic systems include stock markets, economies, traffic patterns, supply logistics

    and resource allocation, and urban development. Simons ant example and Hayeks

    notion of spontaneous order are stigmergic in all but name.12 The point of Simons ant

    example, which he modeled in much greater detail in an earlier paper (Simon, 1956), is to

  • 18 show that the postulating of a utility function is superfluous to theories of rational

    behavior, behavior that is better conceived as a theory of perception and cognition.

    In what follows, the mechanism of stigmergy is explicated by recasting Simons ant

    example as a swarm algorithm. Clarks claim is substantiated by recasting Hayeks

    spontaneous order and Simons bounded rationality as stigmergic social externalism since

    both share the twofold presupposition that (a) no one mind has global knowledge and (b)

    calculation or coordination is done through the social artifacts, a dynamicism of

    iterated looping of behaviors.

    Zoologist Pierre-Paul Grass (who coined the term stigmergy) discovered in the

    coordination and regulation of termite colonies the phenomenon of indirect

    communication mediated by modifications of the environment (Grass, 1959). Grass

    sought to understand the mechanisms underlying the emergence, regulation, and control

    of collective activities in social insects. Put in economists terms, Grass sought to

    address the coordination paradox. How does one reconcile prima facie chaotic behavior

    at the individual level with the global/societal level of the termite colony? Grass

    observed that the coordination and regulation of the termites impressive building

    activities did not depend on the individual agents themselves, but were subject to a

    cybernetic feedback loop through pheromone traces and environmental modifications

    made by other ants. In other words, the environment acts as a kind of distributed memory

    system. Though Hayek and Simon took economists optimization-talk13 to task, the

    discussion that follows of particle swarm optimization (PSO formulated by Kennedy et

  • 19 al., 2001), is inherently stigmergic in that each individual contributes to the evolution of

    collective knowledge, which in turn impacts upon the individual. PSO is a social

    algorithm and runs on a socio-cognitive model of social influence and learning

    embodying the three standard social principles; the ability to evaluate, compare, and

    imitate.14 PSO seems particularly well suited to the way in which Simons and Hayeks

    social externalism operates as extended cognitive systems. It might be suggested that the

    concept of stigmergy, typically associated with ant- or swarm-like agents with minimal

    cognitive ability, is inappropriately deployed in the human-human realm. Simon

    preempts this criticism: There is nothing particularly remarkable about this description

    of rational choice, except that it differs so sharply from the more sophisticated models of

    human rationality that have been proposed by economists and others (Simon, 1956, p.

    130). To make the point in the explication that follows, ant is substituted by an individual

    human agent. In any event, Simons homo adaptivus is relatively simple, necessarily

    existing in a complex environment about which it has only partial knowledge

    stigmergically ameliorated through environmental interaction.

    The starting point of my reconstruction is as per Simon (1956, p. 130)15:

    The organisms life space may be described as a surface over which it can locomote. Most of the surface is perfectly bare, but at isolated, widely scattered points there are little heaps of food, each adequate for a meal. The organism's vision permits it to see, at any moment, a circular portion of the surface about the point in which it is standing. It is able to move at some fixed maximum rate over the surface. It metabolizes at a given average rate and is able to store a certain amount of food energy, so that it needs to eat a meal at certain average intervals. It has the capacity, once it sees a food heap, to proceed toward it at the maximum rate of locomotion. The problem of rational choice is to choose its path in such a way that it will not starve. Now I submit that a rational way for the organism to behave is the following:

  • 20 (a) it explores the surface at random, watching for a food heap;

    (b) when it sees one, it proceeds to it and eats (food getting); (c) if the total consumption of energy during the average time required, per meal, for exploration and food getting is less than the energy of the food consumed in the meal, it can spend the remainder of its time in resting.

    Consider a group of n blind individuals randomly placed in a landscape at time 0.16 The

    group has the task of finding the lowest point in the landscape. Every minute (i.e. at time

    t), each individual i moves ki(t) steps in a given direction (e.g. specified by the angle i(t)

    to the East-West direction). In other words, at time t, each individual moves along a

    certain vector vi(t) (see figure 3).

    The PSO algorithm is a model for the way in which each individual in the landscape

    develops a strategy to achieve the goal of identifying the lowest point. At the heart of the

    algorithm lies the idea that the individual will move so as to account for both the lowest

    point it has reached so far, and the lowest point achieved by the group (including itself)

    so far. So-called acceleration constants cind(t) and cgroup(t) determine the weights to be

    put on a move towards ones own best position and the group best position respectively.

    When cind(t) > 0 and cgroup(t) = 0, the individuals progress completely independently,

    drawing no benefit from the findings of the rest of the group. This would amount to a

    situation in which the relevant knowledge has no social component. On the contrary,

    when cind(t) = 0 and cgroup(t) > 0, each individual only takes into account the group best,

    so that the information acquired by the individual along the way is discarded as long as it

    does not define the group best position. This amounts to equating the relevant knowledge

    with its social dimension.

  • 21 The ideal weighting is obtained for when cind(t) cgroup(t). Note that in the

    optimization process, some randomization is added to the iterative procedure to enable

    some flexibility in the actual weightings which are ascribed to the individual and group

    components of the information acquired so far. This also has the advantage of more

    realistically mimicking the way in which actual strategies manage the relative weights of

    individual and group knowledge, i.e. generally in a non-totally deterministic way, but

    rather with some random variability. Thus, if )(tyij represents the component in the jth

    dimension (in the example there are only two dimensions, i.e. the Northing and Easting)

    of the best position achieved so far by individual i, and )(^ty j the component in the jth

    dimension of the group best position so far, and if )(txij is the actual position in the jth

    dimension of individual i, the move to the next position )1( +txij is defined by:

    - an individual component which is proportional to the discrepancy between the

    individual best and the current position, with a coefficient of proportionality

    )()( , trtc jindind , i.e. the weight )(tcind but randomly perturbed by )(, tr jind (which is

    uniformly distributed between 0 and 1);

    - a group component which is similarly proportion to the discrepancy between

    the group best and the current position, with a coefficient of proportionality

    )()( , trtc jgroupgroup , i.e. the weight )(tcgroup but randomly perturbed by

    )(, tr jgroup (which is uniformly distributed between 0 and 1).

  • 22

    Figure 3: A group of n individuals randomly parachuted in a landscape at time 0. The group has the task of finding the lowest point in the landscape.

    In line with the example of the individuals scanning a landscape, we can see how the

    process by which a group acquires knowledge can be modeled in this way. The

    stigmergic aspect of this process is encapsulated in the impact the groups knowledge has

    upon the individuals investigative strategy, and vice-versa, the contribution the

    individuals discoveries make to the knowledge possessed by the group. To make the

    algorithm more suitable for his application, one might wish to dispense with the

    oversimplified assumption of perfect knowledge by each individual of the knowledge

    acquired by the group (e.g. by introducing some additional randomness).

    Another use of the PSO algorithm would be the modeling of the process of

    acquisition of knowledge by individuals. Here the population or group best are more or

    less fixed and uninfluenced by the individuals knowledge acquisition. The algorithm is

    H

    P -m0

    P P n1

    -m0 -m0

  • 23 thus chiefly designed to represent the learning curve characterizing knowledge

    acquisition. That is, the individuals understanding of a body of knowledge is not a matter

    of just assimilating it in one go, but rather of progressively integrating aspects of this

    body of knowledge from the perspective the individual is coming from.17

    In the PSO algorithm, the role played by the groups best position, which

    represents the groups knowledge is crucial to each individuals evolution. It is important

    to note that in the algorithm, this group knowledge corresponds to some individuals

    knowledge at any given time, but there is no single individual whose knowledge it is over

    time.

    Stigmergy is precisely the interaction of these two forms of knowledge and gives

    credence to the proposition that if social epistemology has the formation, acquisition,

    mediation, transmission and dissemination of knowledge in complex communities of

    knowers as its subject matter, then its third party character must surely be essentially

    stigmergic. If stigmergic-talk is deemed an overly whimsical rational reconstruction of

    Simon and by extrapolation, Hayek, then it is to a more recent theorist we need to turn.

    Don Lavoie, an Austrian school economist, saw the resonance of swarm behavior

    to human-human stigmergy in no uncertain terms.18 Like Hayek and Simon, Lavoie

    accepts the presupposition of cognitive closure (Lavoie, 1985, pp. 65-66, 68-69). Lavoie

    explicitly and repeatedly cites the work of sociobiologist E. O. Wilson, a leading theorist

    on termite stigmergy. Wilson (1975/2000, pp. 186188) identifies two main variants of

    stigmergy:

    Sematectonic stigmergy

    Sign-, cue-, or marker-based stigmergy

  • 24 Sematectonic stigmergy connotes communication via modification of a physical

    environment, an elementary example being the carving out of trails. One needs only to

    cast an eye around any public space, a park or a college quadrangle to see the grass being

    worn away, revealing a dirt pathway that is a well-traveled, unplanned and thus indicates

    an unofficial intimation of a shortcut to some salient destination. Marker-based

    stigmergy denotes communication via a signaling mechanism. A standard example is the

    phenomenon of pheromones laid by social insects. Pheromone imbued trails increase the

    likelihood of other ants following the aforementioned trails. Unlike sematectonic

    stigmergy which is a response to an environmental modification, marker-based stigmergy

    does not make any direct contribution to a given task.

    Though Lavoie doesnt ever invoke the term stigmergy one should be in no doubt

    that the features of mass coordination across all domains of sociality are for him

    stigmergic indeed, the terms tradition and the market are shorthand for stigmergic

    sociality (Lavoie, 1985, p. 29). Lavoie makes the link between mass communication

    and the knowledge problem (Lavoie, 1985, pp. 27-28) and rightly focuses on the

    mechanism of coordination. For Lavoie the similarity between insects and man is greater

    in this respect than it may appear and moreover the human analogue of the insects

    pheromone is the expenditure of money in market exchanges (Lavoie, 1985, pp. 69-71,

    72).

    The principle the sociobiologists call mass communication reveals how partial, localized knowledge on the part of a termite in one part of a colony can be merged in such a way that the systems overall allocation of resources is informed by more knowledge than any one participant to the process can possess. It seems to me that the very same kind of mass communication is the principle that operates in market systems (Lavoie, 1985, p, 76.)

    In language reminiscent of Hayek, Lavoie is of the view that:

  • 25 These diverse spontaneous orders, from primitive insect societies to such complex institutions as markets and science, all exhibit as a basic organizing principle a competitive process of discovery whereby each participant both actively contributes and passively responds to signals (Lavoie, 1985, p. 86).

    In other words, the stigmergic interest lies in the stochastic spread of a marker through a

    population of strangers whereby a strong pheromone trail will translate into heightened

    awareness of a given product, which in turn will convert into sales. Such strategies, if

    successful, are both financially and logistically highly efficient.

    VII: Concluding Remarks

    Whatever sociality may be, by definition it cannot reside solely within an individual:

    continuity can only be mediated, albeit imperfectly (not in high-fidelity), through a web

    of social artifacts that contains its own immanent standard of epistemic weight regarding

    its methodological, conceptual and empirical problems. One way is to conceive of

    sociality in terms of epistemic engineering that stigmergy proposes. This would be

    consistent with the idea of informational flow (traditions and practices as external

    artifacts or downstream epistemic engineering as Sterelney 2003 puts it) between

    generations and the idea of cooperation conceived as distributed cognition.

    Despite their differences, i.e. Hayeks bidirectional complexity and Simons

    unidirectional complexity, both positions fall under what Godfrey-Smith has termed c-

    externalist explanations (a species of a more general externalism) whereby environmental

    complexity explains cognitive (internal) complexity (1996, pp. 31, 57-60). Let us

    summarize or loosely adduce the argument that has been presented.

  • 26 immergence emergence Mind: (a) Individual cognition is delimited

    (b) Mind is a conditioned complex adaptive system Knowledge: (c) Social epistemology is, by definition, stigmergic

    Society: (d) Sociality is adverbial, adaptive and stigmergic ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Cognition: (e) Cognition is distributed, conditioned and stigmergic

    Figure 4: The small arrows connote a two-way interaction between elements (a) to (d); the larger arrows

    connote emergence (novel behavior emerging from a lower level specification of a system) and its corollary immergence (individual interaction informed by a global state of affairs).

    If mind is constitutionally delimited then it must somehow augment its epistemic and

    computational capacity: adaptive evolutionary imperatives demand it. Hayeks and

    Simons shared a priori presupposition that mind is constrained in its computational

    capacity should not be taken as an exercise in armchair philosophizing.19 The point

    shouldnt be lost that both men were motivated by a practical concern. That is, they were

    deeply concerned by an uncritical acceptance of rationalism in its two most extreme (and

    hence) sinister guises: central planning rationalism (favored by collectivism) and the

    vulgar individualism of homo economicus (favored by orthodox economics).20 Hayek

    made the very distinctive link between mind and freedom: All institutions of freedom

    are adaptations to this fundamental fact of ignorance (Hayek, 1960/1978, p. 30). For

    Simon the great sin of central planner was their arrogance in believing that they knew

    best for all, while the great failing of radical individualists lay in their arrogant belief that

    the individual could reason as God would (Crowther-Heyck, 2006, p. 273). Their key

    insight is that perfect knowledge is both unnecessary, impracticable and indeed

    irrelevant if one understands the mechanism at work in complex sociality, a stigmergic

    sociality that in effect augments or scaffolds cognition.21

  • 27

    References

    Baggier, L. (2001). Sources of Complexity in Human Systems. Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life

    Sciences, Vol. 5, No. 1, 3-19. Butos, W. (Ed.) (2010). The Social Science of Hayeks The Sensory Order.Advances in Austrian

    Economics. Bingley: Emerald. Butos, W. N., & Koppl, R. G. (2007). Does The Sensory Order have a useful economic future? Cognition

    and Economics. Advances in Austrian Economics, 9, 1950. Caldwell, B. (2000). The emergence of Hayeks ideas on cultural evolution. Review of Austrian Economics,

    13, 522. Chalmers, D. J. (2006). Strong and Weak Emergence. http://consc.net/papers/emergence.pdf Chalmers, D. J. & Clark, A. (1998). The Extended Mind. Analysis 58:10-23. Clark, A. (1996). Economic reason: The interplay of individual learning and external structure. In: J.

    Drobak & J. Nye (Eds.), The Frontiers of the New Institutional Economics (pp. 269290). San Diego: Academic Press.

    Conlisk, J. (2004). Herbert Simon as Friend to Economist Out of Fashion. In: M. Augier & J. G. March (Eds.) Models of Man: Essays in Memory of Herbert A. Simon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Crowther-Heyck, H. (2005). Herbert A. Simon: The Bounds of Reason in Modern America. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Crowther-Heyck, H. (2006). Herbert Simon and the GSIA: Building an Interdisciplinary Community. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 42(4), 311334.

    Dietrich, E. & Gray Hardcastle, V. (2004). Sisyphuss Boulder: Consciousness and the Limits of the Knowable. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Egidi, M. & Marengo, L. (2004). Near-Decomposability, Organization, and Evolution: Some Notes on Herbert Simons Contribution. In: M. Augier & J. G. March (Eds.) Models of Man: Essays in Memory of Herbert A. Simon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    rdi, P., Diwadkar, V. & Ujfalussy, B. (2008). The Schizophrenic Brain: A Broken Hermeneutic Circle. Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol. 5164, Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer

    Feser, E. (2006). Hayek the cognitive scientist and philosopher of mind. In: E. Feser (Ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hayek. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Flanagan, O. (1984). The Science of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gallagher, S. & Crisafi, A. (2009). Mental Institutions. Topoi 28:4551. Gigerenzer, G. (2004). Striking a Blow for Sanity in Theories of Rationality. In: M. Augier & J. G. March

    (Eds.) Models of Man: Essays in Memory of Herbert A. Simon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press. Grass, P. P. (1959). La reconstruction du nod et les coordinations interindividuelles chez Bellicositermes

    natalensis et Cubitermes sp. La theorie de la stigmergie: Essai dinterpretation du comportement des termites constructeurs. Insectes Sociaux, 6(1), 4183.

    Haack, S. (2008). Warrant, Causation, and the Atomism of Evidence Law. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, Vol. 5, Issue 3, 2008, 253-265.

    Haack, S. (2011). Epistemology: Who Needs It? KRITIK September 2011. Hardwick, D. F. & Marsh, L. (in press). Clash of the Titans: When the Market and Science Collide.

    Advances in Austrian Economics Hayek, F. A. (1952/1976). The Sensory Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F. A. (1952/1979). The Counter-Revolution of Science: Studies on the Abuse of Reason.

    Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Press. Hayek, F. A. (1960/1978). The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F. A. (1967). Studies on Philosophy, Politics and Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago

    Press. Hayek, F. A. (1994/1998). Hayek on Hayek: An Autobiographical Dialogue. In: S. Kresge & L. Wenar

    (Eds.), Indianapolis: Liberty Fund Press.

  • 28 Johnson, N. (2009). Simply Complexity. Oxford: Oneworld Publications. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Strauss & Giroux Kennedy, J., Eberhart, R. C., & Shi, Y. (2001). Swarm Intelligence. San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann

    Publishers. Knauff, M., & Wolf, A. G. (2010). Complex cognition: The science of human reasoning, problem-solving,

    and decision-making. Cognitive Processing, 11(2), 99102. Kriegel, U. (2003). The New Mysterianism and the Thesis of Cognitive Closure. Acta Analytica Volume

    18, Issue 30/31: 177-191. Lavoie, D. (1985). National Economic Planning: What Is Left? Cambridge, MA: Ballinger. Marsh, L. (2010). Hayek: Cognitive Scientist Avant La Lettre. In: W. Butos (Ed.) The Social Science of

    Hayeks The Sensory OrderAdvances in Austrian Economics. Bingley: Emerald. Marsh, L. (2012). Hayek and Oakeshott: Situating Cognition. In: P. Franco & L. Marsh (Eds.) A

    Companion to Michael Oakeshott. University Park: Penn State University Press. Marsh, L., & Onof, C. (2008). Stigmergic epistemology, stigmergic cognition. Cognitive Systems Research,

    9 (12), 136149. Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living.

    Dordrecht: Reidel. McGinn, C. (1989). The Problem of Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell. Mitchell, M. (2009). Complexity: A Guided Tour. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mithen, S. (2000). Mind, Brain and Material Culture: An Archaeological Perspective. In: Evolution and the

    Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Metacognition (Eds.) P. Carruthers and A. Chamberlain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Morton, A. (2004). Epistemic Virtues, Metavirtues, and Computational Complexity. Nos 38:3 481-502. Morton, A. (2010). Human bounds: rationality for our species. Synthese 176: 5-21. Norman, D. A. (2011). Living with Complexity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Proctor, R. (2008). Agnotology: A Missing Term to Describe the Cultural Production of Ignorance (and Its

    Study). In: R. N. Proctor & L. Schiebinger (Eds.) Agnotology: The Making and Unmasking of Ignorance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Rescher, N. (1998). Complexity: A Philosophical Overview. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers. Rescher, N. (2009). Unknowability: An Inquiry Into the Limits of Knowledge. Lexington, VA: Lexington

    Books. Rescher, N. (2009). Ignorance: (On the Wider Implications of Deficient Knowledge). Pittsburgh: University

    of Pittsburgh Press. Samuelson, P. A. (2009). A few remembrances of Friedrich von Hayek (18991992). Journal of Economic

    Behavior & Organization, 69, 14. Simon, H. A. (1956) Rational choice and the structure of the environment, Psychological Review, 63: 129-

    138. Simon, H. A. (1957). A behavioral model of rational choice. In: Models of Man. New York: Wiley. Simon, H. A. (1962). The Architecture of Complexity. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,

    Vol. 106, No. 6. (Dec. 12, 1962), pp. 467-482. Simon, H. A. (1972). Theories of bounded rationality. In: C.B. McGuire & R. Radner (Eds.) Decision and

    Organization. Simon, H. A. (1979). Rational Decision-Making in Business Organizations. Nobel Memorial Lecture. The

    American Economic Review Vol. 69, No. 4: 493-513. Simon, H. A. (1991). Models of my Life. New York: Basic Books Simon, H. A. (1996). The Sciences of the Artificial. 3rd ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sterelney, K. (2003). Thought in a Hostile World. Oxford: Blackwell. Stoljar, D. (2006). Ignorance and Imagination: The Epistemic Origin of the Problem of Consciousness.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wilson, E. O. (1975/2000). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees (Eds.). Oxford:

    Blackwell. NOTES

  • 29 1 Neither the Hoover Institution (Hayek archives) nor Carnegie Mellon (Simon archives) reveal any exchange between these two. My thanks to Nicholas Siekierski, Assistant Archivist, Hoover Institution and Jennie Benford, University/Heinz Archivist, Carnegie Mellon University for their respective assistance. 2 It is puzzling as to why there is a paucity of literature examining Hayek and Simon. One explanation might be that these two polymaths have tended to be viewed more as dilettantes (regarding Hayek see Hayek, 1994/1998, p. 152; Samuelson, 2009, p. 3, note 2; regarding Simon see Crowther-Heych, 2005, p. 4). Be that as it may, Hayeks and Simons stars are in the ascendency, gaining new-found appreciation for their fusion of philosophical psychology with social epistemology, arguably the most important aspects to their voluminous corpora. 3 To complicate matters Hayek is a died-in-the-wool constructivist yet it is so-called constructivism that he takes to task. Hayek attributes to constructivists the impulse that, since all aspects of sociality are in some sense artifactual (in being created by man, the residua of conscious minds), therefore sociality in all its forms must be amenable to alteration (Marsh, 2012). 4 The extended mind literature is as controversial as it is suggestive and has generated a vast literature. Clarks early statement (with David Chalmers) termed active externalism ran on what they termed the parity principle. Roughly speaking its the idea that if a part of the extra-cranial world, say a computer chip, were embedded within the cranium, wed have no problem accepting the functional similarity of the chip as part of the brains cognitive machinery. Cognitive archaeologist Stephen Mithen (2000) also argues that artifacts can form a literal extension of the mind. Gallagher & Crisafi (2009) are of the view that the Clark-Chalmers thesis can be extrapolated to include social institutions deploying a highly suggestive appeal to Hegel a Hegel lite if you will. 5 To say that complexity is inextricably linked to cognition is not to deny ontological objectivity (Rescher, 1998, p. 36) or to deny epistemic progress (Rescher, 1998, p. 49). There are facts of the matter but they are not accessible (Rescher, 2009, p. 2). 6 It should be noted that complexity connotes a state of the world; complicated a state of mind (Norman, 2011, pp. 2, 4. 40, 53; Rescher, 1998, p. 17). Another distinction that has been drawn is between structural complexity and functional complexity. The former concerned with the mereological composition of a system; the latter concerned with what the system is supposed to do (Godfrey-Smith, 1996, p. 26) but as Godfrey-Smith concedes, structural complexity might well be required for functional simplicity (p. 27). 7 Take the concept of God: the concept does not achieve enough clarity and distinctness to be discussable. When we cite the divine attributes omniscience, omnipotence, and so on we dont have the least purchase on these ideas which generate paradoxes almost immediately. 8 Im indebted to William Dennis for bringing this idea to my attention. 9 This has resonance with two variations of Reschers argument. The first (1998, pp. 25-54, 71): 1. The worlds descriptive complexity is infinite (even finite phenomenon can exhibit infinite complexity) 2. A complete inventory of facts can never be made ----------------------------------------------------------------- 3. Therefore, reality is bound to be cognitively opaque The second (Rescher, 2009, p. 66): (1) Physical reality is reflective of the work of a mind more powerful than ours (2) A mind of lesser power is unable to understand the workings of a mind of greater power ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- (3) Therefore, an adequate apprehension of nature is beyond our grasp 10 Simon, 1979, p. 497: In a footnote Becker indicates that he denotes as irrational [A]ny deviation from utility maximization. Thus, what I have called bounded rationality is irrationality in Beckers terminology. 11 This is sharply borne out by the experiments formulated by Nobel laureate Daniel Kahneman and his collaborator Amos Tversky, presented in popular form in Kahneman (2011).

  • 30 12 Hayek with his characteristic prescience did hint at the issue of swarm behavior/stigmergy but not being a modeler, as Simon was, never provided the fine-grained detail required to illustrate a spontaneous order. 13 Rational inquiry is a process of optimization that is, maximization under constraints (Rescher, 1998, pp. 57, 169); (Gigerenzer, 2004, pp. 390-91); cf. optimization dogma (Conlisk, 2004, p. 194). 14 Note: the particle component in PSO denotes an individual and the swarm in PSO denotes a process or grouping. 15 The more technically orientated reader should look at the algorithms Simon formulates in this same paper. 16 Amended from Marsh & Onof, 2008. 17 There are in fact typically different types of neighborhoods to be considered in the process of acquisition of knowledge by an individual or a group. For most matters, pertaining to what one takes to be correct, there are three types of neighborhoods: the specialists in the relevant field; the cultural milieu; and the family/geographical neighborhood. The first neighborhood is defined by its being necessarily associated with the acquisition of knowledge; the second is associated with the necessary belonging to a cultural milieu, but the fact it is this one rather than another is a contingent matter; the third is entirely contingent: it is an entirely contingent matter whether one has geographical/genetic neighbors which have an influence upon ones acquisition of knowledge. The existence of a number q of neighborhoods is best taken into account by altering the PSO algorithm to have several croup(t) weightings:{ cgroup1(t), cgroup2(t), . cgroupq(t)}. In the case where several groups are considered, as proposed in the modification of the lbest algorithm to reflect the multiplicity of bodies of expert knowledge, there is therefore a distribution of knowledge both among the groups and among the individuals of any given group. 18 Im indebted to Steve Horwitz and Adam Martin for bringing this aspect of Lavoies work to my attention. 19 Even those who are not out of sympathy with the Hayek-McGinn line are concerned that although we might not be able to specify a solution, it is incoherent to suggest that we couldnt understand what would count as a solution (Kriegel, 2003, p. 184). 20 Egidi & Marengo (2004) have made a good but limited start at examining both Hayek and Simon. I do however take issue with their view (p. 336) that the main difference between Hayek and Simon is that Hayek gave epistemological prioricity to the market (see Hardwick & Marsh, in press). Elsewhere I have looked at Hayek as cognitive scientist rather than social theorist/economist Marsh 2010; 2012. It is odd that a major bounded rationality theorist does not reference Simon see Morton, 2004, 2010. 21 Im indebted to my colleague David Hardwick for the ongoing stimulating discussion on all these issues and for his practical support; to Nicholas Rescher for generously sending me some of his preprints, to Douglass North for providing a missing reference and to Shannon Selin for proofreading and for sending my way salient references I wouldnt have come across myself.