33
7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/mcinerneyalthussermontesquieurobertson 1/33  MONARCHY, DESPOTISM, AND ALTHUSSER'S 'LINGUISTIC TRICK': WILLIAM ROBERTSON AND THE LITERARY REPRODUCTION OF MONTESQUIEU'S CONCEPT OF 'FUNDAMENTAL LAW' David McInerney David McInerney is a Lecturer in the School of Communication, International Studies and Languages at the University of South Australia. He edited the special journal issue Althusser and Us (borderlands e-journal, Vol. 4, No. 2, 2005) and is currently co-editing a series of volumes of the collected works of the Marxist philosopher Wal Suchting (Brill, forthcoming) in addition to a number of other projects, including an extended study of the literary reproduction of the concept of despotism in Anglophone political thought from John Locke to James Mill. THIS IS A PROOF ONLY. PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION. THE TEXT SHOULD BE THE SAME AS THE PUBLISHED VERSION, IN LAURENT DE SUTTER (ED.), ALTHUSSER AND LAW (ROUTLEDGE, 2013).

McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    1/33

    MONARCHY, DESPOTISM, AND ALTHUSSER'S 'LINGUISTIC TRICK':

    WILLIAM ROBERTSON AND THE LITERARY REPRODUCTION OF

    MONTESQUIEU'S CONCEPT OF 'FUNDAMENTAL LAW'

    David McInerney

    David McInerney is a Lecturer in the School of Communication, International Studies

    and Languages at the University of South Australia. He edited the special journal

    issueAlthusser and Us (borderlands e-journal, Vol. 4, No. 2, 2005) and is currently

    co-editing a series of volumes of the collected works of the Marxist philosopher Wal

    Suchting (Brill, forthcoming) in addition to a number of other projects, including an

    extended study of the literary reproduction of the concept of despotism in Anglophone

    political thought from John Locke to James Mill.

    THIS IS A PROOF ONLY. PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION. THE TEXT SHOULD BE THE SAME AS

    THE PUBLISHED VERSION, IN LAURENT DE SUTTER (ED.), ALTHUSSER AND LAW (ROUTLEDGE, 2013).

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    2/33

    1

    True moderation is neither the strict separation ofpowers (pouvoirs) nor a

    juridical concern and respect for legality. [I]t is all very well to say that

    despotism is the regime in which a single person governs alone, without rules

    or laws, or that the despot appears in every prince or minister who goes

    beyond the law and abuses his power. At bottom, this is not what is at issue,

    for we are familiar with regimes in which despotism reigns even under the

    appearance of laws, and, says, Montesquieu, that is the worst of tyrannies.

    Moderation is something quite different: it is not mere respect for legality, it is

    the balance of powers, i.e. the division of the pouvoirs among the puissances,

    and the limitation or moderation of the pretensions of onepuissance by the

    pouvoir of the others. The famous separation of powers is thus no more than

    the calculated division ofpouvoir between determinatepuissances: the king,

    the nobility and the 'people'.

    (Althusser 1972: 91)

    For Marxists attempting to develop an Althusserian approach to constitutional law

    and the state Althusser's first book Montesquieu:la politique et l'histoire (1959)

    would appear to be one natural point of departure, given the undeniable historical and

    theoretical importance of Montesquieu'sL'esprit des lois since its publication in 1748.

    In 1959 Althusser's book represented a major intervention within the literature on

    Montesquieu, and retained this significance within that literature even when his

    reading of Marx fell out of favor during the 1980s. One effect of Althusser's

    intervention has been, however, to downplay the significance of Montesquieu's theses

    on the laws or, at least, those on real laws and statutes and to depictL'esprit des

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    3/33

    2

    lois as a work within the theory of government rather than one within constitutional

    law. Three theses, important in themselves, have combined to produce this effect.

    The first is Althusser's emphasis on the nature-principle unity within each form of

    government, which leads him understand the corruption of each of Montesquieu's

    three forms in terms of a contradiction within such unities in which the principle

    remains determinant in the last instance (Althusser 1972: 4653). The second is that

    the 'theoretical model' of a rigorous 'separation of powers' that late nineteenth century

    jurists discovered in Chapter VIII ofL'esprit des lois is in fact "purely imaginary",

    and "quite simply does not exist in Montesquieu" (Althusser 1971: 8890). The third

    thesis, which is a critique of Montesquieu rather than his interpreters, is that this

    juridical interpretation finds its textual basis within a certain "ambiguity [in

    Montesquieu's] conception of law" that arises out of an occasional conflation of "the

    object of scientific observation" ("the laws ordained by men") with "the results of the

    investigation itself" ("the laws really ordering the actions of men") that, combined

    with his "juridical mode of reflection" (Althusser 1972: 3437), enables Montesquieu

    to present a "political problem of the relations of forces" as an abstract "juridical

    problem concerning the definition of legality and its spheres" (Althusser 1972: 91).

    Considered separately each of these theses is valid and important, but when combined

    with Althusser's tenuous interpretation of Chapter IV of Book II ofL'esprit des lois

    namely his claim that Montesquieu deploys a 'linguistic trick' in order to represent the

    very existence of the nobility and the clergy as if it were in itselfa fundamental law of

    the monarchical form of government, via an ambiguity in Montesquieu's use of 'law'

    the result is a simple reversal of the strategy that Althusser attributes to Montesquieu,

    pushing 'real laws' aside to focus on relations between social forces (puissances) in

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    4/33

    3

    abstraction from the political and legal structures to which they are immanent (see

    Althusser 1972: 6768). While this enables Althusser to displace the 'Republican

    Marxist' theses of Georges Lefebvre et. al. on relations between the nobility and

    bourgeoisie in eighteenth-century France (Althusser 1972: 97102; Comninel 1989:

    1218), it does so at the expense of a materialist account of the relation between each

    'form of government' and its 'fundamental laws' within Montesquieu's theory.1

    This essay attempts to open a space for an Althusserian materialist analysis of this

    concept of 'fundamental law' via a detour through the literary reproduction (Macherey

    1998: 4251) of Montesquieu's work in the histories of the Scottish Enlightenment,

    focusing on the writings of William Robertson on despotism and monarchy in three

    non-European societies: Turkey, Peru, and India. In doing so it highlights three

    distinctions in Robertson's work that are crucial for grasping the importance of the

    concept of 'fundamental law' to the Montesquieuan problematic: first, that between

    the nature of a form of government and thefundamental laws that establish and

    perpetuate that government; second, that between accidental and constitutional

    constraints on the exercise of power, especially with regard to the role of religion;

    and, third, the distinction between the establishment of 'social ranks' and the

    establishment of 'intermediate social bodies'.

    ALTHUSSER'S "LINGUISTIC TRICK"

    Macherey has identified the ways in which, in the guise of explaining the

    literary work, critics have reduced it to an intention external to it, an origin

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    5/33

    4

    to which it would be restored. These, however, are not the only ways in which

    criticism denies the objective existence of the literary text. Even as it

    renounces the search for its real existence outside of it, criticism may reduce

    the work to an internal principle, whether a structure or meaning, hidden

    within it. Interpretation seeks that meaning that proves inaccessible on first

    reading, a meaning that can be recovered by great care. Interpretation

    depends on the notion that the literary work possesses an exterior and an

    interior, a surface and depth. The act of interpretation reduces the work to

    its meaning. It demonstrates that the apparent diversity of the work is in fact

    an expression of the meaning that underlies it.

    (Montag 2003: 5859)

    Althusser has posited a whole or structure that leads a latent existence

    beneath or behind the manifest content, the truth of which it is the task of

    interpretation to decipher.

    (Montag 1998: 71)

    Warren Montag has suggested that two incompatible practices of reading and

    conceptions of structure co-exist within Althusser's early works, one of which

    Althusser later pushed aside by deleting a series of passages from and adding a new

    foreword to the second edition ofReading Capital. Montag demonstrates that this

    interpretive practice of reading, which carefully 'reads between the lines' and/or posits

    an underlying and unifying 'meaning' beneath the apparent disorder of the text's

    surface, appears in the first edition ofReading Capital in its supposition a structure or

    combinatory that functions as a latent interiority.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    6/33

    5

    Montag's account of Pierre Macherey's intervention against this tendency in Althusser

    and Althusser's acceptance of that critique and subsequent self-criticism raises the

    question of how we are to read his writings prior to that self-criticism, especially

    those of the late 1950s, when Althusser had already adopted certain theses that were

    to reappear in his subsequent work but had not yet engaged seriously with the works

    of Spinoza, which appear to have been crucial for the development of his method.

    Here we might follow the example of Althusser's reading of Marx, drawing lines of

    demarcation within Althusser's work between theses consistent with his materialism

    and other theses that arise out of such idealist practices of interpretation; one clear

    example of the latter being the following passage from Althusser's reading ofL'esprit

    des lois, where Allthusser reads 'between the lines' of Montesquieu's text to discover a

    'linguistic trick' that cannot be clearly discerned within the letter of the text itself:

    Read carefully Book II Chapter 4. You will find that the first sentence

    identifies the nature of monarchical government, government 'by fundamental

    laws', and the 'intermediate, subordinate, and dependent powers'. Thus

    'intermediary bodies' are to be laws!

    (Althusser 1972: 66)

    When we turn to Montesquieu's own text and read its first sentence to the letter we

    find that the support for Althusser's thesis is slender at best: "The intermediate,

    subordinate, and dependent powers constitute the nature of monarchical government;

    I mean of that in which a single person governs by fundamental laws" (Montesquieu

    1949: 15). Even if this sentence implies that despotism does not have 'fundamental

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    7/33

    6

    laws' it does not in itselfsupport Althusser's conclusion that Montesquieu equates

    'intermediary bodies' with 'fundamental laws'; while Montesquieu does state that the

    monarchical form of government is established by fundamental laws, and that those

    lawspresuppose the powers that enact them this does not in itself imply that we can

    simply reduce those fundamental laws to those powers (puissances). Althusser goes

    on from here to note, correctly, that the law of royal succession and the establishment

    of a 'depository of the laws' independent of the king are not only fundamental laws but

    also real laws (Althusser 1972: 6667); however, it is unclear here exactly why the

    legal exclusion of the monarch from exercising judicial power can be reduced to the

    puissance of the great (as the social body constituted as the 'depository of the laws')

    while the law of royal succession is not similarly reducible to thepuissance of the

    king, or how, indeed, Althusser can claim this paragraph is 'worth its weight in gold':

    'These fundamental laws necessarily suppose the intermediate channels

    through which the power flows' These 'channels' are precisely the nobility

    and the clergy. But by a linguistic trick we are again facing a purely legal

    problem. The 'necessarily' ('these laws necessarily appear . . .') is thus really

    worth its weight in gold. For until now the necessity for the nobility and the

    clergy has not been at all obvious!

    (Althusser 1972: 67)

    This thesis of a 'linguistic trick' facilitates a shift from the legal field to the social

    field, or, alternatively,from real laws to the spirit of the laws via the word 'law':

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    8/33

    7

    The fundamental law is the fixity and constancy of a regime. All right. We are

    in the legal field. But it is also the existence of privileged orders. Now we are

    in the social field. It follows from this reasoning that these orders are identical

    with the fixity and constancy. Hence we can conclude that in essentials,

    these fixed and established laws are no more than the fixity of the

    establishment of the nobility and the clergy.

    (Althusser 1972: 6768)

    However, it is precisely this shift from the legal field to the social field that Althusser

    claims presents what is 'social' as 'legal', and thus enables "the juridical argument [to

    return] to the fore" throughpresenting social bodies as laws (Althusser 1972: 68).

    This argument supports Althusser's claim that Montesquieu's despotic form represents

    a regime without laws, a limit-form with neither legal-political nor social structures.2

    However, while this figure of the despot as a ruler without laws can certainly be found

    in various places within Montesquieu's work it is contradicted in others, and as the

    reading of Robertson's below demonstrates this usage of 'despotism' as a 'regime

    without laws' was not predominant within eighteenth century historiography, where

    despotism generally appears as a simple legal-political structure, the fundamental laws

    of which establish the absolute rather than moderated power of the prince.

    ROBERTSON ON THE FUNDAMENTAL LAWS OF DESPOTISM IN TURKEY

    AND PERU

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    9/33

    8

    The maxims of Turkish policy do not authorize any of those institutions,

    which, in other countries, limit the exercise, or moderate the rigour of

    monarchical power: they admit neither of any great court with constitutional

    and permanent jurisdiction to interpose, both in enacting laws, and in

    superintending the execution of them; nor of a body of hereditary nobles,

    whose sense of their own preeminence, whose consciousness of what is due to

    their rank and character, whose jealousy of their privileges circumscribe the

    authority of the prince, and serve not only as a barrier against the excesses of

    his caprice, but stand as an intermediate order between him and the people.

    (Robertson 1792a: 224)

    This passage comes from The History of the Reign of Emperor Charles V(1769),

    where William Robertson contrasts the 'Asiatic despotism' of the Ottoman Sultans

    with the "monarchical and republican forms of government" found in the European

    states that he discusses in the preceding pages of that work (Robertson 1792a: 224).

    The Montesquieuian character of Robertson's work is clearly evident here, and

    especially given its subject matter of Turkish despotism the casual reader might

    reasonably assume that this passage has in fact been taken fromL'esprit des lois itself.

    Indeed, passages such as this one led Nicholas Phillipson to declare Robertson "one of

    the most Montesquieuian of the Scottish historians" (Phillipson: 61), and one can find

    therein each of the core aspects of Montesquieu's account of the differences between

    monarchy and despotism. Furthermore, given the sales of Robertson's Charles V(in

    both English and French) one can assume that Robertson's account of the Turks had

    considerable influence on the literary reproduction ofL'esprit des lois during the late

    eighteenth century.3 One significant aspect of that reproduction is the emphasis on

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    10/33

    9

    the distinction betweenfundamental and occasionallaws within Robertson's account

    of the despotic form of government, with its crucial defining characteristic being the

    absence of a social division ofpouvoirs (and the constitution of 'intermediate orders'),

    rather than an absence of laws and forms of social subordination (or 'social ranks').

    This aspect of Robertson's use of Montesquieu is evident when we consider how he

    defended his use of the concept of despotism against Sir James Porter in the 'Notes

    and Demonstrations' that close the first volume ofCharles V. Porter argued against

    Robertson in the introduction to the second edition of his Observations on the

    Religion, Law, Government, and Manners of the Turks (Porter 1771) that the Ulema

    whom in Montesquieu's terms constitute part of the 'clergy' moderate the power of

    the Sultans in exercising the judicial power of government (Porter 1771: xixxx);

    Robertson responded to this critique is the 1787 edition ofCharles Vby arguing that

    whatever authority the Ulema might have derives not from a fundamental law giving

    them a share in powers of government but rather from their role as ministers of

    religion, and thus (in accordance with Montesquieu) represents an accidental rather

    than a constitutional constraint, and that it is therefore the case that the form of

    government under the Ottomans remains despotic (Robertson 1792a: 470472).

    To better understand Robertson's rejoinder to Porter's argument we can draw on

    Althusser's discussion of the distinctions betweenfundamental and occasional laws

    and accidental and constitutional constraints within Montesquieu's theory. Althusser

    notes that Montesquieu divides real laws into 'fundamental' and 'occasional' laws:

    fundamental laws being those laws that are "constitutive of the regime" and which

    determine the form of government, while occasional laws "are decreed in response to

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    11/33

    10

    events" (Althusser 1972: 62). Laws of the first category of laws are logically if not

    historically anterior to any given regime, while those of the second depend on them.

    The exercise of power depends upon the establishment of fundamental laws, even if

    those laws establish an unmoderated, despotic form of government; thus when we

    turn to consider Montesquieu's account of despotism we find that even it has a

    fundamental law, namely the delegation of undivided absolute authority:

    A man whom his senses continually inform that he himself is everything and

    that his subjects are nothing, is naturally lazy, voluptuous, and ignorant. It

    is, therefore, more natural for him to resign [the management of public affairs]

    to a vizier, and to invest him with the same power as himself. The creation of

    a vizier is a fundamental law of [despotic] government.

    (Montesquieu 1949: 18)

    This structure of delegation is replicated at each subordinate level, with authority

    being distributed via a pyramidal structure of organization in which each subordinate

    retains the same unlimited power over all below him that his superior holds over

    himself, down to the lowliest subject, whom, as a father and head of household,

    retains absolute power within his realm (Montesquieu 1949: 3233). While this law

    establishes the distribution of power and the mode in which it is exercised it does not

    entail a social division of power at all, in that none of these subordinate offices

    represents the establishmentof 'intermediate orders' in Montesquieu's sense, as the

    retention of any power delegated to a subordinate remains contingent on the whim of

    that superior: any office can be lost at any time and there is no secure inheritance or

    transfer of status and goods.4 The issue here is not the absence of laws but rather that

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    12/33

    11

    this fundamental law establishes the absolute and undivided social character of the

    exercise of power rather than the monarchical moderation of the power of the prince

    throughthe combination, fusion and liaison of socialpuissances (Althusser 1972: 90).

    Robertson discusses the nature of the government of the Ottoman Sultans in exactly

    these terms in Charles V, emphasizing the absence of 'intermediate orders' and its

    dependence on maintaining compliance and servility through theprinciple of fear.5

    This distinction between despotism and monarchy in terms not of the presence or

    absence of laws but rather the presence or absence of a constitutional division of the

    pouvoirs between established socialpuissances allows Robertson to provide an

    effective rejoinder to Porter's critique, which uses the presence of a 'fixed' body of

    laws (based in the Koran) and, crucially, a hereditary order of legal interpreters (the

    Muftis) to claim that the Turkish government is monarchical rather than despotic

    (Porter 1771: xxxxxxiii). Here Robertson demarcates between 'constitutional' and

    'accidental' restraints on sovereign power, a distinction that he takes directly from

    L'esprit des lois, where Montesquieu claims that religion represents a substantial

    restraint upon the conduct of the Sultans with regard to practices proclaimed in the

    Koran to be sinful (haram), and suggested there that while the subjects of the Sultan

    "will abandon, nay they will slay a parent, if the prince so commands he cannot

    oblige them to drink wine" (Montesquieu 1949: 28). Here Robertson claims that the

    absence of 'constitutional restraints' on sovereign power entails that the limits on

    Ottoman despotism are 'accidental' only, being limited to the capacity of the 'ministers

    of religion' and the military to withdraw or supply their ideological and repressive

    support (Robertson 1792a: 231). This restraint on government is 'accidental' in that it

    acts upon the government not from inside, via the regular functioning of its 'channels'

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    13/33

    12

    of power, but rather from the outside, through their influence on popular violence

    and/or submission. This leads Robertson to suggest in a critique of Porter that

    echoes the critique that James Mill would make of Robertson'sHistorical Disquisition

    three decades later in The History of British India (1817)6 that such accidental limits

    on the conduct of the Sultans derive ultimately from the dread of insurrection:

    There is not in Turkey any constitutional restraint upon the will of the

    sovereign, of any barrier to circumscribe the exercise of his power, but the two

    which I have mentioned: one afforded by religion, the principle upon which

    the authority of the Sultan is founded; the other by the army, the instrument

    which he must employ to maintain his power. The author [i.e., Porter]

    represents the Ulema, or body of the law, as an intermediate order between the

    monarch and the people. But whatever restraint the authority of the Ulema

    may impose upon the sovereign, is derived from religion. TheMoulahs, out of

    whom the Mufti and other chief orders must be chosen, are ecclesiastics. It is

    as interpreters of the Koran or Divine Will that they are objects of veneration.

    The check, then, which they give to the exercise of arbitrary power cannot

    be very considerable. The Mufti, who is the head of the order, as well as every

    inferior officer of law, is named by the Sultan, and is removable at his

    pleasure. The strange means employed by the Ulema in 1746, to obtain the

    dismission of a minister whom they hated, is a manifest proof that they

    possess but little constitutional authority which can serve as a restraint upon

    the will of the sovereign. If the author's [i.e., Porter's] idea be just, it is

    astonishing that the body of the law should have no method of remonstrating

    against the errors of the administration, but by setting fire to the capital.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    14/33

    13

    (Robertson 1792a: 471472)

    In this passage Robertson emphasizes that the Sultan retains the judicialpouvoir, in

    that the Mullahs are all 'named by the Sultan, and removable at his pleasure'; in other

    words, the only fundamental law at work here is the contingent delegation of absolute

    power to a 'subordinate officer', in this case an officer of the law. Furthermore, as

    Althusser notes in his reading of Montesquieu, the judicialpouvoir does not really

    constitute a power to be balanced against others (Althusser 1972: 90; Montesquieu

    1949: 156159); rather its importance consists on the fact that the constitutional

    exclusion of the prince from exercising that power necessarily forces the power of the

    prince to flow through the 'proper channels' (Althusser 1972: 69). Thus while there

    are 'social ranks' in Robertson's Turkey there are no 'intermediate social bodies' no

    puissance of 'the great' that would constitute its form of government as monarchical.

    This does not mean, however, that the Sultans of Turkey are necessarily tyrants: while

    relations between social forces under despotism are immediate and unmoderated

    Robertson suggests that this form of government is only rarely tyrannical, at least with

    respect to the common people; indeed, as Althusser notes inMontesquieu, while fear

    remains theprinciple inherent to the retention of despotic power vis--vis those

    subordinates to whom the prince's power is delegated the common people, on the

    other hand, "know a kind of peace" (Althusser 1972: 84). Indeed, Robertson suggests

    that a certain peace is essential to the reproduction of despotism, and that, therefore,

    pace Porter, the absence of tyranny is not evidence of the absence ofdespotism.7

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    15/33

    14

    Robertson develops Montesquieu's account of despotism further in this direction in

    the account of Peru in his next work, The History of America (1777), in which he

    claims that social tranquility, despotic power, and a complete and regular social

    system of subordination combine in what represents "the most absolute of all

    despotisms" through the specific constitutional role of the Peruvian religion

    (Robertson 1792b: 210212):

    The most singular and striking circumstance in the Peruvian government, is

    the influence of religion upon its genius and laws. [T]he whole system of

    civil policy was founded on religion. The Inca appeared not only as a

    legislator, but as the messenger of Heaven. His precepts were received not

    merely as the injunctions of a superior, but as the mandates of a Deity. His

    race was held to be sacred; and in order to preserve it distinct, without being

    polluted by any mixture of less noble blood, the sons of Manco Capac married

    their own sisters, and no person was ever admitted to the throne who could not

    claim it by such a pure descent. To these Children of the Sun the people

    looked up with the reverence due to beings of a superior order. They were

    deemed to be under the immediate protection of the deity from whom they

    issued, and by him every order of the reigning Inca was supposed to be

    dictated. Whenever the decrees of a prince are considered as the commands

    of the Divinity, it is not only an act of rebellion, but of impiety, to dispute or

    oppose his will. Obedience becomes a duty of religion; as it would be profane

    to control a monarch who is believed to be under the guidance of Heaven, and

    presumptuous to advise him, nothing remains but to submit with implicit

    respect.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    16/33

    15

    (Robertson 1792b: 204205)

    While Robertson claims that the Islamic religion constitutes an accidental constraint

    on Turkish despotism it is clear that he understands the religion of Peru to constitute

    thefundamental law that founds the absolute power of the Incas. Thus Robertson

    argues that while a regular gradation of social ranks was established in Peru the divine

    authority of the Inca did not allow for the powers of government to be divided and

    shared with other social ranks such that those powers could counter that power, and

    that thus the relations of even the most noble ranks of Peruvian society to the Incas

    remained one of abject servility (Robertson 1792b: 205). Under such a constitution

    private, inheritable property cannot exist, and all lands remained vested in the person

    of the Inca. Thus although a third of all arable land was divided each year according

    to "the rank, the number, and the exigencies of each family" it was granted anew each

    year, with another third being set aside for the temples of the Sun, with the remaining

    third being set aside for the uses of government (Robertson 1792b: 21011). This

    division of lands, combined with the lack of other large cities, meant the division of

    labor was limited, with only those "artists employed in works of mere curiosity or

    ornament" being separated from the remainder of the population within the division of

    labor, with the those "arts which were of daily and indispensible utility [being]

    exercised by every Peruvian indiscriminately" (Robertson 1792b: 224).

    For Robertson each of these facts flows directly from the 'Divinity' of the Incas.

    Religion could not limit the power of the Inca, given that the Inca's authority is

    established as 'supernatural' in character. Thus the effects of the state religion of Peru

    were very different from the effects of Islam vis--vis Turkish despotism, in that it

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    17/33

    16

    was not an accidental restraint from the outside but rather constitutive of the most

    perfect form of despotism (one without a single instance of tyranny or rebellion).8

    Thus, to sum up, we find in Robertson's accounts of Turkey and Peru two very

    different historical examples of despotism that are established by fundamental laws;

    both of these books by Robertson reproduce import aspects of Montesquieu's work

    but also place a much stronger emphasis on the effects of religion on government.

    The singularity of these two instances of despotism in relation to their state religions

    appears in a clearer light when we consider Robertson's account of the ancient

    constitution of India inAn Historical Disquisition Concerning the Knowledge Which

    the Ancients Had of India (1791).

    ROBERTSON ON THE FUNDAMENTAL LAW OF 'CASTE' IN INDIA

    Though monarchical government was established in all the countries of India

    to which the knowledge of the ancients extended, the sovereigns were far from

    possessing uncontrolled or despotic power. No trace, indeed, is discovered

    there, of any assembly, or public body, the members of which, either in their

    own right, or as representatives of their fellow-citizens, could interpose in

    enacting laws, or in superintending the execution of them. Institutions

    destined to assert and guard the rights belonging to men in social state, how

    familiar soever the idea may be to the people of Europe, never formed a part

    of the political constitution in any great Asiatic kingdom. It was to different

    principles that the natives of India were indebted for restrictions which limited

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    18/33

    17

    the exercise of regal power. The rank of individuals was unalterably fixed,

    and the privileges of the different casts were deemed inviolable.

    (Robertson 1794: 238239)

    One of the most interesting developments of Montesquieu's theory in the work of

    Robertson is his defense of the Indian institution of 'caste' as the fundamental law of

    an ancient Indian variation of the monarchical form. Robertson claims that this

    institution not only established the privileges of the various ranks, but also established

    the division of labour9 and most crucially fixed both the station of every family

    within those orders and that division of labour in perpetuity, thus preventing any

    individual leaving their caste for another and in the process allocating specific

    pouvoirs to certain 'social bodies' orpuissances:

    The whole body of the people was divided into four orders or casts. [No

    individual] can ever quit his own cast, or be admitted to another. The station

    of every individual is unalterably fixed; his destiny is irrevocable; and the

    walk of life is marked out, from which he must never deviate. This line of

    separation is established not only by civil authority, but confirmed and

    sanctioned by religion, and each order or cast is said to have proceeded from

    the Divinity in such a different manner, that to confound them would be

    deemed an act of most daring impiety.

    (Robertson 1794: 231232)

    In terms of Montesquieu's theory of moderation as a 'balance of powers' the most

    important aspect of caste is its constitutional division of thepouvoirs of government

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    19/33

    18

    between the Raja (and his Kshatriyacaste) and the Brahmin (or 'priestly') caste as aresult of the relations between their specified professions and the doctrine of spiritual

    pollution, such that while the executivepouvoir is allocated to the Raja and can only

    be delegated to subordinate members of his own caste the judicialpouvoir must be

    allocated to the Brahmins, whom not only retain ritual superiority vis--vis the Raja

    but also retain a strict monopoly of direct knowledge of the sacred texts (Robertson

    1794: 330), including those containing the laws.

    Indeed, the role of the Brahmin caste is crucial, as it not only constitutes a 'depository

    of the laws' but also forces the power of the sovereign to flow through established

    channels, and thus the prince is not only profane in stark contrast to Peru but also

    unable engage with the Divine Will except via the sacred intermediaries of the order

    of Brahmins, which in no sense resembles the servile 'nobility' of Peru:

    The members of the first [cast], deemed the most sacred, were the priests,

    the instructors, and philosophers of the nation. The monarchs of India

    behold among their subjects an order of men far superior to themselves in

    dignity, and so conscious of their own pre-eminence, both in rank and in

    sanctity, that they would deem it degradation and pollution, if they were to eat

    of the same food with their sovereign. Their persons are sacred, and even for

    the most heinous crimes, they cannot be capitally punished; their blood must

    never be shed. To men in this exalted station monarchs must look up with

    respect, and reverence them as the ministers of religion, and the teachers of

    wisdom. On important occasions, it is the duty of sovereigns to consult them,

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    20/33

    19

    and to be directed by their advice. Their admonitions, and even their censures,

    must be received with submissive respect.

    (Robertson 1794: 231240)

    Compare this with Robertson's account of Peru, where "all crimes" even those

    committed by the most 'noble' ranks of Peruvian society "were punished capitally

    as insults offered to the Deity" (Robertson 1792b: 206), whereas the 'person' of a

    Brahman remains 'sacred' and 'their blood must never be shed', 'even for the most

    heinous crimes.' Here we can see how this fundamental law of 'caste' (and the

    strictures against 'spiritual pollution' that it entails) constitutes (in Robertson's

    account) not only the monarchical nature of the Indian government but also its

    principle, in that it certainly represents a 'sense of their own pre-eminence' and a

    'consciousness of what is due to their rank and character', together with a definite

    'jealousy of their privileges' in other words, all of the features of Montesquieu's

    monarchical principle of 'honour'. Furthermore, this law not only establishes the

    sacred authority of the Brahmins and a division of thepouvoirs between that caste and

    the Raja but also establishes and reproduces the remainder of the Raja's caste as an

    'intermediate social body' orpuissance with a share in thepouvoirs of government:

    The members of the second order were entrusted with the government and

    defence of the state. In peace they were its rulers and magistrates, in war they

    were the generals who commanded its armies and the soldiers who fought its

    battles. While the sacred rights of the Brahmins opposed a barrier against

    the encroachments of regal power on the one hand, [that power] was

    circumscribed on the other by the ideas which those who occupied the highest

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    21/33

    20

    stations in society entertained of their own dignity and privileges. As none but

    the members of the cast next in rank to that which religion has rendered

    sacred, could be employed in any function of the state, the sovereigns of the

    extensive kingdoms anciently established in India, found it necessary to

    entrust them with the superintendence of the cities and provinces too remote to

    be under their own immediate inspection. In those stations they often acquired

    such wealth and influence, that offices conferred during pleasure, continued

    hereditarily in their families, and they came gradually to form an intermediate

    order between the sovereign and his subjects; and, by the vigilant jealousy

    with which they maintained their own dignity and privileges, they constrained

    their rulers to respect them, and to govern with moderation and equity.

    (Robertson 1794: 232241)

    The remainder of Robertson's appendix to hisHistorical Disquisition can be read as

    supporting this thesis. His claims of the 'high civilization' of ancient India contrast

    with his altogether more circumspect and mixed assessments of Mexico and Peru in

    The History of America, and while this might be read in part as an argument in favor

    of religious toleration it is more the case that these are the effects one would expect to

    find in a moderate monarchy with what he assumed to be based on the volume of

    the 'India trade' in both ancient and modern times a wealthy mercantile economy.10

    Despite recent claims that Robertson abandoned the concept of despotism in this last

    work the dependence of this positive view of ancient India largely depends upon a

    contrast with the rule of India's 'despotic' Muslim conquerors,11 as is evident in those

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    22/33

    21

    passages where Robertson claims that the fundamental law of caste despite finding

    its origin in an 'arbitrary arrangement' 'fixes' the 'genius' and 'character' of the

    Hindus of India in such a manner that not even the "ferocious violence and

    fanaticism" of the Muslim invaders renders them mutable: "What is now in India

    always was there, and is likely still to continue: neither the ferocious violence and

    fanaticism of its Mahomedan conquerors, nor the power of its European masters, have

    effected any considerable alteration" (Robertson 1794: 235). This thesis fits well with

    that which was soon to predominate within Orientalist scholarship, and which can be

    seen in embryo in theHistorical Disquisition: the hypothesis of a 'degradation' of the

    Hindus under the effects of Muslim rule.12 Robertson's deployment of this thesis is not

    simply an anachronistic anomaly within an otherwise 'liberal' text; rather Robertson's

    claims of the effects of 'illiberal' Islamic despotism and, indeed, his conventional

    claim that the 'liberal' emperor Akbar represents the exception that proves the rule

    (Robertson 1794: 249250) reveal not only the persistence of the concept of

    despotism within his work but also that his understanding of the monarchical form of

    government remained dependent upon the figure of despotism as its definitive Other.13

    THE STATE MACHINE AND THE IDEOLOGY OF LAW

    [T]he state is a machine for producing legal power because even when

    the state is despotic, and 'dictatorial' to boot, it always has an interest,

    practically speaking, in basing itself on laws; if necessary, laws of exception,

    even, if necessary, in order then to violate or arbitrarily 'suspend' them. As

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    23/33

    22

    we all know, to our consternation, the most tyrannical and fanatical, the most

    horrible states gave themselves laws, endowed their regimes of terror and

    extermination with laws: Hitler promulgated laws concerning the Jews and the

    extermination of Jews. We also know that no state on earth is more

    punctilious about its own laws than the USSR, where there rages a form of

    repression that is legally selective and thus protected, since it is required by

    law. The state, in this respect, is a machine for producing legal power.

    (Althusser 2006: 106107)

    The figure of Montesquieu rarely appears in Althusser's work after 1960, and even in

    his Soutenance d'Amiens part of which was supposedly dedicated to a defense of his

    first book he barely mentions Montesquieu at all, and focuses instead on his broader

    intervention within the history of eighteenth century political thought, of which

    Montesquieu formed a portion, devoting considerable space within that defense to the

    works of Rousseau and, especially, Machiavelli (Althusser 1990: 205209).14 Despite

    this G.M. Goshgarian has drawn our attention to the continuities between

    Montesquieu and Althusser's (post1965) self-criticism, especially in relation to his

    critiques of Stalinism, Kruschevism, and Eurocommunism. This is clearest in a

    section of Goshgarian's introduction to the Philosophy of the Encounter, where he

    illuminates a striking continuity in the use of one particular metaphor inMontesquieu

    and the (previously unpublished manuscript) 'Marx in his limits', written almost two

    decades later. This metaphor, included in the passage above, is that of the state as a

    machine that runs only on a certain fuel, and thereby transforms one form of energy

    (heat) into another (motion).15 This continuity, however, conceals an important

    divergence: inMontesquieu Althusser uses this metaphor in relation to the

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    24/33

    23

    determination in the last instance of the principle in Montesquieu's three forms of

    government, with theprinciple being represented as "the intersection of the nature of

    the government with the real life of men" (Althusser 1972: 46), grasped in terms of

    their manners and morals (which, in terms of Althusser's subsequent work, we might

    understand as 'ideology'),16 while in 'Marx in his limits' this metaphor is used to

    elucidate the transformation of the violence of the class struggle intopower in the

    form of law, through the 'rule of law' and the 'neutrality of the state' (Althusser 2006:

    108110).17

    The thesis presented in this essay of the centrality to the Montesquieuian problematic

    of the establishment of some real law whether that law be 'religious' or 'secular' in

    origin as afundamental law might open another path betweenMontesquieu and

    Althusser's late work, in this case via the concept of 'reproduction' from his essay

    'Ideology and the Ideological State Apparatuses' (and the manuscript from which that

    was extracted, published as Sur Reproduction) and the concept of 'to take hold' or 'gel'

    (prendre) from his late work on Machiavelli and the manuscript 'The Underground

    Current of the Materialism of the Encounter' (Suchting 2004: 15). We might argue,

    following these late works, that the establishment of a fundamental law is thinkable

    only from "the point of view of reproduction" (Althusser 1971: 131), in the 'taking

    hold' of a heterogeneous ensemble of elements including not only manners and morals

    but also various pre-existing legal forms, which might have been 'occasional' or even

    'fundamental' laws in a previous life. Such an assemblage would only take hold if,

    among other conditions, such laws can provide the conditions of existence of the

    nature-principle unity of a possible form of government. While this essay has focused

    on the non-European examples within the works of Montesquieu and Robertson this

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    25/33

    24

    would also be the case for Montesquieu's model for the 'monarchy of the future' (the

    English constitution), in which we can detect the combination of at least two different

    bodies of law: first, as Bernard Edelman notes in his reading of the Grundrisse, the

    'reprise' of Roman property law, which it has combined with the bourgeois subject-

    form; and, second, the 'rediscovery' of the 'Gothic constitution', which Montesquieu

    claimed the English found, as Althusser notes, "'in the woods' of their past" (Edelman

    1979: 103104; Althusser 1972: 94).18 Robertson's cases of Peru and India not only

    illustrate how Montesquieu's concepts were modified in the course of debates on non-

    European regimes but also represent just two examples of aleatory assemblages of

    singular elements that took hold and lasted a long time, even if not forever.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    26/33

    25

    ENDNOTES

    1 One could claim here that, as Althusser claimed with regard to Marx's errors in his

    account of Feuerbach, Althusser "needed this mistake" (Althusser 2006: 65) in order

    to complete this intervention against juridical interpretation of Montesquieu.

    2 "The first feature of despotism is the fact that it is a political regime which has so to

    speak no structure. Neither legal-political nor social. Montesquieu repeats several

    times that despotism has no laws, and by that we should understand first of all no

    fundamental laws." Althusser 1972: 76.

    3 The first quarto edition sold nearly 3,000 copies in the first four months after its

    publication, even at the expensive price of 2 12s 6d. According to Richard Sher,

    more than 3,500 quarto and 5,000 octavo sets had been sold by the British publishers

    by 1785, not including other editions published in Ireland and Pennsylvania, and the

    French translation that first appeared in 1771. Sher 1992: 164195.4 "In a despotism nothing distinguishes between men: it is the realm ofextreme

    equality which lowers all subjects to the same uniformity It is the suppression of

    orders by a general leveling down. No hereditary order, no nobility: this sanguinary

    regime cannot tolerate greatness in blood. Nor greatness in goods: the tyrant cannot

    suffer the continuity of 'families' that time enriches and the succession and effort of

    generations elevate in human society. Better, he cannot tolerate any of the greatnesses

    of establishment that he himself confers on certain of his subjects. For ultimately a

    vizir, governors, bashaws and cadis are needed! But this greatness is only occasional,

    taken back the moment it is conceded, almost evanescent. It is nothing the moment it

    has arrived. Every clerk may thus hold all the power of the despot, but his life is a

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    27/33

    26

    postponed disgrace or assassination: that is all his freedom, that is all his security!"

    Althusser 1972: 7778.

    5

    "Under the Turkish government, the political condition of every subject is equal. To

    be employed in the service of the Sultan, is the only circumstance that confers

    distinction. Even this distinction is rather official than personal, and so closely

    annexed to the station in which any individual serves, that it is scarcely communicated

    to the persons of those who are placed in them. The highest dignity in the empire

    does not give any rank or pre-eminence to the family of him who enjoys it. As every

    man, before he is raised to any station of authority, must go through the preparatory

    discipline of a long and servile obedience, the moment he is deprived of power, he

    and his posterity return to the same condition with other subjects, and sink back into

    obscurity. It is the distinguishing and odious characteristic of Eastern despotism, that

    it annihilates all other ranks of men, in order to exalt the monarch; that it leaves

    nothing to the former, while it gives everything to the latter; that it endeavours to fix

    in the minds of those who are subject to it, the idea of no relation between men but

    that of a master and of a slave, the former destined to command and to punish, the

    latter formed to tremble and to obey." Robertson 1792a: 224225.

    6 "Insurrection is a principle of salutary operation, under the governments of the East.

    To that is owing almost every thing which the people are left any where to enjoy.

    In a situation where there is no regular institution to limit the power of gratifying the

    will, the caprices, and the desires of the sovereign and his instruments, at the expense

    of the people, there is nothing which hinders the people from being made as

    completely wretched as the unbounded gratification, at their expense, of the will,

    caprices, and desires of those who have sovereign power over them can render human

    beings, except the dread of insurrection." Mill 1817: 630631.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    28/33

    27

    7 "[W]hen the form of government in any country is represented to be despotic, this

    does not suppose that the power of the monarch is continually exerted in acts of

    violence, injustice, and cruelty. Under governments of every species, unless some

    frantic tyrant happens to hold the scepter, the ordinary administration must be

    conformable to the principles of justice, and if not active in promoting the welfare of

    the people, cannot certainly have their destruction for its object." Robertson 1792a:

    470.

    8 "The dominion of the Incas, though the most absolute of all despotisms, was

    mitigated by its alliance with religion. The mind was not humbled and depressed by

    the idea of a forced subjection to the will of a superior; obedience, paid to one who

    was believed to be clothed with divine authority, was willingly yielded, and implied

    no degradation. The sovereign, conscious that the submissive reverence of his people

    flowed from their belief in his heavenly descent, was continually reminded of a

    distinction which prompted him to imitate that beneficent power which he was

    supposed to represent. In consequence of those impressions, there hardly occurs in

    the traditional history of Peru, any instance of rebellion against the reigning prince,

    and among twelve successive monarchs, there was not one tyrant." Robertson 1792a:

    208209.

    9

    "[T]he members of each cast adhere invariably to the profession of their forefathers.

    From generation to generation, the same families have followed, and will always

    continue to follow, one uniform line of life." Robertson 1794: 232233.

    10 Nicholas Phillipson and Karen O'Brien both emphasize this theme of 'religious

    toleration'. Phillipson 1992: 7273; O'Brien 1992: 91. For the passages in the

    Historical Disquisition discussing the trade in 'Indian manufactures' as evidence of

    'civilization' and 'moderation' see Robertson 1794: 236238.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    29/33

    28

    11 J.G.A. Pocock claims that in theHistorical Disquisition Robertson abandoned the

    concept of despotism altogether (Pocock 2005: 202), while Geoffrey Carnall is more

    circumspect in his suggestion that Robertson's attitude toward Muslim rulers was

    more positive than that of his contemporaries, claiming only that Robertson

    "emphasised the ability, ambition, [and] even the enlightenment of the Turkish

    monarchs ... Selim and Solyman the Magnificent", while "Robertson's supreme

    example of the enlightened ruler was Muslim, although an exceptional one." Carnall

    1992: 225.

    12 For an example see Robertson claim (in his account of the philosophy and sciences

    of India) that the Brahmins "have been so studiously depressed by [the] fanatical

    zeal [of the Mahomedan conquerors of India] that the modern members of that

    order are as far inferior to their ancestors in science as in power" and that this caste

    "derive[s] the most liberal sentiments which they entertain at present [from the

    writings of their ancient Pundits], and [thus] the wisdom for which they are now

    celebrated has been transmitted to them from ages very remote" (Robertson 1794:

    321). This thesis of the degeneration of Indian institutions and culture under the

    influence of Muslim despotism was one that was already gaining currency in 1790,

    and was soon elaborated by Sir Henry Thomas Colebrooke in a thesis of a 'Golden

    Age of Hinduism' that owed much to Edward Gibbon's narrative ofThe Decline and

    Fall of the Roman Empire. See Kopf 1969: 40.

    13 References to Muslim despotism and its effects abound within Robertson's

    appendix, even if these claims are more often than not couched in terms of the

    'illiberal', 'intolerant', and 'zealous' character of Islam. For examples see Robertson

    1794: 235, 243, 249, 262, 315, 321, 333334, 416, 423425.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    30/33

    29

    14 Montesquieu is mentioned again (almost in passing) inMachiavelli and Us

    (Althusser 1999: 1416). This relative absence of Montesquieu from the work of

    Althusser after 1959 places the claims of Mariana Valverde regarding the absence of

    Montesquieu from the work of Michel Foucault in a somewhat different light. See

    Valverde 2008: 145146.

    15 "If theprinciple of the government is its spring, that which makes it act, that is

    because it is, as the life of the government, quite simply its condition of existence.

    The republic will only 'go', to coin a phrase, on virtue, just as some motors will only

    go on petrol. Without virtue the republic will fall, as will monarchy without honour,

    despotism without fear." Althusser 1972: 46. "The state is a machine in the full,

    precise sense of that term, as established in the nineteenth century after the discovery

    of the steam engine, the electro-magnetic machine, and so on: that is to say, in the

    sense of a man-made device [dispositif] comprising a motor driven by the energy 1,

    plus a transmission system, the purpose of the whole being to transform a specific

    kind of energy (A) into another specific kind of energy (B)." Althusser 2006: 105.

    On the relations between these passages see Goshgarian 2006: xxxiixxxiv.

    16 Althusser claims (in his 'Letter on Art in Reply to Andr Daspre' of August 1966)

    that "ideology is identical with the 'lived' experience of human existence itself"

    (Althusser 1971: 204); from this we might assume that the 'principle' of a form of

    government represents the imaginary relation of subjects to their political conditions

    of existence as such, and thus constitutes a specific ideological form.

    17 See also the following passage, where Althusser notes that the state appears in

    liberal ideology as "a Neutral Institution that stands 'above the classes' [and] limits

    their struggle and their excesses in such a way as to guarantee that the 'public interest',

    or the 'general' or 'public' interest, will prevail." Althusser 2006: 119. As Goshgarian

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    31/33

    30

    notes, this seems to largely repeat the criticism contained in the following similar

    sentence fromMontesquieu: "The mythical notion of the nature of the State is to

    imagine that a political power can be established and exercised outside classes and

    over them, even in the general interests of society." Althusser 1972: 102; Goshgarian

    2003: xxi.

    18 Montesquieu, in contrast with Althusser, posits this as the location of an absolute

    origin: "This beautiful system was invented first in the woods." Montesquieu 1949:

    161.

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Althusser, L. (1971)Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, London: New Left

    Books.

    __ (1972) Politics and History: Montesquieu, Rousseau, Hegel and Marx, London:

    New Left Books.

    __ (1990) Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of the Scientists and Other

    Essays, London: Verso.

    __ (1999)Machiavelli and Us, London: Verso.

    __ (2006) Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 19781987, London: Verso.

    Carnall, G. (1992) "Robertson and Contemporary Images of India," in S.J. Brown

    (ed.), William Robertson and the Expansion of Empire, Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Comninel, G.C. (1989)Rethinking the French Revolution: Marxism and the

    Revisionist Challenge, London: Verso.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    32/33

    31

    Edelman, B. (1979) Ownership of the Image: Elements for a Marxist Theory of Law,

    London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Goshgarian, G.M. (2003) 'Introduction', in L. Althusser, The Humanist Controversy

    and Other Writings, London: Verso.

    __ (2006) 'Translator's Introduction', in L. Althusser, Philosophy of the Encounter:

    Later Writings, 19781987, London: Verso.

    Kopf, D. (1969)British Orientalism and the Bengal Renaissance: The Dynamics of

    Indian Modernization, 17731835, Berkley: University of California Press.

    Macherey, P. (1998)In a Materialist Way: Selected Essays, London: Verso.

    Mill, J. (1817) The History of British India, London: Baldwin, Craddock, and Joy.

    Montag, W. (1998) "Althusser's Nominalism: Structure and Singularity (19626),"

    Rethinking Marxism, Vol. 10, No. 3, 6473.

    Montag, W. (2003)Louis Althusser, Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Montesquieu, C-L. (1949) The Spirit of the Laws, New York: Hafner.

    O'Brien, K. (1992) "Robertson's Place in the Development of Eighteenth-Century

    Narrative History," in S.J. Brown, William Robertson and the Expansion of Empire,

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Phillipson, N. (1992) "Providence and Progress: An Introduction to the Historical

    Thought of William Robertson," in S.J. Brown, William Robertson and the Expansion

    of Empire, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Pocock, J.G.A. (2005)Barbarism and Religion: Barbarians, Savages, and Empires,

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Porter, Sir J. (1771) Observations on the Religion, Law, Government, and Manners of

    the Turks, 2nd edn, London: J. Nourse.

  • 7/28/2019 McInerney_Althusser_Montesquieu_Robertson

    33/33

    Robertson, W. (1792a) The Reign of Emperor Charles V, 7th edn, London: Strahan,

    Cadell, and Balfour, Vol. I.

    Robertson, W. (1792b) The History of America, 6th edn, London: Strahan, Cadell, and

    Balfour, Vol. III.

    Robertson, W. (1794)An Historical Disquisition Concerning the Knowledge Which

    the Ancients Had of India, 2nd edn, London: Strahan, Cadell, and Balfour.

    Sher, R.B. (1992) "Charles Vand the Book Trade: An Episode in Enlightenment

    Book Culture," in S.J. Brown, William Robertson and the Expansion of Empire,

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Suchting, W. (2004) "Althussers Late Thinking About Materialism,"Historical

    Materialism, Vol. 12, No. 1, 370.

    Valverde, M. (2008) "Law versus History: Foucault's Genealogy of Modern

    Sovereignty," in M. Dillon and A.W. Neal, Foucault on Politics, Security and War,

    Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan.