53
Leftovers

Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Leftovers

Page 2: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

The Gambler’s Fallacy

Page 3: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Independent Events

Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower the probability of B.

Pr(B/ A) =Pr(B)

Page 4: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Games of Chance

Games of chance, like dice-rolling, coin-flipping, roulette, etc. involve random, independent events.

What side a coin lands on is independent of what happened on previous tosses.

Page 5: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Tossing Coins

Let HHHHH abbreviate a run of 5 tosses of a coin, each of which lands heads.

Pr(HHHHH) = 1/25 = 1/32

Imagine that you toss a fair coin 5 times and it lands heads each time. That’s pretty rare!

Page 6: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Six Tosses

What is the probability that the next toss will land heads? You might think it was even more unlikely, because:

Pr(HHHHHH) = 1/26 = 1/64

And yes, it is very unlikely for a coin to land heads six times in a row!

Page 7: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

But…

But we are not interested in Pr(HHHHHH)! We are interested in Pr(Heads on next toss/ HHHHH)– the probability the coin will land heads assuming that it landed heads five times in the past.

Page 8: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Two Possibilities

Tosses First Second Third

Fourth Fifth Sixth

Possibility 1 H H H H H HPossibility 2 H H H H H T

This is the past. It cannot change.

Page 9: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Two Possibilities

Tosses First Second Third

Fourth Fifth Sixth

Possibility 1 H H H H H HPossibility 2 H H H H H T

One in two chance of heads next flip.

Page 10: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

The Gambler’s Fallacy

The gambler’s fallacy is when someone assumes that if something happens more often in the past, it will happen less often in the future.

Page 11: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Monte Carlo

On 18 August 1913, the ball on one of the roulette wheels at the Monte Carlo Casino in Monaco fell black 26 times in a row.

Page 12: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Improbable!

In roulette, the ball has a 50-50 chance of landing red or black. So the probability of landing black 26 times in a row is:

1/226 = 1/67108864

Page 13: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Improbable!

But in fact, the probability of any sequence of reds and blacks is:

1/226 = 1/67108864

And the probability of landing red (or black) after any sequence is always 1/2.

Page 14: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Losing Money

On that night in 1913, gamblers bet millions of French francs against black.

Each time the wheel landed black, they became more and more certain it would land red the next time, and bet increasingly large sums… which they lost.

Page 15: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Children

People commit the gambler’s fallacy frequently. A lot of people think that if you have three daughters, your next child will be a boy.

But the probability of having a boy is always 50%. It’s independent of the children you previously had.

Page 16: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

Page 17: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Every A is a B

A

B

Page 18: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Every dog is an animal

Dog

Animal

Page 19: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

Every dog is an animal:Being an animal is a necessary condition for being a dog.Being a dog is a sufficient condition for being an animal.

Page 20: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Necessary Conditions

A necessary condition for X is any condition you must have if you are X.

If you are a dog you must be an animal. So being an animal is a necessary condition for being a dog.

If you are a triangle you must have three sides. So having three sides is a necessary condition for being a triangle.

Page 21: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Not Necessary

To show that some condition is not a necessary condition for X, you show that you can be X without having that condition.

Example: Dr. Asay once asked students to give a necessary condition for life. One student wrote “pork.” (I assume he or she meant “eating pork.”)

But you can be alive without eating pork. There are living vegetarians!

Page 22: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Sufficient Conditions

A sufficient condition for X is any condition whose presence is guaranteed by X.

If you are a dog, you are guaranteed to be an animal. So being a dog is a sufficient condition for being an animal.

If you are a square, you are guaranteed to have four sides. So being a square is a sufficient condition for having four sides.

Page 23: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Solving a Problem

Which of the following is true?a. Being a dog is necessary and sufficient for being an animal.b. Being a dog is necessary but not sufficient for being an animal.c. Being a dog is not necessary, but it is sufficient for being an animal.d. Being a dog is not necessary and not sufficient for being an animal.

Page 24: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Solving a Problem

Which of the following is true?a. Being a dog is necessary and sufficient for being an animal.

Every animal is a dog and every dog is an animal.b. Being a dog is necessary but not sufficient for being an animal.

Every animal is a dog but not every dog is an animal.c. Being a dog is not necessary, but it is sufficient for being an animal.

Not every animal is a dog, but every dog is an animal.d. Being a dog is not necessary and not sufficient for being an animal.

Not every animal is a dog and not every dog is an animal.

Page 25: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Solving a Problem

Which of the following is true?a. Being a dog is necessary and sufficient for being an animal.

Every animal is a dog and every dog is an animal.b. Being a dog is necessary but not sufficient for being an animal.

Every animal is a dog but not every dog is an animal.c. Being a dog is not necessary, but it is sufficient for being an animal.

Not every animal is a dog, but every dog is an animal.d. Being a dog is not necessary and not sufficient for being an animal.

Not every animal is a dog and not every dog is an animal.

Page 26: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Remember

X is a necessary condition for Y = Every Y is XX is a necessary condition for Y = If you are Y, then you are X

You cannot be Y without being X

X is a sufficient condition for Y = Every X is YX is a sufficient condition for Y = If you are X, then you are Y

X’s must be Y’s

Page 27: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Definitions

Page 28: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Types of Definitions

If you open up a dictionary, you find a bunch of definitions.

But not all definitions are trying to do the same thing. There are different types of definitions.

Page 29: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example

Uncle: a male brother of one’s father.

This definition gives an expression “male brother of one’s father” that means the same thing as the expression “uncle.”

Being a male brother of my father is a necessary and sufficient condition for being my uncle.

Page 30: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example

Uncle: a male brother of one’s father.

We call this definition a “descriptive” definition because it (accurately) describes the meaning of the word it defines.

Page 31: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example 2

Red: the color of a ripe tomato.

This definition is correct in the following sense: everything that is red is the same color as a ripe tomato and everything that is the same color as a ripe tomato is red.

Page 32: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example 2

Red: the color of a ripe tomato.

But this is not the meaning of the word ‘red.’ If tomatoes started ripening blue, that would not mean that water was red and the sky was red and blueberries were red…

Page 33: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example 2

Red: the color of a ripe tomato.

We call definitions like this “extensional” definitions. They allow you to pick out everything you can truly describe with the word (for example, ‘red’) without giving you the meaning of the word.

Page 34: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Stipulative Definition

A stipulative definition does not report the meanings of words as they are actually used.

Instead it introduces a new meaning, either for an already existing word, or for a new, made-up word.

Page 35: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Spotting Stipulative Definitions

There are many ways people have of indicating that they are stipulating a meaning:

• “Let us define X as…”• “In what follows, we will understand X to mean…”• “Suppose we say that a thing is X when…”

Page 36: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Purposes of Stipulative Definitions

Sometimes there is not a word for what you want to talk about, so you have to invent one.

Science and math are full of words with stipulative definitions. (“prime,” “composite,” “whole,” “continuous”…)

Page 37: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Precising Definitions

Precising definitions are a combination of descriptive and stipulative definitions. This is when you take the normal meaning of a word, and stipulate some aspects of its meaning.

“Criminals cannot apply for this job.”“Students get a set lunch discount.”

Page 38: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Using Precising Definitions

Precising definitions can often be used to resolve certain arguments.

“If by ‘marriage’ you mean that gays can have a religious ceremony, live together, and call each other ‘spouse’ then yes, gays can get married in our country; but if you mean by ‘marriage’ a recognition by the government and society of the validity of such a relationship, then they cannot.”

Page 39: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Summary

Descriptive definition: gives the meaning of a wordExtensional definition: does not give the meaning; categorizes the things that the word applies toStipulative definition: introduces a new meaning for a wordPrecising definition: takes the old meaning of a word and changes it in some way

Page 40: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

For the Sake of Argument

Page 41: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Assumptions for the Sake of Argument

Sometimes we make assumptions for the sake of argument.

We either know that the assumption is false or we don’t know whether it is true or false.

But in some cases it is useful to make false or unknown assumptions…

Page 42: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Conditional Proof

Suppose you want to prove a conditional (“if-then”) statement.

For example, suppose you want to show that if the accuser is telling the truth, then the accused should go to jail.

Page 43: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

The Accusation

Michael kicked me.

Page 44: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Assuming for the Sake of Argument

First, you would assume for the sake of argument that the accuser is telling the truth. Assume that Michael did in fact kick the puppy.

(Even though of course he’s innocent.)

Page 45: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Conditional Proof

Then you would use that assumption to show that Michael belonged in jail.

You would argue that since kicking puppies violates article 2, section 6, paragraph 3 of the criminal code, Michael belongs in jail.

Page 46: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Conditional Proof

Finally, you would stop assuming that Michael did actually kick the puppy and conclude:

If the accuser is telling the truth, then Michael belongs in jail.

Page 47: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Assume the Antecedent

If the accuser is telling the truth, then Michael belongs in jail.

Assume this

Page 48: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Prove the Consequent

If the accuser is telling the truth, then Michael belongs in jail.

Prove this

Page 49: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Conclusion

If the accuser is telling the truth, then Michael belongs in jail.

Conclude this (No longer assume the antecedent)

Page 50: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Reductio ad Absurdum

Another type of argument that makes assumptions we don’t believe is reductio ad absurdum (reduction to absurdity or proof by contradiction).

This is a common type of argument form in mathematics.

Page 51: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Example

Here’s a proof that there is no smallest rational number (number that can be expressed as a fraction.

Assume: There is a smallest rational number, N.Use mathematical reasoning: If N is rational, N/2 is rationalUse mathematical reasoning: N/2 < NConclude: N is not the smallest rational number.

The assumption is false because it leads to an absurdity!

Page 52: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Reductio

Step 1: Assume the opposite of what you’re trying to prove.Step 2: Prove something absurd by using that assumption.Step 3: Conclude the opposite of your assumption.

Page 53: Leftovers. The Gambler’s Fallacy Independent Events Two events A and B are independent if A does not raise the probability of B and A does not lower

Real Life Example

According to the defendant, he was at the library at the time of the crime.However, the crime occurred at 22:30, and the library is not open at that time.Therefore, the defendant was not at the library!