Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    1/39

     

    PHI 105 (1/19/09)An act is legal, if and only if, it’s permitted by the law.

    This is not what determines if an act is morally right or wrong.

    Ex.) Adultery, lying, historical example: Slavery.Acts that are morally permissible but illegal. Examples?

    Speeding late at night, little traffic no cameras. Smoking cannabis, which you grew yourself, in

    the privacy of your own home.

    Marrying someone of a different race in South Carolina prior to 1998.

    Moral claims are distinct from prudential claims.

    Morality is essentially tied to the welfare of others, whereas prudence is not.

    Imprudent: Not wise. Lack of caution I practical affairs.

    Prudent: careful and sensible; marked by sound judgment.

    Sometimes its morally impermissible to do what’s in your long-term best interest.

    Examples:Get refunded money for college, send all to Haiti.

    **Moral claims are distinct from claims about etiquette.

    I expect Doug not to pick his nose during class, but it’s not morally wrong.

    Etiquette: “Delineates expectations for social behavior according to contemporary conventional

    norms within a society, social class, or group.” (Wiki)

    Examples of some norms of etiquette?

    Morality, by contrast, delineates those actions for which we can rightly be held blameworthy

    or praiseworthy.

     Agents are necessarily blameworthy for freely and knowledgeably violating the requirements

    of morality, but agents are not necessarily blameworthy for freely and knowledgeablyviolating the requirements of etiquette.

    Whether a person is blame worthy only depends on if we believe what they did was wrong.

    What we have then is a disagreement of if what the person done is actually wrong or not.

    Normative Ethics (and its three branches)

    A theory of the Right: What makes an act right//wrong?

    A theory of the right takes the following firm:

    An act is morally permissible (or impermissible or obligatory or supererogatory (actions

    that go beyond the call of duty)) if and only if, and because… 

    Example: An act is morally impermissible if and only if, and because, it is forbidden by

    God.

    1/21/10

    Normative Ethics (Cont.)

    A Theory of the Good: What features of tings, events, or states of affairs make them good or

    bad?

    A Theory of Virtue: What character traits make a person virtuous or vicious?

    Meta-Ethics:

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    2/39

    Moral Language

    Moral Metaphysics

    Are their facts about what’s right or wrong?

    Moral Epistemology

    Study of knowledge. How do we know what the facts are.Moral Psychology

    What’s the relationship between making a moral judgment and being able to act

    accordingly?

    Applied Ethics:

    Is this or that particular type of action (e.g., abortion, capital punishment, affirmative action, etc.)

    right or wrong?

    Categories of Deontic Evaluation:

    Morally Obligatory – that which is required, that which it would be wrong to refrain from doing.

    Morally right/permissible – which is not prohibited.

    Morally optional – that which is neither required nor prohibited.

    Supererogatory  – that which is above and beyond what is morally required; that which is

    both morally optional and morally better than some other permissible alternative.

    Ex.) Bring a sick friend soup. Buy from store but you spend all day making soup.

    Merely permissible: that which is morally optional but not supererogatory.

    Divine Command Theory: What god says makes things right or wrong.

    The Aims of Moral Theory:

    Practical Aim: The main practical aim of moral theory is to discover a decision procedure that

    can be used as a guide in our moral deliberations about what to do.

    Theoretical Aim: The main theoretical aim of moral theory is to discover what underlying

    features of actions make them right and wrong and then, on that basis, to formulate a criterion

    of moral rightness that states the most general conditions under which actions are right or

    wrong.

    Moral Theorizing: The Method of Narrow Reflection Equilibrium you want to just keep going

    straight on one moral path. You want a theory that is consistant with your morals. - (An equilibrium

    in which you don’t want to change your intuition or moral)

    Start with some provisional moral judgments.

    Formulate some provisional moral theory (or general principle) that accounts for these

    provisional moral judgments.

    Test this provisional moral theory (or general principle) to see whether its implications conflict

    with any of your other moral judgments. When conflicts arise, it is an open question as to

    whether it is the theory or the judgments that need to be revised. Decide which to revise on the

    basis of which seems more intuitively plausible after reflection. Do this until no further revisions

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    3/39

    are necessary.

    An illustration via a set of cases:

    Does it matter is you chose to be in the situations or not? Or if you were forced to choose.

    The Boat Rescue (Save the 1 person or the 5)

    The Transplant (Kill your patient (non-consented) to save 5 people who need the

    patients organs)What’s the moral judgment that explains why you don’t save five people in

    the transplant?

    Right of self ownership?

    (1) It is permissible to let someone die to save five, but not

    permissible to kill one to save five.

    The Runaway Trolley

    Train can run through 5 people, unless you flip a switch which then makes the

    train run only over one person.

    If you choose to kill the one then (1) is flawed.

    You still kill one person through the action of killing that one person.Doctrine of allowing?

    ~Doing harm is wrong but allowing harm is ok?~

    Why we shouldn’t stop after having only reached a narrow reflective equilibrium.

    The method of narrow reflective equilibrium is too conservative. It helps to us to render our

    moral beliefs consistent, but we should not be satisfied with simply rendering our own beliefs

    consistent.

    To enrich our reflection, we must reflect on alternative theories, alternative judgments,

    counterarguments to our theory, counterarguments to our judgments, the source of moral

     judgments and the reliability of that source, our background assumptions, and our competencyto judge.

    The Method of Wide Reflective Equilibrium

    The method tells us to do three things (DePaul):

    Reflect on the interconnections among our beliefs.

    Leave nothing out of our reflections. Reflect not only on our own initial beliefs and their

    interconnections, but also on ourselves and our competency to judge, and reflect on alternative

    beliefs, theories, and arguments.

    Settle any conflicts that emerge, deciding what to believe on the basis of what seems to be the

    most intuitively plausible upon reflection.

    Is there any rational alternative to this?

    1/25

    DCT: An act is obligatory if and only it, and because, God commands it.

    H1: God commands/forbids certain actions, because they are obligatory/wrong.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    4/39

    H2: Actions are obligatory/wrong, because God commands/forbids them.

    A tyrant is someone who exerts power over others without either the proper moral authority of

    sufficient moral justification for doing so.

    2/2/10

    DTC (Cont.)On DCT, what is it to say that God is good?

    Answer: It’s to say that God is it doesn’t make sense with this view because it is to say

    something that god commands us to bring about or preserve. But, surely, this can’t be

    right. God’s not good. Not bad. Neutral.

    This is the depriving God of His goodness objection.

    Argument Against H1

    P1: If H1 is true, then God can’t change the fact that X is wrong (or right).

    P2: If God can’t change the fact that X is wrong (or right), then God isn’t omnipotent.

    P3: God is omnipotent.C: Therefore, H1 is false.

    What does it mean to say that God is omnipotent?

    Can God create a boulder that even He cannot lift?

    He can do anything that is logically possible. Anything that does not create a

    contradiction.

    The Problem of Evil

    The fact that X is wrong (or right) is either a necessary truth or a contingent truth. If it’s a

    necessary truth, we should reject P2. And if it’s a contingent truth, we should reject P1. So,

    either way, then, the argument is unsound.

    Necessary and contingent truths.Which of the following are necessary? Which are contingent?

    Barack Obama was the President of the United States in 2009. Contingent.

    Either it is the case that Doug has a wife or it is not the case that Doug has a wife. Necessary.

    Masses attract one another. Contingent.

    All bachelors are unmarried. Necessary.

    2/4/10

    Another Argument Against H1

    P1: If H1 is true, there’s a standard of right and wrong that’s independent of God.

    P2: If there’s a standard of right and wrong that’s independent of God, then God didn’t create

    morality.

    P3: If God didn’t create morality, then God isn’t the Creator of all that is.

    P4: God is the Creator of all that is.

    C: Therefore, H1 is false.

    Is this a good argument?

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    5/39

    Evaluating this argument

    P1. H1 claims only that morality is independent of God’s commands, not that morality is

    independent of God. Two Examples: (1) Fiona and her dad. (2) The laws of nature and

    God.

    Of course, one might argue that, unlike the laws of nature, the laws of morality are

    necessarily what they are. What then?We should, then, reject P4. He is not the creator of all that is. Only contingent truths.

    God is the Creator of that is contingent. After all, [Redacted].

    Some Conclusions

    The DCT/H2 seems to conflict with a number of common theistic tenets: (1) God is good. (2) that

    gos commands are not morally arbitrary, and (3) that God is not a tyrant.

    The DCT/H2 also implausibly implies that anything goes with regard to what’s right and wrong.

    H1, by contrast, conflicts with no theistic tenets. It’s compatible with both the idea that God is

    the creator of all that contingently is and with the idea that God is omnipotent.

    It seems, therefore, that even the theist should reject DCT and embrace H1.

    1. Moral Relativism

    What’s right and wrong for a person to do is ultimately determined by the fundamental (i.e., basic) moral

    norms of his or her culture.

    More precisely, moral relativism says: an act, A, performed by a subject, S, who is a member of a

    culture, C, is morally permissible if and only if, and because, the fundamental moral norms of C permits

    A to perform S.

    2. Definitions

    D1: C is a culture =df. C is a collection of people, often living in close proximity to each other, sharing aset of social norms, conventions, and practices.

    D2: X is a moral norm =df. X is a standard (that is, a rule or a principle) that renders some verdict

    regarding the moral status of some act-type (e.g., “it is wrong to commit adultery”).

    3. Continued 

    D3: X is a fundamental moral norm =df. X is a moral standard that doesn’t derive from any more

    fundamental moral standard. (e.g., the divine command theorist takes “it is wrong to act as God

    forbids” to be a fundamental moral norm).

    D4: X is a fundamental moral norm of C =df. the vast majority of the members of C believe that X is a

    fundamental moral standard.

    4. Moral Absolutism and Moral Non-Absolutism

    Moral absolutism is the view that certain types of acts are wrong no matter how valuable their

    consequences. Examples: Pacifists. Kant and the Inquiring Murderer.

    The distinction between an act-token and an act-type.

    Moral non-absolutism is the view that there are no types of acts that are wrong types of acts that are

    wrong no matter how valuable their consequences.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    6/39

    Note that there is a problem with defining the moral absolutist as one who believes that there are

    absolute (exception-less) moral rules. Consider act-consequentialism: an act is morally permissible if and

    only if, and because, there is no available alternative that would produce more good than it would.

    5. The Context-Sensitivity ThesisTimmons defines the thesis as follows:

    “The rightness or wrongness of an action (performed in some particular context) partly depends

    on nonmoral facts that hold in the context—facts concerning agents and their circumstances” (p.

    42).

    This thesis is fairly uncontroversial, but it should not be confused with moral relativism.

    Someone can accept this thesis and deny moral relativism. And someone can accept this thesis

    while also accepting moral relativism.

    6. Moral Objectivism

    Moral Objectivism (a.k.a. the Universality Thesis): There are universal moral norms that arebinding on all persons irrespective of the culture/society to which they belong. On moral

    objectivism, the truth of a moral claim/judgment does NOT depend on whether it

    conforms to the norms, beliefs, attitudes, or conventions of any group or individual. It

    depends, rather, on what the objective moral facts are.

    7. Continued…

    More precisely, moral objectivism says: an act, A, performed by a subject, S, is morally

    permissible if and only if, and because, the universal moral norms that are binding on all

    persons permit S to perform A.

    Examples: Act-Consequentialism; Divine Command Theory.Can the moral objectivist accept moral non-absolutism?

    8. A practice quiz (but first some preliminaries)

    P and Q are compatible =df. it is logically possible for both P and Q to be true.

    P and Q are incompatible =df. it is logically impossible for both P and Q to be true.

     Are the following sets of claims compatible?

     A1: John is married. A2: John is a bachelor. (Incompatible.)

    B1: John is a professional philosopher. B2: John is a rock star. (Compatible.)

    C1: John is not happy. C2: John is not unhappy. (Compatible.)

    D1: John is not insane. D2: John is not sane. (Incompatible.)E1: John Kerry is tall. E2: George W. Bush is a Democrat. (Compatible.)

    9. The Questions

    For each of the numbered claims below, state (a) whether it’s compatible or incompatible with

    moral relativism (MR) and (b) whether it’s compatible or incompatible with moral objectivism

    (MO).

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    7/39

    (C1) Acts of cruelty, slavery, terrorism, and genocide are wrong whether people or societies

    condemn or condone them.

    MR?

    MR: Incompatible. Thus. MR has some seriously counterintuitive implications.

    MO?

    MO: Compatible.

    10. Continued…

    (C2) In the United States, certain fundamental moral norms (e.g., those with regard to how

    women and minorities should be treated) have changed for the better.

    MR?

    MR: Incompatible. Note that, on MR there can be no moral progress in the sense of society's

    norms changing for the better. There can only be moral progress in the sense of peoples rate of

    compliance with the moral norms increases.

    11. Continued…MO?

    MO: Compatible. On MO, there is an objectively correct set of moral norms. And, thus, there

    can be moral progress when our society's moral norms change from those that are incorrect to

    those that are correct.

    12. Continued…

    (C3) The people of different societies accept different moral norms.

    MR?

    MR:  Compatible.

    MO?MO: Compatible. According to MO< there is one objectively correct set of moral norms. But the

    moral objectivist does not claim that all societies accept these norms or even that all societies

    will accept the same norms.

    13. Continued…

    (C4) Whether lying is right or wrong depends on the value of the consequences of doing so.

    MR?

    MR: Compatible.

    MO?

    MO: Compatible. The moral objectivist can be a moral non-absolutist.

    14. Continued…

    (C5) Although it would be wrong for DWP to let his grandparents freeze to death just so that he

    can use his disposable income to take a vacation rather than to pay their heating bill, it wasn’t

    wrong for the Eskimos to let their elders freeze to death as they sometimes did prior to the 20th

    century.

    MR?

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    8/39

    MR: Compatible.

    MO?

    15. Continued…

    MO: Compatible. The moral objectivist can accept C5 by asserting that the following is a

    universal moral norm: This principle yields different moral verdicts for DWP and the historicalEskimos given that their circumstances are/were very different. But, of course, if DWP did

    ever find himself in relevantly similar circumstances, then the moral objectivist must admit that

    DWP would be permitted to let his elders die.

    16. Continued…

    (C6) What it is right and wrong to do can depend on the customs of a given society.

    MR?

    MR: Compatible.

    MO?

    MO: Compatible. On MO, fundamental moral norms are universal, but the moral objectivist canaccept the context-sensitivity thesis and hold that derivative moral norms vary from one culture

    to another.

    17. Continued…

    Suppose that the following is a universal, fundamental moral norm: "Be polite to a gracious

    host." Given this principle, what should a man do before entering a church? A synagogue? What

    should someone do if invited into someone’s home in Japan? The mainland U.S.? Since what’s

    right and wrong to do can depend on what’s considered polite, and since what’s considered

    polite just depends on the customs of a given society, what it is right and wrong to do can

    (indirectly) depend on the customs of a given society

    18. Continued…

    (C7) Whether or not women should go around bare-breasted and whether or not men should

    wear a suit and tie to work is just a matter of custom. There is no objective truth about such

    matters.

    MR?

    MR: Compatible.

    MO?

    MO: Compatible. Arguable, norms of dress are not moral norms, but rather norms of etiquette.

    The moral objectivist is only committed to there being an objective truth about morality, notetiquette.

    19. Continued…

    (C8) One’s own society isn’t in a privileged position with regard to knowing what’s right and

    wrong for one to do.

    MR?

    MR: Incompatible. One's own society is in a privileged position with regard to knowing what's

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    9/39

    right and wrong for one to do, for, on MR, what's right and wrong for one to do just depends on

    what the norms of one's society.

    MO?

    MO: Compatible.

    20. Continued…(C9) People of all societies should be tolerant of one another’s religious beliefs.

    MR?

    MR: Incompatible. Whether or not someone should be tolerant of someone else's religios

    beliefs is a moral question. And, on MR, such moral questions are determined by the moral

    norms of one's culture. Since, in some cultures...

    21. Continued…

    MO?

    MO: Compatible. Indeed, since C9 is stating a universal moral norm, one most be an moral

    objectivist to accept C9.

    22. Why accept or reject moral relativism?

    Next, we will look at various arguments for and against moral relativism.

    23. The Moral Diversity Thesis (MDT)

    Many people accept MR on the basis of the following thesis.

    The Moral Diversity Thesis: People in different societies accept different fundamental moral

    norms (a.k.a. basic moral norms).

    Note that the MDT is a claim about what people believe to be true, whereas MR is claim about

    what is true.Is MDT true?

    24. The Argument for the Moral Diversity Thesis

    People in different societies make different moral judgments regarding the same type of action.

    If people in different societies make different moral judgments regarding the same type of action,

    they must accept different fundamental moral norms.

    Therefore, people in different societies accept different fundamental moral norms. (The Moral

    Diversity Thesis)

    25. P2 is falseSome other possible explanations for moral disagreement:

    Different Non-moral beliefs (Ex. Apply “One ought not kill sacred beings” to both Hindu and

    Christian cultures.)

    Different Customs (Ex. Apply “One ought to be polite to a gracious host.” to different

    cultural contexts.)

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    10/39

    26. Continued…

    Different Environmental Conditions  (Ex. Apply “Save people from death unless doing so

    will very likely increase the number of deaths overall.” to different environmental

    conditions.)

     Although P2 of the Argument for the Moral Diversity Thesis is false, it doesn’t follow that the

    moral diversity thesis is false. So, for the sake of argument, I will grant the proponent of moralrelativism that it is true. The following are two arguments based on the moral diversity thesis.

    27. The Argument from Fundamental Moral Disagreement, v1 (a.k.a. The Anthropologist’s

     Argument, v1)

    People in different societies accept different fundamental moral norms. (=MDT)

    If people in different societies accept different fundamental moral norms, then MO is false.

    Therefore, MO is false.

    28. Evaluating the Argument

    Is this a good argument?Well, as we saw, P1 is questionable.

    In any case, P2 is false. The fact that people disagree about X does not entail that there

    is no objective fact about X.

    Consider the shape of the Earth.

    29. The Argument from Fundamental Moral Disagreement, v2

    OBSERVATION: The quality and quantity of moral disagreement appears to differ significantly

    from the quality and quantity of disagreement that we find with regard to objective matters of fact

    (e.g., matters of science).

    EXPLANATION: One possible explanation for the observation in P1 is that there is no objectivemorality.

    COMPARISON: No other explanation for the observation in P1 provides at least as good an

    explanation as the explanation given in P2.

    Therefore, there is no objective morality.

    30. The Main Thrust of the Argument

    Some philosophers believe that what explains inter- and intra-societal moral disagreement is that

    there are simply no moral facts, but only differing moral attitudes. According to these

    philosophers, differences in moral belief are more readily explained by the hypothesis that they

    reflect people’s differing attitudes than by the hypothesis that they reflect people’s variousdistortions, misperceptions, or ignorance of an objective moral reality.

    31. Continued…

    Now we should note that there has been an awful lot of genuine disagreement in the areas of

    science and metaphysics, and from this, we do not conclude that there are no scientific facts

    and no metaphysical facts. So these philosophers must claim that moral disagreement is

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    11/39

    somehow more substantial or more fundamental than the kind of disagreement we find in these

    other areas where there is clearly some objective fact of the matter.

    32. Is moral disagreement more fundamental or substantial?

    We must keep the following in mind:

    There may be less moral disagreement and more moral agreement than you think.Disagreement about specific moral rules often issues from disagreement concerning the

    relevant non-moral facts. Consider, for example, the issues of abortion and capital punishment.

     And there is a fair amount of moral agreement. For example, there is wide agreement that

    suffering is bad and ought to be prevented.

    33. Continued…

    There may be more disagreement in the sciences than you think. At bottom, science relies on

    abductive reasoning. But there is nearly as much disagreement concerning the principles of

    abductive reasoning as there is concerning moral principles.

    Non-religious moral inquiry is relatively young compared to scientific inquiry. If we look atscientific inquiry in its infancy, there was a tremendous amount of disagreement. Yet we would

    have be wrong to conclude back then, that the best explanation for these disagreements was

    that there are no objective scientific facts.

    34. Continued…

    Consider that the breadth and depth of disagreement regarding other philosophical issues is no

    greater than that regarding moral issues in particular. Philosophers disagree just as much about

    metaphysical issues—such as, about whether God exists, about whether free will is compatible

    with determinism, and about whether the mind is identical to the brain—as they do about moral

    issues—such as, whether the ends justify the means. So we face a dilemma: either this breadthand depth of disagreement warrants denying objectivity about any of these issues or it warrants

    denying objectivity about none of these issues. But do we really believe that there is no objective

    fact as to whether, say, God exists?

    35. Problems with Moral Relativism

    Problems of Formulation

    The Problem of Intercultural Evaluation - cant evaluate other cultures based on our

    fundamentally moral norms.

    The Problem of Intracultural Evaluation -

    The Moral Reformer Problem - There is no objective truth about what's morally right orwrong so moral laws cant be reformed for the better. (Or worse)

    The Problem of Conflicts with Our Considered Moral Judgments

    36. Moral Relativism and Tolerance

    Suppose that we grant that moral relativism is true. Would it follow that people of all societies

    should be tolerant of each other’s differing norms and practices? After all, it’s not as if one’s

    society’s norms and practices would be any better than another society’s norms and practices,

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    12/39

    would it?

    37. Evaluating DCT

    Consistency

    Determinacy

    Intuitive AppealInternal Support

    Explanatory Power

    External Support

    38. Conclusions

    We’ve found no good argument in support of moral relativism.

    We’ve found that moral relativism, but not moral objectivism, is wildly at odds with our

    commonsense intuitions.

    Douglas Portmore

    LECTURE 4:

    Values in a Scientific World

    Last Updated: 1/28/10

    1. The Challenge for Moral Objectivism

    “Suppose, with [moral] objectivism, that moral judgments are true, and true quite independently

    of what we happen to think of them. They are true, when they are, because they accurately

    report objective moral facts. But the nature of such facts can appear very mysterious. We readily

    grant that geologists and chemists, physicists and astronomers deal in objective truth, because

    we believe that their findings are targeted on a natural world whose features exist independently

    of whether anyone recognizes them. Botanical facts are facts about plants; geological facts are

    facts about rocks….”

    2. The Challenge for Moral Objectivism (continued…)

    “…In botany and geology, evidence is supplied by three-dimensional, tangible, physical stuff. We

    can taste it, smell it, and see it. We can’t taste wrongness or hear rightness. Moral facts, if they

    were to exist, would have to be quite odd sorts of things, certainly nothing at all like the kinds of

    phenomena studied by the recognized sciences” (91).

    3. Are moral facts scientifically confirmable (i.e., scientifically verifiable)?

    Can we see, touch, taste, hear, or smell the wrongness of an act?

    Some reject the idea that there are moral facts given that moral facts are not scientifically

    confirmable.

    4. The Confirmation Test

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    13/39

     According to the confirmation test, a claim (or putative fact) is true if and only if it is

    scientifically confirmable (i.e., empirically verifiable).

    Note that only true claims can be confirmed. However, some true claims are not

    scientifically confirmable. For instance, we cannot scientifically confirm either that parallel

    lines do not intersect or that the sum of the angles of any triangle equals 180 degrees.

    The confirmation test cannot be true. If it were true, it would refute itself, for it states a claimthat is not itself scientifically confirmable. Thus, it's a self-refuting claim.

    5. The Confirmation Test (continued…)

    In any case, even scientific claims (such as the claim that the Earth is not flat) cannot be

    confirmed via empirical observation alone.

    The example of a boat disappearing over the horizon.

    Observations are theory-laden. And, thus, at the end of the day, science must rely on abductive

    reasoning (reasoning from best explanation). And the principles of abductive reasoning are not

    themselves scientifically confirmable. So even science rests on claims that are not themselves

    scientifically confirmable.

    6. But are moral facts needed to explain anything?

    People’s moral beliefs? People’s moral attitudes? People’s moral (or immoral) behavior?

    What about other moral facts? Might we need some moral facts to explain other moral facts?

    Perhaps, but this would beg the question.

    It seems, then, that we do not need to postulate moral facts to explain any non-moral fact. And

    although we might need moral facts to explain other moral facts, we can’t just assume that there

    are any moral facts that need explaining, for doing so would amount to begging the question.

    7. Occam’s RazorSome might employ Occam’s razor against the idea that there are moral facts.

    Occam’s razor  (a.k.a. the principle of parsimony): Other things being equal, one hypothesis is

    better than another if it is simpler than the other, and one hypothesis is simpler than another if

    and only if it requires us to postulate the existence of fewer unknown facts, entities,

    properties, or processes-- that is, fewer facts, entities, properties, and processes

    beyond those that we already know about it.

    8. Occam’s Razor (continued…)

    The simplest explanation is not necessarily the one that is the least complex or the easiest

    to understand.Examples: Explaining (1) biological organisms, (2) crop circles, (3) reports of alien abduction, (4)

    noises in the walls when the hot water is turned on, etc.

    Occam’s razor doesn’t say that it is more likely that there are n as opposed to n+1 facts, entities,

    properties, or processes in the universe. It does not say, for instance, that, in absence any

    evidence either way, it is more likely that silicon-based life-forms don’t exist than it is that

    silicon-based life-forms do exist, other things being equal. Rather, it says only that, in the

    absence of any evidence for the existence of silicon-based life-forms, an explanation that doesn’t

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    14/39

    postulate their existence is superior to one that does, other things being equal.

    9. Occam’s Razor (continued…)

    Why is the one superior to the other?

     Answer: Because it has fewer commitments that might turn out to be false.

    Of course, this means that an explanation that postulates nothing with respect to whethersilicon-based life-forms exist is, other things being equal, superior to an explanation that

    postulates that silicon-based life-forms don’t exist.

    Thus, an explanation that postulates some unknown negative existential claim is just as

    worrisome as an explanation that postulates some unknown positive existential claim.

    So Occam’s razor does not support the contention that there are no facts or properties beyond

    those that are needed to explain our empirical observations. Indeed, such a contention is quite

    controversial.

    10. The Argument from Explanatory Impotence

    If X (some fact, entity, property, or process) exists or is real, then its reality/existence must benecessary to explain some of our empirical observations.

    The reality/existence of moral facts and properties isn’t needed to explain any of our empirical

    observations.

    Therefore, moral facts and properties don’t exist and are not real.

    11. Why we should reject Premise 1 of the explanatory impotence argument

    Why accept Premise 1?

    Premise 1 has counter-intuitive implications. Premise 1 implies that such things as

    “atmospheres, rock strata, newts, and dandelions” don’t exist or are unreal, for none of these are

    needed to explain our empirical observations. After all, it seems that we need only postulate theexistence of sub-atomic particles to explain our empirical observations.

    But even if you don’t have a problem with such a sparse ontology, there is another reason to

    reject premise 1. If we accept Premise 1, then we must deny the reality of all normative facts

    and properties, including the normative fact that we ought to infer the Conclusion (i.e., 3) from

    Premises 1 and 2.

    12. Why all normative facts seem to be in the same boat

     A normative fact is a fact about whether S ought or has reason to φ, where S stands for some

    rational subject and φ stands for some reason-sensitive attitude such as a desire, a belief, or an

    intention. These facts includes prudential and epistemic facts.No normative fact is scientifically confirmable. Nor are normative facts needed to explain any of

    our empirical observations.

    So if we reject moral facts on such grounds, then we must reject all normative facts, including all

    prudential facts and all epistemic facts. And that’s a tough pill to swallow.

    13. Explanation versus Prescription

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    15/39

    To insist that, for moral facts and properties to exist, they must be able to explain some of our

    empirical observations is just to miss the point and purpose of moral thinking. The “point of

    thinking about what is right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust, is not, it seems, to figure out

    what happened or why, but to figure out what should happen and why” (Sayre-McCord). Thus the

    point is prescription, not explanation—that is, to prescribe what ought to be the case as opposed

    to explain what is the case.

    14. Continued…

    So, yes, it’s true that moral facts and properties are not needed to explain anything, but that

    doesn’t mean that we should deny that there are such facts and properties, for explanation is not

    all that there is. There is also prescription (or normativity). And, for there to be prescription, there

    must be normative facts and properties.

    15. Are moral facts compatible with a scientific worldview?

    The answer depends on whether the scientific worldview is taken to be (a) the view that there

    are no other facts or properties besides those that are studied by empirical sciences or(b) the view that all events in space and time are best given scientific explanations.

    If (a), the answer to the above question is no.

    If (b), the answer to the above question is yes.

    Which is more plausible: (a) or (b)?

    16. Continued…

    It may seem that if normative claims are non-scientific claims, then they must conflict with the

    claims of science. This is not so. Of course, some non-scientific claims do conflict with the

    claims of science, viz., those that “involve claims about events occurring in space and time, and

    about what things cause or are caused by them” (Scanlon). But unlike various causal claimsinvolving the paranormal and the supernatural (ESP, ghostly hauntings, acts of God, therapeutic

    touch, demonic possessions, etc.), which are all very implausible given our ordinary empirical

    standards for assessing such causal claims, normative claims make no claims about events in

    space and time.

    17. Continued…

    It may be objected that our beliefs about normative facts must have motivational efficacy if

    they’re to retain their practical relevance. And thus our normative beliefs must be able to cause

    us to have the attitudes that they support our having, and this, some might argue, would be just

    as mysterious as supernatural causal powers, such as therapeutic touch. But there is nothingmysterious here, for it is not the normative fact that must have motivational/causal efficacy.

    Rather, it is the normative belief  (a natural, psychological state) that must have

    motivational/causal efficacy. So it is the natural state of believing some normative fact, not the

    normative fact itself, that has the power to cause the formation of the attitude that is called for by

    the normative fact.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    16/39

    18. Conclusions

    We’ve seen that that the fact that moral facts are not scientifically confirmable does not support

    the contention that there are no moral facts.

    We’ve seen that Occam’s razor does not support the contention that there are no moral facts.

     And we’ve seen that the fact that moral facts are not needed to explain any of our empirical

    observations does not support the contention that there are no moral facts.Furthermore, we’ve seen that moral facts seem to be in the same boat as other normative facts.

    If we reject moral facts on the grounds that they’re not empirically verifiable, then we would have

    to also reject epistemic facts, for they are no more empirically verifiable than moral facts are.

     And if we reject epistemic facts, then we must deny that there is any reason to reject the view

    that there are moral facts.

    Possible Exam Questions concerning Lecture 4

    (a) What does the confirmation test say? (b) Is the confirmation test true? Explain.

    (a) Explain Occam’s razor. (b) Give an example where, according to Occam’s razor, one

    explanation is superior to another. (c) Is the simplest explanation the one that is the easiest tounderstand? Explain. (d) Does Occam’s razor support the contention that there are no moral

    facts or properties? Explain.

     Are moral facts needed to explain anything? Explain.

    Critically assess the following argument:

    If X (some fact, entity, property, or process) exists or is real, then its reality/existence must be

    necessary to explain some of our empirical observations.

    The reality/existence of moral facts and properties isn’t needed to explain any of our empirical

    observations.

    Therefore, moral facts and properties don’t exist and are not real.

    What is point of thinking about what is right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust? Are moral facts compatible with a scientific worldview? Explain.

    PHI 105

    LECTURE 5:

    Utilitarianism

    Last Updated: 3/2/10

    1. Act-Utilitarianism Characterized

    The view is consequentialist: Actions are to be judged right or wrong solely in virtue of the

    goodness or badness of their consequences.The view is welfarist: In assessing the goodness (or badness) of an act’s consequences,

    the only thing that matters is welfare (i.e., that which makes someone’s life go well for

    him or her). Welfare is the only thing good for its own sake.

    The view is universalist, impartialist, and aggregative: The right act is the one the

    produces the greatest net sum of welfare while weighing impartially increases and

    diminutions in the welfare of all those affected by the act.

    The view endorses a maximizing conception of right action: An act is permissible if and

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    17/39

    only if there is no available alternative that would produce more utility than it would.

    2. Hedonistic Act-Utilitarianism

    Hedonistic Act Utilitarianism: An act is morally permissible if and only if, and because, it

    maximizes hedonic utility.

    Hedonic Utility: The hedonic utility of an act equals the total amount of hedons itproduces minus the total amount of dolors it produces, where a hedon is the standard

    unit of measurement of pleasure and a dolor  is the standard unit of measurement of

    pain.

     An act maximizes hedonic utility  if and only if there is no alternative act available to

    the agent that would produce more hedonic utility than it would. Note, then, that

    more than one act can maximize hedonic utility.

    3. An Example of the HAU Calculus

     An Example of the HAU Calculus: Suppose that the available alternatives are a1, a2, a3,

    and a4. And suppose that the people who would be affected are p1, p2, p3, and p4…

    4. An Example of the HAU Calculus (continued…)

    p1 p2 p3 p4 HU

    a1 10 6 14 -10 =20

    a2 100 -90 8 0 =18

    a3 5 5 5 5 =20

    a4 -10 -10 -10 35 =5

    5. The Motivation for HAU

    The thought is that HAU is just a natural extension of the familiar balancing and

    maximizing conception of rationality from diachronic intrapersonal contexts to

    diachronic interpersonal (moral) contexts.

    The diachronic intrapersonal context: The temporal location of a benefit or harm within a

    life does not, as such, have any rational significance. We should, therefore, be temporally

    neutral with respect to when harms and benefits occur in our lives. And we should be

    willing to make sacrifices now for the sake of future benefits that will more than offsetthese sacrifices.

    6. Continued…

    The diachronic interpersonal (moral) context: From the moral point of view, no one

    person’s welfare is any more or less important that another’s. So, the location of a benefit

    or harm within a population of persons has no moral significance. And thus, as we move

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    18/39

    from the point of view of individual rationality to the point of view of morality, we should not

    only be temporally neutral with respect to when harms and benefits occur, but also be

    person-neutral (or impartial) with respect to who receives some harm or benefit.

    Furthermore, we should again be willing to make trade offs (to balance) for the sake of

    maximizing welfare over time and across individuals.

    7. Getting a feel for the theory: A Practice Quiz

     Answer the following questions according to what hedonistic act utilitarianism (HAU)

    entails. Answer either “Necessarily True” or “Not Necessarily True.”

    (Q1) An act is morally impermissible if it causes someone a lot of pain and no pleasure.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted].

    8. Continued…

    Suppose that there are exactly three act alternatives available to the agent: a1-a3. Further

    suppose that these acts will have effects on only three persons: p1-p3. Now let ‘HU(p1)’stand for ‘p1’s hedonic utility’, and let ‘HU’ stand for ‘the total aggregate utility’. Suppose,

    then, that the scenario is this:

    act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU(p3) HU moral status

    a1 +10 −100 +130 +40 permissible

    a2 +5 +5 +5 +15 impermissible

    a3 +15 +25 0 +40 permissible

    9. Continued…

    Lesson: On HAU, [Redacted]. This means that one may permissibly impose great

    sacrifices on some for the sake of greater gains in the aggregate.

    (Q2) An act is morally impermissible if it produces, in the aggregate, more pain than

    pleasure. In other words, an act is morally impermissible if it has negative hedonic utility.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    10. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. Consider, for instance, the following scenario:act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU(p3) HU moral status

    a1 +10 −100 +30 −60 impermissible

    a2 +5 −5 −5 −5 impermissible

    a3 +15 +25 −41 −1 permissible

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    19/39

     

    11. Continued…

    Lesson: According to HAU, whether or not an act is permissible can only be determined

    by [Redacted].

    (Q3) If an act produces pleasure for many and pain for no one, then it is morally

    permissible. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    12. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, it’s not always sufficient to produce pleasure for many

    and pain for no one; one must [Redacted]. Consider the following scenario:

    act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU(p3) HU moral status

    a1 +10 −100 +130 +40 impermissible

    a2 +100 +100 +100 +300 impermissible

    a3 +100 +101 +100 +301 permissible

    13. Continued…

    Lesson: Because HAU requires that we always maximize hedonic utility, it will be a

    [Redacted]. It will require each of us to perform an altruistic self-sacrificing act whenever

    the self-sacrifice that we thereby make will be more than offset by altruistic benefits we

    thereby bestow on others.

    (Q4) It is morally impermissible to listen to Metallica on the car’s CD player if the othertwo people in the car would get more pleasure from listening to The Beatles. Assume

    that listening to Metallica and listening to The Beatles are the only two available options.

     Assume that you and the other two people in the car are the only ones who will be

    affected by this choice. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    14. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. If HAU was a democracy, it would be “[Redacted]”; it would not be

    “[Redacted].” Let a1 = listen to Metallica, and let a2 = listen to The Beatles. Now

    suppose that the scenario is this:

    act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU(p3) HU moral status

    a1 +10 +10 +80 +100 permissible

    a2 +15 +15 +15 +45 impermissible

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    20/39

    15. Continued…

    Lesson: Some people will [Redacted] simply because they stand to gain or lose more

    than others do. There might even be utility monsters: people who get so much pleasure

    from getting what they want that the rest of us would all be morally required to do

    whatever we can to fulfill their every desire.

    (Q5) In an effort to help his patient, Dr. Smith injects Jones with a shot of penicillin afterdutifully asking him whether he’s allergic to penicillin and hearing Jones say that he isn’t.

    Nevertheless, it turns out, unbeknownst to Jones even, that Jones is severely allergic to

    penicillin, and, consequently, he dies as a result of the injection. Assuming that there

    would have been more hedonic utility had Dr. Smith not injected Jones with the shot of

    penicillin, it follows that what Dr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or not

    necessarily true?

    16. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, [Redacted] are irrelevant in assessing whether his or her

    act is permissible or not; it’s only the consequences of the action and of their alternativesthat matter.

    Lesson: HAU says nothing about [Redacted]. Thus it does not require that we are

    always motivated to act out of a concern to maximize hedonic utility. Sometimes we will

    act out of a partial concern for ourselves or for our loved ones, but what’s important is

    that our acts accord with HAU, not that they are motivated by a desire to act in

    accordance with HAU.

    17. Continued…

    (Q6) Anyone who acts wrongly as Dr. Smith did above is a morally bad person,

    deserving of both blame and punishment. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. As it stands, HAU evaluates [Redacted]. So it entails nothingabout whether such a person is morally bad or deserving of blame.

    18. Continued…

    Caveat: Even if HAU commits us to the view that an agent’s motives and intentions are

    irrelevant when assessing the moral value of her actions, it doesn’t commit us to the view

    that an agent’s motives and intentions are irrelevant when assessing the moral goodness

    of her character.

    (Q7) It is morally permissible to torture an innocent baby in certain circumstances.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, [Redacted], and thus virtually any type of act can, inprinciple, be justified and, indeed, will be justified if it maximizes hedonic utility.

    19. Continued…

    To illustrate, let a1 = torture the innocent baby, a2 = refrain from torturing the innocent

    baby, p1 = the would-be torturer, and p2 = the would-be torture victim. Now consider the

    following scenario:

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    21/39

    act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU moral status

    a1 +100 −99 +1 permissible

    a2 0 0 0 impermissible

    20. Continued…

    Lessons: First, on HAU, everyone’s welfare counts, and counts equally, regardless of

    desert. Second, on HAU, it is permissible to maim, murder, and even massacre innocent

    people provided that doing so will maximize hedonic utility. On HAU, most any type of act

    is, in principle, justifiable.

    (Q8) The effects that our actions will have on people’s welfare millions of years from now

    are just as important as their immediate effects. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    21. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, [Redacted]. Let a1 = stay after class and talk to John, a2= go home immediately after class, stopping to talk to no one, pc = the six billion or so

    people that currently exist, and pf = the ten billion or so people that will exist three

    generations from now. And let’s suppose that if I stay after class and talk to John, John

    will after we’re finished go to the local coffee shop and meet a woman standing behind

    him in line, a woman whom he falls in love with and has a child with. Assume that this

    child’s grandchild ends up being an evil fascist dictator who causes untold suffering.

    Lastly, assume that had I not stayed after class to talk with John, he would have left for

    the coffee shop much earlier, and, consequently, this evil fascist dictator would have

    never existed.

    22. Continued…

    Suppose, then, that the scenario is this:

    act HU(pc) HU(pf) HU moral status

    a1 +1 −100 tr. −999,999,999,99

    9

    impermissible

    a2 0 0 0 permissible

    23. Continued…Lesson: Given that there are, at any given moment, an infinite number of available act

    alternatives, and given that one would need to know what effects each of these will have

    from now until the end of time to know what their hedonic utilities are, one can never

    know with any degree of certainty what one morally ought to do on HAU. Some have,

    therefore, objected to HAU on the grounds that it is too impractical to be action guiding.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    22/39

    24. Continued…

    (Q9) While waiting at a crosswalk, Mr. Smith sees a stranger about step off the curb into

    the path on an oncoming, speeding bus. Without thinking, Mr. Smith reaches out, grabs

    the stranger, and pulls him back onto the curb, saving his life. Mr. Smith does this without

    even thinking about what the hedonic utility of this act or any of its alternatives might be.

    What Mr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or not necessarily true? Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, what matters is not [Redacted], but whether the way you

    in fact acted maximized hedonic utility.

    25. Continued…

    To illustrate, let a1 = your instinctually grabbing the stranger and pulling him back to

    safety, a2 = your calculating the likely hedonic utility of each of the various act alternatives

    available to you while the stranger is struck and killed by the bus, p1 = you, and p2 = the

    stranger. Suppose, then, that the scenario is this:

    act HU(p1) HU(p2) HU moral status

    a1 +20 0 +20 permissible

    a2 −20 −999,980 −1 mil. impermissible

    26. Continued…

    Lesson: HAU is a [Redacted]. To understand the difference, consider the difference

    between the criterion for being HIV infected (or brain dead), and the procedure that we

    might use to determine whether someone is HIV infected (or brain dead). And note that

    HAU is no more impractical than the view that the most prudent act is the one that willmaximize one’s utility over time. And no one would suggest that we ought to reject the

    investment principle “Buy low, and sell high” just because it is often times practically

    impossible to know whether the price of a stock is headed up or down.

    27. Continued…

    (Q10) If you promised a kid ten bucks to wash your car and he did as promised (he

    washed your car and did a nice job), you should give him the ten bucks. Necessarily true

    or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. Whether or not you should give the kid the ten bucks depends, not

    on whether [Redacted], but rather on whether [Redacted].Lesson: HAU is entirely [Redacted]. What happened in the past is, on HAU, irrelevant in

    determining what one morally ought to do. The past is irrelevant, because nothing you do

    now can affect the hedonic utility of any past event.

    28. Continued…

    (Q11) Mr. Smith has an extra $500 this month after paying all his bills. He uses that $500

    to buy his son a set of encyclopedias to help with his son’s schoolwork. But had Smith

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    23/39

    instead used that $500 to buy some stranger’s kid a set of encyclopedias that would have

    produced slightly more hedonic utility. What Mr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or

    not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. On HAU, [Redacted] pleasures and pains count equally,

    regardless of one’s relationship to those affected. The hedonic utility of one’s friends and

    family members are no more (or less) important, on HAU, than that of completestrangers.

    Lesson: On HAU, there are no special obligations, and special relationships have no

    intrinsic importance.

    29. Continued…

    (Q12) In deciding what to eat for breakfast this morning, Mr. Johnson is morally required

    to make the choice that produces the greatest hedonic utility. Assume that, according to

    HAU, Mr. Johnson ought to eat something for breakfast this morning, and that what

    choice he makes will affect only himself. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted].Lesson: According to HAU, morality is [Redacted]. Every practical decision and choice

    is a moral one, even those that are quite trivial and have no ramifications for anyone but

    the agent. There is no moral asymmetry between the self and others. You have just as

    much moral reason to promote your own hedonic utility as to promote anyone else’s.

    30. Continued…

    (Q13) The King of Siam must adopt either policy X or policy Y. This decision will affect

    only those people belonging to one of the following two populations: population A and

    population B. Population A consists in a hundred poor persons with 10 hedons each.

    Population B consists in a hundred affluent persons with 100 hedons each. The King ofSiam adopts policy X, which has no effect on the people in population A, but raises the

    number of hedons for each person in population B by 90 hedons. Had the King of Siam

    adopted policy Y instead, this would have had no effect on the people in population B, but

    would have raised the number of hedons for each person in population A by 90 hedons.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    31. Continued…

    Policy X, therefore, worsens the already existing inequality that exists between the two

    populations, whereas policy Y would make things equal by raising the level of welfare of

    the worse off. Given that the people in population A are equally deserving of 100 hedons

    as the people in population B are, it was wrong of the King of Siam to have adopted policy

    X.

    32. Continued…

     Answer: [Redacted]. Let a1 = adopt policy X, a2 = adopt policy Y, pA = population A, and

    pB = population B. The scenario is as follows:

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    24/39

    act HU(pa) HU(pb) HU moral status

    a1 +10,000 +10,000 +20,000 permissible

    a2 +1000 +19,000 +20,000 permissible

    33. Continued…

    Lesson: On HAU, [Redacted]. HAU is not sensitive to concerns about desert or

    distributive justice.

    (Q14) On HAU, there are no supererogatory acts (i.e., acts that go above and beyond

    what duty requires). Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. Whether it is true or not depends on what counts as a

    supererogatory act. Some define supererogatory acts as those that do more for the sake

    of others than duty requires. Others define supererogatory acts such that S’s performing

     x  is supererogatory only if there exists some available alternative, y , such that (a) S ismorally permitted both to perform x  and to perform y , and (b) S has more moral reason

    to perform x  than to perform y .

    34. Continued…

    If the former definition is correct, then HAU can accommodate supererogatory acts. But if

    the latter is the correct definition, then HAU cannot accommodate supererogatory acts.

    Let HU(s) = the hedonic utility that accrues to oneself and HU(o) = the hedonic utility that

    accrues to others.

    act HU(s) HU(o) HU moral status

    a1 +10 +5 +15 permissible

    a2 +5 +10 +15 perm. or super.(?)

    a3 +10 0 +10 impermissible

    35. Continued…

    Lesson: Either HAU leaves no room for supererogatory acts or there is no more moral

    reason to perform a supererogatory act than there is to perform some permissible but

    non-supererogatory alternative.(Q15) Mr. Smith knowingly sends an innocent man to prison for ten long years. What Mr.

    Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     Answer: [Redacted]. It may be that punishing this innocent man [Redacted].

    36. Continued…

    Lesson: On HAU, we should punish someone if and only if [Redacted]. This means that,

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    25/39

    on HAU, we should punish the innocent and we should refrain from punishing the guilty

    whenever doing so will maximize hedonic utility. Also, on HAU, the severity of the

    punishment should not necessarily be in proportion to the severity of the crime. The

    punishment for a less severe crime should be greater than the punishment for a more

    severe crime if this will maximize hedonic utility.

    37. The Practical Objection to HAU

    On HAU, it is often times practically impossible to know how you ought to act. To know

    what you ought to do, you would have to consider every possible alternative act open to

    you, and, for each, you would need to know, all of its effects from now until the end of

    time.

    Response: HAU is a criterion of rightness ([Redacted]) not a decision procedure

    ([Redacted]).

    Note that HAU is no more impractical than the view that the most prudent act is the one

    that will maximize one’s utility over time. No one would suggest that we ought to reject

    the investment principle “Buy low, and sell high” just because it often times practicallyimpossible to know whether the price of a stock’s price is headed up or down.

    Note that the utilitarian can employ [Redacted].

    38. Theoretical Objections to HAU

    Punishment: HAU will, in certain circumstances, call for punishing the innocent as well as

    call for disproportionate punishment vis-à-vis the severity of the crime.

    Rights: HAU doesn’t allow for the notion that people have rights that protect them from

    certain forms of treatment absent their autonomous consent.

    Distributive Justice: [Redacted].

    39. Continued…

    Backward-Looking Reasons: HAU is entirely forward-looking. Thus the fact that

    someone, in the past, made some promise, committed some injustice, or was the victim

    of some injustice is morally irrelevant.

    Demandingness: HAU is extremely demanding. There are few moral options on HAU.

    HAU requires great personal sacrifice even when the resulting outcome is only marginally

    better than it would be had you not sacrificed.

    40. Continued…

    Supererogation: On HAU, there are no supererogatory acts. An act is supererogatory if

    and only if there is more moral reason to perform it than to perform some morallypermissible alternative.

    Special Relationships: On HAU, one’s special relationships are morally irrelevant. HAU

    requires acting in a way that’s completely impartial. (However, it doesn’t require that your

    motives be impartial.)

    41. Responses to these theoretical objections

    First Line of Defense: Appeal to [Redacted]. Some proponents argue that, in most real

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    26/39

    world cases, HAU does not have the wildly counter-intuitive implications that it is

    purported to have.

    42. Continued…

    Second Line of Defense: [Redacted]: Some proponents admit that HAU does have

    wildly counter-intuitive implications in at least hypothetical cases, but they cite variousreasons for questioning our commonsense intuitions in such cases.

    Evolutionary Reasons: Greene’s Work on Our Intuitions in Different Trolley

    Cases: Personal vs. Impersonal Violations

     Anthropological Reasons: Our intuitions have been wildly mistaken in the past:

    The Case of Slavery and the Subjugation of Women.

    Consistency Reasons: Our intuitions are often inconsistent: Singer on charity and

    animal experimentation

    Possible Exam Questions concerning Lecture 3

    (a) Explain hedonistic act-utilitarianism (HAU). (b) What is the hedonic utility of an action?(c) Fill in the blank: An act maximizes hedonic utility  if and only if…. (d) Explain the

    motivation for hedonistic act-utilitarianism.

    (a) Explain hedonistic act-utilitarianism (HAU). (b) Explain four of the seven theoretical

    objections to HAU that were discussed in class.

    (a) Against these theoretical objections, the utilitarian can appeal to remote effects.

    Explain how this defense goes. (b) The utilitarian could also just bite the bullet and argue

    that the fact that HAU has counter-intuitive implications isn’t overly worrisome given that

    our intuitions about such matters are suspect. Explain how this defense goes.

    (a) Explain hedonistic act-utilitarianism (HAU). (b) Critically assess the practical objection

    to HAU. (c) What sort of decision procedure should hedonistic act-utilitarians adopt? (d)Explain the distinction between a criterion of rightness and a decision procedure.

     Answer the following questions according to what hedonistic act utilitarianism (HAU)

    entails—answer either “Necessarily True” or “Not Necessarily True.” In each case, explain your

    answer and what lesson (or lessons) we should take from it.

     An act is morally impermissible if it causes someone a lot of pain and no pleasure.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

     An act is morally impermissible if it produces, in the aggregate, more pain than pleasure.

    In other words, an act is morally impermissible if it has negative hedonic utility.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    If an act produces pleasure for many and pain for no one, then it is morally permissible.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    It is morally impermissible to listen to Metallica on the car’s CD player if the other two

    people in the car would get more pleasure from listening to The Beatles. Assume that

    listening to Metallica and listening to The Beatles are the only two available options.

     Assume that you and the other two people in the car are the only ones who will be

    affected by this choice. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    In an effort to help his patient, Dr. Smith injects Jones with a shot of penicillin after

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    27/39

    dutifully asking him whether he’s allergic to penicillin and hearing Jones say that he isn’t.

    Nevertheless, it turns out, unbeknownst to Jones even, that Jones is severely allergic to

    penicillin, and, consequently, he dies as a result of the injection. Assuming that there

    would have been more hedonic utility had Dr. Smith not injected Jones with the shot of

    penicillin, it follows that what Dr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or not

    necessarily true? Anyone who acts wrongly as Dr. Smith did above is a morally bad person, deserving of

    both blame and punishment. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    It is morally permissible to torture an innocent baby in certain circumstances. Necessarily

    true or not necessarily true?

    The effects that our actions will have on people’s welfare millions of years from now are

     just as important as their immediate effects. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    While waiting at a crosswalk, Mr. Smith sees a stranger about step off the curb into the

    path on an oncoming, speeding bus. Without thinking, Mr. Smith reaches out, grabs the

    stranger, and pulls him back onto the curb, saving his life. Mr. Smith does this without

    even thinking about what the hedonic utility of this act or any of its alternatives might be.What Mr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    If you promised a kid ten bucks to wash your car and he did as promised (he washed

    your car and did a nice job), you should give him the ten bucks. Necessarily true or not

    necessarily true?

    Mr. Smith has an extra $500 this month after paying all his bills. He uses that $500 to buy

    his son a set of encyclopedias to help with his son’s schoolwork. But had Smith instead

    used that $500 to buy some stranger’s kid a set of encyclopedias that would have

    produced slightly more hedonic utility. What Mr. Smith did was wrong. Necessarily true or

    not necessarily true?

    In deciding what to eat for breakfast this morning, Mr. Johnson is morally required tomake the choice that produces the greatest hedonic utility. Assume that, according to

    HAU, Mr. Johnson ought to eat something for breakfast this morning, and that what

    choice he makes will affect only himself. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    The King of Siam must adopt either policy X or policy Y. This decision will affect only

    those people belonging to one of the following two populations: population A and

    population B. Population A consists in a hundred poor persons with 10 hedons each.

    Population B consists in a hundred affluent persons with 100 hedons each. The King of

    Siam adopts policy X, which has no effect on the people in population A, but raises the

    number of hedons for each person in population B by 90 hedons. Had the King of Siam

    adopted policy Y instead, this would have had no effect on the people in population B, but

    would have raised the number of hedons for each person in population A by 90 hedons.

    Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    On HAU, there are no supererogatory acts (i.e., acts that go above and beyond what duty

    requires). Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

    Mr. Smith knowingly sends an innocent man to prison for ten long years. What Mr. Smith

    did was wrong. Necessarily true or not necessarily true?

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    28/39

     

    1. Singer’s Thesis

     All animals (human and non-human) are equal, in the same sense that all humans are

    equal.

    2. The Notion of EqualityWhen we claim that all human beings, whatever their race, creed, or sex, are equal, what

    exactly are we asserting?

     Are we asserting that all human beings are equal in their abilities and capacities?

     Are we asserting that all races, and both sexes, are equal in their abilities and capacities?

    Two reasons why we ought not to base our opposition to racism and sexism on any kind

    of actual equality, even the limited kind that asserts that variations in capacities and

    abilities are spread evenly between the different races and both sexes:

    It may turn out that variations in capacities and abilities are not spread evenly between

    the races and sexes, and some variations turn out to be innate.

    We would, then, have no basis for opposing an inegaltarian society based on factualdifferences. 

    4. Factual Equality vs. Prescriptive Equality

    “The principle of the equality of human beings is not a description of an alleged actual

    equality among humans; it is a prescription of how we should treat humans.”

    5. The Basic Principle of Equality

    The Principle of Equal Consideration of Interests: We ought to give equal consideration to

    the interests of all sentient beings—whatever their race, creed, sex, or species—in our

    moral deliberations.

    6. Interests and Suffering

    The capacity for suffering is sufficient for having interests. Any being with the capacity to

    suffer has an interest in avoiding suffering.

    Most animals (unlike stones, plants etc) have the capacity to suffer.

    Therefore, most animals have an interest in avoiding suffering.

    Equal consideration requires that animal interests in not suffering be taken equally into

    account with human interests in not suffering.

    Failure to give equal consideration to both human and animal interest is speciesm.

    7. Racism, Sexism, and Speciesism

    What is racism? What is sexism?

    Speciesism: A bias towards the interest of the members of one's own species and

    against those of the members of another species.

    species : speciesism :: race : racism :: sex : sexism

    Note, then, that on Singer’s conceptual framework the view that one race/sex/species is

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    29/39

    superior to another is a certain respect is not racist/sexist/speciest.

    8. Why is racism wrong?

    Why is racism wrong? Why is it wrong to let our treatment of others be dictated by their

    race?

     Answer : Because race is not itself, relevant to how others ought to be treated.

    9. Is species membership relevant?

    Is species membership morally relevant? What is it to belong to the species Homo

    sapiens?

    Does one have to have the capacity for language?

    Does one have to have the capacity for abstract reasoning?

    Membership in the species Homo sapiens seems both too narrow and too broad to serve

    as a legitimate basis for giving direct moral consideration.

    Direct versus indirect moral consideration.

    Too Narrow: Intelligent aliens.Too Broad: Brain-dead humans.

    11. The Argument from Marginal Cases

    The Argument from Marginal Cases is meant to show that if we don’t owe animals direct

    moral consideration, then we don’t owe marginal cases of humanity direct moral

    consideration either. Here’s the argument:

    If we are justified in denying direct moral consideration to animals, then we are justified in

    denying direct moral consideration to the marginal cases.

    We are not justified in denying direct moral consideration to the marginal cases.

    Therefore, we are not justified denying direct moral consideration to animals.

    12. To avoid being speciesist…

    …must we treat all animals the same?

    Equal consideration for different beings may lead to different treatment where

    interest differ, treatment may differ.

    “Animals can feel pain…, [and] there can be no moral justification for regarding the pain

    (or pleasure) that animals feel as less important than the same amount of pain (or

    pleasure) felt by humans.”

    13. HoweverHowever, we must note that…

    The same amount of physical pain can cause more total human suffering than animal

    suffering; humans have extra capacities:

    human memory and anticipation

    emotional ties between humans

    social communication and stability

    But this may not apply to orphan human infants.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    30/39

    We also must note that an animal’s lack of ability to understand may lead to its greater

    suffering.

    14. To avoid being speciesist…

    …must we extend the same rights to all animals?

    Equal consideration for different beings may lead to different rights e.g. asserting thatdogs have a right to vote is just as asserting that men have a right to an abortion.

    15. To avoid being speciesist…

    …must we value the lives of all animals equally?

    We may admit that some features of certain beings (e.g., self-awareness, the ability to

    understand abstract concepts, the ability to act for a reason, etc.) make their lives

    more valuable than the lives of other beings who do not have these features; but

    there will surely be some nonhuman animals whose lives, by any such standards, are

    more valuable than the lives of some humans.

    16. Continued…

    The question is should we treat severely disabled humans as we now treat nonhuman

    animals with equivalent abilities and capacities, or should we treat these nonhuman

    animals with the same care that we currently extend to even the most severely disabled

    humans. Or perhaps we should adopt some middle position.

    17. Why the belief that human life, and only human life, is sacrosanct is speciesist?

    To hold that the boundary of the right to life runs exactly parallel to the boundary of our

    own species is irredeemably speciesist. “Those who hold the sanctity of [human] life do

    this because while distinguishing sharply between humans and other animals they allowno distinctions to be made within our own species, objecting to the killing of the severely

    retarded and the hopelessly senile as strongly as they object to the killing of normal

    adults.

    18. The test for speciesism:

    If we are willing to do X to certain nonhuman animals but unwilling to do X on humans

    who are in all morally relevant respects inferior to these nonhuman animals, then

    we are acting speciesist in doing X to those nonhuman animals.

    19. Speciesism in Practice:Factory Farming

    Defenses?

     Animal Testing and Experimentation

    Defenses?

    20. A Potential Problem with Singer’s Account of Sexism/Racism/Speciesism

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    31/39

    Is it sexist for a woman to donate her money to breast cancer research as opposed to

    prostate cancer research even if the principle of equal consideration of interests supports

    the latter?

    Is it racist for an African American to set up a scholarship for disadvantaged African

     Americans as opposed to setting up a scholarship for disadvantaged Native Americans

    even if the principle of equal consideration of interests supports the latter?The importance of special relationships…

    21. Continued…

    Do we have a special relationship with other members of our species in the way that,

    say, women have a special relationship with other members of their sex?

    How does this problem bear on Singer’s arguments against practices such as animal

    testing and factory farming?

    22. The argument from fairness, an argument against speciesism

    Fairness demands that beings that are alike in all morally relevant respects be treatedalike.

    Fairness demands that brings that are alike in all morally relevant respects

    be treated alike.

    Speciesism/racism/sexism involves treating different beings differently

    simply because they belong to a different species/race/sex.

    What species/race/sex a being belongs to is not, in itself, morally relevant.

    Therefore, speciesism is unfair.

    What species/race/sex a being belongs to is not, in itself, morally relevant.

    Therefore, speciesism is unfair.Objections?

    The Problem: Absolute Poverty

    Nearly one-fifth of the world’s population lives in absolute poverty. Absolute poverty is

    poverty by any standard, which is to be distinguished from the relative poverty that we are

    familiar with in industrialized nations. Robert McNamara, past president of the World

    Bank, describes absolute poverty as follows: “A condition of life so characterized by

    malnutrition, illiteracy, disease, squalid surroundings, high infant mortality rate and low lifeexpectancy as to be beneath any reasonable definition of human decency.”

    2. Continued…

    Those living in absolute poverty have:

     An infant mortality rate that is eight times higher than that in most industrialized nations.

     A life expectancy that is one-third lower that that in most industrialized nations.

     A nutritional level, for one of every two in the population, below acceptable standards.

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    32/39

    Little to no access to even basic health care.

    Little to no access to safe drinking water.

    -- The above information is from Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, 2nd Edition (New York:

    Cambridge University Press, 1993).

    3. Some widely available facts about some easily preventable deathsEach year millions of children die from easily preventable causes. Each year around

    three million children die from dehydrating diarrhea. Most of these deaths can be

    prevented by administrating oral rehydration salts at a cost of around 15 cents a packet.

     Also millions of children die from immunizable diseases. Each year over a million die

    from measles alone, and it only costs $17 to vaccinate a child against measles.

    Pneumonia claims 3.5 million children each year, making it the leading childhood killer.

    However, most of these deaths can be prevented with a simple shot of antibiotics costing

    about 25 cents. Many malnourished children have a deficiency in vitamin A, causing their

    immune systems to be greatly debilitated. Many of these children can be saved with a

    semiannual dose of vitamin A costing only 10 cents.

    4. Some misconceptions about the problem

    Reducing the infant mortality rate in the Third World would cause a population explosion.

    The best available evidence supports the claim that decreasing infant mortality rate

    actually lowers the rate of population growth. Consider the poverty-ridden Indian state of

    Kerala. In this state, the infant mortality rate is significantly lower than average. Yet it has

    a low Total Fertility Rate, 1.9, meaning that the population size is actually in decline.

    Reducing the infant mortality rate would be pointless because there is little chance that

    even those children that make it through infancy will live on into adulthood.Those children that make it through the first five years of life have a 90 percent chance of

    living beyond the age of 21.

    5. Continued…

    Poverty is inseparably linked with high infant mortality and low life expectancy.

    Consider again the Indian state of Kerala, one of India's poorest states. Because

    Keralans have an adequate supply of food, safe drinking water, and basic health care,

    they have the highest life expectancy of any state in India and a lower than average infant

    mortality rate.

    There is not enough food to meet the nutritional needs of everyone in the world.There is more than enough food to feed the world's population. Most of the grain

    produced in industrialized nations is fed to farm animals, converting it into meat, milk, and

    eggs. Because this is a very inefficient process, wasting up to 95% of the nutritional value

    of the animal feed, people in countries such as the U.S. consume more than three times

    as much grain per capita than those countries that consume less animal products.

    -- The above information comes from Peter Unger’s Living High and Letting Die: Our

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    33/39

    Illusion of Innocence (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).

    6. Focusing on the Philosophical Issue

    For our purposes, we will not be concerned with whether or not Unger and Singer have

    their facts right. We will instead be interested in the following philosophical question: If

    these facts are correct, does it follow that we have an ethical obligation to do somethingto alleviate absolute poverty and, if so, what exactly?

     And, for the sake of argument, let’s assume that there are some easily identifiable

    organizations (such as, Oxfam and UNICEF) such that the following is true: were you to

    give a substantial portion of your income to those organizations, the good that that

    organization would do with your money would far exceed the good that would come from

    your spending that money luxuries for yourself and for your loved ones. More specifically,

    let’s assume that for each $200 donation that you make some child who would otherwise

    die in infancy will instead live a reasonably long life that is well worth living.

    7. Singer’s ArgumentIf [it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby

    sacrificing anything of moral significance, we ought, morally, to do it.], we ought,

    morally, to do it.

     Absolute poverty (i.e., suffering and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care) is

    bad.

    There is some absolute poverty that we can prevent without sacrificing anything of

    (comparable) moral significance.

    Therefore, we (morally) ought to prevent some absolute poverty.

    8. Critically Assessing the ArgumentIs the argument valid?

     Yes.

    The argument is valid because there is no possible way for the conclusion

    to be false while the premises are true.

    Which, if any, premises are controversial?

    Premise 2 is incontrovertible.

    Premise 3 is controversial, but we're going to accept it for the sake of the

    argument since we’re interested in the philosophical issue of whether assuming

    that Premise 3 is true we’re obligated to do something to prevent absolute

    poverty.This leaves us with Premise 1.

    9. Premise 1: Singer’s Principle

    By “without sacrificing anything of (comparable) moral significance,” Singer means

    without causing anything else (comparably) morally bad to happen, or doing something

    that is wrong in itself, or failing to promote some moral good (comparable in significance

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    34/39

    to the bad thing we can prevent).

    Does giving up luxuries count as sacrificing anything of moral significance let alone as

    sacrificing anything of comparable moral significance?

    By eliminating both the parentheses and the words enclosed by them, we obtain the

    moderate principle. By eliminating the parentheses and keeping the words they

    enclosed, we obtain the strong principle.

    10. Getting Clear on What the Principle Says

    Is either version of Singer’s principle equivalent to the act-utilitarianism (a.k.a. the

    principle of utility)?

     Answer: No.

    Neither principle requires that we do anything in a world in which nothing

    bad is going to happen. Act-utilitarianism requires us not only to prevent

    what is bad but also to promote what is good.

    What does he mean by “morally ought to give aid”? Does he mean that it would be

    supererogatory to do so or that it would be wrong not to do so? Answer: He means that you're morally obligated to give and thus it would

    be wrong not to do so.

    What does Singer say in support of his principle?

     Answer: He gives the example of the shallow pond and our intuition of we

    are morally obligated to save the child.

    11. Two Implications of His Principle

    It makes no difference whether the person I can help is a neighbor’s child ten yards away

    from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten thousand miles away.

    The situation where there are millions of other people who are equally able to provide aidbut are not doing so is not significantly different, morally speaking, from the situation

    where I am the only person who can provide aid.

    12. With regard to the first implication

    Proximity may make it more likely, for obvious psychological reasons, that I shall assist

    him, but it is not obvious that proximity makes any difference concerning whether I ought

    to assist him.

    Distance can matter indirectly, as where proximity puts me in a better position to judge

    what a person needs are. But is it at all unclear what the Bengali’s refugee’s needs are?

    Distance can also matter indirectly, as where proximity puts me in a better position toeffect a positive outcome. But famine relief organizations have people in the field who

    can direct our aid to distant strangers in need just as effectively as we could someone on

    our own block. In fact, they might even be more effective.

    13. With regard to the second implication

    Consider the case where I see other people around the shallow pond, no further away

  • 8/17/2019 Intro to Ethics Notes (PHI 105)

    35/39

    than I am, who have also noticed the drowning child but are doing nothing.

    Is my obligation to save the child diminished?

    But suppose that if everyone was to give $10 to the Bengal Relief Fund, there would be

    enough to provide food, shelter, and medical care for all the refugees. Why should I be

    required to give more than $10?

    Here’s the argument:If everyone in circumstances like mine were to give $10, I would have no obligation to give

    more than $10. Therefore, I am not obligated to give more than $10. This is invalid.

    What premise would we need to add to make the argument valid?

    Is that premise true?

    People in the same circumstances have the same obligation, but the fact that others

    have given or not given, or are expected or not expected to give, are relevant

    circumstances.

    14. Objections

    Does his principle (the moderate version) imply that we should take care of those inabsolute poverty before taking car