Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    1/38

    1

    Introduction

    Modern Philosophy:

    from Descartes to Marx

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    2/38

    2

    0.1 Introduction

    Whatever the definition given to philosophy, it is assumed that this activity wouldnt exist

    unless rationality exists. Rationality is possible only in as far as it is embodied in an action,

    whether linguistic or non-linguistic, and in thought, whether expressed or simply potentially

    expressible. There are other types of rational objects, such as a rational law, or a rational

    policy; however, these objects are simply actions and thoughts of a higher kind. Thus it

    seems that a proper examination of what is rational is intimately related to an analysis of

    action and thought insofar as they embody reason.

    The history of philosophy can be described as the history of humankind dealing with

    rationality. The philosopher relates to rationality in two ways. First, he attempts to act and

    think in accordance with what is rational.1

    Second, he makes rationality the subject-matter of

    philosophy. In this sense, recalling Hegels critique of Kant, rationality can be the instrument

    or medium of philosophical activity, but also the object investigated by that very instrument

    or medium. In the first type rationality is present, it may be said, only in the background of

    the philosophical activity; in the second type, it is brought to the foreground.

    It is commonly accepted that with the beginning of modernity, the issue of rationality

    acquired a new dimension. It was brought to the foreground of the philosophical activity.

    Descartes, who is usually accredited with beginning modernity, attempted to show the

    independence of reason from dogma. The position of self-sufficient rationality dominated

    1A particular example would be logic; to think rationally, in this case, would mean to think logically or in

    accordance with logic.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    3/38

    3

    the thoughts that followed the Cartesian revolution.2 As such, it can be said that modern

    rationality is at the same time emancipatory rationality. But Modernity is also characterised

    by the formalisation or instrumentalisation of reason; reason was reduced to mere effective

    application of means to given ends.

    The focus of this work is Habermass reconstruction of reason; that is to say his response to

    the rationality issue that culminated in the modern period, and also to matters that surround

    this same issue. A proper investigation of his response necessitates a prior review of the

    contributions put forward by his predecessors. This chapter deals with the issues that

    stemmed in the modern period, from Descartes to Marx. This will be followed, in Chapter 1,

    by a discussion of the thoughts of Habermass more proximal predecessors, i.e. the Frankfurt

    School theorists. But before dealing with the particular contributions of modern

    philosophers, some remarks will be made on modernity itself and on the rationality issue that

    took over the philosophical scene of modernity.

    Modernity and Rationality

    The word modern is derived from a Latin word meaning in this time. In the English

    language, the term has two meanings. First, it denotes contemporary, present time.

    Second, it refers to a particular epoch in history that followed the medieval and post-

    medieval eras. (Kolb, 1986, pp. 1-2) These two senses of modern are sometimes used

    interchangeably, implying that the period that followed medieval and post-medieval period

    2This idea is highlighted in the work of both Spinoza and Leibniz (usually associated with Leibniz), who

    employ the principle of sufficient reason. This principle states that nothing can be so without there being a

    reason why it is so. (Blackburn, 1996, p. 367)

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    4/38

    4

    is still on. Other times, the period that we are living in today is termed postmodern, implying

    that there is something in our present era that is radically different from the modern period.

    In this work, the first categorisation will be used, however without refuting the thesis that in

    our contemporary, present time something radically different is taking place.

    Modernity is said to have begun with Ren Descartes (1596 1650) in France and Francis

    Bacon (15611626) in England. (Copleston, 1960a, p. 1) The former, usually referred to as

    the father of modern philosophy, sought to free certainty or truth from dogma. He aimed to

    attain truth by the use of reason alone. The latter, promoted instrumental efficacy as the

    criterion that ought to guide science. (Taylor, 1991, p. 104) He was highly critical of the

    Aristotelian science as it has contributed nothing to relieve the condition of mankind.

    (Taylor, p. 104) While these two thinkers can be said to stand in opposition with regard to

    the theory-practice dialectic as Descartes made theoretical reflection the primary

    characteristic of the human being, and Bacon outlined the principles of the new empirical-

    practical scientific method (the novum organum, new instrument), thus making the empirical

    and the practical as fundamental both, in their own different way, paved the way for the

    instrumentalisation of reason.

    This last theme, the instrumentalisation or formalisation of reason3, highlights the principal

    distinctive feature that sets modernity apart from earlier eras. In modern social theory, the

    discussion of the formalisation of reason was made famous by Max Weber. Weber argued

    3The two terms, instrumental reason and formal reason, have similar meanings, albeit different ones.

    Instrumental reason refers to the usage of reason in a means-end situation. In this context, reason is conceived

    as a tool or instrument necessary to attain a particular goal. Formal reason refers to a kind of rationality that

    follows from the application of formal rules. Formal rules are the type of rules that govern artificial systems,

    from the functioning of a simple electronic device to the functioning of capitalist systems and modern law. In

    the modern period, rationality can be said to have become instrumental through formalisation.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    5/38

    5

    that modern life is characterised by the prominence given to formal rationality over

    substantive rationality. (Kolb p. 11) Substantive rationality establishes the values and goals

    that ought to guide our actions. On the other hand, formal rationality, deals with the

    maximum efficient application of a set of means to given ends, which makes efficiency and

    consistency the final tribunal of legitimation. In the case of the latter, the ends are not

    established by reason itself, but are self-chosen. (Kolb p. 11)

    While it may be argued that the prominence given to formal rationality over substantive

    rationality is modernitys principal distinctive feature, it should also be noted that it is not

    the sole one. It is in fact, related to other major characteristics that helped to modernise the

    western world. The prominence of instrumental or formal rationality over substantive

    rationality gave the individual greater power in three principal spheres of life: the individual

    sphere, the social-political sphere and the technical-scientific sphere.

    In the individual sphere, the individual became master of his own life. If no world-view can

    be inferred using reason, then it follows that it is up to the individual to decide on how to

    shape his or her own life. In other words, with modernity, the individual acquired more

    individual freedom. This individual freedom, is related to, and cannot exist without, a

    freedom that is granted and protected by a liberal state. Thus if the individual has more

    freedom, it is because society in general has been emancipated from the fetters of dogma

    (Habermas would later refer to this phenomenon as the rationalisation of the lifeworld, see

    Chapter 3). Finally, with the disenchantment of the world, that is to say with the sterilisation

    of substantive rationality, things are in sense up for grabs. (Taylor p. 5) They become

    mere raw materials or instruments for our projects. (Taylor p. 5)

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    6/38

    6

    A proper review of the themes just mentioned requires much more space than it was

    dedicated above. This introduction should suffice only to direct the reader to the themes that

    will be discussed in this work. More will be said in the chapters that follow. For now

    attention shall be turned to the major thinkers that dominated the early part of the modern

    period, i.e. from Descartes to Marx.

    0.2 The subject as foundation: Descartes and the rise of the modern

    subject

    Ren Descartes is considered the founder of a new kind of philosophy, a philosophy that

    posits the thinking subject at the basis of any rational and scientific inquiry. Inspired by the

    exactness and success of mathematics, Descartes attempts to develop a philosophical system

    using the deductive method employed in mathematics, where certain propositions are to be

    derived from a single, self-evident proposition. The system developed by Descartes was to

    have a profound impact on subsequent thought.

    In the Meditations on First Philosophy Descartes sets himself the task of revising all his

    formerly held opinions. In the First Meditation he develops a number of arguments through

    which he casts everything he believes he knows, including his own existence, into doubt. He

    however argues in the Second Meditation, that while every proposition he had previously

    accepted could in theory be doubted, the very fact that he exists could not. There must be

    someone or something that performs the act of thinking for there to be doubt at all. Thus he

    concludes that the I exists, and that this I exists insofar as it thinks.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    7/38

    7

    The importance of the Cartesian project lies in the fact that with Descartes the meaning of

    old concepts are given a new formulation. In this way, Descartes sets the philosophy of

    modernity into a particular direction. In his lectures on Nietzsche4, Heidegger argues that

    four central philosophical concepts, that is to say the concepts of man, thinking, other

    beings and rationality, are given a new formulation in the Cartesian system.

    With Descartes, man becomes essentially a disengaged subject, i.e. an entity whose nature is

    characterised by its subjective experiences. This subjectivist approach is evidenced by the

    style employed in The Meditations on First Philosophy. This work is characterised by usage

    of the subjective pronoun I, and by a particular self-reflective approach.

    The subject is according to Descartes essentially a thinking subject. In the Second

    Meditation ofThe Meditations, after casting everything into doubt, Descartes claims:

    So that, after having thought carefully about it, and having scrupulously examined

    everything, one must then, in conclusion, take as assured that the proposition: I am, I exist, is

    necessarily true, every time I express it or conceive it in my mind. (p. 103)

    Thinking thus becomes the experience which confirms the existence of the subject. The

    verification of the existence of the subject is only possible because the subject is able to

    think. However, thinking is not simply a means to verify the subjects existence, but also that

    which characterises the subject. Later on, in the same meditation, he makes this point clearly,

    when he says: I am, I exist: this is certain; but for how long? For as long as I thinkI am

    therefore, precisely speaking, only a thing which thinks. (Descartes, p. 105)

    4Heidegger argues that with the Cartesian method, the following were given a new formulation: i. beings

    become objects; ii. truth becomes certainty; iii. man becomes subject; iv. relation between faith and reason

    becomes emancipation; v. understanding of the world becomes representation as picture. For a detailed

    discussion see Messinese, L. Heidegger e la Filosofia dellEpoca Moderna, pp. 159 -176.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    8/38

    8

    The reduction of man to a disengaged subject requires that other beings become the objects

    with which the subject is opposed and contrasted. A subject can only be postulated if and

    only if objects are also postulated. There is no subject unless there are objects, or at least,

    one object.5

    Moreover, a subject is always related to, or relates with, its objects. Thinking,

    which as said above is the fundamental characteristic of the Cartesian subject, is that act

    which relates the subject with its objects. But the thinking that Descartes seems to have in

    mind, as Heidegger points out, is representational thinking. (Messinese, 2000, p. 167) In any

    thinking act, there is always an object that is being represented, whether the object exists in

    reality or not.

    If man becomes a disengaged subject, and other beings its objects, and thinking is reduced to

    mere representation, then rationality is also given a new formulation. It becomes nothing

    other than the correct representation of objects by the subject. Rationality is reduced by

    Descartes to perceiving something in a clear and distinct manner. To perceive something in a

    clear and distinct manner means to have a proposition whose certainty is beyond doubt.

    Heidegger points out that Descartes model prepares the groundwork for a rationality that

    would go instrumental. He argues that the subject in representing (thinking) secures the

    certainty of the object represented. (Messinese, p. 170) In this way, the thinking subject also

    becomes the subject that controls objects through representation. Consequently, according to

    Heidegger, rationality becomes defined as the disengaged application of thinking,

    5One may object that in the Second Meditation, where the meditator is only certain of his existence and of the

    fact that he thinks, no objects are postulated, thus rendering the above thesis incorrect. On the contrary it should

    be argued that the meditator, in establishing the existence of the subject that thinks, also objectifies the subject

    that is performing the thinking. In an act of self-reflection, the subject objectifies himself through thinking.

    Therefore, in so far as the subject is the object of thought and not just that which performs the thinking, it is

    also an object.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    9/38

    9

    understood as representation, with the aim of theoretically controlling objects. (Messinese, p.

    164)

    Although recent thinkers have criticised the Cartesian conception of the subject and

    rationality, it must be acknowledged that Descartes was one of the earliest thinkers who

    recognised the Enlightenment principle that the subject has sufficient rational ability to

    decide on what is rationally acceptable. While de facto, he was probably influenced by the

    dominating powers of the time, namely the Church6, he nonetheless, at least on a theoretical

    level, sought to show the independence of rationality from dogma. Of this opinion is Charles

    Taylor, who in his Ethics of Authenticity says that Descartes disengaged subject is

    grounded in a moral ideal, that of a self-responsible, self-controlling reasoning. He goes on

    to say that this ideal of rationality is at the same time an ideal of freedom, of autonomous,

    self-generating thought. (pp. 103 4) Thus, in a sense, Descartes can be said to be a

    precursor of the Enlightenment thinking.

    0.3The Enlightenment

    The Enlightenment, sometimes referred to as the Age of Reason, was a historical period that

    brought remarkable social, cultural and intellectual changes in the western world. It was a

    period where man, as Kant puts it, started to emerge from his self-imposed immaturity,

    where immaturity is understood as the inability to use one's understanding without guidance

    from another. (Kant, par. 1) The period can be characterised and defined by reference to

    6Evidence of this is the fact that he withheld the publication of the Treatise on the Universe in 1633, after he

    came to know of Galileos condemnation. (Scruton, 1995, p. 29)

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    10/38

    10

    two distinct, yet related philosophical 'facts': the acceptance of reason as the final arbiter of

    all issues i.e. religious, scientific and political matters, and the belief that reason and

    knowledge lead to enlightenment, which in turn leads to emancipation.

    Probably, one of the most incisive expressions of free thinking in the Enlightenment period

    was the publishing of the Encyclopaedia, edited by Denis Diderot (1713 - 84) and Jean le

    Rond D'Alembert (1717 - 83). (Copleston, 1960b, p. 43) The contributors of this work, such

    as Diderot and D'Alembert themselves, Voltaire, Montesquieu and d'Holbach, differed

    considerably in the views held. For example Voltaire, at the time of the Encyclopaedia

    subscribed to Deism; on the other hand, d'Holbach, was an outspoken materialist. But the

    importance of the Encyclopaedia, which as its editors admitted, left much to be desired

    (Copleston, p. 39), lies not in its contribution to knowledge, but rather in its ideological

    statement: it is reason, and the liberty to use ones own reason freely, and not the Church or

    the State, which should be the final judge of religious, scientific and moral issues.

    The idea that reason can lead to enlightenment, and then to emancipation, was of great

    importance to the philosophers of the period. The connection between enlightenment and

    emancipation, however, was not a new idea to western philosophy. The first philosopher to

    articulate this idea was Plato, who in theRepublic had argued that enlightenment was a state

    that only philosophers could attain, and consequently he concluded that the best rule is rule

    performed by philosophers. The intellectuals of the Enlightenment were however, much

    more confident in the average mans ability to be enlightened. (Ingram, 1990, p.3)

    The Enlightenment was also characterised by two important intellectual controversies, which

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    11/38

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    12/38

    12

    On the proper source of Knowledge

    Kant's Critique of Pure Reason was written as a response to the rationalist-empiricist debate.

    The rationalists, as explained above, had claimed that proper knowledge is acquired through

    deductive methods. Descartes, one of the major exponents of rationalism, in his Meditations,

    provides the wax argument to make his rationalist case. He says that no one would doubt that

    the same wax remains when it is brought close to fire and melts even though the wax

    changes all its observable properties. Thus, he contends, the conclusion that the melted wax

    is the same one that was previously solid cannot be based on empirical observation but on

    the inspection of the mind alone. (Descartes, pp. 108 - 9)

    The empiricists, on the other hand, had claimed that scientific knowledge can only be

    attained through empirical observations. David Hume (1711-1776), the most radical

    exponent of the school, maintained that truths of reason, such as '3 + 3 = 6' and 'He will

    either pass the exam or not' are mere tautologies, that although certain, are not informative.

    Informative propositions are what Hume called 'matters of facts' i.e. beliefs regarding the

    existence of things and their properties. These, Hume contended, by contrast to tautologies,

    have their origin in sense-experience. However, Hume agreed with Descartes in that sense-

    perception does not provide solid knowledge. (Ingram, 1990, p. 7) Starting from an

    empirical standpoint, Hume ends up accepting sceptical conclusions.

    Hume argued that certain notions we take for granted are in actual fact highly doubtful and

    cannot be ascertained. He denied that there is a necessary link between what we see as a

    cause and its perceived effect. The link, he maintained, is constructed by the mind out of

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    13/38

    13

    habit, and cannot be rationally inferred that future events will conform to past events.

    (Ingram p. 7) Apart from casual necessity, Hume also deconstructed the Cartesian Ego, and

    maintained that the postulation of a permanent ego is unfounded. He pointed out that

    whenever it is asked the question 'what am I?', the only rational answer that can be given is

    that 'I am all the ideas I have together'. In other words, there is no observable object which

    corresponds to the 'I'. (Scruton, 1995, p. 130) Finally, Hume also denied moral freedom, and

    argued that reason was handmaiden to passions (Ingram, 1990, p. 8)

    Kant agrees with Hume in that causal necessity is not something inherent in reality, but he

    was not ready to accept his sceptical conclusion. He argues that the problem with the

    rationalists and empiricists was that both assumed a passive mind whose sense-impressions

    are imposed on it from the outside. In his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant proposes a

    revolution similar to the one put forward by Copernicus. (Scruton, 1995, p. 142) He argues

    that the mind organises experience by imposing its own innate structure on sense-perception.

    Thus, for example, the mind is a priori equipped, or knows a priori, that for every cause

    there must be an effect; when perceiving two distinct events, say a melting ice-cream and the

    heat of the sun, the mind structures the two events in such a way that the melting is

    conceived as an effect of the heat. In this way, the mind is envisaged as actively organising

    experience according to its own, innate, logical knowledge. However, innate knowledge on

    its own, or what Kant terms the categories, are empty; on the other hand, unstructured

    experience is blind. This productive notion of reason that Kant develops, as will be

    explained below, must also assume a unity of consciousness, without which no active

    organisation of experience would ever be possible.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    14/38

    14

    The Unity of Apperception, Freedom, Morality

    In The Critique of Pure Reason Kant deals with a number of antinomies of reason. An

    antinomy is a paradox that arises when two contradictory positions can be shown to be

    reasonably acceptable. (Copleston, 1960b, p. 286) In resolving the rationalist-empiricist

    debate Kant argues that the mind makes sense of the information captured through the senses

    by organising it according to an a priori structure. Thus, it was said above, that every event

    is conceived as having a cause, and as causing a further event (its effect). In contrast, actions,

    as opposed to events, seem to be caused by a spontaneous ego. These two contradictory

    positions, however, create a contradiction, an antinomy - how can an action, which is always

    also an event, be caused spontaneously by the ego, and at the same time be determined by an

    antecedent cause?

    Kant argues that experience is only possible if there is a permanent ego that provides a

    ground for uniting experience (a unity of apperception). The ego is a necessary condition for

    any experience whatsoever. Since experience is real, Kant argues, its necessary condition

    must mutatis mutandis be real as well. However, he also agrees with Hume in that the

    permanent ego is never given in experience. Therefore, on the one hand a permanent ego

    seems to be a necessity for experience, while on the other hand, a permanent ego is never

    empirically observed. To resolve this contradiction, Kant distinguishes between an empirical

    ego, an ego given in experience but which is not permanent, and a transcendental ego, a

    necessary permanent ego for experience. By postulating a transcendental ego as the

    guarantor of the unity of apperception, Kant was able to free the ego from the rigid

    determinism that the understanding seems to impose. The ego, says Kant, as an empirical

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    15/38

    15

    ego, is subject to the deterministic law of cause and effect. As a transcendental ego (whose

    existence cannot nonetheless be verified), however, it is not. (Copleston, 1960b, pp. 2846)

    To show that the two egos can exist even if they seem to be mutually exclusive, Kant also

    distinguishes between the phenomena and the nuomena.7

    The distinction between the

    empirical and the transcendental ego holds only if a distinction between phenomena and

    nuomena is also made. The phenomena refer to sense-experience as organised according to

    the categories. Phenomena are observable events and objects. The nuomena, on the other

    hand, refer to the things in themselves. So, the empirical ego, Kant argues, is the ego as

    perceived by the senses and organised according to the categories, while the transcendental

    ego is the ego in itself. In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant argues that the human being can

    never access the nuomena, since he are confronted only with already structured sense-

    perception. In fact, in The Critique of Practical Reason, he acknowledges that we can never

    prove that we are free (i.e. that a transcendental ego exists); but on other hand, he argued, we

    can show that freedom is not logically impossible. As such, since practical reason demands

    that we are free, for unless we are free we can never act morally, we ought to think of

    ourselves as free.

    In his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant develops the necessary structure of possible experience,

    in other words, the categories through which sense is made of the world. Similarly, in the

    Critique of Practical Reason, he attempts to develop the a priori principles that are

    7There are various interpretations of what Kant actually meant when he distinguished between the nuomena

    and phenomena. In this work, we will stick to the widely accepted interpretation that by nuomena and

    phenomena, Kant meant that there is one object but two different standpoints. This is usually called the Two

    Standpoint/Aspect Theory, as opposed to the Two World/Object Theory. For a discussion of the issue, one cansee Robert Hannas work, where the author develops a third view, which he calls the Two Concept/Property

    Theory see. Hanna, R. (2006). Kant, Science and Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon. Press.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    16/38

    16

    applicable to morality. Such a principle is called by Kant the categorical imperative. To

    explain what the categorical imperative is, it is useful to first distinguish it from the

    hypothetical imperative. An imperative is hypothetical if it is dependent on an antecedent

    condition that needs to be satisfied. For example, If you want to live a happy life, then you

    ought to act morally is a hypothetical imperative. Thus, a hypothetical imperative h as the

    logical form of If a then b. For Kant, such an imperative cannot be adequately

    universalised; a truly a priori imperative, that is applicable to all actions, must be categorical

    i.e. not depending on any antecedents. (Copleston, 1960b, p. 322)

    Kant said that there is only one categorical imperative. However, he also said that there are

    three formulations of the categorical imperative, and he then gives five formulations.

    Copleston interprets this apparent contradiction as meaning that Kant gave various

    formulations of the same, categorical imperative in order to explicate further the categorical

    imperative. (1960b, p. 326) The important point to bring out here is that according to Kant

    reason can offer a rational guide to morality.

    0.5 Philosophy of History: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

    Hegels philosophy represents a departure from Kant's transcendentalism towards a more

    worldly definition of reason. Unlike Kant, Hegel conceives reason as developing in

    interaction and labour. It can be said, that the most important notions that Hegel introduces

    in relation to Critical Theory are his ideas that reason is shaped and influenced by the

    historical conditions it is faced with, and that it is dialectical, or dynamic. With regard to the

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    17/38

    17

    first, Engels, Marx's colleague, had said:

    What distinguishes Hegel's mode of thinking from that of all other philosophers was theexceptional historical sense underlying it. However abstract and idealist employed, the

    development of his ideas run always parallel to the development of world history, and the

    latter is indeed supposed to be only the proofof the former. (Singer, 1983, p. 123)

    Both ideas, the dynamism of reason and the historicity of reason, are related to yet another

    important Hegelian notion: freedom. For Hegel, as it will be argued below, the development

    ofreason in history is also the development offreedom.

    Criticism of Kant

    In the Introduction to the Phenomenology of Mind Hegel deals with the philosophical

    problem of finding a valid starting-point for philosophy. He says that philosophers have

    attempted to find rational criteria that would demarcate proper knowledge from mere

    apparent knowledge. (Norman, 1991, p. 9) Such an approach has been undertaken by both

    rationalists and empiricists alike. Descartes, for example, in the Discourse on Method, had

    developed a number of rules that have to be followed if one is to make correct use of the

    intellect. However, while what Hegel says in the Introduction applies to any philosophical

    endeavour which seeks to establish a set of criteria before engaging in any philosophical

    activity, it is clear that he has Kant in mind. (Norman, p. 11)

    Hegel argues that the sceptical8

    approach that seeks to delimit the use of reason has to

    presuppose three particular assumptions. First, that knowledge is itself fundamentally a sort

    8The sceptical approach is the approach that attempts to establish the limits of reason and the understanding

    before making any constative proposition.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    18/38

    18

    of instrument or medium, and consequently, one must first examine its appropriateness

    before making use of it. Second, that there exists a real distinction between knowledge, or

    what Kant called knowledge of the phenomena, and real knowledge, or what Kant called

    knowledge of things-in-themselves (and what Hegel calls Absolute knowledge). Third, it

    must also assume that knowledge of the phenomena can properly be called knowledge.

    (Norman p. 11) Presuppositions, however, are themselves claims to knowledge, and any

    genuine sceptical approach requires that such suppositions are critically examined. Thus, any

    attempt to delimit the use of reason, is bound to lead either to an infinite regress or to

    circularity. (Norman p. 12)

    In theLesser Logic, Hegel presents a very clear criticism of the above mentioned approach,

    this time with an explicit reference to Kant:

    We ought, says Kant, to be acquainted with the instrument, before we undertake the work

    for which it is to be employed; for if the instrument be insufficient, all our trouble will be

    spent in vain Unless we wish to be deceived by words, it is easy to see what this amounts

    to. In the case of other instruments, we can try and criticise them in other ways than bysetting about the special work for which we are destined. But the examination of knowledge

    can only be carried out by an act of knowledge. To examine this so called instrument is the

    same thing as to know it. But to seek to know before we know is as absurd as the wise

    resolution of Scholasticus, not to venture into the water until he had learned to swim. (The

    Logic of Hegel in Norman, p. 11)

    Since philosophy cannot proceed by first establishing the limits of the knowing subject, as

    this would lead either to an infinite regress or circular reasoning, Hegel proposes instead to

    begin philosophy by immediately examining phenomena. In this way, he avoids the dilemma

    of epistemology that haunts the Kantian approach.

    The phenomenology of Hegel differs from the Kantian approach in two main respects. First,

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    19/38

    19

    it recognises the historical nature of reason. For Hegel, reason is an objective historical

    force that must be conceived dynamically or developmentally (Ingram, 1990, p. 11)

    Second, Hegel conceives the dialectic tension in thought as being productive, unlike Kant

    who regarded contradictions as resulting out of a mis-usage of the cognitive faculties.

    (Ingram, p. 12) To appreciate these two characteristics of Hegels philosophy, it is necessary

    to make some remarks on Hegels Phenomenology.

    The Odyssey of the Mind

    In the Phenomenology of MindHegel writes the detailed history of the process of training

    and educating consciousness itself up to the level of science. (Singer, 1983 p. 169) While

    for Kant science was the starting point of any valid philosophy, for Hegel it was the end of

    the philosophical process. He envisages the Mind as passing through a number of stages in a

    struggle to understand itself, to attain knowledge of the whole (the Absolute Idea). (Ingram,

    1990, p. 13)

    For Hegel, contradictions or dialectic tensions are conceived as an opportunity for the Mind

    to attain positive knowledge. (Ingram, 1990, p. 13) They are part and parcel of the minds

    progression towards absolute knowledge. The Mind first accepts an idea that it thinks

    explains reality. However, it soon realises that the accepted idea, the thesis, is countered by

    another idea, the antithesis, and which thus invalidates the content of the former. The Mind

    thus rejects the thesis and instead upholds the antithesis. Then again, a moment comes when

    the Mind understands that the antithesis is also faulty. It thus unites the two opposing ideas,

    into a higher more correct idea: the synthesis. This process of thesis, antithesis and synthesis

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    20/38

    20

    is repeated until the Mind appropriates the absolute idea.

    The dialectical process is related to another very important Hegelian notion: the idea that

    reason manifests itself in society. Hegel argues that the progress achieved by the Mind in the

    logical sphere, is manifested in society as institutional and political change. For Hegel the

    logical and the historical are two sides of the same coin. (Ingram, 1990, p. 13) He views

    history as being powered by the contrast between the real (say a thesis), that is society

    organised according to a particular idea, and the ideal (say the antithesis). When

    philosophers or religious leaders make explicit or articulate the contradiction that exists

    between the cultural sphere (the social sphere) and the ideal (the logical sphere), a rationality

    crisis occurs. This leads to a revolution that attempts to adjust the real in accordance with the

    ideal. The process goes on until Absolute knowledge is achieved and society is made to

    correspond in accordance to the absolute idea. (Ingram, p. 14)

    Hegel's odyssey of Mind is thus rooted in his philosophy of history. In the Philosophy of

    History, Hegel states that The history of the world is none other than the progress of the

    consciousness of freedom. (Singer, p. 125) Hegel conceives history as having a purpose,

    and consequently he engages into a philosophy of history, or reflection about the

    significance and purpose of history. His basic idea is that the development of Mind shouldnt

    be understood only logically, as in his Phenomenology of Mind, but should also be traced

    historically through different historical periods, as has been hinted above. Thus, for example,

    from the Persian period to the Greek period, he sees a development of consciousness, where

    in the Persian Empire only one consciousness has freedom, that being the emperor, in

    Ancient Greece the development of individual freedom takes place, even though this

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    21/38

    21

    freedom is limited to male citizens. For Hegel, the history of consciousness is thus also the

    history of freedom.

    0.6 Marxs Historical Materialism

    Karl Marx (18181883) was influenced by Hegel's philosophy of history. He, like Hegel,

    accepts the thesis that history can be understood and consequently explained with reference

    to particular historical and social realities. Moreover, he accepts the dialectical approach.

    Evidence of this is the way his monumental workCapital is structured. However, contrary to

    Hegel, he does not think that ideas stand at the basis of development; on the contrary, he

    argues that ideas are mere expressions of existing material conditions. This section deals

    with three main Marxist themes, these being his concept of alienation, historical materialism

    and his ideas on ideology and exploitation. In Chapter 2, the issue of whether Marx was a

    determinist or not, linking this debate with the schism that occurred in the first half of the

    twentieth century between orthodox Marxists and Western Marxists will be dealt with.

    Alienation

    One Marxian commentator9argues that Marxs system of alienation stands at the core of the

    Marxian system. (Wood, 2004, p. 5) The concept of alienation occurs throughout Marxs

    work; however, it is clear that in Marxs later writings, the concept of alienation loses the

    9The commentator in question is Istvan Meszaros. See Wood p. 4.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    22/38

    22

    centrality Marx had assigned to it in his early works. In his fragment Estranged Labour'10,

    Marx seems to be arguing that all types of alienation are but different aspects of a single

    system, where each type is based on one paradigm form of alienation: alienated laboring

    activity. (Wood, p. 4) In this text, alienation is assigned a basic explanatory role. Wood

    argues that although the concept of alienation occurs in many of Marxs later writings, such

    as in the Grundrisse and in Capital, in the later writings it takes a more peripheral role. If in

    Marxs early writings alienation is explanatory, in his later writings, it becomes descriptive

    or diagnostic. (Wood, p. 7)

    Marx owes the concept of alienation to both Hegel and Feuerbach. Hegel, as explained in the

    previous section, conceives the history of humanity as a process of de-alienating Mind. On

    the other hand, Feuerbach argues that man is alienated when he projects an imaginary God,

    and directs his affirmation and love to this imaginary deity. The postulation of a God

    requires, Feuerbach contends, the degradation of human beings. To enrich God, he says,

    the human being must become poor; that God may be all, the human being must be

    nothing. (Wood, p. 12) While Feuerbach is critical of Hegels quasi-mystical philosophy,

    he however agrees with the latter in equating alienation with false consciousness i.e. an

    erroneous conception of mans relation to ultimate reality. (Wood, p. 10) Both thinkers thus,

    consider alienation as being essentially a theoretical mistake. Consequently, both argue that

    the remedy to alienation resides in a correction of such false consciousness.

    From his early writings, Marx makes it clear that his understanding of alienation has to do

    10The fragment in question makes part of The Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, which are sometimes

    referred to as The Paris Manuscripts.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    23/38

    23

    with the practical productive life of the workers. In his famous fragment Estranged Labour,

    Marx says that the medium through which estrangement takes place is itselfpractical.

    (Marx, XXV) For Marx, alienation results from the kind of labouring activity that takes

    place within the capitalist society.

    The early Marx, in the Estranged Labour fragment, develops a four-fold typology of

    alienation: alienation from ones product, from the labouring activity, from ones humanity

    or species being, and finally from other men. In capitalism, man, Marx argues, confronts the

    product as something alien, as apower independent of him. (Marx, XXII) The product that

    man produces in a capitalist society is never owned by the producer who makes it.

    Alienation in this sense shows the unnatural separation that takes place in capitalist

    production. The product thus appears as loss of realizationfor the workers. (Marx, XXII)

    The product is estranged from the worker only because the production act itself is alienating.

    The alienated product is just the summation of the alienating labouring activity. (Marx,

    XXIII) Thus the first form of alienation, alienation from the produced product, is in reality a

    result of the second type, that is, alienating labour activity. Thirdly, man is also alienated

    from his own nature, his own species being. What is supposed to be an expression of mans

    essential being, in capitalism becomes merely and exclusively a means for subsistence.

    Marx says that different from animals, man can produce in freedom and in accordance with

    the laws of beauty. (Wood p. 7) In capitalistic production, this distinctive characteristic of

    man, which sets him apart from other animals, is lost. Thus in this kind of production, Marx

    says, what is animal becomes human and what is human becomes animal. (Marx, XXIV)

    Finally, man is also alienated from other man. The product that the workers produce is at the

    end of the day owned by other men. (Marx, XXIV)

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    24/38

    24

    Wood points out that Marxs conception of alienation rests on a particular unde rstanding of

    human nature. This, however, does not mean that Marx thinks that man has an objective

    nature independent of any social formation. On the contrary, he asserts that the human

    condition cannot be grasped apart from the social structure within which it exists, especially

    the economic structure. Nevertheless, Marx argues that there is something distinctive about

    human beings that set them apart from the rest of nature. (Wood, p. 17) This distinctive

    feature is production. Wood interprets Marx as saying that human beings are essentially

    productive beings. (p. 28) What is distinctive in human production is that man produces

    consciously and purposively. (p. 32)

    If human beings are fundamentally productive beings, Wood argues, it follows that human

    self-fulfilment is achieved in production. (p. 28) However, not any kind of production is self-

    fulfilling. According to Marx, as he writes in Estranged Labour, man fulfils his nature

    when he produces freely. It is production free from physical need. In this fragment, Marx

    argues that in capitalist societies, the workers most humane characteristic, their ability to

    duplicate themselves in reality through the product produced, is reduced to a mere means for

    subsistence. (Marx, XXIV) This creative element in human nature is frustrated. Thus, argues

    Wood, alienation results when human essential powers are frustrated, stopped from

    developing. (Wood, p. 24) In this way, the workers experience a life that lacks meaning and

    self-worth. (Wood, p. 8)

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    25/38

    25

    Historical Materialism

    Marx disagrees with Hegels claim that social progress is an effect of progress in the realm

    of ideas. Hegel had argued that when the Mind ascents to a more accurate conception of

    reality, social organisation adjusts itself to the newly acquired understanding. On the

    contrary, Marx maintains that social life in general is determined by material production.

    Accordingly, economic reality stands at the base, of which social formation is just an effect.

    (Wood, pp. 63 - 4) He claims that his materialist conception of history turns Hegels

    dialectic rightside up. (Ingram, 1990, p. 19)

    Marx maintains that material production is determined by what he calls forces of

    production. In the narrowest sense, forces of production include the labour power of the

    workers and the tools and instruments used to perform the work. In a wider sense, forces of

    production also include the organisation of the work done, or the division of labour. Marx

    asserts that the forces of production, understood as instruments, determine a particular

    division of labour. (Wood p. 67) Productive forces in the wider sense, i.e. workers labour

    power, instruments, as well as a particular division of labour, determine a particular set of

    relations of production, i.e. a certain set of social and economic institutions, relationships of

    power, authority and ownership within which labor is carried on. (Wood, p. 68) Thus for

    Marx, within the economic structure (which is itself more fundamental when compared to

    the superstructure), productive forces are the most fundamental element.

    In the Marxian materialist conception of history, relations of production always adjust to

    changes in the forces of production. Marx conceives material progress as being dominated

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    26/38

    26

    by a dialectical tension between developing forces of production and relations of production.

    When the former expand to the extent that their unfulfilled potential is constrained by the

    kind of production relations that exist in a given society at a particular point in time, a

    revolution occurs. The revolution changes the relations of production that hinder the

    fulfilling of the potential of the forces of production. Thus, for example, according to Marx,

    capitalist relations of production prevailed over feudal relations of production because the

    latter got in the way of the developing forces of production. Similarly, socialism would

    emerge out of capitalism once the latters relations of production begin to hinder the

    expression of the developing forces of production. (Wood, p. 81) Relations of production are

    thus conceived by Marx as changing in accordance with the necessities of the ever

    developing forces of production. However, he does not claim that change is automatic.

    Counter-forces, such as ideologies and social institutions (which pertain to the

    superstructure), tend to back the current relations of production and delay the above

    mentioned adjustment.

    While Marx definitely claims that at the basis of the economic base stand the developing

    forces of production, he does not explain change as occurring with an absence of mind. At

    the end of the day, it is people that bring change; more specifically classes. In fact Marx

    regards history as a history of struggles between social classes. In this respect, individual

    motives and actions become secondary to a general understanding of a dynamic history of

    classes. (Wood, p. 89)

    Marx never completed the section on classes in Capital. However, by class, he seems to

    have understood a group of individuals with a common situation and common interests that

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    27/38

    27

    arise out of definite relations of production. (Wood, p. 90) Conflicts between classes, rather

    than conflicts within classes are considered by Marx to be historically determining. (Wood,

    p. 91) History, as he sees it, can be explained as a struggle between two major classes: that

    which owns the means of production, and that which has labour to offer in exchange for

    money. It must be said though, that for Marx a true class is a class in itself; a class that is

    conscious of its own interests. (Wood, p. 92) This does not mean that for a class to be for

    itself it must develop a sophisticated theoretical analysis, but it does imply some kind of

    political organisation. (Wood, p. 94) Each class has a particular goal in history, this being the

    establishment of a particular set of production relations that favour the interests of that

    particular class. (Wood, p. 95) A class in-itself is a class that manages to recognise its

    interests together with the kind of production relations that would actualise these same

    interests.

    Ideology and Exploitation

    Wood discerns three basic uses of ideology in the Marxian corpus. (p. 118) The first use of

    the concept of ideology is found in The German Ideology, a work co-authored with Engels.

    In this work, ideology refers to the idea that the principal determining factor of historical

    change is the idea. (p. 119) As has been explained above when discussing alienation, both

    Hegel and Feuerbach argued that alienation is merely a false consciousness, and the

    overcoming of alienation requires the correction of such a mistake. Marx and Engels

    consider such views as those upheld by Hegel and Feuerbach ideological.

    The second usage of ideology is called by Wood functional ideology. As the term implies,

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    28/38

    28

    functional ideology is an ideology that serves a specific purpose. In this sense, ideology

    refers to the materialist thesis that socially prevalent or influential ideas can be explained by

    showing how they either sanction the social relations determined by the existing stage of

    productive powers or express and promote class interests. (p. 120) It is in this sense that

    Marx says that jurisprudence, religion, art and morality in general are ideological. (p. 120)

    The third usage of ideology is called by Wood ideological illusion. Here ideology means

    consciousness which is ignorant of its own real social and historical significance. (p. 120)

    In other words, ideology in this sense refers to ignorance with regards the materialist basis of

    reality.

    These three uses of ideology are intimately related. For example, historical idealism can be

    both functional ideology, serving the interests of particular class, and also ideological

    illusion, as it negates the materialist basis of reality. (Wood, p. 121) Moreover, it must be

    said that ideological illusion is always functional ideology, but functional ideology need not

    be ideological illusion. (Wood, p. 121) In fact, Wood claims that in principle the materialist

    conception of history can be functional ideology as it serves the interests of a particular

    class, the proletariat. (p. 121)

    In capitalism, ideological illusions serve to justify the exploitative nature of capitalistic

    relations of productions. The concepts of ideology and alienation are closely related to the

    concept of exploitation in the Marxian corpus. In a capitalist society, the capitalist owns the

    means of production, while the worker owns nothing except his labour power. Exploitation,

    according to Wood, results from the fact that labour power is vulnerable to capital and not

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    29/38

    29

    simply from an unfair exchange.11 The workers have no option but to yield to the current

    system of exchangeif they dont they would starve to death. Thus, according to Marx, as

    interpreted by Wood, exploitation results from the fact that the worker is always in weak

    bargaining position. (p. 251).

    0.7 Conclusion: Habermas, Critical Theory and the Philosophical

    Problems of Modernity

    The outline of the thought of the philosophers of early modernity (from Descartes to Marx)

    provides a panoramic view of the problems raised in philosophical modernity. It was argued

    that the main problem that modern thinkers dealt with was that of reason; however, the

    addressing of such an important concept requires the tackling of the web of issues to which

    rationality relates. The school of thought that is usually referred to as the Frankfurt School,

    the school of thought to which Habermas belongs, developed in part12

    as a reaction to the

    philosophical heritage of modern European philosophy. In this brief conclusion of the

    Introduction, a preliminary discussionof the problems of philosophical modernity and the

    way critical theorists responded, in particular Habermas, will be presented.

    The problem of rationality is thus the fundamental problem of modernity itself. An

    understanding of modernity requires an understanding of modern reason, that is to say, the

    11Wood criticises the idea that exploitation refers to the fact that the workers spend only a part of their working

    day for their own subsistence. On the other hand, Ingram seems to argue exactly the contrary. For a comparison

    see Ingram p. 22 and Wood p. 250.12

    Critical Theory is normative, in the sense that it seeks to change the cultural, social and political formation in

    which it is begotten. If this were not the case, then at most it would be critical philosophy. As such, any kind of

    critical theory reacts to both the philosophical andpolitical heritage in which it develops.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    30/38

    30

    way modern philosophers conceived and understood reason. This does not mean however

    that early modern philosophers (from Descartes to Marx), had a univocal understanding of

    what it means to be rational. On the contrary, it may be argued that in philosophical

    modernity there are various conceptions of reason. In fact, it will be argued that in the early

    modern period, there are at least three different conceptions of reason: a subjectivist

    conception, which was roughly embraced by Descartes and Kant, a developmental

    conception of reason which however gives priority to the realm of ideas over the material

    realm, which was developed by Hegel, and another developmental conception of reason

    which gives priority to the material condition over the realm of ideas, which was developed

    by Marx.

    Apart from the theoretical problem of rationality, the early modern period also presents the

    practical problem of rationality. Modern philosophers were not simply interested in

    developing a consistent conception of rationality, but also sought to provide ways in which

    reason can be consistently applied to moral and social-political issues. These two types of

    practical rationality can be separated conceptually, but are in reality intimately related. A

    conception of practical rationality is usually developed to be applied to interactions between

    human beings, understood as being normatively regulated and as belonging, directly or

    indirectly, to the social-political sphere of human life. Central to the problem of practical

    rationality is the issue of how to bridge theory with practice, that is to say, how to ground or

    justify normative claims. In fact, the issue of justification is central to any critical theory.

    Finally, the philosophical issues that stem from early modernity can make the project of

    modernity itself an issue: is modernity, as expressed in the tradition that makes the human

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    31/38

    31

    being and his rational capabilities at the centre of any moral, social and political endeavour,

    misconceived, and thus ought to be abandoned? This third issue has been raised by various

    contemporary philosophers who saw an anti-human element in the tradition of modernity.

    The three philosophical problems just outlined - the problem of a theoretical definition of

    reason, the problem of how to bridge theory and practice, and the issue of the project of

    modernity itself have been tackled by Habermas and other critical theorists. In what

    follows in this introduction, these three problems will be discussed in order to introduce the

    early critical theorists and Habermas.

    The Theoretical Conception of Rationality

    Before delving into the critical theory of the Frankfurt School, it is imperative to clarify what

    is meant by the theoretical conception of rationality. When the question what is

    rationality? is posed, the expected answer would be a theoretical elaboration of what

    rationality is. To be sure, one may seek to define rationality by giving examples of what it

    means to be rational (ostension), but the ultimate answer would be a conception, in strictly

    theoretical terms, of the idea of rationality.

    Early critical theorists refuted both the conception of rationality offered by the subjectivists

    (Descartes and Kant), and by Idealism (Hegel). First generation critical theorists offered two

    different criticisms to the subjectivist conception of reason: one such criticism is found in

    Marcuses Philosophy and Critical Theory, whereas the other is found, amongst other

    works, in Horkheimers and AdornosDialectic of Enlightenment.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    32/38

    32

    In Philosophy and Critical Theory, Marcuse argues that the subjectivist13 and idealist

    conception of rationality is complacent to the status-quo; this is because as a conception it is

    limited to the realm of ideas. In his criticism of Rationalism and Idealism, Marcuse contends

    that real freedom is freedom from material oppression. Basically here Marcuse is rehashing

    the Marxist critique of Hegel. The criticism offered by Marcuse and other early critical

    theorists will be discussed in detail in Chapter 1.3. In the Dialectic of Enlightenment,

    Horkheimer and Adorno equate the subjectivist conception of rationality with the

    instrumental conception of rationality.14The authors argue that the barbarism experienced

    in the twentieth century is nothing other than a consequence of an instrumentalist-

    subjectivist conception of reason that goes back to the ancient world. The arguments

    presented in the Dialectic of Enlightenment(and Habermass critique) will be discussed in

    Chapter 1.7and 1.8.

    Habermas refutes all the three conceptions of rationality discussed above, that is to say, the

    subjectivist, the idealist and the materialist. He argues that his predecessors, most notably

    Horkheimer and Adorno, while understanding that the subjectivist conception of reason is

    faulty and limited, fail to make the necessary paradigm shift towards a fuller conception of

    reason. In his Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Habermas is particularly critical of

    Horkheimer and Adorno. He argues that the criticism levelled by Horkheimer and Adorno

    against the subjectivist conception of reason (as will be argued below, against the project of

    13Marcuse uses the term rationalist to refer to the subjectivist conception discussed here.

    14In this they agree with Martin Heidegger who sees the philosophy of Descartes as preparing the groundwork

    for a conception of reason that would go instrumental. This theme is tackled by Heidegger in various works,

    most notably in his lectures on Nietzsche and in Being and Time. The critique of instrumental reason is then

    radicalized by Heidegger in his famous paper The Essence of Technology. In this paper, Heidegger calls for a

    different attitude of the human being towards Being from that found in the technological-instrumental

    disclosure of Being.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    33/38

    33

    modernity itself), commits them to a performative contradiction. Following Nietzsche,

    Horkheimer and Adorno provide a radical critique of reason with the result being that they

    leave no rational criterion which can justify their critique.

    Habermas argues for a paradigm shift from the philosophy of the subject to the philosophy

    of language. In The Theory of Communicative Action Vol. I & II Habermas distinguishes

    between communicative action and strategic action. This distinction is necessary to

    understand Habermass reconstruction of reason. Communicative action refers to action that

    aims at reaching understanding and agreement. On the other hand, strategic action is action

    that is goal oriented, and thus subjects understanding and agreement to the attaining of ones

    goals. The following is a reconstruction of Habermass argument:

    i. Speech has a rational basis.ii. There are at least two types of social action involving speech: communicative

    action and strategic action.

    iii. Communicative action is fundamental, whereas strategic action is parasitic oncommunicative action.

    iv. Therefore communicative rationality, which is the kind of rationality that governsspeech, is fundamental.

    i. Speech has a rational basis.Habermas argues that whenever a speaker engages in communicative action through the

    uttering of a speech act, he is simultaneously raising four different validity claims: a truth

    claim, a normative claim, a truthfulness claim and comprehensibility claim. In essence, this

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    34/38

    34

    means that the speaker must if the need arises, justify or ground what he says. This

    expectation is inherent in speech, meaning that it is immanent, and effective communication

    cannot by-pass such expectation of grounding.

    ii. There are at least two types of social action involving speech: communicative actionand strategic action.

    Communicative action is not the only possible social action. There are other forms, amongst

    them strategic action. Strategic action is when a speaker utters a speech act knowingly that

    he is being insincere. So whereas communicative action, that is, action oriented towards

    mutual understanding, requires that all four validity claims are raised, the actor who engages

    in strategic action suspends (without revealing what his real intention is) the truthfulness

    claim.

    iii. Communicative action is fundamental, whereas strategic action is parasitic oncommunicative action

    The fact that strategic action requires the suspension of one of the four validity claims that

    are on in communicative action, shows that communicative action is fundamental.15

    iv. Therefore communicative rationality, which is the kind of rationality that governsspeech, is fundamental.

    If communicative action is fundamental, and strategic action is derivative, it follows that the

    kind of rationality that governs communicative action is fundamental and that which governs

    15Habermas offers other arguments to support this claim, which will be discussed in full in Chapter 2. For the

    time being it is enough to note that strategic action is parasitic on communicative action.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    35/38

    35

    strategic action is derivative as well. The rationality that governs communicative action is

    termed by Habermas communicative rationality. On the other hand, the rationality that

    governs strategic action is instrumental. So this means that instrumental rationality that is

    equated by Horkheimer and Adorno with subjectivist rationality, is not the only conception

    of rationality, and more than that, is not even fundamental as they assume in the Dialectic of

    Enlightenment. So through his conception of communicative rationality Habermas is able to

    transcend previous conceptions - the subjectivist-instrumental, the idealist and the

    materialist.

    Theory and Practice

    The issue of grounding is an important theme in critical theory. Any critical theory must

    ground the critique it makes, in order to avoid infinite regress or circular reasoning. First

    generation critical theorists have made used of a technique immanent critique, which they

    borrow from Hegel and Marx. Basically this means comparing the real material situation to

    the ideals that were used to justify the current system of production. For example, capitalism

    is usually justified because it enhances justice and equality. A critical theorist who makes

    use of immanent critique would compare the real situation with the promised ideal.

    Habermas refutes such an approach, as he argues that in late capitalism such ideals are no

    longer used to legitimate current relations. Thus, if Habermas is correct here, immanent

    critique loses the critical thrust it relied on before. This will be discussed in Chapter 1.5.

    Marcuse, attempts to develop a different argument to ground his critique in Eros and

    Civilization. In this work he attempts to unite Freudianism with Marxism. His main

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    36/38

    36

    argument, which will be discussed in Chapter 1.6, is that whereas some needs are real, other

    needs are constructed by the system. Critical theory thus can use the tension between real

    needs and false needs to critique the system. Habermas, again, refutes this argument; one of

    the main objections that he levels against Marcuse is that needs are always linguistically

    mediated, and so it is practically impossible to distinguish between the two. Language,

    which is fundamental for human identity, cannot be removed in a sort of epoch as

    envisaged by Husserl. In other words, needs are mediated linguistically, meaning that they

    can only be articulated and thus comprehended linguistically.

    Instead of immanent critique and biological grounding, Habermas makes use of his

    theoretical conception of reason in order to ground his critique. Through the theoretical

    conception of communicative rationality, Habermas is able to provide a theory that can guide

    practice. Habermass contribution in this regard is twofold. On the one hand, the theory of

    communicative action can serve as a conceptual scheme from where to diagnose and offer

    cures for the pathologies of modernity. In fact the theory of communicative action is used by

    Habermas to offer a critical analysis of the domination by what he calls systems of power

    and money (state and economy) in late modernity. This will be the subject-matter ofChapter

    3. On the other hand, the theory of communicative action can serve as the basis of discourse

    ethics. Habermas argues for a cognitivst morality that is rooted in communication and

    dialogue, contrary to moral scepticism. This will be the subject-matter ofChapter 4.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    37/38

    37

    The Project of Modernity

    Habermass reconstruction of reason, which he develops in The Theory of Communicative

    Action Vol. I & II, cannot be understood in isolation from his theory of modernity.

    Horkheimer and Adorno in the Dialectic of Enlightenment provide a radical critique of

    reason but also a radical critique of the possibility of enlightenment and emancipation.

    Habermas argues that the rejection of the project modernity is based on a misconception of

    reason. Modernity should not be understood as being dominated by instrumental reason.

    Horkheimer and Adorno of the Dialectic of Enlightenmentmis-conceptualise modernity as

    they follow the one-sided analysis of Max Weber. Weber considers modernity to be

    characterised by a rise of formal or instrumental rationality, which he concludes led the

    moderns in an iron cage. Habermas argues that the problem with Webers

    conceptualisation lies in the fact that he fails to see that there were two rationalisation

    processes, and not one. For Weber, modern rationalisation is simply the rise of instrumental

    reason, which resulted from the disenchantment of religious and metaphysical narratives.

    Habermas contends, contrary to Weber (and Horkheimer and Adorno), that such a view is

    one-sided. Modernity for Habermas, is characterised by a rationalisation of the lifeworld,

    which refers to the unleashing of the potential inherent in communicative action, and by a

    rationalisation of systems of power and money, which function on a principle of rationality

    that is strictly instrumental (or functional). Thus, Habermas sees modernity and modern

    western society as being guided by two different rational principles, communicative

    rationality in the lifeworld, and instrumental rationality in administrative and economic

    systems, both of which are necessary for the effective functioning of modern society.

  • 7/31/2019 Habermas's Reconstruction of Reason by Keith Pisani - Introduction

    38/38

    Problems arise, Habermas argues, when the instrumental principle encroaches upon areas

    that ought to function in accordance with communicative rationality. A practical example of

    such an encroachment would be when areas like school and family disputes, are subjected to

    instrumental rationality. This will be discussed in Chapter 3.

    For Habermas modernity is thus an unfinished project, which can, through communicative

    rationality, be completed or improved. However, such progress requires first and foremost a

    proper conceptualisation of the development that occurred in modernity with the aid of

    proper concepts that are lacking in theorists like Weber, Horkheimer and Adorno.