Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    1/6

    COMMENTARIES

    Press.

    Rothenberg, A. (1983a). Creativity, articulation, and psychotherapy.

    Journal of

    he aulemy of

    Psychoanalysis, 11, 55-85.

    Rothenberg,

    A.

    (1983b). Psychopathology an d creative cognition: A

    comparison of hospitalized patients, Nobel laureates, and con

    trols. Archives

    of

    General Psychiatry, 40, 937-942.

    Rothenberg, A. (1986). Artistic creation

    as

    stimulated by superim

    posed versus combined-composite visual images.

    o u r t u ~ l of

    Personality

    and

    Social Psychology, 50, 370-381.

    Rothenberg, A. (1988a). The creativeprocess

    of

    sychotherapy. New

    York: Norton.

    Rothenberg, A. (1988b). Creativity and the homospatial process:

    Experimental studies.

    Psychiatric Clinics ofNorthAmerica, 11,

    443-459.

    Rothenberg, A. (1990a). Creativity and madness: New findings

    nd

    old

    stereotypes.

    Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Rothenberg, A. (1990b). Creativity

    n

    adolescence. Psychiatric Clin

    ics of

    NorthAmerica 13,415-434.

    Rothenberg, A., Sobel, R. S. (1980). Creation ofliter ary metaphors

    as stimulated by superimposed versus separated visual images.

    Journal ofMental Imagery,

    4

    77-91.

    Rothenberg, A., Sobel,

    R

    S. (1981 ). Effects of shortened exposure

    time on the creation

    of

    literary metaphors

    as

    stimulated by

    superimposed versus separated visual images. Perceptual

    and

    Motor Skills, 53, 1007-1009.

    Sobel, R. S., Rothenberg,

    A.

    (1980). Artistic creation as stimulated

    by

    superimposed versus separated visual images. Journal of

    Personality andSocial Psychology, 39, 953-961.

    Creativity Causality and the Separation o Personality and Cognition

    Mark A. Runco

    California State University, Fullerton

    Eysenck' s argument hinges

    on

    the distinction be

    tween (a) creativity, or originality, as a dispositional

    traitor cognitive style, measurable by means

    of

    psycho

    metric tests, normally distributed in the population, and

    general in its application and

    (b)

    creativity defined by

    exceptional achievement. Clearly, this distinction is

    very important for those studying creativity, and, al

    though potential and actual performance have been

    conceptually extricated before (e.g., MacKinnon,

    1965; Maslow, 1971), Eysenck has done a remarkable

    job of

    it. I am especially taken by his integration

    of

    such

    varied lines

    of

    research and

    am

    particularly grateful that

    be has brought biological and genetic research into his

    theory. Clearly, the field

    of

    creativity research is in need

    of such integrative efforts.

    Difficulties naturally arise when integrations are at

    tempted, and several are apparent in Eysenck's work.

    In this commentary, I focus on Eysenck's assump

    tions-at least those I noted and

    question-and

    some

    research findings he overlooked. I

    do

    not itemize the

    stronger points ofEysenck's argument. He presents his

    argument quite well, and there is

    of

    course no need for

    me to reiterate. The most troubling assumptions con

    cern causality, the separation ofpersonality and cogni

    tion, and the role

    of

    problem solving in creativity. I also

    mention his less significant assumptions about diver

    gent thinking, verbal processes, and the distribution

    of

    creative potential.

    Causality

    One

    of

    the most critical

    of

    Eysenck's assumptions

    concerns the direction

    of

    effect. Consider Eysenck's

    suggestion that what may be happening is that high P

    [psychoticism] is necessary for high creativity. Later

    be writes that it appears to be psychoticism

    in

    the

    absence

    of

    psychosis that is the vital element in trans

    lating the trait of creativity (originality) from potential

    into actual achievement, and later still he explicitly

    refers to creativity as an outcome. The notion about

    affinities with schizophrenia and psychotic disorders

    may help explain the oft-cited association between

    creativity and psychopathology (e.g., Becker, 1978;

    Richards, 1981), but the emphasis on one direction of

    effect is disturbing because there are other possibilities

    (Richards, 1990). Put very simply, creativity might lead

    or contribute to what appears to be a disorder (most

    likely a bipolar affective disorder), or the disorder

    might somehow allow creative insights. A third possi

    bility is that creativity and disorder are associated only

    because they both share some underlying tendency.

    (This third variable may very well be what Eysenck

    refers to as

    overinclusive thinking.

    I am not suggesting

    that Eysenck is wrong about psychoticism but rather

    that his theory might not help

    us

    understand the other

    important possibilities, such as when creativity leads to

    anxiety, alcoholism, and depression (Richards, 1990;

    Rothenberg, 1990).

    Eysenck does recognize that there is an optimal level

    ofpsychoticism (or, more accurately, that psychoticism

    is by definition moderate), beyond which psychopa

    thology and creativity are independent. This is entirely

    consistent with work by Bowden (in press) and Rich

    ards (1990) in that it is Bipolar II and III (not the

    schizoaffective Bipolar I) that seem to be associated

    with creativity. According to Bowden and Richards,

    creativity may be associated with mood swings, but the

    disorders are of subclinical levels. In fact, there are

    some creative individuals who want

    to

    avoid clinical

    22

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    2/6

    COMMENTARIES

    treatment precisely because it may interfere with their

    productive periods (Bowden, in press; Rothenberg,

    1990).

    The Creative Personality

    n

    several places, Eysenck offers what strikes me as

    an either/or description

    of

    personality and cognition.

    For example, he writes how "Spearman (1923, 1927)

    suggested that creativity might be a personality charac

    teristic rather than a cognitive characteristic [and] H. J.

    Eysenck (1983) gave some evidence to support this

    notion." The problem is the implication that creativity

    is either

    a

    personality characteristic" or a cognitive

    characteristic." Surely it is both What is really needed

    to understand creativity is the recognition of an inter

    play between cognitive

    and

    extracognitive factors

    (Runco, in press-a; Russ, 1993; Shaw & Runco, in

    press).

    1

    As a matter

    of

    fact, the extracognitive and cognitive

    factors might very well be inextricable. Lazarus (1991)

    reviewed evidence for this, but I will give the example

    wherein an individual cannot be interested in solving a

    problem

    or

    working productively without recognizing

    that there is a

    problem-that

    is, without a cognitive

    appraisal

    of

    the situation as a problem and deserving

    of

    his or her effort (Runco, in press-a). Simply put, the

    cognitive appraisal is necessary for the affective inter

    est. Granted, my example relies on what is usually

    called intrinsi

    motivation

    but that is often included in

    descriptions

    of

    the creative personality (Barron Har

    rington, 1981), and my point is that any either/or argu

    ment is unrealistic.

    A similar oversimplification arises when Eysenck

    discusses the importance

    of

    relevance. I think he is

    correct in questioning the blind or stochastic aspects of

    the creative process, and

    he

    argues convincingly that

    cognitive searches are directed and selective.

    2

    Individ

    uals usually consider only information they believe to

    be in some way relevant or meaningful. My concern is

    with the manner in which the concepts of "relevance"

    and "horizons" are used to distinguish between creative

    1

    Eysenck himsel f calls for work on the cognition-affect interac

    tions.

    n

    particular, he notes the need for research

    on

    "creative

    tension," and this assumes a cognitive appraisal (Runco, in press-a).

    Moreover, both Eysenck and Runco cite Rutter's (1985) theory of

    resilience--Eysenck asking for research on "protective factors,"

    Runco using it to explain the steeling of creative individuals.

    1'hls is entirely consistent with the appraisals already mentioned.

    However, Eysenck does seem to follow the idea

    of

    relevance into one

    dubious alley. I am referring here to his discussion of "delusional

    beliefs, thought disorders, hallucinations, and the like ... [which] ...

    mightbe considered 'creative.'"This seems at odds with his criticism

    of blind factors, for it suggests that purpose is necessary, whereas

    hallucinations and delusions surely lack creative intent. Granted,

    there is some controversy in

    this

    regard, with Mednick (1962) recog

    nizing serendipitous associations and others discounting any "cre

    ativity'' that lacks purpose (Gruber, 1988; Wolf Larson, 1981 ).

    and uncreative persons. I suppose Eysenck's idea is

    simply that there are individual differences, but at this

    point, his discussion seems a bit like a rigid trait

    view

    that is, one downplaying the impact of situations and

    intrapersonal variability.

    Eysenck's trait view is even clearer when discussing

    psychoticism, for there he is explicit that it was not

    psychosis (i.e., a psychopathological state) that was

    related to creative genius, but psychoticism (i.e., a

    dispositional trait

    ...

    )." Eysenck does definepsy hoti -

    ism in terms of susceptibility, but he could bring the

    possible variations more clearly into his model. There

    is an implied connection between "environmental vari

    ables" and "creative achievement," but what about

    specific differences between situations and domains

    (Csikszentrnihalyi, 1990; Gruber, 1988)? Presumably

    an individual can have a wide horizon in one domain

    (e.g., music) but a narrow one in another (e.g., chess).

    The impact or relevance of specific problem types

    might also be recognized, especially those found be

    tween verbal and nonverbal tasks. Empirical evidence

    suggests that associative patterns differ when an indi

    vidual reacts to nonverbal rather than verbal stimuli

    (Guilford, 1968; Richardson, 1986; Runco, 1986).

    Part

    of

    the problem may be Eysenck's reliance

    on

    problem solving. A great deal

    of

    the work he cites-es

    pecially in his discussion

    of

    intelligence and again

    when reviewing the research on overinclusive think

    ing-is specifically on problem solving. This may be

    misleading; creativity should not be too closely tied to

    problem solving. There are several reasons for this,

    including (a) the difficulties involved in definingprob

    lems

    such that artistic creativity

    or

    everyday creativity

    can be explained (Dudek & Cote, in press) and (b) the

    separation between problem finding and problem solv

    ing. The former is more closely tied to creativity than

    the latter (Mumford, Reiter-Palmon, Redmond, in

    press; Okuda, Runco, Berger, 1991; Wakefield, in

    press).

    Verbal Processes

    and

    Divergent

    Thinking

    One reason I appreciate Eysenck's argument about

    relevance is that it highlights the importance

    of

    selec

    tive and evaluative processes. Just as originali ty does

    not guarantee creative performance, so too is creativity

    not solely a divergent, intuitive, generative process.

    Selective, evaluative, and valuative processes are nec

    essary. Here I am only disappointed that Eysenck limits

    himself to what he calls linguistic evidence. There is

    other evidence. The evaluative process

    of

    ideational

    creativity has been studied in several recent investiga

    tions (Runco, 1991b; Runco & Chand, in press; Runco

    & Smith, 1992), and although these are just initial and

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    3/6

    COMMENTARIES

    perhaps even crude attempts at isolating selective and

    evaluative tendencies, at least they are not limited to

    verbal stimuli or associations (see Runco Vega,

    1990). This inclusion

    of

    nonverbal material is a virtue,

    given what was said earlier about associative tenden

    cies differing when elicited by verbal or nonverbal

    stimuli and when following familiar or unfamiliar stim

    uli (Guilford, 1968; Mednick, 1962; Richardson, 1986;

    Runco, 1986; Runco & Albert, 1985). Admittedly, my

    own work on evaluative processes bas its limitations,

    but the focus on ideational data seems reasonable given

    the evidence for the predictive validity

    of

    such mea

    sures (Milgram, 1990; Okuda et al., 1991) and because

    there is an extremely large literature (reviewed by

    Runco, 1991a, 1992) to assist with interpretations.

    In rebuttal, Eysenck might criticize the use of diver

    gent-thinking tasks, just as I have criticized his reliance

    on verbal data.

    As

    a matter of fact, he specifically

    dismisses divergent thinking in his article (or at least

    alludes to deep-sea ted misgivings ). Something

    should be said about this because, although he is right

    that many researchers have given up on the Guilford

    (1968) and Torrance (1974) tests, a careful reading

    of

    the literature suggests that the dismissal of divergent

    thinking is premature (Milgram, 1990; Runco, 1991a,

    1992). Most who dismiss divergent thinking have done

    so because

    of

    dated research findings. Little if any

    attention is given by the critics to research from the late

    1980s or early 1990s. Divergent-thinking tests are now

    administered, scored, and interpreted differently from

    the way they used to be-or, at least they should be,

    given recent research. Eysenck himself cites research

    from before 1959 when discussing the intelligence

    threshold necessary for creativity. Granted, he cites the

    classic work

    of

    Cox and Terman, but more recent

    research should also be considered (see Runco

    &

    Al

    bert, 1986; Simonton, 1984). Eysenck 'sclaim about the

    distributions of creativity as approximately normal

    might similarly be questioned (Runco Albert, 1985),

    as might his unqualified generalizations about the im

    pact

    of

    political unrest (Simonton, 1990).

    I am very interested in Eysenck's ideas about rele

    vance but cannot help but wonder whether he will

    encounter some of the same measurement difficulties I

    did,

    if

    he conducts the actual empirical tests of his

    predictions. I am referring here to the difficulties found

    early in Runco and Charles's (in press) investigation of

    the relation between originality and appropriateness

    appropriateness

    paralleling

    Eysenck s relevance.

    Runco and Charles designed a simple Q-sort study to

    examine the accuracy of judgments of originality, ap

    propriateness, and their interaction as predictors of

    creativity. I naively suspected that the appropriateness

    of ideas would be relatively easy to operationalize-at

    least in the context of divergent thinking, where a

    problem can be used as context. I soon discovered my

    error and now feel that appropriateness and relevance

    are even more subjective than originality. I was naive

    to expect an easy operationalization of appropriateness

    and have lately found several theories explaining its

    subjectivity and elusive qualities (e.g., Gould, 1991;

    Maslow, 1971). At least with originality, statistical

    infrequency can be used (Hocevar, 1979; Runco

    Albert, 1985). Appropriateness and relevance may be

    much more difficult measurement targets because

    of

    their connection with values. Incidentally, Runco and

    Charles (in press) found a strong relation between

    originality and creativity and indications of an inverse

    relation between appropriateness and creativity. The

    expected Originality x Appropriateness interaction was

    minuscule and statistically insignificant. This last find

    ing is contrary to many, many theories that bring appro

    priateness, fit, usefulness, and relevance into the

    definition

    of

    creativity (e.g., MacKinnon, 1965; Mum

    ford

    et

    al., in press;

    O Quin

    Besemer, 1989;

    Rothenberg & Hausman, 1976).

    3

    Conclusion

    and

    Implications

    Eysenck claims that he presents a model with test

    able predictions. I hope what I have written will help to

    modify some of those predictions. Although I question

    some

    of

    Eysenck's assumptions, I certainly have no

    desire to dismiss his model. There is much to be gained

    from

    it.

    Indeed, I wish I had more time to discuss the

    strong points

    of

    Eysenck's theory. As I already men

    tioned, it is especially important that Eysenck has

    looked to biological and genetic contributions.

    t is also important that he mentions practical im

    plications, such as when he describes the need for

    educating ... teachers in the appreciation of the value

    of originality and creativity. Here I only suggest that

    his claim be changed such that it too uses the concept

    of optima, as in optimal appreciation. I say this

    because originality is insufficient for creativity. This is

    implied by Eysenck's discussion

    of

    the optimal levels

    of psycboticism, for too much can lead to originality

    that has no relevance and that is indubitably uncreative.

    Teachers might therefore sacrifice some classroom

    3

    Another potential measurement problem reflects the fact that

    something in addition to relevance might be needed. In particular,

    where does the aesthetic component of creativity fit in? I hesitate

    raising this issue because it in tum leads to the difficult question,

    Where do we stop? f he aesthetic component s included in models

    ofcreativity, along with originality

    and

    relevance, the model beco mes

    more complicated. tmay become more accurate with each additional

    term

    or

    dimension, but t will probably

    lso

    be accurate only in certain

    domains. Complicate d models often lose in generality what they gain

    in accuracy (Wiggins, 1981).

    223

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    4/6

    COMMENTARIES

    structure for divergent thinking and spontaneity; but,

    given the critical roles

    of

    knowledge, information, and

    selections or evaluations, they should only give some

    of the time. I like the concept of optimal appreciation

    because educators could

    jump

    on the creativity band

    wagon and go to the extreme, allowing complete spon

    taneity and individuality. This kind

    of

    open education

    does not benefit creativity (also see Cropley, 1992;

    Runco & Okuda, in press). Educational flexibility

    might allow divergent thinking and self-expression, but

    judgments

    of

    relevance require some conventional

    thinking

    and memorization-and

    thus a dose

    of

    struc

    tured education.

    Looking back, much

    of

    what I have written here has

    to do with how creativity is treated rather than with

    what is included. Consider, for instance, my citing the

    very recent research

    on

    the direction

    of

    effect between

    creativity

    and

    psychopathology and my gripes about

    the older citations for divergent thinking and the thresh

    old theory. The integration

    of

    research is not easy-es

    pecially integrations in creativity research, where there

    is such a high premium placed

    on

    originality (Runco,

    in press-b). Overall, Eysenck does remarkably well. His

    article is a model

    of

    what needs to be done

    to

    keep

    creativity research moving forward- -that is, to main

    tain its own creativity.

    Notes

    I completed this Commentary while holding a Visit

    ing position at the Institute for Cognitive Psychology

    of

    the University

    of

    Bergen. I thank the institute and,

    in

    particular, Geir Kaufmann.

    MarkA. Runco, Department

    of

    Psychology, EC 105,

    California State University, Fullerton,

    CA

    92634.

    References

    Barron, F., Harrington, D. (1981). Creativity, intelligence,

    and

    personality AnnualReview

    of

    Psychology 32 439-476.

    Becker, G. (1978). The mad genius controversy. Beverly Hills, CA:

    Sage.

    Bowden, C. (in press). The relationship of bipolar disorder to creativ

    ity. In M. Shaw M. A Runco (Eds.), Creativity and affect.

    Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Cropley, A J. (1992).

    More ways than one: Fostering creativity.

    Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Csikszentmihalyi,

    M.

    (1990).

    The

    domain of creativity.

    In M. A

    Runco R. S. Albert (Eds.), Theories ofcreativity (pp. 190-

    212). Newbury Park, CA: Sage.

    Dudek, S. Z., Cote, R. (in press). Problem finding revisited. In M.

    A Runco (Ed.), Problem finding problem solving andcreativ

    ity.

    Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Eysenck, H. J. (1983). The roots of creativity: Cognitive ability or

    personality trait?

    Roeper Review 5 10-12.

    Gould, S . J. (1991 ).

    Bully for Brontosaurus. New

    York: Norton.

    Gruber,

    H.

    (1988).

    The

    evolving systems approach to creative work.

    224

    C r e a t i v i t y R e s e a r c h J o u r n a ~ 1 27-51.

    Guilford,

    J.P.

    (1968).

    Creativity intelligence and their educational

    implications. San Diego: EDITS.

    Hocevar, D. (1979). Ideational fluency

    as

    a confounding factor in the

    measurement

    of originality.JournalofEducationalPsychology

    71 191-196.

    Lazarus, R. S. (1991 ). Cognition and motivation in emotion. Ameri

    can Psychologist

    46,352-367.

    MacKinnon, D. W. (1965). Personality and the realization of creative

    potential.

    American Psychologist 20

    273-281.

    Maslow, A (1971). The creative attitude.

    In

    A Maslow

    Ed.), The

    farther reaches of

    hum n

    nature

    (pp. 57-71).

    New

    York: Viking.

    Meduick, S. A (1962). The associative basis of the creative process.

    Psychological Review

    69,200-232.

    Milgram, M (1990). Creativity: An idea whose time has come

    and

    gone?

    In

    M.

    A.

    Runco R. S. Albert (Eds.),

    Theories

    of

    creativity

    (pp. 215-233). Newbury Park, CA: Sage.

    Mumford, M. D., Reiter-Palmon, R., Redmond, M. (in press). In

    M. A Runco (Ed.), Problem finding problem solving and

    creativity. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Okuda, S.M., Runco, M.A., Berger, D. E. (1991). Creativity and

    the finding and solving of real-world problems. Journal of

    PsychoeducationalAssessment 9 45-53.

    O Quin,

    K., Besemer, S. (1989).

    The

    development, reliability,

    and

    validity of the Revised Creative Product Semantic Scale. Cre

    ativity Research Journal 2 267-278.

    Richards, R. (1981 . Relationships between creativity and psychopa

    thology: An evaluation and interpretation of the evidence.

    Ge

    neti Psychology Monographs 103 261-324.

    Richards, R. (1990). Everyday creativity, eminent creativity, and

    health: An afterview for

    CRJ

    special issues on creativity and

    health.

    Creativity e s e a r c h o u r n a ~ 3 300-326.

    Richardson,

    A

    J. (1986).

    Two

    factors of creativity.

    Perceptual and

    Motor Skills 63

    379-384.

    Rothenberg, A (1990). Creativity, mental health, and alcoholism.

    Creativity Research J

    u r n a ~

    3 179-201.

    Rothenberg,

    A, Hausman,

    C. (1976).

    The creativity question.

    Durham, NC: Duke Uuiversity Press.

    Runco, M.

    A

    (1986). Flexibility

    and

    originality

    in

    children's diver

    gent thinking. Journal ofPsychology .120 345-352.

    Runco,

    M

    A

    (Ed.).

    (1991a).

    Divergent thinking.

    Norwood, NJ:

    Ablex.

    Runco, M. A. (1991b).

    The

    evaluative, valuative,

    and

    divergent

    thinkingofchildren.JournalofCreativeBehavior 25,311-319.

    Runco,

    M.A.

    (1992). Children's divergent thinking and creative

    ideation. Developmental ~ W · i e w 12 233-264.

    Runco, M. A (in press-a). Creativity and its discontents. In M. Shaw

    M.

    A

    Runco (Eds.), Creativity and affect. Norwood, NJ:

    Ablex.

    Runco, M. A. (in press-b). Objectivity

    in

    creativity research.

    In

    A.

    Montuori

    (Ed.), Unusual associates: Essays in honorofFrank

    Barron.

    Cresskill, NJ: Hampton.

    Runco, M. A, Albert, R. S. (1985). The reliability and validity of

    ideational originality in the divergent thinking of acaderuically

    gifted and nongifted children. Educational

    and

    Psychological

    Measurement 45 483-501 .

    Runco,

    M.

    A,

    Albert, R. S. (1986).

    The

    threshold hypothesis

    regarding creativity and intelligence: An empirical test with

    gifted

    and

    nongifted children.

    Creative Child andAdultQuar

    terly 11

    212-218.

    Runco, M. A., Chand, I. (in press). Problem finding, evaluative

    thinking, and creativity. In M.

    A

    Runco (Ed.), Problem finding

    problem solving

    and

    creativity. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Runco, M.

    A,

    Charles, R. (in press). Judgments of originality

    and

    appropriateness

    as

    predictors of creativity.

    Personality and In

    dividual Differences.

    Runco,

    M. A,

    Okuda,

    S.M. (in

    press). Reaching creatively gifted

    children through their learuing styles.

    In

    R.

    M.

    Milgram R.

    Dunn

    (Eds.),

    Teaching the gifted and talented through their

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    5/6

    COMMENTARIES

    learning styles.

    New

    York: Praeger.

    Runco, M.

    A

    Smith, W.R (1992). Interpersonal and intrapersonal

    evaluations

    of

    creative ideas.

    Personality andIndividual Differ

    ences,

    13,

    295-302.

    Runco,

    M.

    A Vega, L. (1990). Evaluating the creativity of

    children s ideas. Journal ofSocial BehaviorandPersonality,

    5

    439-452.

    Russ, S. (1993).

    Creativity and affect: The role

    of

    affect and play in

    the creative process.

    Hillsdale,

    NJ:

    Lawrence Erlbaum

    Associ-

    ates, Inc.

    Rutter, M. (1985). Resilience

    in

    the face of adversity: Protective

    factors

    and

    resistance to psychiatric disorders. British Journal

    ofPsychiatry, 147,

    598-611.

    Shaw, M. P., Runco, M.A. (Eds.). (in press). Creativity

    and

    affect.

    Norwood,

    NJ:Ablex.

    Simonton, D.

    K.

    (1984). Genius, creativity,

    and

    leadership. Cam

    bridge,

    MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    Simonton, D. K. (1990). Political pathology and societal creativity.

    r e a t i v i t y R e s e a r c h J o u r n a ~ 3, 85-99.

    Spearman, C (1923).

    The nature

    of

    intelligence

    and

    he principles

    ofcognition. London: Macmillan.

    Spearman, C. (1927). The abilities ofman. London: Macmillan.

    Torrance, E. P. (1974). Torrance Tests

    of

    Creative Thinking. Bensen

    ville, IL: Scholastic Testing Services.

    Wakefield,

    J.

    (in press). In

    M. A

    Runco

    (Ed.),

    Problem finding,

    problem solving,

    and

    creativity. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Wiggins, J. S. (1981). Clinical and statistical prediction: Where

    do

    we

    go from here? Clinical Psychology Review, 1, 3-18.

    Wolt; F. M.,

    Larson

    G. L (1981).

    On

    why adolescent formal

    operators may not

    be

    creative thinkers.Adolescence, 62, 345-348 .

    Blind Variations Chance Configurations and Creative Genius

    Dean Keith Simonton

    University

    of

    California, Davis

    Eysenck's target article is an exciting read. As he

    points out, for some time creativity studies had shown

    signs of entering the stage of a degenerative research

    program. Psychoanalytic accounts

    of

    the creative per

    son and Gestalt accounts

    of

    the creative process now

    seem passe. Psychometric approaches to the same phe

    nomena, although once the rage, have sunk into de

    spondency.

    And

    the current activity

    of

    cognitive

    psychologists in this area, although often provocative,

    fall short

    of

    a comprehensive theory. Their computer

    simulations, for example, concentrate on certain specif

    ics

    of

    the creative process while utterly ignoring per

    sonality and social context. What we lack are widely

    accepted theoretical approaches that explain all import

    ant aspects

    of

    creativity. Eysenck's proposed theory

    tries to fill this sad gap.

    As we

    should expect

    of

    any sweeping theory,

    Eysenck's model is rich in ideas. He has tried to inte

    grate a vast range

    of

    research findings-work that

    spans many decades. Therefore, I cannot possibly pro

    vide a critique of

    his entire scheme. Instead, I focus

    on

    a single

    issue-the

    place

    of

    chance in creativity. Al

    though Eysenck seems to downplay the role

    of

    chance

    in the creative process, I interpret his arguments and

    data quite differently.

    Let me begin by clearing up a potential source

    of

    confusion. Campbell (1960) termed his original model

    of

    creativity the

    blind-variation and selective-retention

    theory.

    My own elaboration

    of

    this theory I styled the

    chance-configuration theory. The rationale for the

    name change was a difference in emphasis and com

    plexity between the two theories. For one thing, by

    introducing the concept

    of

    configuration, I hoped to

    sprinkle a little Gestalt

    on

    the initial Darwinian frame-

    work. The basic idea was that the mind can generate

    innumerable combinations

    of

    concepts, but only a few

    of these will coalesce into a structural

    whole-a

    con

    figuration. To offer an everyday illustration, think what

    happens when you write a sentence that you hope will

    communicate a profound idea. You have at your dis

    posal a host

    of

    words and their synonyms for each

    subject, predicate, object, and other sentence compo

    nent. You also have access to a variety

    of

    syntactical

    constructions that can adjust the expression to the finest

    shades

    of

    meaning. So, you search for that distinctive

    pattern of lexical elements and syntactical structures

    that convey precisely what you mean. That just-right

    sentence seems to encapsulate better than its more

    awkward rivals the meaning that before existed only in

    imagery or intuition.

    Another reason for the name change was my dissat

    isfaction with Campbell's choice

    of

    the adjective blind.

    By claiming that the ideational variations were blind,

    he meant that the combinatory process lacked reason or

    foresight. The more novel a problem is, the more inad

    equate are the received collection

    of

    algorithms and

    heuristics. Having nothing definite to guide the quest

    for a solution, the creator must grope in the darkness.

    The process is one of

    cognitive trial-and-error. It seems

    perfectly reasonable to style this process blind.

    Unfortunately, this word choice leads to some con

    fusion. For those familiar with the problem-solving

    literature,

    blind

    often implies the same thing as

    blind

    search which almost everybody recognizes as the

    heuristic

    of

    last resort.

    As

    Eysenck notes, a genuine

    blind search very quickly encounters a combinatorial

    explosion that makes it most unlikely that the venture

    will converge

    on

    a solution. Moreover, it is evident that

    225

  • 8/19/2019 Creativity, Causality, And the Separation of Personality and Cognition. Runco, (1993).

    6/6

    Copyright© 2 2 EBSCO Publishing