Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    1/33

    The Ethics of Revolution andIts Implications for the Ethics

    of Intervention

    ALLEN BUCHANAN

    Logically, there should be an elaboratejus ad bellumandjus in bello

    for revolutionary war, but development of such a doctrine has never

    been seriously attempted.1

    We may be entering a new Age of Revolution.2 Revolutions have recently

    occurred across North Africa, while the brutal revolutionary conflict in

    Syria continues. The recent flowering of just war theory has not yet

    explicitly extended its reach to revolutions, perhaps due to a suspicion

    that revolutions present ethical issues that are not amenable to a tradi-

    tion of theorizing that focuses on conflicts between states, rather than onthose in which (some of) the people of a state seek to overthrow the

    government. Of course, one major element of an ethics of revolution has

    occupied a central role in Western political thought: Locke, for example,

    has a good deal to say about what qualifies as a just cause for revolution,

    and the idea of just cause is a key component ofjus ad bellumdoctrine.

    The question of whether the other components ofjus ad bellum theories

    developed for interstate wars apply to the quite different situation of

    I am grateful to Cecile Fabre, Christopher Finlay, Jeff Holzgrefe, Mattias Iser, Robert O.

    Keohane, Russell Powell, Uwe Steinhoff, Bas Van der Vossen, Lorenzo Zucca, and

    two anonymous reviewers for this journal for their helpful comments on previous drafts

    of this article.

    . William V. OBrien, The Conduct of Just and Limited War (New York: Praeger,

    ), p. .

    . I will use the term revolution, in what might be called its broader sense, to mean

    the attempt to overthrow an existing regime and replace it with a new one, by violent or at

    least unconstitutional means. Sometimes the term is used in a narrower sense, according

    to which the aim of those who seek to overthrow the existing regime is to replace itwith a fundamentally different type of political order. What I say in this article applies

    to both cases. Furthermore, as will become clear, I am focusing on cases of revolution

    that involve violence.

    Wiley Periodicals, Inc.Philosophy& Public Affairs, no.

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    2/33

    revolution has not been addressed; nor has a jus in bello theory beendeveloped for revolutionary conflicts.3

    Both the humanitarian law of war and contemporary just war theory

    do, however, address one issue that a comprehensive ethics of revolu-

    tion, in itsjus in bellopart, should include: namely, the ethics of irregu-

    lar combatants, fighters who do not wear identifying insignia and who

    mingle with the civilian population. But as I shall argue, developing a

    plausible doctrine on that issue would comprise only one small part of a

    comprehensive ethics of revolution.

    Similarly, although recent work on the ethics of terrorism (and coun-

    terterrorism) clearly has implications for thejus in bello part of an ethics

    of revolutionssince revolutionaries often resort to terrorismit falls

    far short of a thoroughgoing investigation of the ethics of revolution. For

    one thing, the focus of the literature on the ethics of terrorism has been

    acts of violence against noncombatants intended to influence the behav-

    ior of those in political power (by causing fear or terror in their constitu-

    encies, who will then exert pressure on their leaders to change course).

    . Cecile Fabre has begun to develop an account of the ethics of civil wars, a category

    that encompasses revolution as I have defined it. Her focus thus far has been on whether

    nonstate individuals or groups in civil wars may use modes of fighting that are usually

    understood to be prohibited in traditional just war theory. She has briefly discussed the

    ethics of conscripting soldiers to fight in cases of humanitarian intervention, but she has

    not so far discussed the other kinds of morally problematic actions often undertaken by

    revolutionaries who are the focus of this article. Cecile Fabre, Cosmopolitan War(Oxford:

    Oxford University Press,), p. . Christopher J. Finlay has explored the question of

    whether nonstate actors, including revolutionaries, can satisfy the traditional just war

    requirement of competent authority, but he has not engaged the particular moral issues

    facing revolutionaries discussed in this article. Christopher J. Finlay, Legitimacy and Non-

    State Actors,Journal of Political Philosophy():. Mattias Iser argues that the

    violation of civil and political rights can be a just cause for revolution, but does not focus on

    the problems of revolutionaryjus in bellothat are the subject of this article. Mattias Iser,

    draft paper presented at conference on Justice and Violence, Frankfurt, May, . A

    number of other valuable contributions, including the following, explore thejus ad bellum

    part of the ethics of revolution or the ethics of intervention in revolution, but do not

    consider the subject matter of the present article: Arthur Isak Applbaum, Forcing a People

    to Be Free, Philosophy& Public Affairs (): ; Ned Dobos, A State to Call

    Their Own: Insurrection, Intervention, and the Communal Integrity Thesis, Journal ofApplied Philosophy():; Katrin Flikshuh, Reason, Right, and Revolution: Kant

    and Locke, Philosophy & Public Affairs (): ; Adil Ahmad Haque, The

    Revolution and Criminal Law, Criminal Law and Philosophy (): ; and Matthew

    Noah Smith, Rethinking Sovereignty, Rethinking Revolution, Philosophy& Public Affairs

    (): .

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    3/33

    But revolutionaries frequently use violence and sometimes outright actsof terrorism against other noncombatantsnamely, other oppressed

    peoplenot to change the behavior of the regime, but to increase par-

    ticipation in the struggle or to eliminate rivals for leadership of the revo-

    lution.4 Such acts are morally problematic to say the least, but to my

    knowledge they have not been considered in the recent literature on

    terrorism. This omission is both a deficiency in theorizing about the

    ethics of terrorism and a failure to engage with an important element of

    the ethics of revolution.

    Writing on the ethics of humanitarian intervention has tended to

    focus on interventions to stop genocides or large-scale killings, not on

    revolutions. It is true that some supporters of the United Statesled inva-

    sion of Iraq in claimed that it was justified as a case of forcible

    democratization, a democratic revolution from without, as it were (and

    that the absence of weapons of mass destruction was therefore irrelevant

    to the justification of the war). But they did not argue, and could not

    plausibly have argued, that the invasion was an effort to support a revo-

    lution, because no revolution was underway at the time of the invasion.This is not to say that current theorizing about the ethics of humani-

    tarian intervention has no implications for revolution. A popular stance

    on the ethics of humanitarian intervention (in itsjus ad bellumpart) is

    that it is not justified unless there is large-scale violence, and this stric-

    ture could be understood to apply to revolutionary conflicts as well as

    ethnonational conflicts of the sort that have been the focus of the

    humanitarian intervention literature. Nonetheless, neither contempo-

    rary just war theories, nor theories of the ethics of terrorism, nor theoriesof the ethics of humanitarian intervention have engaged seriously with

    the ethics of revolution considered as a legitimate object of normative

    analysis in its own right.

    . Revolutionaries often commit violence against suspected informers or others who

    betray the revolutionary struggle. In some cases, they also punish members of the

    oppressed public who engage in what the revolutionaries consider to be antisocial behav-

    ior (such as drug-selling and prostitution), on the grounds that the people must be purifiedif they are to be fit for the revolutionary struggle or the new era it is supposed to bring

    about. See, for example, the execution of the pimp in the classic film The Battle of Algiers.

    Here, too, the problem of legitimacy looms large. The key question is whether, in spite of

    the fact that the revolutionaries do not comprise a legitimate agent or institution, they can

    be justified in taking such actions.

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    4/33

    In this article, I begin a systematic exploration of the ethicsof revolution, focusing first on the ethics of those who typically

    initiate revolutions, whom I will refer to as The Aspiring Revolutionary

    Leadership (ARL for brevity). Then I will consider the ethics of

    intervention in revolutions.

    In the first part of the article, I argue that in the cases in which the Just

    Cause Requirement is most clearly and fully satisfied, structural features

    of the revolutionary situation will often make it extremely difficult or

    impossible for revolutionaries to satisfy reasonable jus in bello prin-

    ciples, while at the same time satisfying the jus ad bellum Reasonable

    Likelihood of Success Requirement. My initial disturbing conclusion in

    this first part of the article is that it is seldom morally justifiable to initiate

    revolution in the very cases in which the cause for revolting is most

    clearly and fully just. Second, I then argue that when the initiation of

    revolution is not morally permissible, participation in a revolution that

    has already begun can nonetheless be justified. So, a third conclusion

    will be that it is unhelpful to ask whether a revolution was justified.

    Instead, the moral assessment must be disaggregated, distinguishingbetween two subjects of evaluation: the initiation of the revolution and

    its continuance. Paradoxical though it may seem, there is nothing incon-

    sistent in acknowledging that the actions by which a revolution is

    initiatedand which mustbe performed if the revolution is to have a

    significant chance of succeedingare morally unjustifiable, while at the

    same time asserting that the revolution is morally justifiable, where this

    means that the continuation of the revolutionary struggle is morally

    permissible. Next, I argue that on further analysis some of the prima faciemorally impermissible tactics ARLs often employin particular, some

    uses of coercion against fellow oppressed people to overcome regime-

    imposed obstacles to collective action against the regimeare morally

    justifiable, while others are not.

    The second part of the article uses the first parts findings concerning

    the ethics of revolution to explore the ethics of intervention in revolu-

    tion. There I argue for three main conclusions. First, even if the initiation

    of a revolution is severely tainted by immoral actions perpetrated by the

    ARL, it may nonetheless be morally justifiable for third parties to inter-

    vene in support of it.

    Second, given a proper understanding of the tactics frequently

    employed by the ARLand that they often must use if revolution is to

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    5/33

    have a significant chance of succeedingthe practical value of twoseemingly plausible principles of intervention turns out to be much less

    than has been thought. Both the principle that intervention should not

    occur until there is widespread support for a revolution (Mills Principle)

    and the principle that intervention should not occur without the

    consent or approval of the people (the Consent Principle) figure

    prominently in the contemporary literature on the ethics of intervention.

    Both still enjoy considerable popularity, though both have been criti-

    cized. I will advance novel criticisms of them, showing that proponents

    of these principles have failed to see that the behavior of the ARL will

    frequently undercut the rationale for these principles. I conclude that

    Mills Principle and the Consent Principle were designed for a world

    quite different from that in which revolutions typically occur, in blissful

    ignorance of the grim facts about revolutions in our world. Finally,

    I then argue that there is a reason in favor of early intervention that

    has not been appreciated: in principle it can avoid the spiral of coercion

    that occurs as the regime tries to thwart the ARLs attempt to solve

    the collective action problem of mass participation by raising the costsof participation in the revolution and the ARL responds by increasing

    coercive pressure on the masses to participate by raising the costs

    of not participating.

    My methodology in this article is distinctive: I approach the ethics of

    revolution by focusing on the problems that the initiators of revolution

    typically face, drawing on relevant social-science literature, including

    historical work on actual revolutions, and also on the literature on col-

    lective action problems. Then, instead of attempting to apply a theory ofintervention developed for other sorts of cases (in particular, interven-

    tion to stop massive ethnonational violence), I draw out the implications

    of a factually informed investigation of the ethics of revolution for devel-

    oping an ethics of intervention in revolutions.

    I. PROBLEMS THE ASPIRING REVOLUTIONARY LEADERSHIP MUST SOLVE

    A. The Applicability of Just War Principles to Revolutionary Violence

    Before identifying the problems the ARL faces, I will assume for purposes

    of my argument something that I trust is relatively uncontroversial,

    namely, that at least some of the widely recognized principles of just war

    theory apply to violence contemplated by the ARL. These include the

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    6/33

    following requirements: (a) that there must be a just cause for initiatingviolent revolution (the Just Cause Requirement); (b) that there must be

    some reasonable prospect that the revolution will succeed in its major

    aims, at least those referred to in the characterization of the just cause

    (the Reasonable Likelihood of Success Requirement); (c) that the vio-

    lence used by the revolutionaries must be proportional to the aims they

    seek to achieve, especially those referred to in the characterization of the

    just cause (the Proportionality Requirement); and (d) that the revolu-

    tionaries may not deliberately target noncombatants (the Discrimina-

    tion Requirement). I will also limit my discussion to cases in which the

    Just Cause Requirement is most clearly and fully satisfied, cases in which

    the regime the revolutionaries seek to overthrow is what I shall call a

    Resolute Severe Tyranny: a regime that persistently violates some of the

    basic human rights of large segments of the population, is extremely

    authoritarian (that is, wholly undemocratic), and is utterly impervious to

    efforts to reform it.

    I assume that the target of the ARL is a Resolute Severe Tyranny in

    order to show that when revolution is most morally unproblematic fromthe standpoint of the Just Cause Requirement, the ARL typically faces a

    daunting dilemma: they can choose to utilize highly morally problematic

    means of pursuing the revolutionary project, taking actions that appear

    to involve serious violations of the rights of their fellow victims of

    oppression in order to satisfy the Reasonable Likelihood of Success

    Requirement, or they can refrain from taking such actions at the cost of

    violating the Reasonable Likelihood of Success Requirement. My point

    will be that even if the ARL refrains entirely from terrorism as conven-tionally understood, that is, violence that deliberately violates the Dis-

    crimination Requirement with the aim of changing regime behavior,

    they will often face a stark choice: the use of morally impermissible

    coercion against the people they seek to liberate or failure.

    Another reason for focusing on cases in which the Just Cause Require-

    ment is most clearly and fully satisfied is straightforward. History sug-

    gests that the outcome of revolutions is highly uncertain or, perhaps

    more accurately, that there is a significant probability that the outcome

    will be bad. To put it crudely: revolution is highly risky business, not to be

    undertaken except in extreme cases of bad government and strong evi-

    dence that the government is not liable to reform. My aim will be to show

    that it is generally highly risky not just in the sense that good outcomes

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    7/33

    are not very probable, but also in the sense that those who initiate revo-lutions are at great moral risk regarding the tactics they are likely to use,

    if they are committed to the success of the revolution.

    Although the Reasonable Likelihood of Success Principle is familiar in

    traditional just war theory, it is nonetheless problematic, and not just

    because the notion of reasonable likelihood of success is inherently

    vague. In cases in which people are resisting an evil aggressor or an

    extremely tyrannical government, we may think that their willingness to

    fight against steep odds is commendable, indeed heroic, not wrong. My

    surmise is that this intuition is strongest in cases in which the costs of

    failure will fall mainly on those who elect to fight in spite of the likelihood

    that they will fail, rather than on others who have not assumed this risk.

    In most cases, those who launch a revolution against a Resolute Severe

    Tyranny can expect that innocent people will suffer, and given that this is

    the case, they have a strong obligation, other things being equal, to do

    what they can to ensure that the struggle is successful. More specifically,

    it would be irresponsible to launch a struggle that will predictably harm

    innocent people and then proceed to conduct the struggle in a way thatmakes it very unlikely to succeed.

    B. Compensating for Inferior Military Capacity

    At the beginning of the struggle, at least, revolutionaries in the modern

    context often are at a severe disadvantage in terms of military capability

    relative to the regime. The sophistication and expense of modern mili-

    tary equipment and the training needed to use it effectively have greatlyexacerbated this disparity. The ARL often concludes, quite reasonably,

    that it can only hope to mount successful attacks on the regime if it

    resorts to nonconventional modes of attack, where this includes attack-

    ing soft regime targets such as civilian administrative agencies or non-

    military facilities, and doing so without wearing uniforms or insignia so

    that the revolutionary fighters can mingle with the general population.

    The same recognition of the limitations imposed by the disparity of

    military capacity that encourages these sorts of acts may also lead the

    ARL to commit outright acts of terrorism against the regime, if terrorism

    is defined as the use of lethal violence against noncombatants with the

    aim of evoking terror or fear that will cause the regime to change its

    behavior to suit the political agenda of those who perpetrate the

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    8/33

    violence. Because the morally problematic character of using terrorismor nonconventional modes of attack to compensate for the disparity of

    military capacity has been much discussed in the contemporary litera-

    ture on terrorism and the jus in bello part of just war theory, I will say

    nothing more about them here. Instead, I will argue that even if the ARL

    refrains from terrorism and nonconventional modes of attack, in many

    cases it cannot reasonably hope to succeed unless it undertakes other

    highly morally problematic actions.

    C. Achieving Coordination by Consolidating Leadership

    A revolutions prospects for success often depend upon effective leader-

    ship, because success requires coordination and coordination requires

    leadership. But achieving effective leadership by ethically permissible

    means will often be very difficult if not practically impossible, at least

    under the highly constraining conditions in which the Just Cause

    Requirement is most clearly and fully satisfied, that is, under conditions

    of Resolute Severe Tyranny. The regimes behavior will generally not be

    compatible with conditions for the peaceful resolution of disputes as to

    who should lead the revolution. Freedom of assembly, expression, and

    political association will be absent, and no open, free deliberations on

    the part of the public as to who should fill revolutionary leadership roles

    will be possible. Even worse, the regime may preemptively murder, exile,

    or imprison individuals who are likely to be identified by the people

    as appropriate leaders.

    Under these conditions, it is not surprising that struggles amongrival aspirants to leadership are often characterized by violence,

    betrayal, and manipulation of the populations beliefs and emotions.5

    My point here is not to condone such ruthless competition for leadership

    by pleading necessity but merely to indicate why one should expect it to

    occur. Sometimesprobably infrequentlyrevolutions can achieve

    some early successes without coalescing around a leadership, but as

    . There is a wealth of historical examples, from lethal struggles among the Directorateof the French Revolution and Stalins murder of the Old Bolsheviks, to Ho Chi Minhs

    liquidation of rival nationalist groups during the struggle against the French. For a valuable

    comparative work that emphasizes the importance of establishing leadership, see Theda

    Skocpol, States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia and China

    (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ).

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    9/33

    events in Syria suggest, lack of leadership may make it difficult or impos-sible for the revolutionaries to prevail against a resolute regime with

    an effective leadership.

    To summarize: Successful revolution often requires not just wide-

    spread participation, but also coordinated participation, and that typi-

    cally requires leadership. Yet achieving leadership by ethical means

    may be difficult if not impossible, at least under conditions of Resolute

    Severe Tyranny, that is, those conditions in which the Just Cause

    Requirement is most clearly and fully satisfied. To be sure, ruthless

    competition for leadership in actual revolutions is not always driven

    solely or even mainly by the need to solve the coordination problem; in

    some cases, it is a matter of the pure self-interest in power. But it

    is nonetheless important to understand that the typical structure of

    the revolutionary situation under Resolute Severe Tyranny (the best

    situation from the standpoint of the Just Cause Requirement) creates

    strong pressures for morally impermissible solutions to the problem

    of coordinated participation.

    D. Achieving the Public Good of Widespread Participation

    Revolutions are typically small minority affairs at the beginning, but if

    they are to succeed they must garner widespread support among the

    general population. Active participation by the majoritymay not be nec-

    essary (and is probably rarely attained), but if the revolution is to

    succeed, significant numbers of people must participate and many must

    at least refrain from actively supporting the regime.Even if most of the population endorses the goal of revolution, many

    may refrain from participating due to familiar obstacles to collective

    action for securing public goods. The difficulty is most readily grasped

    if we simplify, for the moment, by assuming that people are motivated

    exclusively by self-interest. Each oppressed person may reason as

    follows: either enough others will participate to make the revolution

    succeed or not, regardless of whether I participate; but my participa-

    tion is a cost to me (indeed, in the early stages, the cost may be ones

    life); so, regardless of what others may do, the rational thing for me to

    do is not to participate.

    The collective action problem remains once we jettison the unrealistic

    assumption of purely rationally self-interested individuals, for three

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    10/33

    reasons. First, even if people have strong moral motivations, these aretypically constrained by self-interest or interests in the welfare of those

    near and dear to them in ways that inhibit participation in the revolu-

    tion. Hence, if an individual reasonably doubts whether his personal

    contribution to the revolution will be critical but knows that by partici-

    pating he greatly endangers himself or his family, he may refrain from

    participation. Second, even if an individual does not wish to free ride on

    the participation of others, hoping that enough of them will participate

    to achieve the goal of revolution, he may not be willing to participate

    without assurance that others will do so. He may think (not unreason-

    ably) that the costs one is obligated to bear are limited by a requirement

    of reciprocity or fairness. Third, an individual may require assurance

    of the participation of others as a condition of his own participation

    not as a matter of reciprocity or fairness, but because he recognizes

    that unless a threshold of participation is met, his participation will be a

    dead loss to himself (and his loved ones) and to the cause of the revolu-

    tion.6 Where the regime has fomented divisions among the population

    (along ethnic or religious grounds), effective mobilization may be allthe more difficult.

    My claim is not that there is, strictly speaking, a paradox of rational-

    ity here, that is, that it is irrational for individuals to participate volun-

    tarily in revolution. Rather, it is that there are often significant obstacles

    to achieving voluntarily the collective action needed for revolution, and

    that consideration of costs and benefits, broadly understood as to

    include undeserved harms to those one cares about, often plays a sig-

    nificant role in this being the case.At this point it might be objected that if individuals are rational and do

    care about justice or about the general welfare, they will participate in a

    revolution against a Resolute Severe Tyranny, because they will reason

    as follows: It is true that the chance that my participating will be critical

    for the success of the revolution is very small, but the expected benefit of

    my participating will nonetheless be large, because if the revolution suc-

    ceeds, so many people will benefit. This kind of reasoning is plausible,

    . Mancur Olson,The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups

    (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, ); Gordon Tullock, The Rebels

    Dilemma,Public Choice:; Allen Buchanan, Revolutionary Motivation and Ratio-

    nality,Philosophy& Public Affairs (): .

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    11/33

    and may in fact motivate some people, under circumstances in whichthe costs to the individual of participating are not very high. However, as

    I shall explain in more detail shortly, the costs of participation are not

    fixed: the regime can raise them by increasing the penalties for partici-

    pants and their families and close associates.

    There is another factor that weakens the appeal to large-scale ben-

    efits: as I have already emphasized, there are many ways a revolution can

    go wrong, so the possible outcomes are not limited to continuation of the

    status quo of oppression or a successfulrevolution. Consequently, in

    considering whether to participate, the individual must take into

    account not only the (very small) probability that his participation is a

    necessary condition for overthrowing the regime. He must discount that

    expected benefit by a sober appreciation of the fact that merely over-

    throwing the current regime may not be a significant improvement, if an

    improvement at all. So the problem of collective action does not disap-

    pear once we take into account the fact that if the revolution succeeds,

    many will benefit.

    There are two morally problematic strategies for solving the collec-tive action problem that appear to be frequently used by ARLs. First,

    the ARL may use coercion to tip the balance of incentives toward par-

    ticipation. It is not just states that conscript soldiers: revolutionary

    groups do so as well. Without conscription, the ARL may not be able to

    solve the collective action problem of widespread participation and the

    revolution may consequently fail. The coercive techniques for con-

    scription can range from summary executions or mutilations to levying

    fines or confiscating property to barring nonparticipants from food andother emergency relief.7

    A second strategy that ARLs frequently employ to solve the collective

    action problem is to manipulate the emotions of the people. A favorite

    technique for doing this is to provoke the regime to violence against

    innocent peoplefor example, killing peaceful demonstrators or killing

    innocent hostages in reprisal for irregular attacks by the revolutionaries.

    . Jeremy Weinstein, Inside Rebellion: The Politics of Insurgent Violence(Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,), p.. Weinsteins masterful analysis focuses on explain-

    ing the conditions under which excessive violence toward civilians occurs. He argues

    that it is the organizational characteristics of revolutionary groups that determine whether

    they will engage in violence that is above and beyond what is required to send a signal of

    the costs of defection [or nonparticipation] (p. ).

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    12/33

    The expectation is that if the regime engages in such actions, many peoplewill mobilize against it: their extreme emotional response of anger or

    indignation will override whatever calculations of costs and benefits

    might have hitherto prevented them from participating. Here is one

    example among many. In the s, the militant Zionist Irgun engaged in

    a campaign of violence. . . . Menachem Begin, the Irguns leader, believed

    inflicting sufficient casualties would compel the British to either with-

    draw or adopt repressive measures that wouldradicalize theJewishpopu-

    lation in Mandate Palestine.8 On the face of it, this widely used technique

    of mobilization seems doubly wrong: it not only manipulates peoples

    emotions to cause them to undertakerisks of participation they otherwise

    would not choose to shoulder, but also does so by encouraging the regime

    to engage in indiscriminate violence. The goal of forcing the regime to

    reveal just how brutal and unreformable it is, of course, is a laudable one.

    But achieving it by provoking the regime to murder innocent people is

    deeply problematic.

    Another technique for manipulating sentiments of anger and indig-

    nation to stimulate participation is for the ARL to circulate false or exag-gerated reports of atrocities committed by the regime. For example,

    there is strong evidence that Hamas deliberately exaggerates deaths of

    Palestinians due to Israeli military actions.9 Similarly, in an earlier revo-

    lution which many Americans think of as wholly admirable, revolution-

    aries deliberately fostered false reports that the British were encouraging

    their Indian allies to rape and kill white women along the frontier, and

    this appears to have played a role in mobilizing the militia that harassed

    Burgoyne in his march southward from Lake Champlain and ultimatelydefeated his army near Saratoga.10

    Revolutionaries also sometimes use coercion, indeed sometimes out-

    right terror tactics, to dissuade people from participating in the regimes

    efforts to suppress the revolution. Consider, for example, the notorious

    . Ethan Bueno de Mesquita and Eric S. Dickson, The Propaganda of the Deed:

    Terrorism, Counterterrorism, and Mobilization, American Journal of Political Science

    (): .. Yaakov Katz, World Duped by Hamas Death Count,Jerusalem Post, February,

    ,

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    13/33

    massacre of several thousand counterrevolutionaries in the Vendeeduring the French Revolution.11 The surrendered counterrevolution-

    aries, many of whom were noncombatants, were put aboard specially

    constructed barges which were then sunk. This logistically complex

    affair was not a crime of passion committed in the heat of battle; it was

    almost certainly an act motivated at least in part by the desire to deter

    others from opposing the revolution.

    E. Supreme Emergency?

    At this point it might be objected that there is no genuine moral

    dilemma for the ARL. If the regime they seek to overthrow is a Resolute

    Severe Tyranny, then what Walzer calls the Supreme Emergency Excep-

    tion tojus in bello constraints applies.12 Jus in belloconstraints are not

    absolute; they may be set aside when doing so is necessary for the

    defeat of an extremely heinous enemy. With good reason, Walzer is

    hesitant about the Emergency Exception, suggesting that perhaps only

    the Nazi regime would qualify.There are two reasons why recourse to the Emergency Exception

    cannot relieve the tension between the ARLs commitment to achieve

    successful revolution and the commitment to widely accepted con-

    straints on the conduct of armed struggles, even in the case of Resolute

    Severe Tyranny. First, a regime can qualify as a Resolute Severe Tyranny

    without reaching the depths of evil of Walzers one illustrative case, the

    Third Reich. In other words, there can be a clear and compelling Just

    Cause for revolution against regimes that are not that thoroughly evil.

    Second, and more importantly, in the case of the Third Reich, the evil

    could not be averted by not resisting. The Nazi project was to annihilate

    millions of people (not just Jews, but also a projected thirty million

    . Reynard Secher,A French Genocide: The Vendee (South Bend, Ind.: University of

    Notre Dame Press, ). For other examples of revolutionaries using terror against civil-

    ians to deter them from supporting the regime or to cause them to be neutral in the

    conflict, see the following: Alistair Horne, A Savage War of Peace: Algeria, (New

    York: New York Review Books,), pp.; Cynthia McClintock,Revolutionary Move-

    ments in Latin America: El Salvadors FMLN and Perus Shining Path(Washington, D.C.:United States Institute of Peace Press, ), pp.; and Martha Crenshaw, The Effec-

    tiveness of Terrorism in the Algerian War, in Terrorism in Context, ed. Martha Crenshaw

    (Philadelphia: Pennsylvania State University Press, ), pp. , (which includes

    references to terrorism by Viet Cong).

    . Michael Walzer,Just and Unjust Wars(New York: Basic Books, ), p. .

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    14/33

    citizens of Poland and the Soviet Union) and to enslave millions more. Incontrast, those who are subject to a Resolute Severe Tyranny typically

    can avoid annihilation or slavery simply by not resisting. My conclusion,

    then, is that not all cases of Resolute Severe Tyranny plausibly count

    as Supreme Emergencies and that consequently the conflict between

    the commitment to successful revolution and respect for jus in

    belloconstraints persists.

    F. Peaceful Alternatives?

    The vast social-science and game-theoretic literature indicates that

    there is a range of solutions to collective action problems, some of which

    do not involve morally problematic actions, and that the solutions that

    are available depend upon the particular context in which the collective

    action problem arises. No serious student of this literature would assert,

    however, that all collective action problems, much less those facing the

    ARL in the context of Resolute Severe Tyranny, can be solved in morally

    acceptable ways. Further, even when less morally problematic methodsfor solving the widespread participation problem are available, their

    likelihood of success may be significantly lower than is the case with the

    use of coercion or manipulation of emotions.

    My point, however, is not that successful revolution always requires

    wrongful manipulation of sentiments or coercion for the sake of achiev-

    ing widespread participation, but that there is good reason to believe

    that it often will, or at least that it will often not be unreasonable for the

    ARL to conclude that if it refrains from coercion or manipulation ofthe people the revolution is likely to fail. The more severe and ruthless

    the tyranny, and hence the stronger the just cause, the greater the costs

    of participation in the revolution will be and the more likely it will be that

    manipulation and coercion will be required to get people to participate

    in spite of the costs. The sad truth is that the only thing capable of

    canceling out the regimes threat of coercion against revolutionaries and

    their families may be a more credible threat of coercion by the ARL.

    My suggestion, then, is that the disturbing tendency of ARLs to engage

    in immoral actions toward their fellow victims of oppression is best

    explained as being a function of the structure of the situation the ARL

    finds itself in. My claim is not that all ARLs succumb to the powerful

    temptations that structure createsI am not assuming structural

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    15/33

    determinism. Rather, my hypothesis is that, given the paucity of morallypermissible effective solutions to the problems ARLs face under condi-

    tions of Severe Tyranny, more scrupulous ARLs are likely to either drop

    out of the competition or be weeded out by it or simply fail to be effective

    leaders. To borrow an analogy from evolutionary biology, in those very

    cases in which the Just Cause Requirement is most patently and fully

    satisfied, there will be strong selective pressures for the emergence of an

    ARL that is exceptionally ruthless, and willing and able to disregard even

    the most basic moral constraints.

    There are, of course, a fewI think very fewcases of successful

    revolutions with leaders who seem to have had relatively clean hands.

    Nelson Mandela and Mohandas Gandhi come to mind. However, the

    circumstances in which they led are far from typical.13 Gandhis struggle

    took place in a world in which colonialism was increasingly widely

    condemnedand clearly in declineand his opponents were not ruth-

    less dictators like the current leader of Syria or the former leader of Libya,

    but the leaders of liberal democracy that for some time had been com-

    mitted to eventual Indian independence. Mandela benefited from strongexternal support (especially in terms of the disinvestment campaign) not

    only because of the triumph of anticolonialism but also because the

    regime he opposed was one of institutionalized racism. He thus had

    good reason to believe that the overthrow of Apartheid could be

    achieved eventually without recourse to large-scale coercion or manipu-

    lation of the non-white majority. In addition, there might, perhaps, be

    reasonable disagreement as to whether either the British Raj or Apart-

    heid qualified as Severe Tyrannies (they clearly were not Resolute SevereTyrannies). The key point, however, is that many revolutions, perhaps

    most, do not benefit from powerful external support or from having

    opponents who are unwilling to use the most ruthless means to preserve

    their power. None of this is to detract from the tremendous accomplish-

    ments of these two leaders; it is only to avoid the fallacy of concluding

    that if they could make a successful revolution without using seriously

    immoral tactics, others can as well.

    Suppose one grants, for now, the conclusion toward which my analy-

    sis thus far appears to lead: where the Just Cause Requirement is most

    . Whether the African National Congress engaged in wrongful violence toward

    members of the Inkatha Freedom Party is another matter.

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    16/33

    clearly and fully satisfied, the Reasonable Likelihood of Success Require-ment will probably not be satisfied unless the ARL commits serious

    wrongs against those it hopes to liberate from Resolute Severe Tyranny.

    If that conclusion is sound, then, paradoxically, initiating a revolution in

    those conditions in which, intuitively, revolution is most justified is very

    likely to be morally unjustified. This would be a genuine paradox

    indeed, a contradictionif revolutions could only be justified if their

    initiations were. But that is not the case. It is perfectly consistent to

    acknowledge that the initiation of a revolution was not justified, but then

    go on to affirm that its continuation was justified.

    Suppose we have a situation in which, for reasons articulated above,

    the ARL initiated the revolution by committing wrongs against the

    people it seeks to liberate. It perpetrated violence against rivals for the

    revolutions leadership for the sake of securing effective coordination

    and used a combination of coercion and manipulation of emotions by

    provoking massacres of innocents by the regime to secure widespread

    participation. Nonetheless, it may be justifiable for others to participate

    in the revolution.To see why this is so, consider the case of ordinary people who are

    coerced or emotionally manipulated by the ARL into participating in the

    revolution. By hypothesis, they have a morally commendable reason to

    participate: they will be helping to overthrow a Resolute Severe Tyranny.

    If the coercion or manipulation has succeeded in mobilizing large

    numbers of people, this will help satisfy the Likelihood of Success

    Requirement. The fact that they came to be mobilized because of the

    wrongful actions of others is not a good reason for saying that theirparticipation is morally unjustified. Nor does the fact that they may be

    basing their decision to participate on false beliefs that the ARL has

    fostered by manipulation. The question of justification is whether their

    actions are right, not whether they came to undertake them for the right

    reasons. Whether people are justified in revolting at time T depends

    upon whether the conditions for justified revolution obtain at that time,

    not on whether their motivations for acting are based on false beliefs or

    whether someone else acted wrongly at time Tn. An act can be right,

    even if done for the wrong reasons.

    Further, when people continue a revolution that others began by

    committing unjustified acts, they are not thereby accomplices in the

    initial wrong. To be guilty of complicity, they would have had to have

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    17/33

    voluntarily participated in or at least supported or condoned the initialwrongdoing or culpably failed to prevent it from occurring. Otherwise

    they bear no responsibility and hence are not complicit.

    It is another question, of course, whether the ARL is justified in con-

    tinuing a revolution that it began by committing morally unjustified acts.

    Should we conclude that what matters is whether at time T + N the

    conditions for justified revolutionary action exist (not whether they

    acted wrongly at time T), or that, by acting wrongly in the initial stages of

    the revolution, the ARL somehow forfeits its right to do what it would

    otherwise be justified in doing. To my knowledge, there is no plausible

    theory of the forfeiture of moral rights on offer and what is usually said

    about forfeiturefor example, that criminals forfeit their right to liberty

    and thus may permissibly be incarcerateddoes not apply in any

    obvious way to the case at hand. Some versions of contemporary just war

    theory suggest that by acting in ways that wrongly harm or endanger

    others, one can forfeit ones right to physical security or, in different

    terms, make oneself liable to justified harm or killing. The question at

    issue here, however, is not whether by acting wrongly the ARL forfeits theright to physical security (or to not be attacked), but rather whether it has

    forfeited the right (in the mere liberty or permission sense of right) to

    continue to participate in the revolution after acting wrongly to initiate

    it. Because I doubt that any adequate framework for thinking about this

    question of rights forfeiture exists at present, I will simply flag this issue

    in the ethics of revolution as an important topic for further research. My

    intuition, however, is that the ARLs earlier wrongful acts do not result in

    forfeiture of the right to participate in the continuation of the revolution,though they may invalidate any claim the ARL might make to be the

    rightful leadership of the revolution.

    G. Justification and Legitimacy

    Thus far, I have argued that an immoral ARL is very likely to be a neces-

    sary evil when it comes to successful revolution in the very circum-

    stances in which there is the strongest moral case for revolution. But

    perhaps there is a way to escape that uncomfortable conclusion, or at

    least to mitigate it. After all, the ARL, as I have described it under condi-

    tions of Resolute Severe Tyranny, is not gratuitously coercing and

    manipulating its fellows. It is constrained to do so by conditions beyond

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    18/33

    its controlconditions that the regime created and is culpable forandit is attempting to satisfy the laudable constraint of the Reasonable Like-

    lihood of Success Principle. That is, it is taking seriously the idea that one

    should not engage in revolution (or any sort of large-scale violence)

    unless one has a reasonable prospect of success. And, remember that by

    hypothesis, it is made up of people who are committed to overthrowing

    an extremely unjust regime. Recall, also, that by hypothesis we are con-

    sidering only cases where the Severe Tyranny is resolute: it has stead-

    fastly refused to reform and gives every indication of being willing to use

    the harshest means available to stay in power. Finally, suppose that the

    ARL has, without success, already exhausted less morally problematic

    strategies for solving the widespread participation collective action

    problem. Given all of this, perhaps we should conclude that although the

    ARL is necessary, it is not really evil. The ARLs peculiar situationthe

    severe disadvantages under which it labors due to the unjust acts of

    the regimecreates an exception to the usual moral constraints.

    Some will no doubt find this special pleading less than convincing. It

    might be thought that even if all of these conditions were satisfied, theARL could not be justified in using coercion against its fellow victims of

    oppression to conscript them because it lacks legitimacy (political

    authority). For a state to be justified in conscripting soldiers, one might

    argue, it must be legitimate. But on any reasonable account of legiti-

    macy, the ARL is arguably not legitimate. The conditions of oppression

    created by the Resolute Severe Tyranny prevent the ARL from gaining

    legitimacy, whether through consent, through democratic processes, or

    through the lawful transfer of legitimacy from a legitimate entity, aswhen one government succeeds another according to constitutionally

    specified procedures. Nor can the ARL, at least in the early stages of the

    revolution, satisfy the criteria for legitimacy according to functionalist

    accounts. Functionalist accounts hold that an entity becomes legitimate

    by performing adequately the justifying functions of states, such as pro-

    viding security and basic justice.14 The ARL will not be capable of per-

    forming these functions until the revolution has succeeded.

    . More plausible versions of functionalist accounts of legitimacy include a

    nonusurpation condition: to be legitimate, an entity not only must fulfill the requisite

    functions adequately but also must not have come to power by overthrowing a legitimate

    political authority. In the case of revolution against a Resolute Severe Tyranny, that

    condition is satisfied.

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    19/33

    My aim here is not to resolve the complex debate over what legitimacy(or political authority) is. To motivate this stage of my argument, it is not

    necessary to do so. Instead, I want to argue that in the case of the ARL,

    legitimacy is not a necessary condition of justified coercion of fellow

    victims of oppression on any of the standard views on legitimacy.

    I will begin by calling attention to something that I think is relatively

    uncontroversial: the use of forceagainst a Resolute Severe Tyrannycan

    be justified even if those wielding it lack legitimacy. To reject this asser-

    tion is to take a very extreme position on the ethics of revolution: it is to

    deny that revolution against a Resolute Severe Tyranny is virtually ever

    justifiable, since at the beginnings of such revolutions the conditions of

    oppression will have prevented the formation of any legitimate entity

    capable of opposing the state.15 The question on which I will focus is

    whether the ARL must be legitimate if its use of forceagainst its fellow

    victims of oppressionis to be justified. I will also assume, arguendo, that

    some uses of force by the ARL, including murdering people and making

    it appear that they were killed by the regime, conscripting children, and

    summarily shooting a few people in a village to terrorize the rest intoparticipating, are not justifiable. The question is whether some much

    . Kant notoriously held that revolution is never morally justified, but to my knowl-

    edge no contemporary just war theorist agrees with him. Kant apparently thought that it is

    wrong to attack the state, because only the state can supply basic justice (or the condition

    of right, in Kantian terms). The difficulty with Kants argumenton its most plausible

    construalis that it wrongly assumes that an attack on the regime must result in a condi-

    tion in which justice cannot exist. Locke noted that the destruction of the political authority

    need not mean the destruction of society, with the implication that nonstate social prac-

    tices may do a sufficiently adequate job of securing basic justice, during the transition to a

    new, more just state, to be morally acceptable, given the importance of overthrowing an

    unjust state. The Lockean view receives empirical support from studies of revolutions. In a

    number of cases, revolutionary groups establish parallel institutions prior to their most

    serious attacks on the state, institutions that perform some state functions, thus ensuring

    that the destruction of the state does not mean the loss of all law and order. When this

    strategy succeeds, the interpretation of Kants view that I have sketched loses its bite.

    Nevertheless, it is important to acknowledge that it may be difficult or even impossible to

    establish parallel institutions in cases where the Resolute Severe Tyranny exercises effec-

    tive control over the locales in which they would have to be established. In general, revo-

    lutionary groups seem to be more effective in establishing parallel institutions in remote,rural areas where the regimes military or security forces cannot sustain an effective pres-

    ence. In locales that the regime tightly controls, only rather minimal parallel institutions

    can be established. See, for example, the wedding ceremony conducted by National Lib-

    eration Front officials in the classic film treatment of revolution The Battle of Algiers.

    Conducting wedding ceremonies is one thing, providing basic justice is another.

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    20/33

    less extreme, though nonetheless morally questionable uses of coercion,in particular some techniques for conscripting people to fight against the

    regime, can be justifiable in the absence of legitimacy.

    Why might one think that it is justifiable for the ARL to use force

    against a Resolute Severe Tyranny, even though the ARL lacks legitimacy,

    but that the ARL must be legitimate if its conscription of fighters is to be

    morally justified? The most obvious answer is that the regime and the

    people are in quite different moral situations: the regimes unjust actions

    have made it liable to be attacked (or have forfeited its right not to be

    subject to force), whereas the people the ARL attempts to conscript have

    done no such thing. Thus, one might think that only if an agent or

    institution is legitimate can the presumption against coercion be over-

    come, in the absence of some act that makes one liable to coercion.

    Without denying the asymmetry between the moral situations of a

    tyrannical regime and the people it oppresses, I want nonetheless

    to argue that the ARL, though lacking legitimacy, can justifiably con-

    script fighters, if certain conditions are satisfied. To do this, I want

    to distinguish two related but importantly different principles concern-ing the relationship between legitimacy and the justification of the

    use of coercion.

    CL: Coercive imposition of rules (for example, requiring military

    service) is justifiable only if the institution or agent wielding coercion

    is legitimate.

    CL:Coercive imposition of rules typically requires legitimacy in cir-cumstances in which the resources for obtaining legitimacy are avail-

    able. In contrast, where the resources for obtaining legitimacy are not

    availableand where their lack of availability is not due to the actions

    of the entity seeking to wield coercionlegitimacy is not a necessary

    condition for the justified wielding of coercion.

    My aim is to make the case for CL and against CL. To do this, I will

    explore certain morally significant similarities between the case of revo-

    lution and that of the creation of a state under conditions of anarchy.

    Suppose that a massive natural disaster, an ecological collapse, a

    lethal large-scale bioterrorist attack, or a civil war has destroyed all ves-

    tiges of law and order. There are various armed factions, many of whom

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    21/33

    are willing to use violence indiscriminately for their own benefit, withoutregard for justice or any other moral constraint. Suppose also that there

    is a relatively small group of people who have the resolve and the ability

    to impose the order needed to secure everyones most basic rights: call

    them the aspiring state-founders, or ASF for brevity. Suppose that the

    ASF is firmly committed to establishing basic justice for all and to doing

    so by the least morally objectionable means that are feasible. Finally,

    suppose also that the prevailing extremely harsh conditions preclude the

    possibility of the ASF being a legitimate agent, an agent that has the

    authority to use coercion to transform anarchy into minimal justice on

    any reasonable conception of legitimacy. The situation is simply too

    chaotic and insecure for elections or any less formal democratic autho-

    rization of the ASF or consent, and no other institutional resources for

    transferring or conferring legitimacy exist or can be created prior to

    establishing basic law and order. Finally, suppose also that the ASF has

    not yet achieved sufficient control to satisfy the criteria for legitimacy of

    functionalist theories of legitimacy: it is not yet adequately performing

    the functions of providing order and basic justice that such theories sayconfer legitimacy. As with the case of the ARL, conditions for which it is

    not responsible make it impossible for the ASF to satisfy the require-

    ments of any of the standard theories of legitimacy.

    My intuition is that it would nevertheless be morally justifiable for

    such a group to coerce others into joining its effort to achieve security for

    all. It would be justifiable, for example, for the ASF to threaten individu-

    als with certain penalties if they did not participate in efforts to suppress

    lawless groups, for example, fines or the expropriation of property.Needless to say, their use of coercion would be subject to various moral

    constraints, including those of proportionality and the requirement that

    carrying out a coercive threat would be a last resort.

    Suppose your intuition about the case of anarchy accords with mine:

    you think that the ASF, even if it lacks legitimacy, would be justified in

    using some forms of coercion. If that is your view, then shouldnt you

    also conclude that the ARL can also use similar forms of coercion on

    fellow victims of tyranny without acting impermissibly, even though

    it lacks legitimacy?

    It is important to emphasize that the predicaments of the ASF and the

    ARL are identical in morally relevant ways: both are committed to rem-

    edying severe injustice and both must solve coordination and collective

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    22/33

    action problems in situations in which, through no fault of their own, theconditions for legitimate leadership do not existand cannot be brought

    about until after the basic coordination and collective action problems are

    solved. So it appears either that both the ASF and the ARL act wrongly or

    that neither do. My intuition is that the latter alternative is the correct

    one. Hence principle CL, which makes legitimacy an unconditional nec-

    essary condition for coercion, ought to be rejected. In contrast, principle

    CL, which only requires legitimacy in circumstances in which the

    resources for securing legitimacy are available, explains the intuition

    that both the ASF and the ARL may justifiably use coercion.

    I wish to point out, however, an uncomfortable apparent implication

    of opting for the conclusion that, at least under conditions of Resolute

    Severe Tyranny, an ARL can use coercion against its fellow victims of

    oppression to solve the coordination and participation problems

    without acting wrongly. The problem is this: if one opts for that con-

    clusion, where can one draw the line as to the permissible use of force

    by the ARL? We have assumed, from the outset, that acts of terrorism (as

    conventionally defined) are not morally permissible, even under condi-tions of Resolute Severe Tyranny. Can one consistently hold that the

    ARL can sometimes use coercion against its own people and yet at the

    same time say that using violence against noncombatants to provoke

    terror and fear that will change the political behavior of the regime

    is never justified?

    Of course, one could try to lessen the pain of this query by hypoth-

    esizing that while the need to achieve coordination and widespread par-

    ticipation are typically crucial for the success of revolutions, terrorism isnot. I find that a less than satisfactory response, to put it mildly. A better

    option is to note that when an ARL uses coercion to achieve widespread

    participation in the revolutionassuming that the revolution is other-

    wise justifiedit is doing precisely what legitimate governments rou-

    tinely do and are rightly expected to do: issuing directives, backed with

    force as a last resort, to achieve important collective goods (such as

    national security or order and basic justice) that could not otherwise be

    secured. The same cannot be said, of course, about agents who commit

    acts of terrorism. Legitimate governments do not achieve their ends by

    indiscriminate violence aimed at terrorizing people in order to shape

    political decisions. The morally relevant difference, then, is that when

    an ARL uses the threat of force to secure sufficiently widespread

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    23/33

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    24/33

    be justified, if this were the least coercive effective measure and if it weredone in a nondiscriminatory way and with sufficient advance notice.

    Perhaps one of the most important constraints on justified revolu-

    tionary conscription is that the burdens it imposes should be distributed

    fairly among that portion of the population who are competent to serve

    as soldiers.16 To the extent that revolutionary conscription satisfies this

    fairness constraint and approximates the other constraints observed in

    the least morally problematic instances of conscription by a legitimate

    state, it becomes more plausible to maintain that it is justified, especially

    when the regime, through wrongful acts, has erected formidable

    obstacles to voluntary participation.

    In the next section, I will argue that my analysis of the moral

    predicament of the ARL has important implications for the ethics of

    intervening in revolutions.

    II. INTERVENTION

    I argued above that it can be morally justifiable for people to participatein a revolution whose initiation by an ARL involved seriously immoral

    acts. The same conclusion holds for intervention in support of a revolu-

    tion with tainted origins. The fact that the revolution began with

    immoral manipulation of popular sentiments by the ARL or committed

    wrongful acts of violence against rivals for leadership does not itself

    entail that intervention in support of the revolution would be wrong.

    That fact may be relevant, of course, to the decision whether to inter-

    vene. For one thing, immoral behavior by the ARL may increase the

    probability that the revolution will not turn out well or that the inter-

    vener will become an accomplice in future immoral acts. The key point,

    however, is that intervening in support of a revolution, like participating

    in it, can be morally justifiable even if the acts by which the revolution

    was initiated were not.

    Suppose that the ARL, by dint of morally impermissible acts, has

    achieved sufficient coordination and participation so that the revolution

    has a high likelihood of success if there is intervention in support of it.

    And also assume, as before, that the Just Cause is patent and compelling:the regime is a Resolute Severe Tyranny. Suppose also that all the other

    . Christopher J. Finlay, Fairness and Liability in the Just War: Combatants, Non-

    Combatants, and Lawful Irregulars,Political Studies (): .

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    25/33

    appropriate conditions for justified intervention are present. Surely,the justifiability of intervention depends upon what the current situation

    is, not upon whether at some earlier point, in quite different circum-

    stances, the ARL committed morally impermissible acts to create

    the current situation.

    Even if tainted origins do not preclude justified intervention, there

    are other well-known reasons to regard intervention in support of revo-

    lutions, like interventions for other purposes, with extreme caution.17

    Two principles designed to reduce the risk of mistaken interventions

    have been advanced and have garnered considerable support. The

    second, in fact, seems to be the dominant view in the literature. The

    first, Mills Principle, states that intervention in support of a revolution

    should not occur until and unless there is widespread domestic partici-

    pation in the revolution.18 The second, the Consent Principle, states that

    intervention in support of a revolution should not occur without the

    consent (or approval) of the people who are the intended beneficiaries

    of the intervention.

    Both principles are afflicted by vagueness. Without knowing whatcounts as widespread participation, one cannot know when the sup-

    posed necessary condition for intervention has been met. Similarly, one

    needs to know not only what counts as consent or approval, but also how

    widespread the consent or approval must be. I will simply set aside these

    daunting problems, which are familiar enough, in order to focus on

    problems with both principles that have not been noticed, due to lack of

    attention to the (rather grim) facts about revolutions, and in particular

    about the formidable incentives for immoral behavior that the ARL facesand their consequences for efforts to apply the two principles.

    A. Mills Principle

    On its most plausible construal, Mills Principle recommends wide-

    spread participation as an epistemic proxy for broad, deep, and stable

    commitment to revolution. According to this interpretation, Mill was

    . For a good example of the many works that explore what can go wrong in

    interventions, see Rory Stewart and Gerald Knaus, Can Intervention Work? (New

    York: Norton,).

    . J. S. Mill, A Few Words on Intervention, in Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol.

    , ed. John M. Robson (Toronto: University of Toronto Press,).

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    26/33

    concerned to take seriously the Reasonable Likelihood of SuccessRequirement and surmised that a successful intervention in support of a

    revolution could not be reliably predicted in the absence of a broad,

    deep, and stable commitment to revolution on the part of a substantial

    portion of the population. Widespread participation, he thought, was a

    reliable marker for such commitment.

    The most obvious problem with Mills Principle is that it underesti-

    mates the obstacles to widespread participation in the modern context,

    especially in the case of Resolute Severe Tyrannies. In Mills day, the

    disparity of firepower between the regime and would-be revolutionaries

    was not as great as it generally is today. It is one thing for people to pick

    up their muskets, head for the barricades, and take their chances against

    comparably equipped regime forces; but it is quite another for people

    with a collection of hunting rifles and AK-s to go up against fighter

    bombers and long-range, laser-guided artillery. The point is that, given

    this disparity of firepower, the risks of participation are correspondingly

    greater and, at least in the early stages of revolution, the decision to

    participate may require not just a deep and stable commitment to revo-lution, but also a zealous motivation bordering on the sacrificial.19 So,

    Mills Principle is highly problematic, because the epistemic proxy it

    recommends is much less reliable in our day than it was in Mills.20

    There is another fact about the contemporary revolutionary context

    that further impugns Mills Principle: participation, for some, perhaps

    many, people, may be the result of coercion and manipulation of emo-

    tions by the ARL, and where this is the case, participation will not be a

    reliable proxy for a deep and stable commitment to the revolution. Par-ticipating because one fears the ARL more than the regimes forces is no

    evidence at all of commitment to the revolution. Nor is participating

    because ones emotions have been manipulated in response to an

    episode of harsh behavior by the regime or because one has been fed

    stories about atrocities that never occurred a reliable proxy for a stable

    commitment to the revolution. Mills Principle is flawed, then, not only

    because it underestimates the disincentives to participation created by

    . Bas Van der Vossen also makes this point in The Morality of Humanitarian Inter-

    vention, Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics, ed. Andrew I. Cohen and Christopher H.

    Wellman (New York: Wiley-Blackwell, forthcoming).

    . I thank Jeff Holzgrefe for making this point clear to me and for assisting me in

    researching this article.

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    27/33

    the disparity of firepower in the modern revolutionary context, but alsobecause it overlooks the possibility that participation for some people

    may be an artifact of coercion and manipulation by the ARL rather than

    a sign of deep and stable commitment to the revolution. Both flaws are

    the result of failure to attend to the facts about revolution.

    B. The Consent Principle

    Given what I have just said about Mills Principle, it will not be hard to

    predict my complaint about the Consent Principle. But, first, let us beclear about why many find this principle plausible. The attraction of

    the Consent Principle is that it expresses a commitment to avoiding

    unjustified paternalism. The idea is that it would be unjustifiably

    paternalisticdisrespectful to people regarded as autonomous agents

    with their own values and reasons for actingto impose on them the

    risks that intervention entails without consulting their own judgment as

    to whether those risks are worth bearing.21 To intervene without consent

    or approval is to substitute the interveners judgment for the peoplesjudgment as to whether the expected benefits of the intervention exceed

    the expected costs.

    The most obvious difficulty with the Consent Principle is that if one

    takes its underlying rationale seriously, it is hard to see how intervention

    could be justified withoutunanimousconsent. How could the fact that

    others consent make the intervention any less disrespectful toward those

    who do not consent? Unanimous consent, of course, is a requirement

    that will virtually never be satisfied, in which case the Consent Principle

    would never allow intervention. Even if we set that obvious problem

    aside, there is another, equally familiar difficulty: the very conditions

    that make the moral case for revolution strongestthe situation of Reso-

    lute Severe Tyrannyimpose formidable epistemic barriers to knowing

    whether people consent or not. A Resolute Severe Tyranny does not

    allow referenda on revolution, surveys on approval of intervention, or

    . For two examples among many of theorists of intervention who endorse the

    Consent (or approval) Principle, see Fernando Teson, Ending Tyranny in Iraq, Ethics &International Affairs (): ; and Jeff McMahan, Humanitarian Intervention, Consent,

    and Proportionality, in Ethics and Humanity: Reflections on the Philosophy of Jonathan

    Glover, ed. N. Ann Davis, Richard Keshen, and Jeff McMahan (New York: NYU Press, ).

    McMahan argues that the Consent Principle is best understood as grounded in a rejection

    of unjustified paternalism (personal communication, April , ).

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    28/33

    even expressions of political views that are reliably ascertainable bypotential interveners. Moreover, expressions of animosity against the

    regime cannot be regarded as endorsements of intervention, much less

    of intervention by any particular agent. For example, it may have been

    that prior to March of there was a widespread desire among

    Iraqis to be rid of Saddam Hussein (though how widespread was hard

    to ascertain given the ubiquitous repression), but from that one could

    not infer that there was widespread approval of foreign intervention

    to topple him, much less widespread approval of intervention led by

    the United States.

    Apart from these epistemic worries about the Consent Principle, there

    is another, at least equally serious problem that comes to light only when

    one takes seriously the facts about revolutions and in particular the fact

    that the ARL, in situations where the moral case for revolution is stron-

    gest, is under formidable pressure to utilize coercion and manipulation

    to mobilize the masses. Even if one can overcome the formidable

    obstacles to ascertaining whether people consent or approve of inter-

    vention, their consent or approval will not be normatively potent if it isthe product of coercion or manipulation of sentiments by the ARL.

    Consent or approval that is the product of coercion or manipulation is

    not valid consent or authentic approval. So the objection to the Consent

    Principle is not just that under conditions of tyranny it will be hard to

    know whether people consent or approve, but that under those same

    conditions it is likely that consent or approval in some cases will not be

    morally potent enough to block the allegation of unjustified paternalism.

    C. Two New Reasons to Intervene Early

    So far, I have shown that two well-known principles intended to regulate

    the decision to intervene are much less plausible once one attends to the

    predictable behavior of the aspiring revolutionary leadership toward

    their fellow victims of oppression. Now I want to argue that the same

    facts about the behavior of the ARL count in favor of early intervention.

    The most familiar reason in favor of early intervention in support of

    a revolution is that it may reduce the casualties that the revolutionaries

    and regime forces will inflict on each other if the struggle continues.

    But my analysis shows that there is another, less obvious reason: early

    intervention can, in principle, prevent wrongdoing perpetrated by the

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    29/33

    ARL against its fellow victims of tyranny. Such wrongdoing is not onlysomething to be prevented on its own account; it is also undesirable

    because it can contribute to the corruption of the ARL and thereby of

    the revolution itself. If it becomes accustomed to wrongdoing toward

    its fellow victims of oppression during the revolutionary struggle, this

    may increase the probability that the ARL will mistreat citizens once it

    comes to power. Even worse, the ARLs wrongdoing during the revolu-

    tion may foster a more general culture of brutality in the postrevolu-

    tionary society.

    Social scientists analyzing revolution have made a strong case that

    much of what occurs can be explained as the result of the fact that

    revolutions typically feature a struggle over the conditions under which

    the ARL attempts to solve the widespread participation collective

    action problem.22 In other words, the ARLs collective action problem is

    the locus of strategic interactions between the ARL and the regime. The

    regime attempts to exacerbate the obstacles to successful collective

    action and the ARL in turn takes countermeasures to overcome the

    obstacles the regime erects, and so on. For example, the initial collec-tive action problem the ARL faces is how to get large numbers of

    people to participate in the revolution in spite of the fact that revolu-

    tion has the familiar features of a public good, with the usual incentives

    for individuals not to participate. In particular, as I noted above, the

    individual is likely to reason that his own participation will involve a

    cost and will not be critical for the outcome, and that he will be able to

    enjoy the benefits of revolution regardless of whether he participates or

    not. To overcome this obstacle to participation, the ARL may respondby increasing the costs of nonparticipation: either by now credibly

    threatening nonparticipants with violence or other penalties if they do

    not participate or by credibly pledging to punish them when the revo-

    lution succeeds. The regime, in turn, in order to shift the balance of

    incentives back toward the rationality of nonparticipation, may then

    increase the costs of participation by taking harsher measures, not only

    against participants, but also against their families. The cycle then may

    continue, with the ARL using increasingly coercive measures and more

    . See, for example, Mark I. Lichbach, Rethinking Rationality and Rebellion:

    Theories of Collective Action and Problems of Collective Dissent, Rationality and Society

    (): .

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    30/33

    egregious manipulation of sentiments in order to counteract theregimes escalation of the costs of participation.

    When this familiar spiral of coercion occurs, refraining from early

    interventionwaiting until the death toll is very high or until there is

    evidence of widespread commitment to the revolution or until it

    becomes clear who is really in charge of the revolutionwill come at a

    very high moral cost. The point is that the moral cost of refraining from

    early intervention is not restricted to the additional casualties in battles

    between revolutionaries and regime forces; it also includes the costs of

    the additional wrongs that occur as a result of a continuing strategic

    conflict over the participation collective action problem. If interveners

    can act so as to stop the escalation, they will reduce these costs.

    One way they can do this is to reduce the regimes threat advantage,

    to make it less able to issue credible threats against those who are con-

    templating whether to participate in the revolution. This might be done,

    for example, by effecting a cyber attack on the regimes military com-

    munications network or by disabling its fighter jet and attack helicopter

    forces or by establishing a no-fly zone or by imposing an arms embargoagainst the regime. The rationale for such measures would not be to

    help the revolutionaries succeed, but rather to reduce the risk of a spiral

    of coercion and thereby reduce the risk that the revolutionary leader-

    ship will become corrupted by habituating itself to brutal measures

    against the people.

    Another way to avoid the spiral of coercion, of course, is to reduce the

    ARLs ability to coerce the people. This might be done by injecting

    observers to monitor the ARLs behavior, with the threat that support forthe revolution by external parties will not be forthcoming if they engage

    in excessive coercion against the people. Alternatively or in addition,

    measures might be taken to limit the ARLs access to arms. In some

    cases, early intervention of these sorts could stop the spiral of coercion.

    Of course, the same measures (for example, arms embargoes) that

    serve to reduce the ARLs ability to coerce the people into participating in

    the revolution may also reduce the likelihood that the revolution will

    succeed. If outside agents are to act responsibly in such cases, they must

    weigh the value of preventing a spiral of coercion against the value of

    supporting, or at least not undermining, the revolutionary effort.

    In cases where the revolution is strongly justified, the presumption

    should be that efforts to prevent a spiral of coercion should focus

    Philosophy& Public Affairs

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    31/33

    primarily on reducing the regimes ability to impose costs on participa-tion. If the ARLs use of coercion against the people is chiefly

    reactivean attempt to overcome the obstacles to widespread partici-

    pation created by the wrongful use of force by the regimethen the

    result of such interventions should be a lessening of the use of coercion

    against the people by the ARL. In some cases, the justice of the revolu-

    tionaries cause is dubious because of the kind of regime they hope to

    establish, yet the current regime is undoubtedly unjust. Here a more

    evenhanded approach might be called for, that is, measures to reduce

    the coercive capacity of both parties, again for the sake of preventing a

    spiral of coercion.

    Attention to the way revolutions actually occur also suggests a second

    reason in favor of early intervention: in principle, intervention could

    help establish the conditions under which outsiders could have reliable

    evidence about whether there is widespread valid consent to or authen-

    tic approval of intervention aimed at helping the revolution to succeed.

    This could occur, for example, if the intervener could impose a cease-

    fire, physically separate the two sides, and then investigate the attitudesof the population toward the revolutionary struggle under conditions in

    which they can be freely expressed.

    Recall that the difficulty with applying the principle that intervention

    in support of a revolution should not occur without consent or approval

    on the part of the public is that under the very conditions under which

    revolution and hence intervention in support of revolution are most

    clearly morally justified, it is likely that coercion and manipulation of

    emotions by the ARL will undermine the conditions for valid consent orauthentic approval. If that is the case, then there is something to be said

    for intervening early enough to prevent the ARL from needing to resort to

    behavior that will undermine the conditions for valid consent to or

    authentic approval of intervention in support of the revolution. Notice

    that if a third party intervened for this reasonto help establish the

    conditions under which valid consent or authentic approval could occur

    and be reliably identified as suchit would not be correct to say that it

    was guilty of unjustified paternalism. In intervening for this reason, it

    would notbe substituting its own judgment about the ratio of benefits to

    costs of revolution for that of the people directly affected. It would not be

    intervening to support the revolution, but rather to help create condi-

    tions under which it could determinewhether to support the revolution.

    The Ethics of Revolution and Its

    Implications for the Ethics of

    Intervention

  • 8/13/2019 Buchanan Ethics of Revolution

    32/33

    Such action would not qualify as paternalistic, because its objectivewould not be to promote the good of the people but instead to determine

    whether to act to promote it or to support the regime or to remain

    neutral in the struggle.

    Once we attend to the strategic interaction of the ARL and the regime

    and appreciate the strong incentives for coercion and manipulation this

    creates for the ARL, the costs of delaying intervention are seen to be

    greater than they are usually thought to be. This is not, of course, a

    conclusive argument for early intervention. Intervention at any stage is

    fraught with risks of error and abuse, and early intervention has its own

    peculiar perils. For one thing, a known policy of early intervention

    would create incentives for unscrupulous agents to manufacture the

    conditions that are known to trigger early intervention, in the absence

    of either a solid moral case for revolution or any real prospect that there

    would ever be sufficient deep and stable commitment to it on the part

    of significant portions of the population. Another risk is that the inter-

    veners might, deliberately or unwittingly, encourage unwarranted

    expectations that they will provide long-term, effective support for therevolution and thereby encourage people to participate in a struggle

    that will endanger them without having a reasonable prospect of

    success. My point, however, is not to provide a conclusive novel argu-

    ment for early intervention but rather to show that important consid-

    erations relevant to making an all-things-considered judgment on early

    intervention have been neglected due to inattention to the actual

    dynamics of revolutions.23

    III. CONCLUSION

    The main results of this investigation can now be summarized, without

    recapitulating the arguments for them. First, revolutions typically begin

    with the actions of an Aspiring Revolutionary Leadership that faces

    severe problems whose solution is necessary if the revolution is to

    succeed; yet in conditions under which the moral case for revolution is

    str