Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

    1/5

    Review: De Mundo

    Author(s): Jonathan BarnesReviewed work(s):

    Aristotele: Trattato sul Cosmo per Alessandro, traduzione con testo greco a fronte,introduzione, commento e indici by Giovanni Reale

    Source: The Classical Review, New Series, Vol. 27, No. 1 (1977), pp. 40-43Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/710942

    Accessed: 24/01/2010 11:25

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

    you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

    page of such transmission.

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve

    and extend access to The Classical Review.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/710942?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/710942?origin=JSTOR-pdf
  • 8/6/2019 Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

    2/5

    400 THE CLASSICAL REVIEWHE CLASSICAL REVIEWof the first four books-and arguing for his own choice. But, in the Topics aselsewhere, Aristotle is frequently obscure, and we expect examination of suchobscurities, to find whether Aristotle himself is at fault-and if so what featureof his language or habits of thought has misled him-or whether we ourselveshave failed to understand him. A typical place where Zadro fails us is Book VIII,Chapter 5. Here Aristotle treats evbo~ov and dbo0ov as logical contraries, withpuzzling results, if we compare earlier uses of ~vo~Oov. Zadro, having argued fornotevole as the best translation of evbo~ov in Book I, keeps it here, and ignoresthe obscurity. He also ignores the fact that Aristotle has two words, lrapdooovand '5o~ov, as negatives of evbo~ov, and, worse, uses lrapdbo~ov in his notes onthis chapter where Aristotle has only 'Bo0ov.The fact that here and elsewhere Zadro does not seize the opportunity towork out Aristotle's abstract discussions with actual examples is particularly dis-appointing because he is interested in the development of philosophical language,and the various levels at which arguments may occur. He does however contributeto our understanding of Aristotle's logic in the appendices, setting out a system ofintensional logic which he claims is faithful both to Aristotle's text and to tradi-tional Boolean algebra, and which illuminates the vnrdpxetvrelationship, andtaking up the problem of the interpretation of syllogistic argument first raised byLucaziewicz.He also gives an evaluation of the Commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias-the only ancient commentary we have-which he thinks more useful as a historicaldocument than as an aid to understanding Aristotle, except where Alexandersupplies items of information which may have reached him intact after fivecenturies. An example is the illustration of a geometrical paralogism at 101a1 3.Unfortunately such information is sparse for the Topics.University of Liverpool PAMELAM. HUBY

    DE MUNDOGIOVANNI EALE:Aristotele:Trattato ul CosmoperAlessandro,traduzione on testogrecoa fronte,introduzione, ommentoe indici.Pp. xv + 358. Naples: Loffredo, 1974. Cloth, L. 9,000.The corpus Aristotelicum contains a short treatise de Mundo addressed to Alex-ander the Great. Its professed aim is to 'theologize about all the features of theuniverse' (391b4), and it duly serves up a potted account of science and phil-osophy. Scholars disagree over its date and authorship; but an almost universalconsensus places it at least two centuries after the death of Aristotle.The chief claim of Reale's new edition of the de Mundo is to have explodedthat orthodoxy: the tract, he argues, is genuine. 'It can be proved that the workis, or may be, Aristotle's, it dates, in all probability, from the period whenAristotle tutored Alexander at the court of Macedon, and it is nothing otherthan the handbook to philosophy which he composed for the young prince'(p. xi). The treatise is in fact 'the best Introduction to Aristotle that we couldpossibly desire' (p. xv): doubtless, it was so used in the Lyceum, and it may havebeen lightly retouched by the mature Aristotle and by Theophrastus (see pp. 114-17; 211 n. 2); but the work as a whole is an exoteric exercise, and it can besafely dated to 343/340 (pp. 32---3).

    of the first four books-and arguing for his own choice. But, in the Topics aselsewhere, Aristotle is frequently obscure, and we expect examination of suchobscurities, to find whether Aristotle himself is at fault-and if so what featureof his language or habits of thought has misled him-or whether we ourselveshave failed to understand him. A typical place where Zadro fails us is Book VIII,Chapter 5. Here Aristotle treats evbo~ov and dbo0ov as logical contraries, withpuzzling results, if we compare earlier uses of ~vo~Oov. Zadro, having argued fornotevole as the best translation of evbo~ov in Book I, keeps it here, and ignoresthe obscurity. He also ignores the fact that Aristotle has two words, lrapdooovand '5o~ov, as negatives of evbo~ov, and, worse, uses lrapdbo~ov in his notes onthis chapter where Aristotle has only 'Bo0ov.The fact that here and elsewhere Zadro does not seize the opportunity towork out Aristotle's abstract discussions with actual examples is particularly dis-appointing because he is interested in the development of philosophical language,and the various levels at which arguments may occur. He does however contributeto our understanding of Aristotle's logic in the appendices, setting out a system ofintensional logic which he claims is faithful both to Aristotle's text and to tradi-tional Boolean algebra, and which illuminates the vnrdpxetvrelationship, andtaking up the problem of the interpretation of syllogistic argument first raised byLucaziewicz.He also gives an evaluation of the Commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias-the only ancient commentary we have-which he thinks more useful as a historicaldocument than as an aid to understanding Aristotle, except where Alexandersupplies items of information which may have reached him intact after fivecenturies. An example is the illustration of a geometrical paralogism at 101a1 3.Unfortunately such information is sparse for the Topics.University of Liverpool PAMELAM. HUBY

    DE MUNDOGIOVANNI EALE:Aristotele:Trattato ul CosmoperAlessandro,traduzione on testogrecoa fronte,introduzione, ommentoe indici.Pp. xv + 358. Naples: Loffredo, 1974. Cloth, L. 9,000.The corpus Aristotelicum contains a short treatise de Mundo addressed to Alex-ander the Great. Its professed aim is to 'theologize about all the features of theuniverse' (391b4), and it duly serves up a potted account of science and phil-osophy. Scholars disagree over its date and authorship; but an almost universalconsensus places it at least two centuries after the death of Aristotle.The chief claim of Reale's new edition of the de Mundo is to have explodedthat orthodoxy: the tract, he argues, is genuine. 'It can be proved that the workis, or may be, Aristotle's, it dates, in all probability, from the period whenAristotle tutored Alexander at the court of Macedon, and it is nothing otherthan the handbook to philosophy which he composed for the young prince'(p. xi). The treatise is in fact 'the best Introduction to Aristotle that we couldpossibly desire' (p. xv): doubtless, it was so used in the Lyceum, and it may havebeen lightly retouched by the mature Aristotle and by Theophrastus (see pp. 114-17; 211 n. 2); but the work as a whole is an exoteric exercise, and it can besafely dated to 343/340 (pp. 32---3).

  • 8/6/2019 Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

    3/5

    THE CLASSICAL REVIEW 41Reale's thesis is exciting: if it is correct, then the de Mundo is the earliest ofAristotle's writings to have survived intact; and we possess in it a perfect exampleof those Aristotelian juvenilia upon whose fragments modern scholars have solaboriously lucubrated.The sceptical orthodoxy has argued that the style of the de Mundo is highflown,prosy, and unAristotelian; that its dogmatic treatment of its subject is alien to theaporematic and richly reasoned method of the Aristotelian treatises; and that inphilosophical and scientific doctrine it contradicts Aristotle's familiar opinionsand exhibits Stoic, Neopythagorean, Neoplatonic, and Biblical influences.Reale's long Introduction is primarily devoted to a refutation of those scepticalaspersions. The style of the de Mundo and its method are indeed unlike those ofthe esoteric treatises; but what else should we expect from a popular or exotericexposition addressed to a youthful prince? (See pp. x; 26-9.) The philosophy ofthe de Mundo owes nothing to the Stoa or to any post-Aristotelian school; on thecontrary, all the philosophical assertions can be paralleled from the treatises orfrom the fragments of the early exoteric works (see pp. 51-97). Similarly, thescientific opinions of the de Mundo, whether on matters geographical, astro-nomical, or meteorological, are perfectly Peripatetic; for where they cannot bematched exactly by passages from the Aristotelian corpus, the fragments ofTheophrastus' scientific oeuvre provide convincing parallels (see pp. 99-127).The argument of Reale's Introduction is confirmed in detail by his Commentary(pp. 193-277). In sum, nothing-in the de Mundo indicates any post-Aristotelianinfluence; and numerous parallels with Platonic and early Aristotelian thoughtpoint plainly to the true origin of the tract.Reale's argument is elegantly done: his Introduction is a model of scholarlyexposition, pellucid in expression and meticulous in inference. The annotationsare often illuminating, and sometimes bring new resources to bear upon the text.(Thus the Syriac version of Theophrastus' Meteorologica is frequently appealedto; and the Derveni papyrus advances our understanding of Chapter 7.) Thevolume also contains a Greek text facing an Italian translation, an admirable

    bibliographie raisonnee, and a complete Index Verborum. (I have two complaints:Reale prints the text without any critical apparatus; and his notes are inconveni-ently keyed to the translation rather than to the text. I note an omission fromthe bibliography: G. Rudberg, Gedanke und Gefiibl, Symb.Osl. suppt. XIV, 1953).Whether his main thesis is accepted or rejected, Reale has made a noteworthycontribution to Aristotelian studies.Is the de Mundo genuine? Reale is, in my judgement, uniformly successful inhis objections to the many and various attempts to find post-Aristotelian elementsin the philosophy and science of the tract. And his objections yield one importantresult of a positive nature: Arius Didymus (fr.31 Diels) transcribes a long passagefrom Chrysippus (SVF ii.527) which is strikingly similar, both in substance andin language, to parts of Chapters 2 and 3 of the de Mundo. Reale argues thatChrysippus copied the de Mundo, not the de Mundo Chrysippus (pp. 118-27); andhis argument is cogent. Thus we may set a terminus ante quem for the compo-sition of the de Mundo at c. 250 B.C.That result is corroborated by the remark-able absence of the Stoic term lrpodvo0trom the list of thirty-seven names ofGod in de Mundo 7 (cf. p. 94).Thus the de Mundo is early and Peripatetic, not late and eclectic. But it doesnot follow that it is genuine. And we may allow full force to all the argumentsReale produces, and still resist his conclusion. For he fails to take issue with the

  • 8/6/2019 Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

    4/5

    42 THE CLASSICAL REVIEWmajor and most evident objection to his thesis. He does indeed observe that theliterary style of the de Mundo is not to be judged by canons drawn from theesoteric treatises of our corpus; and his notes contain a few remarks uponindividual words and phrases used in the tract; and he hints at the need fordetailed philological investigation (see p. 317). But he nowhere undertakes tosatisfy that need, and his edition is curiously lacking in stylistic and linguisticcomment. The major objection to Reale's thesis is linguistic; and Reale virtuallyignores it.A cursory reading of the de Mundo discovers in only ten Bekker pages someninety words not found elsewhere in the Aristotelian corpus; and fifty of thoseninety are not attested before the third century B.C. Here are some of thosesingularities, roughly categorized. Two asterisks indicate that the word is, accord-ing to LSJ, atrratXeT6pyevOv;ne, that it is not otherwise found before the thirdcentury:(i) Prepositional compounds: Karolnretu3 (391al0); avvavaxopevco** (b18);avliTreptarp??co* 392alO); lrept/wKtSc (b29); avvepeSc (b 33); rtrrtXar6vc**(393a20); adTvt7aprKCO * ( a31); ovav aarolea&* (bl); nreptareCavdoa (b 17)-bteat'iTco* (394bl5; 397a31); &e~rwve** (394635);? KpT^ct* (395Sa5);

    tEKcO&o*a22); KaTaorrTpia) (bl6); lrep'eoroc** (b25); rrape~ceO&** (b31);avvrwdaao* (b35); 7rpoaavao3a\dX ** (396a6); &vraTroraXXwc** (a8); ovaao-luaronote&o** (a14); &vravaKorrr** (a19); ovlarreptoSedco* (a26); ~repti3X6'co(397a25); rreptox~o,uat** (a25); emK\XV'co (a29); treptirrEo (a34); ?TravaoTr)Xco**(b3); eKv~XOlaat**398b32); bte6pprco** (b34; 399a24); avvemnrx&o399al5);avvercqaapTvpeo (400a 15); &va\v^tjco* (a32); ~Kc)(oao (a32); ~TeptKaraXaai(3davw(bl ); eKox'co* (b4).(ii) Nouns terminating in -ts: &vdaxeoat* (393b2); vnroaraaot*(= ovaia, LSJ III.2,395a30); e~at~tc* (b3); &va r3ovaot* (b21); a&rdrraXait*396a9); &v&~Xvot~*(a22); &vrdoarato* (LSJ II, 397al); ~rrtrdxv~tytq (398a10); ~ca)XtS 399b30; b32).(iii) Alpha privative compounds: &Komrraroc (391a12); &ve~etperoS (392a17);&verepo&oroq* (a32); daaXevroq (b34); a&e0eXoq (394a23); aVd,latXoq** (a23);arpo06oS (395b28); &~evbeda (397al1); dKardX\rT]Xos* (b31); aaelaVoS* (398b4);dK&)ot~UT (401b10); ara7ro?bpaorTo* (401b13).(iv) Words used technically in post-Aristotelian philosophy: vOrooraoti* (395a30);arrTraXtc* (396a9); arroreXelaja* (397a14); oVVrKTLKOS b9; cf. Reale p. 246 n.4).(v) Other notabilia: &vrapKrtKo*(392a4; cf. Reale, p. 206 n. 17); 7yeally (392a9;a22; 393a5; b2; b11; 394b21; 395a5; cf. Bonitz, Index Aristotelicus, 147a44-8;Denniston, Greek Particles, p. 347: 'This combination affords a remarkable ex-ample of a particular author's predilection for a particular particle; etc.') r&aoXa(392b3; 395a31; b4; b9; cf. Reale, p. 231 n. 55); 76co7pa0cko* (393b20; cf. Reale,p. 219 n. 29); 7pa,Laloeitcb* (395a27); ad?tet (396b9; 398bl4; 400bl3; cf.Lorimer, The Text Tradition of Pseudo-Aristotle 'De Mundo', p. 1 n. 2);)kepovtlV,CS* (399al9); &pX~Eyovoq*a26); 0 7evvafq IlXdrco(v 401b24).

    This collection of words is not the fruit of prolonged scholarship; nor are allthe singularities in it surprising: some were perhaps consciously adopted fromPlato (e.g. ijLatra7y7q.94a26 ~ Tim.59 E; bvoa0rcaavptoroq:01a5 ~ Critias115 B); a few poetical items were chosen for literary ends (e.g. ecKatOtptco.397627 ~ cf. E. I.T. 978'; Ka#TartTp6.:00b9 ~ cf. h.Ven. 246); a few are tech-nical terms whose absence from the rest of the corpus need raise no eyebrows

  • 8/6/2019 Barnes - Review de Mundo Reale

    5/5

    THE CLASSICAL REVIEWHE CLASSICAL REVIEW 433(e.g. E7Kor6o}: 393a23; oaTr]pia: 398bl5). But such excuses leave most ofthe singularities of vocabulary of the de Mundo untouched.The purpose of my list, however, is not to compose a refutation of Reale'sthesis: its aim is merely to indicate one part of the evidence which any judge ofthat thesis must take into account. Reale's defence of the de Mundo is only halfdone: he has shown, I think, that the tract cannot be expropriated from Aristotleon purely doctrinal grounds; but he has neither stated nor examined the linguisticarguments for expropriation. And those arguments, I venture to predict, willprove difficult to overturn.OrielCollege,Oxford JONATHAN ARNES

    HOMOCENTRIC SPHERESERKKAMAULA:Studies in Eudoxus' Homocentric Spheres. (Commen-tationes Humanarum Litterarum, 50.) Pp. 124. Helsinki: SocietasScientiarum Fennica, 1974. Paper, FM. 25.It is well known that Plato set before the mathematicians of the Academy theproblem of explaining the apparent motion of the heavenly bodies-'saving thephenomena'-on the assumption that all movements were uniform and circular.It is also well known that Eudoxus in a lost work entitled riepi raXchvgave abrilliant solution of this problem by means of homocentric spheres. The moon,sun, and five planets (Venus, Mercury, Mars,Jupiter, Saturn) were all supposedto move round a stationary earth. For the moon Eudoxus postulates three spheres.The moon was supposed to be at an extremity of an equatorial diameter of theinnermost sphere, which moved uniformly about its centre, which was also thecentre of the earth. But the poles of this innermost sphere were not at rest; theywere on the surface of a larger sphere, concentric with the first, which revolvedwith uniform speed about poles of its own. These poles of the second sphere werethemselves on the surface of a third outermost sphere which turned about itsown poles with its own speed. For the sun likewise Eudoxus postulated threeconcentric spheres, but for each of the five planets he required four concentricspheres, the planet being regarded as at the end of an equatorial diameter of theinnermost. A final enveloping sphere carried the fixed stars and by its uniformrotation accounted for the apparent daily motion. There were thus twenty-sevenspheres in all.For moon, sun, and planets the first (outermost) sphere produced the apparentdaily movement in the heavens and the second the apparent annual movementalong the zodiac. The crown of Eudoxus' achievement was to show that, if thethird and fourth spheres alone are considered, the path of the planet is like afigure of eight, a curve which he called a hippopede (horse-fetter) and which weshould call a lemniscate described on a sphere. In this way he was able to accountfor the stationary points and retrograde motion of the planets.Few quantitative details are given by Aristotle and Simplicius in their accountof the system, and in this monograph a Finnish scholar, Dr. Erkka Maula, makesit his business to see if such details can be found. His starting point is that it ispermissible to use the numerical data for the construction of the World Soul inPlato's Timaeus as evidence for Eudoxus' system. The Timaeus is undoubtedly

    (e.g. E7Kor6o}: 393a23; oaTr]pia: 398bl5). But such excuses leave most ofthe singularities of vocabulary of the de Mundo untouched.The purpose of my list, however, is not to compose a refutation of Reale'sthesis: its aim is merely to indicate one part of the evidence which any judge ofthat thesis must take into account. Reale's defence of the de Mundo is only halfdone: he has shown, I think, that the tract cannot be expropriated from Aristotleon purely doctrinal grounds; but he has neither stated nor examined the linguisticarguments for expropriation. And those arguments, I venture to predict, willprove difficult to overturn.OrielCollege,Oxford JONATHAN ARNES

    HOMOCENTRIC SPHERESERKKAMAULA:Studies in Eudoxus' Homocentric Spheres. (Commen-tationes Humanarum Litterarum, 50.) Pp. 124. Helsinki: SocietasScientiarum Fennica, 1974. Paper, FM. 25.It is well known that Plato set before the mathematicians of the Academy theproblem of explaining the apparent motion of the heavenly bodies-'saving thephenomena'-on the assumption that all movements were uniform and circular.It is also well known that Eudoxus in a lost work entitled riepi raXchvgave abrilliant solution of this problem by means of homocentric spheres. The moon,sun, and five planets (Venus, Mercury, Mars,Jupiter, Saturn) were all supposedto move round a stationary earth. For the moon Eudoxus postulates three spheres.The moon was supposed to be at an extremity of an equatorial diameter of theinnermost sphere, which moved uniformly about its centre, which was also thecentre of the earth. But the poles of this innermost sphere were not at rest; theywere on the surface of a larger sphere, concentric with the first, which revolvedwith uniform speed about poles of its own. These poles of the second sphere werethemselves on the surface of a third outermost sphere which turned about itsown poles with its own speed. For the sun likewise Eudoxus postulated threeconcentric spheres, but for each of the five planets he required four concentricspheres, the planet being regarded as at the end of an equatorial diameter of theinnermost. A final enveloping sphere carried the fixed stars and by its uniformrotation accounted for the apparent daily motion. There were thus twenty-sevenspheres in all.For moon, sun, and planets the first (outermost) sphere produced the apparentdaily movement in the heavens and the second the apparent annual movementalong the zodiac. The crown of Eudoxus' achievement was to show that, if thethird and fourth spheres alone are considered, the path of the planet is like afigure of eight, a curve which he called a hippopede (horse-fetter) and which weshould call a lemniscate described on a sphere. In this way he was able to accountfor the stationary points and retrograde motion of the planets.Few quantitative details are given by Aristotle and Simplicius in their accountof the system, and in this monograph a Finnish scholar, Dr. Erkka Maula, makesit his business to see if such details can be found. His starting point is that it ispermissible to use the numerical data for the construction of the World Soul inPlato's Timaeus as evidence for Eudoxus' system. The Timaeus is undoubtedly