American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    1/25

    The American Frontier as State of Nature

    By Michael J. Faber, University of Southern Indiana

    and Darla Martin, Indiana University

    Prepared for presentation at the 2009 annual meeting of the

    Midwest Political Science Association

    Abstract: John Locke claims that in the beginning, all the world was America. For Locke,

    America offered a glimpse into a world without government, a state of nature with no clear

    governmental power. Specifically, the western frontier of eighteenth- and early nineteenth-

    century America presents a place without institutionalized government in which individuals were

    essentially free to act independent of formal law and to form consensual societies. This paper

    examines how well the frontier fits Lockes understanding of the state of nature, concluding that,

    while it is not a good fit with Locke, the American frontier offers insights into the philosophical

    foundations of government in America. These insights enable us to better understand and defend

    both the liberal consensus theory of Louis Hartz and the frontier hypothesis of Frederick Jackson

    Turner. Lockes claim encourages us to examine the frontier as a state of nature; doing so should

    give us additional understanding of the philosophical underpinnings of American political

    thought.

    1

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    2/25

    In the beginning, asserts John Locke, all the world was America. Locke finds in North

    America (or at least in the myth of North America, circa 1689) the reality behind his hypothetical

    state of nature. Since Locke never visited America, it is difficult to give much credence to his

    image of it, but his ideas certainly had an influence on American political thought in the ensuing

    centuries. The frontier was in some respects a wild and uncivilized place. It was largely beyond

    the reach of government and laws, making it potentially a prime example of a state of nature

    within relatively recent history. Of course, the analogy is far from perfect; in a true state of

    nature, individuals have never known society, and do not begin with clothing, weapons, technical

    knowledge and skills, et cetera. Nonetheless, by examining the American frontier as a state of

    nature, we can explore American political development from another angle. Theorists who

    describe a state of nature invariably use that description to explain how government emerges out

    of anarchy. By treating the frontier as a state of nature, we can begin an exploration of the

    origins of American government, and explain why the institutions of government developed the

    way that they did. We can further examine American ideology, which was shaped at least in part

    by the frontier experience.

    We aim to begin this exploration, using Frederick Jackson Turners frontier thesis and

    John Lockes state of nature to examine the American frontier. If the frontier resembles a

    Lockean state of nature, as Locke himself seemed to believe, and Turners argument that the

    frontier is the most important factor in explaining American development, then we can expect

    the establishment of Lockean institutions and ideology. If it does not, we can explain the

    departures from Locke that are inherent in the American political system. This analysis, of

    course, must begin with Locke himself, and his articulation of the state of nature.

    2

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    3/25

    The State of Nature

    Locke describes his state of nature as a state of perfect freedom [for individuals] to order

    their actions and dispose of their possessions and persons, as they think fit, within the bounds of

    the law of nature; without asking leave, or depending upon the will of any other man. (Locke

    2003, 101) It is a state in which individuals are autonomous, but not one in which license

    prevails. Individuals, Locke claims, are bound by a law of nature, established by natural reason.

    This law of nature ensures personal security and property rights, and gives to each individual the

    right to punish any transgressions of the law of nature. Property rights, for Locke, are

    established by labor; an individual who puts labor into an object, even labor so simple as picking

    it up off of the ground, establishes a right to property, assuming no prior right exists. According

    to the law of nature, all others must respect these property rights; failure to do so is theft.

    Punishment of crimes against the law of nature may be carried out by any individual, for no one

    is superior or inferior in power in the absence of society and government. Further, punishment is

    at the discretion of the individual exercising this executive power.

    Any individual who violates the law of nature establishes a state of war between himself

    and all of mankind, and therefore may be destroyed as a lion or a tiger, one of those wild savage

    beasts with whom men can have no society nor security. (Locke 2003, 104) Because there will

    always be those who will initiate such a state of war, Lockes state of nature is not an entirely

    peaceful place. There is violence and conflict, always begun with a transgression of the laws of

    nature. Basically, this means that there is always a bad guy and a good guy, always a criminal

    and an enforcer of justice. There are not, or rather should not be, any gray areas. Of course, if

    the original criminal believes that he has been unduly punished, or that his punisher went too far,

    he can of course treat that as a new transgression, and use his own executive power to punish

    3

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    4/25

    crimes against the law of nature. The roles, then, would be reversed. Thus a simple act of theft,

    for example, could turn into a long-running feud between individuals, a constant state of war to

    be ultimately resolved only through the death of one of the parties. Since Locke assumes that

    individuals might recruit others to assist them in the administration of justice, and they might

    similarly recruit others to assist in their defense, this can easily turn into a rather extensive

    violent conflict. Lockes state of nature, then, is perhaps not truly a state of peace, but rather an

    intermittent and perilous peace punctuated by bloodshed and war. He insists that as soon as an

    immediate threat has passed, we leave the state of war and return to the peaceful state of nature,

    but persistent conflict and even misunderstanding can lead to frequent returns to the state of war.

    The issue at stake here is justice, and in a state of nature each individual is the enforcer of justice

    and there is no appeal but to Heaven. Between individuals, the enforcement of justice involves

    a state of war, although Locke emphasizes that it is not the enforcement of justice but the original

    transgression that initiates the war.

    If the American frontier approximates a Lockean state of nature, then, we might expect to

    see signs of natural law, broad agreements on what constitutes proper behavior and a broad

    respect for freedom and equality. Where this is absent, we should find that the absence is the

    exception, tied to violence and criminal behavior. If such behavior is rampant, then it becomes

    difficult to distinguish between those breaking the natural law and those merely enforcing it; in

    such a case, we might better conclude that Lockes state of nature does not fit, or at least that

    Locke was too sanguine in his assessment of human nature. Broadly speaking, we are looking

    for three things in assessing the fit of Lockes theory: attitudes towards property rights, the extent

    of mutual voluntary cooperation, and the presence and causes of violence. If property rights or

    cooperation are generally absent, or if violence is a regular part of life rather than an intermittent

    4

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    5/25

    state of war, then we should be inclined to reject Lockes picture in evaluating the American

    frontier.

    Lockes state of nature is of course not the only theory. I have begun with Locke because

    he is so often associated with the American founding. Whether his influence is in fact the

    primary influence on the founders ideology is not critical here1; if the American frontier

    resembles a Lockean state of nature, it is immaterial whether his writings influenced American

    ideology because his theory of government should apply anyway in such a case. The founders,

    though, also drew quite consciously from Montesquieu, who is not generally considered a state

    of nature social contract theorist. Nonetheless, Montesquieu describes a pre-societal state of

    humanity. Men in nature, he claims, would assume themselves weak and impotent, and would

    fear all others. In this state every man, instead of being sensible of his equality, would fancy

    himself inferior. There would, therefore, be no danger of their attacking one another; peace

    would be the first law of nature. (Montesquieu 1949 v.1, 4) This first law, peace, is followed up

    with three other laws: the pursuit of nourishment, the attraction between men and women, and

    the tendency to form society. Thus humanity quickly leaves the state of nature for a state of

    society. Clearly there were associations and interactions on the American frontier, so it cannot

    fit Montesquieus vision of nature, but it may well resemble the kind of society which

    Montesquieu claims will first arise spontaneously from nature. It is interesting to note

    Montesquieus claim that Each particular society begins to feel its strength, whence arises a

    state of war between different nations. (Montesquieu 1949 v.1, 5) At first glance, the American

    frontier can be understood as warring societies of settlers and natives. Looking back, we see

    voluntary societies of settlers that are more or less spontaneous attempting to carve out a life for

    1See Bailyn 1992 for a discussion of other influences on the founders. Gordon Wood makes a similar argument in

    his Creation of the American Republic. The debate over the influence of liberal and republican ideals on the

    American founding is an extensive one, and only tangentially related to this paper.

    5

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    6/25

    themselves. We also see tribes and nations of natives essentially doing the same. Exploring the

    hostile relationship between the two might indeed suggest that this area and time period fits

    better with Montesquieus early society than Lockes state of nature. The key difference

    between Montesquieus early societies and Lockes state of nature is that in the former the

    individuals recognize the enduring presence of society, while in the later it is merely an

    arrangement of convenience. In a state of nature, individuals have no obligation to others, moral

    or legal. They are obliged to follow and uphold the law of nature, but that obligation does not

    specifically extend to other individuals. A mere awareness of societys existence carries with it

    at least a legal, if not moral, obligation to ones fellow men. Thus there is a distinction to be

    drawn here; in the context of this work, we must ask whether individuals on the frontier, whether

    settler or native, felt a clear obligation to their fellows, or whether interaction was a matter of

    convenience and mutual advantage only.

    Of course, this presupposes some element of cooperation and trust. We must remember

    not to make this assumption without careful consideration; Thomas Hobbes famously claimed

    that no such trust could possibly exist in the absence of society and civil laws. The influence of

    Hobbes on the founders is a matter of some dispute, but his state of nature is perhaps even more

    famous than that of Locke. His state of nature is simply a state of war; he sums it up rather

    succinctly, and my words cannot add much to his:

    In such condition there is no place for industry, because the fruit thereof is uncertain: andconsequently no culture of the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities that may beimported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving and removing such things as

    require much force; no knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time; no arts; no letters;no society; and which is worst of all, continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life ofman, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short. (Hobbes 1996, 84)

    This vision of the state of nature, if it applies here, would make the American frontier a violent,

    savage, and dangerous place; on the surface, it was clearly all of these. There is no confusion

    between Lockes relatively peaceful pre-societal cooperation and Hobbes constant war of all

    6

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    7/25

    against all. This is clearly a different vision, and given the brutality that occurred in the early

    American West, we must consider Hobbes in this context. If the frontier is truly a lawless place,

    with no clear reason and no stable peace, no societies and little to no cooperation, then we might

    conclude that it best approximates a Hobbesian state of nature.

    Locke, Montesquieu, and Hobbes give us a useful starting point for assessing the

    American frontier as a state of nature. The condition of the western frontier certainly has an

    impact on the formation of political societies in that region, and it may have a broader impact on

    the development of American political thought and American democracy. This is the argument

    made famous by Frederick Jackson Turner in the late nineteenth century, and it is an argument

    worth revisiting in the context of this analysis.

    Turner and the American Frontier

    Turner famously argued that the American frontier is the most significant explanatory

    factor in American history and development. This claim rests on a particular vision of the

    frontier. A closer look at his thesis and his understanding of the frontier brings us a step closer to

    assessing whether the American frontier resembles a state of nature, and if so, which one.

    In the opening paragraph of his famous essay, The Significance of the Frontier in

    American History, Turner sums up his frontier thesis succinctly: The existence of an area of

    free land, its continuous recession, and the advance of American settlement westward, explain

    American development. (Turner 1966, 199) This is perhaps overstating his case, but a bit of

    exaggeration does not hurt the overall theory, which is an important one. The possibility for

    westward expansion in the United States was certainly a significant factor in American political

    7

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    8/25

    development; the notion of Manifest Destiny was a driving force in public policy for much of the

    nineteenth century.

    The frontier, as Turner envisions it, is not a particular geographic line at a particular point

    in time, but a region that moved over time. Essentially, the frontier is a moving target. As

    wilderness communities grew, they became more established and permanent, and began to

    resemble older societies further east. This does not mean that the frontier ceased to exist, only

    that it moved further west.

    The wilderness disappears, the West proper passes on to a new frontier, and in the former area,a new society has emerged from its contact with the backwoods. Gradually this society loses itsprimitive conditions, and assimilates itself to the type of the older social conditions of the East; but

    it bears within it enduring and distinguishing survivals of its frontier experience. (Turner 1896,289)

    The frontier in the 1750s looks very different from that of the 1780s, the 1820s, or the 1850s.

    But throughout its early development, America always had a frontier, room for expansion and

    new settlement; this westward-moving region is theAmerican frontier that Turner discusses, in

    the form of many successive frontiers over time. Each successive frontier involved similar

    problems with different details, and drew similar individuals with different occupations and

    aspirations. The exploitation of the beasts took hunter and trader to the west, the exploitation of

    the grasses took the rancher west, and the exploitation of the virgin soil of the river valleys and

    prairies attracted the farmer. (Turner 1966, 213) Each subsequent migration had different

    features, but, for Turner, all represented the frontier, and therefore the meaning of America. We

    are concerned here with the first wave of frontier settlers; by the time ranchers and farmers

    reached the frontier, there was some semblance of society in place, and thus clearly not a state of

    nature in the Lockean sense. Turner further describes this advance line of the frontier.

    Thus American development has exhibited not merely advance along a single line, but a return toprimitive conditions on a continually advancing frontier line, and a new development for that area.

    American social development has been continually beginning over again on the frontier. Thisperennial rebirth, this fluidity of American life, this expansion westward with its new opportunities,

    8

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    9/25

    its continuous touch with the simplicity of primitive society, furnish the forces dominatingAmerican character. In this advance, the frontier is the outer edge of the wavethe meetingpoint between savagery and civilization. (Turner 1966, 200)

    It is essentially Turners claim that the frontier involved a return to primitive conditions that

    we are examining in this paper. If the primitive conditions on the frontier resemble Lockes

    state of nature, then we might logically conclude that American social development has

    proceeded along more or less Lockean lines.

    The frontier, of course, was not merely a geographical location. It was part of the

    American mindset, deeply ingrained in our collective national psyche. The psychological

    frontier was in many ways an entirely separate matter from the geographic frontier. Billington

    explains the relationship between the two:

    Certainly modern scholarship has proved that two frontiers have traditionally influencedAmerican thought, and that they bore little relationship to each other. One was the actual frontier,where sweating pioneer farmers braved the greed of their fellow men and the savagery of natureto eke out an existence. The other was an imaginary frontier which persisted in the minds of

    Americans and some Europeans. From the eighteenth century on this image of the Westinfluenced statesmen, fired the imagination of authors, and helped shape the attitude of thepeople toward their own land as well as toward other nations of the world. (Billington 1965, 33-34)

    In one sense, we are concerned here only with the actual historic frontier, and not this

    psychological one. In another sense, though, the psychological frontier is equally important, if

    not more so. If the westward pioneers saw themselves in an essentially Lockean state of nature,

    they would be likely to create limited institutions, with power kept firmly in the hands of the

    people. If they saw themselves in a Hobbesian wilderness, they likely would have submitted to

    whomever could promise their safety. Such institutions would likely develop regardless of the

    actual circumstances of the frontier. Further, for those Americans not pushing westward,

    perceptions of westward expansion may well influence visions of politics. Those who saw a

    savage frontier might be more inclined to call for strong government intervention, especially to

    pacify or defeat the natives. Those who had a more Lockean vision would be more inclined to

    9

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    10/25

    criticize harsh measures against the Indians as unwarranted and illegitimate. Clearly, both

    perceptions persisted at various times in and in various groups within society. For this analysis,

    we are more concerned with the frontier mentality, insofar as such a generalization exists.

    If Turners thesis is basically right, then studying the frontier is not merely helpful in

    understanding American history; it is essential. Here, we claim that the frontier offers us insights

    into the nature and theory of government in the United States. The ramifications of Turners

    frontier thesis are explained well by Billington:

    If the United States is to endure in the shrinking world of the twentieth century it must recognizethat its institutions have been shaped by a unique past and that its ideals have been tailored bytraditions unknown among peoples of the newly emerged nations. (Billington 1965, 43-44)

    The frontier is part of that unique past; it is not the only aspect, but it is perhaps the most

    important. This paper acknowledges the importance of the frontier in understanding American

    politics and history, and aims to better understand the ramifications of the frontier as both

    historical and theoretical place.

    John Locke, Louis Hartz, and American Liberalism

    Turners argument gives us no reason to assume that John Locke is the most relevant

    state of nature theorist here, or even to apply social contract theory at all. Another area of

    American historical literature, headlined by Louis Hartz in his famousLiberal Tradition in

    America, suggests the importance of Locke. The argument of Hartz spawned a substantial

    reaction as well, resulting in extensive study of the republican aspects of the American founding

    by Bailyn, Wood, Pocock, and others. This paper can be viewed as essentially a test of Hartzs

    theory in one key aspect of American history, but this first requires another look at Hartzs

    theory.

    10

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    11/25

    Hartz liberal tradition is a sort of Lockean liberalism, with a few variations on that

    central theme. This dominant liberalism results from the absence of feudal institutions in

    America; without feudalism to argue against, other traditions have been unable to take root.

    American liberalism, however, is a unique tradition, built on pragmatism more than theory.

    There has never been a liberal movement or a real liberal party in America: we have only

    had the American Way of Life, a nationalist articulation of Locke which usually does not know

    that Locke himself is involved. (Hartz 1955, 11) Locke is clearly the central figure here.

    [T]he record of American political thought is a veritable jig-saw puzzle of theoretical confusion.But throughout it all the liberal temper of American theory is vividly apparent. Locke dominates

    American political thought, as no thinker anywhere dominates the political thought of a nation. He

    is a massive national clich. (Hartz 1955, 140)

    American liberalism occurs on a subconscious level, but it is ever-present. This consensus

    presents a danger of unanimity which squelches that which would challenge it; this is the danger

    of public opinion against which Tocqueville warned. The American tradition stemmed from its

    unique situation and revolution. America did not join Europe in its intellectual or political

    traditions, but carved out its own way. It rejected the emphasis on community for a sort of

    individualistic uniformity which took its place. This unanimity is based on common assumptions

    about life and humanity which have never been adequately challenged in American life.

    It is not difficult to claim, with Hartz, that much if not all of American thought relies on

    some level on John Locke; he does not exaggerate in referring to Locke as a massive national

    clich. A close reading of the Declaration of Independence side by side with Lockes second

    treatise should leave little doubt on this score, unless one (foolishly, it would seem) denies the

    seminal importance of the Declaration in American thought. This is not the place for such an

    examination, but Hartz is clearly defensible here. Locke is of central importance in the ideas on

    which this nation was founded. But this does not tell us which parts of Locke we are using,

    11

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    12/25

    beyond those which have been borrowed for the Declaration of Independence. Hartz gives us

    some indication of what was taken. He finds in Locke two main themes: an implicit defense of

    the state, and an explicit limitation on the state. Lockes concept of free individuals in nature

    forming a state by mutual consent is a remarkable defense of the state and its power to

    legitimately coerce individuals. This social norm of free individuals, because of the lack of

    feudal institutions in America, appeared less a norm to be adopted than a simple statement of

    fact, as Hartz explains in his usual lyrical prose.

    History was on a lark, out to tease men, not by shattering their dreams, but by fulfilling them witha sort of satiric accuracy. In America one not only found a society sufficiently fluid to give a touchof meaning to the individualist norms of Locke, but one also found letter-prefect replicas of the

    very images he used. There was a frontier that was a veritable state of nature. There wereagreements, such as the Mayflower Compact, that were veritable social contracts. There werenew communities springing up in vacuis locis, clear evidence that men were using their Lockeanright of emigration. (Hartz 1955, 60-61)

    Hartz thus suggests that the early American frontier was in fact a Lockean state of nature. From

    this starting point, though, the Americans proceeded only to limit the state, without any sense of

    its proper power. Thus they missed half of Lockes argument; the state of early American

    society, Hartz claims, resulted in a partial reading of Locke, missing much of his intent. Hartz

    maintains that Locke can only be properly understood in terms of Filmer and feudalism; in their

    absence he is read in a way that he could neither have foreseen nor intended. It is interesting that

    Hartz himself offers no great summary or analysis of Lockes work; as he claims Americans tend

    to do, he appears to take Locke for granted.

    Hartz never bothers with a full account of Lockes philosophy; he only stops to remind us briefly,from time to time, of some element, as if he merely needs to jog our memory on the subject.

    Hartz felt so comfortable that he already shared an account of Locke with his readers that he sawno need to repeat it. (Dienstag 1996, 498-499)

    Thus Hartz presents a stylized and limited Locke, perhaps oversimplified. His reading of Locke

    is certainly a very basic one, ignoring many of the nuances present in the Two Treatises. Marvin

    12

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    13/25

    Meyers makes this claim in critiquing Hartz; Locke, he says, serves as a convenient abstraction

    for Hartzs theory.

    The liberal formula is largely independent of the complex structure of John Lockes reasoning.Locke connotes the ethos of a nation born equal: the spirit of atomistic social freedom, of

    bourgeois enterprise, and laissez faire. Professor Hartzs Locke, in brief, comes very close toexpressing what Tocqueville called individualism: that mature and calm feeling, nurtured byequality of condition, leading each man to seek his own material well-being with slight regard forfellows or community, ancestors or posterity, tradition or authority. (Meyers 1963, 263)

    This Locke which Hartz uses, Meyers claims, has little connection with John Locke, but is

    rather a homegrown ideology that is distinctively American, with little of the Old World in it.

    By using an American version of Locke, if this interpretation can be so called, Hartz denotes

    clearly the difference between America and Europe, which is a useful distinction in itself. By

    oversimplifying Locke, however, Hartz makes his philosophy less useful for saying anything

    meaningful about American politics.

    All of this implies that the American frontier may not in fact be a state of nature as Locke

    describes, but rather an Americanized version related to this simplified Lockean theory. This

    suggests three things. First, if, as Hartz claims, the frontier essentially follows Lockes state of

    nature, but the resulting society does not resemble that described by Locke, then either Lockes

    theory itself is flawed or American government is illegitimate by that theory. Either of these

    would, of course, be huge and controversial claims. Second, if the frontier departs from Lockes

    account in important ways, we may be able to better explain Hartzs contention that we have

    veered away from Lockes full theory. Third, if the frontier does not resemble Locke, then we

    must explain why American society still has Lockean elements, or we must diminish or dismiss

    the importance of Locke on American society. As we will see, the frontier does resemble

    Lockes, but not closely. This different version of a state of nature, if we can even properly call

    it that, leads to society strikingly different from that described by Locke.

    13

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    14/25

    Turner would not necessarily disagree with Hartzs thesis, especially his claim that

    America must be understood in the context of Europe. Our destiny is interwoven with theirs,

    he observes, asking how shall we understand American history without understanding European

    history? (Turner 1994a, 27) American history and politics is perhaps best understood as an

    offshoot of European ideas, although these ideas have certainly been adapted to a different

    situation. This brings us, of course, back to Turners claim that the American frontier is a

    defining characteristic of American political development. What is different between America

    and Europe, for Hartz, is the absence of feudalism. What is different between the two for Turner

    is the presence of the frontier. The two are related. The early frontier provided ample space for

    expansion, and allowed for individuals to find their own place and purpose. They were not

    bound to land owned by others because there was land to be claimed for themselves. Feudalism

    relies on limited ownership of land and limited geographic mobility; neither was the case in early

    America. Thus Turners thesis is compatible with that of Hartz. Whether the two can be

    combined, though, requires a close look at the American frontier itself.

    Life, Liberty, and Property on the American Frontier

    Turner himself makes a case for the frontier as a state of nature, perhaps of Hobbesian

    characteristics. Remote from the opportunity for systematic education, substituting a log hut in

    the forest-clearing for the social comforts of the town, he suffered hardships and privations, and

    reverted in many ways to primitive conditions of life. (Turner 1896, 291) He describes it as

    the meeting point between savagery and civilization, suggesting that society has basically been

    left behind. Patrick Griffin argues more directly for the frontier to be understood as a state of

    nature. He describes efforts by the British government to prevent settlers from moving west.

    14

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    15/25

    Such efforts proved to be futile, as many British subjects in the New World set out to find new

    areas to settle.

    When they headed west, illegal settlers entered a no-mans-land, a region that except for a fewpockets could not by definition contain subjects. Subjects entering such lands surrendered their

    rights. Since they entered a region with no government, they were regressing to the state ofnature. (Griffin 2007, 44)

    After the revolution, the new American government made less effort to restrict westward

    migration, but the status of the frontier was otherwise unchanged. American settlers moving

    west did not forfeit their rights, but they basically left the privileges and protections of

    citizenship behind.

    This, of course, suggests that the settlers entered something akin to a state of nature,

    though the relatively nearby presence of society means that it is not a perfect state of nature as

    understood by the social contract theorists. Still, it may be close enough for the purposes of

    those theories. To assess whether the American frontier can be understood as a Lockian state of

    nature, as we noted above, we need to look for three things: attitudes towards property rights, the

    presence of voluntary cooperation, and the nature of violence.

    The West was a realm beyond law. There were no courts to evict, no laws to protect

    the interests of the wealthy, no speculative grants to safeguard. In short, the world beyond the

    line lay beyond regulation. (Griffin 2007, 60) As such, property rights were not safeguarded by

    any civil laws, nor were they protected by any formal authority. For Hobbes, this situation

    suggests that property rights do not exist, that such an idea is incoherent in the absence of

    government. It is clear, however, that the settlers on the frontier believed they had a right to the

    land on which they settled. In fact, the draw of the western frontier was the presence of

    essentially free land. Individuals who were not pleased with their fortunes in society often set

    out to lay claim to western land and make a living off of it. In the absence of the concept of

    15

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    16/25

    property, this plan makes no sense. One might object, of course, that the frontiersmen were

    merely transplanting the idea of property from society into the wilderness, and that this property

    assumption does not support a Lockean interpretation of the frontier, or discredit a Hobbesian

    interpretation. We should note, however, that the settlers distinctly brought or developed the

    notion that property is established through labor; this idea contributed to conflicts with Indians,

    who did not take the same view towards property, or at least not towards land. The settlers

    cleared and developed land that the natives saw as essentially their territory. The justification

    here was that if the Indians were not doing anything with the land, meaning they had not

    improved it or labored on it in any way, then it was free land for the taking. This fits well with

    Lockes description of natural property rights; Locke in fact would likely endorse that rationale

    for Europeans settling on Indian lands.

    Once a settler could establish his property, he began to build a new life, which was often

    a solitary one. This does not, however, suggest an absence of cooperation and joint action on the

    frontier. The nature of the west clearly led to a certain amount of individualism, but

    frontiersmen were generally not hermits. Nonetheless, this situation led to a certain amount of

    discomfort and distrust with society, and especially government.

    As has been indicated, the frontier is productive of individualism. Complex society is precipitatedby the wilderness into a kind of primitive organization based on the family. The tendency is anti-social. It produces antipathy to control, and particularly to any direct control. The tax-gatherer isviewed as a representative of oppression. (Turner 1966, 221)

    This hostility to authority suggests the kind of individualism found in Locke, as well as an

    absence of the fear that Hobbes describes. If the frontiersmen were living in constant fear, they

    would have been less suspicious and more respectful of any governmental authority that could

    16

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    17/25

    protect them.2 Rather than turn to government for protection, settlers turned to government

    when it furthered their interests. Billington notes that frontier co-operation was entirely

    reconcilable with individualism. The pioneer was dependent on the social group and was not in

    the least reluctant to solicit aid from his government when his own betterment was involved.

    (Billington 1965, 28) This notion of government as a tool for furthering individual interests

    rather than primarily an instrument of protection, fits much better with Locke than Hobbes.

    Based on Turners reading of the frontier, then, it does not appear a truly Hobbesian state of

    nature.

    Griffin disagrees with this assessment, suggesting that the frontier does resemble the state

    of nature described by Hobbes (one need only read the title of his book,American Leviathan, to

    pick up the influence of Hobbes in his analysis), but his description of a state of nature belies the

    error in this claim. He argues that the European settlers on the frontier had a persistent us

    versus them mentality, leading to a sense of community with other whites and an ingrained

    hostility towards the natives. He claims that this twinned dynamic of the demonization of

    others and the valorization of the people epitomized relations on frontiers from time to time

    during periods of profound tension and violence. (Griffin 2007, 13) Certainly the violence

    Griffin describes fits into the theory of Hobbes, but the sense of being on the same team as

    others, which clearly existed among both settlers and natives, suggests that the situation was not

    a war of all against all, but a war of us against them.

    There was substantial cooperation on the American frontier. On the Indian side,

    extended families and tribes worked together for mutual benefit; in fact, it might be more

    reasonable to treat the natives as individuals in society rather than outside of it. As for the

    2Of course, one could argue that they lived in fear of both nature and authority. I do not engage that argument here,

    because in such a case Hobbes picture of a state of nature is inaccurate anyway since he claims that people in a state

    of nature will willingly submit to strong authority.

    17

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    18/25

    European settlers, there is more isolation but the isolation is not total. Small communities sprang

    up throughout the frontier as settlers found life easier where they could share the labor with

    others. The cooperation of settlers looked much as Locke describes it theoretically; these were

    voluntary associations brought on by mutual benefit and compatible world view. Cooperation

    was far less common between the natives and the settlers, but the fact that anyone was working

    together implies that Hobbes was at least too extreme, if not outright wrong, when his theory is

    applied to the frontier.

    Because of the persistent image of frontier violence, though, it is hard to exorcise the

    specter of Hobbes from this discussion. The Hobbesian nature of the frontier, however, is

    probably overstated, perhaps to the point of being little more than mythology. Bellesiles

    critiques popular portrayals of the Old West, suggesting that they have influenced violence in

    modern society. Nonstop Indian warfare and gunfights in the streets of every western town

    inured Americans to the necessity of violence. From this Hobbesian heritage of each against all

    emerged the modern American acceptance of widespread personal brutality. (Bellesiles 2000,

    285) Of course, he argues, this warfare did not really happen, at least not as often as most people

    believe. We tend to see the frontier as a place right out ofLeviathan, but that does not square

    with reality. Then again, perhaps this Hobbesian vision has an impact on how American politics

    develops; the image may have had more influence than the reality. As Bellesiles himself

    laments, In this contest between the postmodern dialectic of image versus reality, image usually

    wins. It is difficult for the serious scholar to compete with the media's power to form popular

    views of reality through visual impact. (Bellesiles 2000, 284) This perception of violence was a

    significant part of the psychological frontier, and as such it likely had an impact on American

    18

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    19/25

    political development. But it does not square with the level of cooperation and development on

    the physical frontier.

    The level of violence on the frontier is certainly far beyond the peace that Montesquieu

    anticipates, but it is not necessarily beyond Lockes notion of a state of war. Clearly, where

    there was no influence of civil law, peaceful desires did not generally prevail, but it does not

    appear that there was truly a Hobbesian war of all against all, either. To argue that the violence

    that did exist on the frontier follows Lockes concept of natural law, though we need to look

    beyond the level of violence and consider motives. Unfortunately for a Lockean analysis, much

    of the frontier violence of settlers against Indians, or Indians against settlers, was essentially

    senseless violence. It is difficult to assess how much, if any, of the warfare can be attributed to

    one side redressing grievances; since the grievances were real andimagined, general and

    specific, we cannot fairly conclude that either settlers or natives were merely enforcing the law

    of nature. It seems unlikely that they even agreed on what that law of nature contained,

    especially given their possibly irreconcilable differences concerning property rights.

    Griffin offers us some insights into the motives on both sides of the conflict. In both

    cases, we can see some Lockean motives (though certainly not attributable to Lockean influence,

    at least not on the native side) and hints of a law of nature. But rather than a clear picture of

    what constitutes a violation of natural law, we instead see a jumbled cycle of escalating violence

    and unjustified mayhem rather than just recompense and fair punishment.

    Although settlers crossing the line were heading into land that belonged to Indians, few had

    moral reservations about doing so. In fact, many harbored or condoned a violent hatred ofIndians. Frontier people condoned Indian slaughter because of what Indians had done.Settlers conceded that they were partly demented by their own surmisesthat is, theirperceptions of reality in a brutal worldbut asserted that Indian hatred stemmed from their latesufferings under Savage Cruelty. Settlers moving west of the line, in the words of ThomasCresap, despaired of being Massicread by a Barberous and Inhuman Enemy and beingButchered without Immediate Relief and Assistance. (Griffin 2007, 62)

    19

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    20/25

    From the native point of view, the picture was similar; they, too, believed they had been

    wronged, and were entitled to take action, even violent action, in response.

    In such circumstances, Indians had little choice but to defend their lives, liberty, and property. Inparticular, younger men who saw their hunting ground taken over, their relations slaughtered, and

    posts and settlements arising in their lands would not be restrained. They attacked traders, killedwhat they called Virginiansthe catch-all term for land-hungry whites entering the country thatbelonged to themwho made their way down the Ohio River, and savaged white hunters.(Griffin 2007, 69)

    Thus what we see is a cycle of violence based on perceived general wrongs, but not specific acts.

    Individuals were not being punished for their own actions, as Locke expects in a state of nature;

    instead, entire groups, tribes, settlements were being attacked for a general history of violence

    not necessarily attributed to the particular victims of vengeance. Even among whites, the notion

    of revenge was often more prominent than any more abstract idea of justice, as Turner explains.

    The Westerner defended himself and resented governmental restrictions. The duel and theblood-feud found congenial soil in Kentucky and Tennessee. The idea of the personality of lawwas often dominant over the organized machinery of justice. That method was best which wasmost direct and effective. The backwoodsman was intolerant of men who split hairs, or scrupledover the method of reaching the right. In a word, the unchecked development of the individualwas the significant product of this frontier democracy. (Turner 1994b, 86-87)

    Thus vigilante justice and feuds took precedence over any law, civil or natural. Individuals did

    not so much take the law into their own hands as decide who deserved punishment for perceived

    insults and injuries. This is at best a perversion of Lockes theory; at worst it is virtually a

    refutation. At least under these circumstances, a Lockean view of justice did not prevail on the

    American frontier.

    Conclusion

    If the frontier ever did resemble a state of nature, it certainly did not stay as such.

    Pioneers and frontiersmen formed small communities, and eventually societies and even what we

    might call states. These small fledgling states often had fully functional economies and political

    institutions to watch over economic and social matters. The economies and governments were

    20

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    21/25

    adapted to the conditions of the frontier. Not only was the economy of every frontier village

    shaped to supply the needs of the rural area surrounding it, but in each the welfare of the

    community was protected by tight controls over such public businesses as grist-milling or retail

    selling. (Billington 1965, 18-19) Such societies were highly democratic, relying on

    participation and popular input and electing officials, often for very short terms of office. As

    Turner puts it, From the beginning of the settlement of America, the frontier regions have

    exercised a steady influence toward democracy. (Turner 1994b, 81) Local institutions were

    established, relying on representation, and closely and jealously guarded by the people. These

    participatory institutions were made necessary because a vast flow of problems forced a high

    degree of participation in the making of decisions, an acute pitch of political awareness among

    the settlers. (Elkins and McKitrick 1954, 339) Thus democratic institutions were a response to

    practical problems facing the community; to solve these problems communities would join

    together in a democratic fashion, creating democracy as it was needed. Turners frequent claim

    that American democracy was born on the frontier has been assailed by critics claiming that the

    settlers brought democracy with them from the East and from Europe; they did not create it. But

    this involves a misunderstanding of Turner. Billington notes that Turner never makes the claim

    that democracy was born on the American frontier. OnlyAmericandemocracy was born there, a

    version of democracy different from that which existed in the Old World. (Billington 1965, 21)

    It is this democracy and its origins with which we are concerned. We do not aim to offer an

    extensive analysis of democracy as it is practiced everywhere, but only that version that was

    essentially homegrown. And American democracy was something unique to the New World;

    Tocqueville, Bryce, and others have articulated the uniqueness of this particular brand of popular

    21

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    22/25

    rule. A special kind of democracy developed in the United States, and its development, as

    Turner understood, relied heavily on the role of the American frontier in political and social life.

    Understanding this particular version of American democracy requires understanding its

    origins in the American frontier. This necessitates an exploration of frontier conditions in

    theoretical perspective, and this paper is only the beginning of that task. From our analysis, the

    American frontier does not appear to be a Lockean or Hobbesian state of nature, but something

    else entirely. Understanding the state of nature as it existed along the frontier, though, is

    essential to understanding the development of frontier democracy. In concluding that the

    American frontier was not a Lockean state of nature, we do not aim to deny the importance of

    the frontier or of Locke in American political development. We are sympathetic to both Turners

    frontier thesis and Hartzs liberal consensus. But understanding American history and

    development requires more nuance. The frontier was not entirely a lawless place, nor was it

    governed by a consensual law of nature. It was violent but not without cooperation and

    friendliness. It lacked the structure of European or coastal American society, but it was not

    without some civic and legal arrangements that shaped the development of frontier societies.

    Such societies were not spontaneous as we might see from a state of nature, Lockean or

    otherwise; they were offshoots of existing arrangements. Western settlers had placed some

    distance between themselves and centers of political power, but they did not leave society and

    civilization entirely behind.

    The concept of the frontier is still an important one in American life. Geographical

    expansion seems to have come to a halt, but the idea still resonates. We can see the frontier

    notion in the push for human space travel. McLure (2000) finds the frontier ethos in the

    22

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    23/25

    expansion of technology. Similar arguments can be made for most innovations; the frontier is

    thoroughly ingrained in the American psyche.

    23

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    24/25

    References

    Bailyn, Bernard. 1992. The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    Bellesiles, Michael A. 2000. Guns Dont Kill, Movies Kill: The Medias Promotion ofFrontier Violence. The Western Historical Quarterly31(3): 284-.

    Billington, Ray Allen. 1965. The American Frontier. Washington, D.C.: The AmericanHistorical Association.

    Bryce, James. 1995. The American Commonwealth, two volumes. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Dienstag, Joshua. 1996. Serving God and Mammon: The Lockean Sympathy in Early

    American Political Thought. American Political Science Review90(3): 497-511.

    Elkins, Stanley and Eric McKitrick. 1954. A Meaning for Turners Frontier: Part I: Democracyin the Old Northwest. Political Science Quarterly69(3): 321-353.

    Faragher, John Mack. 1994. Rereading Frederick Jackson Turner. New York: Henry Holt and

    Company.

    Griffin, Patrick. 2007. American Leviathan: Empire, Nation, and Revolutionary Frontier. New

    York: Hill and Wang.

    Hartz, Louis. 1955. The Liberal Tradition in America. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Hobbes, Thomas. 1996. Leviathan. Edited by J.C.A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Locke, John. 2003. Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. Edited

    by Ian Shapiro. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    McLure, Helen. 2000. The Wild, Wild Web: The Mythic American West and the Electronic

    Frontier. The Western Historical Quarterly31(4): 457-476.

    Meyers, Marvin. 1963. Louis Hartz, the Liberal Tradition in America: An Appraisal.Comparative Studies in Society and History5(3): 261-268.

    Montesquieu, Charles Secondat Baron de. 1949. The Spirit of the Laws. Translated by Thomas

    Nugent. New York: Hafner Press.

    Tocqueville, Alexis de. 2000. Democracy in America, trans. Harvey Mansfield and Delba

    Winthrop. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Turner, Frederick Jackson. 1896. The Problem of the West. Atlantic Monthly77: 289-297.

    24

  • 8/12/2019 American Frontier as State of Nature_APSA

    25/25

    Turner, Frederick Jackson. 1966 (1893). The Significance of the Frontier in American History.

    Ann Arbor, MI: University Microfilms.

    Turner, Frederick Jackson. 1994a (1891). The Significance of History. In John Mack

    Faragher,Rereading Frederick Jackson Turner. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Turner, Frederick Jackson. 1994b (1903). Contributions of the West to American Democracy.

    In John Mack Faragher,Rereading Frederick Jackson Turner. New York: Henry Holt and

    Company.

    Wood, Gordon. 1972. The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787. New York: W. W.

    Norton and Company.