1.3castro Gomez

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    1/17

    Santiago Castro-Gomez, Adriana Johnson

    Nepantla: Views from South, Volume 1, Issue 3, 2000, pp. 503-518 (Article)

    For additional information about this article

    Access provided by Duke University Libraries (14 Oct 2014 12:13 GMT)

    http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/nep/summary/v001/1.3castro-gomez.html

    http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/nep/summary/v001/1.3castro-gomez.htmlhttp://muse.jhu.edu/journals/nep/summary/v001/1.3castro-gomez.html
  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    2/17

    Traditional and Critical

    Theories of Culture

    Santiago Castro-Gmez

    In his renowned 1937 programmatic

    article Traditionelle and Kritische Theorie [Traditional and critical the-ory], Max Horkheimer (1974 [1937], 223-71) established a distinction be-

    tween two conceptions of theory. The first of them refers to a series of

    propositions whose validity lies in its correspondence with an object already

    constituted prior to the act of representation. This radical separation be-

    tween subject and object of knowledge converts theory into a pure activity

    of thought, and the theorist into a disinterested spectator who is limited to

    describing the world as it is. Such an idea of theory, which considers the

    object of study to be a series of facticities and the subject to be the passiveelement of an act of knowing, is identified by Horkheimer as traditional.

    In opposition to this theory, he describes a second model that he designates

    critical theory. In contrast to traditional theory, critical theory considers

    that both science and the reality it studies are the product of a social praxis,

    which means that the subject and object of knowledge find themselves so-

    cially performed. The object is not simply there, deposited before us and

    waiting to be apprehended, nor is the subject merely the notary of reality.

    Both subject and object are the result of complex social processes. The fun-damental task of critical theory is therefore to reflect upon the structures

    from which both social reality as well as the theories that seek to account

    for it are constructedincluding, of course, critical theory itself.

    Even when Horkheimers project was conceived as a tool in the

    struggle against the positivism of his time, it could, it seems to me, be very

    useful for drawing up a map of modern theories on culture. I will argue

    that such theories can be divided into two basic groups: Those that perceive

    N e p a n t l a : V i e w s f r o m S o u t h 1.3

    Copyright 2000 by Duke University Press

    503

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    3/17

    504

    Nepantla

    culture as natural facticity, that is, that approach their object as if it were

    rooted in human nature; and those that, on the contrary, consider culture

    to be a realm structured by praxis, that is, a social construction of which

    theoretical practice itself is a part. Following Horkheimer, I will call the first

    group the traditional theory of culture and the second the critical theory

    of culture. In what follows, I will identify some characteristic elements of

    traditional theory and then contrast these with the concept of geoculture

    developed by postcolonial theories. With this I propose to present postcolo-

    nialism as a critical theory of culture in times of globalization or, parodying

    Fredric Jamesons phrase, as a cultural critique of late capitalism.

    The Metaphysics of the Subject and the Traditional

    Concept of Culture

    Any consideration of the traditional theory of culture should begin with the

    following epistemological reflection: Culture becomes the object of knowl-

    edge only when man constitutes himself as a subject of history. The concepts

    of culture, history, subject, and man refer to the same genealogi-

    cal root, which, chronologically speaking, emerged and consolidated itself

    between the sixteenth and nineteenth centuries. Before this era, something

    like culture was not thinkable, simply because the episteme that made

    the concepts formation possible had not yet been configured. If we limit

    ourselves solely to the types of theories arisen in the West, we will see that

    neither in Greece nor Rome, nor in the Christian Middle Ages, was a the-

    ory of culture possible in its traditional, much less critical, sense. This was

    due to the fact that morals, politics, and knowledge were viewed as simple

    prolongations of cosmological laws, that is, as a set of natural institutions

    ordered around the consummation of a cosmologically predetermined end

    (telos).

    For Aristotle, truth, goodness, and justice are impossible without

    considering the basic principles which govern the cosmos, because the

    purpose of science, legislation, and morals is to manifest being insofar as

    being, that is, the natural order such as itisand not as itappears. For Aris-

    totle, the reflection on the social life of men does not pertain to theoretical

    sciences, which address only the basic principles of things, but to a type of

    minor and less dignified knowledge designated practical sciences. First

    philosophy, or metaphysics, occupies the pinnacle of the entire gamut ofknowledges, as its task is to establish the most universal notions. The object

    of metaphysics is the immutable laws that rule the cosmos, and it is for

    this reason the most abstract, the most exact, and the most general of all

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    4/17

    505

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    sciences. In contrast, sciences like politics and economy derive their general

    concepts from metaphysics because their object of study, human life, has no

    autonomy whatsoever in relation to the laws of the cosmos. The same is true

    for the fields of morality and legislation. Since the laws of social life have

    a cosmological foundation, independent of human will, the wisdom of the

    good ruler consists precisely in recognizing this foundation and ensuring

    that the laws of the polis are organized around the fulfillment of mans

    natural dispositions.

    The crux of all this is the following: in an epistemological order in

    which morals, politics, and knowledge are thought to be dependent on the

    laws that rule the cosmos, the emergence of an object of knowledge called

    culture is impossible. It is only when human life in its totality is perceived

    as a dynamic process governed by laws created by man himself, and which

    are, therefore, not simple corollaries of natural laws, that it is possible to

    speak of culture in both the traditional and critical senses of the concept.

    The modern idea of man, understood as a being that produces himself

    in history and creates cultural values, can emerge only in the vacuum left

    behind with the disappearance of classical cosmology.

    It is, then, only during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries

    that the idea of culture as a space ofspecifically humanvalues, contrasted to

    nature, began to consolidate itself.1 Under this idea, culture constituted

    that sphere of moral, religious, political, philosophical, and technological

    valuesthatpermittedmantohumanizehimself,thatis,escapethetyranny

    of the state of nature. If, as mentioned above, the metaphysics of the

    cosmos turned social life into a purely derivative element whose dynamics

    reflected the general laws of the universe, now man saw himself as the

    producer of his own forms of political and social organization. That is,

    nature ceased to be the site to which man reverted in order to extract moral

    lessons or contemplate divine glory and came to be seen instead as an object

    to be put at the service of human interests. The metaphysics of the cosmos

    was substituted by the metaphysics of the human. The world that modern

    thinkers such as Bacon, Descartes, and Kant referred to was not the Greco-

    Roman-Medieval cosmos, in which social life was a simple reflection of

    predetermined laws, but a world created by man in his image and likeness.

    But if the world is a human construction and not an inexorable

    reflection of the lex aeterna, then social life assumes an as yet unthoughtdimension: temporality. Neither Plato, nor Aristotle, nor Thomas Aquinas

    contemplated time as an axis from which human action derived cosmo-

    logically predetermined meaning. Since man was not responsible for the

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    5/17

    506

    Nepantla

    creation of something new, time was nothing but the actualization of

    potentialities established beforehand and forever. But when man was per-

    ceived to be the sole architect of his own destiny, then it could be said that

    humanity lay in the capacity to humanize, that is, in mans ability to con-

    stitute himself in time through the creation of his own world: culture. The

    first characteristic of the traditional concept of culture is then the idea that

    the gradual humanization of the species is a process that occurs in time,

    in history, and is not already determined from an outside by cosmological

    laws.

    If through culture man slowly liberates himself from the chains

    imposed by nature, then cultural forms acquire ever increasing degrees

    of perfection to the extent that they permit the unfolding of the spirit,

    that is, the exercise of human freedom. For Hegel, the cultural forms that

    most closely resemble nature possess less dignity than those that are more

    abstract. This is because nature belongs to the sphere of necessity, while

    spirit is the proper site of freedom. Thus, for example, the religions that

    practice in naturalist cults are inferior to Christianity, which possesses a

    more abstract concept of divinity (God is spirit). The same is true of artistic

    manifestations: those which imitate nature or revolve around the purely

    figurative are inferior to those which privilege pure form, since these latter

    have managed to escape the tyranny of material contents, which do not

    befit the free expression of spirit. From Hegels hand we find thus a second

    characteristic of the traditional concept of culture: the privilege of so-called

    high culture over and above popular culture. The lettered, or, as Weber

    would say, rationalized forms of culture (musical codification, secular-

    ized art, literature, philosophy, historiography) are the most elevated, since

    through them man can reflect upon himself and recognize his own spiri-

    tual vocation. The human groups that have not been able to accede to the

    reflexivity of high culture remain rooted in youth and find themselves

    in need of the illumination radiating from lettered peoples, particularly

    philosophers. The lettered and the philosophers are those people who can

    elevate themselves above cultural contingencies and apprehend their object

    from the outside, with the same gaze of adeus absconditusthat condescends

    to contemplate the world.

    But if the evolution of culture is the outcome of a historical process,

    then freedom can also be objectified, particularly in the sphere of politicallife. A nation that has reached maturity has not only developed a high,

    that is lettered, culture, but has been able to constitute itself politically as a

    nation-state. For Hegel, the state is the true bearer of culture, of a peoples

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    6/17

    507

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    national spirit. Only in the state does freedom become objective, because

    it is there that all individuals are reconciled with the ethical substance of

    the collectivity. Individuals must, therefore, subordinate themselves to the

    state, since it is only through its mediation that they can learn to be conscious

    of who they are, what they want, and what their destiny is as members of

    a single nation. Johann Gottfried von Herder, Rousseau, Montesquieu,

    and Johann Gottlieb Fichte also considered the state to be the bearer of a

    peoples national identity. In contrast to the contractualists, they thought the

    state should be established on the basis of geographical conditions, customs,

    language, and the ways of thinking of the people over which it rules. This

    brings us to the third characteristic of the traditional concept of culture: the

    identity between people, nation, and culture. The fullest objectification of

    culture, understood as freedom from imperatives coming from an exterior,

    is the historical construction of the national-popular state. Individuals can

    experience true freedom only as members of a state that juridically reflects

    what Montesquieu called the general spirit, Hegel the Volksgeist, and

    Rousseau the general will.

    Postcolonialism as a Critical Theory of Culture

    Transferring the distinction introduced by Horkheimer to the present sub-

    ject, it can be said that the difference between the traditional and critical

    theories of culture is the recognition, by the latter, that its object of study

    is not a natural facticity but a social construction. Culture is discerned not

    as the site of freedom, that which protects us from the tyranny of nature,

    but as the network of relations of power that produces values, beliefs, and

    forms of knowledge. Theory is, in turn, taken not for a set of analytical

    propositions uncontaminated by praxis, but as an integral part of this net of

    inclusions and exclusions called social power. The theorist is not a passive

    subject who assumes an attitude of scientific objectivity and neutrality, but

    an active subject who finds himself or herself traversed by the same social

    contradictions of the object under scrutiny. Subject and object form part

    of the same lattice of powers and counterpowers from which neither can

    escape.

    Oneof thefundamental tools of critical theory, onewhich distances

    it substantially from traditional theory, is the notion of totality. This con-

    cept implies that society is a sui generis entity whose workings are relativelyindependent of the activity of individuals composing it.2 The social group

    is something more than the total sum of its members and constitutes a sys-

    tem of relations whose properties are different from those of the particular

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    7/17

    508

    Nepantla

    elements that enter into relation with each other. Societys plus compared

    with its individuals lies, then, in the set of relations that individuals estab-

    lish among themselves, so that what counts for critical theory is the kind of

    transaction or negotiation that takes place between subject and structure.

    The life of the structure cannot do without the subjects, as Emile Durkheim

    and Niklas Luhmann proposed, nor can the life of the subjects do without

    the structure, as the communitarians would have it.

    This concept of totality certainly breaks with the metaphysics of

    the cosmos, because the laws that structure the lives of men are not seen

    as simple reflections of a divine or cosmological normativity; but it also

    breaks with the metaphysics of the subject, because social life is no longer

    considered a transparent extension of human consciousness and will. This

    means that social life does not free man from the tyranny of nature, guiding

    him via culture to a gradual humanization, but subjects him instead to a

    new kind of heteronomy, this time under the form of systems that are not

    entirely under his control. Such systems are second nature in the sense

    that they exert an external coercion on individuals and become, as Giddens

    demonstrates, the conditions of possibility for human action. But the action

    of individuals reverts, in turn, to the workings of the systems, impelling

    their historical transformations.

    In contrast to the traditional concept of culture, a critical theory

    of culture posits, then, that social life is not the reign of freedom but that

    of contradiction; that, because social life does not depend entirely on the

    intentionality of consciousness but rather on the dialectic between subject

    and structure, it generally has perverse consequences, that is, outcomes that

    escape all rational planning. It can even be the case, as Beck, Giddens, and

    Bauman show, that these perverse results do not emerge from a lack of

    rationality, but rather as a consequence of it, as the crisis of the so-called

    project of modernity teaches us (Beck 1986). Organized social relations,

    which for traditional theory appear to be the way out of the state of nature

    and an entry into the spiritual or civil site of culture, are perceived by

    critical theory as a space of struggle and confronting interests.

    In the field of postcolonial theories,3 the idea of totality is ex-

    pressed in a categorythe world-system that was coined by the North

    American social philosopher Immanuel Wallerstein (1994), but has been

    widely used by such different theoreticians as Walter Mignolo, EnriqueDussel, Anibal Quijano, and Gayatri Spivak. From a hermeneutical point

    of view, the interest of this category lies in its reference to a structure of

    global dimensions, broadening thus the interpretative horizon of the tex

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    8/17

    509

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    national society that had functioned as the classical referent of social sci-

    ences since the nineteenth century. The world-system is a sui generis set of

    social relations configured in the sixteenth century as a consequence of the

    European expansion over the Atlantic.4

    The world-system is a network of interdependencies that covers

    a single space of social action. Sociologically speaking, this means that,

    from the sixteenth century onward, the lives of an ever greater number

    of people began to be linked by a planetary division of labor, coordinated

    by smaller systemic units denominated nation-states. The differences be-

    tween groups and societies that constitute the world-system do not depend

    on their level of industrial development or degree of cultural evolution,

    but on thefunctional position they occupy within the system. The differ-

    ences are thus not temporal but structural. Some of the systems social

    zones occupy the function of centers, meaning that they monopolize the

    hegemony, while others occupy a peripheral function because they are

    relegated to the margins of the structures of power.5

    For one sector of contemporary traditional theory, this is an un-

    comfortable perspective because it casts doubt upon the idea that the cog-

    nitive, moral, and expressive development of different societies obeys the

    unfolding of specific competencies of the human race. Even while accept-

    ing the idea that the world-system functions as an a priori mechanism that

    quasi-transcendentally organizes the social experience of the three spheres

    described by Jrgen Habermas (1973), we do not find ourselves before a

    transcendental structure invested with anthropological status. It is rather a

    historical structure, with a genesis in the long sixteenth century, a maximum

    systemic equilibrium between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries that

    currently finds itself in a moment of instability and disarticulation. From

    this point of view, the true, the good, and the beautiful, that is, the set of his-

    toric objectifications of human activity we call culture, are not rooted in

    the species transcendental abilities, but rather in relations of power that are

    socially construed and which have acquired a global character. Culture

    is indicative then not of a level of aesthetic, moral, or cognitive develop-

    ment of an individual, a group, or a society, but rather, as Wallerstein (1994)

    affirms, signifies the world-systems field of ideological battles.

    We arrive thus at the second of the characteristics of the modern

    world-system: the colonial logic that since the sixteenth century has con-ditioned itsworkings. In effect, the historical formationof theworld-system

    was fueled for a long time by the incorporation or military annexation of

    new geographic zones by states that achieved a hegemonic position within

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    9/17

    510

    Nepantla

    the system. But this process of colonization was something constitutive and

    not merely additive to its logic of operation, since the basic imperative of

    the world-system has been, and continues to be, the incessant accumulation

    of capital.6 To accomplish this, it was necessary that the hegemonic states

    of the world-system (Spain and Portugal first, then Holland, France, and

    England, and later the United States) open up new sources of supply for

    their internal markets, with the goal of increasing the margin of benefits.

    The power relations configured by the world-system thus acquired a colo-

    nial character, which affected not only the old European colonies but also

    a great number of peoples within the colonizing countries themselves. The

    Peruvian sociologist Anibal Quijano (1999, 99100) has coined the concept

    of coloniality of power to indicate this very situation.

    But what has all of this to do with culture? A great deal, if we

    keep in mind the fact that the social division of labor between central and

    peripheral zones, both at the general level of the world-system, as well as

    in the interior of its basic units, the nation-states, needed to be legitimized

    ideologically by hegemonic groups or contested, also ideologically, by sub-

    altern groups. While traditional theory naturalizes culture, projecting it

    into an ideal space in which order and harmony (aesthetics of the beautiful)

    reign, critical theory emphasizes the political and social, that is the con-

    flictive, nature of culture. In other words, culture is seen as the battlefield

    for the control of meaning. This means that critical theory does not isolate

    culture from the process of its social production and from its structural

    function inside the world-system and its subsystems, but rather advances

    toward the question of the geopolitical economy of culture.7 Postcolonial

    theories radicalize this question by suspecting that the cultural logic of

    the world-system is traversed by the social grammar of colonization.

    Seen from this perspective, culture has been the space wherein the

    coloniality of power has been legitimized or impugned from diverse social

    perspectives. For reasons of space, I will consider only the ways in which the

    coloniality of power was legitimized in ideological terms since the sixteenth

    century, and not occupy myself here with the type of contestation to which

    it has been submitted by what Wallerstein (1994) has named anti-systemic

    movements. As I will argue, the colonial annexation of new zones of the

    world-system was accompanied by the birth of two ideologies that served

    as cultural pillars of the modern world-system: racism and universalism.

    8

    Although social hierarchies have always been justified on the basis

    of the presumed inferiority or superiority of some peoples over others, the

    concept of race is a theoretical construction characteristic of the modern

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    10/17

    511

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    world-system. It arises in the heat of the debates that took place in Spain

    concerning the necessity to submit the American Indians to colonial domi-

    nation, and it takes form in institutions like theencomiendaandresguardo.

    The idea of race served as a criterion for social differentiation between the

    white colonizers and the mulatto or mestizo colonized, seen as infe-

    rior for their color and social origins.9 In the seventeenth and eighteenth

    centuries, once the hegemony of the world-system hadmigrated from Spain

    toward France and Holland, the concept of race was incorporated into the

    theoretical register philosophy of history. Here, the hierarchical differ-

    ences between peoplesand, concomitantly, their corresponding place

    in the social division of laborare justified according to their level of de-

    velopment, measured on a temporal-evolutionary scale. In consequence,

    the peoples that appear more advanced on this scale could legitimately

    occupy the territory of the more backward peoples and bestow the bene-

    fits of civilization upon them with no troubling pangs of conscience. In the

    nineteenth century, coinciding with the consolidation of British hegemony,

    the concept of race was finally unhitched from the philosophy of history

    and scientificized, incorporated into the methodology of positive sciences

    and the nascent social sciences.10 The superiority of some races over others

    was seen as the inevitable result of the evolution of the species; it was an

    inexorable law of nature, capable of being empirically verified.

    What interests me here is the intrinsic relationship between the

    colonial idea of race and the traditionalconcept of culture. If the maximiza-

    tion of benefits was the systemic imperative that impelled the territorial

    annexation of colonies, then it was necessary to justify why their inhabi-

    tants needed to be used as inexpensive labor for the benefit of the coloniz-

    ers: Indians, blacks, and mulattos could and should be enslaved because

    they shared a series of values, beliefs, and forms of knowledge that im-

    peded them from attaining the fruits of civilization on their own. There

    was something in their culture, and perhaps in their very biology, that set

    them at odds with the universalistic values shared by the white man. There

    was no point of contact possible between the culture of the colonizers and

    colonized, because either they possessed two different natures, as Juan

    Gins de Seplveda posited (1987 [1892], 2728), or they possessed a sin-

    gle nature but in different phases of historical evolution. In either case,

    we find ourselves before a naturalist or ideological concept of culture thatlegitimizes the social and political inequalities of the world-system.11

    The intrinsically colonial character of the world-system also tra-

    verses the second ideology considered in this essay: universalism. If racism

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    11/17

    512

    Nepantla

    serves to legitimize the inferiority of the colonized or subaltern groups

    in the colonies, universalism sanctions the superiority of the colonizers or

    hegemonic groups at the national level. As an heir of what I have in this

    essay called the metaphysics of the cosmos, modern universalism is, above

    all, an epistemological posture. It proclaims the possibility of acceding to

    objectively valid knowledges concerning the physical and social world once

    the adequate method is found. It affirms that the validity of this method

    is guaranteed by its neutrality in terms of value, since it transcends the moti-

    vations historically conditioned by culture. Its ground is not thus history,

    and its traditions, but a faculty shared by all men, independently of race,

    gender, age, or social condition: reason.

    Viewed from the perspective of the world-system, universalism is

    fully integrated into the logic that Weber called rationalization. It is not

    now the inscrutable will of God that decides the happenings of individual

    and social life, but man himself who, using reason, is able to decipher the

    inherent laws of nature in order to place them at his service. This rehabili-

    tation of man goes hand in hand with the idea of a domination over nature

    through science and technology, whose true prophet was Francis Bacon. In

    fact, nature is presented by Bacon as mans great adversary, the enemy

    to be overcome in order for the contingencies of life to be domesticated

    and theregnum hominisestablished over the earth (Bacon 1984 [1620]). The

    value-freecharacter of sciences andtechnologies wasconverted thus into the

    ideological guarantee of the modernization promoted by the hegemonic

    states of the world-system and, concretely, by the bourgeoisie of these states.

    The political institutionalization of theregnum hominisdreamt by Bacon

    and Descartes becomes thus a problem of technical character, addressed by

    economists, social scientists, educators, administrators, and experts of all

    kinds. The founding imperative was to eliminate the cultural barriers

    that obstructed the expansion of capital and the maximization of profits.

    On an internal level, universalism served as the instrument of ju-

    ridical and social control within nation-states. Insofar as it was an integral

    part of the modern world-system, the structural function of the state was

    to adjust the body and mind of all individuals belonging to a specific

    territoriality to the global imperative of production. All state politics and

    institutions (school, constitutions, law, hospitals, prisons, etc.) were canal-

    ized toward the disciplining of the passions through work. The purposewas to link all citizens to the global process of production through the sub-

    jection of their time and bodies to a series of norms that were defined and

    sanctioned by scientific-technical knowledge. In order for this to work, the

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    12/17

    513

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    state needed to be able to guarantee an impartial juridical framework

    within which the people under its jurisdiction could be contemplated as

    subjects of law. The juridical-political function of constitutions was pre-

    cisely to invent citizenship, that is, create a formal field of legibility which

    would, on a microphysical level, render the macrostructural imperative of

    the accumulation of capital viable.

    At this point it is necessary to clarify that although postcolonialthe-

    ories take up the microphysics of power analyzed by Michel Foucault, they

    complement his perspective by working with what lurked in the French

    theorists blind spot: relationsof power aremarked by macrophysical imper-

    atives of a colonial character.12 Thus, for example, citizenship was not only

    restricted to men who were married, literate, heterosexual, and proprietors,

    but also, and especially, to men who were white. In turn, the individuals that

    fell outside the space of citizenship were not only the homosexuals, prison-

    ers, mental patients, and political dissidents Foucault had in mind, but also

    blacks, Indians, mestizos, gypsies, Jews, and now, in times of globalization,

    ethnic minorities, immigrants, andAuslndern(foreigners). In this way,

    the genealogy of the microstructures of power is broadened by postcolonial

    theories into a genealogy of the macrostructures of long duration. It can

    be said, then, that postcolonial theories take the program of the ontology of

    the present, masterfully begun by Foucault, to its ultimate consequences.

    I want to conclude by pointing out two things. The first is that,

    at least until the first half of the twentieth century, racism and univer-

    salism configured the dominant geoculture of the modern world-system.

    Racism is a legacy of what Dussel calls the first modernity, the Hispanic-

    Catholic one, while universalism is a legacy of the second modernity,

    the eighteenth-century Enlightenment and its extension into nineteenth-

    century positivism. Both ideologies created a representational sitea

    culturethatlegitimatedtheunprecedentedmobilizationofthelaborforce

    and financial resources, of military campaigns and scientific discoveries, of

    educational programs and juridical reforms; in short, of this whole set of

    Faustian politics of social control, never before seen in history, which we

    know as the project of modernity. Of courseand this is the other side

    of the storythe unequal distribution of riches also generated antisystemic

    movements that were successful to the extent that they could negotiate

    with the hegemonies created by the system.

    13

    The second point is of a diagnostic nature. If one of the character-

    istics of globalization is to have mined the capacity of the nation-states to

    organizeallofsociallife,thenwefindourselvesbeforeaprofoundstructural

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    13/17

    514

    Nepantla

    crisis of the modern world-system. This, as has been noted, was organized

    on the basis of smaller units, nation-states, which guaranteed the fulfillment

    of the imperative that assured the internal equilibrium of the system: the

    endless accumulation of capital through the annexation of new territories.

    But at the outset of the twenty-first century, we find ourselves in a situation

    in which there are no longer any territories to annex and in which social

    life is organized by supranational instances. The slightly ambiguous cate-

    gory of postcoloniality points toward this situation. The end of territorial

    colonialism, propelled by hegemonic nation-states, runs parallel to the ex-

    haustion of the project of modernity, that is, with the end of the institutional

    capacity of these states to exert control over the social lives of peoples.14 But

    this does not necessarily mean that the world-system is mortally wounded,

    nor that its structural geoculture has ceased to be operational. Rather, we are

    in a historical moment in which there are no colonizing countries, but only

    countries colonized by a capital that has become invisible, that has assumed

    a spectral character.

    Faced with this new situation, the critical theory of society faces

    the challenge of recuperating the horizon of totality that contemporary

    cultural critique seems to have lost in the name of the postmodern attack on

    metanarratives and runs the risk of converting itself into a new traditional

    theory. A cultural analysis that limits itself to thematizing the exclusions of

    gender, race, ethnicity, or knowledge, that homogenizes differences, is not

    sufficient to articulate a criticism of capitalism. It is necessary to think the

    world-system that structured social subjects and to ask why this historical

    project of social control (modernity) has exhausted itself, yielding to new

    forms of global (re)structuration. In other words, it is necessary to think the

    historical transformations suffered by the geoculture of the modern world-

    system in its present moment of crisis. This is, to my mind, the main agenda

    for a social theory that understands itself as a critical theory of culture.

    Translated by

    Adriana Johnson

    Notes

    1. I do not want to emphasize here any progress of thought or any historical teleology.

    Critical theory did not substitute for traditional theory after the eighteenth

    century. What I want to underscore is that at this time the material conditions

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    14/17

    515

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    were created for the emergence of a type of theorization that was previously

    impossible.

    2. Here, relatively independent means that the social totality is not an entity that

    is ontologically prior to the individual elements that constitute it, and in

    which these simply assume predetermined roles, as is proposed by classic

    structuralism, but rather that the reproduction of social life takes place as a

    process of negotiation between the whole and its parts. Giddens (1994 [1979])

    has shown that this process implies a certain structuration of subjects but

    also and at the same time a subjectivization of structures.

    3. By postcolonial theory I mean a model of theorization that (a) interrogates the ma-

    terial conditions of possibility of the production of knowledge in modernity

    and (b) specifically points to the colonial experience as one of these condi-

    tions. Although considerations like those of Walter Mignolo (1998)and his

    distinction between the different critical theories loci of enunciationare

    suggestive, they are not relevant for my argument here.

    4. Both Dussel and Wallerstein have pointed outconfronting other Marxist theorists

    like Erik Wolf and Andr Gunder Frankthat in contrast to previous social

    systems, which revolved around a kind of centralized political unity, we live

    today in a system that gathers different political units around a single world

    economy: capitalism. Furthermore, the modern world-system is the only

    historical structure in which the incessant accumulation of interests is taken

    as a value in and of itself. In all other social structures, the accumulation of

    richeswasperceivedas a meansforobtaining something, andnot as an endper

    se. The maximization of surplus value converts itself thus into individual or

    collective virtue, rewarded or punished by an institution called the market.

    See Dussel 1992 and Wallerstein 1994.

    5. I emphasize the idea of social zone to avoid confusing it with the concept of geo-

    graphical zone. By social zone I mean a hegemonic set of social relations

    (what Marx called class) that is primarily configured under the political

    auspices of the national state, but whose structural function transcends in

    some cases the political limits set down by the state. Thus, for example, the

    hegemonic social zones in the European countries in the nineteenth century

    certainly functioned as centers of the interior of their own societies, but their

    economic and cultural hegemony also extended itself to all the peripheral

    social zones of the world-system. In addition, the appropriation of surplus

    value, generated by labor in the colonies, was concentrated in these peripheralzones. In this sense, as we shall see, the hegemony of power assumes a colonial

    character.

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    15/17

    516

    Nepantla

    6. In order to reproduce itself, the world-systemhas developed institutional mechanisms

    (established initially in nation-states and now in the global logic of consump-

    tion) to materially reward and punish individuals according to whether or

    not they adjust themselves to the imperative of the maximization of benefits.

    Horkheimer and Adorno (1994) spoke in this sense of the universalization

    of instrumental reason, even if they erroneously extrapolated this concept

    until it accounted for the totality of human history.

    7. Formulated in this way, the problem we are posing eludes any determinism of the

    base on the economic superstructure of society. The critical theory of

    society proposes a dialectic between subject and structure, in which neither

    element can be thought independently of the other, since both mutually con-

    dition each other. In other texts I have dealt with this idea more extensively

    (Castro-Gmez 1997, 1998).

    8. Racism and universalism are ideological knowledges configured in the sixteenth

    century that serve to legitimize and give meaning to Spains economic and po-

    litical dominion over her colonies. After the seventeenth century, when Spain

    began to cede the hegemony of the world-system to other European powers

    (France and England), these ideological knowledges began to permeate the

    scientific practices that lie at the origin of what we know today as the social

    sciences. From this point of view, social sciences, as they were institutional-

    ized in the nineteenth century and after, did not succeed in establishing an

    epistemological rupture with ideological knowledges such as racism and

    universalism. Concepts elaborated by the social sciences, such as modernity,

    society, and progress, are founded upon ideological knowledges config-

    ured in the sixteenth century. A genealogy of social sciences and humanities

    should begin thus in Spain, and not in France or England.

    9. In this sense, Magnus Mrner speaks of a racial pigmentocracy based upon the

    concept of racial purity (Mrner 1969, 6077). This is an ethnicization of

    the labor force.

    10. In fact, as Edward Said (1995) has demonstrated, social sciences, especially anthro-

    pology, ethnology, and orientalism, generate their languages on the basis of

    the colonial experience and as a consequence of the occupation of overseas

    colonies by France and England.

    11. It should be remembered that when I refer to center and periphery I am not

    speaking only of the relationship between metropolis and colonies, but also of

    the relationship between hegemonic and subaltern groups within Europeannational states.

    12. Foucaults renunciation of methodological holism impedes him from tracing a ge-

    nealogy of structures of long duration. For the critique Foucault will level

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    16/17

    517

    Castro-Gmez . Traditional and Critical Theories of Culture

    at the category of totality, see the discussion proposed by Martin Jay (1984:

    51037).

    13. This is the case, for example, of the labor movements in Europe and the United

    States, or of third world national liberation movements.

    14. I have developed this idea of the end of modernity as a project of political-social

    control in Castro-Gmez 1998, 78102.

    References

    Bacon, Francis. 1984 [1620].Novum Organum. Madrid: Sarpe.

    Beck, Ulrich. 1986.Risikogesellschaft: Auf dem Weg in eine andere Moderne. Frankfurt:

    Suhrkamp.

    Castro-Gmez, Santiago. 1997. Los vecindarios de la ciudad letrada: Variaciones

    filosficas sobre un tema de Angel Rama. InAngel Rama y los estudios

    latinoamericanos, edited by Mabel Moraa. Pittsburgh, PA: University of

    Pittsburgh Press.

    . 1998. Latinoamericanismo, modernidad, globalizacin: Prolegmenos a una

    crtica poscolonial de la razn. InTeoras sin disciplina: Latinoamericanismo,

    poscolonialidad y globalizacin en debate, edited by Santiago Castro-Gmez

    and Eduardo Mendieta. Mexico City: Porra.

    de Seplveda, Juan Gins. 1987 [1892].Tratado sobre las justas causas de la guerra contra

    los indios. Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Econmica.

    Dussel, Enrique. 1992.1492, el encubrimiento del otro: Hacia el origen del mito de la

    modernidad.Santaf de Bogot: Antropos.

    Giddens, Anthony. 1994 [1979].Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure, and

    Contradiction in Social Analysis. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Habermas, Jrgen. 1973.Erkenntnis und Interesse. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Horkheimer, Max. 1974 [1937]. Teora tradicional y teora crtica. InTeora crtica.

    Buenos Aires: Amorrortu.

    Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 1994.Dialctica de la Ilustracin:

    Fragmentos filosficos. Madrid: Trotta.

    Jay, Martin. 1984. Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukcs to

    Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Mignolo, Walter. 1998. Postoccidentalismo: El argumento desde Amrica Latina. In

    Teoras sin disciplina: Latinoamericanismo, poscolonialidad y globalizacin en

    debate.Edited by Santiago Castro-Gmez and Eduardo Mendieta. Mexico

    City: Porra.

    Mrner, Magnus. 1969.La mezcla de razas en la historia de Amrica Latina. Buenos

    Aires: Paidos.

  • 8/10/2019 1.3castro Gomez

    17/17

    518

    Nepantla

    Quijano, Anibal. 1999. Colonialidad del poder, cultura y conocimiento en Amrica

    Latina. InPensar (en) los intersticios, edited by Santiago Castro-Gmez,

    Oscar Guardiola Rivera, and Carmen Milln de Benavides. Santaf de

    Bogot: CEJA.

    Said, Edward. 1995.Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient.London: Penguin.

    Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1994.Geopolitics and Geoculture: Essays on the Changing

    World-System. London: Cambridge University Press.