327
Foundations of Geometry Lecture Notes for Math 370 California State University, Northridge Revised for Spring 2013

Foundations of Geometry - Lecture Notes for Math 370

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  1. 1. Foundations of Geometry Lecture Notes for Math 370 California State University, Northridge Revised for Spring 2013
  2. 2. ii Foundations of Geometry: Lecture Notes to Accompany Math 370 using Venemas Geometry California State University, Northridge Revised for Spring 2013 (last update: November 18, 2012) This document is provided in the hope that it will be useful but without any warranty, without even the implied warranty of merchantability or tness for a particular purpose. The document is provided on an as is basis and the author has no obligations to provide corrections or modications. The author makes no claims as to the accuracy of this document. In no event shall the author be liable to any party for direct, indirect, special, incidental, or consequential damages, including lost prots, unsatisfactory class performance, poor grades, confusion, misunderstanding, emotional disturbance or other general malaise arising out of the use of this document or any software described herein, even if the author has been advised of the possibility of such damage. 2012. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommer- cial No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/ or send a letter to Creative Commons, 171 Second Street, Suite 300, San Francisco, California, 94105, USA. ELEC- TRONIC COPIES MAY ONLY BE DISTRIBUTED FREE-OF-CHARGE. This is not an ocial document. Any opinions expressed herein are totally arbitrary, are only presented to expose the student to diverse perspectives, and do not necessarily reect the position of any specic individual, the California State University, Northridge, or any other organization. Please report any errors to [email protected]. All feedback, comments, sug- gestions for improvement, etc., is appreciated, especially if youve used these notes for a class, either at CSUN or elsewhere, from both instructors and students. With only a few exceptions all of the illustrative gures in this document were generated using GeoGebra (http://www.geogebra.org), exported as SVG les, and converted (oc- casionally with annotation) to PDF format using Inkscape (http://www.inkscape.org). Figures that were taken from other sources are cited in their captions. The document was typeset in LATEXunder Ubuntu Linux. Other image credits: page 7, I. Ovespyan; 6, M. Morehouse; 4, L. Milstein; 16, B. Davis; 24, J. Greenberg; 28, C. Gray; 36, C. Yoon; 39, L. Najmi; 40, S. Devost; 48, S. Ariola; 52, L. Sadighi; 144, M.Duda; 190, L. Tran; 200, Z. Yerkanyan; 185, S. Johnson; 312, R. Miranda; 322, M. Jaime. STUDENTS: THIS IS NOT A TEXTBOOK. IF YOU ARE USING THESE NOTES, PLEASE BUY A COPY OF VENEMA. THESE NOTES WERE CRE- ATED AS A LECTURING AIDE, NOT A TEXTBOOK REPLACEMENT. 4302517811059 ISBN 978-1-105-43025-1 90000 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  3. 3. Contents BUGGY DRAFT MAY CONTAIN ERRORS 1 Preface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 2 NCTM . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5 3 CA Standard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 4 Common Core . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 5 Logic and Proof . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 6 Real Numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 7 Euclids Elements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 8 Hilberts Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33 9 Birkho/MacLane Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 10 The SMSG Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 11 The UCSMP Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45 12 Venemas Axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 13 Incidence Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53 14 Betweenness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61 15 The Plane Separation Postulate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75 16 Angles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79 17 The Crossbar Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87 18 Linear Pairs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 19 Angle Bisectors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95 20 The Continuity Axiom . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 21 Side-Angle-Side . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103 22 Neutral Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107 23 Angle-Side-Angle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111 24 Exterior Angles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 115 25 Angle-Angle-Side . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 26 Side-Side-Side . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 27 Scalene and Triangle Inequality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 28 Characterization of Bisectors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 129 29 Transversals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133 iii
  4. 4. iv CONTENTS 30 Triangles in Neutral Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 31 Quadrilaterals in Neutral Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . 145 32 The Euclidean Parallel Postulate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 33 Rectangles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 167 34 The Parallel Projection Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173 35 Similar Triangles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177 36 Triangle Centers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181 37 Area . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187 38 The Pythagorean Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191 39 Circles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 201 40 Circles and Triangles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213 41 Euclidean Circles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 219 42 Area and Circumference of Circles . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229 43 Indiana Bill 246 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 237 44 Estimating . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239 45 Euclidean Constructions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251 46 Hyperbolic Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 263 47 Perpendicular Lines in Hyperbolic Geometry . . . . . . . 271 48 Parallel Lines in Hyperbolic Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . 275 49 Triangles in Hyperbolic Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 283 50 Area in Hyperbolic Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 289 51 The Poincare Disk Model . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297 52 Arc Length . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 305 53 Spherical Geometry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 313 A Symbols Used . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 319 Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 323 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  5. 5. Section 1 Preface Reections Foundations of Geometry is a content class for future high school teach- ers. In most college math classes, the focus is on a logical development of mathematical tools and techniques; their underlying theory, derivations and proofs; and application to the real world or other mathematical sub- disciplines. As a content class we will do all this, but we will also make an (albeit limited) attempt to integrate the material in a way that it is pertinent to your future as a an educator. On Pedagogy. As teachers you will need to know the most eective way to present the material to others. To be eective, you should be clear, con- cise, and interesting. To be successful your presentation needs to promote understanding and retention. Most of this cannot be learned in the classroom. It requires hard work and lots of practice. I can tell you what I nd eective but that might not help very much. My students are more mathematically mature than yours will be - after all, they are college mathematics majors. My students are people who like math, want to learn more about it, and (in the your case) are anxious to share that excitement with others. Middle school and high school is dierent. So most of what works for me probably wont work very well in your classrooms. As you progress towards your California teaching credential you will take a lot of classes in pedagogy, the art or science of teaching. Some of these will focus on pedagogy in mathematics and others will not. A few of you 1
  6. 6. 2 SECTION 1. PREFACE are enrolled in integrated programs that teach content simultaneously with pedagogy (but in dierent classes), or already have teaching experience and want a refresher in the content area. To these students what I have to say here is probably nothing new. Integrating Content with Pedagogy. Our focus is on mathematical content. But can content be separated from pedagogy? Should it be? This is not an easy question. Some would say that as mathematicians we should leave sociology to the sociologists. This has a grain of truth to it - we can best teach what we know best - and instructors might do more harm than good by straying outside their own specialized disciplines. It seems nearly everybody has an opinion on the matter. But to leave pedagogy out of the equation completely would be you, as a future teacher, a disservice. This is not a class in pedagogy. I am not going to tell you how to teach. I couldnt even if I wanted to. But what I want you to do as you progress through the semester is to think about how you can communicate your knowledge to others. Start with your colleagues in this class. If you really understand something you should be able to explain it to people with back- grounds similar to yours. Ask for their criticism and listen to what they say. Take their suggestions into account the next time you work together. Of course being able to explain your proof of the Pythagorean theorem to the student sitting next to you does not mean youll be able to explain it to your ninth grade students. But it will get you thinking about explaining things in your own words. Listen to what you say. Explain things the way you would want them explained to you. Think about what questions you might have, and answer them to yourself. As a teacher in training, you should continually be asking yourself how am I ever going to teach this? whenever you are presented with new mathematical content. Yes, you should certainly master the material. Yes, you should learn the big picture - how does this new content mesh with what you already know about math? Where else can we go from here? What other theorems, results, and methods can we obtain? How can this content be applied to other applications outside pure math? Topics and Presentation. This class will give you the big picture. Youll get down and dirty in other classes that are more focused on spe- cic grade level requirements. How to present this big picture has a long and well storied history. You could say it all started with Euclid but all he really did was write CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  7. 7. SECTION 1. PREFACE 3 down in a formal manner the knowledge of his day. He started by laying out lists of assumptions and basic axioms, and then asking what could be derived, using the logical methods of his day, from those assumptions. The result has come to be known as Euclidean geometry. Euclid boiled the basics down to ve axioms (after writing a whole mess of somewhat confusing denitions). And followed it with a zillion pages of theorems. In the past century or so other mathematicians have tried to re-formulated Euclids axioms so that they are easier to learn. These other presentations, starting with Hilbert and continuing up to the common core standards used today, are all completely equivalent, in the sense that the same mass of mathematical knowledge is derivable from them. This process of re- dening Euclid to make things easier to teach and learn has not been without controversy. On Standards. The Common Core State Standards Initiative has now been adopted by 45 states, the District of Columbia, Guam, American Samoa, and the U.S. Virgin islands.1 These standards give teachers (or schools, or boards of education, depending upon where you end up teaching) a framework within which to begin your presentation. These recommenda- tions serve as a resource for educators, and help provide a guide for the de- velopment of curriculum, instruction, and assessment. Since the the choice of textbook will, in all likelihood, be determined by factors outside your control, the formal method of presentation may also be pre-determined. The common core standards adopted in California for a high school geome- try class give a list of 48 specic topics that should be covered divided into categories that include congruence, similarity, right triangles, circles, arc lengths, measurement and dimension (among others). As you go through this course I want you to think about how what we are studying ts into this material. Ask yourself questions like this: how can I put this together into a coherent, logical sequence? How can I make it interesting and fun, challenging and not boring? How can I promote comprehension? How can I make my students more autonomous? How can I communicate high ex- pectations to all my students without bias? How can I treat all my students equally? How can I assess my students retention and understanding? How can technology help? What sort of examples would make this easier to un- derstand? What sort of activities would promote retention? What should go into my lesson plan? These are not easy question and there are no easy answers. Thinking about them now, while you are learning geometry for the rst time (or perhaps 1Holdouts are Alaska, Texas, Nebraska, Minnesota, Virginia, and Puerto Rico. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  8. 8. 4 SECTION 1. PREFACE re-learning it from a dierent perspective) should help make you better teachers in the end. There is a lot of work to be done, and a long and bumpy road ahead of you.However, the more traditional approach in our state is to learn the content material rst, then study pedagogy. Spring 2012 Reections The notes have been only marginally modied this semester, primarily to reect an easier to read page size2 . I have also run things through the spell-checker and xed probably half of the spelling er- rors. Unfortunately the grammar and style is still atrocious. I did have fun discovering such interest- ing spelling corrections that were suggested such as circumciser for cirumcenter; orthodontic for ortho- center; verticals for vertices; Ne- braska for Bhaksara; saccharine for Saccheri; Stouer for Ploue; ge- ography for geogebra; conscate for Chudnuvsky; and Yardmaster Kandahar for Yasumasa Kanda- har. The Mohr-Moscheroni Theo- rem became the More Maraschinos Theorem; Clairuts Axiom the Clairol Axiom; Boylais Theorem the Bonsai Theorem; and our venerable textbook by Venema, was reduced to a piti- ful enema. I also discovered that non-mathematicians spell pointwise as two words or with a dash, as in point-wise, and that I cant spell isosceles worth beans. I guess, like the scarecrow, I deserve my Th.D. (Doctorate of Thinkology), for that. Spring 2013. Ive xed all of the bugs that were discovered last spring, added some stu on the common core, and shortened the original preface, though I think its still too wordy. 2That is, for me, with low vision, standing in front of the class, lecturing. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  9. 9. Section 2 NCTM Math Recommendations The National Council of Teachers of Mathematics (http://www.nctm.org) is the worlds largest mathematics education organization, with almost 100,000 members. They have pub- lished several highly inuential and at times, controversial standards over the past several years. The rst set of curriculum standards was released in 1989; professional standards for teach- ers in 1991; and assessment standards in 1995. A more focused set of content standards was released in their 2000 re- port.1 Although California was one of the rst states to adopt much of the original 1989 standards, they remain controversial, even in our own univer- sity. The 2000 report listed four goals of its study: 1. To set forth a comprehensive set of goals for students at all levels (PK-12); 2. To serve as a resource for educators and policy makers; 1Principles and Standards for School Mathematics, NCTM, 2000, ISBN 0873534808. 5
  10. 10. 6 SECTION 2. NCTM 3. To guide in the development of curriculum frameworks, assessments, and instruction; and 4. To stimulate discussion at all levels on how best to help students learn math. It recommendations included six principles for primary and sec- ondary mathematics education and a set of content standards for each subject area. Recommended con- tent is discussed in the next sec- tion. The six principles of school mathematics recommended by the NCTM were Equity, Curriculum, Teaching, Learning, Assessment, and Technology Equity. The report challenges the stereotype that only some students are capable of learning mathematics, and compares it to the pervasive belief that everyone should learn to read and write in English. This bias leads to low expectations for many students, especially among students who live in poverty, are non-native English speakers, have disabilities, or are female, among other groups. The Equity Principle de- mands that high expectations be communicated in words and deeds to all students with instructional programs that are interesting to students and help them see the importance of mathematical study. Curriculum. A curriculum is more than a collection of activities: it must be coherent, focused on important mathematics, and well articulated across the grades. Lessons should be planned so that fundamental ideas form an integrated whole. Teaching. Eective mathematics teaching requires understanding what students know and need to learn and then challenging and supporting them to learn it well. Eective teaching requires knowing and understanding mathematics, students as learners, and pedagogical strategies. Teachers need to understand the big ideas in math and present them as a coherent CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  11. 11. SECTION 2. NCTM 7 and connected subject. They must know where commen misunderstand- ings arise, and be able to present important concepts like a fraction is part of the whole with dierent or multiple representations of each idea or concept. Eective teaching also requires a challenging and supportive classroom environment. Well chosen tasks can encourage students curios- ity. Teachers must decide which aspect of a task to highlight, what ques- tions to ask, and how to support students without doing the thinking for them. Finally, eective teaching requires continually seeking improvement. You will learn much by observing your students, listening carefully to their questions, ideas, and explanations, and analyzing what your students are doing and how your actions aect your students learning. Learning. Students must learn mathematics with understanding, actively building new knowledge from experience and prior knowledge. Factual knowledge, procedural prociency, and conceptual understanding are the three components to this. Memorization of facts without understanding leaves students unable to apply these facts or procedures to knew do- mains, while conceptual understanding together with factual and proce- dural knowledge makes subsequent learning easier. Autonomous learning then becomes possible, and students can eventually take control of their own learning. Assessment. Assessment should support the learning of important mathematics and furnish useful in- formation to both teachers and stu- dents. In the modern age of stan- dardized tests and numerical met- rics for corporate quality and pro- duction this seems to have been for- gotten. Good assessment practices provide information to both the student and the teacher. Scoring guides or rubrics can help teachers understand students prociencies. And poor student performance is just as often an indication that the teacher is not providing sucient grounding in the content being assessed. Finally, since students have dierent learning methods dierent types of assessments may be necessary to make an eective decision regarding student success. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  12. 12. 8 SECTION 2. NCTM Technology. Technology is essential in teaching and learning mathemat- ics; it inuences the mathematics that is taught and enhances students learning. Used properly, technology can help students learn math. This is particularly so where a number of programs allow students to perform the traditional compass-and-straightedge constructions with innite accuracy and neatness. But these constructions can do something that construc- tions on paper cannot: students can drag points and move lines and shapes around and see the results immediately. This is a type of feedback never before possible and we are still grappling with its implications and possi- bilities. The Standards. Four basic standards are dened for all grades; at each grade level certain expectations are to be met. The four basic geometry standards deal with (1) geometric properties; (2) spatial relationships; (3) transformations and symmetry; and (4) problem solving. They are listed in more detail below, along with the specic expectations for grades for 9 through 12. Portions of the standards are published on-line at http: //standards.nctm.org/document/ but beyond this list specic details are lacking from the report; the entire geometry standard is only 10 pages.2 Details are given in the box on the following page. Figure 2.1: Part of an example analyzing properties of two- and three- dimensional geometric shapes to develop mathematical arguments about geometric relationships from the NCTM Standards for high school geome- try. [gure from NCTM Standards (2000), Chapter 7] 2For whatever reason NCTM has chosen not to make these details open-source but instead require membership ($53/year) or document purchase ($54.95) for complete access. Thus many teachers never see this document. There is a copy in the CSUN library, though. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  13. 13. SECTION 2. NCTM 9 California Framework 1. Analyze characteristics and properties of two- and three-dimensional geometric shapes and develop mathematical arguments about geometric relationships to: (a) analyze properties and determine attributes of two- and three-dimensional ob- jects; (b) explore relationships (including congruence and similarity) among classes of two- and three-dimensional geometric objects (gure 2.1), make and test conjectures about them, and solve problems involving them; (c) establish the validity of geometric conjectures using deduction, prove theorems, and critique arguments made by others; and to (d) use trigonometric relationships to determine lengths and angle measures. 2. Specify locations and describe spatial relationships using coordinate geometry and other representational systems: (a) use Cartesian coordinates and other coordinate systems, such as navigational, polar, or spherical systems, to analyze geometric situations; (b) investigate conjectures and solve problems involving two- and three-dimensional objects represented with Cartesian coordinates. 3. Apply transformations and use symmetry to analyze mathematical situations: (a) understand and represent translations, reections, rotations, and dilations of objects in the plane by using sketches, coordinates, vectors, function notation, and matrices; (b) use various representations to help understand the eects of simple transforma- tions and their compositions. 4. Use visualization, spatial reasoning, and geometric modelling to solve problems: (a) draw and construct representations of two- and three-dimensional geometric objects using a variety of tools; (b) visualize three-dimensional objects and spaces from dierent perspectives and analyze their cross sections; (c) use vertex-edge graphs to model and solve problems; (d) use geometric models to gain insights into, and answer questions in, other areas of mathematics; (e) use geometric ideas to solve problems in, and gain insights into, other disciplines and other areas of interest such as art and architecture. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  14. 14. 10 SECTION 2. NCTM CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  15. 15. Section 3 California Framework and Standards In 1997 the California State Board of Education adopted Mathematics Content Standards for Public Schools. These standards list specic content material that should be covered at each level of public education in Mathemat- ics. This material has since been su- perseded by the Common Core Stan- dards, which were adopted by Califor- nia in 2010. by meeting the goals of standards-based mathematics, students will achieve greater prociency in the practical uses of mathematics in every- day life, such as balancing a check book, purchasing a car, and understanding the daily news. Furthermore, when students delve deeply into mathemat- ics, they gain not only conceptual understanding of mathematical principles but also knowledge of and experience with pure reasoning. One of the most important goals of mathematics is to teach students logical reasoning1 . 1If you dont know how to add fractions, you dont know how to add.[Attributed to 11
  16. 16. 12 SECTION 3. CA STANDARD In 2005 California also adopted a Mathematics Framework for California Public Schools. The purpose of this framework was to provide for in- structional programs and strategies, instructional materials, professional development, and assessments that are aligned with the standards with the intent of providing a context for continuing a coordinated eort to en- able all California students to achieve rigorous, high levels of mathematics prociency. These are largely derived from the NCTM standards, and are summarized in the boxes on this and the following pages. An important part of the framework is balance. A balanced program should give the student (a) prociency in basic skills; (b) conceptual understand- ing; and (c) problem solving ability. 1. Become procient in basic computational and procedural skills. These are the basic skills that all students should learn to use routinely and automatically. They should be practiced suciently and used frequently enough to commit them to memory and ensure that these skills are retained and maintained over the years. 2. Develop conceptual understanding. Students who do not have a deep understanding of mathematics suspect that it is just a jumble of unrelated procedures and incomprehensible formulas. In seeing the larger picture and in understanding the underlying concepts, students are in a stronger position to apply their knowledge to new situations and problems and to recognize when they have made procedural errors. 3. Become adept at problem solving. Problem solving in mathematics is a goal-related activity that involves applying skills, understandings, and experiences to resolve new, challenging, or perplexing mathematical situa- tions. Problem solving involves a sequence of activities directed toward a specic mathematical goal, such as solving a word problem, a task that of- ten involves the use of a series of mathematical procedures and a conceptual representation of the problem to be solved. All three components are important; none is to be neglected or under- emphasized. Balance, however, does not imply allocating set amounts of time for each of the three components. professor Barry Simon, Caltech, in a freshman mathematics class.] CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  17. 17. SECTION 3. CA STANDARD 13 Goals for Teachers (2005 CA. Framework) 1. Increase teachers knowledge of mathematics content through professional develop- ment focusing on standards-based mathematics. 2. Provide an instructional program that preserves the balance of computational and procedural skills, conceptual understanding, and problem solving. 3. Assess student progress frequently toward the achievement of the mathematics stan- dards and adjust instruction accordingly. 4. Provide the learning in each instructional year that lays the necessary groundwork for success in subsequent grades or subsequent mathematics courses. 5. Create and maintain a classroom environment that fosters a genuine understanding and condence in all students that through hard work and sustained eort, they can achieve or exceed the mathematics standards. 6. Oer all students a challenging learning experience that will help to maximize their individual achievement and provide opportunities for students to exceed the standards. 7. Oer alternative instructional suggestions and strategies that address the specic needs of Californias diverse student population. 8. Identify the most successful and ecient approaches within a particular classroom so that learning is maximized. Goals for Students (2005 CA. Framework) 1. Develop uency in basic computational and procedural skills, an understanding of mathematical concepts, and the ability to use mathematical reasoning to solve math- ematical problems, including recognizing and solving routine problems readily and nding ways to reach a solution or goal when no routine path is apparent. 2. Communicate precisely about quantities, logical relationships, and unknown values through the use of signs, symbols, models, graphs, and mathematical terms. 3. Develop logical thinking in order to analyze evidence and build arguments to support or refute hypotheses. 4. Make connections among mathematical ideas and between mathematics and other disciplines. 5. Apply mathematics to everyday life and develop an interest in pursuing advanced studies in mathematics and in a wide array of mathematically related career choices. 6. Develop an appreciation for the beauty and power of mathematics. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  18. 18. 14 SECTION 3. CA STANDARD The California Standards (1997) The California Board of Education sets forth 22 specic requirements for geometry in secondary education.2 These specics are listed on pages 42- 43 of Mathematics Content Standards for California Public Schools. The Mathematics Framework for California Public Schools expands on these 22 requirements with specic examples (pages 85-89 of the Framework) and discuss specic considerations for high school geometry on pages 184-189 of the Framework. California Framework 1. Introduce students to the basic nature of logical reasoning. 2. Use inductive reasoning and geometric constructions to build up a breadth of knowledge from from a few basic axioms. 3. Become procient in proofs and learn the basic principles of plane geometry. 4. Study the basic properties of triangles, quadrilaterals, circles, and parallel lines. 5. Use the system built up to prove the Pythagorean theorem and from there develop and understanding of areas of dierently shaped objects. 6. Use coordinates and shapes as a natural jumping o into trigonometry. 7. Show that the proofs of geometry can be repeated analytically using trigonom- etry. 8. Develop the connection between geometry and algebra, introducing the con- cepts of analytic geometry. According to the framework document, the main purpose of the geome- try curriculum is to develop geometric skills and concepts and the ability to construct formal logical arguments and proofs in a geometric setting. The geometry skills and concepts developed in this discipline are useful to all students. Aside from learning these skills and concepts, students will develop their ability to construct formal, logical arguments and proofs in geometric settings and problems. The curriculum is weighed towards plane Euclidean geometry but allows (and encourages) some use on coor- dinate systems and transformations. The considerations section (pages 184-189 of the Framework) walk us through the standards and give us a perspective on how a geometry course might be structured. 2This material has been largely superseded by the adoption of the common core standards by California in 2010. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  19. 19. SECTION 3. CA STANDARD 15 California Geometry Content Standards (1 of 2) 1. Students demonstrate understanding by identifying and giving examples of undened terms, axioms, theorems, and inductive and deductive reasoning. 2. Students write geometric proofs, including proofs by contradiction. 3. Students construct and judge the validity of a logical argument and give coun- terexamples to disprove a statement. 4. Students prove basic theorems involving congruence and similarity. 5. Students prove that triangles are congruent or similar, and they are able to use the concept of corresponding parts of congruent triangles. 6. Students know and are able to use the triangle inequality theorem. 7. Students prove and use theorems involving the properties of parallel lines cut by a transversal, the properties of quadrilaterals, and the properties of circles. 8. Students know, derive, and solve problems involving the perimeter, circum- ference, area, volume, lateral area, and surface area of common geometric gures. 9. Students compute the volumes and surface areas of prisms, pyramids, cylinders, cones, and spheres; and students commit to memory the formulas for prisms, pyramids, and cylinders. 10. Students compute areas of polygons, including rectangles, scalene triangles, equilateral triangles, rhombi, parallelograms, and trapezoids. 11. Students determine how changes in dimensions aect the perimeter, area, and volume of common geometric gures and solids. 12. Students nd and use measures of sides and of interior and exterior angles of triangles and polygons to classify gures and solve problems. 13. Students prove relationships between angles in polygons by using properties of complementary, supplementary, vertical, and exterior angles. 14. Students prove the Pythagorean theorem. 15. Students use the Pythagorean theorem to determine distance and nd missing lengths of sides of right triangles. 16. Students perform basic constructions with a straight edge and compass, such as angle bisectors, perpendicular bisectors, and the line parallel to a given line through a point o the line. 17. Students prove theorems by using coordinate geometry, including the midpoint of a line segment, the distance formula, and various forms of equations of lines and circles. 18. Students know the denitions of the basic trigonometric functions dened by the angles of a right triangle. They also know and are able to use elementary relationships between them. For example, tan(x) = sin(x)/cos(x), (sin(x))2 + (cos(x))2 = 1. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  20. 20. 16 SECTION 3. CA STANDARD California Geometry Content Standards (Continued) 19. Students use trigonometric functions to solve for an unknown length of a side of a right triangle, given an angle and a length of a side. 20. Students know and are able to use angle and side relationships in problems with special right triangles, such as 30 , 60 , and 90 triangles and 45 , 45 , and 90 triangles. 21. Students prove and solve problems regarding relationships among chords, se- cants, tangents, inscribed angles, and inscribed and circumscribed polygons of circles. 22. Students know the eect of rigid motions on gures in the coordinate The Dragon of Proof CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  21. 21. Section 4 Common Core The Common Core Standards Initiative has been an attempt to unify the variously confusing and conicting state curricula and to bring them into alignment with one another. It is coordinated by the National Gover- nors Association for Best Practices (NGA) and the Council of Chief State Schools Ocers (CCSSO). These standards1 attempt to dened the knowl- edge and skills that students should acquire during their K-12 education, in order to survive basic college curricula once they graduate. Common Core Standards: Goals 1. Are aligned with college and work expectations; 2. Are clear, understandable and consistent; 3. Include rigorous content and application of knowledge through high-order skills; 4. Build upon strengths and lessons of current state standards; 5. Are informed by other top performing countries, so that all students are prepared to succeed in our global economy and society; and 6. Are evidence-based. The mathematics standards are progressive, with each level keyed to the next, so that upon successful completion at any given level, the student is prepared for the subsequent level. They provide for a strong foundation in numbers and basic operations (addition, subtraction, multiplication, divi- sion) and fractions at the elementary school levels; geometry, algebra, and probability and statistics in middle school; and and am emphasis on math- ematical modeling (applying math to practical problems) in high school. 1see http://www.corestandards.org/about-the-standards 17
  22. 22. 18 SECTION 4. COMMON CORE At all levels the standards stress both procedural skill and conceptual un- derstanding. The state of California has rewritten its content standards in terms of the common core.2 California Common Core Standards for High School Geometry Congruence Experiment with transformations in the plane Understand congruence in terms of rigid motions Prove geometric theorems Make geometric constructions Similarity, Right Triangles, and Trigonometry Understand similarity in terms of similarity transformations Prove theorems involving similarity Dene trigonometric ratios and solve problems involving right triangles Apply trigonometry to general triangles Circles Understand and apply theorems about circles Find arc lengths and areas of sectors of circles Expressing Geometric Properties with Equations Translate between the geometric description and the equation for a conic section Use coordinates to prove simple geometric theorems algebraically Geometric Measurement and Dimension Explain volume formulas and use them to solve problems Visualize relationships between two-dimensional and three-dimensional objects Modeling with Geometry Apply geometric concepts in modeling situations What the standards NCTM, California, or Common Core do NOT specify is how to develop these concepts. Whether one should follow an axiomatic Euclidean development, or the logical framework established by Hilbert, or start with the smaller sets of axioms developed by groups such as the School Mathematics Study Group (SMSG), the University of Chicago School Mathematics Group (UCSMG) is left up to the individual school (teacher, district, etc). As a teacher learning the advanced mathematical content behind these standards, it is important for you to understand each of these perspectives so that you will understand where the framework that is actually in use in your eventual school placement ts into the big picture. 2See http://www.cde.ca.gov/be/st/ss/. More detail is given in the standard; the box given here is just from the summary page. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  23. 23. Section 5 Logic and Proof in Mathematics This section is intentionally concise as it should be a review of Math 320. The language of mathematics is formal. Statements can be written down in a form that separates their content from their meaning in order to establish consistency and validity. We start with a set of undened terms that are accepted as given without further explanation, such as point, line, plane. Usually these terms can be dened in some further reduced terms but, like a dictionary, we will eventually run into circular denitions if we attempt to continue to rene the denitions, or we end up with a statement that doesnt really make much sense: A point is that of which there is no part. [Euclid, denition 1] Does this really clarify what a point is? Thus it is best to choose our undened terms as something that is more-or-less agreed upon. Following the undened terms, we can dene additional objects in terms of the undened. We then need to state our assumptions. These are called postulates or axioms; in Euclids system there are ve. Next, we have a system of rules for obtaining new true statements from our postulates. This is our logical system. We will sometimes dene new symbols as shorthands to represent parts of our logical system. The true statements are called theorems, and the sequence of steps that justies the validity of the theorem is called a proof. We will write all of 19
  24. 24. 20 SECTION 5. LOGIC AND PROOF our theorems in the following manner: If [hypothesis] then [conclusion] We can give our statements names, like A and B, in which case we write: A B which we read as If A then B or A implies B. For a theorem to be accepted as a true, it must have a proof. A is a list of statements that justies a theorem. Each step must be justied (or explained) by one of the following methods: By hypothesis ... (assume that ...) By axiom X ... (or theorem, denition, postulate, ...) By step Y ... (an earlier step in the proof) By a rule of symbolic logic We will discuss some of the rules of symbolic (formal) logic shortly. There are two special types of theorems: a lemma, and a corollary. Logi- cally there is no dierence between a theorem, a lemma, and a corollary. A lemma is a theorem which is not really interesting (according to the author) in itself, or is a result that is not pertinent to the subject at hand, but is only stated only because it makes the proof of some other theorem more interesting. A corollary is a theorem that follows almost immediately as a result of another theorem with very little proof. A statement A in our logical system will only be allowed to have two values: True and False (we may denote these values by T and F). Just writing a statement does not make it true: If ABC is any triangle then it is equilateral would have a truth value of False. The value of any implication (A B) is given by the following truth table: A B A B true true true true false false false true true false false true The negation operation ( A) turns true to false and false to true. We use negation to prove theorems according to method of RAA (Reductio ad CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  25. 25. SECTION 5. LOGIC AND PROOF 21 absurdum): To prove that A B, assume B and deduce something that is not true. We dene the operations of and (AB) and or (AB) as meaning follows: A B A B A B T T T T T F F T F T F T F F F F We can remember this truth table by the following rule: AB means either A is true or B is true, or both are true; and A B means both A and B are true. The Law of Excluded Middles says that for any statement A, either A is true, or A is true: P, P P The converse of the theorem A B is B A. The converse is a com- pletely dierent statement, and may or may not be true. If both a theorem and its converse are true, we call the theorem a logical equivalence. We write this as A B or A i B is read as A if and only if B and means (A B) (B A) The contrapositive of a theorem A B is B A. The contra- positive is equivalent to the original theorem. This is demonstrated by the following truth table. A B A B A B A B T T T F F T T F F F T F F T T T F T F F T T T T The universal quantier x is read as for all x. The statement (x)(S(x)) means for all x, the statement S(x) is true. The existential quantier y is read as there exists y. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  26. 26. 22 SECTION 5. LOGIC AND PROOF Rene Descartes explaining math to Queen Christina of Sweden (Pierre Louis Dumesnil, 1698-1781); copy by Nils Forsberg (1884). We can then derive the following additional rules of logic using truth tables. ( A) A (5.1) (A B) A B (5.2) A B A B (5.3) (A B) ( A) ( B) (5.4) [xF(x)] x F(x) (5.5) [xF(x)] x F(x) (5.6) The following rule is known as the rule of detachment or modus ponens, [A (A B)] B (5.7) In other words, if A is true, and we know that A B, then we also know CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  27. 27. SECTION 5. LOGIC AND PROOF 23 that B is true. We also have the following rules of deduction: [(A B) (B C)] [A C] (5.8) [A B] A (5.9) For the following example, recall that a rational number is any number x that can be expressed as the ratio of two integers, e.g., x = p/q, where both p and q are integers. An irrational number is a number that is not rational. Example 5.1 Prove that 2 is irrational. Proof. 1. Assume that 2 is rational. (RAA hypothesis) 2. There exists integers p and q such that 2 = p/q (Denition of a rational number) 3. Assume that p and q have no common factors (from our knowledge of numbers we know that we can cancel out all common factors). 4. Therefore at least one of p and q is odd. (otherwise there would be a common factor of 2, which contradicts step 3 5. Since p2 = 2q2 , p is divisible by 2, hence it is even. 6. Write p = 2s where s is an integer (denition of even). 7. Then 4s2 = p2 = 2q2 q2 = 2s2 8. Then q2 is divisible by 2, hence it is even (denition of even). 9. Hence q is even because the square of any odd number must be odd. 10. Since p and q are even this contradicts step 4. Hence our RAA as- sumption is false. We numbered the steps in this proof for clarity. In general we dont do this, because it is somewhat tedious and takes up a lot of space, and instead usually write them as a paragraph. However, until you are comfortable writing proofs, you should write them out in a step-by-step manner. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  28. 28. 24 SECTION 5. LOGIC AND PROOF I Geometry! CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  29. 29. Section 6 The Real Numbers We will take the terms set and element as undened terms. We write a set as the list of elements surrounded by curly brackets: {A, B, C, ...} or by a rule {x|S(x)} where S(x) is some rule such as x is even. We use x S to represent x is an element of the set S. We denote the natural numbers by N = {1, 2, 3, . . . }, the integers by Z = {. . . , 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, . . . }, and the positive integers by Z+ = {0, 1, 2, ..} The union of two sets S and T is given by S T = {x|x S x T} 0This section is intended primarily as a review and hence is necessarily concise. 25
  30. 30. 26 SECTION 6. REAL NUMBERS The intersection of two sets S and T is given by S T = {x|x S x T} We will use the notation A B to indicate set dierence, which we read a A minus B A B = {x|(x A) (x B)} Venema (and some other texts) use the notation A B for this set. The symbol represents the empty set. The symbol Q represents the set of all rational numbers. A rational number r is a quotient of two integers p and q, where r = p/q The symbol R represents the set of all real numbers. We will not give a denition of real numbers, but example 5.1 shows that there are numbers that are not rational. Any real number that cannot be expressed as a rational number is called an irrational number. We will see later that there is a one-to-one correspondence between the points on a line and the real numbers, so in a sense, the real numbers give us anything we can measure. Axiom 6.1 (Trichotomy of the Real Numbers) Let x, y R. Then exactly one of the following is true: x < y, x = y, or x > y Axiom 6.2 (Density) Let x < y R. Then both of the following are true: 1. There exists a rational number q such that x < q < y 2. There exists an irrational number z such that x < z < y Corollary 6.3 There is an irrational number between any two rational numbers. Corollary 6.4 There is a rational number between any two irrational num- bers. Theorem 6.5 (Comparison Theorem) Suppose that x, y R satisfy 1. For every rational number q < x, q < y 2. For every rational number q < y, q < x then x = y. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  31. 31. SECTION 6. REAL NUMBERS 27 Denition 6.6 (Upper Bound) A number M is called an upper bound for a set A if x A, x M. Denition 6.7 (Least Upper Bound) A number m is called a least upper bound for a set A if for all upper bounds M of A, m M, and we write m = lubA. Axiom 6.8 (Least Upper Bound Axiom) Every bounded non-empty subset of the real numbers has a least upper bound. Babylonian clay tablet YBC 7289 (c 1800-1600 BC) showing 2 1 + 21 60 + 51 602 + 10 603 (gure Bill Casselman http://www.math.ubc.ca/ ~cass/Euclid/ybc/ybc.html.) The following property expresses the notion that you can ll up a bucket with spoonfuls of water. We will accept it as an axiom although it fact it can be derived from the Least Upper Bound Axiom. Axiom 6.9 (Archimedian Property) If M > 0, > 0 are both real numbers than there exists a postive integer n such that n > M. Denition 6.10 (Function) A function f is a rule that assigns to each element a A an element b = f(a) B. We call A the domain of f, and we call the subset of B to which elements of A are mapped by f the range of f. We write f : A B. Denition 6.11 A function f : A B is one-to-one (sometimes 1-1 or (1:1)) if a1 = a2 f(a1) = f(a2) Denition 6.12 A function f : A B is onto if (b B)(a A) such that b = f(a). Denition 6.13 A function f : A B that is 1-1 and onto is called a one-to-one-correspondence. Denition 6.14 A function f(x) is continuous on an interval (a, b) if for every > 0 there exists a > 0 such that whenever |xy| < , x, y (a, b), then |f(x) f(y)| < . Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  32. 32. 28 SECTION 6. REAL NUMBERS The Sum of the Squares ... CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  33. 33. Section 7 Euclids Elements Euclid at the Oxford History Museum. Here and in the following sections we will present some of the axiomatic systems that have been used to develop geometry in the west since Euclids time. We will not be using any of thse specic systems in our own de- velopment but they are worth being familiar with. Euclids Elements was written around 300 BC. It consists of 13 Books that are a compila- tion of geometric knowledge that had beed ac- quired over the previous several centuries. We dont know what (if any) parts of it are orig- inal to Euclid. The great contribution of this document is that it sets forth a set of basic as- sumptions (ve postulates) from which all of the remainder of the treatise is logically de- rived. Any logical system requires one to rst dene some basic concepts which are accepted on faith; for geometry these are thinks like points and lines. In fact, Eculid states 23 denitions before his postulates, and follows them with ve additional common notions, which are statements that he expects are so obvious they can be accepted by anyone with reason. It is worth looking at these basic statements to get a feeling for where Euclids geometry starts, so they are extracted below[Euclid]. 29
  34. 34. 30 SECTION 7. EUCLIDS ELEMENTS Euclids Axioms 1 Let it have been postulated to draw a straight-line from any point to any point. 2 And to produce a nite straight-line continuously in a straight-line. 3 And to draw a circle with any center and radius. 4 And that all right-angles are equal to one another. 5 Euclids Parallel postulate. And that if a straight-line falling across two (other) straight-lines makes internal angles on the same side (of itself whose sum is) less than two right-angles, then the two (other) straight-lines, being produced to innity, meet on that side (of the original straight-line) that the (sum of the internal angles) is less than two right-angles (and do not meet on the other side) (see gure 7.1.) Historically the 5th postulate has been considered separate from the rst four and was followed by over 2000 years of at- tempts to derive it from them. It was not until the 19th century (by Euge- nio Beltrami in 1868) that it was shown that postulate 5 could not be derived from the other four. In the process, the existence of non-Euclidean geometries was proven, as well as neutral geometry, the study of the consequences of the rst four postulates. Euclid presumably stated his common notions to make clear what assump- tions he was making that he thought were obvious. Today we would prob- ably state them using algebra, but such expressions had not been invented yet. 0Euclids line is what we call a plane curve. 0Euclids straight-line is what we would call a line segment. The modern concept of a line that extends innitely in each direction was unknown to Euclid. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  35. 35. SECTION 7. EUCLIDS ELEMENTS 31 Euclids Denitions 1 A point is that of which there is no part. 2 And a line1 is a length without breadth. 3 And the extremities of a line are points. 4 A straight-line2 is (any) one which lies evenly with points on itself. 5 And a surface is that which has length and breadth only. 6 And the extremities of a surface are lines. 7 A plane surface is (any) one which lies evenly with the straight-lines on itself. 8 And a plane angle is the inclination of the lines to one another, when two lines in a plane meet one another, and are not lying in a straight-line. 9 And when the lines containing the angle are straight then the angle is called rectilinear. 10 And when a straight-line stood upon (another) straight-line makes adjacent angles (which are) equal to one another, each of the equal angles is a right-angle, and the former straight-line is called a perpendicular to that upon which it stands. 11 An obtuse angle is one greater than a right-angle. 12 And an acute angle (is) one less than a right-angle. 13 A boundary is that which is the extremity of something. 14 A gure is that which is contained by some boundary or boundaries. 15 A circle is a plane gure contained by a single line [which is called a circumference], (such that) all of the straight-lines radiating towards [the circumference] from one point amongst those lying inside the gure are equal to one another. 16 And the point is called the center of the circle. 17 And a diameter of the circle is any straight-line, being drawn through the center, and terminated in each direction by the circumference of the circle. (And) any such (straight-line) also cuts the circle in half. 18 And a semi-circle is the gure contained by the diameter and the circumference cuts o by it. And the center of the semi-circle is the same (point) as (the center of) the circle. 19 Rectilinear gures are those (gures) contained by straight-lines: trilateral gures being those contained by three straight-lines, quadrilateral by four, and multilateral by more than four. 20 And of the trilateral gures: an equilateral triangle is that having three equal sides, an isosceles (triangle) that having only two equal sides, and a scalene (triangle) that having three unequal sides. 21 And further of the trilateral gures: a right-angled triangle is that having a right- angle, an obtuse-angled (triangle) that having an obtuse angle, and an acute-angled (triangle) that having three acute angles. 22 And of the quadrilateral gures: a square is that which is right-angled and equilateral, a rectangle that which is right-angled but not equilateral, a rhombus that which is equilateral but not right-angled, and a rhomboid that having opposite sides and angles equal to one another which is neither right-angled nor equilateral. And let quadrilateral gures besides these be called trapezia. 23 Parallel lines are straight-lines which, being in the same plane, and being produced to innity in each direction, meet with one another in neither (of these directions). Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  36. 36. 32 SECTION 7. EUCLIDS ELEMENTS Figure 7.1: Illustration of Euclids Parallel postulate. The two angles and add to les than 180 degrees, hence the lines h and k meet at a point S on the same same side of g as and . Euclids Common Notions 1 Things equal to the same thing are also equal to one another We might write this today as: If a = b and b = c then a = c. 2 And if equal things are added to equal things then the wholes are equal. We might write this as: if a = c then a + b = c + b. 3 And if equal things are subtracted from equal things then the remainders are equal. Which we might write this as: if a = c then a b = c b. 4 And things coinciding with one another are equal to one another. By this Euclid meant he could imagine picking up the picture of a triangle (or some other object) and lay it on top of another; if they were the same then they were considered equal (or maybe congruent). 5 And the whole [is] greater than the part Which we might write as: if a > 0 and b > 0 then a + b > a and a + b > b. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  37. 37. Section 8 Hilberts Axioms David Hilbert (1862-1943) boiled geometry down to 20 axioms which he classied into seven axioms of connection (we now use the term incidence); ve axioms of order; one axiom of parallels; six axioms of congruence; and one axiom of continuity. He did this because it had been discovered over the centuries that Euclid had left out parts of his arguments and Hilbert was attempting to ll in all the blanks. The axioms below are taken from the lecture notes of his course in geometry given in 1898 and translated by E.J. Townsend in 1902. Hilberts system begins with the follow- ing undened terms: point, line, plane, lie on, between, congruent. His axioms are divided up into dierent sub-areas of geometry: connection, order, paral- lels, congruence, continuity, and com- pleteness. The axioms of connection de- ne things like how points form lines and planes. The axioms of order express the concept of betweenness of points. They are classied into four linear ax- ioms of order and one plane axiom of or- der. The axiom of parallels is a equiva- lent to Euclids parallel postulate. The axioms of congruence formalize our intu- itive notions of equivalences among line segments, angles, and triangles. The ax- 33
  38. 38. 34 SECTION 8. HILBERTS AXIOMS iom of continuity introduces the continuity of real numbers to geometry, and completeness tells us that everything we can possibly know we can learn from these axioms. Hilberts Axioms of Connection 1. Two distinct points A and B always completely determine a straight line a. We write AB = a or BA = a. 2. Any two distinct points of a straight line completely determine that line; that is, if AB = a and AC = a, where B = C, then also BC = a. 3. Three points A, B, C not situated in the same straight line always completely deter- minea plane . We write ABC = . 4. Any three points A, B, C of a plane , which do not lie in the same straight line,completely determine that plane. 5. If two points A, B of a straight line a lie in a plane , then every point of a lies in . 6. If two planes , have a point A in common, then they have at least a second point B in common. 7. Upon every straight line there exist at least two points, in every plane at least three points not lying in the same straight line, and in space there exist at least four points not lying in a plane. Hilberts Axioms of Order 1. If A, B, C are points of a straight line and B lies between A and C, then B lies also between C and A. 2. If A and C are two points of a straight line, then there exists at least one point B lying between A and C and at least one point D so situated that C lies between A and D. 3. Of any three points situated on a straight line, there is always one and only one which lies between the other two. 4. Any four points A, B, C, D of a straight line can always be so arranged that B shall lie between A and C and also between A and D, and, furthermore, that C shalllie between A and D and also between B and D. 5. Let A, B, C be three points not lying in the same straight line and let a be a straight line lying in the plane ABC and not passing through any of the points A, B, C. Then, if the straight line a passes through a point of the segment AB, it will also pass through either a point of the segment BC or a point of the segment AC. Hilberts Axiom of Parallels In a plane there can be drawn through any point A, lying outside of a straight line a, one and only one straight line which does not intersect the line a. This straight line is called the parallel to a through the given point A. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  39. 39. SECTION 8. HILBERTS AXIOMS 35 Hilberts Axioms of Congruence 1. If A, B are two points on a straight line a, and if A is a point upon the same or another straight line a1, then, upon a given side of A on the straight line a , we can always nd one and only one point B so that the segment AB (or BA) is congruent to the segment A B . We indicate this relation by writing AB = A B Every segment is congruent to itself; that is, we always have AB = AB. 2. If AB = A B and also AB = A B , then A B = A B 3. Let AB and BC be two segments of a straight line a which have no points in common aside from the point B, and, furthermore, let A B and B C be two segments of the same or of another straight line a having, likewise, no point other than B in common. Then, if AB A B and BC = B C , we have AC = A C . 4. Let an angle (h, k) be given in the plane and let a straight line a be given in a plane . Suppose also that, in the plane , a denite side of the straight line a be assigned. Denote by h a half-ray of the straight line a emanating from a point O of this line. Then in the plane there is one and only one half-ray k such that the angle (h, k), or (k, h), is congruent to the angle (h , k ) and at the same time all interior points of the angle (h , k ) lie upon the given side of a . We express this relation by means of the notation (h, k) = (h , k ) Every angle is congruent to itself; that is, (h, k) = (h, k). 5. If the (h, k) = (h , k ) and (h, k) = (h , k ) then (h , k ) = (h , k ) 6. If, in the two triangles ABC and A B C the congruences ABV A B, AC = A C and BAC = B A C then ABC = A B C and ACB = A C B . Hilberts Axiom of Continuity (Archimedian Axiom) Let A1A be any point on a straight line AB. Choose A2, A3, .. so that A1 is between A and A2, A2 is between A1 and A3, etc, such that AA1 = A1A2 = A2A3 = Then there always exists a certain point An such that B lies between A and An. In more modern terms, > 0 and x > 0, then m N such that m > x. Hilberts Axioms of Completeness To a system of points, straight lines, and planes, it is impossible to add other elements in such a manner that the system thus generalized shall form a new geometry obeying all of the ve groups of axioms. In other words, the elements of geometry form a system which is not susceptible of extension, if we regard the ve groups of axioms as valid. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  40. 40. 36 SECTION 8. HILBERTS AXIOMS CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  41. 41. Section 9 Birkho/MacLane Axioms Birkho (left); MacLane (right) Geroge Birkho (1884-1944) is best known for his works on dierential equa- tions, taught at Univ. of Wisconsin, Princeton, and Harvard. In 1932 he pro- posed a very compact set of axioms which allow you to use a ruler (a straight edge with marks on it) and a protractor. His purpose was to make geometry more un- derstandable to high school students.1 Saunders MacLane (1909-2005) was a friend (and professional collaborator) of George Birkhos son Garrett, and worked primarily at Harvard (where he met the Birkhos) and the Univ. of Chicago. 2 In 1959 [MacLane, 1959] proposed an extension of Birkhos Axioms that included a distance measure thereby making the system some- what more intuitive than Hilberts. MacLane introduced the concept of distance metrics into the axioms, and added an axiom of continuity. 1The system was published in the paper A Set of Postulate for Plane Geometry based on a Scale and Protractor, in Annals of Mathematics, 33:329-345 (1932). 2he photo is by Konrad Jacobs (CCASA license) and from Wikimedia). 37
  42. 42. 38 SECTION 9. BIRKHOFF/MACLANE AXIOMS Birkhos Axioms Undened Terms: point, line, distance, angle. 1. Axiom of Line Measure. The points A, B, .. of any line l can be put into (1, 1) correspondence with the real numbers x so that |xB xA| = d(A, B) for all points A, B. Here d(A, B) denotes the distance between the points A and B. In other words, you are allowed to use a rule to measure the length of a line. 2. The point-line postulate. One and only one straight line l contains two given points P, Q (P = Q). 3. The Axiom of angle measure. The half lines l, m, .. through any point O can be put into (1,1) correspondence with teh real numbers a mod 2 so that, if A = 0 and B = O are points of l and m respectively, the dierence am al mod 2 is A0B. 4. The Postulate of triangle similarity. If in two triangles, ABC and A B C , of for some constant k > 0, d(A , B ) = kd(A, B), d(A , C ) = kd(A, C), and also B A C = BAC then also d(B , C ) = kd(B, C), C B A = CBA, A C B = ACB. MacLanes Axioms on Distance 1. There are at least two points. 2. If A and B are points, d(AB) is a nonnegative number (that gives the distance between the points). 3. For points A and B, d(AB) = 0 if and only if A = B. 4. If A and B are points then d(AB) = d(BA). MacLanes Axioms on Lines 1. A l ine is a set of points containing more than one points. 2. Through two distinct points there is one and only one l ine. 3. Three distinct points on a line if and only if one of them is between the other two. 4. On each ray from a point O and to each positive real number b there is a point B with d(OB) = b MacLanes Axioms on Angles 1. If r and s are rays from the same point, then rs is a real number (mod 360). 2. If r, s, t are three rays from the same point, the rs + st = rt. 3. If r is a ray from O and c is a real number, then there is a ray s from O such that rs = c. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  43. 43. SECTION 9. BIRKHOFF/MACLANE AXIOMS 39 McLanes Axiom on Similarity If two triangles ABC and A B C have ABC = A B C , d(AB) = kd(A B ), and d(BC) = kd(B C ) for some postive number k then they are similar. MacLanes Axiom of Continuity Let AOB be proper. If D is between A adn B then 0 < AOD < AOB. Here a proper angle is an angle x such that 0 < x < 180. The 37th View of Mt Fuji by Katsushika Hokusai (1760-1849) never made it to wood block. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  44. 44. 40 SECTION 9. BIRKHOFF/MACLANE AXIOMS A Geometric Mind CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  45. 45. Section 10 The SMSG Axioms The School Mathematics Study Group (SMSG) at Yale University was funded by the US National Science Foundation to reform mathematics ed- ucation in the 1950s and developed mathematical curricula that came be know as the new math during the 1960s. A set of 22 s that were intended to make geometry more intuitive and understandable were produced by this group, as was a mimeographed textbook that was later used as the basis of a geometry textbook by E.E. Moise and F.L.Downs (1964) that is still in circulation. Some of the axioms are redundant in the sense that they can be derived from the others. The undened terms are point, line, plane, lie on, distance, angle measure, area, volume, and there are 22 axioms. Axiom 1 Given any two distinct points there is exactly one line that con- tains them. Axiom 2 Distance Postulate. To every pair of distinct points there cor- responds a unique positive number. This number is called the distance between the two points. Axiom 3 Ruler Postulate. The points of a line can be placed in a corre- spondence with the real numbers such that: (1) To every point of the line there corresponds exactly one real number; (2) To every real number there corresponds exactly one point of the line. (3) The distance between two distinct points is the absolute value of the dierence of the corresponding real numbers. Axiom 4 Ruler Placement Postulate. Given two points P and Q of a line, the coordinate system can be chosen in such a way that the coordinate of 41
  46. 46. 42 SECTION 10. THE SMSG AXIOMS P is zero and the coordinate of Q is positive. Axiom 5 Every plane contains at least three non-collinear points, and space contains at least four non-coplanar points. Axiom 6 If two points lie in a plane, then the line containing these points lies in the same plane. Axiom 7 Any three points lie in at least one plane, and any three non- collinear points lie in exactly one plane. Axiom 8 If two planes intersect, then that intersection is a line. Edward Grith Begle (1941-1978), director of SMSG for ten years. Photograph by Paul Halmos, Archives of American Mathematics, Dolph Briscoe Center for American History, University of Texas at Austin. Axiom 9 Plane Separation Postulate. Given a line and a plane containing it, the points of the plane that do not lie on the line form two sets such that: (1) each of the sets is convex; and (2) if P is in one set and Q is in the other, then segment PQ intersects the line. Axiom 10 Space Separation Postulate. The points of space that do not lie in a given plane form two sets such that: (1) Each of the sets is convex; and (2) If P is in one set and Q is in the other, then segment PQ intersects the plane. Axiom 11 Angle Measurement Postulate. To every angle x there corre- sponds a real number between 0 and 180 . The real number is called the measure of the angle and denoted by m(x). Axiom 12 Angle Construction postulate. Let AB be a ray on the edge of the half-plane H. For every r between 0 and 180 there is exactly one ray CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  47. 47. SECTION 10. THE SMSG AXIOMS 43 AP, with P in H such that m(PAB) = r. Axiom 13 Angle Addition postulate. If D is a point in the interior of BAC, then mBAC) = m(BAD) + m(DAC). Axiom 14 Supplement postulate. If two angles form a linear pair, then they are supplementary. Axiom 15 SAS postulate. Given a one-to-one correspondence between two triangles (or between a triangle and itself). If two sides nd the included angle of the rst triangle are congruent to the corresponding parts of the second triangle, then the correspondence is a congruence. Axiom 16 Parallel postulate. Through a given external point there is at most one line parallel to a given line. Axiom 17 To every polygonal region there corresponds a unique positive real number called its area. Axiom 18 If two triangles are congruent, then the triangular regions have the same area. Axiom 19 Suppose that the region R is the union of two regions R1 and R2. If R1 and R2 intersect at most in a nite number of segments and points, then the area of R is the sum of the areas of R1 and R2. Axiom 20 The area of a rectangle is the product of the length of its and the length of its altitude. Axiom 21 The volume of a rectangle parallelepiped is equal to the product of the length of its altitude and the area of its base. Axiom 22 Cavalieris Principle. Given two solids and a plane. If for every plane that intersects the solids and is parallel to the given plane the two intersections determine regions that have the same area, then the two solids have the same volume. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  48. 48. 44 SECTION 10. THE SMSG AXIOMS CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  49. 49. Section 11 The UCSMP Axioms The University of Chicago School Mathemat- ics Project was founded in 1983 with the aim of upgrading mathematics education in el- ementary and secondary schools throughout the United States. They have developed a set of axioms that are in wide use today, and are also redundant in the sense that some axioms can be proved from others. The purpose of the redundancy was to make the learning of ge- ometry more intuitive. These axioms used in- corporated a transformational approach. De- tails of the projects history is given on its web page at (http://ucsmp.uchicago.edu/ history.html). Many of todays elementary and secondary textbooks are based on these standards, which encompass all of mathematics, not just geometry. The only undened terms are point, line, and plane. Point-Line-Plane Axioms Axiom 1 Through any two points there is exactly one line. Axiom 2 Every line is a set of points that can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the real numbers, with any point corresponding to zero and any other point corresponding to the number 1. Axiom 3 Given a line in a plane, there is at least one point in the plane that is not on the line. Given a plane in space, there is at least one point 45
  50. 50. 46 SECTION 11. THE UCSMP AXIOMS in space that is not on the plane. Axiom 4 If two points lie in a plane, the line containing them lies in the plane. Axiom 5 Through three non-collinear points, there is exactly one plane. Axiom 6 If two dierent planes have a point in common, then their inter- section is a line. Distance Axioms Axiom 7 On a line, there is a unique distance between two points. Axiom 8 If two points on a line have coordinates x and y the distance between them is |x y|. Axiom 9 If point B is on the line segment AC then AB + BC = AC, where AB, BC, AC denote the distances between the points. Triangle Inequality Axiom 10 The sum of the lengths of two sides of a triangle is greater than the length of the third side. Angle Measure Axiom 11 Every angle has a unique measure from 0 to 180 . Axiom 12 Given any ray V A and a real number r between 0 and 180 there is a unique angle BV A in each half-plane of V A such that BV A = r. Axiom 13 If V A and V B are the same ray, then BV A = 0. Axiom 14 If V A and V B are opposite rates, then BV A = 180. Axiom 15 If V C (except for the point V ) is in the interior of angle AV B then AV C + CV B = AV B. Corresponding Angle Axiom Axiom 16 Suppose two coplanar lines are cut by a transversal. If two corresponding angles have the same measure, then the lines are parallel. If the lines are parallel, then the corresponding angles have the same measure. Reection Axioms Axiom 17 There is a one to one correspondence between points and their images in a reection. Axiom 18 Collinearity is preserved by reection. Axiom 19 Betweenness is preserved by reection. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  51. 51. SECTION 11. THE UCSMP AXIOMS 47 Axiom 20 Distance is preserved by reection. Axiom 21 Angle measure is preserved by reection. Axiom 22 Orientation is reversed by reection. Area Axioms Axiom 23 Given a unit region, every polygonal region has a unique area. Axiom 24 The area of a rectangle with dimensions l and w is lw. Axiom 25 Congruent gures have the same area. Axiom 26 The areas of the union of two non-overlapping regions is the sum of the areas of the regions. Volume Axioms Axiom 27 Given a unit cube,every solid region has a unique volume. Axiom 28 The volume of box with dimensions l, w, and h is lwh. Axiom 29 Congruent solids have the same volume. Axiom 30 The volume of the union of two non-overlapping solids is the sum of their volumes. Axiom 31 Given two solids and a plane. If for every plane which intersects the solids and is parallel to the given plane the intersections have equal areas, then the two solids have the same volume. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  52. 52. 48 SECTION 11. THE UCSMP AXIOMS CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  53. 53. Section 12 Venemas Axioms Venema [Venema, 2006] introduces a set of axioms that meld together parts of the axiom systems of Birkho, MacLane, the SMSG, and the UCSMP. We present them here for reference, since we will be using this system in the remainder of the class. Venemas Undened Terms The undened terms are point, line, distance, half-plane, angle-measure, area Venemas Axioms of Neutral Geometry Existence says that at least some points exist, and incidents says that every pair of distinct points denes a line. 1. Existence Postulate. The collection of all points forms a nonempty set with more than one (i.e., at least two) points. The set of all points in the plane is called P. 2. Incidence Postulate. Every line is a set of points. For every pair of distinct points A, B there is exactly one line = AB such that A, B . The ruler postulate allows us to associate real numbers and hence mea- surements with distances and line segments. 49
  54. 54. 50 SECTION 12. VENEMAS AXIOMS 3. Ruler Postulate. For every pair of points P, Q there is a number PQ called the distance from P to Q. For each line there is a one-to-one mapping f : R such that if x = f(P) and y = f(Q) then PQ = |x y|. The Plane Separation Postulate says that a line has two sides; it is used to dene the concept of a half-plane. 4. Plane Separation Postulate. For every line the points that do not lie on form two disjoint, convex non-empty sets H1 and H2, called half-planes, bounded by such that if P H1 and Q H2 then PQ intersects . The protractor postulate encapsulates our common notions (to use a Euclidean term) about angles: they can be measure, added, and ordered. 5. Protractor Postulate. For every angle BAC there is a real number (BAC) called the measure of BAC such that 1. 0 (BAC) < 180 2. (BAC) = 0 AB = BC 3. Angle Construction Postulate. r R such that 0 < r < 180, and for every half-plane H bounded by AB, there exists a unique ray AE such that E H and (BAE) = r. 4. Angle Addition Postulate. If the ray AD is between the rays AB and AC then (BAD) + (DAC) = (BAC) As we shall see later in the discussion, the rst ve postulates are not sucient to ensure that our common notions about triangle congruence will hold (for example, the following postulate fails in taxi-cab geometry). 6. SAS (Side Angle Side Postulate) If ABC and DEF are two triangles such that AB = DE,BC = EF, and ABC = DEF then ABC = DEF. Parallel Postulates The combination of the rst six postulates, when taken together, are known as neutral geometry. They can be extended with one of three possible par- allel postulates. It turns out that the second of these the elliptic parallel postulate, is inconsistent with the plane separation postulate and the con- cept of betweenness but the other two postulates are each consistent with neutral geometry. In fact, it can be proven that they are mutually exclusive if you accept either one of the Hyperbolic or Euclidean parallel postulates CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  55. 55. SECTION 12. VENEMAS AXIOMS 51 under neutral geometry, the other is provably false; and if either is taken as false, the other is provably true. Euclidean Parallel Postulate For every line and for every external point P, there is exactly one line m such that P lies on m and m Elliptic Parallel Postulate For every line and for every external point P, there is no line m such that P lies on m and m Hyperbolic Parallel Postulate For every line and for every external point P, there are at least two lines m and n such that P lies on both m and m and m and n . Area Postulates Neutral Area Postulate Associated with each polygonal region R there is a nonnegative number (R), called the area of R, such that: 1. (Congruence) If two triangles are congruent, then their associate re- gions have equal area; and 2. (Additivity) If R = R1 R2 and R1 and R2 do not overlap, then (R) = (R1) + (R2) Euclidean Area Postulate (Venema 9.2.2) If R is a rectangle, the (R) = length(R) width(R). Reection The Reection Postulate (Venema 12.6.1) For every line there exists a transformation : P P such that: 1. If P then (P) = P 2. If P , then P and (P) lie on opposite half planes of . 3. preserves distance, collinearity, and angle measure. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  56. 56. 52 SECTION 12. VENEMAS AXIOMS CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  57. 57. Section 13 Incidence Geometry We will use the expression a geometry to refer to the consequences of a particular set of axioms. For example by Hilbert Geometry we mean the geometry that is the consequence of Hilberts axioms; by Euclidean Geometry we mean the consequences of Euclids Axioms, etc. Here we will describe a particular type of nite geometry, that is, a geometry with a nite number of points. Incidence Geometry is a term we will use for the geometry that we can derive from the following three axioms. Axiom 13.1 (Incidence Axiom 1) For every pair of distinct points P and Q there exists exactly one line such that both P and Q lie on . Axiom 13.2 (Incidence Axiom 2) For every line there exists at least two distinct points P and Q such both P and Q lie on . Axiom 13.3 (Incidence Axiom 3) There exist three points that do not all lie on the same line, i.e., there exists three non-collinear points. Denition 13.4 Three points A, B, C are collinear if there exists at least one line such that all three points line on . They are said to be non- collinear if no such line exists. Example 13.1 3-Point Plane Geometry. In this example of a nite geometry that obeys all the axioms of incidence geometry, we dene: A point is an element of the set {A, B, C} A line is a pair of points such as = {A, B} A point P lies on a line if P . 53
  58. 58. 54 SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY Figure 13.1: Graph diagram illustrating three-point geometry. Parallel lines do not exist in this geometry. There are three possible lines in this geometry: {A, B}, {B, C}, {A, C} We will describe nite geometries with graph-diagrams consisting of nodes and line segments (gure 13.1). The nodes represent the points, and the line segments connecting the nodes represent the sets that represent lines. This is a representation of a nite geometry, not a picture of the points of lines in the usual sense. In other words, the 3-point geometry does not look like a triangle; we just represent it by a graph that looks like a triangle. Example 13.2 Four-point Geometry. Here we dene (see gure 13.2): A point is an element of the set {A, B, C, D} A line is a pair of points such as = {A, B} A point P lies on a line if P . There are six lines in this example: {A, B}, {A, C}, {A, D}, {B, C}, {B, D}, and {C, D}. Example 13.3 Fanos Geometry. Here we have seven points given by the set {A, B, C, D, E, F, G} and we dene lines as any of the following seven specic subsets: {A, B, C}, {C, D, E}, {E, F, A}, {A, G, D}, {C, G, F}, {E, G, B}, {B, D, F} as illustrated in gure 13.3 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  59. 59. SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY 55 Figure 13.2: Graph diagram illustrating four-point geometry. Every line has precisely one other line that is parallel to it, and and there is precisely one parallel line through each point that is not on a given line, and hence four point geometry obeys the Euclidean parallel postulate. Figure 13.3: Graph diagram illustrating Fanos geometry. Each line seg- ment and the circle represents a line in this geometry. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  60. 60. 56 SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY Example 13.4 The Cartesian Plane. This is the traditional example we use in geometry and it obeys all the rules of incidence geometry. Dene a point as an ordered pair of real numbers {x, y}. Then a line is the collection of all points ax + by + c = 0 for some choice of real numbers a, b, c. The usual notation for this set is R2 . Example 13.5 Surface of a Sphere. Consider a unit sphere centered at the origin in normal 3-space. The surface of this sphere is given by the set of all points {x, y, z} such that x2 + y2 + z2 = 1 Dene a point as any point on the surface of the sphere, and dene a line as any great circle on the plane (a great circle is the intersection of the unit sphere with any plane that goes through the center of sphere; or equivalently, it is any circle on the sphere whose radius is equal to the radius of the sphere, which is 1). This geometry does not obey incidence geometry because any two antipodal points (points at opposite poles of the sphere) are on an innite number of common lines. This violates Incidence Axiom 1. Furthermore, there are no parallel lines in this geometry because any two great circles meet. Example 13.6 The Klein Disk. Consider the interior of the unit disk centered at the origin of R2 . This is the set of all points such that x2 + y2 < 1 Dene a point as any ordered pair of numbers (x, y) such that x2 +y2 < 1, and dene a line as any the part of any Euclidean line that lies inside this circle. See gure 13.4. The Klein Disk obeys incidence geometry but does not obey Euclids fth postulate. Denition 13.5 (Parallel Lines) Two lines and m are said to be parallel if there is no point P such that P lies on both and m. We denote this by m. Euclids fth axiom is equivalent to the following statement: Axiom 13.6 (Euclidian Parallel Postulate) For every line and for every point P there is exactly one line m such that P lies on m and m . Four point geometry and geometry of the Cartesian plane each satisfy the Euclidean Parallel Postulate. There are two other possible parallel postulates that are incompatible with the Euclidean Parallel Postulate but which lead to consistent geometries. CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  61. 61. SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY 57 Figure 13.4: A Klein Disk. Lines l and n pass through point P, and are both parallel to line m. The Klein Disk is a model of Hyperbolic Geometry. Axiom 13.7 (Elliptic Parallel Postulate) For every line and for every point P there is no line m such that P lies on m and m . Three-point geometry and geometry on the sphere satisfy the Elliptic par- allel postulate. Axiom 13.8 (Hyperbolic Parallel Postulate) For every line and for every point P there are at least two lines m such that P lies on m and m . The Klein Disk and Five Point geometry (gure 13.5) satisfy the hyperbolic parallel postulate. Theorem 13.9 If and m are distinct, nonparallel lines, then there exists a unique point P such that P lines on both and m. Proof. By hypothesis, = m and m. Then by the negation of the denition of parallel lines, there is a point P that lines on both and m. To proove that P is unique, we assume that there is a second point Q = P that also lies on both lines as our RAA hypothesis. By incidence axiom 1, there is exactly one line n that contains both P and Q. Since P is on , then since n is unique, = n. But since Q is on m, then since n is unique, m = n. Hence = m. This contradicts the hypothesis that = m. Hence our RAA Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  62. 62. 58 SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY Figure 13.5: Illustration of ve point geometry: the points are represented by the symbols A, B, C, D.E and the lines are represented by any subset of precisely two points. Since lines {B, D} and {B, C} are both parallel to line {A, E} and both pass through point B, this model satises the hyperbolic parallel postulate hypothesis must be wrong, i.e., P = Q. Hence the point P is unique. Here are some other useful results that hold in incidence geometry. Theorem 13.10 Let be a line. Then there exists at least one point P that does not lie on . Theorem 13.11 Let P be a point. Then there exist at least two distinct lines that contain P. Proof. By Incidence Axiom 3 there exist at least three points R, S, T that are non-collinear. Either P {R, S, T} or P {R, S, T}. If P {R, S, T} then without loss of generality we can relabel the points so that P = R. Dene = PS and m = PT. Since P, S, T are non-collinear, then and m are the desired lines. If P {R, S, T} then either P RS or P RS. If P RS then let = RS and m = PT. By construction, T RS, else R, S, T would be collinear. Since T m and T , = m. Hence and m are the two distinct lines that contain P. If P RS then let = PR and m = PS. By construction R , but CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  63. 63. SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY 59 R m, else P, R, S would be collinear, and we have assumed otherwise. Hence and m are distinct lines that contain P. Theorem 13.12 Let be a line. Then there exist two distinct lines m and n that intersect . Proof. Let be a line.By incidence axiom 2 there are two points P, Q that lie on . By theorem 13.10 there exists a third point R that does lie on . By incidence axiom 1, there exist lines m = PR and n = QR. Since P and P m, intersects m (denition of intersection). Since Q and Q n, intersects n (denition of intersection). Since R then any line that contains R is dierent from . The two lines m and n contain R, hence m = and n = . Suppose m = n. By denition of m, P m. By dention of n, Q n. Hence if m = n, Q m, i.e., both P and Q line on m. Hence m = by the uniqueness part of incidence axiom 1. This contradicts the previous paragraph, m = . Hence the assumption m = n must be wrong. Hence m = n, which means there are two distinc lines that intersect . Theorem 13.13 Let P be a point. Then there exists at least one line that does not contain P. Theorem 13.14 There exist three distinct lines such that no point lies on all three of them. Theorem 13.15 Let P be a point. Then there exist points Q and R such that P, Q, R are non-collinear. Proof. Let P and Q be points such that Q = P. By incidence axiom 1, there is a unique line that contains P and Q. By theorem 13.10 there exists at least one point R that does lie on . The points P, Q, R are non-collinear. Theorem 13.16 Let P = Q be points. Then there exists a point Q such that P, Q, R are non-collinear. Revised: 18 Nov 2012 CC BY-NC-ND 3.0.
  64. 64. 60 SECTION 13. INCIDENCE GEOMETRY CC BY-NC-ND 3.0. Revised: 18 Nov 2012
  65. 65. Section 14 Betweenness In this section we will begin our formulation of plane geometry based on Venemas axiomatic system. Our undened terms are: point, line, distance, half-plane, and angle measure. Axiom 14.1 (Existence Postulate) The collection of all