Transcript
Page 1: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ���

Stephen E. Rosenbaum, “How to be Dead and Not Care” (1986)

PHIL 102, Fall 2015 UBC

Christina Hendricks

Except images noted otherwise, this presentation is licensed CC-BY 4.0

Page 2: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Nagel: Even if there is nothing after death, is death still a bad thing for the one who dies?

Isn’t it obvious that it is? Why even ask the question?

Page 3: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Epicurus & Lucretius Death can only be bad for a person if they can experience it as bad.

BAD for that person

Page 4: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Nagel’s argument Conclusion: Death is bad for the person who has died. What did you get from his article as to his argument for this?

(Outline it on the board)

Page 5: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Objections 1.  How can we say the dead person has “lost”

anything once they’re dead? They no longer exist.

Reply: think of persons as extended temporally: a combination of their history, their present state, and their future possibilities

Icon  by  Harold  Weaver,  from  the  Noun  Project  

Makes sense of the bad of betrayal?

Page 6: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Objections 2. If death is bad for the person who dies, then

why isn’t the time before birth also bad for him/her? (or is it?)

Reply: If born earlier, wouldn’t be the same person, so couldn’t be bad for him/her.  

Time  1  

Time  2  

Can’t  be  Person  A  

Person  A  

Icon  by  CreaAve  Stall,  from  The  Noun  Project  

Page 7: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Objections 3. Must we take the loss of life as always a bad thing, because a loss of future possibilities, since we are naturally mortal?

Reply: From perspective within our lives, it would be good to have more, even if we recognize (from outside) that we can’t; so loss is still bad.

Icon  by  Harold  Weaver,  from  the  Noun  Project  

Page 8: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Summary Death is bad for the person who dies b/c it’s a loss to that person of future possibilities of a good thing (life).

Page 9: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Putting it all together Fill out the outline of Nagel’s argument (on other screen)

Page 10: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Rosenbaum: “How to be Dead and Not Care: A defense of

Epicurus” (1986)

Page 11: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Definitions of terms

Dying

Death

Being dead

Experience: one experiences something only if it can causally affect one (124) •  e.g., imagining something ≠ experiencing it

Page 12: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Rosenbaum’s reconstruction of Epicurus’ argument

•  See pp. 121-122 (or 218 in JSTOR version) •  Shown on separate screen

Page 13: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Supporting Premise A

Inductive arguments: claim the conclusion follows from the premises with a significant degree of probability Deductive arguments: claim the conclusion follows from the premises with certainty

o  If the premises are true, the conclusion must be true

Generalization from normal cases (induction)(123)  

Premise  1  

Premise  2  

Premise  3  

Conclusion  

Premise  1  

Premise  2  

Premise  3  

Conclusion  

Page 14: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Supporting Premises C and D

Premise (C): comes from def. of “experience” (124-125) 1.  For a person P to experience a state of affairs, it must have

causal effects on P 2.  States of affairs can only have causal effects on a person

who exists 3.  At death, P ceases to exist 4.  Therefore, “P can experience a state of affairs only if it

begins before P’s death”

Premise (D): “true by definition” (126)

Page 15: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Conclusion follows from the premises? With certainty/necessity or with high probability?

Hint: look at the intermediate conclusions (B) and (E) and their connection to the final conclusion

Premise  A   Premise  D  Premise  C  

Premise  B  Intermediate  conclusion  

Final  conclusion  

Premise  E  Intermediate  conclusion  

Page 16: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Response to Nagel

What in Rosenbaum’s argument does Nagel disagree with? Rosenbaum’s response: •  Deception, betrayal, brain injury example

compatible with (A) o  (A) just requires that P could experience something

Page 17: Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and Stephen E. Rosenbaum ...blogs.ubc.ca/phil102/files/2015/02/NagelRosenbaum-Death-102-F15.pdf · Thomas Nagel, “Death” (1979), and ! Stephen

Response to Nagel

Nagel: time before birth & after death are different; latter bad, former not

What is Rosenbaum’s response?


Recommended