Transcript
Page 1: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

“NEO-REPUBLICANISM “ :A CRITICAL

INTRODUTION

PAPER for Workshop 2 “The History of Political Concepts “ at ECPR Joint Sessions

Copenhagen, 14-19 April 2000

RICARDO LEITE PINTO

Law and Political Science Departments

of the Universidade Lusíada de Lisboa

Rua da Junqueira, 188-198

1349-001 Lisboa, PORTUGAL

e.mail : [email protected]

ABSTRACT:

The ”intelectual history” developed by the Cambridge school ( POCOCK e

SKINNER, amongst others ) and the “conceptual history” under the label of

“Begriffsgechichte” in Germany ( KOSELLECK, amongst others ) , led to the

recuperation of the concept of “republic”, and contributed to the revival of

republicanism not only in terms of an explanatory paradigm in the History of Ideas but

also in legal studies and political philosophy. The objective of this paper rather to

draw up a critical proposal is to assess “the state of art” about “ neo-republicanism”.

For this purpose we shall resort to three examples : a historical research project related

to the studies of the XIX th and XX th centuries in Portugal, republicanism as a

modern political philosophy and the development of so called “ republican

constitutionalism” in the modern north-american constitutional theory.

Page 2: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

“NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL

INTRODUTION

Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments

of the Universidade Lusíada de Lisboa)

1. “HUMPTY DUMPTY” AND THE HISTORY OF IDEAS: LANGUAGE OF

REPUBLICANISM AS A HISTORICAL, POLITICAL AND LEGAL

PARADIGM

“Politics is a communicatively constituted activity. Words are its coin, and speech its medium. And yet,

notoriously, the words that make up this medium have hotly contested and historically mutable meaning.

Terence Ball and J.G.A. Pocock, (1988:1)

“When I use a word,” said Humpty Dumpty with disdain, “it means exactly what I want it to mean - no

more, no less.”

“The question,” said Alice, “is whether you are able to make words have such different meanings!”

“The question is,” said Humpty Dumpty, “who should be master.”

Lewis Caroll, Alice Through the Looking Glass

Political innovation and the change in meaning of words in politics go hand in hand.

Words which join the circuit of political language change throughout history, acquire

new meanings and lose others. Sometimes, after long periods of lethargy, they are

recuperated with meanings which differ from the original. And so they take on new

meanings and become subject to theoretical and doctrinaire re-orientations. Words in

political language change their meaning and as such win new usages which end up

having radical implications on the history of ideas and political thought and action.

As a rule such changes are slow and gradual. However, sometimes, at moments of

great political density linked to revolutionary events or far-reaching and relevant

change when political debate is more intense, such conceptual changes emerge more

rapidly and ostensibly. Linguistic changes are not always accepted pacifically without

complaint especially as, being used in the political game, they are sometimes used

purely for the sake of rhetoric in order to win temporary victory in a purely party-

political context (BALL and POCOCK, 1988:2). However, when the difference in

political language is a result of an elaborate debating effort be it theoretical, rhetorical

or philosophical, then the divergence ceases to be a simple semantic battle and

Page 3: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

becomes a true change of paradigm in political language in accordance with that

which is thought, written, spoken and done.

The study of the history of ideas, which gives importance to political language and

conceptual changes, originates from projects which are different but, in part,

complementary. On the one hand, the “history of concepts” or “conceptual history”

was developed in the Federal Republic of Germany in mid XXth

century under the

label of “Begriffsgeschichte” by REINHART KOSELLECK (KOSELLECK, 1985)

amongst others. In the 70’s and 80’s this movement gave rise to several collective

works in German with evident encyclopaedic pretensions based on the History of

political languages in Germany and France (RICHTER, 1995)1. On the other hand, in

the Anglo-Saxon field, the historical study of political languages - the history of ideas2

- was largely due to the pioneering work of J.G.A. POCOCK (POCOCK, 1962)3,

JOHN DUNN (DUNN, 1968) and QUENTIN SKINER (SKINNER, 1969)4.

Although the approximations referred are not exactly the same, the truth is that both

announce the emergence of the history of ideas as separate subject to political

philosophy. The traditional way of studying the History of Ideas was to organise the

intellectual systems chronologically without paying attention to political languages.

For example, POCOCK, DUNN and SKINNER maintain that it is through political

language and its changes that we may understand political thought and organise it

historically according to a logic of intellectual paradigms.

For this purpose it is essential to situate the texts in the ideological context in which

they were produced, to ask which were the central political issues of the society and

time in which they were written, what real answers they aim to give or what deliberate

silences they keep (SKINNER, 1978: xi-xiii). However, to reach this level of

1 According to RICHTER’s information (1995: 9) the reference works are “Geschichtliche

Grundbegriffe: Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialer Sprache in Deutschland, (OTTO

BRUNNER, WERNER CONZE and REINHARDT KOSELLECK, eds), Stuttgard, 7 volumes (1972 -);

“Historisches Worterbuch der Philosophie” (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED GRUNDER, eds),

8 volumes, Basle and Stuttgart, (1971 -) and “Handbuch politisch-sozialer Grundebegriffe in

Frankreich, 1680-1820” (ROLF REICHARDT, HANS JURGEN LUSENBRINK, GERD VAN DEN

HEUVEL and ANETTE HOFER, eds), 11 volumes, Munich (1985 -). 2 See POCOCK & SKINNER (1985).

3 In more recent works J.G.A. POCOCK takes up and develops his approximation to the History of

Ideas, resorting to linguistic paradigms in the same way as THOMAS KHUN uses them in terms of the

History of Science (see POCOCK, 1971, 1975, 1985). 4 It should be noted that the history of “mentalités” developed in France by followers of the “École des

Annales” in France (MARC BLOCH and LUCIEN FEBVRE) as is the case of MICHEL VOVELLE,

has similar characteristics to “Begriffsgeschichte” (RICHTER, 1995: 79).

Page 4: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

understanding, it is not enough to read the texts and understand them. It is necessary

to understand the society in which they were produced and, going back to the previous

question, to identify the political vocabulary of the time. Understanding which are the

problems a writer wants to address and how he uses the concepts available is the same

as understanding which are his basic intentions in writing.

“When attempt in this way to locate a text within its appropriate context, we are not

merely providing historical background for our interpretation; we are already engaged

in the act of interpretation itself” (SKINNER, 1978: xiv).

This historical-linguistic approximation followed its course, overflowing into political

philosophy or modern legal studies in the way in which former political language

came to illuminate contemporary arguments5.

Words which are used nowadays in politics with a different meaning to that which

they had historically are common. And no less common are the situations in which

political vocabulary exists in transition, trying to disassociate itself from its traditional

meaning and acquire a new meaning. Political scientists, historians or jurists become

aware of these difficulties when they have to explain the concepts of “sovereignty”,

“Constitution”, “State”, “federalism”, “corruption” or “republic” in a historical

context, to give but a few examples.

Now this raises two issues: firstly, the identification of the meaning which those

words have had throughout history, assuming that they did not have one sole meaning,

secondly, the identification of their current meaning, scrutinising what is new, what is

adaptation or inspired by the past and what is exactly the same.

Let us reconstitute the dialogue quoted above6 between Alice and Humpty Dumpty.

Alice asks Humpty Dumpty whether we can give words other meanings. Humpty

Dumpty says it is a question of knowing who is master. Humpty Dumpty is the

Hobbesian representation of History and Alice is the historian who desperately seeks

to establish a meaning for the words. But she cannot. Humpty Dumpty is sufficiently

slippery not to let himself get caught in his constant word game.

The method proposed by the “Begriffsgeschichte”, the history of the “mentalités” and

by POCOCK, SKINNER or DUNN, amongst others, who seek to overcome the

avatars of the Alice / Humpty Dumpty two man show makes for the illumination of

5 See also BALL & POCOCK, 1988

6 Which is analysed by POCOCK (POCOCK, 1971: 24)

Page 5: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

certain ideas or concepts of specific authors or periods of history and the resolution of

some questions unsatisfactorily resolved in History, Political Philosophy or Law.

Of the above mentioned examples, we shall concentrate on the word “republic” and its

derivative “republicanism”.

There are those who maintain that the word “republic” is unintelligible (WOOTON,

1994: 2). It expressed and still expresses different and sometimes contradictory

meanings. It has meant the common good and virtue, it was the word that designated

the State and community, it became associated to Human Rights and popular

sovereignty and assimilated the ideas of the separation of powers, mixed government

and even religious freedom. But it has always been present, with greater or lesser

prominence, since the primordial times of the History of Ideas and, today, it is the

cause of a complex but significant movement in historical, political and legal studies

which goes by the name of “neo-republicanism” (WILLIAMS, 1994: 76). The

expression “neo-republicanism” aims to designate a broad current in fashion in the

academies which includes authors of various sciences and areas of knowledge.

And on the other hand, the republicanism which is studied or propounded is not

always truly “new”. Strictly speaking it is not, therefore, either it is limited to

plumbing the depths of history for hidden or as yet un-revealed signs of a republican

language which was unknown and which possibly still exists today, or, it presents re-

formulations of old concepts and republican values. What can be stated, giving due

justice to the name, is that these contributions are innovative for their respective fields

of knowledge and understanding.

Curiously, it was the above mentioned historians of ideas, specifically POCOCK

(1975) and SKINNER (1978,1981, 1983) who, in applying the historical method

which they put forward, made the “republic” into a explanatory and interpretative

example which, apart from them, many others undertook to develop in History,

Political Philosophy and Constitutional Law. Sometimes this model goes so far that it

is not even recognisable in its basic assumptions. Other times it appears transfigured

and adapted in the views of those who do not even claim to be republicans. But in any

case, the word “republic” is currently undergoing a conceptual change which renders

it an undeniable protagonist in political innovation.

Is this an excessive claim? We don’t think so. If we move from the theoretical and

academic field into that of concrete political action, a republican hue is clearly

Page 6: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

recognisable in contemporary political language which was manifestly not there ten

years ago. The world’s political leaders from both the left and right wing quote

JURGEN HABERMAS (HABERMAS, 1998) and his “republican integration” as

well as the heralds of the third way such as ANTHONY GUIDENS (GUIDENS,

1998: 65) and include the republican “apport” when, for example, they recall the

duties and responsibilities of the citizen. In terms of examples, mention may also be

made of the impact which the republican agenda is increasingly having in Australia

and which placed republicanism at the centre of the country’s political debate

(HUDSON & CARTER, 1993) during the last ten years.

What republicanism is this which is nowadays in everything and on everyone’s lips?

What is the explanation for this sudden and powerful intellectual wave which is

spreading throughout Universities7? What has changed and what has remained the

same in the word “republic” throughout History to the point of, today, allowing us to

speak of a conceptual change and a new (or re-formulated) historical, political and

legal paradigm?

It is important to note that the “history of ideas” school represented by names such as

KOSELLECK, POCOCK or VOVELLE led not only to the recuperation of the

“republic” but also gave rise to many other novelties in the field of the history of

ideas. In fact POCOCK (1971: 26-27) took it upon himself to survey the historical

contributions which the new historical-linguistic approximation gave us. The issue is

that a large part of these contributions and, namely, some of the more far-reaching

works of this school’s Anglo-Saxon historians, contributed to the revival of

republicanism not only in terms of an explanatory paradigm in the History of Ideas but

also in legal studies and political philosophy.

To what extent this model, and through it, “neo-republicanism” made for innovation

in History, Political Philosophy and Law is what we shall try to ascertain in this article

whose objective is rather to assess the “state of the art” than specifically draw up a

critical proposal. For this purpose we shall resort to three examples: a historical

research project related to the study of the XIXth

and XXth

centuries in Portugal,

7 There are those who explain the sudden enthusiasm for republican revivalism in the following way:

“When the disappearance of communism as an alternative ideology created, albeit fleetingly, the

illusion of “the end of history” around the self proclaimed victory of the liberal model, the whole

emergence of “another political line” could not help but captivate the critical conscience” (MESURE &

RENAUT, 1999: 148)

Page 7: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

republicanism as a modern political philosophy and the development of so-called

“republican constitutionalism”.

2. RUI RAMOS AND THE CENTRALITY OF REPUBLICANISM IN THE

POLITICAL CULTURE OF THE XIXTH

CENTURY IN PORTUGAL

“There is no difference in the beliefs of monarchists and republicans in Portugal.

What exists is a difference of positions. We are all republicans even if we are monarchists.”

João Chagas, João Franco, Lisboa, 1907, p. 225

One of the most relevant and promising revisions of Portuguese historiography this

that put forward by RUI RAMOS (1992, 1994, 1997, 1998). Since the beginning of

the 90’s this historian has propounded a review of XIXth

and XXth

Portuguese History

marked by the republican paradigm.

According to his theory Portuguese historiography has ignored the republican concept

in studying the XIXth

century and the Ist Republic, reducing the former to liberal

postulations supported by the constitutional monarchy and the latter to a

straightforward continuation of constitutionalism “no man’s land between monarchic

constitutionalism and the principles of Salazar” (RAMOS, 1992: 231).

Scorn for the republican concept “has prevented the perception of something

extremely important for the understanding of Portugal’s contemporary history which

is the enormous influence which republicanism - the republican culture - had in

Portugal, an influence which surpassed, by a long way, that of the Portuguese

Republican Party organised in 1876 and that of the 1910 regime” (RAMOS, 1992:

230).

Historians from the 70’s - a historiography limited by sociological preconception -

described the republicans as “petit bourgeois from Lisbon” and their ideology as “the

banal ramblings of an alienated class”. This approach - “which historians given over

to sociological principles believe is proven by ingenuously calculating the percentage

of salesmen there were in the Masonic lodges” (RAMOS, 1992: 236) - is contested

by the author who proves the presence of the republican concept amongst the

Page 8: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

intellectuals and politicians of the XIXth

century with a special focus on OLIVEIRA

MARTINS and ALEXANDRE HERCULANO; this was conceived in classical terms,

in other words as a revival of the civic humanism which, born in Rome, was

cultivated by the renaissance men MAQUIAVEL and HARRINGTON and which

reached modern times through MONTESQUIEU and ROUSSEAU (RAMOS, 994:

589).

Classical republicanism was based on three fundamental principles: “first, that the

strength of a community resided in the cohesion of its members; second, that that

cohesion is attained through participation in the kind of collective action represented

by the Government or the defence of the community; third, that man only truly has

access to his own individual autonomy through the experience of collective autonomy.

The republic’s cardinal virtue and the basis of its cohesion is patriotism, the

dedication of individuals to the common good. Nations fall into decadence when the

members of the community place their private interests above the collective interest

and civic life falls apart. This is the principle of the corruption of republics”

(RAMOS, 1998: 171).

This thinking was present even amongst the most radical of the Republican Party’s

enemies and amongst those who were hostile to the republic while it merely signified

the regime in which the Head of State was elected. It was the republican concept

which JOÃO FRANCO tried to import into the monarchy; this explains the notorious

discomfort of the Republican Party with Franco’s dictatorship. OLIVEIRA

MARTINS and HERCULANO reflected on the History of Ancient Rome and it was

based on that paradigm - the linguistic paradigm of virtue / corruption - that both

criticised portuguese expansion overseas in XVth and XVIth centuries. It is in the

light of this republican tradition that, for example, we should interpret Portugal’s

decadence attributed to the 70’s generation. It is also this - the idea of making

Portugal into a body of patriotic citizens, a splendidly autarchic community living off

its own work, endowed with good laws - which is at the root of MOUZINHO DA

SILVEIRA’s legislation (RAMOS, 1998: 137). Everybody accepted that the best

political regime was that in which the concept of the republic might be realised,

arguing only as to whether it should be the republican party which should lead such a

regime. This dominance of the republic as a way of conceiving the domestic situation

- and therefore far from being reduced to the Republican Party’s programme and

Page 9: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

practice - was so strong wrote RAMOS (1992: 239) that António Sardinha –

monarchical leading theorist - himself accepted the hypothesis that “integralism

represents no more nor less than the doctrine of a Republic with a King at its head”.

RUI RAMOS’ “opus magnum” in which he puts into practice his interpretation of

Portuguese XIXth

and XXth

century History in the light of the republican paradigm is

the sixth volume in the History of Portugal co-ordinated by JOSÉ MATOSO. Here it

becomes clear that the republic was not the simple continuation of the constitutional

monarchy8. It is true that for both regimes the departure point was the individual

citizen. But while the constitutional monarchy tended to see itself principally as a

guarantee system for the individual freedom of that citizen, the emphasis of

republicanism was different. The republicans wanted citizens to be free men in order

that, without depending on anyone and voluntarily, they might decide to put service to

the community above any other interest. In the Republic the free individual was raw

material for the construction of a collective body - the republican nation - which

would then have priority over that individual” (RAMOS, 1994: 401). This republican

thinking was never refuted even when modern States in the XIXth

century became

commercial and had large populations. Hence the affirmation of the primacy of the

human person faced with liberalism, “it was never a simple atomic egoism such as

caricatured by its critics: it was always founded on a vision of the last political

situations inherited from classical republicanism” (RAMOS, 1998: 171).

The author’s desire is to prove that the last stage of the liberal monarchy and the Ist

Republic was marked by an intellectual climate whose bedrock is distinctly republican

and whose objective was the definition of a “national community” whose political

expression was the republican State. Hence the volume’s symptomatic name - A

Segunda Fundação ( second foundation) - taken, in fact, from an expression of

António Sardinha who exactly summarises the intentions of the age.

Republicanism as an explanatory paradigm of the intellectual framework of the XIXth

century in Portugal is studied from the author’s point of view as a language which can

be deduced from certain texts of a political, historical or literary nature. RUI RAMOS

8 Most constitutionalists adhere to this point of view, applying it to the Portuguese constitutional

History. Thus they end up diluting the 1911 Constitution over an ample liberal period which ranges

from 1820 to 1926 (MIRANDA, 1997: 244) or at least associating it to the radical liberalism which

dates back to the 1820 Cortes Gerais (CANOTILHO, 1999: 158). See also our point of view (PINTO,

1998, a).

Page 10: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

seeks and finds the republican paradigm in Oliveira Martins’ “História da República

Romana” or the “História da Civilização Ibérica” on in the “Cartas sobre a História de

Portugal” or in the articles in Alexandre Herculano’s “A Voz do Profeta”. In all the

author finds the same kind of language: that of classical republicanism. Essentially a

certain, more profound and meaningful way of thinking things through in politics and

history, as a model for thought rather than the mere adhesion to a non-monarchical

regime. This way of thinking should be studied not so much through descent and

genealogy - in the case of analysis of the written work - but, above all, through the

analogy of arguments (RAMOS, 1997: 124).

Thus, it is by resorting to J.G.A. POCOCK’s (POCOCK, 1975) and QUENTIN

SKINNER’s (SKINNER, 1978) historical research on classical republicanism and

precisely in the use of the historical method also put forward by these historians that

RUI RAMOS presents new clues as to how to understand Portugal as a Nation-State:

“It would be of the greatest interest if we were to try to begin understanding how

much the way in which we relate, well or badly, to that which we call “our country” is

due to the 1848 revolutionaries, the 1870 positivists and the 1912 “renaissance men” -

all republicans and not by chance” (RAMOS, 1992: 239).

We therefore stand before a huge re-orientation of Portuguese history which bears

significant conceptual changes. It launches amongst us the linguistic model of the

historical school which we saw before, placing “republicanism” at the centre of the

debate on Portuguese History over the last 150 years.

3. NEO-REPUBLICANISM IN POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY: “LET US TAKE

OUR DUTIES SERIOUSLY”

“(…) unless we place our duties before our rights, we must expect to find our

rights themselves undermined”

Quentin Skinner (1990: 309)

“(…) the legal republic needs to become a civil reality.”

Philip Pettit (1997: 280)

Page 11: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

In the 70’s the republic and republicanism did not exist in political theory dictionaries.

Nowadays any dictionary which claims to be up to date cannot but include an entry

under “republicanism”. Neo-republicanism achieved a status of great intellectual

importance. The addition of the word “republicanism” to the title of any academic

work makes the oeuvre more important and respectable” (ENGEMANN,1993: 331).

The success of this group of ideas was inspired by the recuperation of the republican

paradigm in north American historical studies in the 60’s, motivated, according to

some, by a notorious dissatisfaction with the north American identity

(HAAKONSEN, 1993: 568). The historical republican paradigm (SHALHOPE, 1972,

1982) began by emerging in the USA, wending its irresistible way through the search

for alternative ideological roots to those found in LOCKE’s liberalism (BAYLIN,

1976, WOOD, 1969, RAHE, 1994) but it ended up having its European interpretation

based on MAQUIAVEL through historians such as J.G.A. POCOCK (POCOCK,

1975) and QUENTIN SKINNER (SKINNER, 1978).

Curiously “neo-republicanism” was born in the Anglo-Saxon academic context and,

in comparison to the Anglophone debate, modern French thinking is substantially

poorer (see, despite everything KRIEGEL, 1998, NICOLET, 1992, POLIN, 1997,

GOYARD-FABRE, 1997, TENZER, 1993). This is so because, on the one hand,

French republican tradition, which is undergoing an attempted revival, lost conceptual

clarity and thoroughness and, on the other, as French academics themselves admit,

because “French style” republicanism is “very regional” (MESURE & RENAUT,

1999: 150).

The history of neo-republicanism in contemporary political philosophy is not a linear

and coherent history. Many authors invoke republican values but not all call

themselves republicans (HABERMAS, 1996 a). Others claim a conciliation of

liberalism and republicanism (DAGGER, 1997; TERCHEK, 1997). Others also

include some principles of civic humanism or classical republicanism but exclude

others (MICHELMAN, 1988 or LLANO, 1999). There are even those who do not

identify with republicanism but see themselves labelled so as is the case of

DWORKIN. There is also the communitarian assertion which uses republican values

but claims an autonomous position from the theoretical or philosophical point of view

(BARBER, 1984).

Page 12: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

The point which is common to the various authors who directly or indirectly claim

republican values - which includes names as diverse as PETTIT (1997), BRUGGER

(1999), MAIHOFER(1990), SKINNER (1990, 1998), VETERLI & BRYNER (1989),

SPITZ (1995), ACKERMAN (1993), GINER (1998), HABERMAS (1996),

TERCHEK (1997), GOODWIN (1995), COATS Jr. (1994), ONUF (1998) or

SANDEL (1996) - is precisely the use of past political theories or historical political

concepts to illustrate current political and philosophical arguments. In this case, very

briefly, it was a question of using the Latin word “res publica” and its original Roman

concept - the “public thing” - as something which links a given ordered community to

the determination of the common good. In this sense the “res publica” would oppose

“res privata” (private, family life). Associated to this idea the History of Rome ended

up relating the “res publica” to a certain form of political organisation, - a

constitutional architecture - which would best ensure the essential value of the

“common good”. A mixed form of government which, while reconciling democracy,

aristocracy and monarchy, - the government of all, some and one sole individual, in

ARISTOTELES’ classical description - would provide the appropriate constitutional

vehicle for the expression of the “common good”. This meaning of “republic” was

reclaimed in the Italian Renaissance (MAQUIAVEL, GUICIARDINI), extended itself

in the context of the British Commonwealth-men (SYDNEY, HARRINGTON) and

of Dutch commercial republicanism, revitalised itself and re-invented itself in the

north American and French revolutions and arrived at the present day.

This complex migration of the concept of “republic” over more than two thousand

years is in itself an event. But that it should have withstood the periods in which it

almost disappeared from the history of ideas and re-appeared today full of virtualities

makes us try to understand the success of POCOCK and SKINNER’s historical

method in the light of the ascendancy of neo-republicanism.

Neo-republicanism is, therefore, explained through a complex process of historical

revision which begins to question the liberal affirmation of the priority of natural

rights in the construction of the modern State and society. This history, developed by

liberal theoreticians, is seen by republicans as unilateral because it does not cover the

role of republican ideas, values and institutions born in Roman times and re-lived in

the Renaissance.

Such values evolve around the following assumptions:

Page 13: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

a) civic virtue (“virtú” / “civic virtue” as opposed to Christian virtues) designating

the defence of freedoms, the involvement of the community, the love of laws and

the homeland, the continued preference given to public interest and the search for

the common good as opposed to corruption (the ineptitude for a free life, self

absorption, the emergence of private interests, the “factions” in the rhetoric of the

north American federalists) (SKINNER, 1978: 164; DAGGER, 1997: 196);

b) political involvement which, from the republican point of view, comprises an

extension of the process of discussion and deliberation in which everyone may

participate under equal conditions for access to the public arena and which is

called deliberative democracy (NINO, 1996: 107; BOHMAN & REHG, 1997: ix);

c) dialogic reason, a fitting way to reach the common good which is reflected in a

conversational commitment which sinks its roots in renaissance republicanism

(“audi alteram parte”, always hear the other side, as a way of understanding and

resolving disagreements through dialogue, (PETTIT, 1997: 188, HABERMAS,

1994:12));

d) the idea of popular sovereignty which, according to the neo-republicans, would

be affiliated to a new way of conceiving “res publica”, originating from

MAQUIAVEL, and in accordance with which would result in a community in

which freedom is associated to the elective principle (SPRINGBORG, 1992: 197);

e) the modelling of citizenship as the reconstruction of the role of man in political

society through civic dialogue and participation the “polis” in which duties and

responsibilities are highlighted as an ideal of freedom ( a citizen in a republic acts

and participates in the community in order that he may see himself as the author

and receiver of the law) (MICHELMAN, 1986; HABERMAS, 1996).

The importance which the different authors give to these values is not the same. Some

underline civic virtue (GUINER, 1998) and individual responsibility (SHERRY,

1986, 1995), others citizenship and participation in the community (OLDFIELD,

1990) and yet others the process of political participation (SUNSTEIN, 1988) and the

deliberative democracy model (NINO, 1996) and, lastly, others highlight the forms or

institutions of the republican State and, within them, the role of the Constitution and

the Law (PETTIT, 1997).

Neo-republicanism was born in competition with liberalism but a radical separation

between the two as modern philosophical currents - although some continue to refer to

Page 14: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

it (HABERMAS, 1994: 1) - does not seem to win a majority vote. Nowadays, the

rigid dichotomy between positive freedom and negative freedom is undergoing a

crisis. As seen before, many try to reconcile liberalism with republicanism or to put

forward a kind of third way between the two, a procedural democracy which

reconciles human rights and popular sovereignty (GUINER, 1998). Others, however,

claim that in the republican field there would be a “strong republicanism” in line with

Aristotelian civic humanism (TERCHEK, 1997:66) which would be difficult to

reconcile with liberal claims and a classical republicanism compatible with the theory

of liberal justice(RAWLS, 1995: 202).

However, in recent work, although drinking from the contributions of the neo-

republican wave of the last ten years, PETTIT proposed the idea of freedom as non

domination, affiliating it to the concept of negative freedom as an organisational

element of republicanism. According to him, there would therefore be a distinctly

republican idea of freedom which has been present in republican literature since

Roman times and which would not revert to any stereotype. Freedom as non

domination would allow the citizen to be immune from all and any arbitrary control.

This concept illuminates republicanism and gives form to a group of proposals related

to Law and the State. Republican freedom is not freedom as non interference since

non interference, in accordance with the liberal paradigm, would not always offer and

guarantee a complete non domination. The very proof of this is exemplified in the

master/slave relationship in which the hypothetical benevolence of the master who

does not interfere with his slave’s choices does not free the latter from the situation of

non freedom which is specific to the slave. PETTIT therefore concludes that freedom

can be lost even if there is no interference.

So, in order to safeguard republican freedom the author demands a strong

constitutional state in which the institutions rather than guaranteeing freedom, in

themselves constitute that freedom. This is what justifies a traditional topic of the

republicans when the latter state that a rule of law (law) brings freedom. Having

defined republican freedom as an attractive political ideal, PETTIT throws himself

into describing what the State should do to promote it. The republican State should

respect several constitutional conditions: that of the rule of law, that of the “dispersion

of power “ (separation of powers, a two chamber system, decentralisation) and the

counter-majoritarian condition (legal or institutional restrictions on a majority

Page 15: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

deliberation which is precipitate or about which the people are not informed which,

for example, questions Fundamental Rights). But it should also organise itself

according to a democratic model under the terms of which the contestation takes place

(contestative democracy as variant of deliberative democracy). And finally, neither

the State nor the law are enough: the republic must be a civic reality. The defence of

non domination (respect for republican freedom) may only be guaranteed if everyone,

based on objective reasons, recognises it.

In essence the substance of the neo-republican undertaking is to contest the

communitarian ffirmation expressed, for example, by ALASDAIR MACINTYRE

(1981: 241) that today’s great moral question lies in the opposition between the

tradition of individual liberalism and the Aristotelian tradition of freedom. From this

point of view the idea of positive freedom and the citizens’ reinforced civic

participation specific to the community position (BARBER, 1984, OLDFIELD, 1990:

145) which appeals to the concepts of citizenship and deliberative democracy would

not in essence be anything more that an equivocal reading of the traditional republican

freedom. In other words, neo-republicanism tried to overcome that apparent

opposition - negative freedom versus positive freedom - proposing a different

understanding for the fundaments of politics and the modern State. The legal tradition

of Natural Rights as part of the historical liberal ballast which dates back to LOCKE

goes hand in hand with the recuperation of the republican modes of citizenship (the

republican virtue). Republicanism thus shares a negative ideal of freedom with

liberalism - freedom as non domination (PETTIT, 1997) - made possible by the

republican institutions.

4. THE “REPUBLICAN REVIVAL”: LOOKING AT THE NORTH

AMERICAN CONSTITUTION THROUGH REPUBLICAN EYES

“(…) republican figures less a canon that an ethos, less a blueprint than as

conceptual grid, less a settled institutional fact than a semantic field for normative

debate and constructive imagination”

Frank Michelman, (1986: 17)

Page 16: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

The north American legal academy was one of the first to use the historical

investigations of BAYLIN, WOOD and POCOCK, applying them to the study of the

1787 Constitution. This movement was born at the end of the 80’s and still exists

today, claiming the republican tradition to be present at the founding moment of the

American nation - the Philadelphia Convention, the debate between the federalists and

the anti-federalists, the texts of “Publius”, the thinking of Thomas Jefferson (KLEIN,

BROWN &HENCH, 1993) (McDOWELL & NOBLE, 1997) - as part of modern

America’s heritage in order to look at the Constitution through republican eyes

(SUNSTEIN, 1988: 1576).

The aim of this revivalism is not univocal and nor are the approaches to the subject.

The works of MICHELMAN, (1986, 1988), SUNSTEIN (1988, 1993), ACKERMAN

(1989, 1993), SHERRY (1986, 1994, 1995), SELLERS (1994, 1997, 1998),

ABRAMS (1988) or POPE (1990) amongst many others prove this to be so. From the

outset because, while for some, republicanism might permit the modern questions of

American public right to be considered from a different point of view - restrictions on

the funding of electoral campaigns, fundamental rights, the citizens’ political

participation - thus working as a current of constitutional interpretation in competition

with others such as interpretativism or originalism (GRIFFIIN, 1996: 188), for others,

it would mean reacting against that which is bad in the America which “lost the idea

of civic republicanism, leaving only a somewhat distorted heritage of rights”

(SHERRY, 1993: 63). Then, taking POCOCK literally, because the republicanism

which people aspire to relive is one moment based on the standards of classical

republicanism and the next presents itself as a republicanism which has been

transformed and adapted to new situations; in this case it is always necessary to know

what is the relationship between the old paradigm and modern theories (FALLON,

1989: 1699).

In any case, it is possible to identify a collection of assumptions organised around

civic virtue, the common good, participation, dialogic commitment and the egalitarian

dimension which are, in fact, common to the values which the neo-republicans put

foward in the field of political philosophy and which we have already looked at.

Nevertheless, amongst republican jurists there is particular emphasis placed on the

definition of the common good through dialogue / conversational commitment , (the

republican dialogue) which presupposes the value of civic virtue. The republican

Page 17: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

quality of democracy shall, in essence, be assessed by the breadth, depth and

universality of the “dialogue” between the members of the community prior to

democratic deliberation. Thus, the republic is a “republic of reasons” which shape

deliberation and give it meaning.

What is not clear is the understanding as to the “forum” where this “republican

dialogue” may and should take place. While MICHELMAN (1986: 24) or DWORKIN

(1986: 379)9 situate it in the courts of the Supreme Court which may also correct the

absence of the “republican dialogue”, SUNSTEIN (1988: 1578) reverts to the

“Madison” solution of centring dialogue on the elected representatives of the people

who end up filtering “popular will” and ACKERMAN (1993: 240) or POPE (1990:

310) maintain that this role belongs to the people who in extraordinary moments -

“constitutional politics” - deliberate about the interests of the community.

Now, the question of the means or forum where republican dialogue might take place

although important, does not, nevertheless, mask the fundamental issue of republican

constitutional theory in the United States which is one of affirmation of the multi-

sourced origin of the American revolution. In other words, the American Constitution

has at its roots both LOCKE’s theory of Natural Rights and the virtue/corruption

dialectic of the republican tradition.

This claim leads us to another proposal which is certainly more ambitious but which

results from the former: the attempt to overcome the dichotomy between the

Constitution and Democracy. Also known as the “counter-majority paradox”

(BICKEL, 1962: 16), the question which has run through north American

constitutional theory from the outset lies in the circumstances of the Constitution

proclaiming popular sovereignty but simultaneously establishing limits - rights - and

a mechanism - the “judicial review” - which at a given historical moment may oppose

that popular sovereignty.

The paradox more recently was transferred to the criticism of the role of the Supreme

Court’s constitutional adjudication based on the idea that democratic principles are

incompatible with such a model.

9 Not claiming to be a republican, DWORKIN, nevertheless, is becoming categorised as one on account

of the way in which he considers the relationships between the Constitution and Democracy above all

in “Law’s Empire” (CHRISTODOULIDIS, 1998: 59).

Page 18: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

With a view to dissolving the counter-majority paradox the republicans maintain that

democracy and the Constitution are not incompatible and do not mutually exclude

each other. And they propound another understanding: it is the Constitution which

supports the political community, promoting participation, emancipation and the

community. The forum for “republican dialogue” is, after all, the Constitution because

it is the latter which reinforces popular sovereignty by conferring on it a “home ” for

political deliberation (CHRISTODOULIDIS, 1998: 10). For constitutional republicans

it is the Constitution that underpins the community´s politics in one and the same

stroke, promoting participation, capacitation and emancipation.

North American constitutional republicanism is completely aware of its ideological

roots. It is thus in their claim of overcoming the antinomy between the Constitution

and Democracy by resorting to classical republican jargon “civic virtue, participation

and the common good” that the new republicans reject the nostalgia with which some

of the modern philosophers (ARENDT, 1963) consider the Aristotelian tradition of

the “polis”. “As a tradition of political thought, republicanism is less a canon than an

ethos (…) less an institutional fact that a semantic field for normative debate and

constructive imagination” (MICEHLMAN, 1986: 17).

In the manner of a conclusion it could be said that modern constitutional

republicanism, above all developed in the United States, had the merit of putting the

main accent on authenticity, exemption and diversity of the constitutional dialogue by

means of a sophisticated re-interpretation of the republican tradition without rejecting

liberal claims on account of the way in which it gives importance to fundamental

rights. Hence it presents itself as “the saviour of liberalism and of its own excesses

and, as such, a liberal-republicanism” (PINTO, 1998: 190).

5. CONCLUSIONS

What was at the root of this vast movement which spread through history, political

and constitutional theory and which we call neo-republicanism? It is probable that

originally it was a triple dissatisfaction - historiographical, political (SPITZ, 1997:

VII-XVII) and legal-constitutional.

Page 19: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

From the historical point of view neo-republicanism meant and means the criticism of

a written history based on the legal paradigm - consent, legality, legitimacy and

fundamental rights. In studying republican language - with the resource of “the history

of ideas” or “Begriffsgeschichte” - it added another dimension, forgotten for many

years: the civic spirit, virtue in the face of corruption, the return to principles,

education for citizenship. And this allowed us to see that not only the theory of natural

rights but also the “Machiavellian moment” lay at the origins of modernity.

But moreover, from the political and legal point of view, modern republicanism

questions itself as to the possibility of men and women continuing to be free and

masters of their own destiny in a world in which the mechanisms of representation,

the political parties, interest groups and the professionalisation of politics questions

precisely that freedom (SPITZ, 1997: xx). And it answers by proposing a return to the

principles of virtue, dedication to the common good, responsibility and dialogic

tradition which are specific to European and continental republicanism, conferring on

the Constitution an irreplaceable role as the “home ” for political deliberation. In this

way it would seek to overcome the apparent antinomy between the Constitution and

Democracy (the counter-majority paradox). It would essentially mean correcting the

current democracy by appealing to republican principles and announcing the

democracy of the XXIth

century.

Page 20: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

BIBLIOGRAPHY

ABRAMS, Kathryn,( 1988), “ Law´s republicanism” in The Yale Law Journal,

,vol.97(1988),pp. 1591 e ss.

ACKERMAN, Bruce,(1989) “Constitutional Politics/ Constitutional Law” in Yale

Law Journal , vol. 99( 1989),pp. 453 e ss.

ACKERMAN, Bruce,(1993), We the People Foundations, Cambridge, London, The

Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1993

ARENDT, Hannah( 1963) On revolution, Penguin Books, 1990( 1ª ed. 1963)

BALL, Terence & POCOCK, J.G.A.( eds.)(1988) , Conceptual Change and the

Constitution, Lawrence, Kansas, The University Press of Kansas, 1988

BALL, Terence, FARR, John & HANSON, R,L,(eds.),(1989) Political Inovation and

Conceptual Change, New, , York, Cambridge University Press, 1989

BARBER, B. (1984), Strong Democracy, Berkeley, University of California Press,

1984

BAYLIN, Bernard,(1967) The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution ,

Cambridge, London, The Belknap Press, 1992( 1ª ed. 1967)

BICKEL, A (1962) The Last Dangerous Branch, Cambridge MA, Cambdrige

University Press, 1962

BOCK, Gisela, SKINNER, Quentin e VIROLI, Maurizio( eds.) (1990), Machiavelli

and Republicanism, Cambridge Unversity Press, 1990

BOHMAN , James & REHG (eds) , William,(1997) Deliberative Democracy,

Cambridge, London, The MIT Press, 1997

BRUGGER, Bill (1999), Republican Theory in Political Thouhgt, Virtous or Virtual ?

, London, Mac Millan Press, 1999

CANOTILHO, Gomes,(1999) Direito Constitucional e Teoria da Constituição, 3ª ed.

Coimbra, Almedina, 1999

COATS, Jr. , Wendell John,(1994) A Theory of Republican Character and Related

Essays, London &b Toronto, Susquehanna University Press, 1994

CHRISTODOULIDIS, Emilios,(1998) Law and Reflexive Politics, Dordrecht, Boston

,London Kluwer Academica Publishers, 1998

DAGGER, Richard,(1997) Civic Virtues,Rigthts, Citizenship and Republican

Liberalism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997

Page 21: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

DWORKIN, Ronald,(1986) Law´s Empire, Cambridge, London, The Cambridge

University Press, 1986

DUNN, John (1968) “The Identity of History of Ideas” in Political Obligation in its

Historical Context Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1980

ENGEMANN, T.S.(1993), “Liberalism, Republicanism and Ideology” in The Review

of Politics ,lV, 2 (1993),pp. 331 e ss.

FALLON, Richard,(1989) “ What is Republicanism and is it worth reviving ? “ in

Harvard Law Review, vol. 102, (1989),pp. 1695 e ss.

FONTANA, Biancamaria (eds.)(1994) The Invention of the Modern Republic,

Cambridge, Cambridge Unversity Press, 1994

GIDDENS, Anthony,(1998) The Third Way, The renewal of social-democracy,

Cambridge, Polity press, 1998

GINER, Salvador(1998), “Las Razones del republicanismo” in Claves de Razón

pratica, nº 81(1998),pp. 2 e ss.

GOODWIN, Charles Stewart,(1995) A Resurrection of the Republican Ideal, Lanham,

New York, London, The Unversity Press of America,1995

GOYARD-FABRE, Simone, (1997), Les Principes Philosophiques du Droit Politique

Moderne, Paris, PUF, 1997

GRIFFIN, Stephen,(1996) American Constitutionalism, From Theory to Politics,

Princeton, Princeton Unversity Press, 1996

HAAKONSEN, Knud (1993), “Republicanism” in A Companion to Contemporary

Political Philosophy ( Robert Goodin & Philip Pettit,eds),Oxford, Cambridge,

Blackwell, 1993

HABERMAS, Jurgen, (1994) “Human Rights and Popular Sovereignty: The Liberal

and Republican Versions” in Ratio Juris, vol.7 ( 1994),pp. 1 e ss.

-----------------------------(1996) Between Facts and Norms, Contributions to a

Discourse Theory of law and Democracy, Cambridge , MA, The MIT Press, 1996

---------------------------, (1996 a)“Paradigms of Law” in Cardoso Law Review vo. 17

nºs 4-5 ( 1996) pp. 771 e ss.

---------------------------,(1998) L´Integration Républicaine, Essais the Théorie

Politique, Paris, Fayard, 1998

HUDSON, Wayne & CARTER, David,( eds.)(1993) The Republicanism

Debate,Kesington, Australia, New South Wales University Press, 1993

Page 22: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

KLEIN, Milton, BROWN, Richard & HENCH, John,(eds.)(1992) The Republican Synthesis

Revisited,Worcester, American Antiquary Society, 1992

KOSELLECK, Reinhart,( 1985) , “ Begriffsgeschichte and Social History” in Futures Past ,

Cambridge; Mass, 1985,pp. 420 e ss.

KRIEGEL, Blandine,(1998) Philosophie de la Republique, Paris, Plon, 1998

LLANO, Alejandro,(1999) , Humanismo Cívico, Madrid, Ariel, 1999

MACINTYRE, Alasdair,(1981) After Virtue, London, Duckworth, 1981

MAIHOFER, Werner,(1990) “The Ethos of the Republic and the Morality of

Politics” in Machiavelli and Republicanism, 1990, pp.283 e ss.

McDOWELL, Gary & NOBLE, Sharon,(eds.) (1997), Reason and Republicanism,

Thomas Jefferson Legacy of Liberty,Lahnam, Boulder, New York, London, Rowman

& Littlefield, 1997

MESURE, Sylvie & RENAUT, Alain (1999) , Alter Ego, Les paradoxes de l´identité

démocratique, Alto, Aubier, Paris, 1999

MICHELMAN, Frank,(1986) “ Foreword: traces of self –Government” in Harvard

Law Review nº 100(1986),pp. 4 e ss.

----------------------------,(1988) “Law´s Republics” in Yale Law Journal , nº 97(

1988),pp. 1493 e ss.

MIRANDA, Jorge,(1997) Manual de Direito Constitucional, Tomo I, 6ª ed.Coimbra,

Coimbra Editora, 1997

NICOLET, Claude (1992), La République en France, Paris, Seuil, 1992

NINO, Carlos Santiago,(1996) The Constitution of the Deliberative Democracy, New

haven , London, Yale University Press, 1996

OLDFIELD, Adrinan,(1990), Citizenship and Community, Civic Republicanism and

the new World, New York, Londom Routledge, 1990

ONUF, Nicholas Greenwood,(1998) The Republican Legacy in International

Thought, Cambridge University Press, 1998

PETTIT, Philip,(1988) “The Freedom of The City, A Republican Ideal”, in The Good

Polity, Normative Analysis of the State ( Alan Hamlin e Philip Petit, eds ), Oxford,

Blackwell, 1988

--------------------------(1993), The Common Mind, Na essay on Psychology, society

and Politics, New York e Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1993

---------------------------(1997), Republicanism, A Theory of Freedom and Government,

Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997

Page 23: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

PINTO, Ricardo Leite (1998), O Momento Maquiavélico na Teoria Constitucional

Norte-Americana, Republicanismo, História, Teoria Política e Constituição, Lisboa,

Edições da Universidade Lusíada, 1998

-----------------------------,(1998 a) “ Algumas Hipóteses sobre a República e o

republicanismo no Constitucionalismo Português” in Perspectivas Constitucionais,

Nos vinte anos da Constituição de 1976,vol. IIII ( Jorge Miranda, ed.) ,Coimbra,

Coimbra Editora, 1998

POCOCK, J.G.A (1962) , “ The History of Political Thought : a metodological

Inquiry” in Philosophy, Politics and Society, series II , Peter Laslett e W.G.Runciman

, Oxford, Blackwell, 1962,pp. 183 e ss.

-------------------------(1971), Politics , Language & Time, Essays on Political Thouhgt

and History, ( 1971), Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press, 1989

---------------------------,(1975) The Machiavellian Moment, The Florentine Thought

and the Atlantic Republican Tradition, Princeton, N.J., Princeton University Press,

1975

----------------------------,(1985) Virtue, Commerce and History, New York, Cambridge

University Press, 1985

POCOCK, J.G A & SKINNER , Quentin, (1985), “What is Intectual History ? “ in

History Today, 35(1985),pp. 46 e ss.

POLIN, Raymond, La République entre Démocratie Sociale et Démocratie

Aristocratique, Paris, PUF,1997

POPE, J.G. (1990) , “ Republican Moments : The Role of Direct Popular Power in the

American constitutional Order” in University of Pennsylvania Law Review, vo. 139(

1990),pp. 287 e ss.

RAMOS, Rui, (1992)“A ideia republicana e a história da república em Portugal(a

propósito de alguns livros recentes) in Análise Social, vol.XXVII(115) , 1992,pp. 229

e ss.

------------------,(1994) História de Portugal ( José Matoso, dir.) , Sexto volume, A

Segunda Fundação, Lisboa, 1994

-------------------,(1997) “As origens ideológicas da condenação das descobertas e

conquistas em Herculano e Oliveira Martins” in Análise Social, vol. XXXII(140),

1997,pp. 113 e ss.

Page 24: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

--------------------, (1998)“Oliveira Martins e a Ética Republicana” in Penélope 18,

1998, pp. 167 e ss.

RAHE, Paul A.( 1994), Republics, Ancient & Modern, Invention of Prudence :

Constituting the americna Regime, Chapell Hil & London, The University of North

Carolina Press, 1994

RAWLS, John,(1993) Political Liberalism, New York, Coumbia University Press,

1993

RICHTER, Melvin (1995) , The History Of Political and Social Concepts, A critical

Introduction , New York,Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995

SANDEL, M. (1982), Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge, Cambridge

Unviersity Press, 1982

----------------------,(1996) Democracy´s Discontent, America in search of a Public

Philosophy, Cambridge , London, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,

1996

SELLERS, M.N.S.,(1994) American Republicanism , Roman Ideology in the United

States Constitution, New York, New York University Press, 1994

--------------------------,(1997) “Republicanism, Liberalism and the Law” in Kentucky

Law Journal, vol. 86 (1997/98), nº1, pp. 1 e ss.

------------------------------, (1998)The Sacred Fire of Liberty, Republicanism,

Liberalism and the Law, New York, New York University Press, 1998

SHALHOPE, R.,(1972) “ Toward a Republican Synthesis : The Emergence of na

Understanding of Republicanism en American Historiography” in William and Mary

Quaterly, 29 (1972),pp. 49 e ss.

-----------------------,(1992) “Republicanism and Early American Historiography” in

William and Mary Quaterly, 39(1992),pp. 334 e ss

SHERRY, Suzanna,(1986) “Civic Virtue and the Feminine Voice in Constituitional

Adjudication” in Virginia Law Review,vol. 72 (1986),pp. 543 e ss.

---------------------------,(1995) “Responsible republicanism; Educating for Citizenship”

in The University of Chicago Law Review,vo. 62 (1995),pp. 131 e ss.

SKINNER, Quentin,(1969) “ Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas”

(1969) in Meaning and Context : Quentin Skinner and his Critics , J.Tully (ed.) ,

Cambridge, Polity Press, 1988

Page 25: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

-------------------------,(1978) The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2 vols,

vol.I ,The Renaissance, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1978

-------------------------,(1981) Machiavelli, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1981

-------------------------, (1983)“Machiavelli on the maintenance of Liberty” in Politics,

18( 1983),pp.3 e ss

---------------------------,(1984) “The Idea of negative Liberty” in Philosophy in

History, (R.Rorty, J.B. Schneewind e Q.Skinner, eds.), Cambridge, Cambridge

University Press, 1984

-----------------------------(1990) “ The Republican Ideal of political liberty” in

Machiavelli and Republicanism( Bock, Skinner & Viroli, eds), 1990,pp.293 e ss.

-----------------------------(1998), Liberty before Liberalism, Cambridge, Cambridge

University Press, 1998

SPITZ, Jean Fabien,(1994) “The concept of Liberty in a “Theory of Justice and it´s

republican version”

in Ratio Juris, vo. 7(1994),pp. 331 e ss.

-------------------------(1995) La Liberté Politique, Paris, PUF, 1985

-------------------------(1997), prefácio a “J.G.A POCOCK, Le Moment

Machiavélien”( tradução francesa) Paris, PUF, 1997

SPRINGBORG, Patricia,(1992) Western republicanism and the Oriental Prince,

Cambridge, Polity Press, 1992

SUNSTEIN, Cass, (1988)“Beyond the Republican Revival” in The Yale Law Journal,

vol.97(1988),pp. 1539 e ss.

---------------------------,(1993) The Partial Constitution, Cambridge e London, Harvard

University Press, 1993

TENZER, Nicolas,(1993), La République, Paris, PUF( Col. Que sais-je ?),1993

TERCHEK, Ronald,(1997) Republican Paradoxes and Liberal Anxieties, Lanham,

Boulder, New York, London, Rowman & Littlefield, 1997

TUCK, Richard, (1993)“The Contribution of History” in A Companion to

Contemporary Political Philosophy ( Robert Goodin & Philip Pettit,eds.) Oxford,

Cambridge, Blackwell, 1993, pp. 72 e ss.

VETERLI, Richard & BRYNER, Gary, (1987) In search of The republics, Public

Virtue and the Roots of the American Government, Lahnan, Roman & Littlefield,

1996 ( 1ª ed. 1987)

Page 26: Neo-Republicanism: A Critical Introduction · “NEO-REPUBLICANISM”: A CRITICAL INTRODUTION Ricardo Leite Pinto (Law and Political Science Departments ... (JOACHIM RITTER and KARLFRIED

WILLIAMS, David,(1994) “European and US Perspectives on Civic republicanism”

in Indiana Journal of Global Studies, vol.2(1994),pp. 71 e ss.

WOOD, Gordon (1969) , The Creation of The American Republic, 1776-1787, New

York, Norton Company, 1993 ( 1ªed. 1969)

WOOTON, David,(1994) Republicanism, Liberty and Commercial Society

(1649/1776), Stanford University Press, 1994