41
Delft School of Design Series on Architecture and Urbanism Series Editor Ari e G raafl and Editorial Board K. Mi cha el H ays (H arvard University , USA) | Ákos Moravánszky (ETH Züri ch, Switzerl and) Mi cha el Müll er (B remen University , G ermany) | Frank R. Werner (University of Wuppert al, G ermany) G erd Zimmermann (B auhaus University , G ermany) Cog n i t i ve A r c h i t e ct u r e . Fr o m B i o p o li t i c s t o N oo p o li t i c s . A r ch i t e c t u r e & M ind in t h e A ge of Co mmun i c a t i o n a nd I n f o r m a t i o n

Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Editors Deborah Hauptmann and Warren Neidich

With contributions by Andreas Angelidakis, Lisa Blackman, Ina Blom,

Felicity Callard, Suparna Choudhury, Jordan Crandall, Elie During,

Keller Easterling, Lukas Ebensperger, Boris Groys, Janet Harbord,

Deborah Hauptmann, Patrick Healy, Maurizio Lazzarato, Daniel Margulies,

Markus Miessen, Yann Moulier Boutang, Warren Neidich, John Protevi,

Steven Quartz, Andrej Radman, Philippe Rahm, John Rajchman, Patricia Reed,

Gabriel Rockhill, J.A. Scott Kelso, Terrence Sejnowski, Elizabeth Sikiaridi,

Jan Slaby, Paolo Virno, Frans Vogelaar, Sven-Olov Wallenstein, Bruce Wexler,

Charles T. Wolfe

010 Publishers Rotterdam 2010

Delft School of Design Series on Architecture and Urbanism

Series Editor

Arie Graafland

Editorial Board

K. Michael Hays (Harvard University, USA) | Ákos Moravánszky (ETH Zürich, Switzerland)

Michael Müller (Bremen University, Germany) | Frank R. Werner (University of Wuppertal, Germany)

Gerd Zimmermann (Bauhaus University, Germany)

Cognitive Architecture.From Biopolitics to Noopolitics.Architecture & Mind in the Age of Communication and Information

Page 2: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Cognitive Architecture.From Biopolitics

to Noopolitics.Architecture & Mind

in the Age of Communication and Information

Page 3: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Editors Deborah Hauptmann and Warren Neidich

With contributions by Andreas Angelidakis, Lisa Blackman, Ina Blom,

Felicity Callard, Suparna Choudhury, Jordan Crandall, Elie During,

Keller Easterling, Lukas Ebensperger, Boris Groys, Janet Harbord,

Deborah Hauptmann, Patrick Healy, Maurizio Lazzarato, Daniel Margulies,

Markus Miessen, Yann Moulier Boutang, Warren Neidich, John Protevi,

Steven Quartz, Andrej Radman, Philippe Rahm, John Rajchman, Patricia Reed,

Gabriel Rockhill, J.A. Scott Kelso, Terrence Sejnowski, Elizabeth Sikiaridi,

Jan Slaby, Paolo Virno, Frans Vogelaar, Sven-Olov Wallenstein, Bruce Wexler,

Charles T. Wolfe

010 Publishers Rotterdam 2010

Delft School of Design Series on Architecture and Urbanism

Series Editor

Arie Graafland

Editorial Board

K. Michael Hays (Harvard University, USA) | Ákos Moravánszky (ETH Zürich, Switzerland)

Michael Müller (Bremen University, Germany) | Frank R. Werner (University of Wuppertal, Germany)

Gerd Zimmermann (Bauhaus University, Germany)

Cognitive Architecture.From Biopolitics to Noopolitics.Architecture & Mind in the Age of Communication and Information

Page 4: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

I P last ic ity and Pote nt ia l ity64 Movement Paolo Virno 78 The Politics of I Can Patricia Reed

90 Comrades of Time Boris Groys 100 The Neural Basis of Cognitive

Development: A Constructivist Manifesto Steven Q uartz & Terrence

Sejnowski 116 Metastable Mind J. A. Scott Kelso

I I E p ige n ic Reconfigurat ions142 Shaping the Environments that Shape Our Brains: A Long

Term Perspective Bruce Wexler 168 Deleuze and Wexler: Thinking

Brain, Body, and Affect in Social Context John Protevi 184 From

Spinoza to the Socialist Cortex: Steps Toward the Social Brain

C harles T. Wolfe 208 Other Minds, Other Brains, Other Worlds

Patrick Healy 232 Designing the Lifeworld: Selfhood and Architecture

from a Critical Neuroscience Perspective Lukas Ebensperger, Suparna

C houdhury & Jan Slaby

8 Acknowledgments

10 Introduction: Architecture & Mind in the Age of

Communication and Information Deborah Hauptmann

46 Noopolitics, Life and Architecture Sven- O lov Wallenstein

Page 5: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

I P last ic ity and Pote nt ia l ity64 Movement Paolo Virno 78 The Politics of I Can Patricia Reed

90 Comrades of Time Boris Groys 100 The Neural Basis of Cognitive

Development: A Constructivist Manifesto Steven Q uartz & Terrence

Sejnowski 116 Metastable Mind J. A. Scott Kelso

I I E p ige n ic Reconfigurat ions142 Shaping the Environments that Shape Our Brains: A Long

Term Perspective Bruce Wexler 168 Deleuze and Wexler: Thinking

Brain, Body, and Affect in Social Context John Protevi 184 From

Spinoza to the Socialist Cortex: Steps Toward the Social Brain

C harles T. Wolfe 208 Other Minds, Other Brains, Other Worlds

Patrick Healy 232 Designing the Lifeworld: Selfhood and Architecture

from a Critical Neuroscience Perspective Lukas Ebensperger, Suparna

C houdhury & Jan Slaby

8 Acknowledgments

10 Introduction: Architecture & Mind in the Age of

Communication and Information Deborah Hauptmann

46 Noopolitics, Life and Architecture Sven- O lov Wallenstein

Page 6: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

V Cap ita l ism and th e Mutat ing Inte l l ect454 Mutations in Contemporary Urban Space and the Cognitive Turning

Point of Capitalism Yann Moulier Boutang 470 A Specter is Haunting

Globalization G abriel Rockhill 488 From a Politics of Nostalgia to

a Politics of Change Markus Miessen 502 ‘Exiting Language,’ Semiotic

Systems and the Production of Subjectivity in Félix Guattari Maurizio

Lazzarato 522 Idensity E lizabeth Sikiaridi & Frans Vogelaar 538 From

Noopower to Neuropower: How Mind Becomes Matter Warren Neidich

582 Contributors Biographies

588 Credits

I I I A dm in ister ing A tte nt ion250 Disposition Keller Easterling 266 Loose Coexistence: Technologies

of Attention in the Age of the Post-Metropolis E lie During

284 ScreenSpaces: Can Architecture Save You from Facebook Fatigue

Andreas Angelidakis 302 Technologies of Mediation and the Affective:

A Case-study of the Mediated Environment of MediacityUK Lisa B lackman

& Janet Harbord 324 The Industrious Subject: Cognitive Neuroscience’s

Revaluation of ‘Rest’ Felicity C allard & Daniel Margulies

IV Th e Noo- S e nsor ium348 Deleuze’s Time, or How the Cinematic Changes Our Idea of Art

John Rajchman 368 Spectacle versus Cinematic Sociality: Art and

the New Media Architecture Ina B lom 386 Edible Architecture Philippe

Rahm 402 Movement, Agency, and Sensing: A Performative Theory

of the Event Jordan C randall 430 Figure, Discourse: To the Abstract

Concretely Andrej Radman

Page 7: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

V Cap ita l ism and th e Mutat ing Inte l l ect454 Mutations in Contemporary Urban Space and the Cognitive Turning

Point of Capitalism Yann Moulier Boutang 470 A Specter is Haunting

Globalization G abriel Rockhill 488 From a Politics of Nostalgia to

a Politics of Change Markus Miessen 502 ‘Exiting Language,’ Semiotic

Systems and the Production of Subjectivity in Félix Guattari Maurizio

Lazzarato 522 Idensity E lizabeth Sikiaridi & Frans Vogelaar 538 From

Noopower to Neuropower: How Mind Becomes Matter Warren Neidich

582 Contributors Biographies

588 Credits

I I I A dm in ister ing A tte nt ion250 Disposition Keller Easterling 266 Loose Coexistence: Technologies

of Attention in the Age of the Post-Metropolis E lie During

284 ScreenSpaces: Can Architecture Save You from Facebook Fatigue

Andreas Angelidakis 302 Technologies of Mediation and the Affective:

A Case-study of the Mediated Environment of MediacityUK Lisa B lackman

& Janet Harbord 324 The Industrious Subject: Cognitive Neuroscience’s

Revaluation of ‘Rest’ Felicity C allard & Daniel Margulies

IV Th e Noo- S e nsor ium348 Deleuze’s Time, or How the Cinematic Changes Our Idea of Art

John Rajchman 368 Spectacle versus Cinematic Sociality: Art and

the New Media Architecture Ina B lom 386 Edible Architecture Philippe

Rahm 402 Movement, Agency, and Sensing: A Performative Theory

of the Event Jordan C randall 430 Figure, Discourse: To the Abstract

Concretely Andrej Radman

Page 8: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

9

!is book would not have been possible without the support of the Faculty of Architecture at Delft University of Technology. In "##$ my coeditor and I held a symposium entitled Architecture in Mind: From Biopolitics to Noopolitics, sponsored by the Delft School of Design. Several contri b-utors to this volume were present at this conference and this volume owes much to their enthu-siasm and dedication to the issues raised during these proceedings. !us I would like to extend special thanks to the following contributors: Andreas Angelidakis, Yann Moulier Boutang, Jordon Crandall, Keller Easterling, Scott Kelso, Markus Miessen, John Protevi, Bruce Wexler and Charles Wolfe. I would also like to extend my appreciation to Abdul-Karim Mustapha, a partici-pating member of the conference who elegantly summarized the proceedings in closing remarks, and who later contributed greatly to the early formulations of this volume.

Of course, developing the issues addressed at a conference into a volume of the scale of Cognitive Architecture entailed no small task: a task that would have been insurmountable without the intel-lectual e%orts and accumulated knowledge of my co-editor, Warren Neidich. For over a decade, Neidich has been critically engaged in the discussions that underpin this volume. I believe that he has worked persistently and tirelessly, both within his art work and his theoretical contributions, to the discourse we here identify as noopolitics, what Neidich in his own work develops as neuro-power.

Finally, I would like to thank all the contributors to this volume as they have helped us to navigate the vague terrains of what to our mind remains very much a burgeoning discourse. !e academy can be very unforgiving when its members are perceived to stray too far afield from the accepted boundaries of their so-called legitimate research. And thus I remain extremely grateful to the scholars and scientists who, coming from such varied disciplines, have agreed to support us in our transdisciplinary approach with their contributions to this volume.

Deborah HauptmannRotterdam, November "#&#

Acknow l e dgm e nts

Page 9: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

9

!is book would not have been possible without the support of the Faculty of Architecture at Delft University of Technology. In "##$ my coeditor and I held a symposium entitled Architecture in Mind: From Biopolitics to Noopolitics, sponsored by the Delft School of Design. Several contri b-utors to this volume were present at this conference and this volume owes much to their enthu-siasm and dedication to the issues raised during these proceedings. !us I would like to extend special thanks to the following contributors: Andreas Angelidakis, Yann Moulier Boutang, Jordon Crandall, Keller Easterling, Scott Kelso, Markus Miessen, John Protevi, Bruce Wexler and Charles Wolfe. I would also like to extend my appreciation to Abdul-Karim Mustapha, a partici-pating member of the conference who elegantly summarized the proceedings in closing remarks, and who later contributed greatly to the early formulations of this volume.

Of course, developing the issues addressed at a conference into a volume of the scale of Cognitive Architecture entailed no small task: a task that would have been insurmountable without the intel-lectual e%orts and accumulated knowledge of my co-editor, Warren Neidich. For over a decade, Neidich has been critically engaged in the discussions that underpin this volume. I believe that he has worked persistently and tirelessly, both within his art work and his theoretical contributions, to the discourse we here identify as noopolitics, what Neidich in his own work develops as neuro-power.

Finally, I would like to thank all the contributors to this volume as they have helped us to navigate the vague terrains of what to our mind remains very much a burgeoning discourse. !e academy can be very unforgiving when its members are perceived to stray too far afield from the accepted boundaries of their so-called legitimate research. And thus I remain extremely grateful to the scholars and scientists who, coming from such varied disciplines, have agreed to support us in our transdisciplinary approach with their contributions to this volume.

Deborah HauptmannRotterdam, November "#&#

Acknow l e dgm e nts

Page 10: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

185

1 G illes Deleuze in conversation with Toni Negri in 1 9 9 0 (originally in Futur Antérieur), in G illes Deleuze, Negotiations 1972-1990, translated by M. Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1 9 9 5), 1 76 .2 Dorothy Cheney, Robert Seyfarth and Barbara Smuts, ‘Social relationships and social cognition in nonhuman primates,’ Science 2 3 4 :478 2 (1 9 8 6): 1 3 61-6 ; Leslie Brothers, ‘The social brain: a project for integrating primate behaviour and neuropsychology in a new domain,’ Concepts in Neuroscience 1 (1 9 9 0): 2 7-51 ; Robin Dunbar, ‘The social brain hypothesis,’ Evolutionary Anthropology 6 (1 9 9 8): 1 78-9 0 ; and Social Brain, Distributed Mind, eds. Robin Dunbar, C live G amble and John Gowlett (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 9).3 James J. G ibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1 9 79). See also: Michael Losonsky, Enlightenment and Action (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 2 0 01), 8-9 ; Andy C lark, Microcognition: philosophy, cognitive science and parallel distributed processing (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 8 9), 6 3-6 , 1 3 2-5 ; and Michael Wheeler, Reconstructing the Cognitive World (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 5), which argues that we don’t even need to normatively impose a ‘Heideggerian AI’ à la Dreyfus; it comes on its own.

‘Subjectivation, événement ou cerveau, il me semble que c’est un peu la même chose.’&

We have not yet left the Decade of the Brain proclaimed by George Bush père, which was supposed to be the &''#s but shows no signs of ending; however, something has changed, perhaps in keeping with communitarian stirrings that are felt in various places across the globe, in rejection of ‘meth-odological individualism.’ Consider the study of cognition. From its individualistic beginnings in seeking to model ‘agent intelligence,’ discover the neural correlates of consciousness or perhaps find ‘localized’ brain areas that would explain various mental functions, this field or rather cluster of fields has begun to take something of a ‘social’ turn in the past ten to twenty years, with the publication of books, anthologies, and journal issues called Social Neuroscience, Social Brain and such, picking up momentum in the past five years." Topics such as imitation, empathy, ‘mind-reading,’ and even group cognition have come to the fore. Outside of the specifically ‘neuro-’ or ‘cognitive’ or ‘embodied’ arenas, there has been a fresh wave of reassessment of the pragmatists, notably John Dewey, for their ‘social theory of mind,’ and their overall theorization of mind as a set of practices within the world of action, augmenting ideas that in the &'(#s were associated with the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein (meaning as use, forms of life, and so on); cognitivists and philosophers of perception have also sought to emancipate themselves from ‘behaviorism’ or other constraints by appealing to Heidegger-as-read-by-Hubert-Dreyfus (an avatar of the philos-opher of Geworfenheit, the Black Forest, and the ‘authentic path’ of an ecological culture in which he suddenly becomes a cutting-edge theorist of skill, agency, and embedded cognition), and to ‘ecological’ thinking in the sense articulated by the psychologist of perception James J. Gibson.) In short, from the study of cognition to very diverse corners of the philosophical landscape, the social dimension of mind, intellect, or action has come to the fore.

But I will be interested in a di%erent locus of the social here: the brain. And di%erently from the newly emerged field of social neuroscience, the social brain I shall discuss here might also be called ‘!e Spinozist Brain’ or, in a more mysterious turn of phrase, based on a longer formulation from a &'"#s’ Bolshevik psychologist, Aaron Zalkind, ‘!e Socialist Cortex.’ I shall clarify this expression later on, but for now would like to emphasize that the expression ‘social brain’ should be understood in specifically a Spinozist sense. Expressed in historical terms, I wish to reconstruct a tradition of

From Sp inoz a to th e Soc ia l ist Cortex : S te ps Tow ard th e Soc ia l B ra in Charles T. Wolfe

Page 11: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

185

1 G illes Deleuze in conversation with Toni Negri in 1 9 9 0 (originally in Futur Antérieur), in G illes Deleuze, Negotiations 1972-1990, translated by M. Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1 9 9 5), 1 76 .2 Dorothy Cheney, Robert Seyfarth and Barbara Smuts, ‘Social relationships and social cognition in nonhuman primates,’ Science 2 3 4 :478 2 (1 9 8 6): 1 3 61-6 ; Leslie Brothers, ‘The social brain: a project for integrating primate behaviour and neuropsychology in a new domain,’ Concepts in Neuroscience 1 (1 9 9 0): 2 7-51 ; Robin Dunbar, ‘The social brain hypothesis,’ Evolutionary Anthropology 6 (1 9 9 8): 1 78-9 0 ; and Social Brain, Distributed Mind, eds. Robin Dunbar, C live G amble and John Gowlett (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 9).3 James J. G ibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1 9 79). See also: Michael Losonsky, Enlightenment and Action (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 2 0 01), 8-9 ; Andy C lark, Microcognition: philosophy, cognitive science and parallel distributed processing (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 8 9), 6 3-6 , 1 3 2-5 ; and Michael Wheeler, Reconstructing the Cognitive World (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 5), which argues that we don’t even need to normatively impose a ‘Heideggerian AI’ à la Dreyfus; it comes on its own.

‘Subjectivation, événement ou cerveau, il me semble que c’est un peu la même chose.’&

We have not yet left the Decade of the Brain proclaimed by George Bush père, which was supposed to be the &''#s but shows no signs of ending; however, something has changed, perhaps in keeping with communitarian stirrings that are felt in various places across the globe, in rejection of ‘meth-odological individualism.’ Consider the study of cognition. From its individualistic beginnings in seeking to model ‘agent intelligence,’ discover the neural correlates of consciousness or perhaps find ‘localized’ brain areas that would explain various mental functions, this field or rather cluster of fields has begun to take something of a ‘social’ turn in the past ten to twenty years, with the publication of books, anthologies, and journal issues called Social Neuroscience, Social Brain and such, picking up momentum in the past five years." Topics such as imitation, empathy, ‘mind-reading,’ and even group cognition have come to the fore. Outside of the specifically ‘neuro-’ or ‘cognitive’ or ‘embodied’ arenas, there has been a fresh wave of reassessment of the pragmatists, notably John Dewey, for their ‘social theory of mind,’ and their overall theorization of mind as a set of practices within the world of action, augmenting ideas that in the &'(#s were associated with the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein (meaning as use, forms of life, and so on); cognitivists and philosophers of perception have also sought to emancipate themselves from ‘behaviorism’ or other constraints by appealing to Heidegger-as-read-by-Hubert-Dreyfus (an avatar of the philos-opher of Geworfenheit, the Black Forest, and the ‘authentic path’ of an ecological culture in which he suddenly becomes a cutting-edge theorist of skill, agency, and embedded cognition), and to ‘ecological’ thinking in the sense articulated by the psychologist of perception James J. Gibson.) In short, from the study of cognition to very diverse corners of the philosophical landscape, the social dimension of mind, intellect, or action has come to the fore.

But I will be interested in a di%erent locus of the social here: the brain. And di%erently from the newly emerged field of social neuroscience, the social brain I shall discuss here might also be called ‘!e Spinozist Brain’ or, in a more mysterious turn of phrase, based on a longer formulation from a &'"#s’ Bolshevik psychologist, Aaron Zalkind, ‘!e Socialist Cortex.’ I shall clarify this expression later on, but for now would like to emphasize that the expression ‘social brain’ should be understood in specifically a Spinozist sense. Expressed in historical terms, I wish to reconstruct a tradition of

From Sp inoz a to th e Soc ia l ist Cortex : S te ps Tow ard th e Soc ia l B ra in Charles T. Wolfe

Page 12: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

18 6 187

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

4 Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy (Harmonds-worth: Penguin, 1 9 73), 6 9 4 , 70 9 .5 The most eloquent version of this slightly paranoid critique (and the Rand Corporation, DAR PA and others will keep such theorists busy for generations to come) is the long, anonymous text entitled ‘L’hypothèse cybernétique,’ in the post-Situationist journal Tiqqun 2 (2 0 01): 4 0f.6 Nicholas Humphrey, ‘The social function of intellect’ (1 9 76), in Machiavellian Intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes and humans, eds. Richard Byrne and Andrew Whiten (Oxford: C larendon Press, 1 9 8 9); see also the sequel volume, Machiavellian Intelligence II: Extensions and Evaluations, eds. Alex Whiten and Richard Byrne (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 1 9 9 7).7 Vittorio G allese, Christian Keysers and G iuseppe Rizzolatti, ‘A unifying view of the basis of social cognition,’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (2 0 0 4): 3 9 6-4 0 3 ; G allese and Alvin Goldman, ‘Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading,’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1 2 (1 9 9 8): 4 9 3-5 5 0 ; On Imitation: From Neuroscience To Social Science, 2 vols., eds. Susan Hurley and Nick Chater (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 5). Note: On Imitation, vol. 1 of which contains several presentation papers by Rizzolatti et al.8 Sarah-Jayne B lakemore, Joel Winston and Uta Frith, ‘Social cognitive neuroscience: where are we heading?’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5 (2 0 0 4): 21 7 ; G allese, Keysers and Rizzolatti, ‘A unifying view of the basis of social cognition,’ 3 9 7. Also see the useful summary of the research from Atsushi Iriki’s R IKE N lab on macaque monkeys (but also on certain rodents that have also been trained to use tools) in Laura Spinney’s ‘Tools maketh the monkey,’ New Scientist 2 6 77 (8 O ctober 2 0 0 8): 4 2-5 and in the lab’s report ‘Using tools: the moment when mind, language, and humanity emerged,’ RIKEN Research Report 4 :5 (1 5 May 2 0 0 9), online at http://www.rikenresearch.riken.jp/eng/frontline/5 8 5 0 .9 James M. Baldwin, ‘A new factor in evolution,’ American Naturalist 3 0 :3 5 4 (1 9 8 6): 4 4 0 , online at http://www.brocku.ca/MeadProject/ Baldwin/ Baldwin_1 8 9 6_h.html; David Depew, ‘Baldwin and his many effects,’ in Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsid-ered, eds. David Depew and Bruce Weber (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 3), 7. I won’t be able to discuss Baldwin in this paper but his views concerning language as a supplemental level beyond Darwinian evolution offer intriguing resonances with Vygotsky and Negri.10 John T. C acioppo and G ary Berntson, ‘Analyses of the social brain through the lens of human brain imaging,’ in Key readings in social neuroscience, eds. J.T. C acioppo and G .G . Berntson (New York: Psychology Press, 2 0 0 4), 1-1 7 ; and, John T. C acioppo, G ary Berntson and Ralph Adolphs, Essays in social neuroscience (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 4).

actions, responding only to the observation of hand-object interactions and not to the same action if performed by a mechanical tool, such as a pair of pliers; more recent research has shown the presence of other mirror neurons which respond to the sound of known activity (such as the crunching of peanuts). Somewhat modifying the earlier research which stressed the di%erence between the goal-directed activity of intentional, biological agents and the activity of inanimate tools, recent work done with Japanese macaques in Atsushi Iriki’s Lab for Symbolic Cognitive Development has indicated that training in tool use over several months produces changes in neural activity such that certain neurons now respond to a rake as if it were an extension of the hand. Indeed, that this training in tool use is successful at all is a major discovery and challenges received knowledge.$

Imitation had already been pinpointed in the late nineteenth century by the American psychologist James Mark Baldwin (of ‘Baldwin e%ect’ fame): ‘By imitation the little animal picks up directly the example, instruction, mode of life, etc. of his private family circle and species.’' Since the early &''#s Cacioppo and Berntson have used the term ‘social neuroscience’ to describe their work, but this has rather little to do with our interest in the social brain, as the focus seems to be chiefly on correlations between neural states and behavior.&# Closer in spirit to the tradition I shall be dis-cussing is the study of the culturally and socially constructed nature of the brain, which more

thinking about the brain as social that is ultimately Spinozist in nature, via Marx, Lev Vygotsky and the contemporary philosopher Antonio Negri – the last two of whom explicitly refer to Spinoza’s philosophy as a basis for their projects. One of the points I will make in light of this reconstruction is that the Marxist hostility to cognitive science might have to be reconsidered to some extent. (Marx himself uses the expression ‘social brain.’* Or, put di%erently, an incidental accomplish-ment of my reconstruction of this tradition should be to make it harder for politi-cally motivated critiques of cognitive science and artificial intelligence to claim that theories of intellect and action that seek to involve the brain are necessarily individualistic, ‘reactionary,’ in the service of the military-industrial complex, and so forth.+ If anything, the danger will be from the side of the ‘group mind,’ as we shall see in closing.

I shall proceed in five steps: after a brief review of recent discussions of social cognition, I shall try to make explicit the Spinozist context for the social brain; next I shall summarize some key ideas of the ‘Soviet school’ (Vygotsky, Luria), then move from the ‘socialist’ to the ‘avant-garde’ brain (which are really two ways of describing the same thing, as we shall see); finally, I discuss the ‘Italian’ moment of the social brain, with Negri and Virno, including some reflections on tools and prostheses, and conclude with some considerations on the social brain and the group mind.

Varieties of Social Cognition Obviously not all ‘social brains,’ or rather their conceptualizations, are equal. Social epistemology, the emphasis on the primacy of emotions and the importance of ‘common notions’ are not all the same. !e ‘social’ dimension that is being emphasized in the discussions of ‘social intellect,’( which culminated in the notion of ‘Machiavellian intelligence’ and its presence in the primate world, is that of the individual’s capacity to interact successfully with social groups, to predict and manipulate behavior, to make and break promises, and so forth. !e energetic demands of such a complex situation are ultimately presented as responsible for the large size of primates’ brains, so that some evolutionary anthropologists and their collaborators in related fields took to calling the Machiavellian Intelligence hypothesis, the ‘social brain hypothesis.’

!e ‘social’ in ‘social cognition’ focuses notably on mirror neurons, which indicate the existence in the brain of a particular recognition or decoding of action and thus of the imitation of action,, implying an understanding of other people’s intentions, goals and desires. Mirror neurons, found in the ventral premotor cortex of macaque monkeys, are activated both when the monkey executes grasp-ing actions (grasping a peanut, for example) and when it observes someone else (or another monkey) making grasping actions, or even the preparation of a motor act. Mirror neurons appear to distinguish between biological and nonbiological

Page 13: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

18 6 187

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

4 Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy (Harmonds-worth: Penguin, 1 9 73), 6 9 4 , 70 9 .5 The most eloquent version of this slightly paranoid critique (and the Rand Corporation, DAR PA and others will keep such theorists busy for generations to come) is the long, anonymous text entitled ‘L’hypothèse cybernétique,’ in the post-Situationist journal Tiqqun 2 (2 0 01): 4 0f.6 Nicholas Humphrey, ‘The social function of intellect’ (1 9 76), in Machiavellian Intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes and humans, eds. Richard Byrne and Andrew Whiten (Oxford: C larendon Press, 1 9 8 9); see also the sequel volume, Machiavellian Intelligence II: Extensions and Evaluations, eds. Alex Whiten and Richard Byrne (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 1 9 9 7).7 Vittorio G allese, Christian Keysers and G iuseppe Rizzolatti, ‘A unifying view of the basis of social cognition,’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (2 0 0 4): 3 9 6-4 0 3 ; G allese and Alvin Goldman, ‘Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading,’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1 2 (1 9 9 8): 4 9 3-5 5 0 ; On Imitation: From Neuroscience To Social Science, 2 vols., eds. Susan Hurley and Nick Chater (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 5). Note: On Imitation, vol. 1 of which contains several presentation papers by Rizzolatti et al.8 Sarah-Jayne B lakemore, Joel Winston and Uta Frith, ‘Social cognitive neuroscience: where are we heading?’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5 (2 0 0 4): 21 7 ; G allese, Keysers and Rizzolatti, ‘A unifying view of the basis of social cognition,’ 3 9 7. Also see the useful summary of the research from Atsushi Iriki’s R IKE N lab on macaque monkeys (but also on certain rodents that have also been trained to use tools) in Laura Spinney’s ‘Tools maketh the monkey,’ New Scientist 2 6 77 (8 O ctober 2 0 0 8): 4 2-5 and in the lab’s report ‘Using tools: the moment when mind, language, and humanity emerged,’ RIKEN Research Report 4 :5 (1 5 May 2 0 0 9), online at http://www.rikenresearch.riken.jp/eng/frontline/5 8 5 0 .9 James M. Baldwin, ‘A new factor in evolution,’ American Naturalist 3 0 :3 5 4 (1 9 8 6): 4 4 0 , online at http://www.brocku.ca/MeadProject/ Baldwin/ Baldwin_1 8 9 6_h.html; David Depew, ‘Baldwin and his many effects,’ in Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsid-ered, eds. David Depew and Bruce Weber (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 3), 7. I won’t be able to discuss Baldwin in this paper but his views concerning language as a supplemental level beyond Darwinian evolution offer intriguing resonances with Vygotsky and Negri.10 John T. C acioppo and G ary Berntson, ‘Analyses of the social brain through the lens of human brain imaging,’ in Key readings in social neuroscience, eds. J.T. C acioppo and G .G . Berntson (New York: Psychology Press, 2 0 0 4), 1-1 7 ; and, John T. C acioppo, G ary Berntson and Ralph Adolphs, Essays in social neuroscience (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 4).

actions, responding only to the observation of hand-object interactions and not to the same action if performed by a mechanical tool, such as a pair of pliers; more recent research has shown the presence of other mirror neurons which respond to the sound of known activity (such as the crunching of peanuts). Somewhat modifying the earlier research which stressed the di%erence between the goal-directed activity of intentional, biological agents and the activity of inanimate tools, recent work done with Japanese macaques in Atsushi Iriki’s Lab for Symbolic Cognitive Development has indicated that training in tool use over several months produces changes in neural activity such that certain neurons now respond to a rake as if it were an extension of the hand. Indeed, that this training in tool use is successful at all is a major discovery and challenges received knowledge.$

Imitation had already been pinpointed in the late nineteenth century by the American psychologist James Mark Baldwin (of ‘Baldwin e%ect’ fame): ‘By imitation the little animal picks up directly the example, instruction, mode of life, etc. of his private family circle and species.’' Since the early &''#s Cacioppo and Berntson have used the term ‘social neuroscience’ to describe their work, but this has rather little to do with our interest in the social brain, as the focus seems to be chiefly on correlations between neural states and behavior.&# Closer in spirit to the tradition I shall be dis-cussing is the study of the culturally and socially constructed nature of the brain, which more

thinking about the brain as social that is ultimately Spinozist in nature, via Marx, Lev Vygotsky and the contemporary philosopher Antonio Negri – the last two of whom explicitly refer to Spinoza’s philosophy as a basis for their projects. One of the points I will make in light of this reconstruction is that the Marxist hostility to cognitive science might have to be reconsidered to some extent. (Marx himself uses the expression ‘social brain.’* Or, put di%erently, an incidental accomplish-ment of my reconstruction of this tradition should be to make it harder for politi-cally motivated critiques of cognitive science and artificial intelligence to claim that theories of intellect and action that seek to involve the brain are necessarily individualistic, ‘reactionary,’ in the service of the military-industrial complex, and so forth.+ If anything, the danger will be from the side of the ‘group mind,’ as we shall see in closing.

I shall proceed in five steps: after a brief review of recent discussions of social cognition, I shall try to make explicit the Spinozist context for the social brain; next I shall summarize some key ideas of the ‘Soviet school’ (Vygotsky, Luria), then move from the ‘socialist’ to the ‘avant-garde’ brain (which are really two ways of describing the same thing, as we shall see); finally, I discuss the ‘Italian’ moment of the social brain, with Negri and Virno, including some reflections on tools and prostheses, and conclude with some considerations on the social brain and the group mind.

Varieties of Social Cognition Obviously not all ‘social brains,’ or rather their conceptualizations, are equal. Social epistemology, the emphasis on the primacy of emotions and the importance of ‘common notions’ are not all the same. !e ‘social’ dimension that is being emphasized in the discussions of ‘social intellect,’( which culminated in the notion of ‘Machiavellian intelligence’ and its presence in the primate world, is that of the individual’s capacity to interact successfully with social groups, to predict and manipulate behavior, to make and break promises, and so forth. !e energetic demands of such a complex situation are ultimately presented as responsible for the large size of primates’ brains, so that some evolutionary anthropologists and their collaborators in related fields took to calling the Machiavellian Intelligence hypothesis, the ‘social brain hypothesis.’

!e ‘social’ in ‘social cognition’ focuses notably on mirror neurons, which indicate the existence in the brain of a particular recognition or decoding of action and thus of the imitation of action,, implying an understanding of other people’s intentions, goals and desires. Mirror neurons, found in the ventral premotor cortex of macaque monkeys, are activated both when the monkey executes grasp-ing actions (grasping a peanut, for example) and when it observes someone else (or another monkey) making grasping actions, or even the preparation of a motor act. Mirror neurons appear to distinguish between biological and nonbiological

Page 14: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

18 8 18 9

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

11 See, Edward Hutchins, Cognition in the Wild (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 9 5); a recent example of ‘distributed cognition’ work is Morana Ala �, ‘Working with Brain Scans: Digital Images and G estural Interaction in a fMR I Laboratory,’ Social Studies of Science 3 8 (2 0 0 8): 4 8 3-5 0 8 . After writing an earlier version of this paper I discovered: Michael Cole and James V. Wertsch, ‘Beyond the Individual-Social Antinomy in Discussions of P iaget and Vygotsky,’ Human Development 5 (1 9 9 6): 2 5 0-6 , which makes some connections here (notably between Vygotsky and the idea of ‘distributed cognition’), but does not mention the actual relation to the brain. G eertz’s quote is from ‘The Growth of Culture and the Evolution of Mind’ (1 9 6 2), in The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1 9 73), 76 (thanks to John Sutton for this reference).12 Thomas Metzinger and Vittorio G allese, ‘The emergence of a shared action ontology. Building blocks for a theory,’ Consciousness and Cognition 4 (2 0 0 3): 5 4 9 .13 Antonio Negri, Marx Beyond Marx, ed. J. F leming, translated by H. C leaver, M. Ryan and M. Viano (New York: Autonomedia, 1 9 8 4). See also the prefaces by Yann Moulier and Matteo Mandarini to Negri, The Politics of Subversion, translated by J. Newell (Oxford: Polity/ B lack-well, 1 9 8 9) and Autonomia: Post-Political Politics, eds. Sylvère Lotringer and Christian Marazzi (New York: Semiotext(e), 2 0 0 7 [1 9 8 0]).14 The only work I am aware of that makes a connection between the autonomist Marxist theory of the ‘social brain’ and Vygotsky’s landmark research at the intersection of social psychology, developmental psychology, linguistics and neuroscience is Virno’s ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation’; Virno was himself active in the former movement. See: Paolo Virno, ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation,’ Multitudes 7 (2 0 01): 1 0 3-1 7 – also at the URL http://multitudes.samizdat.net/article.php3?id_article = 6 5 .15 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘Spinoza’s Theory of the Emotions in Light of Contemporary Psychoneurol-ogy,’ translated by E. Berg, Soviet Studies In Philosophy 1 0 (1 9 72): 3 6 2-8 2 ; and for his biography, Jaan Valsiner and René van der Veer, The Social Mind (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 2 0 0 0), 3 2 5f. On the idea that Spinoza anticipated contemporary ‘affective neuroscience’ (from Damasio to G allese’s study of mirror neurons), see the short but useful commentary by Heidi Morrison Ravven, ‘Spinozistic Approaches to Evolutionary Naturalism: Spinoza’s Anticipation of Contemporary Affective Neuroscience,’ Politics and the Life Sciences 1 (2 0 0 3): 70-4 .

that the concept of social brain appears in various passages in the works of the ‘autonomist’ Italian Marxist thinkers Toni Negri and Paolo Virno, where they use it synonymously with the even more mysterious expression ‘General Intellect,’ derived from the so-called ‘Fragment on Machines’ in Marx’s Grundrisse, his notebooks of the late &$+#s which Negri ‘rediscovered’ as a source for another, heterodox Marxism in celebrated lectures given at the École Normale Supérieure in Paris in the late &',#s, at the invitation of Louis Althusser.&) !e Spinozist tradition of the social brain runs con-currently from Spinoza to Marx and his reinterpretation by Negri, and from Spinoza to the neu-ropsychologists Lev Semyonovich Vygotsky and Alexander Romanovich Luria in Russia in the &'"#s and &')#s. (!ey worked together notably at the Institute of Experimental Psychology in Moscow, starting in &'"*, until Vygotsky’s untimely death from tuberculosis in &')*, at the age of ),.)&* !e story could be extended to include both the ‘coevolution’ approach to brain and language proposed by Terrence Deacon and, in a more ‘American’ and ‘therapeutic’ vein, the type of ‘a%ec-tive neuroscience’ proposed by Antonio Damasio. Indeed, claims about the embodied, embedded nature of cognition, or the ultimate ‘commonness’ of its contents, are inseparable from an a%ective component, as in Spinoza, and Vygotsky noticed this, authoring a manuscript on Spinoza’s theory of the emotions or ‘a%ects’ which was published posthumously; Spinoza’s Ethics, which he had received as a gift from his father at a young age, remained his favorite book throughout his life.&+

recently has focused on its necessarily ‘networked’ dimension – the ‘mind-like properties of social groups,’ in the words of Ed Hutchins, the chief theorist of ‘distributed cognition’; for an early, and broader statement of what we might call the cultural sca%olding of the mental, consider this passage from a &'(" paper by Cli%ord Geertz:

!e accepted view that mental functioning is essentially an intracerebral process, which can only be secondarily assisted or amplified by the various artificial devices which that process has enabled man to invent, appears to be quite wrong; the human brain is thoroughly dependent upon cultural resources for its very operation; and those resources are, consequently, not adjuncts to, but constituents of, mental activity. In fact, thinking as an overt, public act, involving the purposeful manipulation of objective materials, is probably fundamental to human beings; and thinking as a covert, private act, and without recourse to such materials, a derived, though not unuseful, capability.&&

However, these di%erent approaches that stress the role of culture, social institu-tions, and so forth in structuring the mind, still do not make ontological claims about the brain itself. Instead, we are interested in the social and materialist variant of the claim ‘the brain possesses an ontology too.’&"

Under the influence of J.J. Gibson, in their influential paper ‘!e Extended Mind’ (&''$), Andy Clark and David Chalmers and in a di%erent vein the ‘enac-tivist’ approach to cognition proposed by Francisco Varela and others, ‘ethological’ and ‘ecological’ approaches to the study of brain, body, and mind have become mainstream; they are simply part of the framework for understanding the behav-ior of an organism. But the environment that’s studied there still tends to be viewed in terms of stimulus and response (the red spot of paint that the little bird pecks at), and not in terms of the symbolic world, the historically, socially, and culturally determined world of representations, of role-playing, of recognition in which we actually live and act. In fact, symbolic practices are not a mere, external ‘cultural environment’ in which ‘brains’ lie floating. Instead, both these practices and the organ called ‘brain’ possess a fundamental plasticity, and we need to understand them together.

But rather than seek to broker agreement between various schools of thought, or retreat behind the safe posture of the intellectual historian relating the discovery of the ‘fact’ that our selves or minds, which turn out to be our brains, are socially produced and perhaps determined, I would, as indicated above, like to analyze a tradition out of which a unique concept, ‘the social brain,’ has emerged, from the post-Cartesian metaphysics of Spinoza to its neurological and Marxist reprisals in Vygotsky and Negri.

!is will not, however, be a study in the history of Marxism – su-ce it to say

Page 15: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

18 8 18 9

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

11 See, Edward Hutchins, Cognition in the Wild (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 9 5); a recent example of ‘distributed cognition’ work is Morana Ala �, ‘Working with Brain Scans: Digital Images and G estural Interaction in a fMR I Laboratory,’ Social Studies of Science 3 8 (2 0 0 8): 4 8 3-5 0 8 . After writing an earlier version of this paper I discovered: Michael Cole and James V. Wertsch, ‘Beyond the Individual-Social Antinomy in Discussions of P iaget and Vygotsky,’ Human Development 5 (1 9 9 6): 2 5 0-6 , which makes some connections here (notably between Vygotsky and the idea of ‘distributed cognition’), but does not mention the actual relation to the brain. G eertz’s quote is from ‘The Growth of Culture and the Evolution of Mind’ (1 9 6 2), in The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1 9 73), 76 (thanks to John Sutton for this reference).12 Thomas Metzinger and Vittorio G allese, ‘The emergence of a shared action ontology. Building blocks for a theory,’ Consciousness and Cognition 4 (2 0 0 3): 5 4 9 .13 Antonio Negri, Marx Beyond Marx, ed. J. F leming, translated by H. C leaver, M. Ryan and M. Viano (New York: Autonomedia, 1 9 8 4). See also the prefaces by Yann Moulier and Matteo Mandarini to Negri, The Politics of Subversion, translated by J. Newell (Oxford: Polity/ B lack-well, 1 9 8 9) and Autonomia: Post-Political Politics, eds. Sylvère Lotringer and Christian Marazzi (New York: Semiotext(e), 2 0 0 7 [1 9 8 0]).14 The only work I am aware of that makes a connection between the autonomist Marxist theory of the ‘social brain’ and Vygotsky’s landmark research at the intersection of social psychology, developmental psychology, linguistics and neuroscience is Virno’s ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation’; Virno was himself active in the former movement. See: Paolo Virno, ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation,’ Multitudes 7 (2 0 01): 1 0 3-1 7 – also at the URL http://multitudes.samizdat.net/article.php3?id_article = 6 5 .15 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘Spinoza’s Theory of the Emotions in Light of Contemporary Psychoneurol-ogy,’ translated by E. Berg, Soviet Studies In Philosophy 1 0 (1 9 72): 3 6 2-8 2 ; and for his biography, Jaan Valsiner and René van der Veer, The Social Mind (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 2 0 0 0), 3 2 5f. On the idea that Spinoza anticipated contemporary ‘affective neuroscience’ (from Damasio to G allese’s study of mirror neurons), see the short but useful commentary by Heidi Morrison Ravven, ‘Spinozistic Approaches to Evolutionary Naturalism: Spinoza’s Anticipation of Contemporary Affective Neuroscience,’ Politics and the Life Sciences 1 (2 0 0 3): 70-4 .

that the concept of social brain appears in various passages in the works of the ‘autonomist’ Italian Marxist thinkers Toni Negri and Paolo Virno, where they use it synonymously with the even more mysterious expression ‘General Intellect,’ derived from the so-called ‘Fragment on Machines’ in Marx’s Grundrisse, his notebooks of the late &$+#s which Negri ‘rediscovered’ as a source for another, heterodox Marxism in celebrated lectures given at the École Normale Supérieure in Paris in the late &',#s, at the invitation of Louis Althusser.&) !e Spinozist tradition of the social brain runs con-currently from Spinoza to Marx and his reinterpretation by Negri, and from Spinoza to the neu-ropsychologists Lev Semyonovich Vygotsky and Alexander Romanovich Luria in Russia in the &'"#s and &')#s. (!ey worked together notably at the Institute of Experimental Psychology in Moscow, starting in &'"*, until Vygotsky’s untimely death from tuberculosis in &')*, at the age of ),.)&* !e story could be extended to include both the ‘coevolution’ approach to brain and language proposed by Terrence Deacon and, in a more ‘American’ and ‘therapeutic’ vein, the type of ‘a%ec-tive neuroscience’ proposed by Antonio Damasio. Indeed, claims about the embodied, embedded nature of cognition, or the ultimate ‘commonness’ of its contents, are inseparable from an a%ective component, as in Spinoza, and Vygotsky noticed this, authoring a manuscript on Spinoza’s theory of the emotions or ‘a%ects’ which was published posthumously; Spinoza’s Ethics, which he had received as a gift from his father at a young age, remained his favorite book throughout his life.&+

recently has focused on its necessarily ‘networked’ dimension – the ‘mind-like properties of social groups,’ in the words of Ed Hutchins, the chief theorist of ‘distributed cognition’; for an early, and broader statement of what we might call the cultural sca%olding of the mental, consider this passage from a &'(" paper by Cli%ord Geertz:

!e accepted view that mental functioning is essentially an intracerebral process, which can only be secondarily assisted or amplified by the various artificial devices which that process has enabled man to invent, appears to be quite wrong; the human brain is thoroughly dependent upon cultural resources for its very operation; and those resources are, consequently, not adjuncts to, but constituents of, mental activity. In fact, thinking as an overt, public act, involving the purposeful manipulation of objective materials, is probably fundamental to human beings; and thinking as a covert, private act, and without recourse to such materials, a derived, though not unuseful, capability.&&

However, these di%erent approaches that stress the role of culture, social institu-tions, and so forth in structuring the mind, still do not make ontological claims about the brain itself. Instead, we are interested in the social and materialist variant of the claim ‘the brain possesses an ontology too.’&"

Under the influence of J.J. Gibson, in their influential paper ‘!e Extended Mind’ (&''$), Andy Clark and David Chalmers and in a di%erent vein the ‘enac-tivist’ approach to cognition proposed by Francisco Varela and others, ‘ethological’ and ‘ecological’ approaches to the study of brain, body, and mind have become mainstream; they are simply part of the framework for understanding the behav-ior of an organism. But the environment that’s studied there still tends to be viewed in terms of stimulus and response (the red spot of paint that the little bird pecks at), and not in terms of the symbolic world, the historically, socially, and culturally determined world of representations, of role-playing, of recognition in which we actually live and act. In fact, symbolic practices are not a mere, external ‘cultural environment’ in which ‘brains’ lie floating. Instead, both these practices and the organ called ‘brain’ possess a fundamental plasticity, and we need to understand them together.

But rather than seek to broker agreement between various schools of thought, or retreat behind the safe posture of the intellectual historian relating the discovery of the ‘fact’ that our selves or minds, which turn out to be our brains, are socially produced and perhaps determined, I would, as indicated above, like to analyze a tradition out of which a unique concept, ‘the social brain,’ has emerged, from the post-Cartesian metaphysics of Spinoza to its neurological and Marxist reprisals in Vygotsky and Negri.

!is will not, however, be a study in the history of Marxism – su-ce it to say

Page 16: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 0 191

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

16 Respectively, P.F. Strawson, Individuals (London: Methuen, 1 9 5 9), 9 7 and Fred Dretske, Naturalizing the Mind (C ambridge, MA.: MIT Press, 1 9 9 5), 6 5 .17 Henri Bergson, Matière et mémoire (Paris: PU F, 1 9 3 9 [1 8 9 6]), 4 6-7. English: Matter and Memory, translated by N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer (1 91 0) (New York: Zone Books, 1 9 8 8).18 John Dewey, Experience and Nature (London: Allen & Unwin/Chicago: Open Court, 1 9 2 9), 1 9 2 .19 Baruch Spinoza, Ethics (1 6 76), in Ethics / Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect /Selected Letters, translated by Samuel Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1 9 9 2). See II, prop. 7.20 Ibid., see III, prop. 6 . This striving is frequently misread outside of Spinoza scholarship as being specifically ‘vital’ or ‘biological,’ including in Damasio’s version where it becomes a particular disposition of cerebral circuits such that an internal or external stimulus will induce them to seek out their well-being or survival. See: Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (New York: Harcourt, 2 0 0 3). For a rather touching expression of the ‘goalless drive’ quality of the conatus, see Boris Achour’s ‘ Conatus’ video series, such as http://borisachour.net/index.php?page = conatus-le-danseur.21 Ibid., see IV, prop. 3 9 , building on II, prop. 1 3 , Scholium (the ‘little physics’ of the Ethics), especially lemmata 1 , 7, scholium; Short Treatise, II, 1 4 .22 Ibid., see II, axiom 2 . For a nice summary, see Vittorio Morfino, ‘Ontologie de la relation et matérialisme de la contingence,’ Actuel Marx 1 8 (2 0 0 3): § 5 . ‘Spinoza: An Ontology of Relation?’, revised and shortened version of ‘Ontologie de la relation,’ in Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, New School for Social Research, 1 (2 0 0 6): 1 0 3-2 723 Ibid., III, prop. 2 , scholium.24 Alexander Romanovich Luria, ‘Psychoanalysis as Monistic Psychology’ (1 9 2 5), in The Selected Writings of A.R. Luria, ed. M. Cole (New York: M.E. Sharpe, 1 9 78). 25 In the yet unwritten history of vitalism (a project in which I am partly engaged), a study of Vygotsky’s and Bakhtin’s respective critiques of vitalism would make an interesting chapter. See the unknown text by Bakhtin on Driesch: Mikhail Bakhtin, ‘ Contemporary Vitalism’ (1 9 2 6), translation in The crisis in modernism. Bergson and the vitalist controversy, eds. F. Burwick and P. Douglass (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 1 9 9 2). It is possible that, despite the former’s invocation of a common cause between socialism and the cortex, both Vygotsky and Bakhtin (with Spinoza on their side) would not fully follow the Deleuzean-Negrian immanentist and vitalist gesture to make the brain itself a locus of resistance, since this would lead into contradictions: a) all humankind possesses such brains, yet; b) not all of humankind is either ‘avant-garde’ or ‘revolutionary’; I am responding here to an objection first put to me by Katja Diefenbach. However, one might reply that the brain is a tool …

mind (and hence emotion and other forms of cognition; ideas and bodily states, etcetera) are interrelated as particular relations within this network: ‘!e order of the actions and passions of our body coincides in nature with the order of the actions and passions of the mind.’") In this sense we should not overly emphasize a possible tension between a ‘rationalist’ tendency in Spinozism toward the second and third kinds of knowledge, and an ‘a%ective’ tendency.

Alexander Luria’s ‘monistic’ critique of psychology is explicitly Spinozist."* He thinks that both Feuerbachian materialism and psychoanalysis contribute to this monistic approach, unlike the ‘soul’-oriented tradition of philosophical psychology. (Vygotsky disagreed with this essay for inappropriately trying to synthesize Freudianism and Marxism without acknowledging their specific di%erences.) In Luria’s view, psychology was too dualistic – either too mechanistic, with no recognition of activity, or too vitalistic,"+ with no recognition of the causal (and thus determin-istic) relations within which life, including mental life, takes place – and it has been this way at least since Descartes’ Passions of the Soul. Similarly, Vygotsky proposed a Spinozist ‘reform’ of psy-chology, arguing that: ‘!inking is nothing other than a function of the brain. Mental life does not have an independent existence; following Spinoza’s definition, thinking is not a substance but

Networks and Common Notions: Some Spinozist Basics Discussions of ‘person,’ ‘self,’ ‘experience,’ even when they bring in an embodied, material dimension, frequently appeal to a first-person concept of experience. !is is usually opposed to a third-person view, typically presented as the point of view of the natural scientist with her measuring instruments. Many philosophers hold that we will never know what it is like to have someone else’s first-person experi-ence. One trait shared by all the thinkers discussed here, from Spinoza to Negri, is that they do not hold this view. We might call this the di%erence between internalists and externalists. If the internalist holds that ‘states, or experiences … owe their identity as particulars to the identity of the person whose states or experiences they are,’ the externalist holds that ‘no fact is only accessible to a single person,’&( and finds it merely a sign of laziness or potential mistakes that it is easier to consult oneself than to consult Nature. An unexpected ally of exter-nalism is Bergson, who declares: ‘Why should I go, against all appearances, from my conscious self to my body, then from my body to other bodies, while in fact I am located from the outset in the material world in general, and gradually limit the center of action which will be called “my body,” thereby distinguishing it from all other bodies?’&, Or Dewey: ‘!ere is nothing in nature that belongs absolutely and exclusively to anything else; belonging is always a matter of reference and distributive assignment.’&$ Spinoza, too, is an externalist.

In an important proposition of the Ethics, Spinoza declares that ‘the order and the connexion of ideas is the same as the order and the connexion of things.’&' Spinoza locates the individual within a world of relations; to be an individual is in fact nothing other than being a particular intersection in a giant universe of rela-tions. !is is what it is to be a finite mode of an infinite substance. One might think of a connectionist model, a neural net in which particular links are reinforced. Within this Spinozist universe of relations, any such intersection, whether it is a stone, a Fanta can, an animal, or me, strives to persevere in existence, as the finite mode it is; this striving is the conatus."# What this implies for Spinoza’s view of the ‘subject’ or ‘agent’ is that she will not be defined by her interiority, by private mental states, a fortiori private and foundational mental states. An individual is a certain quantum of striving, and thereby a certain relation between di%erent points in the total causal network. And the di%erence between a live individual and a dead individual is simply that each is a di%erent ‘ratio’ of motion and rest (ratio motus et quietis)."&

Exactly as a contemporary practitioner of ‘social’ or ‘a%ective’ neuroscience might have it, the passions are not properties of an essential human nature, or an iso-lated individual, but rather of a relational spectrum between a plurality of indi-viduals. Instead of Descartes’ cogito ergo sum, Spinoza says homo cogitat,"" ‘man thinks’: there is no foundational self, but always a process – a network. Body and

Page 17: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 0 191

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

16 Respectively, P.F. Strawson, Individuals (London: Methuen, 1 9 5 9), 9 7 and Fred Dretske, Naturalizing the Mind (C ambridge, MA.: MIT Press, 1 9 9 5), 6 5 .17 Henri Bergson, Matière et mémoire (Paris: PU F, 1 9 3 9 [1 8 9 6]), 4 6-7. English: Matter and Memory, translated by N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer (1 91 0) (New York: Zone Books, 1 9 8 8).18 John Dewey, Experience and Nature (London: Allen & Unwin/Chicago: Open Court, 1 9 2 9), 1 9 2 .19 Baruch Spinoza, Ethics (1 6 76), in Ethics / Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect /Selected Letters, translated by Samuel Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1 9 9 2). See II, prop. 7.20 Ibid., see III, prop. 6 . This striving is frequently misread outside of Spinoza scholarship as being specifically ‘vital’ or ‘biological,’ including in Damasio’s version where it becomes a particular disposition of cerebral circuits such that an internal or external stimulus will induce them to seek out their well-being or survival. See: Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain (New York: Harcourt, 2 0 0 3). For a rather touching expression of the ‘goalless drive’ quality of the conatus, see Boris Achour’s ‘ Conatus’ video series, such as http://borisachour.net/index.php?page = conatus-le-danseur.21 Ibid., see IV, prop. 3 9 , building on II, prop. 1 3 , Scholium (the ‘little physics’ of the Ethics), especially lemmata 1 , 7, scholium; Short Treatise, II, 1 4 .22 Ibid., see II, axiom 2 . For a nice summary, see Vittorio Morfino, ‘Ontologie de la relation et matérialisme de la contingence,’ Actuel Marx 1 8 (2 0 0 3): § 5 . ‘Spinoza: An Ontology of Relation?’, revised and shortened version of ‘Ontologie de la relation,’ in Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, New School for Social Research, 1 (2 0 0 6): 1 0 3-2 723 Ibid., III, prop. 2 , scholium.24 Alexander Romanovich Luria, ‘Psychoanalysis as Monistic Psychology’ (1 9 2 5), in The Selected Writings of A.R. Luria, ed. M. Cole (New York: M.E. Sharpe, 1 9 78). 25 In the yet unwritten history of vitalism (a project in which I am partly engaged), a study of Vygotsky’s and Bakhtin’s respective critiques of vitalism would make an interesting chapter. See the unknown text by Bakhtin on Driesch: Mikhail Bakhtin, ‘ Contemporary Vitalism’ (1 9 2 6), translation in The crisis in modernism. Bergson and the vitalist controversy, eds. F. Burwick and P. Douglass (C ambridge: C ambridge University Press, 1 9 9 2). It is possible that, despite the former’s invocation of a common cause between socialism and the cortex, both Vygotsky and Bakhtin (with Spinoza on their side) would not fully follow the Deleuzean-Negrian immanentist and vitalist gesture to make the brain itself a locus of resistance, since this would lead into contradictions: a) all humankind possesses such brains, yet; b) not all of humankind is either ‘avant-garde’ or ‘revolutionary’; I am responding here to an objection first put to me by Katja Diefenbach. However, one might reply that the brain is a tool …

mind (and hence emotion and other forms of cognition; ideas and bodily states, etcetera) are interrelated as particular relations within this network: ‘!e order of the actions and passions of our body coincides in nature with the order of the actions and passions of the mind.’") In this sense we should not overly emphasize a possible tension between a ‘rationalist’ tendency in Spinozism toward the second and third kinds of knowledge, and an ‘a%ective’ tendency.

Alexander Luria’s ‘monistic’ critique of psychology is explicitly Spinozist."* He thinks that both Feuerbachian materialism and psychoanalysis contribute to this monistic approach, unlike the ‘soul’-oriented tradition of philosophical psychology. (Vygotsky disagreed with this essay for inappropriately trying to synthesize Freudianism and Marxism without acknowledging their specific di%erences.) In Luria’s view, psychology was too dualistic – either too mechanistic, with no recognition of activity, or too vitalistic,"+ with no recognition of the causal (and thus determin-istic) relations within which life, including mental life, takes place – and it has been this way at least since Descartes’ Passions of the Soul. Similarly, Vygotsky proposed a Spinozist ‘reform’ of psy-chology, arguing that: ‘!inking is nothing other than a function of the brain. Mental life does not have an independent existence; following Spinoza’s definition, thinking is not a substance but

Networks and Common Notions: Some Spinozist Basics Discussions of ‘person,’ ‘self,’ ‘experience,’ even when they bring in an embodied, material dimension, frequently appeal to a first-person concept of experience. !is is usually opposed to a third-person view, typically presented as the point of view of the natural scientist with her measuring instruments. Many philosophers hold that we will never know what it is like to have someone else’s first-person experi-ence. One trait shared by all the thinkers discussed here, from Spinoza to Negri, is that they do not hold this view. We might call this the di%erence between internalists and externalists. If the internalist holds that ‘states, or experiences … owe their identity as particulars to the identity of the person whose states or experiences they are,’ the externalist holds that ‘no fact is only accessible to a single person,’&( and finds it merely a sign of laziness or potential mistakes that it is easier to consult oneself than to consult Nature. An unexpected ally of exter-nalism is Bergson, who declares: ‘Why should I go, against all appearances, from my conscious self to my body, then from my body to other bodies, while in fact I am located from the outset in the material world in general, and gradually limit the center of action which will be called “my body,” thereby distinguishing it from all other bodies?’&, Or Dewey: ‘!ere is nothing in nature that belongs absolutely and exclusively to anything else; belonging is always a matter of reference and distributive assignment.’&$ Spinoza, too, is an externalist.

In an important proposition of the Ethics, Spinoza declares that ‘the order and the connexion of ideas is the same as the order and the connexion of things.’&' Spinoza locates the individual within a world of relations; to be an individual is in fact nothing other than being a particular intersection in a giant universe of rela-tions. !is is what it is to be a finite mode of an infinite substance. One might think of a connectionist model, a neural net in which particular links are reinforced. Within this Spinozist universe of relations, any such intersection, whether it is a stone, a Fanta can, an animal, or me, strives to persevere in existence, as the finite mode it is; this striving is the conatus."# What this implies for Spinoza’s view of the ‘subject’ or ‘agent’ is that she will not be defined by her interiority, by private mental states, a fortiori private and foundational mental states. An individual is a certain quantum of striving, and thereby a certain relation between di%erent points in the total causal network. And the di%erence between a live individual and a dead individual is simply that each is a di%erent ‘ratio’ of motion and rest (ratio motus et quietis)."&

Exactly as a contemporary practitioner of ‘social’ or ‘a%ective’ neuroscience might have it, the passions are not properties of an essential human nature, or an iso-lated individual, but rather of a relational spectrum between a plurality of indi-viduals. Instead of Descartes’ cogito ergo sum, Spinoza says homo cogitat,"" ‘man thinks’: there is no foundational self, but always a process – a network. Body and

Page 18: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

192 193

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

26 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘The genesis of higher mental functions,’ quoted in Alexandre Métraux, ‘Die zer brochene Psychophysik. Anmerkungen zu Lev Vygotskijs Spinoza-Rezeption,’ Studia Spinozana 8 (1 9 9 2): 1 9 7 (my translation from the G erman).27 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘On Psychological Systems,’ in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 3 : Problems of Theory and Method in Psychology, eds. R.S. Rieber and J. Wollock, translated by R. van der Veer (New York: P lenum Press, 1 9 9 7), 1 0 3 .28 Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (C ambridge, MA: Oxford University Press, 1 9 8 4), 2 81 . 29 Spinoza, Ethics II, prop. 3 8 .30 Ibid., prop. 3 9 .31 Terrence Deacon, The Symbolic Species (New York: W.W. Norton, 1 9 9 7), 41 9 .32 On the role Spinoza played in the radical thought of Negri, Balibar and others, see the very detailed (but turgid) review essay: C éline Spector, ‘Le spinozisme politique aujourd’hui,’ Esprit 77 (May 2 0 0 7): 2 7-4 5 .33 René van der Veer, ‘Some Major Themes in Vygotsky’s Work,’ in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 3 , 5 .

Negri will add quite consistently, our brains – common. Common notions are conceptions of things ‘which are common to all.’"' !ere are common notions shared between bodies, and the more I ‘have’ or ‘know’ them, the more I have adequate knowledge of body, and more materialisti-cally, the more my body has in common with other bodies, the more my mind is capable of per-ceiving things adequately.)# !e common notions allow us to step beyond the consideration of singular things and see (some of ) the greater network-machine beyond us: we then see how finite modes are produced by an infinite substance. !ey are not to be confused with an aesthetic or sen-sory modality such as the sensus communis. Put di%erently, with reference to the a%ects: they are necessarily social, being about ‘otherness’ or ‘exteriority.’ For example, laughter and sobbing are distinctly human features activated by limbic structures; importantly, they are the first two social valorizations that children make, and they induce responses in others that are highly predictive of emotional states.)&

Let’s move now from the Spinozist context to the socialist cortex (in the language, summarized, of one Bolshevik child psychologist in the &')#s, but also of Vygotsky himself, as we shall see). If this sounds like a leap from the quiet, cautious lifestyle of Bento Spinoza, one should bear in mind the explicit political ramifications of his metaphysics (to be precise, the two are on the same plane): Spinozism is the, or at least a key form of ‘absolute democracy,’ understood as a situation in which spontaneous practices that are generated by civil forms of interaction and cooperation are never taken as ‘fixed’ by the state. As Negri notably has done much to emphasize, Spinoza holds that all other forms of government are warped, constraints on human society, whereas democracy is its natural fulfillment.)"

The Socialist Cortex Given this Spinozist framework, the first real ‘pass’ toward the vision of the brain itself as social – of cerebral architecture as reflecting changes in the linguistic, social, and cultural environments – was made by Lev Vygotsky and his collaborator Alexander Luria in Russia in the &'"#s and &')#s. Vygotsky died quite young but he managed to lay the foundations for a variety of fields of inquiry (he and Luria are the founders of neuropsychology, along with Kurt Goldstein,)) and he is a first-rank figure in social psychology, linguistics, and developmental psychology). Among the unpublished manuscripts he left behind, one was on

an attribute. A “psychic” [or “mental” – ./] phenomenon does not exist in itself but is rather … a necessary moment in a complex psychophysical process.’"(

!e first Spinozist point was an ontological one, about the nature of the world as a total set of interconnections within which we find ourselves as embodied agents (a ‘relational’ claim familiar in a di%erent form, perhaps, to readers of Michel Callon and Bruno Latour: what they call ‘actor network theory’). !e second Spinozist point is the non-independence of mind and brain with regard to this world. What is missing so far is the ‘self-sculpting’ element, which falls under the heading of emotions or a%ects. Vygotsky adds in another text that:

Spinoza … was a determinist and, in contrast to the Stoics, claimed that man has power over his a%ects, that the intellect may change the order and con-nection of the passions and bring them into accord with the order and con-nections that are given in the intellect. Spinoza expressed a correct genetic relationship. In the process of ontogenetic development the human emotions get connected with general sets both in what regards the individual’s self-con-sciousness and in what regards his knowledge of reality.",

And he regularly emphasizes the a!ective dimension of communication (in stark contrast to what we would now think of as the information-theoretic approach to communication). !is third point, acknowledging the ‘primacy’ of the a%ects, occurs in independent fashion in Vygotsky, in Negri, and in Damasio, each time with reference to Spinoza. For instance, it’s precisely inasmuch as we belong to a greater causal world that we are capable of e%ecting changes in ourselves and internalizing knowledge from the outside (this is also Spinoza’s doctrine of liber-ation as emendation). !e British philosopher Derek Parfit expressed precisely this insight of Spinoza’s when he described the change that came over him once he began thinking about people, and the world as a whole, in reductionist terms:

Is the truth depressing? Some may find it so. But I find it liberating, and con-soling. When I believed that my existence was such a further fact (like a soul or something existing separately from one’s experiences), I seemed impris-oned in myself. My life seemed like a glass tunnel, through which I was moving faster every year, and at the end of which there was darkness. When I changed my view, the walls of my glass tunnel disappeared. I now live in the open air. !ere is still a di%erence between my life and the lives of other people. But the di%erence is less. Other people are closer. I am less concerned about the rest of my own life, and more concerned about the lives of others."$

Now, given these three points, if we add a fourth and last one, it will take us to the ‘social brain’: it is the ‘common notions’ we have which make our persons – and,

Page 19: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

192 193

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

26 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘The genesis of higher mental functions,’ quoted in Alexandre Métraux, ‘Die zer brochene Psychophysik. Anmerkungen zu Lev Vygotskijs Spinoza-Rezeption,’ Studia Spinozana 8 (1 9 9 2): 1 9 7 (my translation from the G erman).27 Lev S. Vygotsky, ‘On Psychological Systems,’ in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 3 : Problems of Theory and Method in Psychology, eds. R.S. Rieber and J. Wollock, translated by R. van der Veer (New York: P lenum Press, 1 9 9 7), 1 0 3 .28 Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (C ambridge, MA: Oxford University Press, 1 9 8 4), 2 81 . 29 Spinoza, Ethics II, prop. 3 8 .30 Ibid., prop. 3 9 .31 Terrence Deacon, The Symbolic Species (New York: W.W. Norton, 1 9 9 7), 41 9 .32 On the role Spinoza played in the radical thought of Negri, Balibar and others, see the very detailed (but turgid) review essay: C éline Spector, ‘Le spinozisme politique aujourd’hui,’ Esprit 77 (May 2 0 0 7): 2 7-4 5 .33 René van der Veer, ‘Some Major Themes in Vygotsky’s Work,’ in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 3 , 5 .

Negri will add quite consistently, our brains – common. Common notions are conceptions of things ‘which are common to all.’"' !ere are common notions shared between bodies, and the more I ‘have’ or ‘know’ them, the more I have adequate knowledge of body, and more materialisti-cally, the more my body has in common with other bodies, the more my mind is capable of per-ceiving things adequately.)# !e common notions allow us to step beyond the consideration of singular things and see (some of ) the greater network-machine beyond us: we then see how finite modes are produced by an infinite substance. !ey are not to be confused with an aesthetic or sen-sory modality such as the sensus communis. Put di%erently, with reference to the a%ects: they are necessarily social, being about ‘otherness’ or ‘exteriority.’ For example, laughter and sobbing are distinctly human features activated by limbic structures; importantly, they are the first two social valorizations that children make, and they induce responses in others that are highly predictive of emotional states.)&

Let’s move now from the Spinozist context to the socialist cortex (in the language, summarized, of one Bolshevik child psychologist in the &')#s, but also of Vygotsky himself, as we shall see). If this sounds like a leap from the quiet, cautious lifestyle of Bento Spinoza, one should bear in mind the explicit political ramifications of his metaphysics (to be precise, the two are on the same plane): Spinozism is the, or at least a key form of ‘absolute democracy,’ understood as a situation in which spontaneous practices that are generated by civil forms of interaction and cooperation are never taken as ‘fixed’ by the state. As Negri notably has done much to emphasize, Spinoza holds that all other forms of government are warped, constraints on human society, whereas democracy is its natural fulfillment.)"

The Socialist Cortex Given this Spinozist framework, the first real ‘pass’ toward the vision of the brain itself as social – of cerebral architecture as reflecting changes in the linguistic, social, and cultural environments – was made by Lev Vygotsky and his collaborator Alexander Luria in Russia in the &'"#s and &')#s. Vygotsky died quite young but he managed to lay the foundations for a variety of fields of inquiry (he and Luria are the founders of neuropsychology, along with Kurt Goldstein,)) and he is a first-rank figure in social psychology, linguistics, and developmental psychology). Among the unpublished manuscripts he left behind, one was on

an attribute. A “psychic” [or “mental” – ./] phenomenon does not exist in itself but is rather … a necessary moment in a complex psychophysical process.’"(

!e first Spinozist point was an ontological one, about the nature of the world as a total set of interconnections within which we find ourselves as embodied agents (a ‘relational’ claim familiar in a di%erent form, perhaps, to readers of Michel Callon and Bruno Latour: what they call ‘actor network theory’). !e second Spinozist point is the non-independence of mind and brain with regard to this world. What is missing so far is the ‘self-sculpting’ element, which falls under the heading of emotions or a%ects. Vygotsky adds in another text that:

Spinoza … was a determinist and, in contrast to the Stoics, claimed that man has power over his a%ects, that the intellect may change the order and con-nection of the passions and bring them into accord with the order and con-nections that are given in the intellect. Spinoza expressed a correct genetic relationship. In the process of ontogenetic development the human emotions get connected with general sets both in what regards the individual’s self-con-sciousness and in what regards his knowledge of reality.",

And he regularly emphasizes the a!ective dimension of communication (in stark contrast to what we would now think of as the information-theoretic approach to communication). !is third point, acknowledging the ‘primacy’ of the a%ects, occurs in independent fashion in Vygotsky, in Negri, and in Damasio, each time with reference to Spinoza. For instance, it’s precisely inasmuch as we belong to a greater causal world that we are capable of e%ecting changes in ourselves and internalizing knowledge from the outside (this is also Spinoza’s doctrine of liber-ation as emendation). !e British philosopher Derek Parfit expressed precisely this insight of Spinoza’s when he described the change that came over him once he began thinking about people, and the world as a whole, in reductionist terms:

Is the truth depressing? Some may find it so. But I find it liberating, and con-soling. When I believed that my existence was such a further fact (like a soul or something existing separately from one’s experiences), I seemed impris-oned in myself. My life seemed like a glass tunnel, through which I was moving faster every year, and at the end of which there was darkness. When I changed my view, the walls of my glass tunnel disappeared. I now live in the open air. !ere is still a di%erence between my life and the lives of other people. But the di%erence is less. Other people are closer. I am less concerned about the rest of my own life, and more concerned about the lives of others."$

Now, given these three points, if we add a fourth and last one, it will take us to the ‘social brain’: it is the ‘common notions’ we have which make our persons – and,

Page 20: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 4 195

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

34 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 3 4 5 .35 William Bechtel and Adele Abrahamsen, ‘L’explication mécaniste et la controverse de l’inné et de l’acquis,’ Bulletin d’Histoire et d’Epistémologie des Sciences de la Vie 1 (2 0 0 5): 75-1 0 0 ; original English ms. available at URL: http://mechanism.ucsd.edu/ ~ bill/research/MechanisticExplanationandtheNatureNurture Contro-versy.pdf.36 John Dewey, Experience and Education (New York: Macmillan, 1 9 3 8 ; reprint, Collier Books, 1 9 6 3), 3 9 .37 John Dewey, Early Works, vol. 5 , ed. J.A. Boydston (C arbondale: Southern Illinois Press, 1 9 71), 5 0 . Quoted by Depew, in Depew and Weber, The Baldwin Effect Revisited, 2 8 , n. 3 . Valsiner and van der Veer’s ambitious book The Social Mind contains chapters on Baldwin, Dewey and Vygotsky (as well as G eorge Herbert Mead, P ierre Janet and a variety of lesser-known figures chiefly from the history of social psychology).38 Lev S. Vygotsky, Mind in Society, edited and translated by M. Cole et al. (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 78), 5 3 ; and, Vygotsky, Collected Works, vol. 3 , 8 8 .39 John A. Bargh, ‘Bypassing the will: Toward demystifying the nonconscious control of social behavior,’ in The New Unconscious, eds. R. Hassin, J.S. Uleman and J.A. Bargh (New York: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 5), 5 0 ; see Bruner’s introduction to A.R. Luria, The Role of Speech in the Regulation of Normal and Abnormal Behavior (New York: Liveright/Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1 9 61); and Merlin Donald, A Mind So Rare: The Evolution of Human Consciousness (New York: Norton, 2 0 01), 2 5 0 .40 Chapter 2 of Thinking and Speech (formerly translated as Thought and Language) is devoted to P iaget, as is chapter 6 , in part. See also Michael Cole and James V. Wertsch, ‘Beyond the Individual-Social Antinomy in Discussions of P iaget and Vygotsky,’ Human Development 5 (1 9 9 6): 2 5 0-6 .41 Lev S. Vygotsky, Thinking and Speech (ch. 7), in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 1 : Problems of General Psychology, ed. R.S. Rieber and A.S. C arton, translated by N. Minick (New York: P lenum Press, 1 9 8 7), 2 5 9 .

Vygotsky describes linguistic activity as necessarily intersubjective: learning a concept involves invoking it, linking it with the performance procedure and external information for which it stands. He calls this the ‘outside-inside’ principle, namely, that symbolic thought first represents external action, and only later becomes internal speech (that is, thought).)' He argues that con-cepts and functions exist for the child first in the social or interpersonal sphere and only later are internalized as intrapsychic concepts. Contra Piaget in particular,*# Vygotsky argues that we don’t move from a solitary, ‘autistic,’ or ‘egocentric’ starting-point toward a gradual socialization, but rather from socialization toward individuality. In these di%erent visions of child development, Piaget looks for universal laws of development, whereas Vygotsky always stresses the plurality of social environments as an irreducible factor in development. But the lessons to be learned go beyond child psychology: ‘!us the central tendency of the child’s development is not a gradual socialization introduced from the outside, but a gradual individualization that emerges on the foundation of the child’s internal socialization.’*&

In the Spinozist terms outlined above, we don’t compose the network(s), they compose us. So far, this is pretty well known – we’ve just restated the necessarily social character of mind or intelligence. Granted that the individual is social and cannot be defined without reference to social factors as primary as the relation of child to mother, what is new is something further, and tied to plasticity: there may even be evidence of consequences in our central nervous system derived from early social interaction. Past experience is embodied in synaptic modifications. !e functional organization of the human brain can be said, in both the Vygotsky-Luria sense and in Deacon’s sense, to reflect socially determined forms or types of activity. As Alexandre Métraux puts it, the origins of the

Spinoza’s Doctrine of the Emotions, in light of but also as the basis for a ‘psychone-urology.’ !e context in which the ideas that concern us appear is in Vygotsky’s work on the development of language in the child. It has powerful resonances with ‘Baldwinian evolution,’ an understanding of evolution that allows for behav-ioral adaptation to precede and condition major biological changes, so that when ‘useful behavior spreads within a population and becomes important for subsist-ence, it will generate selection pressures on generic traits that support its propa-gation’)* (particularly in the case of language: the acquisition of new traits by members of the population changes the social environment and hence sharply intensifies the selection pressures on members of subsequent generations to acquire language), or again, ‘that successful learners will do better in evolutionary competition even though what is learned is not inherited,’)+ this is also referred to as the ‘Baldwin E%ect.’

It may not be surprising that the intellectual trajectory of the brilliant Soviet neuropsychologist intersects with another fan of Spinoza, the great social reformer of the early twentieth century, John Dewey. For Dewey, thought is necessarily symbolic and symbolism is necessarily social, hence the mind is social. Another way of putting this, or possibly a component of it, is to say that there are sources of experience outside the individual:

We live from birth to death in a world of persons and things which is in large measure what it is because of what has been done and transmitted from previous human activities. When this fact is ignored, experience is treated as if it were something which goes on exclusively inside an individual’s body and mind. It ought not to be necessary to say that experience does not occur in a vacuum. !ere are sources outside an individual which give rise to experi-ence.)(

Experience and action or behavior are primary for Dewey (as presumably for all pragmatists), and he believes behavior can be ‘culturally’ selected for in parallel to natural selection, a view which seems to be influenced by Baldwin: ‘one form of life as a whole (is) selected at the expense of other forms… . What di%erence in principle exists between this mediation of the acts of the individual by society and what is ordinarily called natural selection I am unable to see.’), However, Vygot-sky found Dewey’s Aristotelian extension of the ‘tool’ metaphor (language now becoming the tool of tools) too metaphorical, too broad.)$ Another di%erence between them has to do with the status of animals, which do not possess thought for Dewey, whereas Vygotsky integrates into his system a good deal of Wolfgang Köhler’s work with apes, prefiguring the contemporary primate studies I men-tioned above. But for present purposes these di%erences are irrelevant; what remains important is that they share an extreme emphasis on activity, that is, thought and the brain understood as action, as activity.

Page 21: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 4 195

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

34 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 3 4 5 .35 William Bechtel and Adele Abrahamsen, ‘L’explication mécaniste et la controverse de l’inné et de l’acquis,’ Bulletin d’Histoire et d’Epistémologie des Sciences de la Vie 1 (2 0 0 5): 75-1 0 0 ; original English ms. available at URL: http://mechanism.ucsd.edu/ ~ bill/research/MechanisticExplanationandtheNatureNurture Contro-versy.pdf.36 John Dewey, Experience and Education (New York: Macmillan, 1 9 3 8 ; reprint, Collier Books, 1 9 6 3), 3 9 .37 John Dewey, Early Works, vol. 5 , ed. J.A. Boydston (C arbondale: Southern Illinois Press, 1 9 71), 5 0 . Quoted by Depew, in Depew and Weber, The Baldwin Effect Revisited, 2 8 , n. 3 . Valsiner and van der Veer’s ambitious book The Social Mind contains chapters on Baldwin, Dewey and Vygotsky (as well as G eorge Herbert Mead, P ierre Janet and a variety of lesser-known figures chiefly from the history of social psychology).38 Lev S. Vygotsky, Mind in Society, edited and translated by M. Cole et al. (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 78), 5 3 ; and, Vygotsky, Collected Works, vol. 3 , 8 8 .39 John A. Bargh, ‘Bypassing the will: Toward demystifying the nonconscious control of social behavior,’ in The New Unconscious, eds. R. Hassin, J.S. Uleman and J.A. Bargh (New York: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 5), 5 0 ; see Bruner’s introduction to A.R. Luria, The Role of Speech in the Regulation of Normal and Abnormal Behavior (New York: Liveright/Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1 9 61); and Merlin Donald, A Mind So Rare: The Evolution of Human Consciousness (New York: Norton, 2 0 01), 2 5 0 .40 Chapter 2 of Thinking and Speech (formerly translated as Thought and Language) is devoted to P iaget, as is chapter 6 , in part. See also Michael Cole and James V. Wertsch, ‘Beyond the Individual-Social Antinomy in Discussions of P iaget and Vygotsky,’ Human Development 5 (1 9 9 6): 2 5 0-6 .41 Lev S. Vygotsky, Thinking and Speech (ch. 7), in The Collected Works of L.S. Vygotsky, vol. 1 : Problems of General Psychology, ed. R.S. Rieber and A.S. C arton, translated by N. Minick (New York: P lenum Press, 1 9 8 7), 2 5 9 .

Vygotsky describes linguistic activity as necessarily intersubjective: learning a concept involves invoking it, linking it with the performance procedure and external information for which it stands. He calls this the ‘outside-inside’ principle, namely, that symbolic thought first represents external action, and only later becomes internal speech (that is, thought).)' He argues that con-cepts and functions exist for the child first in the social or interpersonal sphere and only later are internalized as intrapsychic concepts. Contra Piaget in particular,*# Vygotsky argues that we don’t move from a solitary, ‘autistic,’ or ‘egocentric’ starting-point toward a gradual socialization, but rather from socialization toward individuality. In these di%erent visions of child development, Piaget looks for universal laws of development, whereas Vygotsky always stresses the plurality of social environments as an irreducible factor in development. But the lessons to be learned go beyond child psychology: ‘!us the central tendency of the child’s development is not a gradual socialization introduced from the outside, but a gradual individualization that emerges on the foundation of the child’s internal socialization.’*&

In the Spinozist terms outlined above, we don’t compose the network(s), they compose us. So far, this is pretty well known – we’ve just restated the necessarily social character of mind or intelligence. Granted that the individual is social and cannot be defined without reference to social factors as primary as the relation of child to mother, what is new is something further, and tied to plasticity: there may even be evidence of consequences in our central nervous system derived from early social interaction. Past experience is embodied in synaptic modifications. !e functional organization of the human brain can be said, in both the Vygotsky-Luria sense and in Deacon’s sense, to reflect socially determined forms or types of activity. As Alexandre Métraux puts it, the origins of the

Spinoza’s Doctrine of the Emotions, in light of but also as the basis for a ‘psychone-urology.’ !e context in which the ideas that concern us appear is in Vygotsky’s work on the development of language in the child. It has powerful resonances with ‘Baldwinian evolution,’ an understanding of evolution that allows for behav-ioral adaptation to precede and condition major biological changes, so that when ‘useful behavior spreads within a population and becomes important for subsist-ence, it will generate selection pressures on generic traits that support its propa-gation’)* (particularly in the case of language: the acquisition of new traits by members of the population changes the social environment and hence sharply intensifies the selection pressures on members of subsequent generations to acquire language), or again, ‘that successful learners will do better in evolutionary competition even though what is learned is not inherited,’)+ this is also referred to as the ‘Baldwin E%ect.’

It may not be surprising that the intellectual trajectory of the brilliant Soviet neuropsychologist intersects with another fan of Spinoza, the great social reformer of the early twentieth century, John Dewey. For Dewey, thought is necessarily symbolic and symbolism is necessarily social, hence the mind is social. Another way of putting this, or possibly a component of it, is to say that there are sources of experience outside the individual:

We live from birth to death in a world of persons and things which is in large measure what it is because of what has been done and transmitted from previous human activities. When this fact is ignored, experience is treated as if it were something which goes on exclusively inside an individual’s body and mind. It ought not to be necessary to say that experience does not occur in a vacuum. !ere are sources outside an individual which give rise to experi-ence.)(

Experience and action or behavior are primary for Dewey (as presumably for all pragmatists), and he believes behavior can be ‘culturally’ selected for in parallel to natural selection, a view which seems to be influenced by Baldwin: ‘one form of life as a whole (is) selected at the expense of other forms… . What di%erence in principle exists between this mediation of the acts of the individual by society and what is ordinarily called natural selection I am unable to see.’), However, Vygot-sky found Dewey’s Aristotelian extension of the ‘tool’ metaphor (language now becoming the tool of tools) too metaphorical, too broad.)$ Another di%erence between them has to do with the status of animals, which do not possess thought for Dewey, whereas Vygotsky integrates into his system a good deal of Wolfgang Köhler’s work with apes, prefiguring the contemporary primate studies I men-tioned above. But for present purposes these di%erences are irrelevant; what remains important is that they share an extreme emphasis on activity, that is, thought and the brain understood as action, as activity.

Page 22: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 6 197

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

42 Métraux, ‘On Luria and the mind-body problem’ (unpublished ms.), § III.43 Jordan Zlatev, ‘The Epigenesis of Meaning in Human Beings, and Possibly in Robots,’ Minds and Machines 1 1 (2 0 01): 1 9 0 .44 Luria, ‘Vygotsky and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ in Luria, Selected Writings, 2 79 . Luria is developing themes from Vygotsky’s ‘Psychology and the Theory of the Localization of Mental Functions,’ translated in Vygotsky, Works, vol. 3 .45 Luria, ‘Vygotsky and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ in Selected Writings or A.R. Luria, 2 79 .46 Aaron Zalkind, quoted in Vygotsky, Pedologija Podrotska, vol. 1 (Moscow, 1 9 2 9),1 4 , quoted in René van der Veer and Jaan Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky. A Quest for Synthesis (London: B lackwell, 1 9 91), 3 2 0 .47 Vygotsky, Pedologija Podrotska, quoted in Van der Veer and Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky, 3 2 0 .48 In particular Halbwachs’ Cadres sociaux de la mémoire (1 9 2 5), which stressed the ‘reconstructive’ dimension of memory; see Alex Kozulin, Vygotsky’s Psychology (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 9 0), 1 2 2-3 . For a different view, which emphasizes the Marxist dimension more strongly see James Wertsch, Vygotsky and the Social Formation of Mind (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 8 5), 8f., and G avriela Eilam, ‘The Philosophical Foundations of Aleksandr R. Luria’s Neuropsychology,’ Science in Context 1 6 (2 0 0 3): 5 51-77, § 2 (the paper is on Luria, but contains various remarks on Vygotsky). The most apt formulation is Métraux’s: Vygotsky’s ‘consistent Spinozist viewpoint’ is also a ‘consistent Marxist viewpoint’ (‘Die zerbrochene Psychophysik,’ 2 0 6). I find the latter reading more convinc-ing (see the image of the cortex and socialism) but it is clear that Vygotsky, like Lukács, Althusser or Negri after him, has to invent a heterodox form of Marxism.49 Vygotsky, ‘The genesis of higher mental functions,’ in The Concept of Activity in Soviet Psychology, ed. James Wertsch (New York: M.E. Sharpe, 1 9 81), 1 6 4 .50 ‘Das menschliches Wesen … in seiner Wirklichkeit ist das Ensemble der gesellschaftlichen Verhältnisse.’51 D.L. Champagne, R.C . Bagot, F. van Hasselt, G . Ramakers, et al., ‘Maternal care and hip-pocampal plasticity: Evidence for experience-dependent structural plasticity, altered synaptic functioning, and differential responsiveness to glucocorticoids and stress,’ Journal of Neuro-science 2 8 (2 0 0 8): 6 0 3 7-4 5 ; and, L.A. Smit-Rigter, D.L. Champagne and J.A. van Hooft, ‘Lifelong Impact of Variations in Maternal C are on Dendritic Structure and Function of Cortical Layer 2/3 Pyramidal Neurons in Rat O ffspring,’ PLoS ONE 4 (2 0 0 9): e51 6 7.52 Respectively, Ranulfo Romo, Adrián Hernández et al., ‘Somatosensory Discrimination Based on Cortical Microstimulation,’ Nature 3 9 2 :6 6 74 (1 9 9 8): 3 8 7-9 0 ; and John B ickle and Ralph Ellis, ‘Phenomenology and Cortical Microstimulation,’ in Phenomenology and the Philoso-phy of Mind, eds. D. Woodruff Smith and A. Thomasson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 5), 1 5 9 . The experiments on macaque monkeys showed that a range of cognitive processes could be initiated and consummated on the basis of artificial stimuli delivered to specific columns of the somatosensory cortex. For more discussion of the implications of this research see my essay ‘Un matérialisme désincarné: la théorie de l’identité cerveau-esprit,’ Matière première 1 (2 0 0 6): Nature et naturalisations, 77-1 0 0 .

including the role of maternal care in hippocampal plasticity in young rats+& and the e%ects of cor-tical microstimulation (a type of experimentation originally pioneered by Wilder Penfield in the &')#s, on epileptic patients) in ‘quantifying the relation between perception and neuronal activity’ and thereby, ‘inducing a phenomenal state’;+" more speculatively, instead of specifically calling the cortex the organ for socialism, we would point, following Terrence Deacon, to the manifestations in cortical architecture of our symbolic, linguistic, and even cultural life (a notion closely related to current debates on ‘niche construction’), or, following J.J. Gibson and Ed Hutchins, we would point to the ways in which perception is necessarily ‘sca%olded’ and cognition ‘distributed.’

We are a ‘symbolic species,’ in Terrence Deacon’s phrase, not because symbols float around in our bloodstream, but because ‘symbols have played a major role in shaping our cognitive capacities in

higher psychological functions such as thinking, believing, wanting, etcetera are not to be sought in the brain or some hidden spiritual entity called ‘spirit’ or ‘mind,’ but in the activity of the members of a society.*" !ese higher functions, one can add, emerge out of ‘the dialectical interaction between specific biological structures (embodiment) and culture (situatedness) through a specific history of development (epigenesis).’*) More dramatically put, as Luria does:

!e fact that in the course of history man has developed new functions does not mean that each one relies on a new group of nerve cells … !e development of new ‘functional organs’ occurs through the development of new functional systems, which is a means for the unlimited development of cerebral activity. !e human cerebral cortex, thanks to this principle, becomes an organ of civilization in which are hidden boundless possibilities.**

He adds that ‘social history ties the knots that produce new correlations between certain zones of the cerebral cortex.’*+

Now we begin to see something new, namely what I referred to as ‘the socialist cortex’: the Bolshevik child psychologist Aaron Zalkind declared (as quoted by Vygotsky) that ‘the cortex is on a shared path with socialism, and socialism is on a shared path with the cortex.’*( A kind of avant-gardism! And Vygotsky himself asserts that ‘history, changing the human type, depends on the cortex; the new socialist man will be created through the cortex; upbringing is in general an influ-ence upon the cortex.’*,

If this were a longer study it would useful at this point to look into the question of Vygotsky’s Marxism. He rejected most of the attempts in his day to link Marx-ism to psychology – including, as we saw, one by Luria – as being inadequate and misconceived; his claim that human mental functions are irreducibly social does not have to be seen as per se derived from Marxism, although he connects himself to this tradition in many other ways, but can also be connected to the French sociological tradition of Émile Durkheim, Lucien Lévy-Bruhl, and Maurice Halbwachs.*$ However, the claim that mind/brain must be understood as ‘the aggregate of internalized social functions,’ once relations have become functions for the individual,*' is explicitly derived from Marx’s Sixth !esis on Feuerbach: ‘Human essence in its reality is the sum of social relations.’+# !at is, Vygotsky is seeking to put cerebral flesh onto the Marxian ontological claim about relations.

The Avant-Garde Brain !e new Socialist man will be created through the cortex … Notice, however, that Vygotsky’s ‘socialist cortex’ stands or falls as a concept without Marxist theory. We would be more likely today to speak of plasticity, of the e%ect of various ecological dimensions on cerebral development,

Page 23: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 6 197

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

42 Métraux, ‘On Luria and the mind-body problem’ (unpublished ms.), § III.43 Jordan Zlatev, ‘The Epigenesis of Meaning in Human Beings, and Possibly in Robots,’ Minds and Machines 1 1 (2 0 01): 1 9 0 .44 Luria, ‘Vygotsky and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ in Luria, Selected Writings, 2 79 . Luria is developing themes from Vygotsky’s ‘Psychology and the Theory of the Localization of Mental Functions,’ translated in Vygotsky, Works, vol. 3 .45 Luria, ‘Vygotsky and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ in Selected Writings or A.R. Luria, 2 79 .46 Aaron Zalkind, quoted in Vygotsky, Pedologija Podrotska, vol. 1 (Moscow, 1 9 2 9),1 4 , quoted in René van der Veer and Jaan Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky. A Quest for Synthesis (London: B lackwell, 1 9 91), 3 2 0 .47 Vygotsky, Pedologija Podrotska, quoted in Van der Veer and Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky, 3 2 0 .48 In particular Halbwachs’ Cadres sociaux de la mémoire (1 9 2 5), which stressed the ‘reconstructive’ dimension of memory; see Alex Kozulin, Vygotsky’s Psychology (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 9 0), 1 2 2-3 . For a different view, which emphasizes the Marxist dimension more strongly see James Wertsch, Vygotsky and the Social Formation of Mind (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 8 5), 8f., and G avriela Eilam, ‘The Philosophical Foundations of Aleksandr R. Luria’s Neuropsychology,’ Science in Context 1 6 (2 0 0 3): 5 51-77, § 2 (the paper is on Luria, but contains various remarks on Vygotsky). The most apt formulation is Métraux’s: Vygotsky’s ‘consistent Spinozist viewpoint’ is also a ‘consistent Marxist viewpoint’ (‘Die zerbrochene Psychophysik,’ 2 0 6). I find the latter reading more convinc-ing (see the image of the cortex and socialism) but it is clear that Vygotsky, like Lukács, Althusser or Negri after him, has to invent a heterodox form of Marxism.49 Vygotsky, ‘The genesis of higher mental functions,’ in The Concept of Activity in Soviet Psychology, ed. James Wertsch (New York: M.E. Sharpe, 1 9 81), 1 6 4 .50 ‘Das menschliches Wesen … in seiner Wirklichkeit ist das Ensemble der gesellschaftlichen Verhältnisse.’51 D.L. Champagne, R.C . Bagot, F. van Hasselt, G . Ramakers, et al., ‘Maternal care and hip-pocampal plasticity: Evidence for experience-dependent structural plasticity, altered synaptic functioning, and differential responsiveness to glucocorticoids and stress,’ Journal of Neuro-science 2 8 (2 0 0 8): 6 0 3 7-4 5 ; and, L.A. Smit-Rigter, D.L. Champagne and J.A. van Hooft, ‘Lifelong Impact of Variations in Maternal C are on Dendritic Structure and Function of Cortical Layer 2/3 Pyramidal Neurons in Rat O ffspring,’ PLoS ONE 4 (2 0 0 9): e51 6 7.52 Respectively, Ranulfo Romo, Adrián Hernández et al., ‘Somatosensory Discrimination Based on Cortical Microstimulation,’ Nature 3 9 2 :6 6 74 (1 9 9 8): 3 8 7-9 0 ; and John B ickle and Ralph Ellis, ‘Phenomenology and Cortical Microstimulation,’ in Phenomenology and the Philoso-phy of Mind, eds. D. Woodruff Smith and A. Thomasson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 5), 1 5 9 . The experiments on macaque monkeys showed that a range of cognitive processes could be initiated and consummated on the basis of artificial stimuli delivered to specific columns of the somatosensory cortex. For more discussion of the implications of this research see my essay ‘Un matérialisme désincarné: la théorie de l’identité cerveau-esprit,’ Matière première 1 (2 0 0 6): Nature et naturalisations, 77-1 0 0 .

including the role of maternal care in hippocampal plasticity in young rats+& and the e%ects of cor-tical microstimulation (a type of experimentation originally pioneered by Wilder Penfield in the &')#s, on epileptic patients) in ‘quantifying the relation between perception and neuronal activity’ and thereby, ‘inducing a phenomenal state’;+" more speculatively, instead of specifically calling the cortex the organ for socialism, we would point, following Terrence Deacon, to the manifestations in cortical architecture of our symbolic, linguistic, and even cultural life (a notion closely related to current debates on ‘niche construction’), or, following J.J. Gibson and Ed Hutchins, we would point to the ways in which perception is necessarily ‘sca%olded’ and cognition ‘distributed.’

We are a ‘symbolic species,’ in Terrence Deacon’s phrase, not because symbols float around in our bloodstream, but because ‘symbols have played a major role in shaping our cognitive capacities in

higher psychological functions such as thinking, believing, wanting, etcetera are not to be sought in the brain or some hidden spiritual entity called ‘spirit’ or ‘mind,’ but in the activity of the members of a society.*" !ese higher functions, one can add, emerge out of ‘the dialectical interaction between specific biological structures (embodiment) and culture (situatedness) through a specific history of development (epigenesis).’*) More dramatically put, as Luria does:

!e fact that in the course of history man has developed new functions does not mean that each one relies on a new group of nerve cells … !e development of new ‘functional organs’ occurs through the development of new functional systems, which is a means for the unlimited development of cerebral activity. !e human cerebral cortex, thanks to this principle, becomes an organ of civilization in which are hidden boundless possibilities.**

He adds that ‘social history ties the knots that produce new correlations between certain zones of the cerebral cortex.’*+

Now we begin to see something new, namely what I referred to as ‘the socialist cortex’: the Bolshevik child psychologist Aaron Zalkind declared (as quoted by Vygotsky) that ‘the cortex is on a shared path with socialism, and socialism is on a shared path with the cortex.’*( A kind of avant-gardism! And Vygotsky himself asserts that ‘history, changing the human type, depends on the cortex; the new socialist man will be created through the cortex; upbringing is in general an influ-ence upon the cortex.’*,

If this were a longer study it would useful at this point to look into the question of Vygotsky’s Marxism. He rejected most of the attempts in his day to link Marx-ism to psychology – including, as we saw, one by Luria – as being inadequate and misconceived; his claim that human mental functions are irreducibly social does not have to be seen as per se derived from Marxism, although he connects himself to this tradition in many other ways, but can also be connected to the French sociological tradition of Émile Durkheim, Lucien Lévy-Bruhl, and Maurice Halbwachs.*$ However, the claim that mind/brain must be understood as ‘the aggregate of internalized social functions,’ once relations have become functions for the individual,*' is explicitly derived from Marx’s Sixth !esis on Feuerbach: ‘Human essence in its reality is the sum of social relations.’+# !at is, Vygotsky is seeking to put cerebral flesh onto the Marxian ontological claim about relations.

The Avant-Garde Brain !e new Socialist man will be created through the cortex … Notice, however, that Vygotsky’s ‘socialist cortex’ stands or falls as a concept without Marxist theory. We would be more likely today to speak of plasticity, of the e%ect of various ecological dimensions on cerebral development,

Page 24: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 8 19 9

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

53 Terrence Deacon, ‘Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system: the problem of language origins,’ in Depew and Weber, Evolution and Learning. The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered, 9 5 .54 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 3 3 6 .55 Deacon, ‘Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system,’ 1 0 0 . 56 Métraux (ms.), § III; Luria, ‘Towards the Problem of the H istorical Nature of Psychological Processes,’ International Journal of Psychology 6 (1 9 71): 2 6 9 57 Deleuze, Negotiations, 6 0/Pourparlers 1972-1990 (Paris: Éditions de Minuit, 1 9 9 0), 8 6 , and the almost visionary discussion of the brain, art and color in G illes Deleuze, Cinéma 2 : L’image-temps (Paris: Minuit, 1 9 8 5), 2 6 6 , n. 2 0 (along with chapter 8 as a whole, which com-prises a section entitled ‘Donne-moi un cerveau,’ ‘G ive me a brain’).58 This Deleuzian approach to the brain is sometimes associated with Francisco Varela’s notion of autopoiesis (emphasizing the self-organizing nature of life and mind – autopoietic systems essentially produce themselves as individuals whereas ‘allopoietic’ systems are, like regular machines, defined by an external output), but this model lacks any recognition of the social. Specifically on Deleuze’s ‘neuroaesthetic,’ see John Rajchman’s excellent discussion in The Deleuze Connections (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 0), 1 3 6-8 .59 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 41 3 , 41 6 .60 Ludwig Feuerbach, ‘On the Dualism of Soul and F lesh’ (Wider den Dualismus von Leib und Seele) (1 8 4 6), in Anthropologischer Materialismus. Ausgewählte Schriften I, ed. A. Schmidt (Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt, 1 9 8 5), 1 77. Compare Bergson’s image of the brain as the ‘bureau téléphonique central,’ as a mere ‘intermediary’ between sensations and motions’ (Matière et mémoire, 2 6 , 1 9 8) … which Vygotsky finds too dualistic! (Vygotsky, Col-lected Works, 1 2 5). See overall chapter 3 of Bergson’s book and Deleuze, Cinéma 2, 2 74 .

Mriganka Sur’s ‘rewired ferrets’ to the recently studied young rats whose hippocampus develops di%erently depending on what kind of maternal care they receive, and onto the Benjaminian realization of the historical conditioning of our forms of perception, we are all avant-gardists in a sense; the same sense in which, according to Deacon, ‘prefrontal overdevelopment has made us all idiots savants of language and symbolic learning.’+'

!e idea is that the brain itself, less in its ‘static,’ anatomical being than in its ‘dynamic,’ physi-ological being – in actu, then – displays features that reflect its embeddedness in or belonging to the social world. !e externalist-Spinozist point to be derived here is that we can only have knowledge about the inner states of others, and indeed, of our own, thanks to the overall structure of symbolic activity (à la Deacon) which externally exhibits the existence of such states, and fur-ther, creates the structure in which such states emerge. Most people don’t realize that Vygotsky and Luria meant the brain itself when speaking about these dynamic, self-transformative features; they usually describe these as belonging to mind or intellect. But Vygotsky and Luria were materi-alists! (Both in the Marxist sense as seen above with respect to the embeddedness of the person in the world of networks – ‘relations’ – and in the more naturalistic sense that they believed intellectual processes could be explainable in terms of, or at least in a causally integrated relation to, cerebral processes.) !e brain for them is no longer just an ‘organ’ mediating between mind and society, through language – not just a ‘physiological abstraction, an organ cut out from the totality of the skull, the face, the body as a whole,’ as Feuerbach put it.(# Extending from the social mind to the social brain is a major step toward, or for materialism. However, neither neurally correlated social cognition nor even Machiavellian primates seem to display anything like the activity of the ‘socialist cortex,’ our shorthand for the transformative dimension of the plastic, socially plastic brain. For this we need not only Spinozist a%ects (along with his reduction of the universe to relations between portions of motion and rest), but a theory of transformation. Behind Vygotsky and Negri, there is also Marx.

ways that are complementary to their special functional demands’;+) ‘language has given rise to a brain which is strongly biased to employ the one mode of associative learning that is most critical to it,’+* namely, ‘the most extensive modification to take place in human brain evolution, the expansion of the cerebral cortex, specifi-cally the prefrontal cortex, reflects the evolutionary adaptation to this intensive working memory processing demand imposed by symbol learning.’++ Hence there is a ‘co-evolution’ of language and the brain. We have learned since at least Walter Benjamin to recognize the historicity of perception; Luria recognized this through his experiments on visual illusions during trips to Uzbekistan in the &')#s; di%er-ent subject groups, depending on their degree of Westernization, had a more or less high chance of seeing the illusions: ‘the more the subjects had dealt with abstract aspects of everyday practice, the less their vision was natural,’ with visual-motor recollection playing a key role – and this recollection being, not a biological invariant but a process ‘determined’ by sociohistorical processes.+(

We might say, ‘!e cortex is the locus of avant-gardism.’ !ink of Deleuze’s phrase: ‘Creating new circuits in art means creating them in the brain’ (Créer de nouveaux circuits s’entend du cerveau en même temps que de l ’art).+, Indeed, there is an entire aesthetic dimension of our construct which I have not discussed here, the first instance of which is Deleuze’s determination of the brain in its plasticity (for instance with reference to Antonioni, in the cinema books). Much like in Benjamin, this is the double-barreled idea that a new kind of brain is required to grasp new spatiotemporal, perceptual, chromatic, a%ective arrangements, such as the modern city, the neorealist city, etcetera, and conversely, these arrangements give rise to a new kind of brain. It is a very unique understanding of neural plasticity. Interestingly, Deleuze’s approach to the brain also has the advantage of bypassing the usual linguistic theories of the mind, or of getting one stuck in debates over the status of representations. And one recalls the vehemence with which Deleuze rejects attempts to apply linguistics to cinema: when he invokes a ‘cerebral’ dimension in his discussions of perception, image, time, and so forth, it is not in order to reduce the ‘artistic’ dimension to a manageable set of quantities or even processes to be studied by a nefarious neurophilosopher (even one with additional firepower from .01 and f234 scans); it is a way of opening onto the openness of perception without immediately sealing it o% into linguistic categories.+$

Indeed, one dimension of the tradition of the ‘social brain’ that is currently popu-lar is ‘neuroaesthetics,’ not in the sense of finding neural correlates of aesthetic experience (promoted by scientists such as Semir Zeki or Jean-Pierre Changeux), but in Warren Neidich’s sense that stresses neural plasticity in relation to the aes-thetic environment. Much as one can say: ‘You don’t see with your retina, you see with your cortex’ (Christof Koch), one can add: ‘Avant-gardism and its reliance on the plasticity of perception happens in and through the cortex.’ From

Page 25: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

19 8 19 9

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

53 Terrence Deacon, ‘Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system: the problem of language origins,’ in Depew and Weber, Evolution and Learning. The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered, 9 5 .54 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 3 3 6 .55 Deacon, ‘Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system,’ 1 0 0 . 56 Métraux (ms.), § III; Luria, ‘Towards the Problem of the H istorical Nature of Psychological Processes,’ International Journal of Psychology 6 (1 9 71): 2 6 9 57 Deleuze, Negotiations, 6 0/Pourparlers 1972-1990 (Paris: Éditions de Minuit, 1 9 9 0), 8 6 , and the almost visionary discussion of the brain, art and color in G illes Deleuze, Cinéma 2 : L’image-temps (Paris: Minuit, 1 9 8 5), 2 6 6 , n. 2 0 (along with chapter 8 as a whole, which com-prises a section entitled ‘Donne-moi un cerveau,’ ‘G ive me a brain’).58 This Deleuzian approach to the brain is sometimes associated with Francisco Varela’s notion of autopoiesis (emphasizing the self-organizing nature of life and mind – autopoietic systems essentially produce themselves as individuals whereas ‘allopoietic’ systems are, like regular machines, defined by an external output), but this model lacks any recognition of the social. Specifically on Deleuze’s ‘neuroaesthetic,’ see John Rajchman’s excellent discussion in The Deleuze Connections (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2 0 0 0), 1 3 6-8 .59 Deacon, The Symbolic Species, 41 3 , 41 6 .60 Ludwig Feuerbach, ‘On the Dualism of Soul and F lesh’ (Wider den Dualismus von Leib und Seele) (1 8 4 6), in Anthropologischer Materialismus. Ausgewählte Schriften I, ed. A. Schmidt (Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt, 1 9 8 5), 1 77. Compare Bergson’s image of the brain as the ‘bureau téléphonique central,’ as a mere ‘intermediary’ between sensations and motions’ (Matière et mémoire, 2 6 , 1 9 8) … which Vygotsky finds too dualistic! (Vygotsky, Col-lected Works, 1 2 5). See overall chapter 3 of Bergson’s book and Deleuze, Cinéma 2, 2 74 .

Mriganka Sur’s ‘rewired ferrets’ to the recently studied young rats whose hippocampus develops di%erently depending on what kind of maternal care they receive, and onto the Benjaminian realization of the historical conditioning of our forms of perception, we are all avant-gardists in a sense; the same sense in which, according to Deacon, ‘prefrontal overdevelopment has made us all idiots savants of language and symbolic learning.’+'

!e idea is that the brain itself, less in its ‘static,’ anatomical being than in its ‘dynamic,’ physi-ological being – in actu, then – displays features that reflect its embeddedness in or belonging to the social world. !e externalist-Spinozist point to be derived here is that we can only have knowledge about the inner states of others, and indeed, of our own, thanks to the overall structure of symbolic activity (à la Deacon) which externally exhibits the existence of such states, and fur-ther, creates the structure in which such states emerge. Most people don’t realize that Vygotsky and Luria meant the brain itself when speaking about these dynamic, self-transformative features; they usually describe these as belonging to mind or intellect. But Vygotsky and Luria were materi-alists! (Both in the Marxist sense as seen above with respect to the embeddedness of the person in the world of networks – ‘relations’ – and in the more naturalistic sense that they believed intellectual processes could be explainable in terms of, or at least in a causally integrated relation to, cerebral processes.) !e brain for them is no longer just an ‘organ’ mediating between mind and society, through language – not just a ‘physiological abstraction, an organ cut out from the totality of the skull, the face, the body as a whole,’ as Feuerbach put it.(# Extending from the social mind to the social brain is a major step toward, or for materialism. However, neither neurally correlated social cognition nor even Machiavellian primates seem to display anything like the activity of the ‘socialist cortex,’ our shorthand for the transformative dimension of the plastic, socially plastic brain. For this we need not only Spinozist a%ects (along with his reduction of the universe to relations between portions of motion and rest), but a theory of transformation. Behind Vygotsky and Negri, there is also Marx.

ways that are complementary to their special functional demands’;+) ‘language has given rise to a brain which is strongly biased to employ the one mode of associative learning that is most critical to it,’+* namely, ‘the most extensive modification to take place in human brain evolution, the expansion of the cerebral cortex, specifi-cally the prefrontal cortex, reflects the evolutionary adaptation to this intensive working memory processing demand imposed by symbol learning.’++ Hence there is a ‘co-evolution’ of language and the brain. We have learned since at least Walter Benjamin to recognize the historicity of perception; Luria recognized this through his experiments on visual illusions during trips to Uzbekistan in the &')#s; di%er-ent subject groups, depending on their degree of Westernization, had a more or less high chance of seeing the illusions: ‘the more the subjects had dealt with abstract aspects of everyday practice, the less their vision was natural,’ with visual-motor recollection playing a key role – and this recollection being, not a biological invariant but a process ‘determined’ by sociohistorical processes.+(

We might say, ‘!e cortex is the locus of avant-gardism.’ !ink of Deleuze’s phrase: ‘Creating new circuits in art means creating them in the brain’ (Créer de nouveaux circuits s’entend du cerveau en même temps que de l ’art).+, Indeed, there is an entire aesthetic dimension of our construct which I have not discussed here, the first instance of which is Deleuze’s determination of the brain in its plasticity (for instance with reference to Antonioni, in the cinema books). Much like in Benjamin, this is the double-barreled idea that a new kind of brain is required to grasp new spatiotemporal, perceptual, chromatic, a%ective arrangements, such as the modern city, the neorealist city, etcetera, and conversely, these arrangements give rise to a new kind of brain. It is a very unique understanding of neural plasticity. Interestingly, Deleuze’s approach to the brain also has the advantage of bypassing the usual linguistic theories of the mind, or of getting one stuck in debates over the status of representations. And one recalls the vehemence with which Deleuze rejects attempts to apply linguistics to cinema: when he invokes a ‘cerebral’ dimension in his discussions of perception, image, time, and so forth, it is not in order to reduce the ‘artistic’ dimension to a manageable set of quantities or even processes to be studied by a nefarious neurophilosopher (even one with additional firepower from .01 and f234 scans); it is a way of opening onto the openness of perception without immediately sealing it o% into linguistic categories.+$

Indeed, one dimension of the tradition of the ‘social brain’ that is currently popu-lar is ‘neuroaesthetics,’ not in the sense of finding neural correlates of aesthetic experience (promoted by scientists such as Semir Zeki or Jean-Pierre Changeux), but in Warren Neidich’s sense that stresses neural plasticity in relation to the aes-thetic environment. Much as one can say: ‘You don’t see with your retina, you see with your cortex’ (Christof Koch), one can add: ‘Avant-gardism and its reliance on the plasticity of perception happens in and through the cortex.’ From

Page 26: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

200 201

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

61 Marx, Grundrisse, 6 9 4 .62 Ibid. 6 9 3 .63 Ibid. 70 6 , emphasis in orginal.64 Virno, ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation,’ section on ‘Marx, Simondon, Vygotski’; Marx, Grundrisse, 70 9 .65 Paolo Virno, ‘G eneral Intellect,’ Lessico Postfordista (Milan: Feltrinelli, 2 0 01). For English (translation by A. Bove) see Historical Materialism. Research in Critical Marxist Theory 3 (2 0 0 7): 3-8 .66 Charlie G ere, ‘Brains-in-vats, giant brains and world brains: the brain as metaphor in digital culture,’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 2 (2 0 0 4): 3 51-6 6 . 67 On the meaning of ‘ontology’ in Negri see my essays: ‘Materialism and Temporality. Antonio Negri’s “Constitutive” Ontology,’ in The Philosophy of Antonio Negri 2 : Revolution in Theory, eds. T.S. Murphy and A.-K. Mustapha (London: P luto Press, 2 0 0 7), 1 9 6-21 8 ; and, ‘Antonio Negri’s ontology of Empire and Multitude,’ Ideas in History 1 (forthcoming). 68 Erwin Straus, Du sens des sens (Grenoble: J. Millon, 1 9 8 9 [1 9 3 5]) (a translation of Vom Sinn der Sinne: Ein Beitrag zur Grundlegung der Psychologie), 1 8 3 .69 Hence it is understandable that Luria was critical of Kurt Goldstein, another (brilliant) forerunner of Varela’s, whose theory of organism makes it very much a solitary, creative, and anomalous entity within the broader world of animate nature. (I discuss the concept of organism further in ‘La catégorie d’‘organisme’ dans la philosophie de la biologie,’ Multitudes 1 6 (2 0 0 4): 2 7-4 0 ; reprinted in Multitudes. Une anthologie, ed. Yann Moulier-Boutang (Paris: Éditions Amsterdam, 2 0 0 7), 8 0-8 9 ; and in ‘Do organisms have an ontological status?,’ History

pendence produce a kind of ‘pure mind,’ total intelligence, total reflexivity, as the final outgrowth of a process that began with basic forms of matter, moving toward atoms and molecules, organisms and ultimately the human mind itself ),(( and indeed there is something uncomfortably spiritual-istic about the idea, as if intellect were more real than a piece of flesh or silicone. !is may indeed be a Hegelian residue in Marx, a residue of Geist, and is also probably why General Intellect and its twin concept, ‘immaterial labor,’ have been the targets of so much hostile criticism from the part of more orthodox Marxists, who feel as if Grandpa gave away the store, so to speak.

If I am emphasizing the term ‘social brain’ here, it’s precisely to show that it’s part of the real (‘wet’ rather than ‘dry’) natural world, not a virtual, strictly informational network. Further, just because the brain is irreducibly social does not mean that it is an ‘empire within an empire’ or ‘kingdom within a kingdom’ (in Spinoza’s famous phrase from the Preface to Book 444 of the Ethics, in which he rejects the idea that we are somehow apart from the rest of Nature, an imperium in imperio). I refer back to the Spinozist ontology of relations and find support in this also from Negri’s recur-ring invocations of ‘ontology’ as a political necessity.(,

!e Spinozist brain, the social brain cannot be extracted or abstracted from this universe of relations (recall Vygotsky’s arguments against Piaget’s ‘egocentric’ perspective). As such, it cannot or should not be confused with either of two major positions or attitudes within twentieth-cen-tury European thought:

Straus’ words),($ or with Varela’s enactivist model, which is rich and full of possibilities but hardly sociopolitical ones; Varela is our Piaget, in a sense: a new idealist, a new metaphysically grounded solipsist for whom the Self is self-positing, self-grounding rather than constituted in and through relation, or challenges of the ‘outside,’ whether this is construed as a Darwinian environment or a Spinozist causal universe.(' If we were not speaking of the brain we could be phenomenologists of

General Intellect As I mentioned at the outset, the notion of social brain appears in Marx’s Grundrisse, notebooks 54-544, a text known as the ‘Frag-ment on Machines’ which has had particular influence on the Italian autonomist tradition of Marxism. !ere, Marx speaks of the ‘general productive forces of the social brain.’(& !e idea is that humanity’s increasing use of automation and of developing networks of communication and transportation has brought about a kind of metaphysical shift in who and what we are, seen here from the angle of labor:

!e production process has ceased to be a labour process in the sense of a process dominated by labour as its governing unity. Labour appears rather as a conscious organ, scattered among the individual living workers at various points of the mechanical system; subsumed under the total process of the machinery itself, as itself only a link of the system, whose unity exists not in the living workers, but rather in the living (active) machinery, which confronts his individual, insignificant doings as a mighty organism.("

Later on in the text, Marx returns to this almost Laplacian level of contemplation and now uses the expression ‘general intellect’ (in English in the original; the provenance of this expression is unknown):

Nature builds no machines, no locomotives, railways, electric telegraphs, self-acting mules etc. !ese are products of human industry; natural material transformed into organs of the human will over nature, or of human partici-pation in nature. !ey are organs of the human brain, created by the human hand; the power of knowledge, objectified. !e development of fixed capital indi-cates to what degree social knowledge has become a direct force of production, and to what degree, hence, the conditions of the process of social life itself have come under the control of the general intellect and been transformed in accordance with it.()

What Marx is saying is that the real ‘operator’ or ‘agent’ of transformation, indeed the sole remaining actor in this process, is the social brain; it has become the pro-ductive force itself. In the words of Paolo Virno: ‘Rather than an allusion to the overcoming of the existent, the “Fragment” is a sociologist’s toolbox and the last chapter of a natural history of society.’(* !at is, it is meant as a description of empirical reality.(+ !e actor is neither the machines by themselves nor the old-fashioned humanist ‘autonomous rational animal,’ but rather the ‘General Intel-lect,’ which resides both in humans and in intelligent machines. Comparisons have been made between this idea of ‘General Intellect’ and Teilhard de Chardin’s ‘noosphere’ (roughly, a vision of an ultimate stage of development of the universe in which increasing complexity but also technological interrelation and interde-

Page 27: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

200 201

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

61 Marx, Grundrisse, 6 9 4 .62 Ibid. 6 9 3 .63 Ibid. 70 6 , emphasis in orginal.64 Virno, ‘Multitude et principe d’individuation,’ section on ‘Marx, Simondon, Vygotski’; Marx, Grundrisse, 70 9 .65 Paolo Virno, ‘G eneral Intellect,’ Lessico Postfordista (Milan: Feltrinelli, 2 0 01). For English (translation by A. Bove) see Historical Materialism. Research in Critical Marxist Theory 3 (2 0 0 7): 3-8 .66 Charlie G ere, ‘Brains-in-vats, giant brains and world brains: the brain as metaphor in digital culture,’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 2 (2 0 0 4): 3 51-6 6 . 67 On the meaning of ‘ontology’ in Negri see my essays: ‘Materialism and Temporality. Antonio Negri’s “Constitutive” Ontology,’ in The Philosophy of Antonio Negri 2 : Revolution in Theory, eds. T.S. Murphy and A.-K. Mustapha (London: P luto Press, 2 0 0 7), 1 9 6-21 8 ; and, ‘Antonio Negri’s ontology of Empire and Multitude,’ Ideas in History 1 (forthcoming). 68 Erwin Straus, Du sens des sens (Grenoble: J. Millon, 1 9 8 9 [1 9 3 5]) (a translation of Vom Sinn der Sinne: Ein Beitrag zur Grundlegung der Psychologie), 1 8 3 .69 Hence it is understandable that Luria was critical of Kurt Goldstein, another (brilliant) forerunner of Varela’s, whose theory of organism makes it very much a solitary, creative, and anomalous entity within the broader world of animate nature. (I discuss the concept of organism further in ‘La catégorie d’‘organisme’ dans la philosophie de la biologie,’ Multitudes 1 6 (2 0 0 4): 2 7-4 0 ; reprinted in Multitudes. Une anthologie, ed. Yann Moulier-Boutang (Paris: Éditions Amsterdam, 2 0 0 7), 8 0-8 9 ; and in ‘Do organisms have an ontological status?,’ History

pendence produce a kind of ‘pure mind,’ total intelligence, total reflexivity, as the final outgrowth of a process that began with basic forms of matter, moving toward atoms and molecules, organisms and ultimately the human mind itself ),(( and indeed there is something uncomfortably spiritual-istic about the idea, as if intellect were more real than a piece of flesh or silicone. !is may indeed be a Hegelian residue in Marx, a residue of Geist, and is also probably why General Intellect and its twin concept, ‘immaterial labor,’ have been the targets of so much hostile criticism from the part of more orthodox Marxists, who feel as if Grandpa gave away the store, so to speak.

If I am emphasizing the term ‘social brain’ here, it’s precisely to show that it’s part of the real (‘wet’ rather than ‘dry’) natural world, not a virtual, strictly informational network. Further, just because the brain is irreducibly social does not mean that it is an ‘empire within an empire’ or ‘kingdom within a kingdom’ (in Spinoza’s famous phrase from the Preface to Book 444 of the Ethics, in which he rejects the idea that we are somehow apart from the rest of Nature, an imperium in imperio). I refer back to the Spinozist ontology of relations and find support in this also from Negri’s recur-ring invocations of ‘ontology’ as a political necessity.(,

!e Spinozist brain, the social brain cannot be extracted or abstracted from this universe of relations (recall Vygotsky’s arguments against Piaget’s ‘egocentric’ perspective). As such, it cannot or should not be confused with either of two major positions or attitudes within twentieth-cen-tury European thought:

Straus’ words),($ or with Varela’s enactivist model, which is rich and full of possibilities but hardly sociopolitical ones; Varela is our Piaget, in a sense: a new idealist, a new metaphysically grounded solipsist for whom the Self is self-positing, self-grounding rather than constituted in and through relation, or challenges of the ‘outside,’ whether this is construed as a Darwinian environment or a Spinozist causal universe.(' If we were not speaking of the brain we could be phenomenologists of

General Intellect As I mentioned at the outset, the notion of social brain appears in Marx’s Grundrisse, notebooks 54-544, a text known as the ‘Frag-ment on Machines’ which has had particular influence on the Italian autonomist tradition of Marxism. !ere, Marx speaks of the ‘general productive forces of the social brain.’(& !e idea is that humanity’s increasing use of automation and of developing networks of communication and transportation has brought about a kind of metaphysical shift in who and what we are, seen here from the angle of labor:

!e production process has ceased to be a labour process in the sense of a process dominated by labour as its governing unity. Labour appears rather as a conscious organ, scattered among the individual living workers at various points of the mechanical system; subsumed under the total process of the machinery itself, as itself only a link of the system, whose unity exists not in the living workers, but rather in the living (active) machinery, which confronts his individual, insignificant doings as a mighty organism.("

Later on in the text, Marx returns to this almost Laplacian level of contemplation and now uses the expression ‘general intellect’ (in English in the original; the provenance of this expression is unknown):

Nature builds no machines, no locomotives, railways, electric telegraphs, self-acting mules etc. !ese are products of human industry; natural material transformed into organs of the human will over nature, or of human partici-pation in nature. !ey are organs of the human brain, created by the human hand; the power of knowledge, objectified. !e development of fixed capital indi-cates to what degree social knowledge has become a direct force of production, and to what degree, hence, the conditions of the process of social life itself have come under the control of the general intellect and been transformed in accordance with it.()

What Marx is saying is that the real ‘operator’ or ‘agent’ of transformation, indeed the sole remaining actor in this process, is the social brain; it has become the pro-ductive force itself. In the words of Paolo Virno: ‘Rather than an allusion to the overcoming of the existent, the “Fragment” is a sociologist’s toolbox and the last chapter of a natural history of society.’(* !at is, it is meant as a description of empirical reality.(+ !e actor is neither the machines by themselves nor the old-fashioned humanist ‘autonomous rational animal,’ but rather the ‘General Intel-lect,’ which resides both in humans and in intelligent machines. Comparisons have been made between this idea of ‘General Intellect’ and Teilhard de Chardin’s ‘noosphere’ (roughly, a vision of an ultimate stage of development of the universe in which increasing complexity but also technological interrelation and interde-

Page 28: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

202 203

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 3 2 (2 01 0): 1 9 5-2 3 2). See, for example, A.R. Luria, ‘L.S. Vygotski and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ Soviet Psychology 3 (1 9 6 7): 5 3-7, reprinted in Selected Writings of A.R. Luria, 2 77. After all, Luria, referring to himself and Vygotsky, spoke approvingly of ‘Pavlovian psychophysiology’ as having ‘provided a materialist underpinning to our study of the mind’ in The Making of Mind: A Personal Account of Soviet Psychology, ed. and translated by M. and S. Cole (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 79), 41 .70 Jean-Paul Sartre, ‘Matérialisme et révolution’ (originally in Les temps modernes of 1 9 4 6), in Situations philosophiques (Paris: G allimard, 1 9 9 0). In this famous work, Sartre describes materialism as an irrationalism, which removes man from the sphere of free, verste-hendes action and forces him into a world of biological, then physical conditioning. Reason is then ‘captive, manœuvrée par des chaînes de causes aveugles’ (Situations philosophiques, 8 6). Man as empire within an empire indeed! One might speak of ‘knee-jerk humanism’ here …71 Antonio Negri, ‘On A Thousand Plateaus,’ translated by C .T. Wolfe. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 1 (1 9 9 5): 9 3-1 0 9 . 72 Paolo Virno, ‘Les anges et le general intellect. L’individuation chez Duns Scot et G ilbert Simondon,’ Multitudes 1 8 (2 0 0 4), also at the URL http://multitudes.samizdat.net/Les-anges-et-le-general-intellect.73 Antonio Negri, ‘Alma Venus. Prolegomena to the Common,’ translated by P. Dailey and C . Costantini, in The Renewal of Materialism, ed. C .T. Wolfe, (Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 2 2 :1 , New York: New School for Social Research, 2 0 0 0), § 1 6b. These texts are also republished in Negri, Time for Revolution, translated by M. Mandarini (London: Continuum, 2 0 0 5).74 Andy C lark, Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies and the Future of Human Intelligence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 2), 1 1 , 4 3 . C lark intersects here with a good deal of recent cultural/literary/media theory (when it concerns itself with the relation between fiction, embodiment, and technological forms) – see in particular Donna Haraway, ‘A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-Feminism in the Late Twentieth C entury,’ in Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1 9 91), 1 4 9-1 81 ; and N. Katherine Hayles’ How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 9 9), and ‘The Life Cycle of Cyborgs: Writing the Posthuman,’ in A Question of Identity: Women, Science and Literature, ed. M. Benjamin (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1 9 9 3).C lark is unique, however, in that he speaks from within cognitive science – which also entails that there is no utopian dimension to his theory. C lark is not calling for a new hybridity or seeking to usher it into being.75 Andy C lark, Being There. Putting Brain, Body and World Back Together Again (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 9 7), 4 5 .76 Ibid., 21 , 8 7.77 On scaffolding, see C lark, Being There; for an original discussion of plasticity-remapping-‘cultured brain’ see Warren Neidich, Blow-Up: Photography, Cinema and the Brain (New York: Distributed Art Publishers, 2 0 0 3); some brief discussion in my essay ‘De-ontologizing the Brain: from the fictional self to the social brain,’ CTheory 1 3 0 :1 (Winter 2 0 0 7), at the URL http://www.ctheory.net/articles.aspx?id= 5 72 . Neidich’s idea has its own potential for being restated as a new form of what phenomenologists call ‘self-affection,’ just as Marxist-operaist G eneral Intellect has a potential to be restated as Pure Mind: ultimate idealism.78 C lark, Natural-Born Cyborgs, 8 6 .79 N. Katherine Hayles, ‘F lesh and Metal: Reconfiguring the Mindbody in Virtual Environments,’ Configurations 1 0 (2 0 0 2): 3 0 0 80 Vygotsky, Mind in Society, 51 ; and Lev S. Vygotsky ‘The instrumental method in psychol-ogy’ (1 9 3 0), presentation at Krupskaya Academy for Communist Education, in Collected Works, vol. 3 .

connections than a twenty-first-century American adolescent who has spent serious time with computer games.’,' !ere is no longer a real separation between body and extension, brain and tool. Vygotsky speaks of ‘psychological tools’ that alter the flow of mental functions by use, such as the knot in the handkerchief: ‘When a human being ties a knot in her handkerchief as a reminder, she is, in essence, constructing the process of memorizing by forcing an external object to remind her of something; she transforms remembering into an external activity.’$# But the concept of tool

the social world; but as I have emphasized, we are in materialist territory here.

Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften, which its very name seeks to over-come: this distinction is crucial for thinkers like Husserl, Heidegger, and Sartre,,#

but also the Frankfurt School. No distinction here between the brute, inanimate world of nature, animals, and machines on the one hand and a free, spiritual world of self-interpreting Daseine on the other. Su-ce it to recall here the charming formula Negri proposed for understanding Deleuze-Guattari’s Mille plateaux: that it was the last great work of the Geisteswissenschaften, but where Geist was replaced by the brain.,&

Scaffolding, Tools and Prostheses I have said that the social brain is not wedded to a concept of ‘privacy’ or ‘interiority,’ the way the Cartesian cogito, but also the phenomenological self (or body, in its embodied variant) are. It is an externalist, relational concept. In a sense, the novelty of the social brain appears most striking in regard to a kind of garden-variety, hermeneutical self. If we recall that Vygotsky’s concepts are born out of a reflection on linguistic devel-opment, and that the ‘a%ective’ dimension that both Vygotsky, Negri, and Virno draw out of Spinoza is ‘always already’ social – such that the general intellect itself is permeated with the ‘linguistic cooperation of a multitude of living subjects’," – we can see a bit better why the distinction between the natural and the ‘herme-neutical’ is of little use here. Ontologically there is no hard and fast border between the natural and the artificial, and thus between a world of amoebas and cane toads on the one hand, and a world of Byrons, Hölderlins or Mandelstams on the other. !e potential of an agent is inseparable from what Negri calls the ‘set of prostheses,’,) essentially the possible set of ‘sca%olding,’ networks and technologi-cal extensions of our perception, cognition, and action. !e idea of ‘sca%olding,’ which has been associated with Andy Clark in recent discussions of cognition (and Clark takes the idea from J.J. Gibson’s work in the &'(#s), is that we are inseparable from the ‘looping interactions’ between our brains, our bodies, and ‘complex cultural and technological environments.’,* In other words, our brains have the talent for making use of the environment, ‘piggy-backing on reliable environmental properties,’,+ which is in fact a far more economical and swift action procedure than processing representations of objects. Sca%olding is one of the vehicles humans employ, so that language, culture, and institutions empower cognitions.,(

On this view, the brain is not a central planner but possesses a ‘sca%olding’ that is inseparable from the external world.,, Indeed, the biological functioning of our brains themselves ‘has always involved [using] nonbiological props and sca%olds,’,$ with direct consequences for brain architecture itself: ‘A youngster growing up in a medieval village in twelfth-century France would literally have di%erent neural

Page 29: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

202 203

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 3 2 (2 01 0): 1 9 5-2 3 2). See, for example, A.R. Luria, ‘L.S. Vygotski and the Problem of Functional Localization,’ Soviet Psychology 3 (1 9 6 7): 5 3-7, reprinted in Selected Writings of A.R. Luria, 2 77. After all, Luria, referring to himself and Vygotsky, spoke approvingly of ‘Pavlovian psychophysiology’ as having ‘provided a materialist underpinning to our study of the mind’ in The Making of Mind: A Personal Account of Soviet Psychology, ed. and translated by M. and S. Cole (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1 9 79), 41 .70 Jean-Paul Sartre, ‘Matérialisme et révolution’ (originally in Les temps modernes of 1 9 4 6), in Situations philosophiques (Paris: G allimard, 1 9 9 0). In this famous work, Sartre describes materialism as an irrationalism, which removes man from the sphere of free, verste-hendes action and forces him into a world of biological, then physical conditioning. Reason is then ‘captive, manœuvrée par des chaînes de causes aveugles’ (Situations philosophiques, 8 6). Man as empire within an empire indeed! One might speak of ‘knee-jerk humanism’ here …71 Antonio Negri, ‘On A Thousand Plateaus,’ translated by C .T. Wolfe. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 1 (1 9 9 5): 9 3-1 0 9 . 72 Paolo Virno, ‘Les anges et le general intellect. L’individuation chez Duns Scot et G ilbert Simondon,’ Multitudes 1 8 (2 0 0 4), also at the URL http://multitudes.samizdat.net/Les-anges-et-le-general-intellect.73 Antonio Negri, ‘Alma Venus. Prolegomena to the Common,’ translated by P. Dailey and C . Costantini, in The Renewal of Materialism, ed. C .T. Wolfe, (Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 2 2 :1 , New York: New School for Social Research, 2 0 0 0), § 1 6b. These texts are also republished in Negri, Time for Revolution, translated by M. Mandarini (London: Continuum, 2 0 0 5).74 Andy C lark, Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies and the Future of Human Intelligence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2 0 0 2), 1 1 , 4 3 . C lark intersects here with a good deal of recent cultural/literary/media theory (when it concerns itself with the relation between fiction, embodiment, and technological forms) – see in particular Donna Haraway, ‘A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-Feminism in the Late Twentieth C entury,’ in Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1 9 91), 1 4 9-1 81 ; and N. Katherine Hayles’ How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 9 9), and ‘The Life Cycle of Cyborgs: Writing the Posthuman,’ in A Question of Identity: Women, Science and Literature, ed. M. Benjamin (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1 9 9 3).C lark is unique, however, in that he speaks from within cognitive science – which also entails that there is no utopian dimension to his theory. C lark is not calling for a new hybridity or seeking to usher it into being.75 Andy C lark, Being There. Putting Brain, Body and World Back Together Again (C ambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1 9 9 7), 4 5 .76 Ibid., 21 , 8 7.77 On scaffolding, see C lark, Being There; for an original discussion of plasticity-remapping-‘cultured brain’ see Warren Neidich, Blow-Up: Photography, Cinema and the Brain (New York: Distributed Art Publishers, 2 0 0 3); some brief discussion in my essay ‘De-ontologizing the Brain: from the fictional self to the social brain,’ CTheory 1 3 0 :1 (Winter 2 0 0 7), at the URL http://www.ctheory.net/articles.aspx?id= 5 72 . Neidich’s idea has its own potential for being restated as a new form of what phenomenologists call ‘self-affection,’ just as Marxist-operaist G eneral Intellect has a potential to be restated as Pure Mind: ultimate idealism.78 C lark, Natural-Born Cyborgs, 8 6 .79 N. Katherine Hayles, ‘F lesh and Metal: Reconfiguring the Mindbody in Virtual Environments,’ Configurations 1 0 (2 0 0 2): 3 0 0 80 Vygotsky, Mind in Society, 51 ; and Lev S. Vygotsky ‘The instrumental method in psychol-ogy’ (1 9 3 0), presentation at Krupskaya Academy for Communist Education, in Collected Works, vol. 3 .

connections than a twenty-first-century American adolescent who has spent serious time with computer games.’,' !ere is no longer a real separation between body and extension, brain and tool. Vygotsky speaks of ‘psychological tools’ that alter the flow of mental functions by use, such as the knot in the handkerchief: ‘When a human being ties a knot in her handkerchief as a reminder, she is, in essence, constructing the process of memorizing by forcing an external object to remind her of something; she transforms remembering into an external activity.’$# But the concept of tool

the social world; but as I have emphasized, we are in materialist territory here.

Naturwissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften, which its very name seeks to over-come: this distinction is crucial for thinkers like Husserl, Heidegger, and Sartre,,#

but also the Frankfurt School. No distinction here between the brute, inanimate world of nature, animals, and machines on the one hand and a free, spiritual world of self-interpreting Daseine on the other. Su-ce it to recall here the charming formula Negri proposed for understanding Deleuze-Guattari’s Mille plateaux: that it was the last great work of the Geisteswissenschaften, but where Geist was replaced by the brain.,&

Scaffolding, Tools and Prostheses I have said that the social brain is not wedded to a concept of ‘privacy’ or ‘interiority,’ the way the Cartesian cogito, but also the phenomenological self (or body, in its embodied variant) are. It is an externalist, relational concept. In a sense, the novelty of the social brain appears most striking in regard to a kind of garden-variety, hermeneutical self. If we recall that Vygotsky’s concepts are born out of a reflection on linguistic devel-opment, and that the ‘a%ective’ dimension that both Vygotsky, Negri, and Virno draw out of Spinoza is ‘always already’ social – such that the general intellect itself is permeated with the ‘linguistic cooperation of a multitude of living subjects’," – we can see a bit better why the distinction between the natural and the ‘herme-neutical’ is of little use here. Ontologically there is no hard and fast border between the natural and the artificial, and thus between a world of amoebas and cane toads on the one hand, and a world of Byrons, Hölderlins or Mandelstams on the other. !e potential of an agent is inseparable from what Negri calls the ‘set of prostheses,’,) essentially the possible set of ‘sca%olding,’ networks and technologi-cal extensions of our perception, cognition, and action. !e idea of ‘sca%olding,’ which has been associated with Andy Clark in recent discussions of cognition (and Clark takes the idea from J.J. Gibson’s work in the &'(#s), is that we are inseparable from the ‘looping interactions’ between our brains, our bodies, and ‘complex cultural and technological environments.’,* In other words, our brains have the talent for making use of the environment, ‘piggy-backing on reliable environmental properties,’,+ which is in fact a far more economical and swift action procedure than processing representations of objects. Sca%olding is one of the vehicles humans employ, so that language, culture, and institutions empower cognitions.,(

On this view, the brain is not a central planner but possesses a ‘sca%olding’ that is inseparable from the external world.,, Indeed, the biological functioning of our brains themselves ‘has always involved [using] nonbiological props and sca%olds,’,$ with direct consequences for brain architecture itself: ‘A youngster growing up in a medieval village in twelfth-century France would literally have di%erent neural

Page 30: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

20 4 205

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

81 A.A. Talankin, speaking at the F irst All-Union Congress on Psychotechnics and the Psycho-physiology of Labor, Leningrad, 1 9 31 . He also attacks Vygotsky on the related charge of import-ing ‘Western’ concepts from Freud and G estalt theory into Soviet psychology. See Van der Veer and Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky. A Quest for Synthesis, 3 77.82 Antonio Negri, Kairos. Alma Venus. Multitude, translated by J. Revel (Paris: C almann-Lévy, 2 0 01), § 1 6bis, 8 4 .83 Negri, ‘Alma Venus,’ § 1 6b. One can see resonances here with the work of Donna Haraway (with the focus on the category of prosthesis and the primacy of artificiality). And in works such as Empire, Hardt and Negri speak favorably of our posthuman, inseparably simian, human and cyborg nature (a viewpoint which is again fully Spinozistic), but they also distance themselves from ‘hybridity [as] an empty gesture’ perhaps on political grounds. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2 0 0 0), 21 6 .84 Antonio Negri, ‘Towards an Ontological Definition of the Multitude,’ originally published in French in Multitudes 9 (May-June 2 0 0 2). Emphasis my own. – in English at the URL: http://multitudes.samizdat.net/article.php3?id_article = 2 6 9 . 85 Deleuze in conversation with Toni Negri in 1 9 9 0 (originally in Futur Antérieur), in Deleuze, Negotiations, 1 76 .86 To be precise, in his reflections on the critique of the personality cult, Althusser wrote: ‘In the beginning, we were few, and John Lewis is right: we were “speaking in the desert,” or what some thought was the desert. But one should be careful of this kind of deserts, or rather know how to trust them. Actually, “we” were never alone. Communists are never alone’ (Louis Althusser, ‘Note sur “la critique du culte de la personnalité”,’ in Réponse à John Lewis (Paris: Maspero, 1 9 73), 78). And at the end of his life, in his autobiography, he reprised the theme: ‘I was quite solitary or alone as a philosopher, and yet I wrote in the Reply to John Lewis, “a Communist is never alone”’ (L’avenir dure longtemps (Paris: Livre de Poche, 1 9 9 4), ch. 1 4 , 1 9 6), (translation mine). Thanks to Yoshihiko Ichida for the reference.87 Compare the recent discussion of ‘group minds’ in Philip Pettit, ‘Groups with minds of their own,’ in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. F. Schmitt (Oxford: Rowan and Littlefield, 2 0 0 3), 1 6 7-1 9 4 ; and Rob Wilson, ‘ Collective memory, group minds, and the extended mind thesis,’ Cogni-tive Processes 4 (2 0 0 5), 2 2 7-3 6 . For a helpful discussion of the pros and cons of the notion of group cognition see G eorg Theiner and Timothy O ’ Connor, ‘The Emergence of Group Cogni-tion,’ in Emergence in Science and Philosophy, eds. A. Corradini and T. O ’ Connor (New York: Routledge, forthcoming 2 01 0).88 At a meeting a few years back I was intrigued by Margarita G luzberg’s visual and theoretical performance ‘How to get beyond the market …’ which proposed a kind of group mind achievable through aesthetic/hallucinatory means. However, this was quickly denounced as ‘dangerously close to Fascism’ by a loyal Frankfurt School theoretician, Diederich Diederichsen. So we might then ask, is the social brain fascist? C learly, if we are speaking in a Spinozist context, the answer is No: one of Spinoza’s chief concerns is to overcome a condition in which the ‘multitude’ is manipulated by political fear. He is the preeminent thinker of ‘absolute democracy,’ as indicated above. As to our biological characteristics in and of themselves, unfortunately it is harder to make

the Spinozist sense that the more ‘extensions’ I have – a notebook, a computer, a pen, a knot in my handkerchief, a friend’s telephone number, a Party membership card, and so forth – the greater my power of acting will be. As Althusser said somewhat whimsically, recalling an earlier era: ‘A Communist is never alone.’$( Not just in a trivial sense of ‘greater influence,’ but because (recall the idea of common notions) I will have more ideas of more bodies. Does the individual disappear in the nets of this reticulated network? No, for the above reason (connection is an increase in power), and also because what Félix Guattari called the ‘production of subjectivity’ is only possible because of the presence of common components in the world of brains: it is not like a popularity contest where I am pushed to ‘connect’ with ever more people! !ird, the social brain concept pre-sented here is definitely not reducible to the individual’s manifestations of a social world around her, since on the contrary (pace Vygotsky, Deacon, and others) cerebral architecture reflects, how-ever minutely, forms of social, linguistic, cultural organization. Does the group then have a ‘group mind’?$, A unified, constrained, ‘transsubjective reality’?$$ !e foregoing discussion does not nec-

is still too instrumental, that is, too external. Indeed, in his day Vygotsky was attacked by Party psychologists for ‘virtualizing’ the concept of tool or that of labor, and allowing for ‘mental’ factors such as culture to be determinations, rather than strict economic factors.$& Given the degree of ‘openness’ of the central nerv-ous system, and on the ‘personal’ level, our ability to identify with non-biological extensions of our body (as has been shown in great detail in experiments by V.S. Ramachandran, Atsushi Iriki, and others, from diverse perspectives), the ‘artifi-cialist’ perspective, in which body and prosthesis, indeed, body and tool, merge, is not so far o%. What Negri speaks of in Spinozist terms as a kind of commonness implies that there is no longer a separation between brain and tool as two distinct entities.$" In Negri’s terms: ‘!e tool … has entirely changed. We no longer need tools in order to transform nature … or to establish a relation with the historical world … we only need language. Language is the tool. Better yet, the brain is the tool, inasmuch as it is common.’$)

!e brain is ‘common’ inasmuch as it is constituted by and inseparable from the network of relations to which we belong. What Spinoza’s common notions, Marx’s General Intellect and the Vygotskyan ‘socialist cortex’ indicate is precisely this commonness, as opposed to the ‘classic’ idea of thinking as a solitary, contem-plative activity (I turn to some potential pitfalls of this commonness below). Negri puts it strongly:

!e metaphysics of individuality (and/or of personhood) constitutes a dread-ful mystification of the multitude of bodies. "ere is no possibility for a body to be alone. It cannot even be imagined. When man is defined as individual, when he is considered as an autonomous source of rights and property, he is made alone. But one’s ownness does not exist outside of the relation with an other. !e metaphysics of individuality, when confronted with the body, negates the multitude that constitutes the body in order to negate the multi-tude of bodies.$*

!e ‘social’ in the ‘social brain’ means that we cannot achieve the privacy of a Cartesian or Husserlian meditator, contemplating the world, but also that we can never be truly cut o% from it; the ‘brain’ in the same expression means that we are not just dealing with a formal property of an arrangement of thoughts or other-wise construed mental states, but with an embodied, biological, natural agent.

Envoi To sum up. First, there is no absolute ontological separation between an individual agent and her brain, and the total network of a%ects, objects, and structures around her. ‘Subjectification, event or brain – aren’t these much the same thing?’$+ Second, individuation is an e%ect of power, both in the Vygotskyan sense that ‘I’ am a product of socialization, and not the other way round, and in

Page 31: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

20 4 205

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

81 A.A. Talankin, speaking at the F irst All-Union Congress on Psychotechnics and the Psycho-physiology of Labor, Leningrad, 1 9 31 . He also attacks Vygotsky on the related charge of import-ing ‘Western’ concepts from Freud and G estalt theory into Soviet psychology. See Van der Veer and Valsiner, Understanding Vygotsky. A Quest for Synthesis, 3 77.82 Antonio Negri, Kairos. Alma Venus. Multitude, translated by J. Revel (Paris: C almann-Lévy, 2 0 01), § 1 6bis, 8 4 .83 Negri, ‘Alma Venus,’ § 1 6b. One can see resonances here with the work of Donna Haraway (with the focus on the category of prosthesis and the primacy of artificiality). And in works such as Empire, Hardt and Negri speak favorably of our posthuman, inseparably simian, human and cyborg nature (a viewpoint which is again fully Spinozistic), but they also distance themselves from ‘hybridity [as] an empty gesture’ perhaps on political grounds. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (C ambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2 0 0 0), 21 6 .84 Antonio Negri, ‘Towards an Ontological Definition of the Multitude,’ originally published in French in Multitudes 9 (May-June 2 0 0 2). Emphasis my own. – in English at the URL: http://multitudes.samizdat.net/article.php3?id_article = 2 6 9 . 85 Deleuze in conversation with Toni Negri in 1 9 9 0 (originally in Futur Antérieur), in Deleuze, Negotiations, 1 76 .86 To be precise, in his reflections on the critique of the personality cult, Althusser wrote: ‘In the beginning, we were few, and John Lewis is right: we were “speaking in the desert,” or what some thought was the desert. But one should be careful of this kind of deserts, or rather know how to trust them. Actually, “we” were never alone. Communists are never alone’ (Louis Althusser, ‘Note sur “la critique du culte de la personnalité”,’ in Réponse à John Lewis (Paris: Maspero, 1 9 73), 78). And at the end of his life, in his autobiography, he reprised the theme: ‘I was quite solitary or alone as a philosopher, and yet I wrote in the Reply to John Lewis, “a Communist is never alone”’ (L’avenir dure longtemps (Paris: Livre de Poche, 1 9 9 4), ch. 1 4 , 1 9 6), (translation mine). Thanks to Yoshihiko Ichida for the reference.87 Compare the recent discussion of ‘group minds’ in Philip Pettit, ‘Groups with minds of their own,’ in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. F. Schmitt (Oxford: Rowan and Littlefield, 2 0 0 3), 1 6 7-1 9 4 ; and Rob Wilson, ‘ Collective memory, group minds, and the extended mind thesis,’ Cogni-tive Processes 4 (2 0 0 5), 2 2 7-3 6 . For a helpful discussion of the pros and cons of the notion of group cognition see G eorg Theiner and Timothy O ’ Connor, ‘The Emergence of Group Cogni-tion,’ in Emergence in Science and Philosophy, eds. A. Corradini and T. O ’ Connor (New York: Routledge, forthcoming 2 01 0).88 At a meeting a few years back I was intrigued by Margarita G luzberg’s visual and theoretical performance ‘How to get beyond the market …’ which proposed a kind of group mind achievable through aesthetic/hallucinatory means. However, this was quickly denounced as ‘dangerously close to Fascism’ by a loyal Frankfurt School theoretician, Diederich Diederichsen. So we might then ask, is the social brain fascist? C learly, if we are speaking in a Spinozist context, the answer is No: one of Spinoza’s chief concerns is to overcome a condition in which the ‘multitude’ is manipulated by political fear. He is the preeminent thinker of ‘absolute democracy,’ as indicated above. As to our biological characteristics in and of themselves, unfortunately it is harder to make

the Spinozist sense that the more ‘extensions’ I have – a notebook, a computer, a pen, a knot in my handkerchief, a friend’s telephone number, a Party membership card, and so forth – the greater my power of acting will be. As Althusser said somewhat whimsically, recalling an earlier era: ‘A Communist is never alone.’$( Not just in a trivial sense of ‘greater influence,’ but because (recall the idea of common notions) I will have more ideas of more bodies. Does the individual disappear in the nets of this reticulated network? No, for the above reason (connection is an increase in power), and also because what Félix Guattari called the ‘production of subjectivity’ is only possible because of the presence of common components in the world of brains: it is not like a popularity contest where I am pushed to ‘connect’ with ever more people! !ird, the social brain concept pre-sented here is definitely not reducible to the individual’s manifestations of a social world around her, since on the contrary (pace Vygotsky, Deacon, and others) cerebral architecture reflects, how-ever minutely, forms of social, linguistic, cultural organization. Does the group then have a ‘group mind’?$, A unified, constrained, ‘transsubjective reality’?$$ !e foregoing discussion does not nec-

is still too instrumental, that is, too external. Indeed, in his day Vygotsky was attacked by Party psychologists for ‘virtualizing’ the concept of tool or that of labor, and allowing for ‘mental’ factors such as culture to be determinations, rather than strict economic factors.$& Given the degree of ‘openness’ of the central nerv-ous system, and on the ‘personal’ level, our ability to identify with non-biological extensions of our body (as has been shown in great detail in experiments by V.S. Ramachandran, Atsushi Iriki, and others, from diverse perspectives), the ‘artifi-cialist’ perspective, in which body and prosthesis, indeed, body and tool, merge, is not so far o%. What Negri speaks of in Spinozist terms as a kind of commonness implies that there is no longer a separation between brain and tool as two distinct entities.$" In Negri’s terms: ‘!e tool … has entirely changed. We no longer need tools in order to transform nature … or to establish a relation with the historical world … we only need language. Language is the tool. Better yet, the brain is the tool, inasmuch as it is common.’$)

!e brain is ‘common’ inasmuch as it is constituted by and inseparable from the network of relations to which we belong. What Spinoza’s common notions, Marx’s General Intellect and the Vygotskyan ‘socialist cortex’ indicate is precisely this commonness, as opposed to the ‘classic’ idea of thinking as a solitary, contem-plative activity (I turn to some potential pitfalls of this commonness below). Negri puts it strongly:

!e metaphysics of individuality (and/or of personhood) constitutes a dread-ful mystification of the multitude of bodies. "ere is no possibility for a body to be alone. It cannot even be imagined. When man is defined as individual, when he is considered as an autonomous source of rights and property, he is made alone. But one’s ownness does not exist outside of the relation with an other. !e metaphysics of individuality, when confronted with the body, negates the multitude that constitutes the body in order to negate the multi-tude of bodies.$*

!e ‘social’ in the ‘social brain’ means that we cannot achieve the privacy of a Cartesian or Husserlian meditator, contemplating the world, but also that we can never be truly cut o% from it; the ‘brain’ in the same expression means that we are not just dealing with a formal property of an arrangement of thoughts or other-wise construed mental states, but with an embodied, biological, natural agent.

Envoi To sum up. First, there is no absolute ontological separation between an individual agent and her brain, and the total network of a%ects, objects, and structures around her. ‘Subjectification, event or brain – aren’t these much the same thing?’$+ Second, individuation is an e%ect of power, both in the Vygotskyan sense that ‘I’ am a product of socialization, and not the other way round, and in

Page 32: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

20 6

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

them bear some innately emancipatory role, albeit perhaps a potential one. Margarita G luzberg, ‘How to get beyond the market – Transsubjective Reality in the Salvia Divinorum Forest,’ presentation at Neuroaesthetics Conference, Goldsmiths College, London, 2 0 0 5 ; transcription at the URL: http://www.artbrain.org/how-to-get-beyond-the-market-%e2%8 0%9 3-transsubjec-tive-reality-in-the-salyia-divinorum-forest-let-the-crowds-in/.

essarily entail that – and indeed, that the brains of a young rat, a young child, an American teenager and a Russian chess master respectively reflect various epige-netic, environmental traits does not at all imply that a club, a sect, or a mob needs to be described as possessing a ‘mind.’

I have simply tried to show that there is a way of thinking about the brain that retains a sociopolitical dimension while at the same time dealing with naturalisti-cally specifiable features of development; a genuinely materialist perspective. From the social dimension of mind – materialized through ethological and sin-gle-neuron studies, ontologically founded with the doctrine of common notions and of being as relation – through the fundamental plasticity of the brain and the remodeling by language and culture of the functional architecture of the cortex: this is the Spinozist tradition of the social brain.

* !anks to Deborah Hauptmann and Warren Neidich for their invitation; to Katja Diefenbach, Luc Faucher, John Protevi, and Georg !einer for useful sug-gestions.

Page 33: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

20 6

From

Spi

noza

to th

e S

ocia

list

Cor

tex:

Ste

ps T

owar

d th

e S

ocia

l Bra

in

them bear some innately emancipatory role, albeit perhaps a potential one. Margarita G luzberg, ‘How to get beyond the market – Transsubjective Reality in the Salvia Divinorum Forest,’ presentation at Neuroaesthetics Conference, Goldsmiths College, London, 2 0 0 5 ; transcription at the URL: http://www.artbrain.org/how-to-get-beyond-the-market-%e2%8 0%9 3-transsubjec-tive-reality-in-the-salyia-divinorum-forest-let-the-crowds-in/.

essarily entail that – and indeed, that the brains of a young rat, a young child, an American teenager and a Russian chess master respectively reflect various epige-netic, environmental traits does not at all imply that a club, a sect, or a mob needs to be described as possessing a ‘mind.’

I have simply tried to show that there is a way of thinking about the brain that retains a sociopolitical dimension while at the same time dealing with naturalisti-cally specifiable features of development; a genuinely materialist perspective. From the social dimension of mind – materialized through ethological and sin-gle-neuron studies, ontologically founded with the doctrine of common notions and of being as relation – through the fundamental plasticity of the brain and the remodeling by language and culture of the functional architecture of the cortex: this is the Spinozist tradition of the social brain.

* !anks to Deborah Hauptmann and Warren Neidich for their invitation; to Katja Diefenbach, Luc Faucher, John Protevi, and Georg !einer for useful sug-gestions.

Page 34: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Andreas Angelidakis Andreas Angelidakis is an architect who likes mountains and clouds and websites as much as buildings and trees, furniture, people and art. He maintains an experimental prac-tice in Athens, Greece, a studio involved in building, designing and speculating about the contemporary ecosystem of life between screens and landscapes.

Lisa Blackman and Janet Harbord Lisa B lackman is a Reader in the Department of Media and Communications, Goldsmiths, University of London, UK. She is the new editor of the journal Body & Society (Sage) and a co-editor of the new journal Subjectivity (Palgrave). She has written three books: Hearing Voices: Embodiment and Experience (2 0 01); Mass Hysteria: Critical Psychology and Media Studies (with V. Walkerdine, 2 0 01); and The Body: The Key Concepts (2 0 0 8). She is currently finishing a manuscript, Im / material Bodies: Affect, Relationality and the Problem of Personality to be published with Sage (2 01 1).

Janet Harbord is a Reader in F ilm and Screen Cultures in the Department of Media and Communications, Goldsmiths, University of London, UK. She is the author of three books: Film Cultures (2 0 0 2); The Evolution of Film (2 0 0 7), and Chris Marker: La Jetee (2 0 0 9). She is currently working on a book project on Trans-mission: the arts and practices of sending by technical means.

Ina Blom Ina B lom is Professor at the Institute of Philosophy, C lassics, H istory of Art and Ideas at the University of Oslo. Her fields of research and teaching are modernism/avant-garde studies and contemporary art and aesthetics, with a particular focus on media art practices and media aesthetics. Her recent books are: On the Style Site. Art, Sociality and Television Culture (2 0 0 7); The Postal Performance of Ray Johnson (2 0 0 3) and Joseph Beuys (2 0 01).

Yann Moulier Boutang Yann Boutang is a Professor in Economics, University of Technology, Compiègne, France; a Visiting Professor of Economics, Ecole Nationale Supérieure d’Architecture Paris Malaquais; and an Associate Professor of Humanities, Ecole Supérieure d’Art et de Design de Saint-Etienne. Since 1 9 73 his research has included critical analysis of labor in contemporary Marxism, with particular focus on the Italian Operaist and Autonomia movements. He has taken part in the publication of the posthumous works of Louis Althusser with the IME C , see: Louis Althusser: The Future Lasts Forever (with O . Corpet, 1 9 9 3). Professor Boutang is an expert in the areas of capitalism, cognitive capitalism, and labor and migration policy. He is Chief Editor of the Journal Multitudes (Paris).

Felicity Callard and Daniel Margulies Felicity C allard, PhD, has disciplinary expertise in the history and living present of psychiatry and in cultural theory. She is currently a research fellow in the N IH R B iomedical Research C entre for Mental Health (South London & Maudsley N HS Foundation Trust/Institute of Psychiatry, King’s Col-lege London), where she collaborates with translational researchers in mental health. One strand of her research focuses on how appro-priations and flows of concepts occur in this current moment of

cross-disciplinary exchange between the neurosciences, social sciences and humanities.

Daniel S. Margulies, PhD, has disciplinary expertise in functional neuroimaging of the brain ‘at rest.’ He is currently a post-doctoral research fellow at the Mind & Brain Institute of Humboldt University and the Max Planck Institute for Human Cognition and Brain Sciences, investigating functional neuroanatomy and how individual patterns of behavior relate to the organization of large-scale brain networks. Before neuroscience, he studied philosophy and literature, and continues to explore intersections of neuroscience with the arts and psychoanalysis.

Suparna Choudhury, Lukas Ebensperger and Jan SlabySuparna Choudhury is a Minerva Junior Professor at the Max P lanck Institute for H istory of Science in Berlin, G ermany, and Associated Researcher at the Berlin School of Mind and Brain. She is currently investigating the development of brain-based theories of adolescence through cognitive neuroscience and their functions in contemporary culture. She has a background in cultural psychiatry and cognitive neuroscience: her postdoctoral research at the Division of Social and Transcultural Psychiatry, Mc G ill University focused on cultural constructions of the brain and her PhD in Cognitive Neuroscience was based on social cognitive development during adolescence at University College London. Jointly with Jan Slaby she founded the C ritical Neuroscience initiative.

Lukas Ebensberger holds a degree in Cognitive Science from the University of Osnabrück, G ermany, and is currently based at the Insti-tute of Cultural Studies at Humboldt University in Berlin. H is work focuses on themes in the intersections and tensions between the nat-ural and social sciences with a special emphasis on neuroscience and its influence on public and scientific discourse. H is main fields of interest include ontology, hermeneutics and the history and philoso-phy of technology and science, and the influence of science and tech-nology on human self-understanding.

Jan Slaby is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Philipps-University Marburg, G ermany. H is working area is theoretical philosophy, with a focus on phenomenology, theories of emotion and feeling, personhood, philosophical anthropology and philosophy of science. He studied Philosophy, Sociology, and English Literature at the Humboldt Uni-versity in Berlin; his PhD in philosophy was completed in 2 0 0 6 at the University of Osnabrück with a thesis on emotions, personhood and intentionality (published as Gefühl und Weltbezug with mentis, Paderborn, in 2 0 0 8). After obtaining his doctorate he worked as a PostDoc researcher in the interdisciplinary project ‘Animal Emotion-ale. Emotions as the Missing Link Between Cognition and Action’ (funded by the Volkswagen Foundation, G ermany), based at the Insti-tute for Cognitive Science at the University of Osnabrück. Jointly with Suparna Choudhury he founded the C ritical Neuroscience initiative.

Jordan Crandall Jordan C randall is Associate Professor in Visual Arts, University of C alifornia San Diego. He is a media artist and the-orist based in Los Angeles. H is most recent video installation _Hotel_ (2 0 0 9) probes into the realms of extreme intimacy, where techniques of control combine with techniques of the self. He is cur-

Contr ibutors B iograph i es

Page 35: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Andreas Angelidakis Andreas Angelidakis is an architect who likes mountains and clouds and websites as much as buildings and trees, furniture, people and art. He maintains an experimental prac-tice in Athens, Greece, a studio involved in building, designing and speculating about the contemporary ecosystem of life between screens and landscapes.

Lisa Blackman and Janet Harbord Lisa B lackman is a Reader in the Department of Media and Communications, Goldsmiths, University of London, UK. She is the new editor of the journal Body & Society (Sage) and a co-editor of the new journal Subjectivity (Palgrave). She has written three books: Hearing Voices: Embodiment and Experience (2 0 01); Mass Hysteria: Critical Psychology and Media Studies (with V. Walkerdine, 2 0 01); and The Body: The Key Concepts (2 0 0 8). She is currently finishing a manuscript, Im / material Bodies: Affect, Relationality and the Problem of Personality to be published with Sage (2 01 1).

Janet Harbord is a Reader in F ilm and Screen Cultures in the Department of Media and Communications, Goldsmiths, University of London, UK. She is the author of three books: Film Cultures (2 0 0 2); The Evolution of Film (2 0 0 7), and Chris Marker: La Jetee (2 0 0 9). She is currently working on a book project on Trans-mission: the arts and practices of sending by technical means.

Ina Blom Ina B lom is Professor at the Institute of Philosophy, C lassics, H istory of Art and Ideas at the University of Oslo. Her fields of research and teaching are modernism/avant-garde studies and contemporary art and aesthetics, with a particular focus on media art practices and media aesthetics. Her recent books are: On the Style Site. Art, Sociality and Television Culture (2 0 0 7); The Postal Performance of Ray Johnson (2 0 0 3) and Joseph Beuys (2 0 01).

Yann Moulier Boutang Yann Boutang is a Professor in Economics, University of Technology, Compiègne, France; a Visiting Professor of Economics, Ecole Nationale Supérieure d’Architecture Paris Malaquais; and an Associate Professor of Humanities, Ecole Supérieure d’Art et de Design de Saint-Etienne. Since 1 9 73 his research has included critical analysis of labor in contemporary Marxism, with particular focus on the Italian Operaist and Autonomia movements. He has taken part in the publication of the posthumous works of Louis Althusser with the IME C , see: Louis Althusser: The Future Lasts Forever (with O . Corpet, 1 9 9 3). Professor Boutang is an expert in the areas of capitalism, cognitive capitalism, and labor and migration policy. He is Chief Editor of the Journal Multitudes (Paris).

Felicity Callard and Daniel Margulies Felicity C allard, PhD, has disciplinary expertise in the history and living present of psychiatry and in cultural theory. She is currently a research fellow in the N IH R B iomedical Research C entre for Mental Health (South London & Maudsley N HS Foundation Trust/Institute of Psychiatry, King’s Col-lege London), where she collaborates with translational researchers in mental health. One strand of her research focuses on how appro-priations and flows of concepts occur in this current moment of

cross-disciplinary exchange between the neurosciences, social sciences and humanities.

Daniel S. Margulies, PhD, has disciplinary expertise in functional neuroimaging of the brain ‘at rest.’ He is currently a post-doctoral research fellow at the Mind & Brain Institute of Humboldt University and the Max Planck Institute for Human Cognition and Brain Sciences, investigating functional neuroanatomy and how individual patterns of behavior relate to the organization of large-scale brain networks. Before neuroscience, he studied philosophy and literature, and continues to explore intersections of neuroscience with the arts and psychoanalysis.

Suparna Choudhury, Lukas Ebensperger and Jan SlabySuparna Choudhury is a Minerva Junior Professor at the Max P lanck Institute for H istory of Science in Berlin, G ermany, and Associated Researcher at the Berlin School of Mind and Brain. She is currently investigating the development of brain-based theories of adolescence through cognitive neuroscience and their functions in contemporary culture. She has a background in cultural psychiatry and cognitive neuroscience: her postdoctoral research at the Division of Social and Transcultural Psychiatry, Mc G ill University focused on cultural constructions of the brain and her PhD in Cognitive Neuroscience was based on social cognitive development during adolescence at University College London. Jointly with Jan Slaby she founded the C ritical Neuroscience initiative.

Lukas Ebensberger holds a degree in Cognitive Science from the University of Osnabrück, G ermany, and is currently based at the Insti-tute of Cultural Studies at Humboldt University in Berlin. H is work focuses on themes in the intersections and tensions between the nat-ural and social sciences with a special emphasis on neuroscience and its influence on public and scientific discourse. H is main fields of interest include ontology, hermeneutics and the history and philoso-phy of technology and science, and the influence of science and tech-nology on human self-understanding.

Jan Slaby is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Philipps-University Marburg, G ermany. H is working area is theoretical philosophy, with a focus on phenomenology, theories of emotion and feeling, personhood, philosophical anthropology and philosophy of science. He studied Philosophy, Sociology, and English Literature at the Humboldt Uni-versity in Berlin; his PhD in philosophy was completed in 2 0 0 6 at the University of Osnabrück with a thesis on emotions, personhood and intentionality (published as Gefühl und Weltbezug with mentis, Paderborn, in 2 0 0 8). After obtaining his doctorate he worked as a PostDoc researcher in the interdisciplinary project ‘Animal Emotion-ale. Emotions as the Missing Link Between Cognition and Action’ (funded by the Volkswagen Foundation, G ermany), based at the Insti-tute for Cognitive Science at the University of Osnabrück. Jointly with Suparna Choudhury he founded the C ritical Neuroscience initiative.

Jordan Crandall Jordan C randall is Associate Professor in Visual Arts, University of C alifornia San Diego. He is a media artist and the-orist based in Los Angeles. H is most recent video installation _Hotel_ (2 0 0 9) probes into the realms of extreme intimacy, where techniques of control combine with techniques of the self. He is cur-

Contr ibutors B iograph i es

Page 36: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Maurizio LazzaratoMaurizio Lazzarato is a sociologist and writer, based in Paris. He is a member of the editorial board of Multitudes. Among his recent publications are: Videofilosofia. La percezione del tempo nel postfordismo (Manifestolibri, 1 9 9 7); Lavoro immateriale. Forme di vita e produzione di soggettività (Ombre Corta, 1 9 9 7); La politica dell’evento (Rubbetino, 2 0 0 4) Les révolu-tions du capitalisme (Empêcheurs de Penser en Rond, 2 0 0 4), Puissances de l’invention. La Psychologie économique de Gabriel Tarde contre l’économie politique (Les empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2 0 0 2); and Le nouveau partage du sensible. L’expérimentation politique aujourd’hui (Editions Amsterdam, 2 0 0 9).

Markus Miessen Markus Miessen is an architect, writer and consultant. In 2 0 0 2 , he set up Studio Miessen, a collaborative agency for spatial practice and cultural inquiry, and in 2 0 0 7 was founding partner of the archi-tecture practice nOffice. In various collaborations, Miessen has published books such as The Nightmare of Participation (2 01 0); Institution Building – Artists, Curators, Architects in the Struggle for Institutional Space (2 0 0 9); When Economies Become Form (200 9); East Coast Europe (200 8); The Violence of Participation (2 0 0 7); With /Without –Spatial Products, Practices and Politics in the Middle East (2 0 0 7); and Did Someone Say Participate? (2 0 0 6). H is work has been exhibited and published widely, including at the Lyon, Venice, Shenzhen, Mani-festa and Performa B iennials. Miessen has taught internationally at institutions such as the Architectural Association, the Berlage Insti-tute, Columbia and MIT. He has consulted the Slovenian Govern-ment, the European Kunsthalle, the Serpentine G allery and the Swiss think tank WIRE. In 2 0 0 8 , he founded the Winter School Middle East. Miessen is a Harvard fellow, a PhD candidate at Goldsmiths, and a Professor for Architecture and Curatorial Practice at the Hochschule für G estaltung, Karlsruhe. nO ffice is currently working on projects for Manifesta 8 , Archive Kabinett, Merve Verlag, SKO R, and Hans Ulrich Obrist archive, among others.

Warren NeidichWarren Neidich is an artist, writer and organizer, based in Berlin and New York. He is a founding editor of the Journal of Neuro-aesthetics (1 9 9 7-2 0 0 9) and Artbrbrain.org, and a visiting Scholar at the Delft School of Design (since 2 0 0 9). Neidich organized the first conference on Neuroaesthetics at Goldsmiths College where he was Artist in Residence in 2 0 0 5 . He is author of Blow-up: Pho-tography, Cinema and the Brain (2 0 0 3). H is recent book Lost Between the Extensivity / Intensivity Exchange (Onomatopee, 2 0 0 9) includes his performative lectures performed at IAS P IS, Stockholm entitled ‘Some Cursory Comments on the Nature of My Wall Drawing.’ After studying photography and psychology Dr. Nei-dich went on to become a research fellow in Neurobiology at C alifor-nia Institute of Technology in the laboratory of Nobel Prize Recipient and Neurobiologist Roger Sperry. He studied medicine and then did a residency in ophthalomology at Tulane University Medical C enter, New Orleans. Louisiana. He retired from his post as C linical Instruc-tor at New York Eye and Ear Hospital in 1 9 9 3 to pursue his artistic and theoretical practice full time.

John ProteviJohn Protevi is Professor of French Studies at Louisiana State Uni-versity in Baton Rouge, Louisiana. He received a PhD in Philosophy from Loyola University of Chicago in 1 9 9 0 , with a dissertation under the direction of John Sallis. H is recent publications include: Political Physics: Deleuze, Derrida and the Body Politic (2 0 01); Deleuze and Geophilosophy: A Guide and Glossary (co-author with Mark Bonta, 2 0 0 4). In addition, he is editor of A Dictionary of Continental Philosophy (Yale, 2 0 0 6). He is a founding editor of the book series New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science with Palgrave Macmillan. H is latest book is Political Affect: Con-necting the Social and the Somatic (Minnesota, 2 0 0 9).

Andrej Radman Andrej Radman is Assistant Professor of Architecture, Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology, where he has taught design and theory courses since 2 0 0 4 . In 2 0 0 8 he joined the teaching and research staff of the Delft School of Design (DS D) as Assistant Professor of Architecture. Radman continues to practice architecture and has won a number of awards from national competitions together with architect Igor Vrbanek, including the C roatian Association of Architects Annual Award for the most accomplished housing archi-tecture in C roatia in 2 0 0 2 , for the design of a family residence in Zagreb. He has designed for the architectural offices of APZ and AP-9 2 in Zagreb and Korteknie Stuhlmacher Architects in Rotter-dam. Radman’s doctoral research focuses on J.J. G ibson’s ecological approach to perception based on the com-plementarities of the perceiver and the environment.

Philippe Rahm Philippe Rahm Architects, Paris. Philippe Rahm, born in 1 9 6 7 stud-ied at the Federal Polytechnic Schools of Lausanne and Zurich. He obtained his degree in architecture in 1 9 9 3 . He currently works in Paris (France). In 2 0 0 2 , he was chosen to represent Switzerland at the 8th Architecture B iennale in Venice and is one of the 2 0 mani-festo architects of Aaron Betsky’s 2 0 0 8 Architectural B iennale Venice. In 2 0 0 9 , he was a nominee for the Ordos Prize in China and in 2 0 0 8 he was in the top-ten ranking of the International Chernikov Prize in Moscow. In 2 0 0 7, he had a personal exhibition at the C ana-dian C entre for Architecture in Montreal. He has participated in a number of exhibitions worldwide (Archilab 2 0 0 0 , S F-MoMA 2 0 01 , C C A Kitakyushu 2 0 0 4 , Frac C entre, Orléans, C entre Pompidou, Beaubourg 2 0 0 3-2 0 0 6 and 2 0 0 7, Manifesta 7, 2 0 0 8 , Louisiana museum, Denmark, 2 0 0 9). Philippe Rahm was a resident at the Villa Medici in Rome (2 0 0 0). He was Head-Master of Diploma Unit 1 3 at the AA School in London in 2 0 0 5-2 0 0 6 , Visiting professor in Men-drisio Academy of Architecture in Switzerland in 2 0 0 4 and 2 0 0 5 , at the ETH Lausanne in 2 0 0 6 and 2 0 0 7, and he is currently a Guest Professor at the Royal School of Architecture of Copenhagen. He is working on several private and public projects in France, Poland, England, Italy, and G ermany. He has lectured widely, including at Cooper Union NY, Harvard School of Design, U C LA and Princeton.

John Rajchman John Rajchman is a philosopher working in the areas of art history, architecture, and continental philosophy. He is an Adjunct Professor

rently developing a new visual philosophical project called _G ather-ings_, which works across the life sciences, the social sciences, the digital humanities, urban design and architecture. He is the founding editor of the new journal Version.

Elie DuringElie During is Associate Professor at the University of Paris – Ouest Nanterre, Philosophy Department. He also teaches at the Ecole nationale des beaux-arts (Paris). He has recently published a critical edition of Henri Bergson’s Durée et Simultanéité [Duration and Simultaneity] (2 0 0 9), to be followed by a study of the Bergson-Einstein controversy: Bergson et Einstein: la querelle de la rela-tivité [Bergson and Einstein: The Quarrel of Relativity] (forthcoming). O ther publications include La Science et l’hypothèse: Poincaré [Science and Hypothesis: Poincaré] (2 0 01); In actu: de l’expérimental de l’art [In actu: Concerning the Experimen-tal in Art] (co-authored, 2 0 0 9); Faux Raccords [Jump Cuts] (2 01 0); as well as a number of articles on contemporary philosophy (Deleuze, Rancière, Badiou). H is current research focuses on the varieties of space-time experience in science, the arts and the city.

Keller EasterlingKeller Easterling is an architect and writer from New York C ity. Her book Enduring Innocence: Global Architecture and its Politi-cal Masquerades (2 0 0 5) researches familiar spatial products that have landed in difficult or hyperbolic political situations around the world. A previous book, Organization Space: Landscapes, High-ways and Houses in America (1 9 9 9), applies network theory to a discussion of American infrastructure and development formats. A forthcoming book, Extrastatecraft, examines global infrastructure networks as a medium of polity. Easterling has lectured and published widely in the USA and internationally. Her research and design work has been most recently exhibited at the Storefront for Art and Archi-tecture in New York, the Rotterdam B iennale, and the Architectural League. She has also published web installations including: Extra-statecraft, Wildcards: A G ame of Orgman and H ighline: P lotting NYC . Easterling is a Professor at Yale University.

Boris GroysBoris Groys is Professor of Philosophy and Aesthetics at the Hochs-chule für G estaltung in Karlsruhe, G ermany and is G lobal Professor in Aesthetics, Art H istory, and Media Theory at New York University. Groys is an expert on late-Soviet postmodern art and literature, and on the Russian avant-garde. Since 1 9 9 4 , he served as curator and organizer of numerous international art exhibitions and conferences. As an artist, Groys develops film and video installations, such as The Art Judgement Show (2 0 01), and Iconoclastic Delights (2 0 0 2). In 2 0 0 8 , he created an installation of three video-collages combining theoretical texts with film fragments: Thinking in Loop: Three videos on iconoclasm, ritual and immortality (ZKM). H is recent books include: Ilya Kabakov: The Man Who Flew into Space from His Apartment (2 0 0 6); and Art Power (2 0 0 8).

Patrick HealyPatrick Healy is Senior Lecturer, Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology. After completion of studies in Philosophy and later Sociology and Near Eastern Languages, Pontifical Univer-sity Maynooth, University College Dublin, Patrick Healy has been engaged in writing, research and teaching, mainly in the area of aes-thetics and contemporary art. H is recent publications include works on aesthetics, the philosophy of science and artists biographies, including a broad range of other activities associated with his work as Professor of Interdisciplinary research for the Free International Uni-versity, Amsterdam, appointed 1 9 9 7. H is recent publications include: The Model and its Architecture (2 0 0 8) and Images of Knowl-edge (2 0 0 5). With Deborah Hauptmann he has carried out a trans-lation of Bergson, Quid Arristotles de loco senserit, completed this year and awaiting publication. This is the first complete transla-tion into English of Bergson’s thesis work for the Sorbonne.

Deborah HauptmannDeborah Hauptmann is director of the Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology where she is Associate Professor in Archi-tecture Theory. Hauptmann lectures internationally and contributes regularly to conferences as a moderator. Her recent work includes: Cities in Transition (ed. 2 0 01); The Body in Architecture (ed. 2 0 0 6); ‘Problematizing the Virtual: On Lefebvre and the Urban Problematic,’ in Visualizing the Invisible (2 0 0 6); ‘A Cosmopoli-tan View on Thinking and Being-in- Common,’ in The Foreign and the Domestic in Architecture (2 0 0 7); and the forward to Writing and Seeing Architecture: Christian de Portzamparc and Philippe Sollers (2 0 0 8). She is currently working on a manuscript on the notion of space in the work of Henri Bergson which includes a definitive English translation of Bergson’s 1 8 8 9 Quid Aristoteles De Loco Senserit [On Aristotle’s Conception of P lace], which she has produced with her colleague, Patrick Healy.

Scott KelsoScott Kelso holds the G lenwood and Martha C reech Chair in Science at F lorida Atlantic University in Boca Raton and is Professor of Psychology, B iological Sciences and B iomedical Science. He is also Visiting Professor of Computational Neuroscience in the Intelligent Systems Research C entre at the University of Ulster’s Magee C ampus in Londonderry, Northern Ireland. In 1 9 8 5 Kelso founded the C enter for Complex Systems and Brain Sciences, the first such interdiscipli-nary field in the USA. Kelso’s research combines advanced brain imaging and behavioral methods to understand how human beings (and human brains) – individually and together – coordinate behavior on multiple levels (from cellular to social) for multiple functions. He is considered an originator of Coordination Dynamics, a theoretical and empirical framework that seeks to identify the laws, principles, and mechanisms underlying the complex dynamical behavior of living things. H is most recent books include: Dynamic Patterns: the Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior (1 9 9 5); Coordination Dynamics (with V. K. Jirsa, 2 0 0 4); and The Complementary Nature (with D.A. Engstrøm, 2 0 0 6). Kelso is the Founding Editor of a book series Understanding Complex Systems (Springer Verlag) which now has over 5 0 volumes.

Page 37: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Maurizio LazzaratoMaurizio Lazzarato is a sociologist and writer, based in Paris. He is a member of the editorial board of Multitudes. Among his recent publications are: Videofilosofia. La percezione del tempo nel postfordismo (Manifestolibri, 1 9 9 7); Lavoro immateriale. Forme di vita e produzione di soggettività (Ombre Corta, 1 9 9 7); La politica dell’evento (Rubbetino, 2 0 0 4) Les révolu-tions du capitalisme (Empêcheurs de Penser en Rond, 2 0 0 4), Puissances de l’invention. La Psychologie économique de Gabriel Tarde contre l’économie politique (Les empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2 0 0 2); and Le nouveau partage du sensible. L’expérimentation politique aujourd’hui (Editions Amsterdam, 2 0 0 9).

Markus Miessen Markus Miessen is an architect, writer and consultant. In 2 0 0 2 , he set up Studio Miessen, a collaborative agency for spatial practice and cultural inquiry, and in 2 0 0 7 was founding partner of the archi-tecture practice nOffice. In various collaborations, Miessen has published books such as The Nightmare of Participation (2 01 0); Institution Building – Artists, Curators, Architects in the Struggle for Institutional Space (2 0 0 9); When Economies Become Form (200 9); East Coast Europe (200 8); The Violence of Participation (2 0 0 7); With /Without –Spatial Products, Practices and Politics in the Middle East (2 0 0 7); and Did Someone Say Participate? (2 0 0 6). H is work has been exhibited and published widely, including at the Lyon, Venice, Shenzhen, Mani-festa and Performa B iennials. Miessen has taught internationally at institutions such as the Architectural Association, the Berlage Insti-tute, Columbia and MIT. He has consulted the Slovenian Govern-ment, the European Kunsthalle, the Serpentine G allery and the Swiss think tank WIRE. In 2 0 0 8 , he founded the Winter School Middle East. Miessen is a Harvard fellow, a PhD candidate at Goldsmiths, and a Professor for Architecture and Curatorial Practice at the Hochschule für G estaltung, Karlsruhe. nO ffice is currently working on projects for Manifesta 8 , Archive Kabinett, Merve Verlag, SKO R, and Hans Ulrich Obrist archive, among others.

Warren NeidichWarren Neidich is an artist, writer and organizer, based in Berlin and New York. He is a founding editor of the Journal of Neuro-aesthetics (1 9 9 7-2 0 0 9) and Artbrbrain.org, and a visiting Scholar at the Delft School of Design (since 2 0 0 9). Neidich organized the first conference on Neuroaesthetics at Goldsmiths College where he was Artist in Residence in 2 0 0 5 . He is author of Blow-up: Pho-tography, Cinema and the Brain (2 0 0 3). H is recent book Lost Between the Extensivity / Intensivity Exchange (Onomatopee, 2 0 0 9) includes his performative lectures performed at IAS P IS, Stockholm entitled ‘Some Cursory Comments on the Nature of My Wall Drawing.’ After studying photography and psychology Dr. Nei-dich went on to become a research fellow in Neurobiology at C alifor-nia Institute of Technology in the laboratory of Nobel Prize Recipient and Neurobiologist Roger Sperry. He studied medicine and then did a residency in ophthalomology at Tulane University Medical C enter, New Orleans. Louisiana. He retired from his post as C linical Instruc-tor at New York Eye and Ear Hospital in 1 9 9 3 to pursue his artistic and theoretical practice full time.

John ProteviJohn Protevi is Professor of French Studies at Louisiana State Uni-versity in Baton Rouge, Louisiana. He received a PhD in Philosophy from Loyola University of Chicago in 1 9 9 0 , with a dissertation under the direction of John Sallis. H is recent publications include: Political Physics: Deleuze, Derrida and the Body Politic (2 0 01); Deleuze and Geophilosophy: A Guide and Glossary (co-author with Mark Bonta, 2 0 0 4). In addition, he is editor of A Dictionary of Continental Philosophy (Yale, 2 0 0 6). He is a founding editor of the book series New Directions in Philosophy and Cognitive Science with Palgrave Macmillan. H is latest book is Political Affect: Con-necting the Social and the Somatic (Minnesota, 2 0 0 9).

Andrej Radman Andrej Radman is Assistant Professor of Architecture, Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology, where he has taught design and theory courses since 2 0 0 4 . In 2 0 0 8 he joined the teaching and research staff of the Delft School of Design (DS D) as Assistant Professor of Architecture. Radman continues to practice architecture and has won a number of awards from national competitions together with architect Igor Vrbanek, including the C roatian Association of Architects Annual Award for the most accomplished housing archi-tecture in C roatia in 2 0 0 2 , for the design of a family residence in Zagreb. He has designed for the architectural offices of APZ and AP-9 2 in Zagreb and Korteknie Stuhlmacher Architects in Rotter-dam. Radman’s doctoral research focuses on J.J. G ibson’s ecological approach to perception based on the com-plementarities of the perceiver and the environment.

Philippe Rahm Philippe Rahm Architects, Paris. Philippe Rahm, born in 1 9 6 7 stud-ied at the Federal Polytechnic Schools of Lausanne and Zurich. He obtained his degree in architecture in 1 9 9 3 . He currently works in Paris (France). In 2 0 0 2 , he was chosen to represent Switzerland at the 8th Architecture B iennale in Venice and is one of the 2 0 mani-festo architects of Aaron Betsky’s 2 0 0 8 Architectural B iennale Venice. In 2 0 0 9 , he was a nominee for the Ordos Prize in China and in 2 0 0 8 he was in the top-ten ranking of the International Chernikov Prize in Moscow. In 2 0 0 7, he had a personal exhibition at the C ana-dian C entre for Architecture in Montreal. He has participated in a number of exhibitions worldwide (Archilab 2 0 0 0 , S F-MoMA 2 0 01 , C C A Kitakyushu 2 0 0 4 , Frac C entre, Orléans, C entre Pompidou, Beaubourg 2 0 0 3-2 0 0 6 and 2 0 0 7, Manifesta 7, 2 0 0 8 , Louisiana museum, Denmark, 2 0 0 9). Philippe Rahm was a resident at the Villa Medici in Rome (2 0 0 0). He was Head-Master of Diploma Unit 1 3 at the AA School in London in 2 0 0 5-2 0 0 6 , Visiting professor in Men-drisio Academy of Architecture in Switzerland in 2 0 0 4 and 2 0 0 5 , at the ETH Lausanne in 2 0 0 6 and 2 0 0 7, and he is currently a Guest Professor at the Royal School of Architecture of Copenhagen. He is working on several private and public projects in France, Poland, England, Italy, and G ermany. He has lectured widely, including at Cooper Union NY, Harvard School of Design, U C LA and Princeton.

John Rajchman John Rajchman is a philosopher working in the areas of art history, architecture, and continental philosophy. He is an Adjunct Professor

rently developing a new visual philosophical project called _G ather-ings_, which works across the life sciences, the social sciences, the digital humanities, urban design and architecture. He is the founding editor of the new journal Version.

Elie DuringElie During is Associate Professor at the University of Paris – Ouest Nanterre, Philosophy Department. He also teaches at the Ecole nationale des beaux-arts (Paris). He has recently published a critical edition of Henri Bergson’s Durée et Simultanéité [Duration and Simultaneity] (2 0 0 9), to be followed by a study of the Bergson-Einstein controversy: Bergson et Einstein: la querelle de la rela-tivité [Bergson and Einstein: The Quarrel of Relativity] (forthcoming). O ther publications include La Science et l’hypothèse: Poincaré [Science and Hypothesis: Poincaré] (2 0 01); In actu: de l’expérimental de l’art [In actu: Concerning the Experimen-tal in Art] (co-authored, 2 0 0 9); Faux Raccords [Jump Cuts] (2 01 0); as well as a number of articles on contemporary philosophy (Deleuze, Rancière, Badiou). H is current research focuses on the varieties of space-time experience in science, the arts and the city.

Keller EasterlingKeller Easterling is an architect and writer from New York C ity. Her book Enduring Innocence: Global Architecture and its Politi-cal Masquerades (2 0 0 5) researches familiar spatial products that have landed in difficult or hyperbolic political situations around the world. A previous book, Organization Space: Landscapes, High-ways and Houses in America (1 9 9 9), applies network theory to a discussion of American infrastructure and development formats. A forthcoming book, Extrastatecraft, examines global infrastructure networks as a medium of polity. Easterling has lectured and published widely in the USA and internationally. Her research and design work has been most recently exhibited at the Storefront for Art and Archi-tecture in New York, the Rotterdam B iennale, and the Architectural League. She has also published web installations including: Extra-statecraft, Wildcards: A G ame of Orgman and H ighline: P lotting NYC . Easterling is a Professor at Yale University.

Boris GroysBoris Groys is Professor of Philosophy and Aesthetics at the Hochs-chule für G estaltung in Karlsruhe, G ermany and is G lobal Professor in Aesthetics, Art H istory, and Media Theory at New York University. Groys is an expert on late-Soviet postmodern art and literature, and on the Russian avant-garde. Since 1 9 9 4 , he served as curator and organizer of numerous international art exhibitions and conferences. As an artist, Groys develops film and video installations, such as The Art Judgement Show (2 0 01), and Iconoclastic Delights (2 0 0 2). In 2 0 0 8 , he created an installation of three video-collages combining theoretical texts with film fragments: Thinking in Loop: Three videos on iconoclasm, ritual and immortality (ZKM). H is recent books include: Ilya Kabakov: The Man Who Flew into Space from His Apartment (2 0 0 6); and Art Power (2 0 0 8).

Patrick HealyPatrick Healy is Senior Lecturer, Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology. After completion of studies in Philosophy and later Sociology and Near Eastern Languages, Pontifical Univer-sity Maynooth, University College Dublin, Patrick Healy has been engaged in writing, research and teaching, mainly in the area of aes-thetics and contemporary art. H is recent publications include works on aesthetics, the philosophy of science and artists biographies, including a broad range of other activities associated with his work as Professor of Interdisciplinary research for the Free International Uni-versity, Amsterdam, appointed 1 9 9 7. H is recent publications include: The Model and its Architecture (2 0 0 8) and Images of Knowl-edge (2 0 0 5). With Deborah Hauptmann he has carried out a trans-lation of Bergson, Quid Arristotles de loco senserit, completed this year and awaiting publication. This is the first complete transla-tion into English of Bergson’s thesis work for the Sorbonne.

Deborah HauptmannDeborah Hauptmann is director of the Delft School of Design, Delft University of Technology where she is Associate Professor in Archi-tecture Theory. Hauptmann lectures internationally and contributes regularly to conferences as a moderator. Her recent work includes: Cities in Transition (ed. 2 0 01); The Body in Architecture (ed. 2 0 0 6); ‘Problematizing the Virtual: On Lefebvre and the Urban Problematic,’ in Visualizing the Invisible (2 0 0 6); ‘A Cosmopoli-tan View on Thinking and Being-in- Common,’ in The Foreign and the Domestic in Architecture (2 0 0 7); and the forward to Writing and Seeing Architecture: Christian de Portzamparc and Philippe Sollers (2 0 0 8). She is currently working on a manuscript on the notion of space in the work of Henri Bergson which includes a definitive English translation of Bergson’s 1 8 8 9 Quid Aristoteles De Loco Senserit [On Aristotle’s Conception of P lace], which she has produced with her colleague, Patrick Healy.

Scott KelsoScott Kelso holds the G lenwood and Martha C reech Chair in Science at F lorida Atlantic University in Boca Raton and is Professor of Psychology, B iological Sciences and B iomedical Science. He is also Visiting Professor of Computational Neuroscience in the Intelligent Systems Research C entre at the University of Ulster’s Magee C ampus in Londonderry, Northern Ireland. In 1 9 8 5 Kelso founded the C enter for Complex Systems and Brain Sciences, the first such interdiscipli-nary field in the USA. Kelso’s research combines advanced brain imaging and behavioral methods to understand how human beings (and human brains) – individually and together – coordinate behavior on multiple levels (from cellular to social) for multiple functions. He is considered an originator of Coordination Dynamics, a theoretical and empirical framework that seeks to identify the laws, principles, and mechanisms underlying the complex dynamical behavior of living things. H is most recent books include: Dynamic Patterns: the Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior (1 9 9 5); Coordination Dynamics (with V. K. Jirsa, 2 0 0 4); and The Complementary Nature (with D.A. Engstrøm, 2 0 0 6). Kelso is the Founding Editor of a book series Understanding Complex Systems (Springer Verlag) which now has over 5 0 volumes.

Page 38: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Sven-Olav Wallenstein Sven- O lav Wallenstein is Professor of Philosophy & Aesthetics, Uni-versity College Södertörn and Professor of Architectural Theory at the Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm. Wallenstein teaches Philosophy at the University College of Södertörn and Architectural Theory at the Royal Institute of Technology. He is the editor-in-chief of SITE (www.sitemagazine.net), the author of several books and essays on contemporary art, philosophy, and aesthetics, and the translator of works by Kant, Frege, Husserl, Heidegger, Levinas, Der-rida and Deleuze. Recent books include: Bildstrider: Föreläsnin-gar om estetisk teori (Image Wars: Lectures on Aesthetic Theory, 2 0 01); Den sista bilden: det moderna måleriets kriser och förvandlingar (The Last Image: C rises and Transformations of Modern Painting, 2 0 0 2); Den moderna arkitekturens filosofier (The Philosophies of Modern Architecture, 2 0 0 4), The Silence of Mies (2 0 0 8); Biopolitics and the Emergence of Modern Architecture (2 0 0 9); as well as Swedish translations of Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgement (2 0 0 3), G illes Deleuze’s The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (2 0 0 4).

Bruce WexlerBruce Wexler is Professor of Psychiatry, Yale University, School of Medicine and Director of the Neurocognitive Research Laboratory, Connecticut Mental Health C enter. He received his BA degree Magna Cum Laude from Harvard College, medical training at Albert Einstein College of Medicine and Psychiatry training at Yale. He also studied psychiatry at Anna Freud’s clinic in Hampstead and neurol-ogy at the Institute of Neurology, Queen’s Square, London. He has published over 1 0 0 scientific research papers and serves on expert panels and grant review committees for the National Institute of Mental Health. In one component of his scientific research, Professor Wexler uses brain imaging and measures of cognition and social cognition to identify distinct subtypes of schizophrenia. In the other component, he has been a world leader in developing computerized brain ‘exercises’ to treat the cognitive dysfunctions associated with schizophrenia by promoting activity-dependent enhancement of underfunctioning neurocognitive systems. H is scholarly book Brain and Culture; Neurobiology, Ideology and Social Change (2 0 0 6) presents new ideas about the relationship between people and their environments. Based on ideas in this book, Professor Wexler founded the organization ‘A Different Future’ to help promote Israeli/Palestinian peace.

Charles T. Wolfe Charles Wolfe is an AR C Research Fellow in the Unit for H istory and Philosophy of Science, University of Sydney (and in 2 01 1 a Mellon Fellow at the C entre for Philosophy of Science, University of P itts-burgh) working chiefly in the history and philosophy of the life sciences, in the early modern period and in contemporary thought. He has edited volumes on materialism, monsters, the body and empiricism in early modern science (The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge, Springer 2 01 0), and on the concept of organism (forthcoming); his essays cover topics including materialist perspec-tives on dreams, laughter, and molecules; constitutive ontology and phantom limb syndrome; the animal economy, automata, determin-ism and embodiment; Locke, La Mettrie, Diderot and Sade. H is cur-rent project is a book on the history of vitalism.

and Director of Modern Art MA Programs in the Department of Art H istory and Archaeology at Columbia University. He has previously taught at Princeton University, MIT, Collège International de Philoso-phie in Paris, and The Cooper Union, among others. Recent publica-tions include: The Deleuze Connections (2 0 0 0) and Rendre la terre légère (2 0 0 5). He is a Contributing Editor for Artforum and is on the board of Critical Space.

Patricia ReedPatricia Reed is an artist who completed her B FA from Concordia University, Montreal. Since then she has participated in the research and residency programs of the C entre for Contemporary Art Kitakyushu, Japan, C C A Jeleni, Prague, Czech Republic, Akademie Schloss Solitude, Stuttgart, and The Banff C entre for the Arts, C anada. C alling her practice Aesthetic Management, Reed operates between various roles within the art field, allowing for a partaking in different modes of production including artistic, curatorial, and textual forms of dissemination. Recent and forthcoming projects include: Secret Publicity, C anada; They go round and round, 0 0 47 Projects, Oslo; ev+a Matters, Limerick Art G allery, Ireland; First Nations /Second Nature, Audain G allery, Vancouver; and Territo-ries of the In / Human, Württembergischer Kunstverein, Stuttgart. As a writer, Reed has contributed texts to the following publications: Shifter Magazine, Fillip, Art Papers, C Magazine, Neue Review and Framework: The Finnish Art Review. She lives and works in Berlin.

Gabriel Rockhill G abriel Rockhill is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Villanova Uni-versity & C entre Parisien d’Etudes C ritiques, Director of the Atelier de Théorie C ritique at the C entre Parisien d’Etudes C ritiques and the Collège International de Philosophie. He is the author of Logique de l’histoire: Pour une analytique des pratiques philosophiques (2 01 0) and is currently completing a manuscript for Les Editions du Sandre on the role of radical historicism in rethinking the relationship between art and politics. He co-edited and contributed to Critique et subversion dans la pensée contemporaine américaine: Dia-logues (2 01 0); Jacques Rancière: History, Politics, Aesthetics (2 0 0 9); and Technologies de contrôle dans la mondialisation: Enjeux politiques, éthiques et esthétiques (2 0 0 9). He also edited and translated Jacques Rancière’s The Politics of Aesthet-ics (2 0 0 4).

Terry Sejnowski and Steven R. QuartzTerrence Sejnowski is an Investigator with the Howard Hughes Medical Institute and is the Francis C rick Professor at The Salk Institute for B iological Studies where he directs the Computational Neurobiology Laboratory. He is also Professor of B iological Sciences and Adjunct Professor in the Departments of Neurosciences, Psy-chology, Cognitive Science, and Computer Science and Engineering at the University of C alifornia, San Diego, where he is Director of the Institute for Neural Computation. He served on the faculty of Johns Hopkins University and was a Wiersma Visiting Professor of Neuro-biology and a Sherman Fairchild Distinguished Scholar at C altech. The long-range goal of Dr. Sejnowski’s laboratory is to understand the computational resources of brains and to build linking principles

from brain to behavior using computational models. This goal is being pursued with a combination of theoretical and experimental approaches at several levels of investigation ranging from the bio-physical level to the systems level. H is papers are widely published and his recent publications include: Toward Brain-Computer Interfacing (co-authored 2 0 0 7); New Directions in Statistical Signal Processing (co-authored 2 0 0 6); Liars, Lovers, and Heroes: What the New Brain Science Reveals About How We Become Who We Are (co-authored with Steen Quartz, 2 0 0 3)

Steven R. Quartz, PhD, is director of the Social Cognitive Neuro-science Laboratory at the C alifornia Institute of Technology and an Associate Professor in the Division of Humanities and Social Sci-ences and the Computation and Neural Systems Program. He was a fellow of the Sloan C enter for Theoretical Neurobiology at the Salk Institute and a recipient of the National Science Foundation’s C ARE ER award, its most prestigious award for young faculty. H i research uses advances and methods in neuroscience to probe fun-damental problems of mind, ranging from how the mind emerges from the developing brain to how we make decisions, from individual decision-making under uncertainty to moral decision making. H is publishes regularly in the journal Science and he is coauthor (with Terrence Sejnowski) of Liars, Lovers, and Heroes: What the New Brain Science Reveals About How We Become Who We Are (2 0 0 3).

Elizabeth Sikiaridi and Frans VogelaarProfessor Elizabeth Sikiaridi and Professor Frans Vogelaar are part-ners at Hybrid Space Lab, Berlin/Amsterdam, an r&d and design practice focusing on the hybrid fields that are emerging through the combination and fusion of environments, objects and services in the information/communication age. In 1 9 9 8 Frans Vogelaar founded at the Academy of Media Arts Cologne the first Department of Hybrid Space worldwide. Their work has been presented at international congresses and exhibitions and has been published internationally: Austria, Belgium, C anada, China, Czech Republic, Denmark, G er-many, Greece, F inland, France, Italy, Latvia, Lithuania, Pakistan, Poland, Portugal, Oman (upcoming in 2 01 0), Singapore, South Korea (upcoming in 2 01 0), Switzerland, Spain, the Netherlands, Turkey, UK, and USA.

Paolo VirnoPaolo Virno is a philosopher who lives in Rome and teaches at the University of C alabria. H is research specializes in political philoso-phy, linguistics and mass media. He was politically active as a member of the Italian political group Potere Operaio during the 1 9 70s, where he was imprisoned for three years before being acquitted. He is a contributor of the philosophical review Forme di vita. Among his recent publications are: Virtuosismo y revolución: La acción politica en la era del desencanto (2 0 0 3); Esercizi di esodo (2 0 0 2): Quando il verbo si fa carne. Linguaggio e natura umana (2 0 0 3); A Grammar of the Multitude: For an Analysis of Contemporary Forms of Life (2 0 0 4); Motto di spirito e azione innovativa (2 0 0 5); and Multitude: Between Innovation and Negation (2 0 0 8).

5 87

Page 39: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Sven-Olav Wallenstein Sven- O lav Wallenstein is Professor of Philosophy & Aesthetics, Uni-versity College Södertörn and Professor of Architectural Theory at the Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm. Wallenstein teaches Philosophy at the University College of Södertörn and Architectural Theory at the Royal Institute of Technology. He is the editor-in-chief of SITE (www.sitemagazine.net), the author of several books and essays on contemporary art, philosophy, and aesthetics, and the translator of works by Kant, Frege, Husserl, Heidegger, Levinas, Der-rida and Deleuze. Recent books include: Bildstrider: Föreläsnin-gar om estetisk teori (Image Wars: Lectures on Aesthetic Theory, 2 0 01); Den sista bilden: det moderna måleriets kriser och förvandlingar (The Last Image: C rises and Transformations of Modern Painting, 2 0 0 2); Den moderna arkitekturens filosofier (The Philosophies of Modern Architecture, 2 0 0 4), The Silence of Mies (2 0 0 8); Biopolitics and the Emergence of Modern Architecture (2 0 0 9); as well as Swedish translations of Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgement (2 0 0 3), G illes Deleuze’s The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (2 0 0 4).

Bruce WexlerBruce Wexler is Professor of Psychiatry, Yale University, School of Medicine and Director of the Neurocognitive Research Laboratory, Connecticut Mental Health C enter. He received his BA degree Magna Cum Laude from Harvard College, medical training at Albert Einstein College of Medicine and Psychiatry training at Yale. He also studied psychiatry at Anna Freud’s clinic in Hampstead and neurol-ogy at the Institute of Neurology, Queen’s Square, London. He has published over 1 0 0 scientific research papers and serves on expert panels and grant review committees for the National Institute of Mental Health. In one component of his scientific research, Professor Wexler uses brain imaging and measures of cognition and social cognition to identify distinct subtypes of schizophrenia. In the other component, he has been a world leader in developing computerized brain ‘exercises’ to treat the cognitive dysfunctions associated with schizophrenia by promoting activity-dependent enhancement of underfunctioning neurocognitive systems. H is scholarly book Brain and Culture; Neurobiology, Ideology and Social Change (2 0 0 6) presents new ideas about the relationship between people and their environments. Based on ideas in this book, Professor Wexler founded the organization ‘A Different Future’ to help promote Israeli/Palestinian peace.

Charles T. Wolfe Charles Wolfe is an AR C Research Fellow in the Unit for H istory and Philosophy of Science, University of Sydney (and in 2 01 1 a Mellon Fellow at the C entre for Philosophy of Science, University of P itts-burgh) working chiefly in the history and philosophy of the life sciences, in the early modern period and in contemporary thought. He has edited volumes on materialism, monsters, the body and empiricism in early modern science (The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge, Springer 2 01 0), and on the concept of organism (forthcoming); his essays cover topics including materialist perspec-tives on dreams, laughter, and molecules; constitutive ontology and phantom limb syndrome; the animal economy, automata, determin-ism and embodiment; Locke, La Mettrie, Diderot and Sade. H is cur-rent project is a book on the history of vitalism.

and Director of Modern Art MA Programs in the Department of Art H istory and Archaeology at Columbia University. He has previously taught at Princeton University, MIT, Collège International de Philoso-phie in Paris, and The Cooper Union, among others. Recent publica-tions include: The Deleuze Connections (2 0 0 0) and Rendre la terre légère (2 0 0 5). He is a Contributing Editor for Artforum and is on the board of Critical Space.

Patricia ReedPatricia Reed is an artist who completed her B FA from Concordia University, Montreal. Since then she has participated in the research and residency programs of the C entre for Contemporary Art Kitakyushu, Japan, C C A Jeleni, Prague, Czech Republic, Akademie Schloss Solitude, Stuttgart, and The Banff C entre for the Arts, C anada. C alling her practice Aesthetic Management, Reed operates between various roles within the art field, allowing for a partaking in different modes of production including artistic, curatorial, and textual forms of dissemination. Recent and forthcoming projects include: Secret Publicity, C anada; They go round and round, 0 0 47 Projects, Oslo; ev+a Matters, Limerick Art G allery, Ireland; First Nations /Second Nature, Audain G allery, Vancouver; and Territo-ries of the In / Human, Württembergischer Kunstverein, Stuttgart. As a writer, Reed has contributed texts to the following publications: Shifter Magazine, Fillip, Art Papers, C Magazine, Neue Review and Framework: The Finnish Art Review. She lives and works in Berlin.

Gabriel Rockhill G abriel Rockhill is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Villanova Uni-versity & C entre Parisien d’Etudes C ritiques, Director of the Atelier de Théorie C ritique at the C entre Parisien d’Etudes C ritiques and the Collège International de Philosophie. He is the author of Logique de l’histoire: Pour une analytique des pratiques philosophiques (2 01 0) and is currently completing a manuscript for Les Editions du Sandre on the role of radical historicism in rethinking the relationship between art and politics. He co-edited and contributed to Critique et subversion dans la pensée contemporaine américaine: Dia-logues (2 01 0); Jacques Rancière: History, Politics, Aesthetics (2 0 0 9); and Technologies de contrôle dans la mondialisation: Enjeux politiques, éthiques et esthétiques (2 0 0 9). He also edited and translated Jacques Rancière’s The Politics of Aesthet-ics (2 0 0 4).

Terry Sejnowski and Steven R. QuartzTerrence Sejnowski is an Investigator with the Howard Hughes Medical Institute and is the Francis C rick Professor at The Salk Institute for B iological Studies where he directs the Computational Neurobiology Laboratory. He is also Professor of B iological Sciences and Adjunct Professor in the Departments of Neurosciences, Psy-chology, Cognitive Science, and Computer Science and Engineering at the University of C alifornia, San Diego, where he is Director of the Institute for Neural Computation. He served on the faculty of Johns Hopkins University and was a Wiersma Visiting Professor of Neuro-biology and a Sherman Fairchild Distinguished Scholar at C altech. The long-range goal of Dr. Sejnowski’s laboratory is to understand the computational resources of brains and to build linking principles

from brain to behavior using computational models. This goal is being pursued with a combination of theoretical and experimental approaches at several levels of investigation ranging from the bio-physical level to the systems level. H is papers are widely published and his recent publications include: Toward Brain-Computer Interfacing (co-authored 2 0 0 7); New Directions in Statistical Signal Processing (co-authored 2 0 0 6); Liars, Lovers, and Heroes: What the New Brain Science Reveals About How We Become Who We Are (co-authored with Steen Quartz, 2 0 0 3)

Steven R. Quartz, PhD, is director of the Social Cognitive Neuro-science Laboratory at the C alifornia Institute of Technology and an Associate Professor in the Division of Humanities and Social Sci-ences and the Computation and Neural Systems Program. He was a fellow of the Sloan C enter for Theoretical Neurobiology at the Salk Institute and a recipient of the National Science Foundation’s C ARE ER award, its most prestigious award for young faculty. H i research uses advances and methods in neuroscience to probe fun-damental problems of mind, ranging from how the mind emerges from the developing brain to how we make decisions, from individual decision-making under uncertainty to moral decision making. H is publishes regularly in the journal Science and he is coauthor (with Terrence Sejnowski) of Liars, Lovers, and Heroes: What the New Brain Science Reveals About How We Become Who We Are (2 0 0 3).

Elizabeth Sikiaridi and Frans VogelaarProfessor Elizabeth Sikiaridi and Professor Frans Vogelaar are part-ners at Hybrid Space Lab, Berlin/Amsterdam, an r&d and design practice focusing on the hybrid fields that are emerging through the combination and fusion of environments, objects and services in the information/communication age. In 1 9 9 8 Frans Vogelaar founded at the Academy of Media Arts Cologne the first Department of Hybrid Space worldwide. Their work has been presented at international congresses and exhibitions and has been published internationally: Austria, Belgium, C anada, China, Czech Republic, Denmark, G er-many, Greece, F inland, France, Italy, Latvia, Lithuania, Pakistan, Poland, Portugal, Oman (upcoming in 2 01 0), Singapore, South Korea (upcoming in 2 01 0), Switzerland, Spain, the Netherlands, Turkey, UK, and USA.

Paolo VirnoPaolo Virno is a philosopher who lives in Rome and teaches at the University of C alabria. H is research specializes in political philoso-phy, linguistics and mass media. He was politically active as a member of the Italian political group Potere Operaio during the 1 9 70s, where he was imprisoned for three years before being acquitted. He is a contributor of the philosophical review Forme di vita. Among his recent publications are: Virtuosismo y revolución: La acción politica en la era del desencanto (2 0 0 3); Esercizi di esodo (2 0 0 2): Quando il verbo si fa carne. Linguaggio e natura umana (2 0 0 3); A Grammar of the Multitude: For an Analysis of Contemporary Forms of Life (2 0 0 4); Motto di spirito e azione innovativa (2 0 0 5); and Multitude: Between Innovation and Negation (2 0 0 8).

5 87

Page 40: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Credits

Delft School of Design Series on Architecture and UrbanismSeries Editor Arie Graafland

Editorial BoardK. Michael Hayes (Harvard University, USA)Ákos Moravánszky (ETH Zürich, Switzerland)Michael Müller (Bremen University, G ermany)Frank R. Werner (University of Wuppertal, G ermany)G erd Zimmermann (Bauhaus University, G ermany)

Also published in this series:1 Crossover. Architecture Urbanism TechnologyIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 6 0 9 32 The Body in ArchitectureIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 5 6 8 33 De- / signing the Urban. Technogenesis and the urban imageIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 61 1 64 The Model and its ArchitectureIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 6 8 4 05 Urban Asymmetries. Studies and projects on neoliberal urbanizationIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 72 4 3 (to be published in 2 01 1)

6 Cognitive Architecture. From biopolitics to noopoliticsEditors Deborah Hauptmann, Warren NeidichText editing D ’Laine C ampBook design by P iet G erards Ontwerpers (P iet G erards and Maud van Rossum), AmsterdamPrinted by DeckersSnoeck, Antwerp

On the cover: Virgil Grotfeldt, ‘Fantastic G arden’, 2 0 0 2 , coal dust and acrylic on paper, superimposed on Stephen J. Dvorak, ‘ Competition drawing’, 1 9 8 5 , ink on paper.

©2 01 0 The authors / 01 0 Publishers, Rotterdamwww.01 0 .nl

IS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 72 5 0

5 8 8

Page 41: Wolfe, Charles - Cognitive Architecture

Credits

Delft School of Design Series on Architecture and UrbanismSeries Editor Arie Graafland

Editorial BoardK. Michael Hayes (Harvard University, USA)Ákos Moravánszky (ETH Zürich, Switzerland)Michael Müller (Bremen University, G ermany)Frank R. Werner (University of Wuppertal, G ermany)G erd Zimmermann (Bauhaus University, G ermany)

Also published in this series:1 Crossover. Architecture Urbanism TechnologyIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 6 0 9 32 The Body in ArchitectureIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 5 6 8 33 De- / signing the Urban. Technogenesis and the urban imageIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 61 1 64 The Model and its ArchitectureIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 6 8 4 05 Urban Asymmetries. Studies and projects on neoliberal urbanizationIS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 72 4 3 (to be published in 2 01 1)

6 Cognitive Architecture. From biopolitics to noopoliticsEditors Deborah Hauptmann, Warren NeidichText editing D ’Laine C ampBook design by P iet G erards Ontwerpers (P iet G erards and Maud van Rossum), AmsterdamPrinted by DeckersSnoeck, Antwerp

On the cover: Virgil Grotfeldt, ‘Fantastic G arden’, 2 0 0 2 , coal dust and acrylic on paper, superimposed on Stephen J. Dvorak, ‘ Competition drawing’, 1 9 8 5 , ink on paper.

©2 01 0 The authors / 01 0 Publishers, Rotterdamwww.01 0 .nl

IS B N 9 78 9 0 6 4 5 0 72 5 0

5 8 8