349
An Investigation of Everyday Morality and Anti-Social Behaviour By Jan Adams Completed in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor in Philosophy Submitted to Edge Hill University Department of Law and Criminology October 2018 1

research.edgehill.ac.uk  · Web viewAn Investigation of Everyday Morality and Anti-Social Behaviour. By. Jan Adams. Completed in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    2

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

An Investigation of Everyday Morality and Anti-Social Behaviour

By

Jan Adams

Completed in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor in Philosophy

Submitted to Edge Hill University

Department of Law and Criminology

October 2018

1

I would like to dedicate this thesis, in loving memory of Nanny Amy.

2

Acknowledgements

Personal Acknowledgements:

Father.

John, husband.

Family and close friends.

Beloved departed.

Professor Andrew Millie.

Dr Leon Culbertson.

Special Acknowledgements:

Academic Supervisors: Professor Andrew Millie & Dr Leon Culbertson.

Dr Nikki Craske & Graduate School.

Jane Hartlebury & Disability Inclusion Team.

Law and Criminology Department.

Dr Debbie Pope & Psychology Department.

Philosophy Reading Group.

Revd Janet Heighton & Rainford Church Friendship Group.

Dr Alana Barton, Professor Jeremy Brown & all Thesis Examiners.

Generous Feedback from kind Academics.

Research Participants & Community Groups.

3

Contents

Acknowledgments - 3

Contents – 4

Abstract – 8

Chapter 1 – Introduction: Anti-Social Behaviour

Introduction - 9

Origins of the term ‘anti-social behaviour’ - 12

History of talk about anti-social behaviour - 18

Political discourse on ASB - 21

Perceptions and tolerance of ASB - 24

Who are perceived as ASB perpetrators? - 28

Alternative methods for tackling ASB? - 30

Family interventions - 32

ASB and deprivation - 34

Crimes of everyday life - 37

Official data on ASB - 38

Conclusions - 41

Chapter 2 - Anti-Social Behaviour and Everyday Morality

Introduction - 43

Common morality - 45

Virtues - 49

Everyday civility – 50

Everyday morality and relativism - 52

Individual morality - 53

A Kantian perspective - 55

Social contexts of everyday morality - 62

Everyday morality and society - 64

Linking perceptions of ASB to everyday morality - 68Conclusions - 70

4

Chapter 3 – ASB, moral regulation and responsibilisation

Introduction - 72

ASB, respect and moral regulation - 72

Self-regulation and responsibilisation - 76

The ‘law abiding’ majority - 78

Talk of moral decline and respect - 81

Civility and social norms - 82

Conclusions - 83

Chapter 4 – Methodology

Rationale - 85

Location selection – 87

Focus groups – 88

Sampling - 89

Use of vignettes - 90

Ethical considerations - 93

Harm to participants - 93

Informed consent - 94

Invasion of privacy - 94

Deception - 94

Rationale for method of analysis - 95

Research appraisal - 99

Limitations of the current study – 100

Chapter 5 - Analysis and Discussion

Introduction - 103

Perceptions of what constitutes ASB - 104

Youthful ASB - 106

Issues of understanding ASB and impacts - 109

What defines ASB? - 111

5

Perceived Causes of ASB - 112

Parenting - 115

Disrespect - 116

Individual factors and ASB - 120

Moral explanations of ASB - 123

Reciprocity of everyday morality - 128

ASB and immorality -134

ASB, immorality and intolerance - 141

ASB and consequences - 143

ASB, what should be, and what is - 145

Morality and parenting - 147

Summary - 152

Chapter 6 – Conclusions

Introduction - 154

Perceptions of ASB - 155

Perceptions of ASB: Everyday morality - 156

How individual context and perception related to ASB - 157

Social deprivation and ASB - 157

ASB, subjectivity and tolerance - 159

ASB and morality - 159

The Golden Rule, Kantian ethics and ASB - 161

Perceptions of everyday morality and ASB – 163

Current climate of ASB - 164

Limitations -166

Contributions to knowledge - 168

Future research directions – 170

References - 172

Appendices

Appendix A – Summary Protocol for Using IPA with Focus Group Data -207

6

Appendix B – Consent Form - 209

Appendix C – Participant Demographic Information Sheet - 210

Appendix D – Participant Debriefing Form - 211

Appendix E – Interview Schedule - 212

7

Abstract

Anti-social Behaviour (ASB) has been described as something that cannot be ignored and a

real concern for the everyday lives of people. A key issue has been the need to address public

perceptions and concerns that a rising tide of ASB is concomitant to a wider societal moral

decline. An assumed rising ASB, moral decline and a lack of respect are widespread

perceptions. ASB is also thought to have an impact on peoples quality of life. Cogent links

have been reported between levels of deprivation and those who perceive ASB as a serious

concern in their communities. What factors underpin these perceptions have previously been

examined, the aim being to introduce policy-based measures that can tackle both ASB and

the perception of ASB.

This thesis considers the everyday morality that informs public perceptions of ASB: namely

what do people believe it means to be anti-social; what is perceived as everyday morality and

how does this relate to ASB; and what role, if any, does everyday morality play in

determining the public’s perceptions of ASB. The thesis utilizes a qualitative approach

involving the use of focus groups and Interpretative Phenomenological Analysis (IPA). Nine

focus groups were conducted in three locations in the North West of England (Skelmersdale,

Rainford and St Helens) selected according to their Indices of Multiple Deprivation score

(IMD, 2010) to represent an area of high deprivation, mixed deprivation and low deprivation.

A deductive IPA analysis revealed that public perceptions of ASB were grounded in people’s

own personal experiences of ASB (and those of friends or family). Whether an act was

perceived as immoral and anti-social was related to the consequences of the behaviour, the

context of when or why it occurred, and public preconceptions regarding their own

experiences. Public perceptions of ASB were found to be subjective, and they varied both

within and between each focus group location. ASB and everyday morality were perceived to

be linked - with everyday morality being perceived as an internal deterrent that may prohibit

one from behaving anti-socially. Further clarification is needed to confirm how deeply public

perceptions are related to everyday morality but also how this might inform approaches to

tackling ASB. It is suggested that everyday morality provides a framework to understand how

individuals navigate everyday social situations in public spaces.

8

Chapter 1.

Introduction: Anti-Social Behaviour

Introduction

The aim of this thesis is to investigate how anti-social behaviour (ASB) and everyday

morality may be linked and what evidence there is for this link. The thesis investigates public

perceptions of ASB and everyday morality. Specifically, what part does everyday morality

play in determining the public’s perceptions of ASB? The thesis draws on criminological and

philosophical conceptualizations of ASB and everyday morality. Everyday morality is

identified as an influential factor in how some people may regard ASB as immoral.

Previous political discourse and ASB interventions have often discussed ASB as being low-

level, uncivil behaviour and linked to a lack of respect and an assumed moral decline

(Coleman, 2005, Browne, 2008 Millie, 2010). This chapter aims to elucidate both how and

why ASB has been described as an issue of morality. Consideration is given to how accounts

of ASB have been perceived as both influencing and being influenced by individual

perceptions of morality. This introduction chapter starts with a discussion of the origins of the

term ASB, including consideration of definitions. The chapter goes on to examine the history

of talk about ASB. The next point is to consider what constitutes ASB and how ASB may be

tackled. The relationship between respect, deprivation and community involvement is then

addressed. Official data on ASB is considered and conclusions drawn focusing on the

relationship between ASB and everyday morality.

Chapter two examines this relationship further by discussing moral philosophy and concepts

that may elucidate the link between ASB and everyday morality. This chapter discusses

concepts including morality, respect, common morality, everyday civility, moral relativism,

individual morality, Kantian ethics and finally the link between ASB and everyday morality.

ASB is linked to morality through a discussion of perceptions and concepts regarding respect,

tolerance, social context, moral regulation and social norms. Particular reference is made to

the role of perception and why some behaviour may be perceived as immoral and anti-social

9

or not. Chapter two concludes by discussing atypical examples of ASB and the issue of

tackling the moral aspects of ASB.

Chapter three describes the relationship between ASB, moral regulation and

responsibilisation. This section of the thesis includes considered discussion of moral

regulation, in addition to the mechanisms adopted to tackle incivility and ASB. The nature of

moral regulation and how governments have tried to address concerns of behaviour is related

to political discourse, legislation and concepts such as responsibilisation. These are discussed

in terms of their utility towards tackling ASB and incivility. Other key concepts are discussed

including moral decline, respect, moral panics, social norms and the ‘law-abiding majority’.

The chapter concludes with a summary of how previous efforts at moral regulation have

focused on specific groups within society and that other behaviours which fall under the

rubric of ASB may be missed. The potential of tolerance and mutual respect to provide a

partial solution towards tackling ASB and moral concerns concludes this chapter.

Chapter four describes the methodology, starting with the rationale for the thesis including a

discussion of previous research that has utilised similar or dissimilar methods to studying

ASB and everyday morality. The locations selected and rationale underpinning the sampling,

focus group method and use of vignettes is detailed next. The sample was selected through

purposive sampling and the locations selected included Skelmersdale, Rainford and St Helens

in North West England. The English Indices of Multiple Deprivation (2010; DCLG, 2011)

was adapted to select locations based upon their level of deprivation (mixed level of

deprivation, more deprived and least deprived). Three focus groups were conducted in each

study location with a minimum of four participants and maximum of 12 (Kruegar and Casey,

2000), with a total of 52 participants. The investigation adopted Interpretive

Phenomenological Analysis (IPA) (Callery et al., 2015) thus enabling the researcher to ‘allow

for unanticipated themes to emerge’ (Callery et al., 2015: 64). An appraisal section considers

the quality criteria for conducting qualitative research and finally a summary concludes with

the potential limitations and countermeasures adopted to overcome research barriers.

Chapter five includes a detailed analysis and discussion. It starts by detailing how IPA

revealed a diverse range of interrelated themes that captured participants’ subjective

experience of ASB and everyday morality. The core themes identified included: perceptions

of what constitutes ASB; youthful ASB; issues of understanding ASB and impacts; perceived

10

causes of ASB; moral explanations of ASB; reciprocity of everyday morality; ASB and

immorality; ASB, immorality and intolerance; and parenting and morality. A notable finding

was that participants perceived that there was a link between everyday morality and ASB.

Furthermore, this link was related to concepts such as parenting, religion and society. Chapter

five concludes with a description of the key themes. The implications of the findings and

potential ramifications for future research are discussed throughout.

In chapter 6 the conclusions of the thesis are presented on how the public perceive everyday

morality and ASB to be related. Perceptions tended to centre on everyday nuisance behaviour

and disruption in association with young people. This perception was linked to other factors

such as deprivation and poor parenting thought to influence the likelihood of young people

engaging in ASB. Another theme detailed perceived issues in the subjective understanding of

ASB and impacts. Participants revealed that what is seen as anti-social to one individual may

not be to another. The negative impacts and consequences of ASB were frequently linked to

perceptions of what ASB is. Personal experience formed an important aspect of participant

narratives in how they perceive ASB.

Morality was perceived as linked to ASB through relationships between a ‘lack of morality’,

or immorality, and the occurrence of ASB. Atypical examples of anti-social and immoral

behaviour were highlighted; for example, tax evasion or avoidance by large companies.

Perceptions of ASB and morality were further linked through participant narratives linking

the two concepts of immorality and intolerance. The study revealed that perceptions of a link,

however, were not unanimous. A further finding was that perceptions of ASB as immoral, or

moral, were subjective. When a link with morality was discussed this was often in terms of

the consequences of an anti-social act. Perceptions of a link tended to be discussed with

reference to the role of parenting. Additional perceived links included with societal, cultural

and peer-related factors. A perceived ‘lack of morality’ was further seen as a cause for ASB

on an individual level. The link between ASB and everyday morality was perceived as one of

cognition and behaviour. (Im)morality was often constructed by participants as the

premeditative stage prior to the anti-social act. Being ‘moral’ was seen as a potential

inhibitor against ASB; however, what is regarded as moral may change from individual to

individual. The limitations of this study and contributions to current knowledge are then

discussed. Key contributions include the identification of unconventional forms of ASB.

11

Examining ASB from a joint criminological and philosophical perspective enabled the

research to detail public perceptions of ASB in relation to everyday perceptions of morality,

not only whether certain acts of ASB are regarded as immoral, but also why they were

perceived as such; for example, the impact on others was used by some to measure the

‘morality’ of an act. Chapter 6 concludes with future research directions and suggests that

examining specific types of behaviour and ASB with ward level data may help address why,

in some areas of varying deprivation, the perceived underlying moral aspects of ASB may be

different. Approaches to address the moral aspects of ASB could then be tailored to each

individual location, based upon the local people’s understanding of everyday moral values.

Origins of the term ‘anti-social behaviour’

According to Pearson (2009) concern about troublesome youth has been a prominent aspect

of British society since at least the seventeenth century. In Hooligan: A History of

Respectable Fears, Pearson (1983) contended that moral panics around issues of disorderly

behaviour and incivility in British cities are not a new phenomenon. Familiar references in

the government and media precede a recycling of ‘respectable fears’ (Pearson, 1983). Pearson

(1983) suggested that responses to urban disorder frequently describe familiar stories of the

‘British way of life’ being under threat from an unruly minority. The perception that this way

of life is under threat from uncivil behaviour is recycled perpetuating the moral panic around

the behaviour of troublesome youths.

There is a perpetual view that ‘young people no longer respect the law, no longer respect

their parents and neighbours, they no longer show any obedience to authority in all its forms,

there is now a carnival of disorder in the streets of the ‘broken’ society’ (Pearson, 2009: 41,

emphasis in original). However, Kirby and Edmondson (2012) argue that ASB has become

more pervasive over recent decades. It would be challenging to validate this claim due to

consistently changing definitions and understandings of troublesome or anti-social behaviour.

This issue is compounded without having comparable historical data. Issues of ASB and

urban disorder have permeated many facets of the UK government since the mid-1990s,

attracting the attention of the media and political bodies (Flint and Powell, 2009). The term

ASB is still widely utilized today (Neary, et al., 2013).

12

According to the Home Office (2012), the term ‘anti-social behaviour’ describes the

everyday nuisances, disorderly and criminal behaviours of concern to local people, or those

behaviours that are not a priority for police forces and local authorities. According to Brown

(2013), ASB is an umbrella term for low-level nuisance behaviours, criminality and public

disorder. It has been the catalyst for continuing debate for the past two decades. The political

and legislative origins of ASB can be traced back to the Public Order Act 1986, introduced

by the Conservative Government (Millie, 2013). Whilst the term ‘anti-social behaviour’ was

not employed here, the language relating to ‘harassment, alarm or distress’ within the 1986

Act was synonymous with the later definitions of ASB employed, such as in the 1998 Crime

and Disorder Act (of more later). The Public Order Act 1986 stated that:

A person is guilty of an offence if he (a) uses threatening, abusive or insulting words

or behaviour, or disorderly behaviour, or (b) displays any writing, sign or other visible

representation which is threatening, abusive or insulting, within the hearing or sight of

a person likely to be caused harassment, alarm or distress. (1986 Public Order Act

S.5(1)).

Another attempt to define ASB arose from the Chartered Institute of Housing (1995: 4) who

claimed that ASB is: ‘Behaviour that unreasonably interferes with other people’s rights to the

use and enjoyment of their home and community’. According to Millie (2009) this

highlighted the link between ASB and housing discourse. There has been a considerable

amount of literature investigating ASB and housing (Burney, 2002; Brown, 2004; Carr and

Cowan, 2006 Flint 2006; Squires 2006) and it has been at the forefront of efforts to tackle

ASB (Flint and Powell, 2009). Later, ASB became a key feature of the Conservatives’ 1996

Housing Act which gave the power to apply for an injunction against certain behaviours. For

example, verbal or physical abuse, criminal damage and the threat of violence could be

grounds for an injunction (without notice). This extended to noise, animal or vehicle related

nuisance behaviour. If injunctions were breached, applicants could apply to attach a power of

arrest for breaching an injunction. Among those who could apply for these injunctions were

local housing authorities, social landlords, housing actions trusts or charitable housing trusts

who may be acting as landlords of premises. According to the 1996 Housing Act (s.152) a

person is guilty of ASB if she or he is:

13

(a) engaging in or threatening to engage in conduct causing or likely to cause a

nuisance or annoyance to a person residing in, visiting or otherwise engaging

in a lawful activity in residential premises to which this section applies or in

the locality of such premises (b) using or threatening to use residential

premises to which this section applies for immoral or illegal purposes, or (c)

entering residential premises to which this section applies or being found in

the locality of any such premises.

The focus of ASB lay squarely on tenants of social landlords. The private rented section of

the 1996 Act contains no reference to the behaviour of tenants, anti-social or otherwise (Carr

et al., 2007). Two years later the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act, as introduced by New

Labour, also attempted to define ASB. According to the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act

(section 1(a-b)) ASB was:

… that the person has acted, since the commencement date, in an anti-social

manner, that is to say, in a manner that caused or was likely to cause

harassment, alarm or distress to one or more persons not of the same

household as himself; and that such an order is necessary to protect relevant

persons from further anti-social acts by him.

The Crime and Disorder Act was New Labour’s first piece of legislation and introduced the

Anti-Social Behaviour Order (ASBO) (Hewitt, 2007). However, the origins of the ASBO are

earlier than this (Hewitt, 2007; Millie, 2009), with an early incarnation contained within a

consultation paper entitled ‘A Quiet Life: tough action on criminal behaviours’ (Labour

Party, 1995). In this document it was claimed that ‘plenty of those guilty of ASB are private

tenants or owner occupiers’ (Labour Party, 1995:7). It also presented plans for the

‘Community Safety Order’ that laid the foundation for the emergent ASBO. Millie (2009)

claimed that, despite ASB not being defined in this document to an adequate standard, there

were elements pertaining to neighbour disputes and people’s right to having a ‘quiet life’ that

would manifest in later legislation regarding ASB.

The emphasis was on controlling offenders of low-level crime and ASB and these were

assumed to be mainly within areas of social housing (Cleland and Tisdall, 2005). Discussions

were also ongoing in the House of Commons Scottish Affairs Committee (1996, as cited in

14

Wigzell, 2014) that, rightly or wrongly, focused on ASB within the housing context. Despite

being initially mentioned by the Conservative government (1996), the Labour Party adapted

ASB as its own agenda and took a pledge to combat ASB which became a core focus of their

election campaign in 1997. When New Labour came to power in 1997 Tony Blair

emphasised the role of the individual in society and community. The underpinning ideology

of New Labour highlighted that respect for oneself as well as others was key to society; the

rights and responsibilities of all were central elements of policy under the New Labour

government (Millie, 2009). Blair drew from exponents such as Amitai Etzioni (1993) who

advocated a communitarian approach:

A Communitarian perspective recognises that the preservation of individual

liberty depends on the active maintenance of the institutions of civil society

where the citizens learn respect for each other as well as self-respect … (p.

253)

The influence of Etzioni (1993) on New Labour policy was exemplified by New Labour’s

approach to tackling ASB making the perpetrators more respectful by introducing civilising

offensives (Flint and Powell, 2009) to censure behaviour. The threat was to make those who

behave anti-socially more respectful and more civilised. Although definitions of respect and

civilised behaviour are based upon what the ‘law-abiding majority’ desire (Millie, 2009). The

aim was for the New Labour government to take an active role in promoting civility and good

behaviour in society. Thus began the Blairite crusade to morally and culturally reform

behaviour in Britain to tackle the lack of respect, moral decline and ASB.

According to Labour MP Frank Field (2003) ASB was the core contemporary social issue of

the political battleground in the UK. The term ‘anti-social behaviour’ becomes more widely

utilized, particularly by the media. According to Waiton (2005: 23, as cited in Millie, 2009):

The catch all term ‘antisocial behaviour’ has today become so widely used it

seems strange to find it was rarely used [in the media] until the 1990s. In the

1980s a couple of articles a year were printed in the UK discussing antisocial

behaviour, whereas in January 2004 alone, there were over 1000 such

articles…

15

The suggestion here is that ASB is a broad term applied to a broad spectrum of people. A key

point here is that the usage of the term ‘ASB’ appeared to increase through the 1990s and

early 2000s. Similarly, according to Wigzell (2014) the term ‘anti-social behaviour’ was

barely used or hardly recognized before the 1990s. Wigzell (2014) uses the metaphor of an

arms race to describe the development of ASB in the political world as parties duelled to win

votes and appear tougher than each other. Subsequently, multifarious laws and policies

emerged to tackle ASB (Wigzell, 2014) as this was the priority issue for criminal justice

legislation (MacDonald, 2002; McCarthy, 2011).

The 1998 Act suggested that ASB must take the form of action or speech, that results in a

person or group of people (most likely not in the perpetrators family) feeling distress (Neary

et al, 2013). A straightforward way to define ASB might be to look at what kinds of actions

or speech are considered anti-social. Such an approach, however, is likely to result in an

unwieldy list. A study conducted in three areas of the West Midlands (Berry, 2003) examined

police records to see what behaviours had been classified as ASB. Thirty-two different

offences had been classified as ASB, but only one of these offences (noise nuisance) was

consistently classified as ASB across the three areas. If a relatively small area of the UK has

such variability in what offences are classified as ASB, then the number of offences that

could potentially be regarded as ASB across the country could be even bigger. Similarly,

Ramsay (2004) suggested that the definition of ASB is intolerably vague and too generalized

to account for contextual variation.

Ironically (given its name), it seems that defining ASB through behaviour alone may not be

appropriate or sufficient. According to Brunger (2008: 13) ‘…the notion of anti-social

behaviour is never clearly pinned down to one kind of behaviour’. The New Labour

Government responsible for the 1998 Act recognised the difficulty in pinning ASB down. For

instance, according to Alun Michael MP, ASB was ‘easier to recognise than to define’ (cited

in Millie, 2009: 1). Some examples of ASB included: vandalism, graffiti, threatening

behaviour in large groups and joyriding (Home Office, 2002, cited in Prior and Paris, 2005).

Some of these behaviours could be regarded as criminal acts in their own right (such as

joyriding), but it is not always clear at what point such behaviours are anti-social and when

they are criminal (Prior and Paris, 2005).

16

In a similar vein of thought, Morgado and Vale-Dias (2013) claimed that there was a general

assumption regarding the meaning of ASB that violates social rules which are meant to

promote respect and consideration, particularly towards other peoples’ life and property (Burt

et al., 2011). Morgado and Vale-Dias (2013) further contended that such general assumptions

and definitional issues are the basis for a belief that ASB is a socially-determined construct

with multifarious subtypes. They then suggested that ASB contains different levels of

destructiveness, forms, functions, consequence, onsets and pathways. Despite the multitude

of examples of ASB, the identification and consideration of ASB is still curbed by the high

level of uncertainty about what this is (Morgado and Vale-Dias, 2013). They concluded that

ASB is a complex concept and the heterogeneous nature of what constitutes ASB needs

further research.

In 2014 the Conservative-led Coalition defined ASB as a:

…broad term used to describe the day-to-day incidents of crime, nuisance and

disorder that make many people’s lives a misery – from litter and vandalism,

to public drunkenness or aggressive dogs, to noisy or abusive neighbours.

(Home Office, 2014: 1)

The most recent definition of ASB is found in the 2014 Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and

Policing Act:

... “anti-social behaviour” means (a) conduct that has caused, or is likely to

cause, harassment, alarm or distress to any person, (b) conduct capable of

causing nuisance or annoyance to a person in relation to that person’s

occupation of residential premises, or (c) conduct capable of causing housing-

related nuisance or annoyance to any person.

According to this definition, ASB has broad parameters. Behaviours that are liable to cause

‘harassment, alarm or distress to any person’ or even ‘nuisance or annoyance’ may be

labelled as anti-social. The suggestion is that behaviours that cause people to feel these

emotions are likely to fall under the rubric of ASB.

17

The lack of a single agreed upon definition of ASB makes collection of statistics regarding its

prevalence difficult (Payne, 2003). Whether a behaviour is deemed anti-social or not does not

seem to be determined by its level of criminality, but rather the extent to which it matches the

behavioural expectations and norms of a time and place (Millie, 2008) and the level of

‘nuisance’ it causes (Brown, 2004: 204). Thus, behaviour can be labelled as anti-social just

because there is the perception it may cause offence, regardless of whether it does so (Millie,

2008). Expectations tend to be set by one group to the exclusion of others.

Definitional concerns have been conveyed by a plethora of research emphasizing the lack of

clarity (MacDonald, 2002; Samuels; 2005; Ramsay, 2004; Millie, 2008; Hodgkinson and

Tilley, 2011). For instance, the definition of ASB in the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act was

described as a ‘catch all’ (Hodgkinson and Tilley (2011) encompassing anything from

littering or dog fouling to assault and street prostitution. There has been a blurring of

boundaries between behaviour that can be considered simply a nuisance and behaviour that is

criminal, an issue related to the elasticity of the definition (Macdonald, 2002; Millie, 2009).

This can be problematic when local authorities and the police must distinguish between these

behaviours (Brown, 2004). It is something that must be seen to be defined, but definitions

vary depending on who is doing the seeing.

Thus, earlier notions of nuisance behaviours have been construed as anti-social (broadly

defined) or just a general nuisance to society. During the 1990s, housing legislation was

directed at tackling ASB within areas of social housing, and finally the 1998 Crime and

Disorder Act gave the first widely used definition of ASB. Understandings of what ASB is

have changed and continue to change, most recently with the 2014 Anti-Social Behaviour,

Crime and Policing Act, as introduced by the Conservative-Liberal Democrat Coalition. The

recent 2014 definition conveyed ASB as being typically a daily type of nuisance behaviour,

involving low level criminality and disorderly conduct that negatively affects the lives of

others.

History of talk about anti-social behaviour

According to Crawford and Flint (2009) from 1999 to 2009 there was an unprecedented

increase in the amount of legislative activity aimed at regulating behaviour and ameliorating

ASB. This included multifarious legal tools, powers and initiatives to tackle ASB (Crawford

18

and Flint, 2009). Similarly, Moran (2003, as cited in Crawford and Flint, 2009) claimed there

has been a long-term proliferation in policy, - or a ‘hyper-politicisation’ - introducing tools

attempting to counteract ASB. History of talk about ASB has centred on a widespread

political belief that ASB is increasing. Hodgkinson and Tilley (2011) claimed that the

prevalence of ASB as a recurring theme on the political agenda was due to the high levels of

political attentiveness and coverage by the media. Flint and Nixon (2006) argued, in a similar

vein, that the notion of increasing levels of ASB has made measures to tackle those behaving

anti-socially of paramount importance. It has been further contended that the term ‘anti-social

behaviour’ has transcended from a political buzzword into everyday vernacular. The political

focus on ASB has even been described by Tony Blair as a ‘crusade’ (2004, as cited in

Squires, 2006).

In political rhetoric, ASB has also been linked with immorality, and the presence of ASB is

regarded by some, particularly within the government and media, of evidence of a moral

decline in society (Millie, 2010). Opponents to this view argue that the ‘moral panic’

generated by official narratives is nothing more than an attempt to cover-up more serious

causes of ASB (Goode and Ben-Yehuda, 1994). In this way, ASBOs and other similar

measures may have been self-defeating, since they do not tackle the root causes of ASB, nor

provide the support needed to address it (Squires and Stephen, 2005). Another concern was

that many people who had been issued with ASBOs had mental health needs or learning

disabilities (Brown, 2004), and it is unlikely that an ASBO would have been effective in

reducing the undesired behaviour. It seems then, that the primary function of ASBOs was to

censure a certain repertoire of behaviours, deemed inappropriate by some, whilst legitimising

other behaviours, such as penalising vulnerable members of society.

It is easy to forget that ASB, before the advent of New Labour, was largely treated by the

police as a nuisance, unless it was also deemed to be criminal (Forrest and Tilley, 2005a;

Forrest et al. 2005b). As already noted, New Labour prioritized ASB in the run up to the

general election in 1997. They highlighted the damage done to some neighbourhoods by

chronic, inconsiderate behaviour. Drawing on policy and literature from the USA, they

focused on more deprived areas where such persistent ASB was thought to facilitate ‘spirals

of decline’, hindered attempts at neighbourhood renewal, and led to tolerance of local crime

(e.g. Skogan, 1990). The notion of ASB facilitating ‘spirals of decline’ was earlier discussed

19

as ‘social disorder’ by Wilson and Kelling and became known as the ‘Broken Windows’

theory (Wilson and Kelling,1982).

This approach entailed compiling a list of behaviours, for example public urination,

prostitution, loitering etc., and a list of physical symptoms of decay which needed to be

addressed to prevent the incubation of more extreme crime or ASB. Wilson and Kelling

suggested that disorder undermines the ability of neighbours to protect themselves, those who

are able will move away, whilst those who remain will withdraw from their community’s

public life and usage of community spaces. Wilson and Kelling (1982) further claimed that

the criminogenic impacts of social disorder originate from a decline of informal social

control. This creates opportunities for crime in undefended areas. This generates disorderly

behaviours that precede the later onset of serious crime. ‘Broken Windows’ theory links

directly observable, physical conditions of a neighbourhood influence to the way individuals

respond to it (Michener, 2013). Those who support this theory argue that minor, but visible,

signs of physical dilapidation lead to criminal violations (Kelling and Coles, 1996). This

fuelled discussion on whether ‘Broken Windows’ could inform policies on crime and

punishment and, if it could, should it be used to do so (Skogan, 2008; Harcourt and Ludwig,

2006). The main contention was that targeting low-level disorderly or nuisance behaviour is

the key to reducing longer term serious, violent crime. The suggestion that physical cues of

dilapidation lead to more serious crimes has been supported more recently (Keizer et al.,

2011). Conversely, other recent research by Wicherts and Bakker (2014) tested this

proposition, reporting that behaviours such as graffiti, litter and environmental cues do not

precipitate the proliferation of norm-violating behaviours. Wicherts and Bakker (2014)

further contended that recent evidence supporting this particular assumption of ‘Broken

Windows’ is methodologically flawed due to confounding variables, observer bias and

statistical weakness. Critiques of ‘Broken Windows’ such as these suggest caution when

applying ‘Broken Windows’ theory to policing and policy to tackle crime and ASB. Yet,

New Labour was attracted to Broken Windows theory.

Matthews (2003) further criticized ‘Broken Windows’, reporting that the process actually

occurs in reverse. Neighbourhood decline is a consequence of declining industry, investment

and employment opportunities. These factors precede the undermining of families and a

breakdown in community structures. This then leads to criminal and uncivil behaviours,

rather than criminal and uncivil behaviours causing the neighbourhood decline (Matthews,

20

2003). Instead of getting tough and imposing ever more punitive sanctions through

legislation, efforts might be better directed at stabilizing and regenerating neighbourhoods in

decline - a fact recognized by the Social Exclusion Unit (2000, as cited in Millie, 2008) who

claimed that those who fall victim to ASB and criminal sanctions are actually the victims of

structural processes.

The punitive philosophy adopted by New Labour legislation reflected the political thinking

that was at work to tackle ASB (Payne, 2003). According to Payne (2003), there are many

factors that underlie the penal approach of the UK government. First is the over-reliance of

disciplinary sanctions against ASB, second is the identification of individual accountability

rather than looking at the broader scope of ASB. Third is the narrow focus of looking only at

the behaviour based on consequences of the action rather than looking at the causal factors.

ASB has historically been portrayed as occurring within disadvantaged areas and as best

counteracted through tough sanctions. However, this was not effectively tackling the complex

aetiology of ASB (Matthews, 2003; Payne, 2003).

Political discourse on ASB

Contemporary political talk of ASB has related to the ideology of developing a ‘Big Society’

(Conservatives, 2010). The ‘Big Society’ involves ‘redistributing power from the state to

society; from the centre to local communities; giving people the opportunity to take more

control over their lives’ (Conservative Party Manifesto, 2010: 39). According to Donoghue

(2012) the Big Society aims to produce social entrepreneurship and active citizenship as part

of an urban renewal, particularly in areas such as crime control and developing community

cohesion. This is to be achieved through the promotion of community engagement aimed to

develop a strong relationship between citizens, communities and crime agencies (Home

Office, 2010).

In this context, discussion by Theresa May when she was Home Secretary was of a ‘new

approach’ to tackle ASB (Home Office, 2010). The Conservative-Liberal Democrat coalition

in 2010 closed the curtain on 13 years of New Labour government within the UK. With this

came the demise of the punitive flagship policy, the ASBO (Hughes, 2011). Further points

made in Theresa May’s speech ‘Moving Beyond the ASBO’ (Home Office, 2010) comprised

of criticizing the ‘top-down’, ‘bureaucratic’, ‘centralised’ and ‘gimmick-laden’ methods

applied by New Labour to tackle ASB. Ultimately, she signalled the dismissal of previous

21

strategies to tackle ASB, instead claiming that different approaches were needed which

would be ‘rehabilitating and restorative rather than criminalizing and coercive’ (Home

Office, 2010: 1). A consultation paper entitled ‘More Effective Responses to Anti-Social

Behaviour’ (Home Office, 2011) advocated an approach that was less centralised and more

local. There was to be more emphasis on the powers of frontline professionals in terms of

increasing local accountability. This aimed to reduce the bureaucracy, because at the most

fundamental level ASB was believed to be a local problem (Home Office, 2011).

This consultation paper proposed that ASB should have two fresh legal instruments to tackle

ASB instead of ASBOs, namely the ‘Crime Prevention Injunction’ (CPI) and the ‘Criminal

Behaviour Order’ (CBO), but these would also include positive requirements to be met

(Hughes, 2011). The CPI was to be a civil order with a civil burden of proof that made it

easier to obtain (Home Office, 2011). A civil burden of proof meant that the injunction could

be obtained quicker and easier based upon the balance of probabilities rather than beyond all

reasonable doubt (Home Office, 2014). A CBO was a civil preventative order that could be

joined with a conviction. This was aimed at protecting the public from behaviour that causes

or is liable to cause distress, alarm or harassment (Home Office, 2011). A court could ban the

individual from locations or activities and further require the offender to participate in

positive activities to address the underpinning reasons for their offending. There was a range

of civil sanctions for breaching the prohibitions attached to the CPI. For adults, a breach of

this would be punished as contempt of court with potential custody or fines. For under

eighteen year olds, sanctions for breaching the CPI included curfews, supervision, detention

or activity requirements.

The CPI was later rebranded as the Injunction to Prevent Nuisance and Annoyance (IPNA).

The IPNA is a civil order to be used against those aged 10 or over (Anti-Social Behaviour,

Crime and Policing Act, 2014). The IPNA can be granted if a court is satisfied that an

individual has, on the balance of probabilities, ‘engaged or threatens to engage in conduct

capable of causing nuisance and annoyance’ (Anti-social Behaviour Crime and Policing Bill,

2014: S.1 (2)). There are also the Community Protection Notice, Community Protection

Order (Public Space) and Community Protection Order (Closure). The Act also introduced

the Public Spaces Protection Order (PSPO).

22

Those issued with a CBO or an IPNA may have to attend a programme such as anger

management or other locally provided public services (Hughes, 2011). Despite this, Hughes

(2011) has claimed it is dubious as to how much would differ from ASBOs. In fact, it may

have made little difference to recipients or even the communities they are meant to protect.

Hughes went further, contending that the critics of ASBOs would not be appeased by these

new tools. The only real change is that justifying a civil standard of proof is easier, thus

making applications faster, cheaper and more liable to succeed. Even more pressing, Millie

(2010: 9) considered the Conservative manifesto (Conservatives, 2010) and claimed that the

rhetoric appeared ‘all too familiar’. Millie (2010: 9), drew on a speech by the Home Secretary

Theresa May (Home Office, 2010), in which she stated ‘I believe it is time for us to stop

tolerating anti-social behaviour’, suggesting that much of the rhetoric remained the same.

Indeed, the new package of measures appeared to exhibit ‘rebranding’ rather than a fresh

approach, which will probably yield similar results to the ASBO (Hodgkinson and Tilley,

2011).

Despite much similarity, it was acknowledged by Bannister and Kearns (2012) that it was too

early to judge the coalition government’s approach to tackling ASB. However, it is entirely

plausible to propose that this approach shared similar qualitative features, such as intolerance

and reassurance, with New Labour’s approach. Three years later, research reported that the

new government’s approach still retained focal elements pertaining to the previous New

Labour regime (Flint, 2014). Flint (2014) stated that the key components kept were: intense

family projects, sanctions, non-negotiable support and Parenting Orders in addition to the

belief that sanctions are an effective deterrent. Even more specifically, Flint claimed that the

new powers introduced by the 2014 Act simply broadened the range of behaviours that could

be described as ‘anti-social’. Further criticisms related to the lowering of thresholds and

lower burdens of proof required for the use of legal tools like the IPNA and CBO. A lower

civil burden of proof, with lesser requirements, meant that ‘potentially lengthy and expensive

criminal proceedings can be bypassed’ (Millie, 2014: 382). This could provide flexibility in

the application of powers. According to the Home Office (2014) the standard of proof for

CBOs required that the court was:

…satisfied beyond reasonable doubt that the offender has engaged in

behaviour that has caused or is likely to cause harassment, alarm or distress to

23

any person; and… The court considers that making the order will help prevent

the offender from engaging in such behaviour. (Home Office, 2014)

There was also no requirement to prove necessity, unlike for the ASBO (Home Office, 2014).

More recent research has noted further issues with these new powers. Eastwood (2015)

reported that the introduction of new legal powers tended to inaugurate the more aggressive

use of these tools against perpetrators. This could be problematic, as Eastwood contends that

the new measures introduced have a broader spectrum of activities covered than the previous

legislation. Eastwood (2015) also noted that in some situations the new legislation

empowered the authorities to use some of these powers without a court order, as is the case

with the ‘Community Protection Notice’ (CPN). As noted, these notices are easier to obtain

due to their lower burden of proof. Eastwood (2015) concluded that the new ASB powers,

similar to their predecessors, would further enhance the vulnerability and exclusion of those

members of society who are subjected to punitive measures that fail to treat the cause, rather

than symptom, of ASB. For example, Eastwood cited some of the factors that contribute to

ASB as housing, mental health problems, poverty and substance misuse, none of which are

fully addressed by the new legislation.

Perceptions and tolerance of ASB

The definitions of ASB used by politicians have tended to be heavily based on perceptions of

behaviour (Mackenzie et al., 2010) rather than the actual behaviour itself. This was reflected

in the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act that viewed the behaviour from the perspective of the

`victims` of the behaviour (Cogan, 2006). This stance is not uncommon amongst definitions

of ASB. Squires (2008: 368) captures this when he says ‘anti-social behaviour is

emphatically about perceptions, relationships, and interactions and contexts. It is important

for what it signals’. Thus, it seems that behaviour cannot be considered anti-social in

isolation, it must be considered in the context in which it arises, and from the viewpoint of

those perceiving the behaviour.

According to Heap (2009: 72) ‘the most common method of assessing the extent of problems

caused by ASB is through the collection and analysis of public perception data.’ Heap noted

that this information can give an indication as to the types of problems which are causing

public concern and that are impacting negatively on communities (Harradine et al., 2004).

24

However, a number of definitional and measurement issues need to be addressed before

examining what affects such perceptions. Wood (2004) reports that this is due to the means

through which ASB is both counted and reported. For example, there could be multiple

reports regarding a single incident, especially if this incident impacted upon multiple people

within the same area. Heap (2009) further purported this is further complicated by tolerance

of behaviours. What is ASB to one may not be to another. Thus, some people may tolerate

certain forms of minor ASB, whereas others may not, leading to further discrepancies in what

is, and what is not reported.

According to the Office of the Deputy Prime Minister, the subjectivity of ASB is what

enables it to be governed by factors such as context, location, quality of life expectations and

community tolerance (ODPM, 2003). A definition with a wide scope can be a positive

mechanism (Heap, 2010) as it accounts for the consequences that multifarious types of ASB

have on quality of life. Conversely, such a wide-ranging definition can simultaneously

produce harmful consequences. Card and Ward, (1998: 108) note that ASB:

…is open to objection on the basis that it will catch conduct which is

unorthodox or unusual, eccentric or bizarre, but which, nevertheless is conduct

which ought not to be the subject of the legal process (Card and Ward,

1998:108).

It is possible that the definition of ASB could impinge upon the behaviour of otherwise ‘law-

abiding citizens’ if their behaviour is perceived to be ‘unconventional’ within a certain

context (Heap 2009). ASB can be influenced by factors such as our own level of tolerance

and behavioural expectations within differing contexts (Millie, 2008; Heap, 2010). Heap

(2010) pointed to the fact that individual incidents of ASB are dealt with on a case by case

basis and issues of subjectivity and tolerance have a different impact in different areas in

relation to the movement of people, a clashing of cultures and varying levels of tolerance.

Heap (2010: 48) purported that, ‘…thresholds of tolerance also determine what behaviours

are deemed anti-social, particularly in relation to the context in which the behaviour is

experienced.’ In a similar vein, Bannister and Kearns (2009) proposed that the setting is

important when considering the effect of tolerance on ASB perceptions:

25

…the socio-spatial situation in which we find ourselves both influences our

predisposition towards tolerance and determines a set of other drivers of the

tolerant response, so that our thresholds of tolerance are spatially specific and

spatially variant (p.182).

For example, some behaviour tolerated in an urban context may not be tolerated in a

suburban neighbourhood, or rural setting (Millie, 2006; 2016; Heap, 2010). According to

Bannister and Kearns (2009), the regulation of behaviours perceived as ‘inappropriate’ can

precipitate a cycle of intolerance. They noted that such attempts are counterproductive;

instead such methods further segregate others through highlighting social differences.

Furthermore, this can convey those social differences as being unacceptable and thus promote

intolerance rather than tolerance. Bannister and Kearns (2009) concluded that a paradox is

created whereby the values of some are prioritised over the values of others, and that ‘a

message of mutual tolerance’ is not conveyed (Bannister and Kearns, 2009: 174). Crawford

(2008: 758) lists ‘location, community tolerance and quality of life expectations’ as potential

influences on whether a behaviour is perceived as anti-social, and Payne (2003: 321) suggests

‘frequency, intensity, duration and whether or not it is considered appropriate, normal or

reasonable behaviour among a particular age group’.

A possible reason for increased attention on ASB may be the decreasing tolerance for

behaviours that might previously have been tolerated or even ignored (Berry, 2003). This

lack of tolerance could be the result of economic changes, and/or social cohesion in

neighbourhoods, which lead to greater mistrust and consequently an increased likelihood of

ambiguous or different behaviour being regarded as threatening (Burney, 2002; Sampson,

2009; Wilström, 2009, cited in Neary et al, 2013). It may be precisely because of the impact

of context that legislation pertaining to ASB (such as the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act) is

left open to interpretation. For example, spitting, associating with friends and family,

travelling on buses in a specific area, going into shops, attempting suicide, not keeping pigs

under control, being sarcastic, being on the street, and political protesting have all been

prohibited through use of these powers (Macdonald, 2006; Fyson and Yates, 2011). Despite

this flexibility, it has been argued that the elasticity of this definition of ASB only stretches

one way with measures vigorously utilized against marginalized groups - but less vehemently

utilized, if at all, against commercial conglomerates who flout planning laws or companies

that cause pollution (Sim, 2009) - both actions that could be conceived as anti-social.

26

If perceptions are important, then the question is whose view is more valid, the person

engaging in the behaviour or the person perceiving it as ASB? On the Home Office website

(2007, cited in Prior, 2009: 9) ASB was defined as ‘…any action that impacts on other people

in a negative way’. But where is the line drawn? For example, a classical music fan living

next to a professional violinist may positively encourage her neighbour to play music loudly

at any time of day, whilst she might consider the playing of club music by her other

neighbour negatively, and therefore define the latter as ASB. In this sense, the behaviour

displayed by each of the neighbours is the same: playing music loudly, but the impact comes

down to a matter of personal taste. Furthermore, her attempts to censure the neighbour who

enjoys playing club music would impact on the neighbour in a negative way (not being

permitted to engage in an activity that brings them pleasure), so is the classical music fan,

actually, the anti-social one? Of course, not all behaviour currently regarded as anti-social

should simply be tolerated, especially when the behaviour also includes serious criminal

offences (Mackenzie et al, 2010); but it is important to consider to what extent certain

behaviours should or could be tolerated.

The assumption that a behaviour, and therefore a person, can be classified as anti-social based

on the perception of others is likely to result in reduced acceptance of difference (Bannister,

2009) with people’s behaviours censured more and more to fit a norm. There is some

evidence that the term `anti-social behaviour` has been used to construct and reinforce social

behavioural norms. For instance, the Chartered Institute of Housing (CIH, 1995, cited in

Scott and Parker, 1998: 3) defined ASB as ‘…behaviour that opposes society’s norms and

accepted standards of behaviour.’ Definitions such as this assume that there is just one set of

accepted and agreed upon norms within society, and that everybody wants to live by these

norms (Scott and Parker, 1998). Indeed, the concept of ASB itself has the function of

favouring some forms of behaviour over others – it explicitly states that only particular

behaviours are welcome in society. It is therefore vitally important that there is inclusive

dialogue over what is and is not regarded as acceptable behaviour across geographical and

political boundaries. This will ensure that there is not one view on how people should behave

in society that is accepted above others.

By trying to keep behaviour to those actions or speech that negatively impact on any member

of a community, it is inevitable that an increasingly narrower range of behaviours will come

to be seen as `acceptable`. An alternative argument would be that actual intolerance of the

27

behaviour of others is itself anti-social. Rather than seeking to classify certain behaviours as

anti-social, society should be encouraged to analyse behaviours and responses to these

behaviours from a range of perspectives. Mackenzie et al, (2010) define this as `social

connectedness`. Arguments such as these validate attempts to define ASB more precisely, as

the consequences of measures to tackle ASB, such as ASBOs and more recent IPNAs, can

have serious and limiting effects on those whose behaviour has been deemed anti-social

(Millie et al, 2005).

It is important to remember that a key reason for introducing ASBOs was to allow a case to

be made against individuals whose actions would not have been sufficient to encounter the

full force of the criminal law (Millie, 2007). ASBOs gave police and communities the power

to criminalise behaviour where, although the individual’s actions may not be themselves

criminal, the length and breadth of them could be problematic: that is, ASBOs were used in

cases ‘where the overall impact of behaviour is far greater than the sum of its parts’

(Macdonald, 2006: 188). Thus, ASBOs resulted in people receiving punishments for

behaviours that would not be sufficient on its own to warrant the full force of the law, and

where decisions about whether the behaviours are anti-social or not were based on the

perceptions of that behaviour by other people.

Who are perceived as ASB perpetrators?

Another outcome of the impact perception can have on classification is the notion that ASB

can occur everywhere and anywhere (Mathews, 2003). In reality, however, there appear to be

certain groups living in certain geographies more likely to be perceived as responsible for, or

affected by, ASB by others. Therefore, when examining what ASB is, it seems pertinent to

consider who is being anti-social and who the victims are. There is a tendency to link ASB

with particular groups in society and, as noted, one such group is young people. For instance,

Brunger (2008) observes that in discussions on ASB in Northern Ireland, young people are

routinely identified as the key perpetrators and the group most in need of regulation. It is not

clear whether this is because young people are more likely to engage in ASB or because their

behaviour is more likely to be perceived as anti-social (Millie, 2010). Linking ASB with

particular groups can be stigmatising, which in turn may make it more likely that the

behaviour from that group will be regarded as anti-social (Neary et al, 2013). This argument

is supported by findings that adults in the UK are particularly concerned about young people

`hanging around` in their local area (Walker et al, 2009). This attitude is problematic as any

28

behaviour can have a number of different interpretations, and it is likely the more positive

ones – such as socialising, and spending time with friends - will be superseded by negative

views, essentially criminalising a legitimate activity (Waiton, 2008; Deucher, 2010, cited in

Neary et al, 2013). Legislation such as the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act allowed courts to

require a child to stop particular behaviours, behaviours that were not previously censored

(Tisdall, 2006). There is a risk that young people engaging in seemingly innocent activities

will increasingly be legislated against purely because there is the perception that they are

likely to be behaving anti-socially.

This suggestion has been reinforced by research that advocates an intergenerational approach

to tackle ASB (Moore and Statham, 2006). Moore and Statham (2006) recognized that acts

classed as anti-social, such as youths ‘hanging around’, or what they termed ‘youth specific

acts’, could attract reports biased against a younger demographic. They acknowledged the

social construction of ASB, that whilst young people in a group may appear intimidating to

members of the public, gathering in a group is not necessarily an anti-social activity.

Wood (2004) examined the relationship between such perceptions of ASB and reported

incidents. According to Wood, what ASB is can be determined by geographical location and

social background. Yet the majority of respondents in his study did not report ASB to the

police. Wood concluded that this may be due to a belief that contacting the police would not

achieve anything or that there was ambivalence about where these ‘anti-social acts or

behaviours’ stood in relation to legislation and social norms.

In conclusion, what is perceived as anti-social is entirely subjective (Brown, 2004). There is

no perfectly lucid legal definition of which behaviours are anti-social with boundaries

between ASB and criminality often blurred. This creates issues for those on the frontline

tackling ASB, as it is up to personal discretion for those utilising legal tools to combat

behaviour perceived to be anti-social. ASB is most likely to be defined in terms of how the

behaviour is interpreted by people other than the perpetrator. As Brown (2004: 206) has

contended, ‘anti-social behaviour is purely about behaviour’ and is a ‘triumph of

behaviourism’, but is all about others’ perceptions of behaviour rather than the underlying

motivations. However, aiming to tackle the underlying perceptions about what ASB is and

promoting tolerance may provide a fresh solution to tackling ASB.

29

Alternatives methods for tackling ASB

Broadly speaking, there are two key approaches to tackling ASB. These are: tackling the

ASB directly through punishment/attempted change in the perpetrator, or tackling the ASB

through changing how the behaviour itself is perceived. Since the New Labour government of

the late nineties, governments in the UK have very much adopted the first approach in their

attempts to reduce ASB. More specifically, there has been an emphasis on ASB as a moral

wrong to be punished and that perpetrators require moral improvement. Tony Blair, for

example, emphasised theories of moral decline in explaining the root cause of ASB (Etzioni,

1993, as cited in McLaughlin et al, 2001), and argued that the way to tackle ASB was through

raising moral standards. In January 2006, the New Labour government launched the Respect

Action Plan (Respect Task Force, 2006; Bannister et al., 2006; Millie, 2009). This document

outlined an extensive and wide-ranging set of strategies designed to confront and, ideally, to

eradicate ASB. These strategies included legislative reform, policing initiatives, parenting

programmes, schooling initiatives and youth activities. The Respect Action Plan aimed,

through its constituent parts, to ‘enforce a modern culture of respect’ (2006: 3). Respect is

briefly and loosely defined as ‘an expression of something that people intuitively

understand’, comprising ‘values that almost everyone in this country shares’, ‘which the

majority of people want’ and that ‘relies on a shared understanding and clear rules and is

strengthened by people acting together to tackle problems and improve their lives’ (Respect

Task Force, 2006: 5). ASB is described as ‘the most visible sign of disrespect’ and portrayed

as impacting upon the majority, whilst associated with the activities and behaviour of a

minority. The notion of instilling society with a stronger sense of cultural respect was one

step further than simply punishing ASB and took ASB policy into the realm of moral

philosophy. However, the actions taken to achieve this respect were, once again, portrayed as

something to be enforced to combat moral decline (Millie, 2010). It was contended that the

restoration of law and order could be attained via remoralising families to self-regulate their

behaviour and by building cohesive communities. Crime and ASB were deemed morally

wrong, and the New Labour government was to take a no-nonsense approach to tackling

them (McLaughlin et al., 2001).

It was claimed that, in order to tackle ASB, a 'cultural shift' back towards a more traditional,

respectful 'British society' (Blair, 2005, cited in Flint and Nixon, 2006) was needed. It was

proposed that this could be achieved by actively promoting those values which were believed

30

could reduce ASB, such as being polite, considerate and thoughtful (Field, 2003, cited in

Flint and Nixon, 2006). Whilst New Labour placed much emphasis on developing respect

within society, it was less clear if, or how, one would go about doing such a thing (Millie,

2010). The subsequent Conservative–led coalition government carried on with this view of

ASB through its emphasis on the 'broken society' (Millie, 2010) that needed to be fixed

through the notion of 'big society'. The big society perpetuated the view that tackling ASB

requires an emphasis on working together to reduce unwanted behaviours.

Thus, ASB is situated within the individual or groups performing the behaviour, and

perpetrators of ASB are not acting in a way that is 'British' or morally right. Given such a

view, it is logical that attempts to tackle ASB involve trying to 'eliminate' that behaviour at

the individual level (e.g. through the use of ASBOs or their replacement) and the societal

level (e.g. through civic education). The message sent out by this approach is clear: only

certain types of behaviour are acceptable within a ‘respectful’ or `big society` and people

performing unacceptable behaviours will be punished. Indeed, the initial introduction of

ASBOs was the result of the belief that 'something had gone fundamentally wrong with

British society' (Millie, 2010: 8) which had led to the perceived increase in ASB; and that the

only way to tackle that was to try to make everyone conform to society's behavioural norms

and standards.

A second, less mainstream approach to tackling ASB takes an opposing view. It is different

in two key ways. Firstly, it advocates tolerance as a key strategy in reducing ASB. Secondly,

it does not attempt to put standards on people's behaviour. Sandercock (2003, cited in Millie,

2010), for example, suggests that it would be helpful to adopt a stance of 'togetherness is

difference', an approach she terms `cosmopolitan urbanism.` This means that it would

become accepted and even expected that behaviour different to one's own, or society's norms,

will exist, but that this is not necessarily a negative thing. Rather, it is a consequence of large

numbers of people living alongside each other. This is echoed by Mackenzie et al. (2010)

who promote the idea of 'social connectedness'. They argue that ASB could be reduced

through increased attempts to view people's behaviour from other points of view. The

rationale for this approach is that consideration of other people’s perspectives will lead to

greater understanding within and between groups and communities (Millie, 2010). This

would, in turn, mean that people are better equipped to judge the behaviour of others as social

31

or anti-social (Mackenzie et al. 2010). This is especially important when you consider the

role perception plays in government adopted definitions of ASB.

This notion of tolerance is often linked to acceptance and respect of others (Sennett, 2003). In

a similar vein, Millie (2010: 10) suggests that one way of reducing ASB is to accept that, for

example, ‘...not all youth (mis)behaviour given the ASB badge is necessarily problematic’. In

this way, this view is not suggesting that all behaviour is tolerated; rather it is suggesting that

some be tolerated and accepted. Thus, the way this approach would tackle ASB is by

redefining what is and is not perceived as anti-social.

Earlier approaches to tackle ASB, such as those included in the 1998 Crime and Disorder Act

and the 2003 Anti-Social Behaviour Act focused on punishment rather than promoting

tolerance. The more recent 2014 Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Act was no

different. The myriad range of punitive enforcement measures which have been utilized

against ASB have included informal or formal warning letters, verbal warnings, referral to

Youth Inclusion Programmes, Parenting Contracts, Acceptable Behaviour Contracts (ABCs),

Parenting Orders, Child Safety Orders, Curfew Orders, Dispersal Orders, Individual Support

Orders, custodial penalties and tenancy enforcement actions (Pitts, 2005). Another punitive

measure was eliminating disrespect through ‘naming and shaming’. This was the idea that

inducing emotions such as shame and guilt will negatively impact on someone’s image. This

implies shaming them into not repeating negative behaviours, such as ASB, in the future

(Kaufman, 1993). Conversely, it was claimed that this could have the opposite impact and

incite further, even more serious, forms of ASB due to the perpetrator’s withdrawal from

society. This would be due to emotions such as angst and rage which could amplify incidents

of negative behaviours (Gaskell, 2008).

Family interventions

More supportive measures to tackle ASB came with the introduction of Family Intervention

Projects (FIPs) (Hodgkinson and Tilley, 2011). FIPs were first introduced during January

2006 as part of the Respect Action Plan (Respect Task Force, 2006b) to offer a range of

individualized support services to the most ‘anti-social families’ responsible for a significant

amount of ASB towards neighbours and a strain on local authority resources. According to

White et al. (2008), these types of families were those with the greatest need for support. The

FIP was later replaced by the Conservative coalition government’s Troubled Families

32

Programme (TFP, Bate, 2017). This was a targeted intervention for families with multiple

problems, including crime, anti-social behaviour, unemployment, mental health issues,

domestic abuse and truancy (Bate, 2017).

FIPs aimed to address root causes of ASB that enforcement-only approaches were not

adequately tackling (White et al., 2008). White et al. (2008) further reported that early

outcomes from the FIP intervention were encouraging. Families’ current housing situations

had improved in addition to a decrease in the risk of families engaging in ASB. Positive

impacts further included a reduction in the burden on local services working with challenging

families. However, White et al. did note that it is less clear what happens following exit from

a FIP - although Nixon et al. (2008) claimed that the positive outcomes were sustained later

down the line. Further support came from Wenham (2017) who claimed that considerable

improvements were evident in all key areas of the FIP’s work. However, White et al. (2008)

noted that the conclusions were deduced from very small samples. These samples, evaluators

themselves claimed, were biased and had no control groups to compare outcomes (Gregg,

2010).

Gregg heavily criticised the FIPs claiming that they targeted only ‘socially inadequate

families’ (2010: 14) and misrepresented the families involved – most of whom had

‘significant mental and physical health problems and learning disabilities’ (Gregg, 2010: 14).

Gregg boldly stated that the FIPs demonstrated ‘the nightmare place to which populist

political rhetoric and ‘policy-based evidence’ can deliver us.’ (2010: 16).

Recent research by Cate et al. (2016) has claimed that interventions are less effective if they

are solely criminogenic, that the promotion of positive behaviour is as important as the

reduction of anti-social behaviour. Similar to addressing public perceptions of ASB, Cate et

al. (2016) contended that several key factors should be considered when attempting to

intervene on ASB:

…anti-social behaviour is associated not only with individual vulnerabilities

but also social adversity and structural issues; early identification of at-risk

young people is not fool-proof and risks stigmatising and creating self-

fulfilling prophecies; harsh punishment is rarely effective. More broadly, anti-

social behaviour in general and some specific forms of anti-social behaviour

33

are not the social issue they are portrayed to be. With the exception of

vandalism, most acts of anti-social behaviour impact few people outside the

peer group. (Curtis, C. 2016).

Cate argues that incorrect assumptions, and the resulting policies and interventions, run the

risk of being at best ineffective and at worst harmful to the people at whom they are targeted.

To summarise, approaches to tackling ASB differ both in terms of the proposed underlying

causes of ASB and the measures taken to reduce it. The dominant view amongst recent

governments is that ASB is the result of a lack of respect at the individual level and a moral

decline at the societal level. Therefore, attempts to deal with ASB focus on punishing the

perpetrators of the behaviour. The view adopted by some academics (Bannister et al. 2006,

Millie, 2006; 2009) tends to run counter to the government approaches. For example,

Bannister et al. (2006) and Millie (2006) noted that it may be an issue of perception towards

behavioural expectations and intolerance. Millie contended that perceptions of ASB could

reflect a lack of tolerance and understanding of the behaviour of others, and through

misguided attempts to enforce moral standards on behaviour. Similarly, Bannister et al.

(2006) claim that it is contradictory to try to enforce a culture of respect and civility through

zero-tolerance approaches. Similarly, to achieve a more respectful society there must be

engagement between tolerance, civility and respect. Bannister at al. (2006) noted that,

fundamentally, the behavioural expectations of the majority and more powerful, in society

dictate what is perceived as acceptable. Anything that is not in tandem with these

domineering beliefs may be labelled as anti-social and thus deemed uncivil behaviour.

ASB and deprivation

As noted, ASB has been described as a prevalent issue within disadvantaged areas. Certain

groups of people are often perceived to be more anti-social than others. The media has cited

examples of neighbour problems in council estates (Scott and Parkey, 1998) and ASB has

been portrayed as a symptom, metaphor and scapegoat for the perceived decline of

neighbourhoods. The media has also been described as complicit in contributing to

influencing perceptions of ASB rates in such areas (Mackenzie et al., 2010). The mass media

has used derogatory terminology, for example in television shows entitled ‘Neighbours from

Hell’, portraying negative images and bad or excessive habits of the working-class

34

family(McCarthy, 2011). Political rhetoric has also used similar narratives. It has been argued

that this coincided with New Labour’s stigmatisation of single-parent mothers, whilst the

family was constructed as the facilitator of ASB through the capacity of such homes to

produce future criminal offspring (Respect Task Force, 2006; Gillies, 2008).

The notion of a bias against the lower classes in ASB research has also been reported (Sadler,

2008). According to Sadler (2008), research investigating ASB has historically often focused

on areas perceived to be troublesome, marginalised and criminalised. However not all

disadvantaged communities experience ASB problems to the same level (Flint et al., 2007).

There has also been a feeling of persecution amongst young people that are only exacerbated

through the use of ASB legislation (Sadler, 2008). The actual impact of such tools which

focus on the vulnerable, such as young people, may inadvertently accentuate negative

behaviours, including those considered anti-social. If ASB is perceived as a poor person’s, or

young person’s problem, then the underlying moral aspects of the behaviour may be missed,

which may take the focus to a broader population.

Another line of research has investigated heightened anxiety and concern in social housing

estates. According to Millie (2008) poor communities may be more susceptible to claims of

ASB. It has been argued that this may be the result of fallout from unintentional policy

developments, particularly planning and housing legislation (Hancock, 2001). Hancock

(2001) stipulated that much research has suggested the links between disorder and

neighbourhood areas can be altered and mediated by factors such as: residents’ tolerance,

costs and benefits of moving, the current condition and availability of amenities or local

services, as well as the existence of political or economic resources. Furthermore, according

to Clapham and Kintrea (1998), allocation policies within the public sector concentrated

disadvantaged households in unpopular locations whilst the economically advantaged were

housed in popular areas. If ASB is regarded as associated with poor neighbourhoods and

communities, especially vulnerable individuals within these areas, then there is the risk that

some behaviours may be misidentified as anti-social (Millie, 2007a). As Burney (2005)

contended, the congregating of young people in certain areas can be deemed anti-social but

this is a quintessential behaviour that is part of growing up. More concerning is the idea that

individuals with mental health issues or learning difficulties could end up criminalised or

entangled within ASB enforcement methods (Millie, 2007b).

35

It has been claimed that areas of bad housing in Britain have existed since industrialisation

and were associated with the mass migration to the towns and cities (Papps, 1998). The

growth of housing provision evolved from private rental to social housing, where slums were

considered ‘problematic’ areas, or ‘problem estate’ (Papps, 1998). Crawford and Flint (2009)

have stated that the preoccupation with ASB and disorder has recent origins from the context

of social housing, suggesting that this is the breeding ground of ASB. These ‘problem estates’

have been utilised by many to describe the areas of social housing believed to be ‘bad’ due

to: a fear of crime, poor housing conditions, vulnerable tenants or difficult tenants in addition

to instances of ASB (Papps, 1998).

The stigma attached to living in areas perceived to be ‘bad’ tends to precede incidents of

discrimination, such as when an individual from these areas attempt to attain employment

(Reynolds, 1986, as cited in Papps, 1998). It has further been argued that this label

accentuates the ASB tag as something that is lived up to in these areas and generates even

more surveillance and logging of anti-social or deviant acts (Armstrong and Wilson, 1973).

One study investigating concerns about ASB and crime has suggested that residents, who live

in deprived neighbourhoods, or areas perceived to be disadvantaged, are more liable to be

worried and anxious about crime (Kullberg et al., 2009). Egan et al. (2012) have claimed

there is an association between perceptions of young people behaving anti-socially and other

residents’ physical health in areas believed to be disadvantaged. They further stated that

people, particularly the elderly, who do not feel positive regarding the area they live in, are

more liable to identify youth behaviours as anti-social.

If ASB is framed as a social malaise implicitly and explicitly linked to areas perceived to be

poor, troubled locations, then it is further detracting from ASB being an issue of perception

rather than purely social deprivation. Another explanation for why ASB may have become

associated with deprivation is the notion that government welfare provision and approach to

social justice have become more punitive (Brown, 2012).

The coalition government in 2010 also brought austerity cuts alongside the promotion of the

‘Big Society’ as the solution to any social malaise (Levitas, 2012). Those living in

disadvantaged areas became further marginalized and disadvantaged through these economic

cuts (Levitas, 2012). If areas perceived in be in decline, deprived and physically dilapidated

are perceived as the catalysts for ASB, then further punishing those from such areas, both via

36

austerity cuts and the criminalization of youths through intolerance of behaviours perceived

to be ‘anti-social’, then ASB could continue to remain a ‘poor’ person’s problem, rather than

a moral issue affecting everyone. As Boyd (2006) has claimed, questions must be asked about

the nature of civility within society, including the source of it and how it should be cultivated.

It has an important function in modern society and the moral virtues that derive from it. This

emphasizes the importance of civility in helping the moral regeneration that UK policy aimed

to recreate. It is important to understand that ASB is not simply an issue for the poor, but also

a moral issue for all; that moral equality should diffuse throughout all groups within society.

Crimes of everyday life

The relationship between ASB and the everyday morality of all groups within society merits

further study and is considered in more detail in the following chapter. For example, if

everyday morality underlies ASB, it is important to understand how and when it might

influence someone to behave antisocially, and how it affects whether a behaviour is deemed

anti-social or not. Drawing on criminology and moral philosophy would allow deeper

understanding of the roots of everyday morality, the function ASB might serve in different

situations, and the normative factors that might determine if a behaviour is deemed anti-social

or not. Furthermore, such an approach might provide insight into how people make decisions

about how to act, and how to interpret the actions of others.

According to Karstedt and Farrall (2006: 1) there are well established notions of ‘crimes in

the suites’ and ‘crimes in the streets’. They contend that both of these concepts are under-

explored. In their research, everyday crimes and nuisances emerge within the terrain of the

crimes and unfair practices that are committed at the kitchen table, on the settee and from

home computers, from desks and call centres, at cash points in supermarkets or in restaurants,

and in interactions with others. They are committed by those who think of themselves as

respectable citizens, and some who may definitely reject the labels of ‘criminals’ and ‘crime’

for themselves and their actions (Karstedt and Farrall, 2006). These types of crime fall into a

grey zone of legality and morality. They include, amongst other things: jumping red lights;

not paying TV licence fees; making false insurance claims; claiming for refunds one is not

entitled to; requesting and paying ‘cash in hand’ in order to avoid taxes; claiming benefits

and subsidies that one is not entitled to. Not all behaviours comprised in this zone are

formally illegal. It has been claimed that these behaviours are frequently referred to as ‘sharp,

shady or unfair practices, but all are generally seen as morally dubious, both by those who

37

feel victimized and by those who admit to having engaged in some of them.’ (Karstadt and

Farrall, 2006: 1011). These types of behaviours have been described as ‘crimes of everyday

life’.

Interestingly, Karstedt and Farrall (2006) attempted to explore why these types of behaviours,

illegal, unethical or both, are prevalent in society and how they may convey the moral state of

society - even more so, than for instance violent street crimes. Their explanation as to why

some people may commit these ‘everyday crimes’ relates to their willingness to take

advantage of presented opportunities. Karstedt and Farrall (2006) concluded that citizens

discuss justifications and methods of committing crime that can create a moral clime that

encourages this behaviour. Thus, people’s behaviour, in relation to ‘everyday crimes’ that

straddle the line between more serious offending behaviour and those which ‘fall into a grey

zone of legality and morality’ (2006: 1011). Karstedt and Farrall (2006) give the example of

opportunities which people take advantage of for deceit, for example, lying to get their

children into the schools which they desire, should an opportunity for deceit arise. They did,

however, note that these behaviours are not necessarily immoral by definition. In the eyes of

those who may evade paying their TV license, make false tax or insurance claims and behave

in an anti-social manner, they may not perceive their behaviour as immoral.

In conclusion, some behaviours may be reflective of deprivation. But, as Karstadt and Farrall

(2006) suggest, there are also ‘crimes of everyday life’ that are ‘par for the course’ and are

not restricted to the most deprived in society. It may be that certain contexts may induce a

‘moral clime’ that encourages behaviour that would normally not be accepted. Similarly,

ASB may be behaviour that is stereotypically perceived as an issue of the young, poor and

deprived in society; however, those who are not from deprived areas are also capable of being

anti-social. The next section discusses official data on ASB, considering issues of measuring

and reporting ASB.

Official Data on ASB

A government report into findings from the 2005/06 British Crime Survey (Upson, 2006)

examined perceptions and experiences of ASB. It was acknowledged that there was a

relationship between fear and perceived disorderly behaviour. Perceptions of ASB were

measured from seven questions: namely, problems with noisy neighbours or loud parties,

38

teenagers and young people hanging around, rubbish or litter, vandalism and graffiti, people

using or dealing drugs, drunkenness, and finally abandoned cars. According to Upson (2006)

in the year prior to 2004/05, 1 in 6 people had perceived high levels of ASB within their local

community. The dominant type of ASB was perceived as young people hanging around and

littering. The report claimed that 31 per cent of the population (from 16 and over) believed

this was a ‘very’ or ‘fairly big’ problem within their areas. More recently in the Crime Survey

for England and Wales (CSEW) (ONS, 2015) 28 per cent of respondents had experienced or

witnessed ASB within their local area, in the year ending June 2015. More specifically, 10

per cent of adults had experienced or seen drink related ASB and 8 per cent had witnessed

groups congregating. Around one in ten believed that there was a high level of ASB within

their local area. The report was concluded by the claim that most ASB indicators have

decreased since the 2002/03 BCS.

Upson’s (2006) report claimed 53 per cent of people did not think ASB was a problem in

their area (Millie, 2009). According to the ONS (2013), during the 2011/12 period, 82 per

cent of people who had witnessed drink-related ASB reported that this had little or no effect

on their daily routine. In addition, 76 per cent of respondents who had experienced or

witnessed groups congregating around streets reported that this too had little or no impact on

their daily routine. It can be suggested from this that ASB - in particular the most commonly

experienced in an area - may not always be perceived as problematic and have an impact on

witnesses’ daily lives.

One possible explanation as to why some ASB is construed as not serious enough to report

may be the context-specific nature of ASB, which may determine whether a behaviour is

perceived as anti-social in certain areas (Whitehead, Stockdale and Razzu, 2003; MacDonald,

2006; Millie, 2008). For example, Millie (2008) has suggested that within certain contexts,

for example urban areas, the way individuals use urban spaces are mostly determined by our

understandings and expectation of others’ behaviours. Similar research into perceptions of

ASB by Farrow and Prior (2006) claimed that potential explanations for low-levels of

complaints in urban areas could be due to different cultural expectations of behaviour. There

may be greater acceptance of behaviour that is generally deemed anti-social, and within local

communities there may be a reduced need for complaints as problems are dealt with

differently. Another possible reason was that there may be poor knowledge in terms of

knowing who to complain to or there may be low levels of trust between people and local

39

agencies. Therefore, data collection on ASB may also be influenced by context and location,

as these two factors impact on the behavioural expectations and norms of a particular area.

It was reported that there were two million incidents of ASB in the year ending September

2014 (ONS, 2015). The number of recorded ASB incidences, recorded by the police and the

British Transport Police, had decreased by ten percent when compared against the 2013

figures. A decline in ASB was also reported in both the 2007/2008 and 2011/2012 records.

These were consistent with recent trends in the total amount of police recorded crime (ONS,

2015). According to police figures (ONS, 2015) 67 per cent of recorded ASB is categorized

as nuisance, 27 per cent is personal ASB, and 6 per cent is environmental ASB. To

summarise, official measures of ASB appear to have been dropping in Britain. However,

there are critical points to consider regarding data collection methods. The remaining

question to answer is why recorded levels of ASB have decreased in the UK and is this

related to changing perceptions or tolerance of ASB?

The level of subjective interpretation of what constitutes ASB could be influencing ASB

figures. Edwards (2013) has claimed that Home Office guidelines (2004) on what behaviours

fall under each heading are heavily influenced by interpretation, inadvertently generating

much variation in terms of recorded incidents. Edwards (2013) cited the example of an

incident of ‘vehicle related nuisance’ - which may be a life-threatening criminal offence such

as setting a vehicle alight. However, this could also be low-level irritating behaviour such as

cycling on pedestrian footpaths. Further problems such as definitional issues and overlapping

categories of ASB, including different perceptions of recorded ASB between different

agencies, are a challenge for government policy on ASB and impact on all aspects of data

collection (Matthews and Briggs, 2008). For example, Heap (2009) notes it is not clear what

should be measured and which agency, or agencies, are responsible for data collection (see

also Whitehead et al., 2003). Heap further reported that issues defining and measuring ASB

are further compounded by the blurred relationship between ASB and crime. For example,

Innes (2004: 345) suggests that many people have trouble in establishing ‘a clear distinction

between crime and anti-social behaviour when constructing judgements about levels of risk in

an area’.

Despite falls in official crime rates and ASB levels, members of society maintain the

perception that ASB and crime are high. The question emerging from this is why people

40

maintain this view. According to Bremner et al. (2008) there is a gap between measurable

incidents of crime, and the subjective public perceptions of criminality. Bremner et al. (2008)

contend that it is probable that the social construction of crime involves a diverse range of

concerns about social problems in local communities, including ASB such as littering on

streets, broken windows or a simple ‘lack of respect’. The importance of perceptions in

terms of what people believe constitutes ASB has been noted (Mackenzie et al., 2010). It

seems this also applies to crime. How these perceptions or beliefs of a rise in ASB are linked

to a perceived moral decline has also been reported (Millie, 2010). It is possible that one of

the reason for changing figures and trends for ASB could be linked to perceptions within

neighbourhoods as to what constitutes ASB. This could be a contributing factor mediating the

level of reported incidents of ASB.

The perception that ASB is rising was evidenced by the 2011/12 CSEW (ONS, 2013),

according to which almost of a third of individuals had experienced, or been witness to, some

form of ASB in the previous twelve months. Forty-nine per cent of participants believed ASB

was increasing, and 15 per cent had perceived high levels of ASB in their local community

during 2011/12. This was despite statistics from the previous year giving no indication of a

rise in ASB. An underlying explanation for why perceptions are not in tandem with reported

incidences of ASB has been attributed to the interpretive and definitional concerns of what

ASB is (as outlined at the start of this chapter). According to the ONS (2013) the distinction

between an incident of crime and an incident of ASB is not as clear as it needs to be.

According to the ONS, there are multiple occasions when ASB could be also designated

criminal by law. However, these differences in what is crime and what is ASB are something

that the public may overlook (ONS, 2013).

Conclusions

This chapter has provided an account of definitional issues with ASB, and the history of talk

of ASB - from early political discussions to recent debate on tackling ASB through new

legislative tools such as the IPNA (Home Office, 2013). Most talk of ASB has emerged from

the realms of politics, the media, social housing and the public. There are issues in clearly

defining what ASB is, and this was reported to be heavily influenced by perception and

context. This is clearly problematic. First, the role perception plays in determining ASB may

lead to more behaviours being deemed anti-social. Second, the imprecise definitions of ASB,

41

and the power of non-state actors (such as social housing providers) to use punitive legal

tools means that previously ‘non-criminal’ behaviour is now being criminalised (Brown,

2004). Essentially, people are being criminalised for actions which are not sufficient to be

punished by the criminal law. An emphasis on ASB also ignores issues of ‘social

connectedness’ (Mackenzie et al., 2010). A number of people with competing views,

expectations and values all inhabit the same space, particularly in urban environments, and

tolerating behaviour, rather than seeking to condemn it, may be the more positive solution to

dealing with that which is perceived as ‘different’.

Previous interventions aimed at tackling ASB involved punitive legislation, regulation of

behaviour in poverty stricken families or areas, and the attempted enforcement of respect,

morality and civility. The UK official rates of ASB have been decreasing, however public

fears remain high.

The possible link between ASB and everyday morality was introduced, with particular

reference to political talk of respect and a broken society. This is examined in more detail in

the next chapter which considers how the behavioural expectations of people relate to their

sense of morality, and the influence this has on their perceptions of others’ behaviours.

42

Chapter 2.

Anti-Social Behaviour and Everyday Morality

Introduction

ASB has been framed by UK governments as an issue related to a lack of respect and to

moral decline. Brown (2004: 204) has claimed that, ‘although crime is ubiquitous, anti-social

behaviour is deemed by the government to occur principally in social housing areas’. As

highlighted in Chapter 1, ASB is often presented as a poor person’s problem, and not

something that is prevalent within society as a whole. As a result, talk about ASB and moral

decline has tended to focus on those aspects of everyday morality that affect the more

disadvantaged - such as discussions about aggressive behaviour perpetrated on social housing

estates - and ignores those behaviours that are equally anti-social, but more likely to affect

economically advantaged groups, such as tax avoidance.

It is important to understand how and when moral choices might influence someone to

behave antisocially and how everyday morality affects whether a behaviour is perceived to be

anti-social or not. Studying ASB from the perspective of moral philosophy would allow

deeper understanding of the moral roots of perceived ASB, whilst studying it from a

criminological viewpoint could illuminate the purpose that ASB might serve in different

situations, and the normative factors that might determine if a behaviour is deemed anti-social

or not. Thus, looking at ASB through both criminological and philosophical lens could

provide insights into how people make decisions about how to act, and how to interpret the

actions of others. This may also help inform current understandings of what ASB is to

different people in different contexts. It may further elucidate any links between everyday

morality and ASB. Therefore, this chapter examines the relationship between anti-social

behaviour and everyday morality.

The question of morality, what it is and where it comes from has been a concern for

philosophers for a very long time (see e.g. Frankena, 1966). Frankena (1966) stated that

43

asking the question ‘what is morality’ presents a complex task as it is an ambiguous and

vague question. He stated that one such method of addressing this is to answer the question

‘When is an individual, group, or society to be said to have a morality or a moral action-

guide?’ (1966: 688). Frankena (1966) iterated that this may be answered through multifarious

methods (singular or pluralistic concept theories) yet acknowledged that ‘We cannot try to

describe or discuss them all now’ (1966: 688). Building on from Frankenna’s observations, it

is not possible within this scope of this chapter to cover thousands of years of moral

philosophy. Thus, this thesis is selective in focusing on particular aspects of moral

philosophy pertinent to everyday morality. It is further important to acknowledge that other

approaches in moral philosophy may have led to different conclusions in this study. This is

considered in the concluding chapter of the thesis.

It was claimed by Darwin (1871, as cited in DeScioli and Kurzban, 2009) that morality is a

derivation of sympathy which originated as a social instinct found in animals. This sympathy

evolved into morality through a process called group-selection whereby those groups

possessing morality out-competed those without morality. However, this theory could not

account for the variety of moral rules nor why humans believe people should be punished

when these rules are violated (DeScioli and Kurzban, 2009). According to Solomon and

Higgins (2010) a person’s morality is responsible for regulating their behaviour. It ‘sets limits

to our desires, and our actions. It tells us what is permitted and what is not...It tells us what

we ought to do and what we ought not to do’ (Solomon and Higgins, 2010: 257). According

to Bernard Gert (2004), although such moral rules and ideals are often identified constituents

of morality, these alone do not define morality.

Others have asked whether morality can even be defined, a point raised by Skorupski (1993),

who proposed that to define it is impossible, and that the closest that can be got to a definition

is defining its 'sense', its general purpose, but not its precise meaning. One way to try to

understand moral perspectives is to consider the rules or codes that individuals adhere to.

This is a deontological approach to morality, and is the perspective adopted within this thesis.

In the next section the notion of ‘common’ morality is looked at in more detail. A common

morality is a system in which such rules and ideals are entrenched. The focus for the

remainder of this chapter is how morality relates to ASB, exploring notions of civility, moral

relativism, issues of defining morality, Kantian ethics and the social contexts of morality.

44

Common morality

The notion of common morality shares many features with the term ‘everyday morality’ that I

have used in the current study. For example, Bhaskarjit (2007) claimed that in the history of

moral philosophy there has been a common trend to use the phrase ‘common morality’ or

‘common-sense morality’ in reference to every-day, ordinary values and norms. He iterated

that philosophers tend to use this term when they compare or contrast the common view with

the implications of ethical theories for genuine understanding of morality. Bhaskarjit

acknowledged that morality is a complex phenomenon, the origin of which has been traced

back to a diverse range of principles that underpin our everyday common beliefs and

attitudes. He purported that people cannot deny that common sense moral intuitions

underlining beliefs and attitudes constitute the foundation of everyday human practice -

although it has been argued that what constitutes common morality and its contents has been

obscured by the imprecise scope of the term (Bhaskarjit, 2007). One point that remains

consistent is that common sense intuition is an intrinsic element of morality. However,

Bhaskarjit (2007) acknowledged that there has not been an all-encompassing understanding

of ‘common morality’ within a systematic framework for a theory of morality1. Despite this,

Bhaskarjit has reported on a few contemporary definitions that aim to incorporate various

conceptions of what constitutes common morality.

1. A first definition noted was proposed by Tom Beauchamp (2003: 260) who stated that

‘common morality’ is ‘the set of norms shared by all persons committed to the

objectives of morality… it is applicable to all persons in all places, and all human

conduct is rightly judged by its standard’.

2. A second definition noted by Bhaskarjit (2007) was by Samuel Scheffler (1992: 122,

as cited in Van den Hoven, 2006) who believed common morality is ‘a conviction so

widely shared in our culture, and so deeply entrenched, that outside of philosophy it is

scarcely ever articulated, let alone explicitly challenged’.

3. Bhaskarjit also mentioned a third definition by Bernard Gert (2004: 1): ‘Common

morality is the moral system that thoughtful people use, usually implicitly, when they

make moral decisions and judgments. It is the only guide to behavior affecting others

that all rational persons understand and upon which they can all agree.’

1 This point links with the current study’s aim to develop knowledge of what is everyday morality.

45

These definitions suggest that a common morality is something that we all share and have in

common. However, Bhaskarjit (2007) argues that, whether common morality is ‘a moral

system’ or ‘a set of shared norms’ or ‘a widely shared conviction’, the key point to be drawn

from these definitions is that common morality entails an ordinary ethical standard which

corresponds to the minimal moral sentiments of every morally serious person. He further

contended that these sentiments are perceived as a self-approved setup by which we evaluate

and characterize our everyday dealings. First, he concluded that there are norms and

intuitions which are spontaneously shared by all morally serious agents. Second, these are not

specifically theoretical in nature; instead, they are comprehended as simple beliefs, rules,

ideals and basic attitudes of moral deliberation. Third, these norms are self-established by the

way we each construct our ethical convictions, a normative framework that each individual

possesses who is capable of taking moral issues seriously.

Finally, within this moral system, there is a common, collective consciousness that is innate.

This moral system forms the fulcrum of everyday living, for which minimal understanding of

morality is a prerequisite. Based on these definitions and the previous understandings of what

constitutes common morality, the current study suggests a similar approach in

conceptualising what is everyday morality.

Of course, the existence of a common morality is not a recent innovation, although, the

framework for understanding what it is and the studying of common morality is still

relatively new (Bhaskarjit, 2007). This point was bolstered by Beauchamp (2003) who

contended that there is one universal common-sense morality and many more theories of

common morality. Gert (2004) and Beauchamp (2003) both have a deontological

understanding of the structure of common morality which is portrayed by rules, principles

and ideas. This is practised by all individuals throughout the world and the character of

common morality is in fact a universal concept.

Of course, relativists might take a different view, something that is considered in more detail

later in this chapter. For instance, others have argued that common morality is expressed via

our day-to-day moral beliefs and in a looser sense, rather than being explicitly structured in a

certain way on a global scale. This notion was espoused by Turner (2003) who claimed that

the beliefs and norms that underpin common morality may not be universal. They may

46

instead be very much localised within their own right. More specifically, Turner would

contend that something could be construed as ‘common’, not just because it is an

overwhelmingly shared and practiced norm within a society, but also due to reasonable

grounds underlying such a belief. For example, a particular norm may be encouraged,

through approval from others, from any person in a society. This perspective advocates a

more relative approach to understanding everyday morality.

Previous research into morality has attempted to clarify the common morality that guides our

everyday actions and beliefs and how we meaningfully discuss and understand everyday

moral dilemmas and problems (Bhaskarjit, 2007). The perspectives of Gert (2004) and

Beauchamp (2003) have paved the way in terms of providing a framework that can be used to

understand common morality. For instance, Gert (2004) claimed that common morality

provides a framework that enables individuals to integrate information relating to:

Their own view on the scope of morality,

Rankings of the potential harms or benefits of behaviours,

The potential positive or negative ramifications of everyone knowing that a certain

violation is allowed or not allowed, and

The interpretation of rules.

It is this systemic framework that enables individuals to navigate their everyday lives in terms

of moral decisions and judgments which have been incorporated into their moral framework.

Gert (2005) further proposed that one universal feature of morality is, despite all the

variations of it, that anyone who can be judged by moral ideals understands the behaviours

that morality discourages, requires, promotes and encourages. Consequently, moral

judgements can be made about any rational individual, making morality a universal

phenomenon; and what appear to be different moral systems and specifications are simply

variations of a universal, core moral system (Gert, 2005). According to Gert, a common

morality ‘has as a necessary feature that it be a public system that applies to all rational

creatures’ (Gert, 2004: 6). For example, for Gert the following rules would be universal: do

not cause pain, keep your promises, do not kill, and so on. However, there are exceptions to

these rules dependent upon which moral system or approach you consider i.e. deontology,

consequentialism, or virtue ethics. Deontology refers to ethics that derive from a sense of

duty and rules, or what ought to be. Consequentialism emphasises the consequences of

47

actions or thoughts. Virtue ethics focuses on the personal character or virtues of an agent and

their actions, rather than duty or consequences.

Alternatively, according to Rebecca Kukla (2014: 82) common morality is ‘our starting point

for moral reasoning’. She advocates that ‘actions are what do the bulk of the work in settling

the content of common morality.’ (2014: 81). Kukla further suggests:

… what is common between (almost) all of us ... is ... an endlessly complex

yet remarkably stable web of embodied normative responses, coping

techniques, perceptual skills, communicative rituals, ways of making public

our desires and needs, and so on (2014: 81, emphasis in original).

Furthermore, the main content of common morality is conveyed by our ability to interact

through ‘normative transactions’ with each other. This is even when we interact with those

who come from various different backgrounds and experiences. Kukla contends that,

ultimately, we are bound by our common morality in virtue of our lived experience, and it is

not something that we are able to simply ‘opt-out’ of. The common norms that operate in life

are open to change and critique. Whilst Kukla maintains that such norms have a ‘powerful

presumptive weight’ (2014: 83), they are not absolute. However, the debate continues on

whether common morality is in fact universal or dependent on factors such as social context.

The idea that there is a universal understanding, or common knowledge, of morality has

previously been explained through an analogy linking it to how individuals understand

grammar that all competent speakers of a language use (Gert, 2005). Gert (2005) stated that,

although the majority of speakers may not be able to explicitly describe the grammar system,

all competent speakers know how to use it when interpreting others’ speech and when

speaking to others. Therefore, whilst the understanding of many different aspects of morality

may be debated, it has been claimed that a common morality is a universal phenomenon with

various specifications (Gert, 2005).

The concept of a common morality has been a cornerstone idea in the genealogy of

philosophy, but has also featured in contemporary issues pertaining to the political, moral and

legal aspects of society (Outka and Reeder, 1993). It has also been claimed that moral

behaviours, such as the need to circumvent harm, unfairness and inequality, are universal

48

(Bacchini et al., 2013). However, this commonality is not shared by all when defining

morality, to which there are various claims; for example Outka and Reeder (1993: 30)

defined morality as:

…a set of rules or directives for actions and institutions, especially as these are

held to support or uphold what are taken to be the most important values or

interests of persons other than or in addition to the agent.

This definition suggests that morality involves adherence to these rules or directives and that

this is compulsory, irrespective of an individual’s personal proclivities or institutional

involvement. Solomon and Higgins (2010) claimed that moral rules often take the form of

commandments, like the Ten Commandments within Judeo-Christian tradition. These are

orders that tend to be used through words such as ‘ought or ought not’ (Solomon and

Higgins, 2010: 245, emphasis in original). One way that citizens can adhere to these rules and

attain moral respect is through everyday civility.

Virtues

To consider another philosophical perspective, virtue theory places emphasis on the character

of a moral agent. Jeong (2013) claimed that virtue ethics focuses on how virtues and moral

character can help explain the actions of virtuous agents (Jeong, 2013). This contrasts with a

deontological perspective that emphasises the notion of doing one’s duty or following rules,

or consequentialism which focuses on the outcome of actions (Baron, Petit and Slote, 2003).

According to Jeong (2013: 47) questions one might raise as a virtue theorist include; ‘What

kind of person should I be?’ or ‘How should I live?’. Jeong (2013: 47) distinguishes this from

deontology where the concentration could be on ‘What is the right or obligatory thing to do’.

According to Millie (2016: 34) virtue ethics focuses on ‘the qualities of the individual rather

than the quality of a person’s behaviour’ and that the process of evaluating a behaviour is

understood ‘in terms of the character of the person’ (2016: 34). At this point, it would be

prudent to discuss Aristotle who adopted a virtue ethics approach. Aristotle claimed that a

good person is someone who ‘embodied all the excellences of human character’ (Driver,

2007: 137). Millie (2016: 34) identified that what Aristotle refers to as good character

reflects ‘virtues such as honesty, justice, benevolence, courage, prudence, temperance…’.

49

Thus, whether an act is perceived as ‘right’ is deemed so ‘if it exemplifies virtue, or if the

virtuous person, the person who has all the virtues, would do it’ (Bennett, 2015: 97). The

question to answer is what person gets to decide which behaviours are virtuous and which are

not. Millie (2016) iterated that temperance or self-control is often perceived as a virtue, but

restraint is not typically perceived as a good thing. Further, what behaviour is virtuous may

be perceived as not virtuous is dependent upon subjective values. A good example of this is

provided by Millie (2016: 35) who noted that ‘a thief may show courage, but very few people

would argue that this was a good thing’. Thus, for Millie, perhaps context and motives are as

important is dictating what virtues are commended and those which are not.

Critics of virtue ethics have iterated existential issues, for example:

... there is no such thing as a pre-established pattern that dictates how human

beings should live and what they should value. Human beings, the

existentialists claim, are essentially free; they must set their own goals and

aims; and do not just ‘find’ what they ought to do written in the stars.

(Bennett, 2015: 98).

If there is no standard, pre-ordained pattern of human behaviour that all should follow, or

value, then it is a question of who has the authority to decide what behaviours and values

should be followed. Despite the limitations of virtue ethics, according to Millie (2016) it may

help criminological understanding of what types of character and virtues may help people

resist behaving criminally (or anti-socially). Anthony Bottoms (2015: 3) claimed that

acquiring a more virtuous disposition may help someone desist from criminal behaviour or at

least help them find ‘turnaround in their lives’. Building on this, the next section considers

the role of civility and how this may help our understanding of ASB.

Everyday Civility

‘Civility’ can typically be described as ‘an acceptable level of politeness’ (Lent, 2008: 1). It

can be defined as ‘an individual’s capacity or willingness to orient themselves towards the

social’ (Lent, 2008: 1). Civility has also been simplified as respect for the dignity, and the

desire for the dignity, of other people (Shils, 1997, as cited in Boyd, 2006). It has been

50

described as interwoven with the democratic ideology of moral equality. Incivil behaviour,

such as being rude or condescending, is to treat someone as if they are not your moral equal.

At its most fundamental level, civility encompasses the willingness of an individual to

moderate or accept some constraint on their own desires in order to protect the well-being of

others. Lent (2008) contends that when this willingness fails to control an individual’s own

desires there is a crisis of civility. He further explains that this failure exists through human

interaction in public spaces. For example, the unconstrained desire of another to play music

out loud, or to over indulge in alcohol and engage in drunken or disorderly behaviour can all

constitute incivil behaviour. Converse to being civil, incivility has been described as

reflecting a poor quality of relationships between members of different groups which create

and foster social disharmony (Bannister and O’Sullivan, 2013). It can assume the form of

direct or indirect conflict, or opposing expectations of social interactions and the perceptions

that individuals harbour towards others (Bannister and O’Sullivan, 2013). Through this,

social disharmony may manifest itself through the behaviour or perceptions someone has of

others. In the context of this study, ASB can be equated with incivility. Both concepts have

been discussed in political discourse and research (See Chapter 1).

Being civil is a way of ‘generating mutual regard, respect and democratic equality’ (Boyd,

2006: 865). According to Boyd civility has two primary functions. First, it is to ‘ease social

tensions enabling social interaction’ (2006: 863). Second, civility enhances ‘collaboration

irrespective of differences and disagreements.’ (2006: 863). This civility is achieved by

maintaining a formal distance and politeness between people. It has also been claimed that

civility has a moral role through expressing the equality of all members within a democratic

society. It is the formal courtesies and communications that convey respect for the equal

‘moral, social and political status of others’ (Boyd. 2006: 872).

However, it has been claimed that formal acts of civility may lack depth and have the

opposite consequences of undermining interaction between people. In such cases, they may

be construed as arrogant, offensive or aloof, creating the unintended effect of being labelled

‘uncivil’ behaviour (Laegaard. 2008). Laegaard (2008) linked civility to notions of tolerance

and respect, claiming that civility itself is imbued with some elements of the two.

Respectively, both the concepts of tolerance and respect have been linked to ASB as

51

solutions to the problem - and intolerance and disrespect seen as potential causes (Millie,

2006).

According to Laegaard (2008) it means one thing to be civil in relation to everyday social

interactions and another thing in political discourse. In everyday social interactions,

particularly amongst strangers, civility involves being polite and having good manners as

well as being courteous (Laegaard, 2008). ASB has often been equated with the opposite to

civility, namely incivility (e.g. Smith and Phillips, 2004; Millie, 2008; Donoghue, 2010). It is

the contention of this thesis that perceptions of ASB (and everyday incivility) are influenced

by an individual’s moral stance of what constitutes everyday morality. It is suggested that

everyday morality can provide a framework to understand how individuals navigate everyday

social situations in public spaces on a daily basis.

Everyday morality and relativism

According to the anthropologist Jarrett Zigon (2008), philosophers have been struggling for

over 2,000 years over what constitutes the moral, what is the good life and what is the good.

Yet, he acknowledged that, for all of the philosophical explorations that have been conducted,

not much notice has been given to the everyday moral lives of actual, living people. Another

anthropologist Edward Westermarck (1906) proposed that different moralities exist between

different societies, proclaiming that ‘a mode of conduct which among one people is

condemned as wrong is among other people viewed with indifference or enjoyed as a duty’

(1906: 742). Similarly, Ruth Benedict (1956: 195) stated that morality is no more than a

‘convenient term for socially approved habits’. According to Zigon (2008) it was this

definition of morality that became accepted by moral relativists and anthropologists.

Westermarck’s and Benedict’s perspectives on morality were amalgamated into a relativist

definition of morality by Raymond Firth (1951: 183):

Morality is a set of principles on which [judgments of right and wrong] are

based. Looked at empirically from the sociological point of view, morality is

socially specific in the first instance. Every society has its own moral rules

about what kinds of conduct are right and what are wrong, and members of

society conform to them or evade them, and pass judgement accordingly.

52

This is in tandem with the assumption of moral relativists that morality is relative to different

contexts and beliefs. Zigon (2008) claimed that this perspective underlies much of the

anthropological literature on morality and is assumed to mostly be true. For example, Fiske

and Mason (1990: 131) explain that there is an ‘obvious cultural and historical diversity in

moral systems’. Zigon (2008) attempted to exemplify moral relativism through the example

of a father and child relationship. To put this into context, he claimed that a good father may

feel obliged to go outside and play with his child, for example, to teach his son how to throw

and hit a baseball. If the father does not do this, the child may still eventually learn to play

baseball by other means and develop into a baseball star of the future. To compound the

father’s ‘neglect’ of not teaching his son to play baseball, he also does not visit any of his

games. Some people may perceive this as the behaviour of a poor father, but does this make

him immoral? Has the father broken some cultural moral code, is this a moral issue or is it a

culturally prescribed obligation for the father to teach his son as well as exhibit support at his

games? Some may feel this is not immoral behaviour, but it is not behaviour perceived

favourably. Therefore, the issue conveyed here is where the line is drawn between something

that is an issue of morality and something that is not an issue of morality. Similarly, where is

the line drawn between ASB that is immoral and ASB that is not necessarily immoral?

Another pertinent question to ask is how do the public discern whether a certain type of

behaviour is of moral concern or not in their everyday lives and is there a standard, universal

everyday morality that all people live by?

The next issue of defining everyday morality is what actually makes a certain type of

behaviour moral or immoral. In the context of the present study, the moral relativist approach

can be applied to understanding ASB within the UK. The assumption of moral relativists is

that morality differs within and between societies. An alternative to a relativist position is that

there is one predominant morality within a certain social group. Similar to the notion of a

culture, there are homogenous beliefs intertwined with a particular society. Shore (1990b)

espoused a similar position, claiming that moral relativism considers morality as

homogenously bounded within societal groups or societies. The next section will consider

morality on an individual scale.

Individual morality

As noted, the issues of ASB and urban disorder have received much attention from politicians

and the media within the UK since the mid-1990s (Powell and Flint, 2009). Media reports of

53

elderly people being terrorised by children, joy-riding, harassment and noise nuisance were

prolific across Britain (Haworth and Manzi, 1999). Whilst there was a variety of explanation

for this, the root cause of this behaviour was framed as being the consequence of individuals

who were out of control in concentrated areas of lawlessness (Haworth and Manzi, 1999). It

was the immoral behaviour of the few that were at fault for the consequences suffered by

other social housing tenants. As previously highlighted, within this disadvantaged context,

ASB was framed as a poor person’s problems in deprived areas. ASB was blamed on a badly-

behaved minority.

Moral relativists would maintain that the prevalence of ASB within these identified deprived

areas may be consistent with the moral expectation and standards of some groups within

these locations. Contrastingly, moral psychologist Luco (2014) proposed an alternative

deontological definition of morality. According to Luco, a morality contains a system of core

rules, modes of character development and psychological states. These enable the functioning

of ‘mutually beneficial social cooperation’ (Luco, 2014:1) between individuals. Luco

advocates that a set of criteria must be satisfied in order to achieve a definition of morality or

moral systems.

Similar to Gert (2004), Luco notes that morality entails both a descriptive and normative

sense. Luco shares the idea that individuals, who are different, have internalised and endorsed

different codes of conduct. The importance of distinguishing between morality in the

descriptive and normative sense, and the inclusion of ‘rational’ persons, serves to provide an

understanding of group or individual morality that may not be in line with others. Luco

extends this to examples, such as Hitler’s morality or Nazi morality, the Pope’s morality or

Catholic morality. The issue is that morality itself is ubiquitous to human nature; and to have

an increased understanding of human nature, Luco claims, we should be heavily invested and

interested in having a descriptive definition of morality. This is linked to the current

investigation as Luco notes that morality is supposed to provide a reference point to

normative reasons as to why individuals or groups act, feel or think in a particular way rather

than another. He purports that having a descriptive definition of morality would enable us to

answer the question, ‘what does morality demand of us?’. Having a descriptive definition of

morality would allow researchers to try and discern what the prerequisites of morality are for

human nature, namely what are the factors that provide an authoritative moral requirement

for humans in the first place. A descriptive definition of morality is a ‘code of conduct

54

actually endorsed by an individual or group’ (Luco, 2014: 2), thus it can be utilised to speak

of the moralities of various individuals or groups. Luco claims we should be interested in this

as moral discourse has always been present throughout human history; to comprehend what

morality is and why it is ubiquitous are both relevant to the understanding the moral aspects

of why people behave, think, feel or act in one way rather than another. Second, Luco iterated

that morality is believed to have authority in people’s lives and a descriptive definition of

morality may help elucidate what sort of authority or requirements morality demands of

people.

If the current research is able to provide further evidence regarding what people perceive as

everyday morality, then this could contribute to informing the questions posed by Luco.

What are the individual codes, or group codes, of conduct that are internalised in relation to

people’s perceptions of ASB? Is behaviour perceived as being anti-social due to the

perpetrator’s action being not in tandem with others’ moral codes of conduct – an individual

or relativist understanding of morality? The present study may help provide further

perspectives on what people perceive as being a moral or immoral action and, drawing on

relativism, whether this is purely because of different sets of standards.

A Kantian perspective

To take a different perspective on understanding what everyday morality is, a Kantian

framework for understanding morality is considered. According to Millie (2016) Kant’s

approach provides a useful method of understanding why particular behaviours or actions

may be perceived as morally wrong or criminalised. Kant’s work drew on the Golden Rule,

‘a subjective and individualistic approach to morality, but one with wider societal impacts.’

(Millie, 2016: 47). In a general context, the Golden Rule means to treat others how you

would like to be treated; it is universal and reciprocal (Millie, 2016).

Kant (2002b: 118) began with the claim that it is an ‘empirically observable fact’ that people

harbour ‘moral and ethical views’. His perspective was deontological, or rule and duty-based,

where morality is normative and sourced from a sense of duty. The rightness and wrongness

of actions themselves are the pivotal concern, not the consequences of actions (Kant, 2002b).

His two key assumptions are that only humans are capable of rationalism and are capable of

autonomy (Kant, 2002b). Kant’s (2002b) understanding of morality is that rational thought

55

guides us to an objective reality and objective morality; there is a single moral obligation

inherent within all rational beings. Kant (1975/1990) termed this the ‘Categorical Imperative’

(CI) which encompasses the moral law. His first Formula of Universal Law was that we

should:

Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that

it should become a universal law. (Kant, 1975/1990: 1031).

Fundamentally, the concept here is that you should question whether your action could

become a universal law. Millie (2016) gives the example of stealing. If an individual lives by

the maxim to be a thief and steals from others, this individual should ask if this could become

a universal law. Millie stated that the answer is no, as this would mean ‘…the thief would be

content for other people to steal from him’ (2016: 45). The opposite of this, to not steal from

others, would become the categorical moral imperative. According to Millie (2016) the

Categorical Imperative is a useful means to understand why particular behaviours or actions

may be perceived as morally wrong and criminalised. He cited Kant’s example of borrowing

money that may not be paid back:

The maxim of his action would then be expressed as follows: when I believe

myself to be in need of money, I will borrow money and promise to pay it

back, although I know that I can never do so. Now this principle of self-love

or personal advantage may perhaps be compatible with one’s entire future

welfare, but the question is now whether it is right. I then transform the

requirement of self-love into a universal law and put the question thus: how

would things stand if my maxim were to become a universal law? He then sees

at once that such a maxim could never hold as a universal law. (Kant,

1785/1990: 1032).

For Millie (2016) this heuristic has merit in assisting our understanding of what may be

regarded as wrong. In particular, why certain behaviours and actions should be censured. His

explanation for this succinctly conveys the issue of censuring actions:

There are clear benefits to the individual in taking the money, but this would

put the benefits they accrue above the costs to the lender (and to other future

56

borrowers who will no doubt end up paying higher interest rates). (2016: 45).

The implication is that from both examples, the borrower and the thief treated another person

as a means to an end. This is Kant’s second formulation, his Formula of Humanity as an End

in Itself:

Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the

person of another, always at the same time as an end and never simply as a means.

(Kant: 1975/1990: 1036).

This formulation suggests that treating others as you would treat yourself, for example having

respect for yourself and for others. Bartels et al. (2015) have likened Kant’s perspective to the

Ten Commandments of the Old Testament in terms of their absoluteness – for example, an

unambiguous prohibition against murdering another. Similarly, Kant’s first formulation of the

Categorical Imperative is absolute, in that you must act ‘only (emphasis added) in accordance

with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law’

(Kant, 1987/1990: 1031). That said, Bartel et al. (2015) noted that people struggle to

delineate right and wrong. They claimed that people experience moral conflict between

multiple moral principles with differing mandates. Consequently, this creates disagreements

and can generate tension between moral principles. However, they do acknowledge that

variations in context can influence what moral beliefs are more likely to manifest and affect

judgment or decision-making.

The reason Kant’s Categorical Imperative is important is that it emphasises the requirement

for respect for yourself and others. Thus, this may provide insight into why certain

behaviours within contemporary society may be deemed disrespectful, or morally wrong.

Kant contended that the demands of the moral law in humans derive from categorical

imperatives, or principles that are consistently valid across humanity. They require

obedience in all situations and circumstances if we are to adhere to the moral law.

If there are indeed universal features of morality, then Kant’s perspective may offer insight

for the current study by providing a potential, duty-based ethical perspective on why

individuals are perceived to behave anti-socially or not anti-socially. It may also explain why

some obey moral laws and others do not. Therefore, Kant’s stance on morality may provide a

57

framework to understand a link between an all-encompassing ‘everyday morality’ and ASB.

That said, limited attention is given to defining what particular everyday behaviours are or

are not moral. This resonates with the government's reluctance to explicitly define those

behaviours which are and are not anti-social, as considered in Chapter 1.

In that way, it does not make sense to attempt to define which behaviours or actions are

morally good or bad, since there is no comprehensive moral code against which judgements

on behaviour can objectively be made. An alternative approach to understanding whether

actions are judged as morally wrong is the previously noted Categorical Imperative. Millie

(2016) mentions that one example of this would be that the powerless in society should not be

treated different to others in society. Neither should they be more heavily policed, as these

actions would not qualify to become a universal law from a Kantian perspective.

Moral psychology has adapted a Kantian approach in explaining how morality operates on an

individual basis. According to White (2012) Kantian moral psychology and ethics

inaugurates with the notion of autonomy. This is the capacity for rational people to make

choices in moral situations. This is made independent of any external factors or influence

such as social pressure and authority. Internal factors, such as personal desires and interests,

do not impact upon the individual’s rational decision making process in these moral

situations. White further contended that Kant’s notion of autonomy directly implicates the

ability (and responsibility) to make decisions in concordance with the moral law. The rational

reasoning process of everyday people derives from recognising and acknowledging that

everyone is entitled to be treated with equal dignity. However, one stipulation is that all

individuals must have this capacity of autonomous choice.

To comprehend what it is to be autonomous, in terms of what Kant described, the Kantian

moral philosopher Christine Korsgaard (2009: 108) stated; ‘to be autonomous... is to be

governed by principles of our own causality, principles that are definitive of your will’. The

emphasis of Kant’s approach to morality hinges on the belief that people have the ability to

resist their preferences and inclinations, as well as external forces, for them to fulfil their duty

and behave ethically. Although, White (2012) claimed that this does not ordain a choice as

bad or wrong, but the motivation behind that choice is important. If an act is performed that is

itself good, or compliant with duty, but the motivation is derived from personal interest, then

that act is not moral. Therefore, it is heteronomous and not autonomous, but an act that is

58

heteronomous is not necessarily immoral. In Kantian ethics ‘autonomous’ refers to the

capacity for an individual’s will to deliberate and self-govern their own moral law rather than

being obedient to an externally imposed law. ‘Heteronomous’ refers to an individual’s will

which is submitting itself to some other end; it is influenced by an external legislative force

and obedience to rules or actions derives from an outside source such as government law.

Similarly, Korsgaard (1996: 22) explained that, ‘when you are motivated autonomously, you

act on a law that you give to yourself; when you act heteronomously, the law is imposed on

you by means of a sanction’. Korsgaard (1996) provides the example of an individual paying

taxes heteronomously, to avoid further penalties, rather than paying taxes autonomously due

to it being the morally right thing to do. In relation to the present study, Kantian moral

psychology can be linked to the law and how this can help explain obedience or defiance to

the law.

Other research has also drawn from the Kantian model of moral psychology to help explain

the relationship between individual everyday morality and ASB. One such position was

advocated by Hart (1961) a legal philosopher who purported that individuals who internalise

the law comprehend legal rules and norms on a more in-depth level. To these individuals,

these laws are their laws instead of being an external force. Those who internalise the law

attribute moral value and worth to it. Individuals with an external view of the law perceive it

as constraints enforced by an external authority that serves only to prohibit behaviours via

laws. Conformity to laws against behaving criminally, or anti-socially, is greater when

individuals have an internal view of the law. Hart further contended that the morally perfect

individuals internalise laws as a restraint on their actions that should never be transgressed

despite any potential personal benefit from the act.

Conversely, an amoral individual might treat these laws as mere information in terms of costs

and benefits from behaving in a manner that would be in violation of these laws. These

external authorities would be interpreted as parallel to any other factor that would impact on

the decision to behave in accordance with the law or against it.

Kant’s perspective may also provide a framework to study whether behaviour that is deemed

anti-social is morally acceptable. For example, a typical act of environmental ASB, as

previously noted, is the common problem of littering within public spaces, and the

59

Categorical Imperative could provide a method for determining where this act stands as a

moral issue. If we take the first formulation of the Categorical Imperative, we would have to

devise a maxim that exemplifies the reason for littering being an immoral act, or determine if

it is morally permissible. The second step would be to then apply this maxim as a universal

law that all rational people would be able to comprehend and act accordingly, as you yourself

would also act in these circumstances. The next step would be to consider whether this

maxim is conceivable within the context of a world that would adhere to and be governed by

this maxim. Finally, we must determine whether we would rationally, ‘will’ this maxim to

become universal. If the logic in uninhibited and these steps are followed then the action is

morally permissible (or impermissible). From this, it could then be conceived whether the act

is morally right or morally wrong dependent on whether it derives from a CI. Of course, this

depends on all rationality coming to a similar conclusion, which may not be the case.

Kant claimed that moral goodness is not derived from good outcomes, but only comes from

actions that are motivated by good will. In other words, as noted, his approach was non-

consequentialist. There are two types of imperatives that explain what we ‘ought’ to do:

1. A Categorical Imperative (CI) is a moral obligation that is intuitive, immediate,

absolute and understood by all rational beings.

2. A Hypothetical Imperative (HI) is based on ‘what I want’ and the means to get what I

desire. Hypothetical Imperatives are ‘a posteriori’ and discovered through empirical

fact or experience.

It is the CI which tells us what we ‘ought to do’ in a situation irrespective of our personal

inclinations. To explain, Kant argues that we ought always do what our duty requires of us

and refrain from doing what duty forbids. Unlike the HI, the CI is an unconditional obligation

in the sense that it operates independent of will or desires. There were three formulations of

the CI:

1. Universalizability: the CI, noted previously, is ‘Always act in such a way that you

could will that the maxim of your act become a universal law’. This is the requirement

of ‘universalizability’ (could everyone act the same way).

60

2. Human dignity: The second formulation is ‘Always act in such a way that you treat

humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another as an end in itself

and never merely as a means’. This is a prerequisite of basic human dignity, where

you must not use people.

3. The Kingdom of Ends: The third formulation is ‘Always act in such a way that you

are both legislator and legislated in the Kingdom of Ends’. This entails reciprocating

behaviour in accordance with the moral law to others and yourself. Once all adhere to

the first and second formulation, they become members of the Kingdom of Ends.

(Johnson and Cureton, 2018)

In concordance with Kant, when making a decision an individual needs to ask ‘Would I want

everyone in the entire world in this situation to make the same decision as me?’ If the answer

is yes, and there is no contradiction in the logic, then essentially this could be made a

universal law. For example, within the ASB context, the belief is that littering is wrong.

Therefore, all should subconsciously recognize it is wrong to litter and refrain from doing it.

However, in today’s society some may treat themselves as the exception. Subconsciously

they may perceive that littering is wrong but choose to do so anyway. Or perhaps some would

be happy if everybody were litterers; or perhaps, simply at the moment of dropping litter,

they do not care. In a Kantian society one would always try to abide by the moral law. If the

conclusion is that this behaviour is indeed morally permissible and not immoral, the question

whether the act had any moral worth must be asked. According to Kant, an act has moral

worth (is morally good) if it adheres to three precepts:

firstly it must be in accordance with the moral law (obligatory or morally

permissible),

secondly it must not be performed from personal inclination, regardless of whether

the intention is selfish, benevolent or otherwise,

thirdly, it must be performed with respect for the moral law (Johnson and Cureton,

2018).

According to Gert (2004) there has always been sufficient justification for acting morally,

being rationally allowed. It has been claimed by Gert (2004) that it is extremely difficult, if

not impossible, to show that the reasons for acting morally always have as much force or

61

more force than the reasons for not acting morally. This has led some philosophers

(Frankena, 1966; Skorupski, 1993; Gert, 2004) to try to answer the question ‘Why be moral?’

rather than the question ‘Why act morally?’. Of these two questions, the first is about why an

individual should be a moral person. Why should they have the moral virtues, not why a

person should act morally in a particular situation?

In the context of the current thesis, it is important to consider who decides which acts of ASB

are immoral or moral, and how this is justified. These are questions that, if answered, would

help explain links between ASB and everyday morality. The next section addresses the social

contexts of everyday morality, relating to the acceptance or rejection of behaviours deemed

inappropriate, such as ASB.

Social contexts of everyday morality

A recent investigation by Carnes et al. (2015) has suggested that morality is embedded in a

variety of different social contexts. In their research they purported that morality facilitates

sociality between people. For example, when one interacts with strangers, colleagues, friends,

the community, or other members of society, morality plays a role in promoting sociality.

Morality helps individuals ‘navigate their social worlds’ (Carnes et al., 2015: 1). Similarly,

Haidt (2008) noted that morality is important for social life. He defined morality as an,

…interlocking sets of values, practices, institutions, and evolved

psychological mechanisms that work together to suppress or regulate

selfishness and make social life possible. (2008: 70).

Carnes et al. (2015) claimed that research has often been negligent of this and instead

conveyed what people’s general beliefs are. Their study examined what moral principles

were perceived as being, as anchored in social contexts. Carnes et al. (2015) state that moral

interpretation varies, whether we are interacting with acquaintances, strangers, co-workers,

friends, family, civic society or the community. Due to this, Carnes et al. claim, morality

must be a far richer phenomenon than simply being the product of a set of rules, associations,

intuitive or abstract principles. What is highlighted is the potential relationship between

people’s every day, daily life and contexts and their perceptions of morality.

62

In relation to the current study, participants were recruited for focus group discussion on ASB

and everyday morality from areas selected based upon their level of deprivation (see Chapter

3). To some extent, this provides a glimpse of the associated contexts in these areas regarding

people’s experiences of ASB and how their perceptions of everyday morality are linked, or

not, to the level of deprivation in the area they are from. Similar to the Carnes et al. (2015)

study, the current exploration aimed to capture the distinct beliefs and views of the

participants regarding (everyday) morality, and it helps to illuminate the different types of

morality that are embedded in each group. The research presented in the forthcoming

chapters is an initial step aimed at understanding the socially embedded nature of morality in

what is perceived as anti-social. More specifically, this study investigates the extent to which

people believe that distinct moralities are embedded in different groupings (for example,

families, loosely associated strangers, and broad social categories). According to Carnes et al.

(2015) the idea that morality may be ‘socially embedded’ suggests that it is likely there may

be ‘some consensus in the way people understand the role of moral principles in distinct

social contexts’ (p.352). From this opinion, individuals are deemed to perceive different

moral principles in relation to the roles they play in different social situations. This is because

they fulfil different ‘context-specific’ functions, which Carnes et al. claim, function

differently in different social situations.

Carnes et al. (2015) further purported that people perceiving different moral principles know

they play various roles in different social contexts and this is due to the ‘context-specific’

roles which facilitate and regulate social life. Additionally, different types of groups provide

both opportunities and challenges to social actors, and moral principles are the vehicles

through which these individuals are able to navigate said social contexts.

To reinforce this contention, previous evidence from Clark and Mills (1979) reported that

norm reciprocity amongst ‘co-workers’ was expected. However, this was not the same for

communal relationships such as families. According to Clark and Mills this is due to the

different types of relationships themselves having different goals and priorities. As such,

individuals expect norms that are best in line with the corresponding goals pertaining to the

type of relationship - i.e. communal or exchange. Furthermore, these are relatively

independent of personal preferences, for both communal and exchange norms (Clark and

Mills, 1979).

63

In an extension of this, Carnes et al. (2015) contend that these moral principles are in fact

moral norms, but merely embedded in different types of social organisations. As norms are

‘shared beliefs that both guide and govern our behaviour in a specified context’ (Carnes et al.,

2015: 352), they claimed that the success of group existence is dependent upon having

functional, naturally understood norms, both moral and otherwise. Another point by Carnes et

al. was that, despite individuals who may differ in the extent to which they truly endorse

different norms, there may still be consensus regarding when different moral principles are

applicable in different social contexts. The problem Carnes et al. (2015) conveyed was that a

focus from other morality research on individual acts of morality may be obscuring research

investigating the idea that there may be a strong consensus of the moral norms which operate

in different group contexts. Therefore, Carnes et al. (2015) focused on the extent to which

individuals have a strong consensus in their beliefs regarding moral norms and principles that

are believed to regulate social life in various social contexts. The focus on consensus in their

research is important as they purport it may unveil something regarding how much people

perceive and agree that moral principles can be particular for different groups. They reported

that there was in fact a considerable level of consensus from their participants, that moral

principles are perceived to be operant in different settings, and thus morality is perceived as

‘socially shared’.

Everyday morality and society

According to Whitley 1976, (cited in Sitelman, 1977: 591) the morality of society is ‘the

practice of requiring or banning certain types of action and praising or blaming certain

dispositions of character’. This view may have implications for perceptions of crime or ASB.

Behaviours deemed acceptable or unacceptable - or moral and immoral - within a particular

society could be subject to the dominant perceptions and values of that society. According to

Millie (2011) there is a need to address the role value judgments play in the process of

criminalisation. He defined criminalisation as ‘the processes by which actions or omissions

become defined as crimes, or certain people or uses become defined as criminal or potentially

criminal.’ (Millie, 2011: 1). Millie further stated that behaviours which may be outside the

normal values of the majority may be too readily perceived as inappropriate thus leading to

them being criminalised. He noted that behaviour becomes unacceptable if it is perceived to

be causing sufficient harm to the victim. However, not all harmful behaviours may be

criminal (Millie, 2011) – nor for that matter, anti-social. The issue is that some behaviours

may be criminalised due to them causing offence, what Millie termed a ‘particularly

64

problematic and subjective sub-set of harm’ (2011: 3). A problem further arises when

determining what is offensiveness, and this is intrinsic to ‘disgust, obscenity and moral

(in)tolerance’ (Millie, 2011: 3). What may be perceived as morally offensive by society, or

by legal institutions, is not set in stone (Millie, 2011). In earlier research, Millie (2008) noted

that behavioural expectations, similar to perceived harm and offence, were context-specific.

Individual taste, aesthetics and subjective – or emotive – values all influence expectations of

behaviour. Millie further stated that individual tastes influence economic, aesthetic,

prudential and moral judgments - thus suggesting that what is acceptable is fluid, not fixed.

Just as behavioural expectations are not fixed, perhaps morality cannot be seen as a fixed

concept either – counter to the Kantian ethics outlined above. Instead it is something which

does (and must) adapt with the changes and actions within society (Herman, 2000). For

Herman, the biggest influence on morality is that of the political. Whiteley (1976, cited in

Sitelman, 1977: 593) distinguishes between the rules of society as dictated by political elites

and societal morality by arguing that the former are indeed imposed on the majority by a

minority, but that the latter have ‘the general support of members, in that most of them are in

favour of these rules being obeyed and these ideals pursued’. It may be that the powerful

minority set the moral agenda, but it is the majority who decide if this becomes part of the

fabric of society - that is, if it will become part of the common morality, or everyday morality

by which most people govern their own and others' behaviour. Whiteley’s view is

consequentialist and utilitarian in that he claims that the likelihood of some moral code being

accepted is dependent on the extent to which people can see its usefulness and their belief

that adherence to it will be beneficial to themselves and society. This is where beliefs can

differ in the sense of what morality is. For some, like Whiteley, what is considered moral can

be changed depending on need and desire. The opposite stance is that morality can only ever

be concerned with right and wrong, irrespective of the views of the individual or society.

Solomon and Higgins present this argument quite clearly when they say:

Morality is not just another aid to getting us what we want; it is entirely

concerned with right and wrong. And these considerations are above

tampering by any individual, no matter how powerful (2010: 26)

Following on from this then, it may be that, if morality is a fixed rather than fluid construct, it

can be displaced if it is no longer deemed necessary or relevant within a particular context.

65

Some philosophers, such as Whiteley (1976; 1982), view society as shaping morality, that is,

morality is fluid and comes to reflect the values of society - and in that way morality will

always exist. The contrary argument put forward by Hinde (2011) is that morality is fixed,

and that as society changes, morality does not adapt with it, until it finally becomes obsolete.

It is almost as if morality is an out of touch relic that has no place in modern society. In fact,

Hinde acknowledges that morality’s past association with religion may have resulted in it

being viewed as outdated or irrelevant in modern society. In Hinde’s paper, morality is seen

as an important aspect in society, something which is vital if it is to function in a positive,

peaceful manner.

How society contributes to defining morality is difficult to measure. Some attempts include

the study of behaviours which exist without any laws, explicit purpose or benefit, for

example, behaviours including being generous or displaying acts of kindness (Solomon and

Higgins, 2010). Often, acts of selflessness can be detrimental to the individual performing

them (such as giving up their time to help somebody) as well as to society (if a person helps

someone for free that could potentially be taking a paid job from somebody else). If society

dictates what is moral, and if acceptance of moral codes is dependent on their perceived

utilitarian benefit, it does not follow that those behaviours that do not follow these rules

would not only exist, but also be held in the high regard that they are. Whiteley (1982)

explains the existence of such behaviours by linking morality to conscience. Whiteley claims

that if a person has a conscience, they will act in a morally right way. Therefore, they will do

what is right, not what will bring the most benefit to them. To act otherwise, according to

Whiteley, means that one does not have a conscience.

This leads neatly onto consideration of what influences people to act in accordance with a

particular set of moral beliefs. Millie (2011) notes that such moral judgements are also of

interest to criminologists. For Whiteley (1982), the conviction that something is morally right

is justification enough to act in a certain way. Herman (2000) proposes that it is not enough to

simply ask what the morally right thing to do is. Instead, you must also ask why somebody

would choose to act in a way that is moral. Herman argues that it is more beneficial to

understand a person’s or society’s motives for acting in a certain manner, rather than seeking

out the moral compass that may or may not underlie their behaviour.

66

In summary, there are competing views on the relationship between morality and society. For

some, society determines what is deemed morally right and wrong, whilst for others morality

is a fixed concept which society can either have or not have: there can be no altered or

watered-down morality. Taken together, these approaches can go some way to explain why

there may be a perceived ‘moral decline’ in society (Millie, 2010). If society changes what is

moral and more and more behaviours become accepted by society, morality itself would be

‘shrinking’, giving the impression that morality is on the decline. Conversely, if less

behaviours are tolerated, there may be the sense that more and more people are immoral as

they continue to engage in an expanded list of censored behaviours, and therefore, morality is

again perceived to be declining. Alternatively, if morality is fixed, but no longer has a place

in society, those holding moral views will feel out of place and out of touch with a society

which does not seem to pay attention to moral values. This sense of alienation would also

result in fears that society has become a moral vacuum.

Alternatively, morality can be regarded as relativistic. For example, Millie (2016: 33)

described how a moral relativist perspective may state that morality and values can be ‘down

to personal opinion or taste’. According to Julia Driver (2007) one of the opposing

perspectives to moral universalism (the notion that some norms and values are universal, as

with the earlier mentioned Kantianism) is relativism. She claimed that moral relativism is the

belief that there are no universal standards of morality that can be applied to all contexts,

cultures and times. Millie (2016) noted that relativism appeals due to its appearance of being

tolerant towards everyone’s individual way of life. He comments that the issue with this is

that it can suggest tolerance of behaviours regarded as morally impermissible, such as

‘racism, slavery or rape.’ (Millie, 2016: 34). From this, it was concluded that it is possible

some universal truths do exist that may be applicable to everyone. There is flexibility for

interpretation on moral truths beyond relativism, such as individual and societal perceptions

(Millie, 2016). The next section will consider the link between perceptions of ASB and

everyday morality.

Linking perceptions of ASB to everyday morality

67

Accounts of morality implicate society as both influencing and being influenced by morality.

The types of behaviour perceived as acceptable or unacceptable within society seem to

change over time and location. It is logical to infer from this that everyday morality and

judgements about what is and is not moral also change over time and location. Furthermore,

if this is the case, we can deduce that what is considered social or anti-social will also change

over time and location, as everyday morality within and between societies shifts. In this way,

behaviours that were once seen as morally good, or at least morally acceptable or tolerable,

can become viewed as no longer morally good and, consequently, be branded as 'anti-social'.

The rise in ASB in popular imagination does not necessarily mean that more people are

giving up on society; rather it could mean that everyday morality is becoming more rigid, less

forgiving. Behaviours that were once accepted are no longer accepted, and are regarded as

immoral. For example, Yunxiang Yan (2014) in an examination of immorality reported that

behaviours, such as animal cruelty, which were once more widely accepted are now

perceived as immoral. Yet, conversely, pre-marital sex has become widely accepted as

normal, or at the very minimum amoral. The situation is not straightforward. Whilst it might

appear that more people are engaging in anti-social or immoral behaviour, in fact the level of

behaviour has remained the same, and it is simply the classification of that behaviour that has

changed. The problem then is not a lack of, or reduction in morals, rather it is the changing

number of behaviours regarded as immoral and therefore intolerable.

Within criminology the issue of ASB and tolerance has been highlighted (e.g. Bannister et al.

2006; Millie, 2006; Mackenzie et al. 2010). According to Millie (2006) what is regarded as

anti-social may be specific to certain individuals or groups. Even minor uncivil or rude

behaviours could be construed as anti-social. Millie (2006) reported that participants in a

study of ASB had all, to differing extents, experienced ASB, although what was considered

as ASB varied. The suggestion is that ASB is subjective. If perceptions of what ASB is vary

from one person to another then it may be an issue of intolerance towards a specific

behaviour rather than it simply being anti-social. This argument can be also used to explain

why ASB appears to be a predominantly 'poor persons' problem – as noted in the previous

chapter - and why acts that could be regarded as immoral are not always classified as anti-

social. If everyday morality is both shaped by and is a reflection of society, and if the people

who shape society have a particular agenda in mind, it is logical that certain behaviours will

be censored whilst others will be encouraged. As noted, Herman (2000) emphasised the

68

impact of the political on setting the moral agenda. If politicians want to encourage business

and investment, or if they tend to support the status quo, it makes sense that the behaviour of

these groups will be protected and more likely regarded as moral. Conversely, the behaviour

of people seen as a 'threat' to the political ideal, for example those who make less of a

contribution, will be censored in an attempt to both reduce the behaviour, and to raise the

status of the political values the government is expounding.

Whiteley (1976, cited in Sitelman, 1977) argued that a moral code would only be accepted by

the majority if there was consensus over its usefulness and benefit to individuals and society

as a whole. This might account for why governments and media are keen to demonise certain

parts of society and behaviour. By doing so, they create a 'threat' to the majority's way of life,

thereby making the majority more susceptible to agree to moral codes that could protect them

from this threat. Further support for the notion of demonising behaviours that precedes the

enforcement of moral codes was found by Cohen (1972). Cohen contended that creating a

moral panic and generating ‘folk devils’ (believed to have caused the potential threat)

facilitates the regulation of behaviour through new legislation. This enables the censoring of

behaviour not in line with the majority, for instance through linking ASB and morality via

creating a ‘moral panics’.

A link between ASB and everyday morality also explains why ASB cannot be neatly defined

as a list of behaviours, and why ASB must 'be seen' to be recognised. In short, the

classification of a behaviour as anti-social is determined by whether it is perceived as moral

or not. Perceptions of morality are fluid and change with time and location. To know if a

behaviour is anti-social, one must first know if it is perceived as moral or immoral, and this

can only be decided within the circumstances in which the behaviour occurs. Therefore,

behaviour can only be labelled as anti-social once the context in which the behaviour has

arisen has been assessed, and a moral judgement passed. To attempt to define all the

circumstances under which every behaviour would and would not be deemed anti-social

would be an impossible, if not futile, task. It therefore can appear logical that behaviours are

instead individually judged as anti-social or not, as and when they occur. A reason to favour a

more fluid concept of ASB is precisely because it is so closely tied with morality – assuming

conceptions of what is moral are also fluid.

Conclusions

69

This chapter began by introducing and discussing the concept of an everyday, or common,

morality. It was reported that throughout the history of moral philosophy the term ‘common’

morality or ‘common-sense’ morality has been utilised to reference everyday norms and

values. Morality has been traced back to a broad spectrum of principles that underlie our

common, everyday views and beliefs. Subsequently, it was reported that whilst a sense of

common morality has been the foundation of moral philosophy, it also has been heavily

involved in discussions of politics, education, law and behaviour. The focus then progressed

onto civility, and how this may provide a link between everyday morality and ASB.

Perceptions of everyday civility have been reported to influence an individual’s moral stance

regarding their concept of everyday morality. It was then suggested that everyday morality

can provide a framework to understand how individuals experience their everyday social

world. The evidence of moral relativism provided a platform to consider how everyday

contexts and cultural beliefs underlie our moral systems.

The current research contends that investigating the underpinning perceptions of what

everyday morality means to people could help us understand the moral aspects of ASB. For

example, what perceived moral codes do individuals attribute to ASB perpetrators? What

moral standards and norms affect whether ASB is perceived as immoral or not? It was

suggested that morality may be socially embedded. Furthermore, there may be an underlying

consensus regarding the role of moral principles within certain contexts. Individuals may also

perceive different moral principles within particular contexts dependent on the role they are

playing in a social situation. At which point a behaviour or action becomes deemed immoral

was not clear. Similarly, in the context of ASB, it is not clear who decides which behaviours

are anti-social, and morally ‘bad’.

The relationship between morality and society was considered next. There are competing

views on how society and morality interact. If society changes what is moral and more

behaviours become accepted by society, morality may appear to be ‘shrinking’, perhaps

suggesting that morality itself is declining. This chapter then considered morality from a

deontological approach, namely by consideration of Kantian ethics. It was noted that Kant’s

perspective suggested morality is normative, deriving from a set of duties whereby people

adhere to rules. Rather than the consequences being the central concern of an action, it is the

rightness or wrongness that is important. The paramount moral obligation to all people was

termed by Kant as the ‘Categorical Imperative’. The CI is, in essence, a moral law consisting

70

of three key formulations. If an action passes each of these then it is a moral obligation. In the

current study, Kantian Ethics provided a framework to examine how ASB may be understood

as immoral or moral. Littering, theft and borrowing were provided as examples of applying

Kant’s approach. However, there may be limitations of adopting a Kantian perspective. For

example, according to MacIntyre (1981: 67), ‘natural and human rights… are fictions’ and

obligations deriving from duty may neglect other ethical considerations - for example, the

influence of good character and virtues rather than focusing on obligations and rights as

Kantian ethics focuses on.

The link between ASB and everyday morality was suggested to provide an answer as to why

ASB cannot be lucidly delineated within a list of behaviours. Whilst a Kantian approach to

ASB might be attractive due to its simplicity, the everyday lived reality of ASB might mean

that understandings of ASB could be context specific; understandings of morality might also

be context specific thus both can be more fluid. The importance of context might also provide

an answer as to why ASB cannot be delineated to a finite list of behaviours. It is a matter of

perception. ASB might only be considered as such once the context in which the behaviour

occurred has been considered. Similarly, the moral aspects of the behaviour may only be

assessable once the circumstances surrounding the action are considered. A moral judgment

could then be contrived. Thus, moral judgments may be influenced by individual and group

perceptions of behavioural expectations.

Chapter 3.

71

ASB, moral regulation and responsibilisation

Introduction

This chapter considers the relationship between ASB, moral regulation and responsibilisation.

It explores what moral regulation is, and how this is practiced through government efforts to

tackle ASB. The chapter also addresses how these concepts have been linked through UK

political discourse, legislation and concepts such as civility. Subsequently this chapter

discusses the media and moral panics as factors influencing perceptions. The role of self-

regulation and responsibilisation in strategies aimed at tackling ASB and incivility are then

considered. The idea of a ‘law-abiding majority’, and the reasons why an individual may or

may not adhere to standards of behaviour and the law, will precede talk of moral decline and

respect. Examples of atypical ASB in groups other than the usual suspects – the young, poor

or deprived - and how these may violate codes of civility and social norms are then

considered.

ASB and moral regulation

As previously highlighted, a link between everyday morality and ASB has been conveyed in

politics, where there has been an understanding of ASB as being ‘fundamentally caused by a

lack of respect for other people’ (Home Office, 2003: 7). This notion guided New Labour

policy interventions built on the idea that there needs to be a ‘cultural shift’ (Home Office,

2003: 6) to restore a ‘sense of respect’ within British society (Blair, 2005). New Labour’s

Respect and Responsibility White Paper (Home Office, 2003) suggested that civility must be

maintained by, as well as being the responsibility of, all members of society. As ASB was

framed as a lack of respect, interventions to (re)create morally-sound and respectful cultures

were aimed at the liberal governance of self-regulating individuals.

This was to be achieved through a framework of desired ethical conduct (Rose, 1999). This

framework would involve enhancing civility and respect through establishing new contracts

of responsibility for citizens. These would be for themselves, their communities and between

72

the government and citizens. The process of achieving these aims through governmental

strategies has been linked to the concept of ‘moral regulation’, a term often utilized in the

realms of economics and politics. For example, according to Hunt (1999: 17), ‘moral

regulation is a discrete mode of regulation existing alongside and interacting with political

and economic modes of regulation’. According to Hunt (1999) moral regulators are social

agents who reject behaviour they consider immoral. They seek to control the behaviour of

others through legal or other methods. Moral regulation also involves changing the behaviour

and identity of perpetrators, which may indirectly require that those who regulate such

behaviour also change their own. Others have described this as a revolutionary process that

permeates through the methods governments use to exert their identity and instil this in its

citizens:

We call this moral regulation: a project of normalizing, rendering natural,

taken for granted, in a word ‘obvious’, what are in fact ontological and

epistemological premises of a particular and historical form of social order.

Moral regulation is coextensive with state formation, and state forms are

always animated and legitimated by a particular moral ethos (Corrigan and

Sayer 1985: 4).

Traditional examples of perceived ‘immoral’ behaviours that moral regulators have focused

on pertain towards alcohol consumption, gambling and sexual promiscuity. Hunt (1999)

concluded that moral panics have an alternative role as an extreme method of social control

through moral regulation, especially during times when there is a perceived moral or cultural

crisis.

Young (1971) claimed that moral panics refer to the near hysterical and exaggerated reactions

of society to events which challenge the traditional norms and values of a society. Similarly,

Cohen (1972: 1) described a situation of ‘moral panic’ as follows:

A condition, episode, person or group of persons emerges to become defined

as a threat to societal values and interests; its nature is presented in a stylized

and stereotypical fashion by the mass media.

73

He further contended that an important process in the creation of a moral panic is the

demonisation of ‘folk devils’ by the media - those perceived as the source of the social issue.

This evokes an irrational fear created within society and amplifies the issue until it becomes a

systemic concern. The consequences of this then provoke a legal or social shift aimed at

tackling the problem (Bearfield, 2008). According to Miller and Kitzinger (1998, as cited in

Rohloff and Wright, 2010) moral panics have been utilized as an umbrella term to cover

everything from working mothers to single mothers, ecstasy, guns, pornography on the

internet and state censorship. Others have argued that moral panics are used as an instrument

to expose the underlying processes which may precipitate the creation of social issues

(Rohloff and Wright, 2010).

Moral panics can operate through the media, to reinforce prevalent conceptions of what is

moral behaviour whenever the accepted standards are challenged (Denham, 2008). According

to McRobbie and Thornton (1995) moral panics aid news agencies through their propensity

to create emotional dimensions in otherwise mundane stories. In fact, it has been claimed that

the more deviant the people or issues are, the more liable they are to be included in the media

content, and thus there is increased likelihood of being stereotyped (Shoemaker and Reese,

1996). Therefore, critics of the media’s role in assisting moral panics contend that they create

an inaccurate portrayal of the societal threat or those considered ‘folk devils’ (Shoemaker and

Reese, 1996). Jewkes (2004) has suggested that Cohen’s (1972) conception of a moral panic

is biased towards younger subcultures within society and places too much emphasis on the

media’s role rather than the deviant behaviour. Despite such criticism, Jewkes stated that

moral panics should, be ‘regarded in the way that Cohen intended – as a means of

conceptualizing the lines of power in society and the ways in which we are manipulated into

taking some things too seriously and other things not seriously enough’ (Jewkes, 2004: 85).

It is the use of the word ‘manipulation’ by Jewkes (2004) that is important in understanding

possible links between ASB, morality and political and media reaction regarded as a moral

panic. In relation to ASB, one example of moral panic and resultant moral regulation is the

political and media portrayal of hoodie-wearing young people. According to Hayward and

Yar (2006) ‘chav’ fashion of the late 1990s and early 2000s was characterised as including

the hooded top, baseball caps, trainers and sports attire. Hoodies were symbolic of the

stereotypical young ASB perpetrator. This became a symbol of an assumed youth moral

decline and preceded governmental attempts to moralise the activities of the British youth

74

(Coleman, 2005). The moral panic and public anxiety regarding ASB were used to justify

legislative endeavours to ameliorate Britain’s perceived moral decline through tackling the

‘hoodie’ and, consequently, ASB (Hier, et al., 2011). This belief that ASB was related to

‘hoodies’ and particular items of clothing was an association utilised within the media as a

tool through which hoodie wearing young people could be blamed for ASB and crime (Hier

et al., 2011).

Waiton (2008) has claimed that modern politics itself has instigated an era where anxiety and

worry about, what he called ‘amoral panics’ are rife. This has led to further moralisation to

manage ASB. The suggestion of ‘amoral’ politics and the over-enforcement of moral

regulation to serve the ruling elite has been previously noted (Hall et al., 1978). Some have

also claimed that moral panics are simply an instrument which enables the elite classes of

society to obscure the underlying crises in the government. Hall et al. (1978) proposed that

moral panics are engineered simply to avert public attention away from a specific ‘moral

evil’. Instead, other moral concerns or issues are construed to be a serious threat towards

societal values and morals. Subsequently, these concerns then become the focus of regulatory

action.

The perceived threat of ASB was one such issue that was subject to regulatory action aimed

at eliminating this threat to the moral fabric of society. Whilst it has been maintained that

moral regulation projects are aimed at the entire spectrum of activities perceived as risks to

society, it has been acknowledged that ‘no age group is more associated with risk in the

public imagination than that of ‘youth’’ (Thompson, 1998: 43). The youth of Britain are

actually identified, not just as an at risk group within society, but as one of the primary

sources of risk or menace towards society (Cohen, 1972; Burney, 2002). There have been

myriad attempts to regulate the behaviour of young people, resulting in a plethora of hybrid

moral-legal devices (Hier et al., 2011). The belief was that youth (mis)behaviour in public

spaces could be controlled through the regulation of dress codes and behaviours.

When New Labour’s Respect Agenda was announced (Respect Task Force, 2006) the use of

language such as ‘disrespect’ and ‘decency’ by government, alongside representations of

hoodie-wearing young people within the media, has been described as indicative of a

breakdown of moral regulation (Hier et al., 2011). It is evident that calls for respect through

moral regulation further link the concept of morality to agendas on ASB. The next section

75

focuses on attempts to enhance responsibilisation and promote shared norms and standards

for individuals to live by.

Self-regulation and responsibilisation

According to Haworth and Manzi (1999) in the 1990s responsibilisation strategies were

increasingly being adopted within UK housing management to promote moral norms of

behaviour and self-conduct. The main objective of such methods was to instil these values in

citizens and increase individual responsibility where members of society enhance social

cohesion through a shared sense of identity within their communities. Flint (2002) claimed

the increasing use of responsibilisation strategies reflected a broad trend aimed at promoting

a common set of values for members of society to live by (Flint, 2002). This would,

theoretically, enable them to self-regulate their behaviours (Kearns and Forrest, 2000). The

link between responsibilisation strategies and morality becomes evident when responsibility

is defined in terms of the need to adhere to moral norms of behaviour and self-conduct (Rose,

1996). In relation to ASB, it was the belief that this strategy would challenge ‘immoral

norms’ to tackle ASB in areas such as social housing. In these areas the aim was to encourage

tenants to take responsibility, ensuring their own and their children’s moral values and

behaviour are within such shared codes (Flint, 2002). Once more the link between ASB and

morality is exemplified through this belief that morality is something to be infused within

society through self-regulation.

However, Flint (2002: 631) also acknowledged that, despite these strategies being based on

the idea of self-regulation, they are nonetheless an attempt to impose norms and make people

conform to ‘an idealistic definition of the identity of wider society’. Others have reported that

it was assumed that everyday morality could be enforced and people could be made to be

more respectful (Millie, 2010). Millie (2010) further contended that government-led

civilizing initiatives may only be productive if the government follows its own example.

Papps (1998) criticized such attempts to counteract ASB, claiming that the governmental

concern about how poor people conduct themselves is selective as there is no comparable

scrutiny of the behaviour of people who are not poor.

Despite such criticism, the governmental and political focus remains on tackling ASB

through the enforcement of legislation and the enforcement of everyday morality. This is

76

particularly geared towards those labelled as an ‘underclass’, and women and young people

have experienced the brunt of such methods (Millie, 2010). Critics have also taken issue with

the governmental emphasis that respect is something which ‘cannot be learned, purchased or

acquired, it can only be earned’ (Home Office, 2006b: 30). The implication here is that those

who have not ‘earned’ respect do not deserve to be treated with respect. Somerville (2009)

stated that, at the most basic level, respect requires equality and mutuality, but government

policy initiatives on ‘respect’ do not address the lack of equality, such as that between the

government and its citizens.

An alternative approach to promoting self-regulation may be the use of moral education to

tackle ASB and incivility. According to Taboada (1998: 1) the best method to tackle crime

and ASB is to ‘embark on an educational process to help people confront and resolve issues’.

From this perspective, Taboada suggests that moral education can provide the context for

crime prevention policy. He claims that opposing views that emerge whenever personal

interest is balanced against collective interest can be resolved through educational processes

involving moral education. By teaching social and cultural values it may be possible to

counteract the friction between competing views of behaviour. This suggestion appears to be

reminiscent of attempts at promoting ‘tolerance’ amongst people. This preventative approach

would be based upon the principle of ‘moral worth’. The concept of moral worth is in turn

influenced by the formulations of each autonomous moral person which they develop through

interaction within their community. The practical application of this moral education involves

multiple methods; Taboada notes the following value-forming processes as being intrinsic to

moral education:

1)…encouraging self-knowledge and moral consciousness within situations of

understanding and dialogue ("classification of values," "exercises of self-

expression," "discussion of moral dilemmas," "recognition of alternatives and

preview of consequences," "debates," and various types of "analysis of

values"), and 2) those seeking attitudinal change, as well as an end to

behaviours that cause physical or mental harm, together with those that are

antisocial. The process of self-regulation of the individual is the constant

theme. (Taboada, 1998: 2)

77

Through this approach, it may be possible to promote values, behaviours and standards that

increase responsibilisation amongst those who are perceived to behave anti-socially.

In conclusion, government attempts at self-regulation have typically tried to promote

responsibility amongst individuals in communities and create shared values. However, these

interventions primarily have been directed at the poor and the so-called underclass. The

respect that the UK government has aimed to instil in these communities has been found

lacking in terms of reciprocal respect from government. Due to a lack of scrutiny on those

who are not usual suspects for moral regulation strategies, there is inequality and bias present.

An alternative approach would by promoting moral education amongst those who are

perceived to behave anti-socially, irrespective of where they live or what their income is.

Promoting moral education amongst anti-social individuals - whoever they are - may help

offenders to self-regulate and increase their own sense of responsibility.

The ‘law abiding’ majority

Tyler and Darley (1999) have claimed that individuals are internally motivated to follow

rules. This motivation is the feeling of obligation or responsibility to conduct oneself

according to what is considered appropriate. The implication is that a ‘civic’ culture could be

created where most people abide by laws. This enables the regulation of behaviours and

maintenance of social control whilst developing social values. Tyler and Darley (1999)

further acknowledged that morality and the law are inextricably linked in terms of attempting

to build a law-abiding society - if the law and the public’s beliefs of morality are consistent.

The link may be idiosyncratic, however, and therefore it would be difficult to apply one

understanding of morality to all.

The concept of a law-abiding majority has been described as ‘an imagined connection

between the elected and electorate’ (Millie, 2016: 85). The narrative of a law-abiding

majority in political discourse is reduced to representing only those who are believed to work

hard, maintain standards of behaviour and adhere to society’s laws (Millie, 2016). Thus, the

narrative is intolerant of individuals who are believed to be not behaving in accordance with

the law. Millie claimed that the notion of having a law-abiding majority is ‘mythical’ (2016:

85). In fact, those individuals who may regard themselves as being law-abiding citizens could

be equally guilty of ‘breaking rules, be they breaches of law or other normative standards’

78

(2016: 85). For example, fraudulent tax behaviours or driving through red lights are also

breaches of social norms (Karstedt and Farrell, 2006). Thus, it would appear that other groups

within society, rather than just the poor or marginalised, could be guilty of breaking the rules

of society or behaving anti-socially. For example, Millie noted examples of both politicians

and corporations ‘stretching the limits’ (2016: 86) of the rules. He cited cases of the

parliamentary expenses scandal in 2009, the Volkswagen emissions scandal of 2015 and the

global banking crisis of 2008. These exemplify how other members or groups of society can

push the moral boundaries and laws to the edge. It may therefore follow that ASB is also

prevalent amongst the so-called ‘law-abiding majority’ within society.

To give an example, Halla and Schneider (2014) have investigated the link between benefit

fraud, tax evasion and morality through studying the social norms claimed to be responsible

for cheating on the government. These social norms, named Benefit Morale and Tax Morale,

are conceptualised as ‘the motivation an individual has to abstain from cheating on the state

through tax evasion or benefit fraud’ (Halla and Schneider, 2014: 413). Halla and Schneider

adopted a utilitarian approach and contended that the social norms of Tax Morale and Benefit

Morale were determined by ‘prices’ (i.e. the cost of acting morally). The citizens who have

more opportunity to cheat rationalise it through developing an attitude that it is a trivial

offense. Therefore, individuals self-servingly adjust their moral values. This study linked

everyday norms to economic factors (the ‘price’ of cheating) and to an individual’s

motivation to comply with the law. It concluded that social norms are determinants of

individual economic behaviour.

The subjective definition of ASB may be so broad that economic crimes such as tax

evasion/avoidance could potentially be construed as causing annoyance, nuisance or

harassment to other members of society and are therefore anti-social. An increased tax burden

caused by tax evasion may even be linked to ASB if members of society perceived this

causing economic nuisance or annoyance. Other types of harm, such as environmental

pollution or noise, can have dire consequences for individuals and communities with

repercussions extending to both physical and emotional harm. According to South (1998, as

cited in Croall, 2009) the accumulation of even micro-scale local pollution incidents can

precipitate damage from a moderate to a devastating scale and on their conditions of life.

Even if some offences do not have an emphatic impact, physically or otherwise, they can be

conceptualised as a threat to people’s quality of life (Croall, 2004, as cited in Croall, 2009).

79

Noise pollution, dirty business operations, breaches of food regulations, selling unsafe or

counterfeit goods or invading householders’ privacy via aggressive marketing could all

equally be described as anti-social or uncivil behaviour. If ASB, low-level or otherwise, can

impact on another individual’s quality of life, then these wider crimes and harms could also

be conceptualised as being anti-social.

Karstedt and Farrall (2006) have suggested that individuals have a selective regard for legal

codes and that they morally differentiate between laws, for instance, that cycling on the

pavement is (usually) illegal, but - understandably - is not treated with the same moral

contempt as committing a murder. Morality is not absent, but individuals’ moral regard for

the law is influenced by a sophisticated reasoning process dependent upon their own

circumstances. Karstedt and Farrall (2006) concluded that this may be indicative of how

issues such as ASB, crime and incivility are influenced by both everyday morality and laws.

The issue here is people’s idiosyncratic understandings of what constitutes appropriate, moral

behaviour. Understanding the link between everyday moral choices and ASB could be more

complex due to the heterogeneous standards of moral behaviour that each individual

maintains.

Despite the issue of adherence to laws on an individual level (being dependent on individual

beliefs on moral codes) it has been argued that laws must not be enforced through coercive

measures. Instead they should build on a common understanding of the social values of

individuals (Tyler and Darley, 1990), a sentiment shared by Millie (2010) who takes the

position that ‘enforcing respect’ is a strange notion. Further warning about trying to enforce

respect was conveyed by Sennett (2003: 260) who stated that, ‘[t]reating people with respect

cannot occur simply by commanding it should happen. Mutual recognition has to be

negotiated’. Sennett (2003) suggested that respect at the most fundamental level is

understanding the needs of others within society and encouraging mutuality. Conversely, the

New Labour government’s interpretation of respect was biased towards what was labelled as

unacceptable behaviour and the punishment of this behaviour - as well as trying to enforce

respect (and, as noted, therefore not reciprocating that very same respect they are striving to

attain). An approach which promotes social values and a common understanding such as that

suggested by Tyler and Darley (1990) is a far cry from the coercive measure adopted by New

Labour’s Respect initiative.

80

Talk of moral decline and respect

It has been claimed that social values, such as the aforementioned respect, in Britain are

changing rapidly under the perception that there is a widespread decline in morals and values

(Browne, 2008). Conversely, however, it has been argued that there have been many moral

improvements within Britain since the 1950s, with measurable constructs such as income,

health, tolerance and fairness in society greatly increasing (Browne, 2008). Some have

suggested that this is part of a broader civilizing process (Elias, 2000; Powell and Flint,

2009). Powell and Flint (2009) adopted Norbert Elias’s (2000) framework to understand

governmental ASB interventions within the UK. Briefly, the Civilising Process is continuous

and ‘represents a change in human conduct and sentiment located with broader processes of

social development’ (Powell and Flint, 2009: 161). The key theme of this process is the

interconnection between society and the individual. Through intense state regulation, a

counter-intuitive decivilising process can occur. Societal responses to ASB and crime

interventions can construct differences between ‘elites and “targeted” populations’ (Powell

and Flint, 2009: 175). In turn, this can act as a form of social control where attempts to tackle

a perceived incivility and a lack of respect lead to decivilizing ‘justice mechanisms’. For

example, naming and shaming may lead to social stigmatization rather than rehabilitation

(Powell and Flint, 2009). Naming and shaming measures entail offender details being

publicized by government organisations, local authorities, social landlords, police, or others

(Powell and Flint, 2009). Powell and Flint (2009) also claimed that the Respect Agenda

contained decivilising elements through penal legislation. Rather than tackling ASB and

incivility, the promotion of civility through such measures can, paradoxically, act as a

divisive tool. This in itself can be decivilising and lead to exclusion, where only the elite in

the hierarchy are served (Boyd, 2006).

To summarise, it is evident that the concepts of morality, respect and ASB have been

intrinsically linked through political rhetoric and legislation. The belief system in place was

that introducing laws which could regulate morals and behaviours may reduce disrespect and

thus decrease ASB. This could be achieved through promoting shared common values to

combat incivility. However, the relationship between morality and ASB did not appear fully

understood in terms of the governmental response to this issue, particularly the lack of

understanding in conceptualising respect and attempts to socially engineer this into society

through enforcement.

81

Civility and social norms

The link between civil cooperation and strong social norms is underpinned by an inherent

awareness of other members of society (Bannister and O’Sullivan, 2013). This awareness has

been described as a necessary cultural and social expression that needs more stimulation. In

turn, this would create more meaningful social interactions that can promote civility

(Bannister and O’Sullivan, 2013). Bannister and O’Sullivan (2013) claimed that, if others are

to be perceived as a welcome presence by the majority, then there must be a willingness to

adjust, or be accepting towards, minorities within society. This acceptance has a foundation

based on civility and, according to Boyd (2006: 863), civility ‘denotes a sense of standing or

membership in the political community with its attendant rights and responsibility’. He

further contended that this understanding of civility generates the notion of an, ‘active and

affirmative moral relationship between persons. Being civil is a way of generating moral

respect and democratic equality’ (p.863). From this perspective, Boyd views civility as a

‘moral obligation borne out of an appreciation of human equality’ (p.863).

From this understanding, civility is explicitly linked to morality and the underlying notion

that acceptance and tolerance of others are prerequisites to the creation of civility. In fact,

Boyd (2006) describes civility as a type of moral disposition that derives from moral equality,

or a moral obligation that all members of society owe to strangers. It has also been

intrinsically linked by Boyd (2006) with the political community, based on the relationship

between the need for political equality between those who are the ruling elite and those who

are ruled. In relation to ASB, it is these notions of civility, respect, and morality that have

been imbued within government initiatives to tackle this perceived social malaise.

Shklar (1998, as cited in Boyd, 2006) has described the typical vices that she claims are

symptomatic of a democratic society, termed ‘undemocratic behaviours’. These include

behaviours such as hypocrisy, arrogance, snobbery and condescension; all regarded as subtle

forms of disrespect and incivility. Shklar hinted that these subtle forms of incivility could be

linked to political crimes and exclusion. These minor instances of incivility affect the kinds

of moral relationships that can lead to more extreme instances of uncivil behaviour and would

include insults, racial slurs, differential treatment and other behaviour that can pave the way

for further dehumanisation (Shklar, 1998, as cited in Boyd, 2006) – all conceivable anti-

social actions.

82

The importance of understanding the link between everyday morality and ASB is further

underpinned by individual factors, for example personality, which have been reported as

influential in whether someone behaves anti-socially or not (Miller and Lynam, 2001). Miller

and Lynam (2001) claimed that personality is important for decision-making processes and

self-regulation of behaviour and can alter that very moment a behaviour occurs.

To summarise, a link between social connectedness and civil cooperation may be improved

through more awareness of other members of society. Promoting civility may help to boost

civil cooperation and strengthen society. In turn, it may be possible to promote notions of

respect and tolerance through increased awareness of other citizens’ values or norms.

Previous government policy has attempted to tackle the perceived social malaise of an

assumed moral decline and lack of respect. The link between everyday morality and ASB has

often been discussed through notions of civility, respect and values. However, individual

factors such as personality could play a role - a role not acknowledged by government

initiatives to tackle ASB, nor attempts to elucidate the underlying causes.

Conclusions

Many factors may influence why a behaviour is perceived as morally wrong or not. ‘Moral

panics’ are an important factor in perceptions of crime, fear and morality. Threats to societal

values, norms and interests are presented in a ‘stylized and stereotypical fashion by the mass

media’ (Cohen, 1972: 1) that amplifies the public concern. Consequently, a change in legal

policy, or a social shift, are prompted by the widespread systemic concern until the problem

is tackled. ASB, Self-regulation and responsibilisation were discussed and it was reported

that there have been many attempts by the UK government to promote self-regulation of

behaviours such as being civil and instilling shared values of respect. Despite this, some

mechanisms were one-sided, lacked mutuality and were directed at specific groups within

society. Moral education was discussed as a potential alternative to penal strategies.

Atypical examples of ASB perpetrated by the assumed law-abiding majority were then

considered, with behaviours such as tax evasion potentially falling under the rubric of ASB.

Furthermore, ASB may be present in other members or groups of society beyond the poor

and lower classes – including the so-called law abiding majority. In order to tackle the moral

83

aspects of ASB, improving social cohesion and civil cooperation may help improve positive

social standards amongst communities. Previous government initiatives have utilised punitive

and enforcement-based measures to tackle ASB, such as via the Respect Agenda (Respect

Task Force, 2006). Promoting tolerance and mutual respect may help tackle the underlying

moral and individual aspects of ASB.

84

Chapter 4.

Methodology

Rationale

A high proportion of research investigating crime or intrinsically related areas has used

quantitative methods (Sherman and Strange, 2004). It has been argued that in criminology,

whilst qualitative research approaches may be under-utilized, they are relevant for enabling

more in-depth data to be collected (Miner-Romanoff, 2012). According to Smith et al. (2009)

qualitative methods of inquiry allow consideration of the complex and variable nature of

criminality, including individual and social contexts. In this regard, Miner-Romanoff (2012)

has claimed that Interpretive Phenomenological Analysis (IPA) can be particularly useful.

She reported from her own investigation that IPA allows researchers to include and reflect on

their own experiences in conjunction with uncovering the underpinning decisions and

motivations of criminal offenders, whilst also eliciting a more in-depth and profound

response from participants. This non-positivist perspective leads to significant improvements

in other areas. Miner-Romanov (2012) has cited examples including: informing more

effective crime control strategies; enlightening the understanding of offenders’ cognitive

processes; and enhancing the generation of more effective policy aimed at increasing

prevention of crime and lowering recidivism. The phenomenological tradition has been

recommended to encourage individuals involved in crime to explain the underlying

mechanisms which led to their criminal behaviour (Seidman, 2006).

IPA is informed by phenomenology, hermeneutics and ideography (Callery et al., 2015).

According to Callery et al. (2015: 63) phenomenology describes ‘the “what” and “how” of

individuals’ experienced phenomena’. Hermeneutics refers to a theory of interpretation that

focuses on the meaning of textual information, for example language that divulges the

intentions and context of a speaker (Smith et al., 2013). Ideography refers to the ‘details and

thorough analysis of small cases’ (Callary et al., 2015). How these three positions influence

the IPA method is effectively described by Callary et al., who stated:

85

IPA is idiographic because a detailed analysis of one case occurs before

moving onto the next. Secondly, IPA is inductive, meaning research questions

are broadly constructed to allow for unanticipated themes to emerge. Interplay

between induction and deduction in data analysis may exist; however, the

inductive approach takes precedence. Thirdly, results are discussed using

existing literature, creating an interrogative element… (Callary et al., 2015:

64)

The current study adopted this approach as it combined the detailed analysis of the

ideography whilst being able to ‘allow for unanticipated themes to emerge’ (Callary et al.,

2015: 64). A discussion grounded in existing literature could then be conducted, allowing

both inductive and deductive aspects of the IPA analysis to interact. This revealed thematic

narratives that were able to be linked to already established research on ASB and everyday

morality.

Bloomberg and Volpe (2012) suggested that qualitative research enables the researcher to

gain the participants’ views and perspectives of the research, and promotes an in-depth,

detailed understanding of a social situation. According to Chamberlain (2013: 53) individuals

are ‘assumed to create their social worlds by organizing their own understandings of it and

giving it meaning’. Furthermore, a researcher can draw on their ‘common sense knowledge to

aid their research and help develop empathic understanding of another person's world view’

as they seek to ‘construct a thick descriptive narrative account of it’ (Chamberlain, 2013: 53).

Moreover, Chamberlain suggested that qualitative researchers tend to highlight the

importance of social context and seek to intuitively build an understanding of causality in

terms of the meaning people assign to their own and other people’s actions.

Qualitative research uses a range of methods including face-to-face interviews, focus groups,

participant observation and documentary analysis to capture and examine lived experience as

well as the meaning people attribute to their actions and the differing socio-cultural worlds

they live their lives in (Chamberlain, 2013). Furthermore, qualitative methods can be used to

explore the lived experience and personal understandings of individuals labelled by society as

deviant and delinquent, the victims of crime, those categorized as convicted criminals

alongside members of the agencies of crime control. As such, qualitative research methods

86

undoubtedly play a foundational role in the development of sociological criminology.

The empirical aspect of this study centred on the use of nine focus groups with residents from

three areas in North-West England, namely Rainford village (St Helens Borough), St Helens

town centre (St Helens Borough) and Skelmersdale (West Lancashire). Focus groups

enabled group interaction and an open discussion of ASB and everyday morality - a method

that is ‘helpful for participants to discuss perceptions, ideas, opinions and thoughts’ (Kruegar

and Casey, 2000, as cited in Onwuegbuzie et al., 2009: 2) and to investigate ‘peoples’ views

or perceptions of, attitudes towards, and experiences of particular areas in life’ (Hyden and

Bulow, 2003: 306).

Location selection

All three areas are near each other, but were selected due to the disparity in their 2010

English Index of Multiple Deprivation (EIMD) rank, produced by the Office for National

Statistics (ONS) (DCLG, 2011). The 2010 EIMD consists of several distinct categories that

comprise an overall measure of deprivation. These categories are: income, employment,

health and disability, education skills and training, barriers to housing and services, crime,

and finally living environment. The EIMD generates a relative ranking of 32,482 Lower

Layer Super Output Areas (LSOAs) within England. (LSOAs have an average of 1,500

residents.) The ranking conveys the most deprived LSOA (being 1), to a high score or rank

conveying the least deprived (32,482).

Skelmersdale represented one of the most deprived locations nationally according to the

EIMD. Rainford was representative of a least deprived location. St Helens provided a blend

of participants with a range of experiences of deprivation. Out of 32,482 LOSA areas,

Skelmersdale town was ranked 2,971. On a more local level, the Digmoor area of

Skelmersdale had a score of just 283, followed by two more very low scores of 541

(Moorside) and Birch Green (662). The Skelmersdale groups were held within the ‘West

Lancashire Ark’, a community and ecumenical centre which is located within the Birch

Green area.

The second location selected for data collection was St Helens town centre. St Helens

represented mixed deprivation ranging from very low ranks (44) to much higher ranks of very

87

little deprivation (30,074). The EIMD ranked St Helens as the 51st most deprived local

authority in England (out of 326) in 2010. Focus groups were held in the St Helens public

library and in the St Helens Millennium Centre (a community hub area).

The third location selected for the focus groups was in Rainford, within the wider St Helens

Borough. Rainford is the third least deprived area within the St Helens Borough with an IMD

ranking of 27,603. On a more local scale there is an area within Rainford which has a very

high IMD ranking of 29,935; hence it is considered to have very little deprivation. The

Rainford focus groups were conducted within a local church hall. The locations of each of the

focus groups were selected as they provided close and efficient access to participants from

each location.

Focus groups

In total there were nine focus groups (three focus groups in each of the three areas). Five to

six participants comprised each focus group (with focus group 2 in St Helens having seven

participants), giving a total of 50 participants across all the groups. In the study there were

thirty-four female participants and sixteen male participants. Seventeen participants were

from Skelmersdale. Fifteen participants were from Rainford and eighteen were from St

Helens. The participants ranged in age from nineteen to sixty-nine.

Focus groups were selected as they provide ‘an economical, fast and efficient method for

obtaining data from multiple participants’ (Kruegar and Casey, 2000, as cited in,

Onwuegbuzie et al., 2009: 2). Focus groups help facilitate a sense of belonging that can help

promote information sharing when participants feel willing to share their views (Vaughn et

al, 1996). Other methods such as semi-structured or structured interviews may not have

provided an environment where participants could interact and discuss their perceptions.

Focus groups enabled the researcher to facilitate participants’ sense of cohesiveness (Peters,

1993) in an environment that created the opportunity for spontaneous responses (Butler,

1996).

Focus groups should bring together a group of people who, under the guidance of a

moderator, engage in a group question and answer discussion. However, as the study

progressed it became necessary to adapt to potential problematic circumstances, such as

88

people withdrawing or becoming unavailable for participation. The focus groups were

conducted in a semi-structured format. An interview schedule was developed (see Appendix

C), although participants could debate and discuss questions interactively. The interview

schedule had fifteen questions organised into four sections. The first question was a rapport

building mechanism for participants to briefly introduce themselves. The second section had

four introductory questions on ASB and everyday morality to invite general discussion. The

next section focused on the relationship between ASB and everyday morality in more depth.

Subsequently, six vignette scenarios with specific accompanying questions (Appendix C)

were provided for participants to discuss. Finally, the fourth section detailed the final

questions to summarise and bring the discussion to a close. Participants were then invited to

ask questions or add further on any aspect of the focus group and thanked for their time.

Each group was allocated a sixty-minute time slot. Participants were recruited through local

organisations and community hubs in each location. They were invited by the researcher to

participate if they met the criteria of living in that location. Recruited participants were then

organised into groups based on a suitable and appropriate time that they were available.

Demographic information was collected about participants, for example what age range they

were in and their residential status. All focus group data were recorded using an audio

recording device and all were transcribed verbatim.

Sampling

Purposive sampling was used for this study. Denovan and Macaskill (2013) have claimed that

the strength of using purposive sampling in IPA research is the assurance that the topic

investigated is relevant for the sample studied. However, ASB has been acknowledged as a

widespread phenomenon (Home Office, 2011). It has also been the recipient of much media

attention and coverage (Flint and Powell, 2009). It was the contention of this current study

that suitable participants could potentially include those who simply have views and beliefs

regarding morality in relation to ASB, or have directly experienced ASB themselves. Whilst

participants were not specifically targeted with regards to having experience of ASB,

individuals were selected from areas with various levels of deprivation. In previous chapters

it has already been reported that ASB has often been framed as an issue in deprived contexts

and interventions were aimed at the poor (Bate, 2017; Crossley and Lambert, 2017; Sayer,

2017). Thus, the study included participants from a location that could be considered

89

deprived according to the 2010 IMD (Skelmersdale) as well as a mixed area (St Helens) and a

more affluent area (Rainford).

In terms of what size of sample should be used for IPA, a typical study could include any

amount ranging from one participant to fifteen participants (Bramley and Eatough, 2005).

However, there has been evidence suggesting that smaller samples are more useful, as too

many may cause difficulty in analysing qualitative data (Smith, 2003). Focus groups are not

intended to develop a consensus regarding views on a topic, but instead seek to collect

various perceptions and beliefs regarding a subject (Kruegar and Casey, 2000). The bare

minimum of participants should be no less than three focus groups and between 4-12

participants per group (Kruegar and Casey, 2000). For Morgan (1998) there should be 6-10

participants. This should allow enough data to be collected and analysed. However, Merton et

al. (1990: 137) commented on focus group composition, noting that:

…the size of the group should manifestly be governed by two

considerations… it should not be so large as to be unwieldy or to preclude

adequate participation by most members nor should it be so small that it fails

to provide substantially greater coverage than that of an interview with one

individual.

Taking this into consideration, a minimum of five participants and maximum of ten would

enable a balance between quantity and quality of data for IPA. Krueger (1994) mentions that

smaller group sizes are preferable when participants have a great deal to share about the

topic, although Krueger (1994) also states that larger group sizes provide for a greater range

of perceptions in more general terms. The number of focus groups deemed appropriate for

valid research varies from eight to fifty-two, with a tendency for the range to be mainly from

ten to fifteen (Deacon et al., 1999, cited in Bryman, 2012). As noted, the current investigation

included nine focus groups.

Use of vignettes

The current study utilised tailored vignettes to assist with the data collection on perceptions

of everyday morality and ASB. Vignettes have been used by researchers from a wide range of

disciplines. They can ‘capture how meanings, beliefs, judgements and actions are

90

situationally positioned’ (Barter and Reynolds, 1999: 308). According to Hazel (1995: 2, as

cited in Barter and Reynolds, 1999: 308) vignettes are stories that provide: ‘Concrete

examples of people and their behaviours on which participants can offer comment or

opinion’. The researcher can utilise these stories to generate a discussion and facilitate debate

on any key terms used in the participants’ dialogue or comments. Early research has

purported that utilising vignettes can enable the nature of values that underlie moral decisions

to be extrapolated (Wilks, 2004). Wilks contends that vignettes can assist our understanding

of the relationship between an individual’s actions, values and perceptions.

Using open-ended vignette scenarios enabled a degree of flexibility in participant responses

and facilitated a greater depth of data (West, 1982, as cited in Finch, 1987). Participants

become empowered to define the situation according to their own cognitions and ideas (West,

1982 as cited in Finch, 1987). However, a point to consider when designing vignettes is the

requirement to provide a sufficient level of context; otherwise the situation may be too vague

and fail to evoke a response. The vignettes adopted for this study provided context to ensure

participants could generate a response. When participants were unable to respond, the

researcher could utilise questions that acted as prompts to promote discussion. For example,

vignette one had questions to complement the scenario including; ‘is it morally permissible to

behave this way?’ (Appendix C).

Barter and Reynolds (1999) note that providing sufficient, contextual material gives

respondents additional information that may influence their decisions and judgments. The

vignette description should be as neutral and bias free as possible. Due diligence was taken to

‘bracket’ the researcher’s own preconceptions when devising the scenario. For example, what

behaviours the researcher perceives to be immoral, anti-social, or both should not heavily

influence the context of the vignettes.

A further key point to consider when utilising vignettes is whether they will be used in

conjunction with another investigative method. Barter and Reynolds (1999) reported that

vignettes have frequently been employed successfully with other data collection methods.

The current approach comprised both semi-structured focus group questions and vignettes.

The use of vignettes provided opportunities for comparisons, enabling different perspectives

to be collected regarding a situation (Barter and Reynold, 1999). This had the benefit of

identifying and isolating some individual factors to be considered during analysis, such as

91

what behaviours were perceived as anti-social and moral or immoral. Therefore, whilst

having disparate groups may be divisive and a potential limitation, the research suggests that

the wider context of different groups’ perceptions and views can be explored; thus, enabling

the exploration of differences in interpretation regarding a certain phenomenon (Barter and

Reynolds, 1999). Despite this, there were some disparities in the sample of the current focus

groups. For example, there was no specific age range, background or other factors as criteria

for inclusion in the study. This may have hindered the identification of some characteristics

that may influence perceptions of ASB and everyday morality.

According to Neff (1979) vignettes are most effective whenever the situation they are meant

to represent is perceived as accurate by the participants. There is previous research that has

attempted to construct vignettes whilst bearing this idea in mind, for example, Harden et al.,

(1999, as cited in Barter and Reynolds, 1999). However, when utilising vignettes, Barter and

Reynolds (1999) explained that it is important to consider that some scenarios can potentially

be distressing. Furthermore, the act of telling participants that a scenario is based upon a real

story may increase the risk of distress, for example if the participant can relate to the story or

is in a similar position.

This necessitated careful consideration for the researcher. In the current study, all participants

were informed prior to their involvement that they may withdraw at any point if they are in

any way distressed. Furthermore, if the researcher either observed or was made aware of any

participant becoming distressed due to a scenario presented in a vignette, regarding ASB,

then they did not have to remain involved and could withdraw. That said, Barter and

Reynolds (1999) found that participants’ ability to engage with the narrative of a vignette

may have been enhanced if they had personal experience of the situation described.

Therefore, this could be a strength of the present study.

Finally, another point to consider when using vignettes is comparing data sets across groups.

For example, Barter and Reynolds (1999) previously found that comparing participants’

responses from more than one type of group (residential workers’ experiences and young

people’s accounts) can present a problem when participants provide different amounts of

information regarding a question or vignette than another. They utilised semi-structured focus

group questions in addition to vignettes, reporting that there was ‘different degrees of

recollection’ (Barter and Reynolds,1999: 320) between events recalled in the study that both

92

groups of participants had experience of. The subsequent effect of this was that potential

‘mediating factors’ can be missed due to vague recollection or confusion between two

different stories regarding the same phenomenon.

Another strength of vignettes is their ability to be employed as ‘ice-breakers’ (Hazel, 1995: 2,

as cited in Barter and Reynolds, 1999). Indeed, Hazel claimed they can function to instigate

the initial discussion within a focus group. Furthermore, they may act as a ‘cool-down’ when

nearing the finish of an interview, or to broaden the focus of the study from the more personal

aspects of the experience to the more abstract (Wade, 1999). The versatile nature of vignettes

is further exemplified by the variety in issues that may be investigated utilising this

technique. For example, Knutsen et al. (2010) adapted the vignette method to investigate

moral judgment. Knutsen et al. (2010) noted that myriad types of vignettes have been

employed by previous research on moral beliefs and judgment. However, one issue they

noted was the lack of standardised, common vignettes based in real life. The current study

does not employ a set of standardised vignettes due to there being a lack of research using

this technique in criminological research investigating ASB.

Ethical considerations

Ethical approval was attained from the Edge Hill University Ethics Committee prior to any

activity involving participants. The University’s Code of Ethics as well as the British Society

of Criminology’s Statement of Ethics were strictly adhered to throughout all stages of the

research. The research addressed four ethical principles (Diener and Crandell, 1978, as cited

in, Bryman 2012: 135):

1. Whether there is harm to participants;

2. Whether there is a lack of informed consent;

3. Whether there is an invasion of privacy; and

4. Whether deception is involved.

Harm to participants

It was not expected that participants would be harmed or at risk of psychological or physical

harm during this study or that research participation would be disturbing. All participation

was entirely voluntary. Precautionary measures to safeguard participants included respect to

93

confidentiality and maintenance of confidential records, ensuring anonymity that individuals

were not identifiable or identified, and for information to be suitably stored in compliance

with the Data Protection Act (1998). If participants were distressed, felt uncomfortable or did

not wish to answer certain questions they had the option to not answer any questions or to

terminate their involvement in the project.

Informed consent

All participants were provided with an information sheet prior to collection of any data

detailing the nature and requirements of the study. Importantly, all participants were fully

informed of their right to withdraw from the study within four weeks of data collection and

were fully debriefed after their participation.

Invasion of privacy

Participants’ rights to privacy were not violated by agreeing voluntarily to take part in the

research study. Confidentiality of taking part, specifically not being named, identified or any

personal details being revealed was confirmed verbally prior to the commencement of the

study. It was also conveyed within the consent form. This reiterated participants’ right to

anonymity. Right to anonymity was not guaranteed if serious harm or criminality were

revealed. However, this did not present as an issue during the study. Participants were given

the right to withdraw prior to commencement if concerned in relation to this. To further

protect confidentiality participants’ data were securely stored. The audio transcripts and

electronic copies of the data were password protected and any identifiable data destroyed

following full transcription and analysis of the participants’ data. To further protect

participants’ confidentiality each were given a pseudonym. No data used will be able to lead

to the identification of the participant.

Deception

There was no deception involved in the research project. All participants were given a verbal

explanation outlining the nature of the research study and their participation, and written

details in the consent form which verified their willingness to continue. Following the

research participation, individuals were given a verbal explanation and written debrief sheet

to conclude the research task. Transparency, honesty and integrity were adhered to

throughout.

94

In addition, ethical principles, personal safety, well-being and risk for the researcher were

duly considered. It was considered there was no reason for concern prior to or throughout the

process, especially mindful of environmental factors, participants, the nature of the research

project, the type of venue for hosting and the data collection.

Rationale for method of analysis

The study aimed to investigate beliefs regarding ASB and everyday morality through focus

groups involving the open discussion and debate of individuals’ experiences, beliefs and

perceptions. The phenomenological approach is suitable if investigating the lived experiences

of individuals who have ‘the internal experience of being conscious of something’

(Groenwald, 2004: 4). The suggestion is that phenomenology aims to capture the social and

psychological phenomena through examining the perceptions of participants (Groenwald,

2004). In phenomenology, individuals who have personally witnessed or experienced a

specific phenomenon are normally chosen for study (Groenwald, 2014). It had been noted

that IPA has not got a single, prescribed method of how to analyse data. However, Palmer et

al. (2010) acknowledge there is a common set of guidelines that may be applied flexibly to

using IPA. This is dependent on the analytical requirements from the data (Reid et al., 2005,

as cited in Palmer et al., 2010). IPA is an iterative and inductive process that entails following

these steps:

1. Reflection on preconceptions and processes (Smith, 2007);

2. Line-by-line analysis (coding) of experiential claims, concerns and understandings of

participants with close attention to the language used (Larkin et al., 2006);

3. Identifying emergent patterns of themes (Eatough and Smith, 2008); and

4. Dialogue between researcher and data in terms of what the participants’ concerns

might mean within this context (Larkin et al., 2006; Smith; 2004), helping to induce

an interpretive account of the data.

These steps informed each stage of the data analysis and were utilised as prompts to engage

with the data and to reflect on aspects which may have required more focus during analysis

(as recommended by Palmer et al., 2010). These steps were malleable in the way that they

evolved during analysis and were influenced by focus group variables such as when questions

were asked, or elicited strong debate between participants. This was to ensure that, instead of

95

these steps being strict guidelines they would conversely complement the individual steps

taken to conduct IPA and enrich the analysis. Participants’ experiential narratives were

recorded whilst the researcher simultaneously noted additional commentary during the focus

groups. For example, it was noted how claims contributed to the facilitation of the group

discussion.

According to Bloomberg and Volpe (2012) phenomenological research has origins in the

philosophical works of Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) and subsequent philosophical

discussions by Heidegger (1889–1976) and Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961). More recently,

Moustakas (1994: 11, as cited in Bloomberg and Volpe, 2012) has stated that,

‘phenomenological research involves studying a small number of subjects through extensive

and prolonged engagement to develop patterns and relationships of meaning’. Husserl (1970,

as cited in Dowling, 2007) contended that the lived world is understood as what individuals

experience before reflection. Husserl’s approach entails attempting to comprehend the

quintessential features of a phenomenon as free as possible from cultural context. Caelli

(2000: 132) described Husserl’s phenomenological approach as one that ‘requires that

descriptions of experience be gleaned before it has been reflected on’. Husserl purported that

individuals need to ‘bracket’ out the outer world in addition to individual biases to achieve

the level of neutrality necessary to truly understand a participant’s subjective experience.

According to Valle et al. (1989, as cited in Dowling, 2007: 132) a phenomenologist must

‘bracket one’s preconceptions and presuppositions’ by making them as overt and lucid as

possible. This can be achieved through phenomenological reduction, a process described by

Valle et al. (1989: 11) who stated that ‘reduction’ is when an individual ‘reduces the world as

it is considered in the natural attitude to a world of pure phenomena or, more poetically, to a

purely phenomenal realm’. Phenomenological reduction enables the researcher to achieve an

understanding of the subject as free from prejudice as possible, so it can be precisely

described and understood. Parse (2001: 79) described this as ‘the process of coming to know

the phenomenon as it shows itself as described by participants’.

Van Manen contended that phenomenologists focus on describing ‘what all participants have

in common’, the fundamental purpose of research being to ‘reduce individual experiences

with a phenomenon to a description of the universal essence’ (as cited in Bloomberg and

Volpe, 2012: 32). He further suggested that phenomenological research involves ‘dynamic

interplay’ between research activities:

96

The researcher focuses on a phenomenon or lived experience that is an abiding

concern.

The researcher reflects on essential themes that constitute the nature of this lived

experience.

The researcher then writes a description of the phenomenon, maintaining a strong

relationship to the topic of inquiry.

Phenomenology is not only description, however; it is also an interpretive process in which

the researcher interprets the meaning of the lived experience. As Moustakes (1994, as cited in

Robson, 2011: 492) has stated, ‘the concept of epoche involves bracketing one's own

experiences as much as possible to take a fresh perspective of the phenomenon under

consideration’. The word ‘epoche’ means to ‘refrain from judgement or abstain from the

everyday, typical approach to perceiving things.’ (Robson, 2011: 492). However, Moustakes

(1994) noted that ‘epoche’ is not something frequently attained in qualitative research.

In a similar vein, Vanderstoep and Johnstone (2009: 207) describe ‘a unique feature of

phenomenology as being the demand on the researcher to suspend all judgments about what

are real, suggesting phenomenologists maintain that human experience makes sense to those

who live it.’ (2009: 207). The requirement to refrain from typical judgment and ‘bracket’ the

researcher’s own experience was required for the current approach. It is worthwhile to note,

however, that some have debated whether it is possible to divorce our own values from

research (Becker, 1967). For example, the sociologist Howard Becker (1967) once proposed

that a value-neutral approach to research is not possible. He stated:

… one would have to assume, as some apparently do, that it is indeed possible

to do research that is uncontaminated by personal and political sympathies. I

propose to argue that it is not possible and, therefore, that the question is not

whether we should take sides, since we inevitably will, but rather whose side

we are on.’ (Becker, 1967: 239).

Essentially, this may hold true for disciplines such as philosophy, criminology and other

academic disciples. Millie (2016) agreed that value or bias free research is not possible,

stating that ‘impartiality is an impossibility’ (2016: 15). Millie (2016) gives the example of

criminologists, who regardless of their persuasion make value-judgments when deciding what

97

is important to study and which method to adopt. Becker arrived at the conclusion that often

researchers are likely to have deep sympathy with participants. For example, when studying

those who engage in deviant behaviour, researchers are likely to sympathise and attribute

their behaviour to ‘something going on that puts the deviants in the position they are in’

(Becker, 1967: 240). Becker claimed that ‘we must always’ look at the matter from

someone’s point of view.’ (1967: 245). A researcher cannot avoid taking sides; the issue is

whether this distorts findings or makes the analysis ‘useless’ (Becker, 1967: 245).

The best method of attempting to counter this is through utilizing research techniques as

impartially as possible and avoiding sentimentality throughout the research process (Becker,

1967). Becker noted that this is not a solution, rather a method to ‘satisfy the demands of our

science by always making clear the limits of what we have studied, beyond which our

findings cannot be safely applied’ (1967: 247). Becker advocated the following to provide

some minor reprieve when conducting research:

…limit our conclusions carefully, recognize the hierarchy of credibility for

what it is, and field as best we can the accusations and doubts that will surely

be our fate. (1967: 247)

Thus, a value-judgment free process is not possible. In line with Becker, the current study

examined - as much as possible - ASB and everyday morality through the eyes of

participants. Whilst the role of the researcher may not be wholly unbiased or value-neutral,

Becker maintained that at the minimum effort can be made to avoid any distortions that might

affect the data to ‘satisfy the demands of our science’ (1967: 247). Furthermore, value

judgements are a key factor in determining what people, governments and societies deem to

be appropriate or inappropriate behaviour (Millie, 2016). Thus, what constitutes criminal or

anti-social behaviour is linked to value judgments – and these are of interest to criminological

enquiries (Millie, 2016). Ultimately, the aim of the researcher is to understand the experience

of the participants (Vanderstoep and Johnstone, 2009) as much as is possible.

IPA has been described by Smith and Osborn (2003: 51) as a method of inquiry whereby ‘the

participants are trying to make sense of their world; the researcher is trying to make sense of

the participants trying to make sense of their world’. This was particularly suitable for this

study, which was seeking to understand how people make decisions about what is or is not

98

ASB, and how they perceive the role of morality in ASB. Participants were asked to give

detailed accounts of their experiences of ASB and the thought processes that underpinned

their experiences. Attention was given to the role everyday morality played in these accounts.

Another advantage of IPA was that the participants themselves need not have directly

experienced ASB, as IPA is more interested in perceptions.

The completion of IPA analysis of the focus group transcripts involved roughly four stages

(Smith and Eatough, 2006). The first stage of analysis involved several close, detailed

readings of the transcripts. This was to give the researcher a good overview of the participant

accounts and a feel for the ‘story’ they were telling. This ensured that the final analysis

remained true to the original narrative. The second stage involved the identification of initial

themes, which were then organised into master and sub themes. The third stage entailed

reading through the transcripts and organizing themes.

It was important that quotes relating to each theme were highlighted, as this ensured the

original meaning of what the participants were saying was not lost under a vague theme

heading. Once the themes had been decided, stage three involved refining the themes in more

detail, and identifying links between them. For example, if ‘emotions’ was one master theme,

how does this relate to the other master themes, and what can these relationships tell us about

the phenomena under study? The fourth stage involved bringing everything together to

present a narrative of the participants’ lived experiences of the phenomena under study. At

this point, however, it is acknowledged that the account produced cannot be separated from

the researcher’s own interpretation of that account. The end stage of analysis is described as

‘…the interplay between the interpretative activity of the researcher and the participants’

account of their experience (Smith and Eatough, 2012: 450).

Research appraisal

Tracy (2010) has constructed a simple checklist for appraising and/or thinking about quality

criteria for qualitative research. This was used for the current study and includes the

following eight criteria:

1. Worthy topic – relevant, interesting and significant, etc.

2. Rich vigour – rich data supplied in abundance and appropriately.

99

3. Sincerity – the researcher is reflexive about values and biases and is transparent in

approach.

4. Credibility – implements practices such as thick descriptions, triangulation and

respondent validation.

5. Resonance – has an effecting impact on readers.

6. Significant contribution – makes an impact in terms of such outcomes as theory,

practice and morality.

7. Ethical – considers and engages in ethical practices.

8. Meaningful coherence – addresses what it claims to address, uses appropriate

methods, and links research questions, literature findings and interpretations.

In conjunction with note-taking and memo-taking, the research consistently referred to this

criteria in striving to attain ‘qualitative quality’ (Tracy, 2010: 849). This included maintaining

copies of raw data such as transcripts, procedure notes and making the research process

transparent. Seale (1999) described this as an audit process in which the researcher provides

‘a methodologically self-critical account of how the research was done’ (Seale, 1999: 468).

Limitations of the current study

The qualitative nature of the study relied on a semi-structured format to maintain direction

within the discussions. It therefore required questions or actions to act as ‘nudges’ or prompts

to further the discussion. Such prompts may have elicited repeat stories or viewpoints

(spiralling) but may also have created a new account as a response (Burck, 2005). Burck

suggests prior experiences, although beneficial, may be detrimental during the data collection

process regarding researcher responses. Internal dilemmas when responding as a researcher

can be difficult to overcome. It is important to maintain self-awareness when responding and

reflexivity during transcript analysis.

A Strength of IPA was that it explicitly acknowledged that the researcher brought their own

views and experiences to the research situation, and that this may have influenced how the

findings were interpreted. This potentially could have been an issue in the current study

where just one researcher was responsible for all aspects of the research process. Although,

potential researcher bias is a factor that must be considered a limitation, according to Yardley

100

(as cited in Crossley, 2000), this is a common criticism of qualitative research especially

when prompting during research and when analysing the data.

To minimise potential researcher bias great care was taken to ensure there was no leading

questions, assisted by advice from senior colleagues. In the analysis phase, a key way of

reducing researcher bias was to ensure negative-case analysis. This meant that quotes and

experiences which did not align with dominant themes were also presented in the final

analysis. That is, exceptions as well as the rule were sought. This should have prevented the

researchers’ own interpretation of the participants’ accounts having too much influence over

the analysis. As a further check, the focus group transcripts and the analysis were offered to

the participants at the end of the study so that they could determine if they felt their views

have been accurately represented.

Another method to counteract researcher bias was by attempting to attain an objective as

possible record of the data set. The investigation enabled the open discussion and interaction

between participants, which according to Kruegar and Casey (2000), is a strength of focus

group research. The focus group structure places emphasis on group dynamics such as

debate, and contextual relationships shaped through this discussion that minimise the role of

the researcher. There was also the risk that the specific sample of participants recruited may

limit the generalisability of findings to the wider population.

An important limitation to acknowledge is the difficulties involved within Interpretative

Phenomenology. Lopez and Willis (2004) identify one such difficulty concerning

Heidegger’s (1962) concept of freedom. Leonard (1999, as cited in Lopez and Willis, 2004:

727) refers to this concept as ‘situational freedom’, suggesting that individuals may make

their own decisions and choices; however, such actions are circumscribed by their lived

experiences as well as social, cultural and political factors involved in said experiences

(Burck, 2005). In the case of this study, the use of participants purely from the North West of

England would inevitably produce lived experiences based on similar social, cultural and

political factors. It would therefore be unviable to extrapolate findings to a wider population

where such factors would most likely differ and therefore produce distinctly different

experiences and perspectives.

101

The situational freedom produces a further difficulty of IPA in the challenge of correct

interpretation. Not only does one have to interpret participants’ narratives, but one must

interpret the narratives in relation to the context of social, cultural and political factors

(Smith, 1987, as cited in Lopez and Willis, 2004). The advantage of prior experience and

expertise allows more meaningful extractions to be made from such narratives (Maxwell,

2005); however, the interpretation must be made from the lived experience perspective.

Heidegger accepted that it would be impossible to rid oneself of background understanding

throughout interpretation. Yet, it is important to remain open to new ideas and concepts so as

not to become restricted by existing theories and concepts (Groenewald, 2004). Conroy

(2003: 21) refers to a concept of a ‘double internal tap’ whereby the researcher ‘absorbs’

what is being said and separates ‘their own interpretations from the participants’. Tools such

as personal reflections and note-taking, aid in acknowledging and tackling such limitations

(Smith et al., 2009).

A reflective diary could have been used throughout the duration of the study (Elliot et al.,

1999). However, this was not done as there was potential for a reflexive diary to dilute the

researcher’s attempt to achieve a high level of phenomenological reduction. Starks and

Trinidad (2007: 1376) have claimed that a researcher ‘must be honest and vigilant about her

own perspective, pre-existing thoughts and beliefs, and developing hypotheses’. To achieve

this, researchers must ‘recognise and set aside (but do not abandon) their a priori knowledge

and assumptions, with the analytic goal of attending to the participants’ accounts with an

open mind’ (Starks and Trinidad, 2007: 1376). The researcher maintained notes throughout

all stages of the study.

Previous research has reported that if part of a discussion leads the open debate of a sensitive

or even potentially offensive subject then participants may not reveal their inner beliefs

(Whitaker et al., 2003). In the current study, there was the potential limitation that the open

discussion of ASB may have evoked a negative emotional response and limited the revealing

of inner views. However, participants did have the option to not answer questions and were

open to leave the group if they felt the need to do so.

102

Chapter 5.

Analysis and Discussion

Introduction

Interpretive Phenomenological Analysis (IPA) of the focus group data revealed a variety of

interrelated themes. The themes were coded on a case-by-case basis, developed from

emergent themes that were later analysed with all data to identify recurrent themes. This

ensured that the themes reflected both shared and divergent perceptions regarding ASB and

everyday morality. To effectively capture the participants’ subjective experiences, there was

less focus on imposing distinctiveness within each theme. The analysis focused on aspects of

the data that best represented the participants’ own lived experiences of ASB and everyday

morality. Whilst acknowledgment was made of the variances between and within the three

locations of the present investigation (Rainford, St Helens and Skelmersdale), there was a

pivotal focus on the participants’ own individual perceptions. However, similar experiences

and perceptions regarding both ASB and everyday morality were evident during the analysis,

regardless of locale or other demographic characteristics. This enabled a broader scope of

findings that could be analysed in both an individual and group context.

The first theme comprised perceptions of what constitutes ASB. This provides a foundation

upon which perceptions and experiences of ASB could be established within each focus

group. The themes then progressed into more focused aspects of ASB and perceptions

regarding:

What constitutes ASB;

The consequences, and potential antecedents of ASB;

Deprivation and ASB; and finally

Moral explanations of ASB.

103

The themes regarding moral explanations of ASB focus on perceptions of morality and

reciprocity, and what it means to be moral or immoral. Following on, perceptions centre on

whether there is a link between ASB and immorality, ASB and consequences, and

relationships between parents and morality.

Perceptions of what constitutes ASB

The rhetoric discussed earlier in this thesis regarding the nature and definition of ASB was

echoed by the participants from the lower status Skelmersdale focus groups. When asked

about their thoughts on ASB there was a familiar range of examples reported:

First thing that comes to my mind is gangs… threatening behaviour and all of

the things just said you know noisy neighbours and that sort of thing, erm…

swearing at you and that sort of abuse, you know its gangs and threatening

behaviour. (P.4. Skelmersdale, Focus Group 2)

…for me it’s things that I can see I can put a label on as being ASB such as

graffiti, willful damage of property, that kind of thing. (P.4, Skelmersdale

Focus Group 3)

erm… anti-social behaviour is anything that affects the area or the people in

the area and things like that, so graffiti or causing damage to building or

garages and things… or even being intimidating if there are like kids in groups

that could become intimidating to people. Things like that, or any kind of

disturbance or disruption to how people go about their lives and things like

that, and any form or way of disrupting someone else is a form of being anti-

social. (P.3, Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

It has previously been claimed that ASB is socially constructed and the interpretation of what

ASB is may be entirely subjective (Brown, 2004; Mackenzie et al., 2010; Morgado and Vale

Dias, 2013; Heap, 2014). It was also noted that ASB may be determined more by perception

and intolerance rather than a behaviour being ‘anti-social’ (Millie, 2006; Mackenzie et al.,

2010). As previously noted, ASB can be influenced by factors such as our own level of

tolerance and behavioural expectations within differing contexts.

104

In this thesis, participant views of whether a behaviour is anti-social, or not, appeared to vary

in accordance with perceptions of acceptability and potential consequences on others. An

issue identified in chapters 1 and 2 was how the subjective definition of ASB impacts upon

public perceptions of what constitutes ASB. Interestingly, Heap (2014) revealed that

community tolerance towards ASB was perceived to be low. This was attributed to the

cultural dynamics of the micro-geographies that had been studied. Thus, tolerance may differ

in accordance with different neighbourhood communities.

Many people with competing views, expectations and values all inhabit the same space,

particularly in urban environments. Millie (2006) has argued that individuals have variations

in what behaviour they expect within public spaces. These result in competing ideas of what

behaviours are deemed acceptable and what are deemed anti-social. Consequently, he

claimed this has impacts on people’s willingness to accept or tolerate different behaviours. As

noted, tolerating behaviour, rather than seeking to condemn it, may be the more positive

solution to dealing with that which is perceived as ‘different’. There indeed could be

multifarious subtypes of ASB which are socially-determined constructs, particularly by our

own subjective standards of what acceptable or unacceptable behaviours are, and how

tolerant we are of such behaviours. For instance, in a higher status focus group in Rainford

(Focus Group 1), a participant acknowledged the subjective aspects of ASB:

[ASB is] people behaving in a way that is objectionable to other people, but

it’s also to do with people’s perceptions, what a person might think, a certain

thing is anti-social and another person might think that’s not anti-social

behaviour you know. So there are different views and different perceptions of

what’s going on in society and I think it’s, erm… common sense assumptions,

people make common sense assumptions about people and then they go on

about it. (P.1, Rainford Focus Group 1)

It is evident from this perspective that what is regarded as ASB may be different from one

person to another. For example, whilst many participants acknowledged the ‘usual’ types of

ASB such as noise pollution, loitering and littering, other not so common descriptions of

ASB were mentioned:

105

I mean for me it’s something quite similar to that… It can be behaviour that’s

against… like the unwritten, like you said, norms and values of society and it

could be something that harms, behaviour that harms, the social well-being of

other people. (P.2, St Helens Focus Group 3)

This perception was one of a minority in the study, although it was not the only response that

indicated that anything may be ASB if it is against the ‘norms and values’ of society. This

notion was further reiterated by another participant in the same focus group:

Erm… Well my first thoughts are… it’s kind of all about perception, what is

anti-social to one person may not be to another… so what comes into my mind

first is anything that goes against the sort of unwritten rules and regulations of

society that guide our everyday behaviour. If something you do, goes out of

your way, to cause harm, harassment or abuse towards another individual, then

that itself is ASB. That’s [what] my first thoughts are of it. (P.1, St Helens

Focus Group 3)

There is an acknowledgment here that motivation is a defining aspect of ASB. Again, the

participant mentions that there are ‘unwritten rules and regulations’ that society should follow

in daily life. However, there is also mention of harassment and abuse, which is similar to

recent understandings of what constitutes ASB. According to the Home Office (2012) the

term ‘anti-social behaviour’ describes the everyday nuisances, disorderly and criminal

behaviours of concern to local people, or those behaviours that were not a priority for police

forces and local authorities. Similarly, Brown (2013) reported that ASB is an umbrella term

for low-level nuisance behaviours, criminality and public disorder. This conceptualisation of

ASB remained steadfast for the majority of focus group participants. The next section

considers youthful misbehaviour.

Youthful ASB

Participants had different perceptions of youth and ASB, as well as varied perceptions of

parental responsibility for youth ASB. Many respondents reciprocated the notion that ASB is

a youth phenomenon, although some acknowledged that it was stereotype:

106

I suppose it’s the stigma associated with groups of youths isn’t it… you’re

intimidated by… so even if they’re not doing anything wrong, you could just

think they are… by your own morals and stigmas. (P.1, Skelmersdale Focus

Group 1)

However, more common perceptions of what ASB is, or who is often noted as the cause of

ASB, were iterated by other participants:

ASB, ’cause I’m getting on a bit, was yobs in my day so… that’s what comes

into my mind straight away is just kids roaming the streets and doing bad stuff

basically. (P.5, Skelmersdale Focus Group 3)

Erm… disrespectful… Anti-social… and going against the rules I always

think of… actually I agree with you, one of the first things that popped into

my head was male youths…. That’s awful isn’t it, stereotyping, but it was.

You always see it on the news. (P.1, Rainford Focus Group 3)

Other typical opinions served to reaffirm conventional views regarding the perpetrators of

ASB:

erm… my thoughts on ASB are… driving through the village and seeing

groups of young teenagers hanging around, sitting on benches in fairly large

groups and… being loud and noisy, maybe even walking past them and

feeling a bit intimidated by them. (P.2, Rainford Focus Group 2)

erm… yeah I guess just groups of young people loitering around… erm…

people just wanting to cause havoc towards other people… Pretty much what

you two have said I suppose [agreeing with P.1 and P.2]. (P.3, Rainford Focus

Group 2)

Across all focus groups there was implicit - or sometimes explicit - reference to youths,

young people, teenagers, and juveniles. This has been reinforced by evidence suggesting that

certain groups are more often perceived to be responsible for ASB than others (see for

instance, Brunger, 2008). Similar reports were evident in the Skelmersdale Focus Groups:

107

… yeah a lot of times it’s tied into like youths and that isn’t it? So, like youths

hanging around on the street causing trouble and that… (P.3, Skelmersdale

Focus Group 1)

However, not all participants linked ASB only to young members of society. For instance,

according to one participant ASB is linked to youths and those ‘a bit rough lookin’’. Another

highlighted the impact on ‘the peace of other people’:

erm I think of youths… or people who are a bit rough lookin’… hanging out at

night and trying to provoke people who are walking past… and you know like

drinking in the street… things that may make people feel uncomfortable. (P.4,

Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

erm… I think ASB is all of those things… erm… and also I think it’s things

like, erm… people dropping litter, speeding through villages when the speed

limit is lower, erm, generally causing a nuisance and upsetting the peace of

other people living in communities, causing trouble that kind of thing. (P.4,

Rainford Focus Group 2)

There were myriad personal experiences of ASB within each area of the study, with only a

minority of participants admitting some involvement in ASB themselves. Interestingly,

Participant 4, from Rainford Focus Group 2, shifted attention from youth behaviour onto the

broader population by discussing ‘speeding through villages’.

Some of the participants’ accounts suggested that ASB has serious consequences. For

example,

… and where we’ve lived we’ve had eggs thrown at window, because we

didn’t fit in, because it was a street where it was like Beirut, because we didn’t

fit in and because we kept ourselves to ourselves, it was ‘oh throw eggs at

their window, throw stones at their window they’re not one of us they’re not

part of our culture’ and whatever… you know… (P.3, St Helens Focus Group

1)

108

Participants from all focus groups told stories of ASB in their lives. It became evident that

they had either first-hand experience of ASB, or they knew another individual or group that

had experienced ASB. Perceptions of ASB were heavily influenced by these stories, by the

negative impacts that ASB has had - but also in recognizing that what is anti-social to one is

not necessarily anti-social to another.

In summary, across all three areas in the study participants gave vivid descriptions of events

and understandings of what ASB means to them. Some agreed that ASB is subjective and

difficult to define. Furthermore, perceptions often reflected the idea that ASB is linked to

youths, although some recognized this as a stereotype. Perceptions of ASB and youths were

often intertwined with negative attitudes and ideas, with a focus on the consequences of such

behaviour. The next section further expands upon perceptions of ASB, focusing on the issues

and perceived impacts of ASB.

Issues of understanding ASB and impacts

There was a consistent focus by participants on the harmful and negative impacts of ASB,

particularly the impacts that ASB can have on victims, whether themselves of others. For

example, the following participants from St Helens Focus Group 1 recounted what ASB is to

them:

I’ve had me car scratched up, I’ve had me windows smashed in, I’ve had nails

put into me tyres (P.2)

being frightened of going past gangs (P.3)

yeah I’ve been attacked in me own house, I’ve been robbed in me own house

em… (P.1)

An intriguing subtext to the participants’ discussion of ASB is how they often could not help

recount what ASB is without describing some experience or narrative that reflects the impact

of it. In these statements, ASB was initially discussed with reference to physical damage and

vandalism to property. Participant two had tyres damaged, whilst participant one was

109

attacked and robbed. Such behaviour may be criminal, yet participants construed these acts as

anti-social behaviour. To these participants ASB had physical and emotional impacts, such as

participant three who felt ASB related to ‘being frightened’. Earlier it was reported that, even

if some behaviours and offences do not have a significant impact on one’s life, physically or

otherwise, they can still be considered a threat to people’s quality of life (Croall, 2004, as

cited in Croall, 2009). In Skelmersdale, one focus group discussion exemplified this:

I remember when… I used to play in a park with my friends, and we’d get like

new equipment in the park, and a week later it has been damaged and broken,

then there was no fun for anyone… It’s just completely destroyed, setting fire

to things and just ruining things… and it just affected everybody else and it

was no fun for anyone. (P.1, Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

Following this, a further two participants in the same group described similar stories of ASB

and the impacts it had on their lives. Yet, it is important to note, however, that early survey

evidence from 2004-2005 has suggested that over two thirds of the population in England and

Wales did not experience any negative impacts from ASB (Millie, 2006; Upson, 2006).

In addition to rich descriptions of their own personal experiences of ASB, some respondents

acknowledged how the perpetrators of ASB may not even be aware of the consequences, or

perceive their actions as anti-social. While perception is key to understanding ASB, perhaps

so too is education. For instance, according to one participant from Skelmersdale:

erm… well with loitering I think some people think that hanging around like

that is naughty… but I suppose… you have got to think well what else have

they got to do? If they’re too young to get jobs or they’re not in school, it’s

either that or staying indoors playing games, erm… so I suppose it is hanging

around doing nothing, but at the same time they’re socializing as well, getting

together… so…. Unless they’re being disruptive or causing distress to

others… it just depends on the situation really (P.1, Skelmersdale Focus

Group 1)

110

One participant in another group mentioned how someone explained that they had

experienced what would be perceived as ASB, yet disagreed that this was anti-social,

supporting Squires’ (2006) emphasis on context and perception:

… I’ve witnessed what other people have told me is anti-social behaviour, but

I haven’t actually agreed… like gangs of youths who… where I live near,

hadn’t actually done anything, but it’s a different section of people, that

actually make that into a problem and say that’s anti-social behaviour (P.5,

Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

What defines ASB?

In terms of the reasons why participants felt the need to question perceptions of what

constitutes ASB, they often noted that there could be any variety of circumstances in either

the victim’s or perpetrator’s situation that can influence whether an act is anti-social or not.

Similarly, Crawford (2008: 758) has described ‘location, community tolerance and quality of

life expectations’ as important considerations that are pertinent to understanding the

credentials of a behaviour to be considered ASB. Another participant acknowledged in the

layperson’s everyday view that ASB could be perceived as:

Against the normal person’s social outlook… Let’s say, bad morals, dog

fouling, kids flying around on motorbikes and noisy neighbours (P.3,

Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

The important point to note here is the reference to a ‘normal person’s social outlook’ in

terms of the everyday credentials of what constitutes ASB. Payne (2003: 321) has suggested

that ‘frequency, intensity, duration and whether it is considered appropriate, normal or

reasonable behaviour among a particular age group’ are important factors in determining

whether a behaviour is deemed anti-social. Amongst the shared perceptions that ASB has

negative impacts on others, participants listed a myriad of other examples of actions they

would consider to fall under the rubric of ASB: littering, graffiti, arson, drinking in public

spaces, disrespectful behaviour, vandalism, petty crime, disorderly behaviour, unlicensed

vehicle drivers, noise pollution, swearing, verbal and physical abuse, and pranking behaviour.

However, some participants questioned the legitimacy of the term ASB and commented on

the label:

111

[ASB is] something that the government came up with… to try and repress

teenagers… As a good way of dealing with them (P.2)

It’s just making a general nuisance… erm loitering… and large groups of

young people I suppose together would just get labelled as anti-social whether

they were being good or not so… just for being in a large group… so it is just

like a label and it is worn like a badge of honour, if anyone gets an ASBO to

all their friends they’re the coolest you know… around... so it’s not… it

doesn’t do anything I don’t think… ASBOs like… (P.3) (Skelmersdale Focus

Group 2)

From each focus group location, there were supportive statements that identified subjectivity

and perception as being important when considering what ASB is. When participants did not

mention perception as being important, the difficulty in categorising and defining ASB was

emphasised. Further examples were descriptions of being ‘disruptive’, being a ‘nuisance’ and

causing ‘distress’. The negative consequences of ASB were frequently mentioned during

discussion of understanding what ASB is and why it is an issue to people. The next section

will discuss perceived causes of ASB.

Perceived causes of ASB

The literature reveals multifarious potential causes for the onset of ASB. Each focus group

discussed what they thought may cause an individual to behave anti-socially. As noted

earlier, the various causes of ASB could possibly be linked to the subjectivity of ASB itself,

for example the 2003 government White Paper (2003:5) stated that ASB ‘means different

things to different people’; and as such, the potential causes could be numerate, dependent on

what behaviour is deemed anti-social. The diversity in participant responses across all focus

groups appeared to reflect both ideas that ASB means many different things to different

people and that there are many possible causes. For example, one participant in a Rainford

focus group was a local religious leader. He linked ASB to more serious criminality, but in a

way that tried to understand underlying structural causes:

112

In my, erm… not long, I suppose as much as the parish before that where I

was in Liverpool, ASB I experienced all the time, we were broken into, the

vicarage before, almost every night really, broken into, vandalized. We had a

new roof put on, that was vandalized, and whatever you tried to do. So that

was anti-social behaviour, stealing cars and driving them around the back of

the vicarage setting fire to them, every night that went so that was anti-social

behaviour. But what I think, what we have to do is dig deeper than that, well

‘what do I mean by anti-social behaviour?’ what about, ‘why are these people

doing these things?’ Maybe a high level of unemployment… which there was.

A high level of drug-taking and all that, ‘well why do people do that?’ It’s a

cycle of deprivation. A lot of the time, the parents have never had jobs, the

grandparents have never had jobs, and that’s the kind of area I lived in, high-

rise flats. So it brings with it all these problems, and it’s all, what we would

say is anti-social behaviour, but the people perpetrating these things don’t

even consider it, they don’t even think of it being anti-social, they’re just

trying to survive. They saw the vicarage as a threat, you see, it was the biggest

house in the parish so, it was a target, ‘why should you live in a big house like

that?’ we’ve got… (P.4)

‘you’ve got more than us’… (P.2)

yeah… mmm…(P.3)

that was wicked… but you’ve got to dig deep, well what’s going on in these

peoples’ lives? (P.4)

(Rainford Focus Group 1)

In this account there was an appreciation for the difficulty of deciding what is and is not

ASB. Perceptions were linked to structural inequalities by participants four and two, whilst

participant three agreed that ASB may be caused by feelings of inequality. Participant two, in

agreement, stated that it’s a ‘you’ve got more than us’ mentality when it comes to ASB. The

notion that ASB may be related to structural inequality is not new. Flint (2006) has contended

that the focus of multiple strategies on tackling ASB within housing was founded upon such

assumptions. The assumptions were that structural inequality and poverty may exacerbate

113

ASB and malfunctioning social relationships. He further claimed that the underpinning

rationale behind this philosophy is the idea ‘that a combination of material improvements,

dialogue and understanding can ameliorate some of the problems surrounding ASB.’ (Flint,

2006: 274). Similarly, perceptions of ASB aetiology were linked to a lack of equality such as

a ‘high level of unemployment’ or a ‘cycle of deprivation’ by participant four. However, this

participant also noted that the perpetrators may not consider this behaviour anti-social,

instead being a survival mechanism for those deprived of material wealth.

More recent evidence bolsters the idea that social inequalities are related to behavioural

issues or disorders (Piotrowska, 2015). During a systemic review of evidence pertaining to

social position and mental health outcomes, Piotrowska (2012: 1) suggested that; ‘Some

evidence demonstrates a social gradient in behavioural problems.’ For example, Piotrowska

(2012) reported that ‘Conduct Disorder’, a mental health disorder that can reveal itself in

anti-social behaviours, refers to:

… a repetitive and persistent pattern of behavior in which the basic rights of

others or major age-appropriate societal norms or rules are violated.

(Diagnostics and Statistics Manual of Mental Disorders, IV-TR, 2000: 93).

Emerson et al. (2006) similarly reported that ‘Conduct Disorder’ had a significantly higher

prevalence in lowest income quintiles. Examples of associated behaviours include theft,

truancy, bullying, and destruction of property (Piotrowska, 2012). Piotrowska (2012) noted

an inverse relationship with disadvantaged children experiencing increased behavioural

issues.

According to the participants in the current study, deprivation and social inequality need to be

addressed. For example, one participant from Rainford, focus group four, stated ‘you’ve got

to dig deep, well what’s going on in these peoples’ lives?’ ASB was perceived as being

influenced by structural inequality, yet this was not the only perceived cause. One participant

in Skelmersdale described late night use of a washing machine as being anti-social and that

the cause was simply being inconsiderate:

Yeah well, in my building one of my neighbours said to me yesterday that the

person upstairs had already received two warnings about noise because,

114

apparently, they were putting their washing machine on at ten to ten at night,

on like full spin so it would shake and stuff, and obviously that’s kind of under

that sort of thing as well… (P.4, Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

Whilst participants talked of structural issues, mental health and people being inconsiderate,

the key perceived causes identified were parenting and disrespect. The next section will

consider the role of parenting and disrespect in turn.

Parenting

One participant noted that a lack of parental investment (here noted in terms of time and

attentiveness) in their children’s lives may precipitate the later onset of ASB:

When I said before, about the three different schools, I think the affluent area

causes more problems… because there’s money, and for a lot, nine times out

of ten for those kids, it was a case of, ‘well I want to speak to my mum and

dad, but they don’t come in till about six o’clock and I’m back out with me

mates again so I’m just left there, so what am I going to do to get somebody’s

attention here? I’ll kick off’ (p.5, Rainford Focus Group 3)

There was a recurring mention of the influence of parents, or a lack of a good upbringing, in

affecting the likelihood of ASB in youths. The belief among participants was that time and

attention are important facets of parenthood. The participant quoted above went on to stress

the crucial role of parents:

I think there is, and you know again we go along in society saying, ‘well the

parents are this, the parents are that, they don’t do this’. I can understand

where they come from, and you know a child’s behaviour starts from a very

early age, and as parents if we don’t, not correct it because they have to be

individuals as well… but lead them down a path, then things are gonna go

wrong aren’t they… but what’s our standards, and parents’ standards is

different. (p.5, Rainford Focus Group 3)

The participant concedes here that there is a prevalent attitude in society which acknowledges

the role parents have in ‘correcting’ the behaviour of children. If parents ‘lead them down a

115

path’, then ‘things are gonna go wrong’ and that parents can be the first to be blamed

whenever behaviour goes awry. Interestingly, there was the focus on correcting ‘children’

and youths; once more reinforcing the view that ASB is a young person’s problem. Similarly,

another participant placed emphasis on parents having influence over their children’s

behaviour:

… yeah if you’re brought up with your parents saying it’s okay to swear at

your grandparents and to swear at the neighbours and to throw and spit things

at police then you’re going to get children who will grow up to do exactly the

same thing and do it during their teenage years and continue it as adults (p.5,

St Helens Focus Group 1).

This statement exemplifies the participant’s belief that the parents have full jurisdiction over

what their children believe is acceptable behaviour, placing responsibility on the parents to

teach their children what behaviours are acceptable and which are unacceptable. This is not

an uncommon perception. According to Gillies (2005) and McDowell (2004) family

members take the responsibility and have a moral duty to ensure their children develop into

‘good citizens’. There are connotations of parents and family as the ‘bedrock’ upon which

‘good parents’ and a ‘good society of the future’ are built (Edwards and Gillies, 2012: 66).

Jensen and Tyler (2012: 3) stated that ‘bad parenting’ and ‘problem families’ are increasingly

linked with propagating both economic and social malaise. Edwards and Duncan (1997)

purported that the blame is often directed towards lone parents and the working-class families

– whether this is fair or not. This was stated by Peters (2011) who highlights that the blame is

more specifically put on mothers rather than mothers and fathers. The next perceived cause

focused more specifically on one feature of parenting, inculcating a sense of respect and

awareness for others.

Disrespect

The narrative on parenting began to develop into consideration of respect:

… but I think also a lot of families, parents don’t, respect’s a two-way thing,

and I don’t think the children are shown respect. So how can parents expect

their children to show them respect and, you know, I was brought up to respect

my elders… (P.1, Rainford Focus Group 3)

116

With this statement ASB is due to a combination of poor parents, disrespect and low overall

standards. Respect has been a central talking point in relation to ASB and crime. In the

introduction, it was reported that ASB itself was assumed to be, ‘fundamentally caused by a

lack of respect for other people’ (Home Office, 2003: 7). It is interesting to note that

participants automatically responded to discussions of ASB impacts and causes by discussing

the importance of respect. Some participants also defined ASB in terms of respect, as one

Skelmersdale participant put it, ‘Erm, I think it’s like being disrespectful’ (P.2, Skelmersdale

Focus Group 1). Another participant in Rainford focused on respect, giving an example of

wearing a hat in church:

… you would say disrespectful as well as anti-social? Well I’ve encountered

people disrespectful in my life, in the Wigan area men used to come into the

church wearing hats, and in my day you didn’t do that. So when in my parish I

used to take a service I used to ask them to remove their hat, it wasn’t my

responsibility but I decided to. Don’t they realise they’ve got to remove their

hat? That’s the thinking now… I wouldn’t say that’s immoral, but it’s

disrespectful. (P.1)

It’s disrespectful… (P.4)

(Rainford Focus Group 1)

A link between disrespect and ASB was further built upon in another participant’s answer:

I think it is yeah… you know they, it’s totally different from when we were

younger, there’s no respect for your elders, there’s no respect for the police, no

respect for the fire service, for any emergency service, and I wouldn’t like to

be in their shoes. There’s no respect whatsoever, no one’s frightened of

anything… and I mean that… as in a younger generation they’re not

frightened of anything, there’s just no respect anywhere whether it be at

school, at home… but a lot of it comes from the home, definitely…

Definitely… (P.1, St Helens Focus Group 2)

117

In this response, the participant takes on a narrative of moral decline, that ‘it’s totally

different from when we were younger’. Whether this is true is another issue often based upon

perception and changing levels of tolerance (Mackenzie et al. 2010). In the earlier extract,

participant one appears to show some intolerance of one behaviour - namely, men who would

‘come into church wearing hats,’ and despite this not being perceived as immoral, the

participant would ‘ask them to remove their hat’ perceiving it to be ‘disrespectful’. This

issue was also explored by Millie (2006) who noted a relationship between tolerance, respect

and ASB. He later contended that proactive engagement with others is one of an ‘essential

foundation of tolerance’ (Millie, 2009: 172), but it is also context-dependent. According to

participant one in St Helens (focus group 2) respect may also be context related, claiming that

there is ‘just no respect anywhere whether it be at school, at home…’

Bannister and Kearns (2009) previously linked respect to ideas of civility. They advocated

that civility is a product of respect for other people and this ‘serves to reduce the need for our

own conduct to be tolerated by others.’ (Bannister and Kearns, 2009: 179). In their

foundations of tolerance model Bannister and Kearns (2009: 178) expounded that

underpinning factors, such as ‘the type of response we offer to unfavoured conduct’ relate to

whether we tolerate the conduct - and if we do, which form the tolerance assumes. Briefly,

according to Bannister and Kearns (2009), respect has two key roles, to increase our

willingness to empathise with others and to support our own civil conduct. They claimed that

having empathy towards others increases the likelihood that an individual will tolerate

behaviour they do not like. And the incivility of one’s own behaviour reduced, ‘the changes

that our behaviour should become the object of others’ tolerance.’ (Bannister and Kearns,

2009: 179). If behaviour does not match the civil and behavioural expectations of a context it

may not be tolerated. In turn this could be perceived as incivility.

Respect is also perceived as generational, and that there is now a lack of respect for the public

services. According to another focus group participant, this time in Rainford, disrespect leads

to fear in others:

… disrespect, upset, fear, I think it creates a lot of fear for people, especially

the elderly, and I think it’s about the way we live our individual lives … (P.1,

Rainford Focus Group 3)

118

Fear appears to provide a link between the impacts of ASB and disrespect. For others a link

was provided by perceived parental input. The suggestion is that ASB stems from the failed

transfer of respect from adult to child, and correspondingly from child to adult; and that

disrespect can lead to fear of others. A lack of reciprocity has been previously regarded as an

issue (see Sennett 2003). The New Labour government’s ‘Respect Action Plan’ (Respect

Task Force, 2006) has previously aimed to ‘enforce a culture of respect’. However what

aspects of disrespectful – or anti-social – behaviour they wanted to tackle was not clearly

defined. The evidence in this analysis suggests that, whilst respect can be loosely defined as

‘an expression of something that people intuitively understand’ (Respect Task Force, 2005:

5), there is nonetheless a perceived shared, ‘general knowledge’ amongst participants of what

it means to be respectful:

erm… yeah I think it’s just living your life to, you know, to certain rules that

you think, are promoting you to be respectful to other people you know, like

you say helping others, and just treating other people how you would want to

be treated. You know in a day-to-day situation, you’re at work, someone says

‘morning’ to you then you reply to people, you’re pleasant and you have

respect for others and show respect for others, and you know, you sort of work

within the rules and regulations and as I say you just treat others as you want

to be treated. (P.2, Rainford Focus Group 2)

The general understanding of respect discussed above involves the Golden Rule of ‘treating

other people how you want to be treated’. This has similar sentiments to the description of

respect mentioned in the Respect Action Plan (Respect Task Force, 2006). The claim is that it

‘relies on a shared understanding and clear rules and is strengthened by people acting

together…’ (Respect Action Plan, 2006: 5). The idea of reciprocal respect and the Golden

Rule maxim were clearly evident in the participant accounts regarding being respectful. The

implication here is that if a shared understanding is absent then disrespect or ASB may occur.

As a precursor of ASB, disrespect was quite commonly identified in the focus groups, the

claim being that some people just do not have the respect for others to inhibit their own

behaviour.

119

Individual factors and ASB

Alongside various contextual influences on ASB, the participants also suggested various

individual factors. One participant suggested that envy has an influence, a mentality of

‘you’ve got more than us’ (P.1 Rainford Focus Group 1). Others contended that it was about

survival, or related to a search for identity:

…but again it’s what [participant one] said, it’s about you know things like the

background they’re coming from, that behaviour to them is survival instinct to

a certain extent… (P.5)

It is… and its attention seeking as well… they need to, they’re seeking an

identity so whenever they do anything that’s anti-social it’s all to seek

attention and they get this attention all the time … (P.1)

(Rainford Focus Group 1)

The importance of the individual is highlighted here. Participant 1 notes that it is about

identity, essentially a sense of belonging, and ASB is simply attention seeking behaviour.

The stigma attached to living in areas perceived to be ‘bad’ can precipitate incidents of

discrimination, such as when an individual from these areas attempts to attain employment

(Reynolds, 1986, as cited in Papps, 1998). Evidence suggests that elderly residents’

perceptions of youths and ASB can be tainted by simply living in a ‘deprived area’ and the

stigma attached to that (Egan et al., 2012). If perceptions of ASB can be influenced and

shaped by the environment in which it occurs, then what is labelled as ASB may too be

tainted. Support for this was present during Focus Group 2 in St Helens where it was

suggested that not all individuals’ and young peoples’ behaviour can be regarded as ASB

simply because they are living in deprived areas or are from a ‘poor background’:

I think it’s in both, fifty-fifty really, fifty percent poor backgrounds and I think

it’s fifty percent of the richer backgrounds… It’s very different backgrounds

but it’s very similar their attitudes, the way that they put things across and I

would probably say more now for the richer kids or the richer people are

targeted more so than the poorer people… But then again you’re not to

120

differentiate those people, you’ve got to treat them people exactly the same.

(P.1, St Helens Focus Group 2)

The same participant went on to suggest:

… but like I say there’s good and bad everywhere. I live in a village, but

there’s good and bad in the village, you can live in the town centre and there’s

good and bad in the town centre … (P.1, St Helens Focus Group 2)

Converse to ASB being a purely contextual issue based upon deprivation, this participant

focused on the individual – in short; there are those who behave anti-socially in all areas, and

from all backgrounds. Whilst acknowledging that background and wealth play a part in

attitudes to behaviour, people should not nonetheless discriminate when interacting with

others, regardless of level of deprivation. The position adopted here very much affirms the

idea that ASB is not something unique to the disadvantaged; instead it is more of a personal

problem.

Alternatively, a participant from Skelmersdale, Focus Group 2 took the view that behaviour

is dependent upon factors such as who we are with and where we are:

I read something really interesting, and it was just everyone has a different

role for everything they are doing in their everyday life… so when you’re at

home, you’re just at home and you’re yourself, then when you go down the

pub and you’re with your mates you’re a different person, when you’re with

your friends you’re more lively you’re with your friends and you want to have

fun and you’re more energetic. And then obviously you could be with your

partner then and that’s a totally different side of you, so everyone has a

different role for everything they are doing every single day and it’s just peers

or other people that affect how we behave. So if you’re in a group with your

friends, especially young, and you’ve got nowhere to go, you’re gonna be on

the street anyway you’re gonna be running around so you’re with your mates,

you’re showing off, you’re like, your mate says go and smash that window in

and next thing you know you’re putting windows in just to get chased by the

police because you’ve got nothing to do. It’s more the fun of the chase, getting

121

chased around the estate. But you wouldn’t do that if you took your girlfriend

would you? Get chased by the police and smash that window? So I think it’s

right in a way, you do have different roles for different times, you know you

act differently in different situations. (P.2, Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

From this perspective, everyone adopts different roles for different situations. The likelihood

of being involved in ASB can be mediated by peers and the desire to be liked or to have a

group identity. Whilst some considered individual factors, participants in the focus groups

most often took a contextual view of the causes of ASB. This may be the contextual influence

of poverty, parental influence, peers or location.

In Chapter 1 it was suggested that ASB has been framed as a phenomenon intertwined with

the poor, resulting in potential ignorance over other sources of ASB in more advantaged

groups in society. Through analysis of how participants conceived the relationship between

deprivation and ASB, it is evident that there are shared notions of ASB occurring within areas

of deprivation. The revelation of more atypical examples of ASB in groups and organisations

outside of the norm warrants further exploration. As one participant put it, there is ‘good and

bad everywhere’, and this is regardless of wealth and background.

In summary, there were common perceptions of what may cause ASB across all three focus

group areas.

1. The first suggestion was the impact and influence that parents are thought to have on

preventing ASB at the source, through promoting values and respect that can

potentially reduce ASB.

2. Second was that peers and age, for example being young and in a group with other

people, in addition to feelings of boredom, desire to be liked and a lack of a sense of

purpose, could all contribute to the likelihood of ASB being committed.

3. Third, there was specific discussion of a lack of respect as a precursor to ASB which

was also quite heavily linked to parenthood.

Perceptions of ASB causes were also related to whether these were individual or contextual

explanations, with more emphasis being placed on the individual than the contextual by many

122

participants. External factors such as being from a deprived location were not often believed

to be an ‘excuse’ as not everyone from those areas may commit ASB. Some participants felt

that ASB is more of a personal problem rather than being environmental.

Moral explanations of ASB

As noted, the subjective definition of ASB may be so broad that economic crimes such as tax

evasion/avoidance could potentially be construed as causing annoyance, nuisance or harm to

other members of society and therefore be regarded as anti-social. The current study,

similarly, found uncommon types of behaviour that can be perceived as ASB. For instance,

the example of a loud washing machine has already been given. In Focus Group 1, in

Skelmersdale, participants also talked about smoking as ASB:

I’ve been on the train a few times where someone has just sat there and pulled

out a fag and smoked it in an enclosed area and I think that’s quite anti-social.

(P.5)

I hate it when people throw their lit cigarettes on the floor, they don’t step on

it or anything, I mean they shouldn’t throw it and step on it but… it’s worse

when its lit… and they throw it on grass or something and I’m like it’s still lit!

and kids are walking around, like children on the floor… that’s morally wrong

I think… because it’s kinda like a lot of people are against smoking anyway…

that’s added to like… the issue of why people don’t like smoking because it’s

creating more litter. (P.4)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

In this discussion, there was a shared idea that smoking in an ‘enclosed area’ can be ‘quite-

anti-social’. More specifically for the participants, it was the act of throwing lit cigarettes on

the ground, especially near children that was anti-social and ‘morally wrong’. The

acknowledgment is that it goes against wider held beliefs or norms; ‘a lot of people are

against smoking anyway…’, suggesting that an act may be both anti-social and morally

wrong for two key reasons:

1. The consequences it may have on others, and

123

2. Because smoking is not, in their perception, a widely endorsed social behaviour,

particularly when the cigarette is thrown on the ground.

This was a unique suggestion to this focus group. In Skelmersdale Focus Group 2 there was a

more abstract form of ASB discussed, far removed from the above example:

Too many people are selfish, the way the economy is… (P.3)

Yeah (P.2)

And the way that you see these three hundred pound a day expenses that they

claim for having… (P.3)

Greedy, greedy! (P.2)

…having a sleep in the House of Commons and that’s it. I was watching it the

other day and that little child outside of … there was about fifteen people sat

in there, the following day it was about Google’s tax… they were paying one

hundred and thirty million pound, it was full. (P.3)

It was full (P.4)

Yeah. (P.2)

They’re corrupt no matter what party they’re from, what their politics are,

they’re all corrupt. (P.3)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

These comments were in response to a question about what behaviours they would perceive

as ‘morally good’ or ‘morally bad’, and whether there is any potential link between ASB and

the morality of acts. Participant 3 associated morally bad behaviour with MPs fiddling their

expenses. This was referring to the expenses scandal of 2009, when certain MPs had

allegedly misused allowances and expenses using fake receipts, initiating something of a

124

moral panic within the UK (Flinders, 2012). Not only was this behaviour denounced as being

anti-social, but it was also morally wrong:

R: Going back to your point on expenses… when thinking about the way an

MP thought when they carried out their claims for their expenses, and their

behaviour, which part was moral or immoral?

Their crime… (P.3)

Their way of thinking… yeah (P.2)

I mean one of them claimed for underfloor heating his outdoor tennis court,

and another one in his big mansion and big lake, a duckhouse (P.3)

Yeah a duckhouse! For his pond! Outside his house like! (P.2)

And you’re, like that, as if he needs the money? It wasn’t a pond, it was a lake.

Very immoral. (P.3)

Yeah, but anti-social as well, because you’re sending the wrong message.

(P.2)

Well criminal as well because they committed fraud. (P.3)

Yeah. (P.2)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

Further questioning and in-group discussion led to an enthused conversation regarding

the MPs’ expenses scandal as ASB. The identified reasons for these acts being ASB were

varied. One participant noted it as a crime and thus immoral, others cited that the items

were luxurious in nature, and that the ‘wrong message’ was being sent out to society. The

MPs’ actions were seen as anti-social, immoral and criminal. This association links back

to the contention that whether an act is perceived as anti-social, or not, may be dependent

upon the extent to which it matches the behavioural expectations and norms of a specific

125

time and place (Millie, 2008). Furthermore, distinctions between ‘anti-social’ and

‘criminal’ labels are less distinct than might be imagined. In this example the linking

feature is the perceived immorality of the action. It was claimed that the MPs’ ‘way of

thinking’ is immoral. There appears to be in tandem a contention that a behaviour can be

labelled as ASB because there is a perception it may cause offence (Millie, 2008), as in

this focus group where the MPs’ actions were ‘sending the wrong message’. This

example goes against evidence discussed earlier regarding ASB as a ‘poor person’s

problem’ pervading only the most disadvantaged in society.

Interestingly, this above discussion was from one of the most deprived locations in the

study in Skelmersdale. The implication is that perceptions of ASB, within this locale at

least, stretch far beyond the typical ‘yob’ and low-level nuisance behaviour. Participants

in Skelmersdale did initially describe the usual types of youth behaviours, such as young

people congregating or littering. However, there was an acknowledgment that anti-social

and immoral behaviour can both be extended to include more atypical behaviours, such

as the MPs’ expenses scandal. Moving on to St Helens Focus Group 1, there were further

associations made between economic crime, ASB and morality. In response to a vignette

(scenario 7) that was given in the focus group where a person is committing tax evasion

(overstating deductions and declaring less income than they are earning), one participant

claimed that:

Well there’s a budget bucket for everyone to go around… and if they’re taking

a little bit more because they think they need it, there’s other people who need

it more. So they’re stealing again, so it is immoral and it is anti-social… (P.4)

Yeah, ’cause your tax is used for the education and for the NHS that

everybody uses… and it’s free… unless you want to pay privately, erm… so

you’re depriving your community, your land area of money which you’ve

earned from there… erm… and there are enough good accountants if you’re,

you know, that will help you save legally, money. There is sufficient help to

bring their tax down erm… [legally] and then there’s the ones who, you know,

people bank in different areas and pretend they don’t have money, you know,

to hand, and big companies… (P.5)

126

Tax avoidance and all… (P.4)

Yeah, the big companies who are notoriously bad, and it’s the individual low

earner who gets taxed ridiculous because they pay VAT and your contribution

to your insurance and then you get taxed at a ridiculously low level of earnings

as well… (P.5)

Yeah, so it’s like… (P.4)

These big companies and these big company directors and footballers who can

just get away with earning loads of money and paying very little tax. I think

they are immoral. (P.5)

(St Helens Focus Group 1)

It is evident from the above discussion that deliberately avoiding paying taxes is seen as

immoral, anti-social and definitely not an acceptable behaviour for these participants.

Similar to the discussion above in Skelmersdale, there is once again the idea that ASB is

not perceived as just stereotypical ‘yobbish’ behaviour, but also present in groups other

than the young and disadvantaged. This is unconventional in that it is not often reported

that such actions are ASB. This discussion occurred in an area with a mixed level of

deprivation. Like the participants in Skelmersdale, initial thoughts on ASB in St Helens

tended to cover typical examples, but these extended to other behaviours outside the

common spectrum when specifically probed, and were also linked to issues of morality.

The perceptions of participants here suggest that such actions are ASB, they cause harm

or distress, whether directly or indirectly, and are also immoral.

Conversely, within the more affluent Rainford focus group 2, there were perceptions that

behaviour such as benefit fraud is also ASB. Thus there was a contrast between the type

of economic crime and ‘anti-social’ behaviours already discussed, as mostly being the

behaviour of MPs, ‘big corporations’ or ‘big company directors’, to those who may be

claiming benefits that they are not entitled to at the lower end of the economic spectrum.

In response to vignette scenario 4, where a person has discovered a neighbour

committing benefit fraud (claiming money not entitled to) two participants agreed that

this was ASB and wrong:

127

Yeah, of course it is, the individual, it is anti-social because at the end of the

day it’s wrong what they’re doing and everybody else who works doesn’t

claim benefits, so… for me… erm… ’cause they’re out of work, there should

be a moral stance that they have, so… for me it is anti-social behaviour.

Erm… I think it’s somebody who doesn’t give, well, they’re not bothered

they’ll just claim for whatever they can, for me it’s anti-social behaviour. (P.1)

Yeah I’d agree… yeah… erm… you know you, you’re perhaps taking away

that money from someone else who really needs it… you know, so you…

you’re telling lies, it’s fraud, and that, yeah... I just think it is anti-social

behaviour, it’s not something that you should be doing and I think it’s

disrespectful to other people who are, you know, claiming by the book sort of

thing. (P.2)

(Rainford Focus Group 2)

This focus group involved participants from one of the least deprived locations. The

discussion also covered a lack of respect, earlier suggested as a potential catalyst for the onset

of ASB. What this example had in common with the discussions of business and MP frauds

was the potential consequences for others. This awareness and consideration of how the act

may cause harm, distress, or annoyance was prevalent for each example.

In summary, while stereotypical examples of ASB were given, more atypical behaviours such

as tax evasion, benefit fraud, and smoking in enclosed spaces were also perceived to be anti-

social. This challenges the notion that ASB is primarily a poor person’s problem. Many

participants appeared to adopt a consequentialist perspective, that acts were ASB based on

their impacts on others or on wider society. There were further examples of behaviours that

participants perceived as ASB such as online social media bullying; however the above

examples were more commonly shared.

Reciprocity of everyday morality

During discussions on everyday morality and how to regulate everyday interactions, the

notion of ‘respect’ came to the fore in all focus group discussions. In Skelmersdale Focus

128

Group 1, one participant made the point that ‘respect’, and being considerate of others, is a

reciprocal process, one which involves an internal understanding of knowing right from

wrong. Earlier in the thesis, it was acknowledged that enforcement of respect is not

conducive to creating tolerance and a level of mutual respect amongst individuals in society

(e.g. Sennett, 2003). The suggestion here is that respect at the most fundamental level is

about understanding the needs of others within society and mutually encouraging others to do

the same. Attempting to enforce respect - and therefore not reciprocating that very same

respect you are striving to attain - is contradictory. The sentiment of mutual respect was

shared in the current study. The notion of treating one another the same has roots in the

‘Golden Rule’, a maxim that is claimed to be universal and has existed in myriad cultures and

religions2. Millie (2016) has described how the rule, like Kant’s Categorical Imperative, is

reciprocal in the sense that we must treat others in the same way that we would expect to be

treated. In fact, this sentiment was very much echoed by participants in the current study who

stated that:

I think it’s, erm… knowing right from wrong and showing respect to others…

treating other[s] like you, you’d like to be treated yourself. (P.5)

It’s like we all like to think we’re being treated the same, we’re all being

treated equally; we’re not if people are doing that then is it? (P.6)

No… (P.1; P.3; P.4)

it’s not fair on everyone else (P.6)

Yeah I agree with, just generally knowing right from wrong… (P.2)

Yeah I agree with what they say… it’s just treating others and how you’d like

to be treated… (P.3)

yeah being respectful to others… Just treat them the way you’d like to be

treated yourself… (P.6)

2 For instance, in the Bible the Golden Rule is stated as “So in everything, do to others what you would have them do to you, for this sums up the law and the Prophets”. (Matthew 7:12, The New King James Version)

129

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

There was widespread agreement that having respect and being fair are important aspects of

what everyday morality means to the participants. Through attempting to ‘treat them the way

you’d like to be treated yourself’ there is emphasis on the reciprocal nature of morality and it

is possible for everyone to maintain respect and treat others the same.

As previously noted, according to Skorupski (1993) defining morality is impossible, but the

closest definition that can be got is to define its ‘sense’ or general purpose. The ‘sense’ that

participants attributed to morality was one based upon mutual agreement and reciprocal

behaviour – and this was often expressed using the language of the golden rule. However,

there were other aspects of morality discussed such as the influence of family, culture and

religion on moral development – although again these were in terms of the golden rule:

Erm, morality I always put together with more of a religious context, if people

have got moral behaviour etc. I don’t know if I’m right on that, but that’s

where I think old fashioned ideas of morality come from. They stem from,

erm… religious ideals, so I automatically kind of have more; I suppose I feel a

bit more comfortable talking about ethics. So if I’m going to talk about a code

of behaviour based on morality, erm… based on morals, based on ethics, it all

comes under the same thing I think, erm… treating people as you want to be

treated yourself. (P.4)

Yeah I agree, I think, erm… also yeah it comes from religion and it’s also

cultural as well. But everyday morality I think is just, you know, a general

code of behaviour which everyone should basically know the right, right from

wrong. (P.1)

Erm, pretty much the same I think, it’s basically imbued in you from when

you’re young, usually from your parents or from religious beliefs what you’re

meant to believe is what’s moral and what is not. You don’t go robbing a shop

that’s immoral then you, your behaviour is imbued in you from a young age.

(P.2)

130

I agree. (P.3)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 3)

Alongside religion and family there is talk of morality also being linked to cultural factors.

This is reminiscent of research cited earlier (Scheffler, 1992: 122, as cited in Van den Hoven,

2006) suggesting that a ‘common morality’ we all have and share would be ‘a conviction so

widely shared in our culture, and so deeply entrenched, that outside of philosophy it is

scarcely ever articulated, let alone explicitly challenged’. Clearly, religious ideas and family

influence can feed in to such cultural norms.

According to New Labour’s Respect Action Plan (Respect Task Force, 2006:5) ‘We should

build a culture of respect for the modern age, based on values of mutuality and shared

responsibility rather than deference and hierarchy’. From this perspective ‘respect’ is a

cornerstone to such cultural norms. In the focus groups, religion was mentioned as almost a

footnote in some discussions, bar one participant who proclaimed religion as his moral

cornerstone. That said, in Rainford, Focus Group 1 there was support for a more religious

foundation of everyday morality:

Well for me morality is attached to my religion which is Christianity. Erm,…

so I try to live by the rules of, you know, what Christianity tells me. I try to

live that kind of life. But, that’s my first thought about it. Of course morality

will apply to many other things, people who are atheist live with a kind of

morality and that’s nothing to do with religion is it? Erm… so it varies from

group to group, whoever you’re talking to. But for me, it’s all to do with my

faith which is Christianity and morality springs from that, all the social mores

and norms really that I try to live by. But then there are general social mores

and norms out there aren’t there, that the general public, maybe people who

are not Christians live by so they are very moral people. (P.1, Rainford Focus

Group 1)

For this participant there was a strong sense of Christian morality; yet there is an

acknowledgment that individuals with no faith, or different faiths, do still have moral codes

and norms to live by. A relevant point is that talk regarding morality within Rainford was

often quite heavily focused on religion as the group included some residents involved with

131

local church organisations. Despite this, the subjectivity of morality and the malleable nature

of individuals’ moral codes were not lost in these discussions. The reciprocal component of

morality, such as treating one another the same and with mutual respect was reiterated in

tandem with religious suggestions of morality. In Rainford Focus Group 2 perceptions of

what everyday morality constitutes continued to be laden with descriptions of how

complementary, ‘good’ behaviour is intrinsic to being a moral member of society:

Yeah, morality I think is respect, erm… you know, having respect for other

people, other peoples’ properties, to a certain degree having respect for

yourself. And it’s how people are brought up as well, I think you’re brought

up to have the right morals, to respect others, to respect yourself, authority,

respect authority, then I think that, you know, makes for people to have good

morals… (P.2)

Erm… morality I think is doing the right thing… what society perceives to be

the right thing generally in terms of human behaviour, respecting people,

erm…some people I think do try and live their lives to kind of a moral

compass and… erm… I don’t know whether other people don’t or whether

they just don’t think about it, but I think morality is about trying to do the right

thing and respect other people, treat people how you’d like to be treated. (P.3)

(Rainford Focus Group 2)

In these statements there is further reinforcement of the reciprocal nature of morality, but also

recognition of it being ‘what society perceives to be the right thing.’ Elsewhere it was noted

that there may not be one ‘true morality’, or no clear-cut comprehension of what it means to

behave the ‘right’ or ‘wrong’ way. Whilst some talked in terms of the golden rule, others

rejected a ‘gold standard’ by which all societies and people can be judged. This idea was

presented by participants in Skelmersdale, Focus Group 3, where one participant claimed:

… because some people can deem one thing moral, and I’m not saying this

again, you know religious morality and personal morality and sometimes they

clash dramatically and then if you’re trying to force one and then the other

there’s literally borders between borders and borders when it comes to

132

morality. Some people deem an action of shooting a criminal as being good…

(P.2)

R: So it’s just what people think and what people do is different?

Yeah I think it’s more ideology isn’t it than morality (P.2)

And also as well, ’cause that’s two different interesting arguments then isn’t it,

because the broad definition of ASB and our morals can get blurred between

people because there’s a difference between people’s, you said [Participant 4],

cultural ideals and what people think is wrong or right, I think this gets really,

really blurred within the lines of the law as well. (P.1)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 3)

The identified conflict between a universal golden rule and there being a multiplicity of moral

codes and diversity in societies, is a source of contention that raises the issue of moral

relativism and how context influences perception. As noted, Millie (2016: 34) critiqued moral

relativism that, despite being seemingly tolerant of other ways of living, may also be ‘tolerant

of actions and omissions that are generally regarded as morally intolerable’. However, there

is room for relativist interpretation and different individual/societal perceptions (Bannister

and Kearns, 2012; Mackenzie et al. 2010). In the current study perceptions of ASB were

based upon subjective perceptions, and interpretation.

If there is no gold standard by which to judge all others’ behaviours, then attempts to define

which actions are moral or not – or even which are anti-social and which are not - become

blurred, dependent on the situation they occurred in. That said, participants did not convey

this as a problem for their own sense of what it means to have an everyday morality. Whilst

acknowledging the blurring of boundaries, both within ASB and morality, there is still an

overarching theme of morality being a concept that needs mutual effort between people.

In summary, the experiences and perceptions of participants regarding morality appear to be

heavily influenced by the relationship between culture, respect, religion, and the reciprocal

nature of behaviour that affirms those standards between people. It was suggested that

morality is more individualistic than universal, that moral codes differ dependent on context

133

and other variables. The relative importance of context was emphasised by participants in

each focus group location. Whilst boundaries may become blurred from society to society or

culture to culture, the one constant for each participant was that morality is based upon a

reciprocal relationship between individuals.

ASB and immorality

During the earlier stages of the thesis it was noted that ASB was often linked to an assumed

moral decline within British society. This was considered by both the public and British

government to be a causal mechanism for ASB and crime. For instance, according to the

London Evening Standard (2007: 1), 83 per cent of people thought that moral standards were

dropping. This of course does not mean there was an actual moral decline however the

emphasis of government projects to tackle ASB have emphasised the lack of morality, and

respect, as causes for ASB. The social theory of Norbert Elias (2000) - in particular his work

on the civilising process - has been noted as providing a useful framework to examine the

governance of ASB in the UK (Millie, 2009; Powell and Flint, 2009). Civilising offences

such as the Respect and Anti-Social Behaviour Agendas aimed to create cultural shifts in

society to eliminate incivility. Civilising offences resonate with government projects aimed at

addressing and improving the social conduct of groups within society that are deemed to be

not in line with the rest of society (Millie, 2009). Key characteristics such as the

problemization and shaming of behaviours are examples of the civilising process. The issue is

that the mechanisms of ASB management aimed at countering a perceived decline in civility

can, paradoxically, serve as a device of exclusion for behaviour that is not in line with the rest

of society. The focus of civilising offensives is to implement self-governance of perceived

problematic behaviour yet conversely these can lead to social exclusion without tackling the

underpinning social dynamics.

Understandings of how perceptions of a moral decline relate to understandings of ASB could

help inform interventions geared towards tackling such behaviour. Bearing this in mind, the

current analysis revealed support among participants for the view that (im)morality and ASB

are linked. For instance, in Rainford, participants felt that to behave in an anti-social way was

not conducive to living a moral life:

134

There is a link between it isn’t there. If you’re living a moral life, you don’t

engage in anti-social behaviour. (P.1)

Anti-social behaviour yeah. (P.4)

Morality encompasses it, it goes beyond those words really (P.3)

If you’re engaging in anti-social behaviour then you’ve got to question the

morals of that person. (P.1)

The anti-social behaviour is dealing with it in the group, morality goes to how

you behave when you’re on your own and nobody sees you. (P.3)

(Rainford Focus Group 1)

According to participant 1, the link between morality and ASB is very simple. If you are a

moral individual, then you do not ‘engage in ASB’, an opinion shared with participant 4. This

sentiment was further bolstered by a participant in another Rainford focus group:

ASB shows a lack of morality so… if you had the right morals you wouldn’t

be committing that type of behaviour, so therefore there is a link between the

two. (P.3, Rainford Focus Group 2.)

The suggestion here is that ASB itself conveys a lack of morality; to be involved in ASB is

associated with having a lack of morality. That said, according to a participant from

Skelmersdale:

You know what? I probably used to think that they’d go hand in hand, they

don’t do they? I mean you could be a genuine, generally a good person but

have the occasional slip up, or have the occasional inconsideration you know

like... blasting your music through the walls… it doesn’t make you a bad

person it just makes you stupid… (P.2, Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

The case is made here that you may be a ‘genuine’ and ‘good person’ but still have the

occasional ‘slip up’. It may be over simplistic to equate ASB to a lack of morality. There is

135

recognition that people do make mistakes, but that does not mean they should be labelled or

stigmatised as immoral or bad people. An individual who lives what could be considered a

‘good moral life’ is still capable of behaving in a morally ‘bad’ manner. For example, no one

lives an entirely morally good life, despite claims for the existence of a ‘moral majority’. This

could, like ASB, be an issue of perception. What one person perceives as immoral, another

may not.

There was nonetheless one participant in St Helens focus group 3 who noted that, whether a

behaviour is labelled as immoral or moral can be determined by the amount of thought that is

‘put into it’:

… but you have to think how much thoughts put into it… I think there’s good

and bad behaviours but there’s also the thought behind what you do…

Someone who is really nice in the day, but isn’t doing it to be nice, isn’t

necessarily doing a moral behaviour, they’re just doing that and it happens to

be good. (P.3, St Helens Focus Group 3)

From this perspective, descriptions of a link between ASB and morality are based upon the

amount of consideration given prior to the occurrence of an action. In terms of ASB,

potentially the same logic could be applied to those who it is claimed do not think about the

consequences of their actions. Yet, despite the disassociation mentioned between morality

and ASB here, there was still more support for the notion of a link between morality and

general behaviour:

I mean your morals are how you believe, and then your behaviour is how you

act on them… but then there’s the grey area in between isn’t there… Like you

could have all the intention to be a good person but through your actions…

Through your actions you might make a couple of mistakes along the way…

but it’s just general… (P.3)

Well I think there is a slight link… but I think there can easily not be a

relationship as well because you could be very moral in a lot of areas and then

totally not in others… you could be a lovely person, always well-mannered…

you know not murder and that kind of stuff, but you might throw litter… you

136

know? But I think it does link when it is… when it also has the thought

process as the morals and then you act on it, so I think it’s kind of

intertwined… You know… (P.4)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

In this discussion, the argument for a link once more reverted back to the claim that morality

is the thought process and behaviour is the ‘by-product’ of the said process. Although, one

further claim here is that there is a ‘grey area’ in between this process and action mechanism.

In this example, morality may be the cognitive aspect of proceedings and behaviour the

action, but that is not enough to determine whether someone is immoral or moral. They may

be a ‘good person’ but just make mistakes, hence the ‘grey area in between’. Participant 4

had the view that everyone may be moral in some respects and immoral in others, dependent

upon perception and context.

There is evidence to suggest that the relationship between crime and morality is often

neglected by students of crime (see Antonaccio and Tittle, 2008). According to Gottfredson

and Hirschi (2010:88), morality ‘typically [refers] to how people feel about their acts rather

than to the likelihood that they will or will not commit them’. Conversely, Etzioni (1998)

took a reductionist view where human behaviour is perceived through cost-benefit

calculations. From this perspective, Etzioni contended that individuals often behave

unselfishly and irrationally, choosing the more dutiful response or through refraining from

committing illegal acts. The reason for behaving in such a fashion, according to Etzioni, is

that people are guided by moral principles and values. In this vein of thought, what would be

regarded as a ‘lack of morality’ (P.3, Rainford Focus Group 2) is almost as a predictor of

anti-social and criminal behaviour. Etzioni (1998) further suggested that a lack of morality

predicting criminal behaviour holds firm even when there is variation in how morality has

actually been measured. Furthermore, evidence appears to be consistent with the suggestion

that moral commitments and moral feelings convey some preventative power in terms of

influencing the onset of criminal behaviour (Hannon et al., 2001; Rogers et al., 2005). This

idea appeared to be shared by three participants in Rainford Focus Group 2:

Erm… Define it as people who have got no morals, people who don’t want to

conform to society, or don’t want to conform to how they should behave. And

people who’ve just got no respect for anybody or anything, they just want to

137

do what they want to do, erm… without prejudice or anything, they’re not

interested in anything they’re… the area they live, the environment, they’re

not interested in anything it’s just what they want to do and they’ll do it,

doesn’t matter what anyone else thinks… (P.1)

Yeah I think it’s lack of respect for others and lack of respect for themselves…

Erm… you know and just… yeah just think it’s that really… (P.2)

Erm… Yeah I agree with that I think morality is erm… being good rather than

bad, trying to do the right thing, erm… trying to help other people and erm…

try and treat people how you’d like to be treated yourself and conforming to

erm… standards and laws and rules laid down by society as a whole so that we

can live in erm… in peace.

(P.4 Rainford Focus Group 2)

Perceptions of the relationship between morality and ASB, or criminality, were dominated by

notions that moral beliefs and standards are the counteracting mechanisms against such

behaviour. The views conveyed here in Rainford Focus Group 2 suggest that morality is

‘being good rather than bad’ and it is conforming to ‘standards and laws and rules’, referring

to morality as being the preventative force. In this example, being moral is the opposite of

behaving anti-socially. Etzioni (1998) further suggests that moral beliefs are a useful concept

in research mainly because people often reflect a good personal definition of what morality

means to them in relation to violations of the law. In relation to the present study, perceptions

of a link between everyday morality and ASB were saturated with participant narratives of

‘bad morality’ being ASB and anything which reflects a lack of respect or consideration of

others.

Contrastingly, there are identified shortcomings in terms of how morality relates to criminal

or anti-social behaviour. For example, Antonacci and Tittle (2008) note that the measurable

impact a lack of morality has on criminal behaviour is not yet fully explored or studied. They

further reported that morality has not been identified as the main influential factor in

conforming behaviour. It could be that morality is a single component in a complex network

of conforming behaviour. It was reported by participants that there are a variety of

contributing factors in terms of what precedes the onset of ASB or criminal behaviour,

138

although much emphasis was placed upon a lack of morality being evident in those who

behave anti-socially. That said, the degree to which an anti-social act was deemed immoral or

moral seemed to depend upon individual perceptions and the consequence of the behaviour, a

theme I return to.

The perceived link between ASB and everyday morality was evident when participants were

discussing either a lack of morals in the perpetrator or the presence of good morals in those

who do not commit ASB. In St Helens one participant was of the view that morality is

universal and built upon perception:

My… initial thoughts on morality are… it’s something that, in one way it’s

ubiquitous in us all… in that we all have some sort of moral compass in life…

but again… it’s all about the perception of what we think is moral as opposed

to what someone else thinks of it… So, my first thought is morality is

something that is sort of ingrained in us all… it’s kind of there to, again, sort

of guide your everyday behaviour, and even your perceptions of whether

someone else is doing something, that it might be, urm… you think is wrong

but it’s just wrong to you and only you. So I believe it’s there sort of to help us

make the decisions between right and wrong, and maybe even good and evil,

that sort of thing… (P.1, St Helens Focus Group 3)

It is interesting to note that in each focus group morality was often described as the ‘guiding’

force that can influence our everyday behaviour. There is a claim that morality is subjective,

dependent upon perception and context similar to previous participants’ suggestions. The

difference here is that there is a counter claim that morality is ‘ingrained in us all’ and is there

to ‘help us make the decisions between right and wrong’. Participant perceptions of morality

and ASB further conveyed that good morals may prevent unwanted or inappropriate

behaviours. The notion that internal constraints such as ‘good’ morals may counteract

inappropriate behaviours is not unique to this finding. For instance, Kempf-Leonard and

Morris (2012) have discussed social control theory (SCT) as an alternative explanation of

why people offend and what internal constraint measures influence this. SCT explains why

people offend through the relationship between rules and behaviour, and internal constraint

mechanisms developed through childhood. Kempf-Leonard and Morris (2012) claim that

deviant behaviour is a consequence of inadequate internal constraints. Those offenders who

139

violate social norms or societal values may still hold the same values as other people, but

they are not likely to conform due to this inadequate development of internal constraints.

Interestingly, the current study found that multiple participants in each area did believe that a

lack of self-regulation, in terms of morals and values, could contribute to later anti-social and

criminal offending

Despite this, not all researchers agree that SCT provides a fully reliable explanation of

inclinations to behave in a criminal or deviant fashion. For example, Antonaccio and Tittle

(2008) have investigated the predictive strength of SCT. They claimed that understanding

personal characteristics, such as self-control, predict ‘misconduct’ in behaviour. For example,

they note that empirical research on self-control, crime and morality not only suggest it is

important to consider these when looking at preventative measures, but they are also

important in identifying crime causation. Yet, personal moral principles and internal

constraints may still function in inhibiting crime and deviance, even in the face of large

economic and other social changes. Given these possibilities, assessment of the powers of

self-control and morality to prevent deviant behaviour is especially important in this

environment. The means through which self-control and moral values can be developed is

frequently suggested to be through moral education and communication.

Perceptions of a link between morality and behaviour were described as the relationship

between cognition and behaviour. According to most participants’ discussions, morality was

the premeditative stage whilst behaviour was the outcome of this process. There were

arguments against a link between ASB and morality, namely due to the subjective nature of

what is moral. Perception was noted as integral to this process, but also the blurring of

boundaries between morality, immoral and ASB was problematic when labelling behaviours

one way or the other. Perceptions in this study suggest that some do believe that ASB is

immoral, and linked to a lack of moral education or failure on both parents and academic

institutions. However, parents were often first and foremost claimed to be at fault. A link

between poor moral values and likelihood of later offending behaviour was a frequently

described perception in the current study.

To summarise, it is evident from the current study that there is support in public perceptions

for a link between morality and ASB. By using less open-ended questioning and in-depth

group discussions similar to the present study, further research may help understand the

140

relationship between morality and ASB. Further investigation into the relationship between

ASB and everyday morality would help illuminate just how much of an influence generally

regarded ‘good’ or ‘bad’ morals have on the potential onset of anti-social or criminal

behaviour. The present study suggests that morality and ASB are linked, yet this is

determined by the impact it has on others and the ‘level’ of morality the perpetrator is

perceived to have - for example whether regarded as having low morals or no morals.

According to this analysis a lack of morals is perceived to be a contributing factor in the

occurrence of ASB.

ASB, immorality and intolerance

A further example of a perceived link between morality and ASB was in Skelmersdale Focus

Group 1, where a link was immediately created between ASB and immorality when one

participant described their experience with a neighbour:

I got to the point where I was leaving my house at stupid o’clock in the

morning and coming back at stupid o’clock in the night and I was coming

back crying because the music was just [imitates loud music noise] (P.2)

Yeah (P.1; P.4; P.6)

So yes, it is extremely immoral. (P.2)

Yeah it’s definitely wrong, like you say it is a common occurrence in this

situation but if it’s just once, it’s not as bad, but if it’s more… (P.4)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

There was substantial support that excessively loud music was ‘extremely immoral’ and was

‘definitely wrong’. However, one participant, interestingly, did note that persistence was the

problem - if it’s ‘just once’ it is not ‘as bad’, it could be tolerated. Persistence is a recognised

aspect of defining whether an action is anti-social (Millie et al., 2005). In this context,

perhaps persistence is also a measure of whether this act is also perceived as ‘extremely

immoral’. It is important to mention that participant 2 commented that the individuals playing

141

the music were from another culture, where playing music loud late at night may be ‘morally

acceptable in their society’:

…but at the same time, the amount of neighbours we’ve had… it’s only been

the foreign ones that have done that [played loud music]. So is that morally

acceptable in their society as opposed to what is in ours? (P.2, Skelmersdale

Focus Group 1)

This brings a return to a relativist position. Who is truly the anti-social party, the one

playing the music or the one complaining? The debate between who is being anti-

social and who is not may be linked to issues of tolerance (Bannister et al, 2006;

Millie, 2006). If what is regarded as anti-social is specific to certain individuals or

groups, then even potentially mildly rude or uncivil behaviours could be conceived as

ASB. Another participant did agree that what is acceptable in this situation varies:

Yeah, it varies and is it acceptable that once they’ve said you know you’ve

knocked on the neighbour’s door and said ‘we’re going to have a party

tonight’ it’s gonna be a bit loud is it alright if… (P.1)

If it’s once in a while then it’s great, it’s when it’s a common occurrence that

it’s causing distress to the neighbours, so it must be quite frequent and

substantial for it to be doing that… (P.3)

(Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

The suggestion that courtesy might mitigate some of the immorality of the concern was

suggested, alongside the issue of persistence. However, not all participants felt that acts could

be labelled as both ASB and immoral. A debate on the link between ASB and immorality

surfaced during Rainford Focus Group 1, where participants were discussing whether ASB

was also immoral:

Erm,… yeah. That’s anti-social, smashing someone’s window. I’m not sure

you’d say it’s immoral, but immoral is… people would do lots of immoral

things don’t they, that we would term as immoral… (P.4)

Yeah… (P.3; P.5)

142

So… erm, and society would say that was immoral, whether they say it’s

anything to do with Christianity, or Buddhism, or Muslim or whatever, erm…

It’s a difficult one, you’ve got to dig deep… (P.4)

(Rainford Focus Group 1)

Here the participant questioned whether the act of smashing another person’s window could

be construed as immoral. The questioning delineates between whether the participant would

perceive this as immoral due to personal religious beliefs. The issue of identifying whether

ASB is seen as immoral appears to be influenced by personal standards and perceptions of

what is moral and immoral - as opposed to others’ views. Once more there is a hint of moral

relativism. Similarly, a participant in Rainford Focus Group 2 wrestled with the labelling of

low-level ASB as being immoral:

I mean the incident with the eggs you could say it’s just childish behaviour,

just teenagers having a bit of fun. But to me it is ASB because you know, it is

disrespectful to, you know, to us as individuals because they’re actually

throwing stuff onto our property. And I think it is ASB because of the lack of

respect. You know, a lack of morals really, they think it’s okay to throw eggs

at other peoples’ property. And also I think when you’re in your own house

you should feel safe… to think that there are people just walking around and

doing that for a bit of fun, I just think it’s not nice and it is ASB. (P.2,

Rainford Focus Group 2)

Despite some participants’ apparent difficulties in labelling some acts of ASB as immoral,

when presented with vignette scenarios - such as the above example of throwing eggs - there

was support for ASB being both immoral and wrong.

ASB and consequences

Through the use of vignettes the current investigation could identify how participants gauged

the moral properties of different examples, albeit not definitively across all groups. The

suggestion by some was that the consequences of the anti-social act were important. For

143

example, one participant in Rainford Focus Group 2 claimed that littering was both anti-

social and morally wrong due to its impact on others and on the environment:

I think it’s morally wrong and anti-social as well because… when people are

talking about people dropping litter out of the car windows or just dropping

litter when they’re walking along, or not disposing of their own household

waste properly, it does have an effect on other people in society, an effect on

the environment, and on the community. Unless people think about other

people and the affect that they’re having on them, if they just carry on doing

that because they don’t care and they can, then, it shows their own lack of care

and consideration for other people and maybe their own standards of morals

are either very low or non-existent, and what kind of world would we be in if

everybody just had no rules at all and they just did whatever they wanted

whether they were offending other people or not… em… I just don’t think it’s

right…

(P.4, Rainford Focus Group 2)

The emphasis here is consequentialist, the ‘effect on other people in society… environment…

community’. Those who behaved in this way were thought to have either had low morals or

no morals. There was further consequentialist support for littering being immoral amongst

participants in Skelmersdale:

R: Do you think that’s morally bad?

Yeah it is morally bad, because yeah, we have a system, we have a refuse

collection and you can phone up and, you have to pay now, but nonetheless

you can get it to the dump. So why not do that, why just dump it on the estate

and make a mess where everyone else lives as well? (P.5, Skelmersdale Focus

Group 2)

There is the claim that littering is a ‘morally bad’ act due to its consequences in making ‘a

mess where everyone lives’.

144

Returning to Kant’s Categorical Imperative, littering is seen as immoral as it breaches a

moral imperative not to litter where someone else lives (because we would not want others to

litter where we live). Kant’s philosophy on morality is deontological, focusing on whether

actions conform to a moral law, namely the Categorical Imperative. Kant maintained an

emphasis on the need for a reciprocal respect between individuals and the self. The same

notion of reciprocity of respect and adherence to a ‘moral law’, or Categorical Imperative,

was apparent in the current study; but there was also a strong emphasis on consequences. It is

also worth mentioning that other vignette scenarios regarding situations involving tax

evasion, benefit fraud, youths congregating, loud music and illegal parking received a

mixture of responses as to whether they were ASB, moral, immoral or amoral. However,

littering was the more vehemently discussed ASB that was deemed to have a high level of

immorality. For most participants, the notion that ASB is wrong or immoral was related to

consequences, linking the behaviour itself with its effect on others.

ASB, what should be, and what is

Morality may influence behaviour, criminal or otherwise, but this may be limited in its

practical applications. According to Haan (1982) morality is much more than mere

observable actions and empiricists are susceptible to believing that the facts we observe are

the whole truth. Haan (1982) gives the example of observed moral actions, claiming that

these are only specific adjustments in behaviour, developed by specific conditions of a place

or time. The issue is that observed moral actions may only represent what an individual ‘must

do, given certain circumstances, rather than what they think they should do’ (1982: 1099).

Consequently, what is a moral action,

…can only be adequately understood in terms of people's ideas of what should

be, and what should be will not be understood without knowing what is. Not

to explicate this relation between enacted and cherished morality is naive

empiricism. (Haan, 1982: 1099, emphasis in original).

What is morally right or good might only be understandable in terms of what people believe

should, or should not, be morally right or good. However, this cannot be understood without

knowing what constitutes a moral action. It is important that morality can be conceptualized

with regards to certain actions, but credence must also be given in terms of how this

manifests in the everyday lives of people. It is also important to know why people act in

145

accordance with their perceived moral beliefs to understand how moral views and judgments

are enacted on an everyday basis. Within the present study, participants claimed that ASB is

immoral only in relation to specific examples or types of ASB. There was also

acknowledgment that what is morally good to one person, or context, may not be to another.

This is related to tolerance once more, with varying thresholds or perceptions as to what is

moral or immoral behaviour. Yet, the issue of knowing what constitutes a moral action, and

what one perceives as being a moral action, are both difficult to delineate and may be

influenced by perception, tolerance and context.

In terms of context, recent evidence suggests that the link between morality and crime may in

fact be related to the ‘moral environment’ of when an offense is perpetrated. According to

Wikström (2012) criminal behaviour in so-called hot spots of crime is not only a consequence

of the location and opportunity, but also the moral context in which it occurred. Wikström

refers to the level of enforcement of ‘common rules of conduct’ which, in these contexts,

interact with the presence of ‘crime-prone’ young people. He found that moral contexts can

encourage crime when young people with this personal characteristic are present.

Some examples of this include city and local centre locations with ‘poor collective efficacy’

or moral contexts in which ‘crime prone’ young people are vulnerable to committing crime,

particularly when the young people are involved in unsupervised activities. A key finding

was that policies need to focus on developing moral education and cognitive nurturing –

which assist with the development of greater self-control. Subsequently, this will help

minimise the emergence of moral contexts which are conducive to crime. Further

understanding of the relationship between social disadvantage and how it influences the

content of young people’s moral education is needed. It can be surmised from this

perspective that moral education may have utility as a form of prevention for criminal or anti-

social behaviour within these locations of specific moral context. The idea that certain

contexts are potential factors in the occurrence of crime or ASB was suggested by

participants, often noting deprived areas as more prone. However, from the participants’

perspectives, morality was linked to parental or family influences first, and the environment

second. The New Labour government suggested that the issue may be due to dysfunctional

families who were perceived as ‘morally deficient’ (Parr, 2010). Poor parenting was

identified as another root cause of ASB and this preceded a ‘raft of policy measures and

legislative programmes’ (Parr, 2010: 717). In the current study it was reported by participants

146

that ‘poor parenting’ could precede ASB due to a lack of instilled morals or respect. Thus, a

lack of ‘good’ parenting was perceived to play a role in youth ASB by participants.

In summary, there was a definite perceived link between ASB and immorality in each focus

group, but this was also linked to issues of (in)tolerance. Loud music and noisy neighbours

were identified as sources of both ASB and immorality for some participants, but others

suggested tolerance if this is not a persistent complaint. The categorisation of acts as being

both anti-social and immoral appeared to be associated with the consequences of the said act.

Whilst youths congregating did not appear to really evoke strong concerns and consequences

for the participants, littering and other environmental ASB did. Littering was one of the most

denounced ASBs that was also perceived to be very immoral.

Morality and parenting

As noted, throughout the focus group discussions there was much emphasis on the influence

that family (especially parents) and other role models have on shaping young people’s sense

of morality. In the UK narratives regarding ‘poor parenting’ became prevalent during the

New Labour Government (1997-2010) and grew to dominate public culture (Jensen and

Tyler, 2012). There was a perception that families were the ‘bedrock’ and good parenting the

key method through which to sustain a ‘good society of the future’ (Edwards and Gillies,

2012: 66). The placing of ‘family values’ and morality at the epicentre of behavioural issues

such as ASB was a perception shared by many participants in the current study. For instance,

in Skelmersdale Focus Group 1, the first responses in the discussion of everyday morality

noted how moral development stems from parents:

I think it’s… morality is your beliefs that you might have been taught by your

parents… or raised to think that… so obviously it varies in everybody… so

everybody is different and things like manners… and being polite… and

keeping promises to others, I just think that is what morality means… (P.1,

Skelmersdale Focus Group 1)

Similarly, in Skelmersdale Focus Group 2, emphasis was placed on the way people are

brought up:

147

Doing the right thing… respecting people, the way we were brought up

basically and to respect people and treat people the way you want to be

treated. (P.4, Skelmersdale Focus Group 2)

This feeds into the reciprocal nature of morality previously discussed. Similarly:

… it’s about setting yourself a standard and trying to hopefully live to that

standard and expecting the same of other people isn’t it, it’s about your

upbringing as well you know, your own sense of worth and stuff. (P.6,

Skelmersdale Focus Group 3)

Further support for morality being related to parents and a person’s broader upbringing was

evidenced in St Helens Focus Group 3 where morality was claimed to be more of a ‘learnt

behaviour’ rather than innate:

I think morality is a bit more of a learnt behaviour to be honest… I don’t think

we are all born with a moral compass… because obviously, that wouldn’t

explain why people do horrendous things. I think you’re taught through an

early age… whether it’s through religious beliefs or parents telling you what

you can and can’t do, or why you should or shouldn’t do things… I see it more

of, it is to do with right and wrong, but I think that’s based on what you’ve

learnt or what you’ve seen. (P.3, St Helens Focus Group 3)

The contention that morality is not something we are all born with frames the concept as

something contextually driven, or socially embedded in the environment and society people

live in. The suggestion that we are not born with a ‘moral compass’ and claims that we are

‘taught’ through our ‘beliefs or parents’ infers that a form of moral education in necessary

when parenting. Failure during this process may lead to a lack of knowledge regarding what

one understands as ‘right’ or ‘wrong’, perhaps preceding ASB. According to Taboada (1998:

1) the best method to tackle crime and ASB is to ‘embark on an educational process to help

people confront and resolve issues’. From this perspective, Taboada suggests moral education

can provide the context in which crime prevention policy could be based. By teaching social

and cultural values, with acknowledgment of law and respect for human rights, it may be

possible to counteract the friction between competing views of behaviour. This suggestion

148

appears to be reminiscent of promoting ‘tolerance’ amongst people. The need for awareness

and education is posited as a method to tackle ASB at the root, rather than tackling

symptoms.

Taboada (1998) notes that beyond parenting, educational institutions have a responsibility to

promote moral education and awareness to younger generations. This is also echoed by

participants in the current study. However, participants placed more emphasis upon parents

than educational institutes in terms of where moral awareness and education derives from.

For example, participants in Rainford Focus Group 1 discussed further the relationship

between moral education through families and ASB. In a few of these cases, participants

perceived morality to be generational and fostered by the family; and ‘good’ moral

development is no longer as evident in contemporary generations:

… and it’s now a generation, it’s going back three or four generations. Now

this is the problem that we’re dealing with, it’s not just this generation…

because I saw it and you saw, sort of saw, the mums bringing in the teenagers

and their teenagers are bringing in their babies and you’re thinking it’s this

cycle, perpetual cycle that’s going on and it’s quite frightening. (P.5, Rainford

Focus Group 1)

According to participant 5, parents’ own behaviour may be the standard upon which their

children’s morals and behaviour will be developed:

… and it’s also on the child’s background, have the parents behaved that way,

have they passed that on to the children? Grandparents? You know... three

generations, never worked, they knew they’d never work, so erm… they just

think it’s a normal way to behave. (P.1, Rainford Focus Group 1)

Here it is evident that the relationship between parent and child, or grandparent and child, is

very much at the forefront of linking the behaviour and perception. One participant in

Rainford Focus Group 2 claimed that a lack of morality stems from poor transference of

moral values from parents to children:

149

I think ASB links into the way you were brought up, erm… I think if you were

brought up with morals, I don’t think you’d commit ASB on a regular basis or,

well, or at all really… if your morals are right you wouldn’t commit ASB,

you’d be more respectful, people’s property and your environment that you

live in. So I think there is a link between morality and ASB. I think if you’re

brought up and your morals are high, you won’t disrespect the things that ASB

is. Which is a lot of the stuff that we’ve discussed? (P.1, Rainford Focus

Group 2).

This is a simplification, but the perception that ASB links into the ‘the way you were brought

up’ it not an unusual suggestion. As already highlighted, ‘bad parenting’ and ‘problem

families’ are increasingly blamed for ‘social and economic ills’ (Jensen and Tyler, 2012: 3).

More specifically, issues such as a lack of parental investment in fostering morality and

‘good’ morals are suggested to be a potential catalyst for ASB, both in research and present

participant narratives:

Yeah I agree, I think morality is linked to, you know, lack of morality is linked

to ASB erm… if someone said to me about school children, naughty school

children, well it’s not always the children who are the naughty ones it’s how

they’re brought up, how their parents bring them up. It’s… you know, they’re

not just always naughty it’s how they’re taught at home, you know to have

morals, to have respect for people. I think ASB and morality is linked, if

you’re brought up well… I think… there must be some link between deprived

areas as well. But even, you know, years and years ago if you lived in a

deprived area, as long as your parents brought you up well then you had the

right morals and I don’t think ASB was as bad then so… yep I do think it’s

linked and it all comes down to how you respect yourself and others and how

you’re brought up. (P.2, Rainford Focus Group 2)

Within this account there are suggestions once more that families are integral to the moral

development of young individuals, being the primary medium through which the

‘transmission of values’ (Valentine, 2008: 2102) can occur. This transmission of values

entails the passing of social and cultural norms and ideals. The implication here is that not

being ‘brought up’ to have ‘good’ morals and learn right from wrong has the potential for

150

ASB and other less socially acceptable actions to be deemed ‘morally okay’, regardless of

consideration for others.

According to Bull (1969, as cited in Devine, 2006: 15) ‘The child is not born with a built-in

moral conscience. But he is born with those natural, biologically purposive capacities that

make him potentially a moral being’. This statement appears to resonate with participant

claims in this study that if ‘you’re brought up well…’ then you will be more respectful and

abide by taught moral rules. La Sage and De Ruyter (2008) investigated whether parents may

hold any responsibility for the criminal behaviour of their offspring. The argument made was

that, because children lack moral reasoning skills, perspective taking, moral emotional

awareness and behaviour control skills, parents must take responsibility for morally educating

their children. Furthermore, parents need to support prosocial behaviour, provide ‘good’

examples, and reject anti-social behaviour whilst also being consistent. This is particularly

pertinent in terms of the current findings, the evidence suggesting that promoting prosocial

‘good’ behaviours and consistent education are important factors in reducing the likelihood of

ASB. Additionally, according to some of the participants, parents must also provide a

framework of discipline and explain moral rules and values - parents are to provide moral

education first and foremost. However, despite such claims, it is important to note that La

Sage and De Ruyter (2008) also stated that moral education will necessarily prevent criminal

(and anti-social) behaviour later in life.

Kohlberg’s (1975) theory of moral development may be useful here, which suggests that:

… rather than attempt to indoctrinate or socialize students, moral education

should seek to stimulate the natural process of development toward more

mature reasoning. Hence the role of the educator ought to be that of a

supportive but questioning guide - a Socratic teacher - who encourages the

articulation and examination of students’ own reasoning about ethical issues

and facilitates exposure to higher stages of reasoning, (Munsey, 1980: 360).

Schemrich (2003) noted that Kohlberg’s (1975) core concept is that both adolescents and

children construct their own morals and values through moral conflict. Rather than just

internalize the morals and values of role models - such as parents and teachers - they develop

increased levels of moral reasoning through this conflict. The key objective of moral

151

education is to stimulate and increase the child’s ability to reason at ‘a higher level of moral

maturity’ (Schemrich, 2003: 8) that promotes thinking and awareness of others’ rights or

needs. Kohlberg more broadly claimed that the development of a moral society is dependent

upon the moral standards of the individuals that coexist within that specific society.

Interestingly, the notion that a more moral society would lead to less ASB and criminality

was suggested by participants in the current investigation.

Summary

In summary, it is evident that participants in each location in the study perceived a

relationship between morality and parenting. Some placed emphasis on parents and role

models as the cornerstone of where people first develop their sense, or lack, of morality. For

others, religious beliefs were of more importance to their sense of where morality originates;

but even within these accounts there was recognition of the role performed by parents in

forming the moral perceptions of younger people. One participant took a different

perspective, noting that morality comes from culture, society and peers. Yet, once again there

was the recognition that parents are embroiled within this process too. Finally, participants

linked ASB and a lack of morality to absent parental investment in teaching ‘good’ morals to

young individuals. A lack of fostering prosocial values and morals was perceived to be one

cause for the presence of ASB. Interestingly, this was not unique to ‘deprived areas’.

Perceptions of everyday morality and ASB were linked through multiple discussions of topics

including: perceived causes of ASB; disrespect; youthful ASB; issues of understanding ASB

and impacts; what defines ASB; moral explanations; whether ASB is more individual or

contextual; the reciprocal nature of everyday morality; ASB and immorality; ASB,

intolerance and immorality; ASB and consequences; and parenting and morality.

Participant perceptions of ASB were found to focus on the impacts of ASB on others. What

ASB was perceived to be was commonly referred to by actions that have adverse

consequences. Tolerance, perception and behavioural expectations within different contexts

were factors that influenced perceptions of what ASB is. Why certain behaviours were

perceived to be anti-social or immoral was reported to be influenced by variables including

the consequences on others and the age profile of the anti-social individuals - i.e. youths

congregating or being noisy.

152

Common perceptions of ASB causes included narratives discussing parental neglect,

deprivation and social inequalities. The influence of peers and disrespect were frequently

discussed by participants as influencing the likelihood of ASB. Individual variables were

noted by some participants who noted that mental health or individuals who need a sense of

belonging to a group. The desire to identify with others and have a sense of belonging to a

group was a common perception in the analysis.

Atypical examples of ASB that were perceived to be immoral included behaviours that had

negative consequences for others. For example, smoking on a train or bus was perceived to

be anti-social and morally wrong, particularly if there were children present. Another atypical

example included behaviours that were perceived as criminal but also anti-social and

immoral; namely the MPs expenses scandal and tax evasion by large businesses.

Interestingly, perceptions of atypical ASB were present in each focus group location,

irrespective of the level of deprivation.

A key finding of this study included participants adopting a consequentialist view of

morality. Perceptions of what everyday morality is and how it may be linked to ASB were

frequently discussed with reference to the outcomes of actions. Perceptions of why some

ASBs may be perceived as immoral, such as littering, were commonly associated with

negative consequences for the environment and safety of others. Interestingly, participant

narratives of what everyday morality is was discussed from mixed perspectives. The Golden

Rule and morality as reciprocal were common findings in the study. Being virtuous and

treating others how you want to be treated were participant responses to conceptualising

everyday morality. Finally, ASB and everyday morality were perceived as being linked

through concepts such as a lack of respect, immorality, behavioural expectations in different

contexts, a lack of moral education and poor parenting.

Next, the conclusion chapter summarises key findings and discusses everyday morality and

ASB by drawing on criminological and philosophical perspectives. It considers the

limitations of the study and how the current findings might contribute to knowledge of ASB

and everyday morality. Suggestions for further research are outlined.

153

Chapter 6.

Conclusions

Introduction

The aim of the present investigation was to examine perceptions of ASB and everyday

morality based upon two key research questions. The first was, through drawing on

criminological and philosophical literature, how are ASB and everyday morality linked, if at

all, and what evidence is there for this link. The second question was how do the public

perceive everyday morality and anti-social behaviour as being related? The aim was to

answer these questions through two key approaches. The first method was to conduct a

literature review of existing criminological and philosophical literatures to develop a broader

picture of the relationship between ASB and everyday morality. The second plan was to

conduct an Interpretive Phenomenological Analysis (IPA) of perceptions of ASB and

everyday morality using in-depth focus group discussions based upon three locations in the

North West of England. The findings suggested that there are various diverse and convergent

public perceptions regarding ASB, everyday morality, and the relationship between these.

The themes were interrelated, and some overlapped but all were evident within each of the

three focus group locations chosen.

In this concluding chapter perceptions of ASB are considered as relating to assumed causes

and consequences and everyday morality. Following this, the importance of individual

context of ASB is considered, including issues of social deprivation. The chapter then reflects

on the key themes of subjectivity and tolerance, ASB and morality, and the relevance of

Kantian ethics. The limitations, contributions to knowledge and future research implications

are further considered. The chapter concludes with a discussion of how these may have

implications for future research from an interdisciplinary perspective.

154

Perceptions of ASB

The findings were organised into key themes, the first of which was people’s perceptions of

what constitutes ASB. It was revealed that prevalent perceptions of ASB focused on the

everyday nuisance and disruptive behaviour most often associated with young people. A

common finding was that participants have either experienced, been witness to, or heard of

others who had been affected by ASB. Narratives from each area focused on the negative

consequences that ASB has on society and individuals. However, in line with previous

research (e.g. Mackenzie et al., 2010), perception itself was identified as being important in

determining what is deemed to be anti-social. Frequently the focus groups mentioned young

people when asked what ASB meant to them. This perception was linked to views that socio-

economic deprivation and poor parenting are factors that can precipitate young people

engaging in ASB. Further, being young was perceived to be related to ASB definitions, and

as a perceived cause of ASB.

Participant narratives identified various perceived antecedents of ASB such as age, peer

relationships, boredom or a lack of purpose. More contextual causes were also discussed,

with participants claiming that social deprivation and background can play roles in the onset

of ASB. Participants also emphasised a lack of respect, potentially associated with poor

parenting. Conversely the transmission of strong values - such as respect - was important in

explaining causes for ASB.

Participants often adopted a consequentialist view of ASB (and of everyday morality),

focusing on the negative consequences of behaviour. Often these centred on the participants’

own experiences of ASB and how it negatively affected themselves or others they knew.

These consequences tended to be either physical or mental health impacts of vandalism of

property or verbal insults and offensive behaviour. Despite difficulties in defining ASB,

according to the participants the impact of a given behaviour on others was a key feature of

what makes something (or someone) anti-social. In the focus groups ASB was always

discussed in relation to the negative consequences it can have on the lives of others.

155

Perceptions of ASB: Everyday morality

According to the focus group participants a perceived lack of morality was causally linked to

ASB, and in particular to not fostering ‘good’ morals and values. Interestingly, this

discussion developed into describing more atypical behaviours that would not often be

perceived as ASB but were viewed as anti-social and immoral. For example, whether it was

tax avoidance by companies, or tax evasion by individuals, participants noted that

deliberately avoiding paying taxes is both immoral and anti-social. This challenges the

assumption that ASB is a poor person’s problem, where perpetrators are often from deprived

areas. Further atypical examples of behaviour perceived as immoral and anti-social were

mentioned, such as smoking in enclosed places or online social media bullying.

Participant narratives suggested that there was a link between perception of ASB and

everyday morality through perceived immorality and intolerance. It is interesting to note that

what was perceived as both, or either, immoral and anti-social was not consistently agreed

upon within all focus groups. Some behaviours did have a larger consensus, including claims

that littering or fly-tipping were very immoral in addition to being anti-social. However,

youths congregating was perceived by some as being ASB and not by others who thought it

was context dependent. It was less identified by participants as being immoral.

Further findings revealed that participants placed great emphasis on a person’s upbringing,

the role of parents in determining the morals and values of their children. Parents were

framed as role models and the very cornerstone of where people develop either their sense, or

lack of, morality. However, some participants perceived religion to be where their source of

morality comes from, whilst some claimed that culture and peers are influential variables that

determine one’s sense of morality.

Public perceptions both supported and questioned the role that everyday morality may have

in ASB. However, the focus group discussions that supported the idea of a link between ASB

and morality perceived the relationship as one of cognition and behaviour. It was often

suggested that morality was involved in that premeditative stage before an individual

behaves, hinting that morality was thought to have the potential to inhibit behaviour that may

be anti-social. The subjectivity of what it means to be moral or immoral pervaded participant

discussions of a link between everyday morality and ASB. Perceptions suggested that if this

changed from one person to the next, then such a link would be so heterogeneous it may not

156

be relevant. That said, it was evident that some felt there is a blurring of boundaries when

categorising behaviours based upon their moral standing and ASB criteria.

How individual context and perception related to ASB

A key finding of the present study was that context and perception are not only important

factors in legislation on ASB, but also for everyday understandings of ASB. For example,

some participants reported that areas simply associated with being deprived or with a bad

reputation may be labelled so, simply through negative stereotyping. As discussed in Chapter

1, this could be influenced through residents’ perceptions that the young have a higher

propensity to commit ASB. For example, one participant noted that normally ASB is just

‘kids’ and referred to a lack of parenting skills in addition to deprivation. ASB research and

policy have been biased towards areas perceived to be troublesome, marginalised and

criminalised (Sadler, 2008). This is despite not all disadvantaged communities experiencing

ASB problems to the same level (Flint et al., 2007). Furthermore, as noted, when ASB was

discussed it was not limited to the most deprived and young, but also to other members of

society.

It was suggested that whilst age and deprivation can play a role in the potential for ASB to

occur, individual factors such as attention-seeking behaviour, a desire to be liked or values

instilled by parents are also perceived to be important. Wider cultural and, religious factors

were also thought to be important with moral codes differing from one society or culture to

another.

ASB was often described by participants as a common characteristic of some families.

According to Curtis (2016) a general milieu lacking in positive experiences is associated with

anti-social behaviour, and this may be on the part of the young person, parents or the whole

family (often developing into a reciprocal pattern).

Social deprivation and ASB

As noted, the perception that ASB is related to socio-economic status and deprivation was a

recurring theme in the present study. For instance, one participant in Rainford noted that ASB

was related to ‘a cycle of deprivation’, subsequently claiming links to structural issues such

as low-opportunities, high levels of unemployment and living in areas where other people

157

have ‘never had jobs’ due to deprivation. Criminological research into ASB has frequently

discussed the relationship between deprivation, social exclusion and ASB (Millie et al., 2005;

Flatley et al., 2008; Burney 2009; Crawford, 2009; Millie, 2009; Taylor et al., 2015 Young,

2016). For instance, Heap (2014) reported ASB perceptions in ‘hard-pressed’ areas are

primarily driven by experience: ‘ASB, be it against neighbours, environmental damage or

through personal experience was the key driver of perceptions in these hard-pressed areas.’

(Heap, 2010: 48). She further noted that in many cases perceptions were influenced by a

combination of the above factors, alongside ‘word of mouth’ and the experiences of others. In

the current study, one participant in Rainford explicitly stated how ASB changes between

locations. In this participant’s village littering and cigarette stubs were the main examples of

ASB. However, in another town (St Helens) the participant expressed how the ASB was of a

more ‘serious’ nature, namely how people treat one another, street drinking, verbal abuse or

swearing, a lack of respect and regard for one another.

To summarise, common perceptions were that areas of deprivation or social housing are

typical locations for the occurrence of ASB. However, some participants reflected the

stereotypical notion that ‘being young’ was a factor in the likelihood of behaving anti-

socially. Egan et al. (2012) noted that being either underprivileged or disadvantaged may

precede an individual being negatively stereotyped and that living in or being associated with

a location deemed to be poor can increase concerns about anti-social or criminal behaviour.

An interesting point to note was that perceptions of deprivation were also linked to ideas of

everyday morality and ASB. One participant claimed that one of the influential factors for

how you behave, in both moral and anti-social terms, was where you live. Namely, whether

you were from a ‘socially deprived background’ or ‘affluent’ location was perceived to be

influential in how you behave. This provides a potential avenue for investigation in future

research. The notion that one’s background influences their likelihood of ASB but also their

sense of morality may unveil further links in the relationship between ASB and everyday

morality, although other participants believed that ASB and immorality could occur

anywhere.

158

ASB, subjectivity and tolerance

What one person deems to be anti-social may be considered acceptable by others. Thus, some

people may tolerate certain forms of minor ASB, whereas others may not, leading to further

discrepancies in what is, and what is not reported. Such subjectivity allows ASB to be

governed by factors such as context, location, community tolerance and quality of life

expectations (ODPM, 2003). A broad, subjective definition can however be a positive device.

It embraces all victims of ASB, as their experience of the behaviour and the consequences it

has upon their quality of life are taken into account. From a victim’s perspective ‘the use of

such a permeable, all-encompassing definition is justified in terms of the need to protect the

self-governing, law-abiding citizen from the dangerous, uncivilised ‘other’’ (Flint and Nixon,

2006:943). Such a wide-ranging definition can simultaneously produce negative outcomes. It

‘is open to objection on the basis that it will catch conduct which is unorthodox or unusual,

eccentric or bizarre, but which, nevertheless is conduct which ought not to be the subject of

the legal process’ (Card and Ward, 1998:108). Therefore, the definition of ASB has the

potential to affect so-called ‘law-abiding’ citizens whose behaviour may be unconventional in

a particular context, rather than anti-social.

As noted, ASB can be influenced by factors such as our own level of tolerance and

behavioural expectations within differing contexts. This was a recurring theme of the data in

this thesis. Tolerance of some behaviour was directly related to the assumed consequences of

that behaviour. Tolerance and subjectivity levels also appeared to vary between

neighbourhoods.

ASB and morality

The current study was informed by research and concepts from both criminology and

philosophy. In addition, IPA, typically a psychological research methodology, was adapted to

analyse participant narratives. Millie (2016) has advocated such a multidisciplinary approach

when developing a broader academic perspective in criminology and philosophy. For

instance, according to Millie, ‘It became clear that there is a great deal that criminology can

learn from closer engagement with philosophy’. (2016: 123). More specifically, the current

study aimed to extrapolate deeper meaning and engagement with morality which has been of

interest to both academic disciplines. For example, morality itself has been linked to those

159

behaviours that enable individuals to navigate their everyday social worlds and influence

behaviours. According to Bottoms (2002: 24), ‘if they are true to their calling, all

criminologists have to be interested in morality’. Similarly, Millie (2016) has stated:

Moral philosophy, or ethics, is concerned with how we live and how we ought

to live with one another. It considers what is good or bad, as well as deontic

judgements of rightness, wrongness, obligation, requirement, reason for doing

and what ought to be (Millie, 2016: 33, emphasis in original).

According to Millie, these concerns are of paramount importance to criminology. Others have

resonated this, including Williams and Arrigo who claimed:

Historically, philosophers have written very little about the subject of crime.

Similarly, criminologists have written very little about the subject of

philosophy. In both cases, the linkages between philosophy and crime have

been left implicit … However; to be sure, law and justice have been

particularly significant concerns throughout the history of philosophy.

(Williams and Arrigo, 2006: 1)

Arrigo and Williams (2006) contend that our understanding of, or knowledge about crime,

law, and justice are given expressive form (become realities) when constructed within

linguistic systems (e.g., the language of the law or legalese). The meaning of these narratives

is derived from how we convey our thoughts; as communicated from the language system

and/or structures we employ. They claim the knowledge we have ‘concerning these realities

is textured by what we say and by how we say it, knowledge about crime, law, and justice is

linked to the power language wields over us’ (Williams and Arrigo, 2006: 14). Milovanovic

(1997) claims that language is powerful as it is the vehicle through which legislation is

framed. According to Millie (2016) the most powerful in society dictate what behaviour

should be censured, based upon their own values and perceptions, through laws. In this study,

participants noted that some powerful members of society, for example members of

parliament, should be setting the example. Yet, some participants perceived their behaviour

as immoral and anti-social on occasion, as example being the MPs’ expenses scandal.

Another example given was tax evasion – which was perceived as immoral and anti-social by

160

some, but not all, participants. Public perceptions of this behaviour were not in tandem with

the views of those who abuse their position of power.

The notion that ASB may be prevalent in social groups other than the more deprived or

disadvantaged has received little attention in the literature. In the current study, tax evasion or

the example of MPs’ expenses, were perceived as being both anti-social and immoral in the

same way as vandalism or littering, as occurring because of a lack of morality and respect.

Morality was described and discussed in similar terms by most focus group participants, with

slight variation in beliefs regarding where we develop our sense of morality from. Future

studies could focus on individuals who may have previously partaken in ASB to see whether

moral values had any impact upon their decision-making and behaviour, and whether the

consequences of this behaviour have any moral ramifications for the perpetrator or not. In the

current study it was the consequences of the behaviour that seemed to influence how ‘moral’

or ‘immoral’ participants perceived the ASB to be.

The evidence here suggested that participants in each of the three locations of this study,

despite levels of deprivation, believed that some ASB was immoral and some ASB was not

immoral. Some participants did not link ASB to morality at all, instead finding this dependent

upon the context of the ASB. For example, benefit fraud was often regarded as immoral and

anti-social, due to it being regarded as ‘stealing’ money from taxpayers; but some appeared to

mitigate the severity of this moral transgression. Instead, benefit fraud was attributed to

circumstances outside of their control, with some people just trying to survive. An

examination of the variations in different social groups, for example ‘typical’ ASB

perpetrators, tax evaders, or Members of Parliament, could reveal how concepts of everyday

morality and ASB are different, if at all. In turn, this could help inform public perceptions of

an assumed moral decline, and assumed increases in ASB in society.

The Golden Rule, Kantian ethics and ASB

Throughout the study morality was commonly expressed through the Golden Rule. In

Chapters two and four of the thesis, the Golden Rule was highlighted as a potentially useful

way of understanding morality – that you ‘do to others what you would have them do to you’

(Matthew 7:12). More specifically, Kant’s Categorical Imperative is useful for understanding

161

why certain actions or omissions ought to be regarded as morally wrong and censurable.

Participants discussed the impacts of ASB on victims, often referencing the Golden Rule as a

sort of criterion on which they could deem an act anti-social or immoral. The implication was

that participants perceived everyday morality to be based on a reciprocal relationship -

treating others as you want to be treated, and being respectful to others, were both described

as features of everyday morality.

Millie (2016) emphasised Kant’s focus on the requirement to respect the self and respect

other people. It was evident in the current findings that respecting others and conducting

yourself with respect for others were important to participants’ concepts of everyday morality

and perceptions of ASB - where perceived causes of ASB were linked to an assumed lack of

respect for others and conducting oneself in a manner that causes nuisance to others.

Similar to the Kantian perspective, participants referred to morality from a duty- or rules-

based perspective; namely that individuals should behave in accordance with moral rules and

codes of conduct. For example, participants often noted that respect should be both given and

received to others. However, whilst Kantian ethics is usually seen as non-consequentialist,

the perceived ‘wrongness’ of the ASB was often described by participants with reference to

the consequences for others. For example, some participants claimed that ASB includes

actions that are ‘against the norms and values of society’ and precede ‘something that harms

the social well-being of others’. Thus, perceptions of what ASB is, were influenced by both

deontological (rule-based) and consequentialist perspectives.

ASB was linked to perceptions, where one individual’s behavioural expectations in a certain

context may differ to another individual in that same context. For example, a group of youths

congregating in a street can be considered ASB. One may perceive this as ASB, and it is

liable for intervention according to Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Act, 2014.

However, another may perceive this behaviour as harmless, and not ASB. Similarly, people

may perceive a group of youths congregating in a location, for example a park, consuming

alcohol and may view it as immoral. Who decides that these activities are ASB is the

legislature as influenced by those with power. However, whether it is immoral (and anti-

social) is a matter of individual perception - despite previously noted governmental efforts to

tackle ASB and immorality through enforcing respect (Respect Task Force, 2006). The point

to take here was that individual perceptions of whether one type of behaviour was either anti-

162

social, immoral, or both differed. This is pertinent to reports that law should not enforce

morality, as what is perceived as immoral may differ from one community to another (Green,

2013). As Green (2013: 473) has stated: ‘Lawyers and philosophers have long debated

whether law should enforce social morality’. Yet, according to Devlin (cited in Green, 2013:

473):

… on the contrary, provided what is at issue is a moral standard whose breach

an average person would regard with intolerance, indignation, and disgust, we

should enforce it.

The key here is what an ‘average person’ would think. What this study has shown is that an

average person might not be so easily identified. Similarly, taking a utilitarian perspective,

Hart claimed that we should never enforce morality, ‘unless doing so attains some good that

outweighs the loss of liberty and happiness that come with enforcement.’ (Hart, as cited in

Green, 2013: 473). How law should reflect morality remains unsettled, and Green (2013:

474) gives an example of this problem during a court case:

In the law of obscenity, for example, courts can in one breath disown

moralistic interpretations of what is obscene, declaring that it is to be defined

not by violations of community standards but instead by reference to

harmfulness, but then in the next breath affirm that what counts as ‘harm’ is

whatever the community regards as harmful. (Green, 2013: 474).

A similar issue is the subjectivity of ASB and its relation to everyday morality, and whose

perceptions determine what behaviours are anti-social and what behaviours are not.

Perceptions of everyday morality and ASB

Perceptions of morality are not only contested, but also change; as described by Green:

Moral views that were once an unremarkable part of our own cultures and then

became minority, even pariah, outlooks, are being given new life. It was not so

long ago that our societies held it morally unproblematic that men should be

entitled to control women’s lives; that family honour should trump individual

163

well-being; that children are vassals of their parents; and that law should

support the true religion. Our current moral consensus against such attitudes is

destabilized by the mobility and migration of peoples who take a different

view. (Green, 2013: 474).

ASB and everyday morality are similarly impacted by subjectivity and changes of

perceptions through time.

The thesis can conclude that perceptions of everyday morality and ASB are linked. However,

variation in participants’ opinions regarding the moral aspects of ASB presented similar

difficulties in attempting to clearly delineate both how and when ASB may be perceived as

immoral. If perceptions are context-dependent, or based upon the perceptions of powerful

social elites, then legislation aimed at tackling ASB may be at fault itself for promoting a lack

of tolerance and respect for others. The behaviour of those with power may not be perceived

as immoral and anti-social, based upon their own views of morality, yet others may take a

different view. In fact, perceptions in this study were quite aligned when it came to certain

groups being immoral and anti-social, such as tax evading companies or the MPs’ expenses

scandal.

Current climate of ASB

The Anti-Social Behaviour Crime and Policing Act 2014 introduced new ASB policing tools

that replaced the previous nineteen orders of previous legislation (Eastwood, 2016,

Johnstone, 2016). The six new orders to tackle ASB included; Criminal Behaviour Orders,

Crime Prevention Injunctions, police directions powers and three categories of Community

Protection Orders (Eastwood, 2015). The three subcategories of Community Protection

Orders include; the Community Protections notice, the Community Protection Order (public

spaces) and Community Protection Order (closure). It has been argued that these new powers

simply continue to undermine the rights of citizens and enhance the government’s power over

the vulnerable and marginalised (Eastwood, 2015). These orders replaced the previous

number of powers and provide measures to counteract ASB that may not have fallen within

the rubric of previous legislative tools. For example, the new powers provide scope to cover a

broad range of behaviours than previous legislation and they require a lower burden of proof

(Eastwood, 2016; Johnstone, 2016). These orders replaced the previous number of powers

164

and provide measures to counteract ASB that may not have fallen within the rubric of

previous legislative tools.

For Eastwood (2016) the reform of old ASB legislation has precipitated a simpler system that

had increased the reach of ASB powers. This could leave individuals at risk of being

punished for behaviours that could be addressed through a more supportive approach.

Instead, similar to the preceding ASB legislation, the marginalised and vulnerable members

of society are still at risk of further punitive methods that do not address underpinning causes

(Eastwood, 2016). Some have criticised the post-2014 approach to ASB as conveying the

same extant measures that will continue to impact upon the vulnerable groups within society

(Johnstone, 2016). For example, the Public Spaces Protection Order (PSPO) were being

implemented against both young people and the homeless (Liberty, 2015). The dispersal of

vulnerable groups including the poor or homeless from areas they are not wanted underpins

the ‘eliminative ideal’ (Johnstone, 2016). Contemporary government approaches to appear to

still be directed at excluding the marginalised from public spaces and the trend of elimination

and exclusion has very much been strengthened by the recent ASB legislation. In fact, the

Anti-social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Act (2014) has bolstered and extended existing

measure that were ‘already enjoyed by the police, courts, municipal authorities and social

housing providers’ (Johnstone, 2016: 723). However, it has been stated that the ASBO’s part

in facilitating young people into the criminal justice system has been diminished by the

replacement of ASBO’s through the Injunction (Johnstone, 2016) as breaching orders is now

not a criminal offence. Since 2014, the debate around ASB control appears to have fallen by

the wayside and ‘debate is much more muted’ (Johnstone, 2016: 724).

In recent years the ASB debate appears to have shifted in political discourse from a focus on

ASB perpetrators to ASB victims and families (Heap, 2014). The Home Office’s ASB victim

policies were identified as a response aimed at addressing the needs of vulnerable people and

repeat victims (Heap, 2014). Then Home Secretary Theresa May claimed that ASB was

‘destroyed good people’s lives’ (May, 2010) conveying the coalition government’s attempts

to gain support to reform ASB policy. The aim was to create ASB policy where the victims’

needs are being met and prioritised (Heap, 2014). However, the reality was that the methods

introduced by the 2014 legislation, including changes to police call management, the

Community Trigger, focusing on victims and improved communication channels were

criticised for not truly putting victims first. Contrarily, it had been claimed that the

165

developments introduced to prioritise victims’ needs were flawed and poorly constructed

(Heap, 2014). Whilst the debate around ASB as a prominent issue appears to have abated, it

is evident that there are still similar issues around current measures to counteract ASB

(Eastwood, 2016; Johnstone, 2016) and attempts to support the victim (Heap, 2014).

Limitations

The current study has its limitations being based on the views of focus group participants

from one area of the North West of England. The focus groups also had an open structure

meaning there were themes identified in Skelmersdale Focus Group 3, that were not

discussed in Rainford, Focus Group 1. The lack of complete generalizability between the

three areas meant that some of the lived experiences of participants, regarding their

perceptions of ASB and morality, could not be explored. In addition, many variables can

influence the direction discussions take, making further generalisations difficult, even

between groups within the same study. For example, Sim (1998) suggests that factors such as

group dynamics, group composition and group situation can all influence what participants

say during different discussions. Despite this, it is testament to the strength of this study’s

approach - utilizing IPA with focus groups across three locales - that similar themes and

findings from the analysis could be extrapolated from the data, thus revealing links between

participant narratives sharing similar perceptions of ASB and morality. Future studies could

examine whether such claims could help shed light on further antecedents of ASB or

potential methods to intervene early and inform initiatives to counteract ASB.

A further concern of the present study was the issue of whether the study truly measured

public perceptions of ASB. Previous evidence suggests that the definitional issues of ASB

extend to attempts at investigating ASB perceptions. Heap (2010) once asked a pertinent

question regarding studying perceptions of ASB:

… can we be sure that when investigating public perceptions of ASB, we are

investigating the perceptions of ASB alone and not the fear of crime, and/or

the marginalisation of young people as well? Based on the findings from this

study, the answer is likely to be no. (Heap, 2010: 205).

166

In the current study there was no means through which to delineate between whether

participant responses were based on the fear of ASB rather than perceptions alone. This could

have been an important variable as one of the thesis’ findings revealed that public perceptions

of ASB were influenced by multifarious factors such as respect, morality, socio-economic

status, and social housing status, amongst others. Whilst the participants were aware that the

study was exploring their perceptions of ASB, there was not a measure to control for whether

these perceptions were driven by fear or the marginalisation of behaviours, or young people.

Public perceptions of defining ASB were both comparable and contrasting, perhaps reflecting

the individual or local nuances between each focus group location. However, this may also

have reflected individual experiences or characteristics. Despite this, the current study was

relatively enterprising in attempting to explore public perceptions of ASB in relation to

everyday morality. The exploratory nature of this qualitative approach was not focused on

strictly measuring public perceptions of ASB; instead the key aim was to gauge how

perceptions of ASB may relate to everyday morality. Therefore, reporting different

perceptions of ASB and everyday morality that varied between individual participants and

focus group locations can be perceived as a strength.

There was no specific age range, background or other factors that were criteria for inclusion

in the study. This may have hindered the identification of specific aspects of the participants’

characteristics that may influence their perceptions of ASB and everyday morality. For the

current study, however, this approach strengthened the investigation as the various

heterogeneous factors helped enrich the depth and scope of data collected.

A common criticism of the IPA approach is that samples are smaller, although this enables an

in-depth analysis that gives full appreciation of each participant’s experiences. Whilst

generalisation is not the aim of IPA studies, evidence has suggested that, ‘through a steady

accumulation of similar studies on other groups, generalisations may become possible over

time’ (Smith, Harre and Van Langenhove, 1995, as cited in Pietkiewicz and Smith, 2012:

365). A strength of the current study is that similar, shared perceptions were found within

each location. Future investigations that build on these findings could investigate in more

depth whether moral views on various types of ASB are shared across particular locations or

social groups.

167

Contributions to knowledge

The focus groups that were conducted as part of this study provided an in-depth analysis of

public perceptions of ASB in three different locations across the North West of England. This

provided the opportunity to confirm existing drivers of perceptions of ASB, as well as

uncover new factors. This process uncovered barriers to effective practice - for example the

reporting of ASB from the public. The current study is also the first time specific enquires

had been made into the way public perceptions were influenced by factors such as everyday

interpretations of morality and immorality, extending the existing body of knowledge, which

typically focuses on ASB as mainly a criminogenic concern rather than related to perceptions

of morality.

Overall this study produced some specific contributions to knowledge. Some of these

contributions involved new findings, while others challenged existing research. The key

contributions were:

Unconventional perceptions of ASB were reported, such as: the 2009 MPs’ expenses

scandal and tax evasion. These findings challenge the traditional types of ASB

reported by previous studies and suggest that perceptions of ASB evolve and are

dynamic. It is suggested that perceptions of ASB and the motivation for not reporting

differ between geographical areas. An important point here is that this challenges the

assumption that ASB is a poor person’s problem.

Some of the findings challenge existing research. For instance, in this study noisy

neighbours were not consistently considered to be a problem, despite their inclusion

in combined perceptions measures. Not all participants believed each vignette

scenario was a behavioural issue, for example some participants did not believe

youths ‘hanging about’ was ASB or immoral.

Drawing on criminological and philosophical perspectives provided the research with

a framework to study the moral features of perceptions of ASB. What categories of

behaviours are perceived as moral or immoral are often not discussed in relation to

ASB, despite the word ‘morality’ being consistently cited in political discourse and

168

government publications regarding ASB. The present study found that public

perceptions of ASB were related to perceptions of everyday morality, yet some

participants perceived littering as immoral but others not. The current study provides

a foundation for future research to explore both what anti-social behaviours are

perceived as moral or immoral, but also why this may be.

Based on the findings produced by this study, it was evident that perceptions of ASB are

multifaceted. It was apparent that experiential factors were important for people in

determining how they perceived ASB. For example, participants’ perceptions of ASB were

typically affected by their own lived experiences, or experiences of others who described this

to them. Furthermore, this was also influenced by other factors such as tolerance, context,

individualism and the consequences of ASB. In addition, the dynamic nature of perceptions

made it difficult to determine which factors were impacting on perceptions at any moment

throughout the study. This presented an issue that was noted by Heap (2014: 234) who stated:

Therefore, can we really rely upon public perceptions as a proxy measure of

the extent of ASB? Probably not, although it could provide a useful indication

of ASB if used in conjunction with other measures, such as demand statistics

and police recorded incidents.

Thus, the current findings on ASB may not be a reliable measure against which to determine

the extent of ASB, but they do tell us something about perception. As also noted by Heap

(2014), there are outlying questions about ASB perceptions that would benefit from further

research and clarification. It would be beneficial if future research on perceptions of ASB and

morality considers the internal processes and dispositions of people who are everyday victims

and perpetrators of ASB (Cate, 2016).

In the current study, parenting was perceived to be important for the regulation of behaviour,

namely the behaviour of young teenagers or adults. The notion that parents are to blame for

ASB is not new (Peters, 2012). Peters (2012) reported that multiple legislative tools that have

employed ‘parent-blaming’ - or ‘mother-blaming’ - have been adopted to tackle ASB. For

example, previously Fixed Penalty Notices could be issued to parents of young offenders.

Similarly, Flint and Nixon (2006) have reported that parental responsibility has been

169

scrutinised and that parents could be judged based on their child’s behaviour. Farrington and

Welsh (2008) reaffirmed this, claiming that the link between perceived inadequate parenting

and later criminal behaviour had become established in research. However, the current study

was not able to clarify why poor parenting was given such weight by participants. Millie et

al.’s (2005a) work on ASB reported that poor parenting is subjective.

Future research directions

Perceptions of ASB still remain a highly under-researched area (see Mackenzie et al., 2010;

Heap, 2014). The current study has explored some of the drivers behind public perceptions of

ASB as related to ideas of everyday morality, but further investigation in the following

suggestions may benefit policy aimed at addressing said perceptions; for example:

Whether perceptions of ASB are influenced by other factors such as personal

characteristics

If current measures of public perceptions are truly reflective of ASB

The factors that influence the perceived high levels of ASB of residents who live in

areas with a relatively low number of ASB incidents

The extent of the link between public expectations and public perceptions of ASB

An evaluation of the interventions used to reduce perceptions of high ASB

An in-depth investigation into the effect the media has upon public perceptions of

ASB

In a more general context, further research could consider the influence of local level context

on ASB interventions, with the prospect of investigating whether this has an impact upon

public perceptions of ASB. Future research could also investigate the (moral) characteristics

of perpetrators of ASB. In addition, further investigations of ASB and everyday morality

using ward level data may be useful. For example, littering was often perceived to be

immoral in the Rainford focus groups in the present study. Yet in Skelmersdale some

participants did not perceive littering to be immoral, even though they did not agree with it.

By isolating ward level data, it may be possible to investigate if higher incidences of littering

in Skelmersdale, or Rainford, are related to people’s understanding of moral values. Whilst

there is scope for future investigations, this research has provided one account of how public

170

perceptions on ASB may be influenced by a multitude of factors, but in particular by

perceptions of everyday morality. The findings from this study highlight an under-researched

topic.

171

References

Altheide, D. (2009). Moral Panic: From Sociological Concept to Public Discourse.

Crime, Media and Culture: An International Journal, 5(1), 79-99.

American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental

Disorders: DSM-IV-TR (4th ed., Text Revision). Washington, DC: American

Psychiatric Association.

Antonaccio, O., & Tittle, C. R. (2008). Morality, self‐control, and crime. Criminology, 46(2),

479-510.

Armstrong, G., & Wilson, M. (1973). City politics and deviancy amplification Politics and

Deviance. London: Penguin.

Bannister, J., Fyfe, N., & Kearns, A. (2006). Respectable or respectful? (In) civility and the

city. Urban Studies, 43(5/6), 919-937.

Bannister, J., & Kearns, A. (2013). Overcoming intolerance to young people’s conduct:

Implications from the unintended consequences of policy in the UK. Criminology and

Criminal Justice, 13(4), 380-397.

Bannister, J., & O’Sullivan, A. (2013). Civility, community cohesion and antisocial

behaviour: Policy and social harmony. Journal of Social Policy, 42(1), 91-110.

172

Bartels, Daniel M., Christopher W. Bauman, Fiery A. Cushman, David A. Pizarro, and A.

Peter McGraw (2015). ‘Moral Judgment and Decision Making’. In G. Keren & G. Wu

(Eds.) The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making (pp. 1-36).

Chichester, UK: Wiley.

Bearfield, D., 2008. The demonization of patronage: Folk Devils, Moral Panics and the

Boston Globe’s Coverage of the Terrorist Attacks of 9-11. International Journal of

Public Administration, 31 (5), 515–534.

Beauchamp, T. L. (2003). A defense of the common morality. Kennedy Institute of Ethics

Journal, 13(3), 259-274.

Becker, H. (1967). Whose Side Are We On? Social Problems,14(3), 239-247.

Berry, G. (2003). Young People and Anti-Social Behaviour. Criminal Justice Matters, 54(1),

12-12.

Blair, T. (2005). Speech outside 10 Downing Street, 6 May, London.

Bottoms, A. (2015). Christianity and Crime, Sermon at Trinity College Cambridge, 26 April,

available at: http://trinitycollegechapel.com/media/filestore/sermons/2015-4-26-

AnthonyBottoms.pdf.

Boyd, R. (2006). The value of civility?. Urban Studies, 43(5-6), 863–78.

173

Bramley, N. and Eatough, V. (2005). An idiographic case study of the experience of living

with Parkinson’s disease using interpretative phenomenological analysis. Psychology

and Health, 20(2), 223–235.

Bremner, P., Duffy, B., Wake, R., Burrows, T. (2008). Closing the gaps - crime and public

perceptions. International Review of Law, Computers & Technology, 22(1), 17-44.

Brown, A. P. (2004). Anti‐social behaviour, crime control and social control. The Howard

Journal of Criminal Justice, 43(2), 203-211.

Brown, K. (2012). Re-moralising ‘vulnerability’. People, Place and Policy Online, 6(1), 41-

53.

Brown, K. J. (2013). The Developing Habitus of the Anti‐Social Behaviour Practitioner:

From Expansion in Years of Plenty to Surviving the Age of Austerity. Journal of Law

and Society, 40(3), 375-402.

Browne, A. (2008). Has there been a decline in values in British society?. York: Joseph

Rowntree Foundation. Retrieved 12th February, 2015 from

https://www.jrf.org.uk/report/has-there-been-decline-values-british-society.

Brunger, M. (2008). Is zero tolerance the answer to our prayers. Fortnight, 462, 12-13.

Retrieved 28th September, 2015 from http://www.jstor.org/stable/25704193.

Bryman, A. (2012). Social Research Methods (4th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

174

Burck C. 2005. Comparing qualitative research methodologies for systemic research: the use

of grounded theory, discourse analysis and narrative analysis. Journal of Family

Therapy, 27(3), 237–262.

Burney, E. (2002). Talking Tough, Acting Coy: What Happened to the Anti-Social Behaviour

Order? The Howard Journal of Criminal Justice, 41(5), 469-484.

Burney, E. (2009). Making People Behave: Anti-Social Behaviour, Politics and Policy (2nd

ed.). Cullompton: Willan Publishing.

Burt, S. A., Donnellan, M. B., Iacono, W. G., & McGue, M. (2011). Age-of-onset or

behavioural sub types? A prospective comparison of two approaches to characterizing

the heterogeneity within antisocial behavior. Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology,

39 (5), 633–644.

Butler, S. (1996). Child protection or professional self-preservation by the baby nurses?:

Public health nurses and child protection in Ireland. Social Science & Medicine, 43,

303–314.

Cabinet Office. (2010). Building the Big Society, London: Cabinet Office. Retrieved 11th

January, 2015 from https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/building-the-big-

society.

175

Caelli, K., 2000. The changing face of phenomenological research: traditional and American

phenomenology in nursing. Qualitative Health Research, 10, 366–377.

Cameron, D. (2010) Big society speech. 19 July. Retrieved 24th September, 2014 from

http://www.number10.gov.uk/news/ speeches-and-transcripts/2010/07/big-society-

speech-53572.

Carnes, N. C., Lickel, B., & Janoff-Bulman, R. (2015). Shared perceptions: Morality is

embedded in social contexts. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(3), 351-

362.

Carr, H., & Cowan, D. (2006). Labelling: constructing definitions of anti-social behaviour? In

J. Flint (eds.) Housing, Governance and Antisocial Behaviour: Principles, Policy and

Practice (pp. 57-78). Bristol: Policy Press.

Carr, H., Cowan, D., & Hunter, C. (2007). Policing the housing crisis. Critical Social Policy,

27(1), 100-127.

Chambers, R. (1989). Editorial introduction: Vulnerability, coping and policy. IDS

Bulletin, 20(2), 1-7.

Charlick, S. J., Pincombe, J., McKellar, L., & Fielder, A. (2016). Making sense of participant

experiences: Interpretative phenomenological analysis in midwifery

research. International Journal of Doctoral Studies, 11, 205-216.

176

Chartered Institute of Housing (1995). Neighbour nuisance: ending the nightmare, Good

Practice Briefing No. 3. Coventry: Chartered Institute of Housing.

Clapham, D., & Kintrea, K. (1986). Rationing, choice and constraint: the allocation of public

housing in Glasgow. Journal of Social Policy, 15(1), 51-67.

Clark, M. S., & Mills, J. (1979). Interpersonal attraction in exchange and communal

relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37 (1), 12-24.

Cleland, A., & Tisdall, K. (2005). The challenge of antisocial behaviour: New relationships

between the state, children and parents. International Journal of Law, Policy and the

Family, 19(3), 395-420.

Crawford, A. (2006). 'Fixing broken promises?': Neighbourhood wardens and social

capital. Urban Studies, 43(5-6), 957-976.

Crawford (2008). ‘Dispersal Powers and the Symbolic Role of Anti-Social Behaviour

Legislation’. Modern Law Review, 71(5), 753–784.

Crawford, A., & Flint, J. (2009). Urban safety, anti-social behaviour and the night-time

economy. Criminology and Criminal Justice, 9(4), 403-413.

Critcher, C. (2008). Moral panic analysis: Past, Present and Future. Sociology Compass, 2(4),

1127-1144.

177

Crossley, S., & Lambert, M. (2017). Introduction: ‘Looking for trouble?’ critically examining

the UK government's troubled families programme. Social Policy and Society, 16(1),

81-85. 

Cogan, P. (2006). A Perspective on Anti-Social Behaviour. Studies: An Irish Quarterly

Review, 95 (377), 41-56.

Cohen, S. (1972). Folk Devils and Moral Panics: The Creation of the Mods and

Rockers. London: McGibbon and Kee.

Coleman R. (2005). Surveillance in the city: Primary definition and urban spatial order.

Crime, Media, Culture, 1(2), 131–148.

Conservatives. (2010). Invitation to Join the Government of Britain: The Conservative

Manifesto 2010. London: The Conservative Party.

Corrigan, P. and Sayer, D. (1985). The Great Arch: English State Formation as Cultural

Revolution. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Crime and Disorder Act (Section 1(a)) 1998. Retrieved October 22, 2014 from

http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1998/37/contents.

Croall, H. (2009). Community safety and economic crime. Criminology & Criminal Justice,

9(2), 165-185.

178

Crossley. M. L. (2000). Introducing Narrative Psychology: Self, trauma and the construction

of meaning. Buckingham: Open University Press.

Curtis, C. (2016). Anti-social Behaviour: A Multi-national Perspective of the Everyday to the

Extreme. London: Sage.

Data Protection Act. (1998). Retrieved June, 09 2015 from

www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1998/29.

Denham, B. E. (2008). Folk devils, news icons and the construction of moral panics: heroin

chic and the amplification of drug threats in contemporary society. Journalism

Studies, 9(6), 945-961.

Denovan, A., and Macaskill, A. (2013). An interpretative phenomenological analysis of stress

and coping in first year undergraduates. British Educational Research Journal, 39(6),

1002-1024.

Department for Communities and Local Government. (2011). English Indices of Deprivation.

Retrieved from https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/english-indices-of-

deprivation-2010.

Donoghue, J. C. (2012). Anti-social behaviour, community engagement and the judicial role

in England and Wales. British Journal of Criminology, 52(3), 591-610.

179

Dowling, M. (2007). From Husserl to van Manen. A review of different phenomenological

approaches. International Journal of Nursing Studies, 44(1), 131-142. 

Driver, J. (2007). Ethics: The Fundamentals. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

Eastwood, N. (2015). The coalition’s overhaul of anti-social behaviour legislation comes into

effect. Drugs and Alcohol Today, 15(2),

https://doi-org.edgehill.idm.oclc.org/10.1108/DAT-05-2015-0023.

Edwards, P. (2013). How the News was Made: The Anti-Social Behaviour Day Count,

Newsmaking Criminology and the Construction of Anti-Social Behaviour. Critical

Criminology, 21(2), 211-225.

Edwards, R., & Gillies, V. (2012). Farewell to family? Notes on an argument for retaining the

concept. Families, Relationships and Societies, 1(1), 63-69.

Egan, M., Neary, J., Keenan, P. J., & Bond, L. (2013). Perceptions of antisocial behaviour

and negative attitudes towards young people: focus group evidence from adult

residents of disadvantaged urban neighbourhoods (Glasgow, UK). Journal of Youth

Studies, 16(5), 612-627.

Elias, N. (2000) The Civilizing Process. Oxford: Blackwell.

Emerson E, Graham H, Hatton C. (2006). Household income and health status in children and

adolescents in Britain. European Journal of Public Health, 16(4), 354–360.

180

Etzioni A. (1988) The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. New York: The Free

Press.

Etzioni, A. (1993). The spirit of community. The Reinvention of American Society. New York:

Touchstone.

Farrington, D. P., & Welsh, B. C. (2008). Saving children from a life of crime: Early risk

factors and effective interventions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Farrow, K., & Prior, D. (2006). ‘Togetherness’? Tackling anti-social behaviour through

community engagement. Criminal Justice Matters, 64(1), 4–5.

Field, F. (2003). Neighbours from hell: the politics of behaviour. London: Politico.

Flinders, M. V. (2012). The demonisation of politicians: moral panics, folk devils and MPs’

expenses. Contemporary Politics, 18(1), 1-17.

Flint, J. (2002). Social housing agencies and the governance of anti-social behaviour.

Housing Studies, 17(4), 619-637.

Flint, J. (2006). Housing, urban governance and anti-social behaviour: perspectives, policy

and practice. Bristol: Policy Press.

181

Flint, J. (2014). Conditionality Briefing: Anti-social Behaviour. Retrieved 13th August, 2015

from http://www.welfareconditionality.ac.uk.

Flint, J., & Nixon, J. (2006). Governing neighbours: Anti-social behaviour orders and new

forms of regulating conduct in the UK. Urban Studies, 43(5-6), 939-955.

Flint, J., Casey, R., Davidson, E., Pawson, H., & Mc Coulough, E. (2007a). Tackling anti-

social behaviour in Glasgow: An evaluation of policy and practice in the Glasgow

Housing Association. Glasgow: Glasgow Housing Association. Retrieved 20th

September, 2014 from: http://www.gha.org.uk.

Flint, J., & Powell, R. (2009). Civilising offensives: education, football and eradicating

sectarianism in Scotland. In Millie, A., (ed.) Securing Respect: Behavioural

Expectations and Anti-Social Behaviour in the UK (219-238). Bristol: Policy Press.

Forrest, S., Myhill, A., & Tilley, N. (2005). Practical Lessons for Involving the Community in

Crime and Disorder problem-solving. Development and Practice Report 43. London:

Home Office.

Forrest S., and Tilley, N. (2005b). Nottingham Anti-Social Behaviour Task Force: Interim

Report. Technical Report to Research, Development and Statistics (RDS) Directorate.

London: Home Office.

Fyson, R., and Yates J. (2011). Anti-social behaviour orders and young people with learning

disabilities. Critical Social Policy, 31(1), 102-125.

182

Gaskell, C. (2008). 'But They Just Don't Respect Us': young people's experiences of

(dis)respected citizenship and the New Labour Respect Agenda. Children's

Geographies, 6(3), 223-238.

Gillies, V. (2005). Meeting parents’ needs? Discourses of ‘support ‘and ‘inclusion’ in family

policy. Critical Social Policy, 25(1), 70-90.

Gillies, V. (2008) ‘Childrearing, Class, and the New Politics of Parenting’. Sociology

Compass, 2(3), 1079–95.

Goode, E., and Ben-Yehuda, N. (1994a). Moral Panics: The Social Construction of

Deviance. Cambridge: Blackwell.

Gottfredson, M. R., & Hirschi, T. (1990). A General Theory of Crime. Stanford, California:

Stanford University Press.

Gregg, D. (2010). Family intervention projects: a classic case of policy-based evidence.

London: Centre for Crime and Research Studies. Retrieved December 03, 2014 from

http://www.crimeandjustice.org.uk.

Green, L. (2013). Should Law Improve Morality?. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 7(3), 473-

494.

183

Groenewald, T. (2004). A phenomenological research design illustrated. International

Journal of Qualitative Methods, 3(1), 1-26.

Haan, N. (1982). Can research on morality be "scientific"? American Psychologist, 37(10),

1096-1104. 

Haidt J. (2008). Morality. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(1), 65-72.

Hall, S., Clarke, J., Critcher, C., Jefferson, T., & Roberts, B. (1978). Policing the crisis:

Mugging, law and order and the state. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Halla, M., & Schneider, F. G. (2014). Taxes and benefits: Two options to cheat on the state.

Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 76(3), 411-431.

Hancock, L. (2001). Community, Crime and Disorder: Safety and Regeneration in Urban

Neighbourhoods, Basingstoke: Palgrave.

Hannon L., DeFronzo J., Prochnow J. (2001). Moral commitment and the effects of social

influences on violent delinquency. Violence and Victims, 16(4), 427– 39.

Harcourt, B. E., & Ludwig, J. (2006). Broken windows: New evidence from New York City

and a five city social experiment. University of Chicago Law Review, 73, 271–320.

Hart, H.L.A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

184

Hayward, K., & Yar, M. (2006). The ‘chav’ phenomenon: Consumption, media and the

construction of a new underclass. Crime, Media, Culture, 2(1), 9-28. 

Heap, V. (2009) “I don’t say that bored kids hanging about are bad, but they are scary!”

Exploring attitudinal factors that affect public perceptions of anti-social behaviour.

Papers from the British Criminology Conference (9): 71-91. Available at:

http://www.britsoccrim.org/volume9/5.Heap09.pdf

Heap, V. (2014) Transforming Anti-Social Behaviour: ASBOs, Injunctions and Cross-

Cutting Criminal Justice Concerns. British Journal of Community Justice 12(3): 67-

79.

Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York:

Harper and Row.

Herman, B. (2000). Morality and everyday life. Proceedings and Addresses of the American

Philosophical Association, 74(2), 29 - 45.

Hewitt, D. (2007). Bovvered? A legal perspective on the ASBO. Journal of Forensic and

Legal Medicine, 14(6), 355-363.

Hier, S. P., Lett, D., Walby, K., & Smith, A. (2011). Beyond folk devil resistance: Linking

moral panic and moral regulation. Criminology and Criminal Justice, 11(3), 259-276.

Hirschi, T. (1969). Causes of delinquency. Berkeley: University of California Press.

185

Hodgkinson S., & Tilley, N. (2011). Tackling anti-social behaviour: Lessons from New

Labour for the Coalition Government. Criminology and Criminal Justice, 11(4), 283-

305.

Home Office. (1999). Crime and Disorder Act 1998 Anti-Social Behaviour Orders:

Guidance. London: Home Office.

Home Office. (2002). A Guide to Anti-social Behaviour Orders and Acceptable Behaviour

Contracts. Retrieved October 28, from http://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk.

Home Office. (2003). Respect and Responsibility: Taking a Stand against Anti-social

Behaviour. London: Home Office.

Home Office. (2003). Anti-Social Behaviour Act. Retrieved December 05, 2014 from

http://www.legislation.gov.uk.

Home Office (2004). Defining and Measuring Anti-Social Behaviour. Retrieved October 28,

2014 from https://www.gov.uk/government.

Home Office. (2006b). Respect Action Plan. Ref. 272299. London: Home Office.

Home Office. (2009). Anti-Social Behaviour Orders: Statistics. Retrieved October 24, 2014

from www.crimereduction.homeoffice.gov.uk/asbos.

186

Home Office. (2011). More Effective Responses to Anti-social Behaviour. London: Home

Office.

Home Office. (2012). Focus on the Victim: Summary Report on the ASB Call Handling

Trials. Retrieved October 24, 2014 from

http://www.acpo.police.uk/documents/LPpartnerships.

Home Office. (2013). Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Bill Fact Sheet: Replacing

the ASBO (Parts 1 and 2). Retrieved December 02, 2014 from

https://www.gov.uk/government.

Home Office. (2014). Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Act 2014: Reform of anti-

social behaviour powers. Retrieved December 02, 2014 from

https://www.gov.uk/government.

House of Commons Briefing Paper (2017). The Troubled Families Programme (England).

Retrieved April 19, 2017 from

http://researchbriefings.parliament.uk/ResearchBriefing.

Housing Act 1996. Retrieved December 02, 2014 from

http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1996/52.

Howitt, D. (2010). Introduction to qualitative methods in psychology. New Jersey NJ:

Prentice Hall.

187

Hughes, N. (2011). Young people ‘as risk’ or young people ‘at risk’: Comparing discourses

of anti-social behaviour in England and Victoria. Critical Social Policy, 31(3), 388-

409.

Hunt, A. (1997). ‘moral panic’ and Moral Language in the Media. The British Journal of

Sociology, 48(4), 632–633.

Hunt, A. (1999). Governing Morals: A Social History of Moral Regulation. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Hyden, L. C., & Bülow, P. H. (2003). Who's talking: drawing conclusions from focus groups

—some methodological considerations. International Journal of Social Research

Methodology, 6(4), 305-321.

Innes, M. (2004). Signal crimes and signal disorders: Notes on deviance as communicative

action. The British Journal of Sociology, 55(3), 335-355.

Jewkes, Y. (2004). Media and Crime: A Critical Introduction. London: Sage.

Johnson, R., and Cureton, A. (2018). Kant's Moral Philosophy. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The

Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.). Retrieved from

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/

Johnstone, C. (2016). After the asbo: Extending control over young people’s use of public

space in England and wales. Critical Social Policy, 36(4), 716-726.

188

Kant, I. (1785/1990). ‘Grounding for the metaphysics of morals’. In S.M. Cahn (ed.) Classics

of Western Philosophy, third edition (pp. 1009-1058). Indianapolis: Hackett.

Karstedt, S., & Farrall, S. (2006). The Moral Economy of Everyday Crime: Markets,

Consumers and Citizens. British Journal of Criminology, 46(6), 1011-1036.

Kaufman, G. (1993). The psychology of shame: Theory and treatment of shame-based

syndromes. London: Routledge.

Kearns, A. & Forrest, R. (2000). Social cohesion and multilevel urban governance. Urban

Studies, 37(5), 995–1017.

Keizer, K., Lindenberg, S., & Steg, L. (2011). The reversal effect of prohibition signs. Group

Processes & Intergroup Relations, 14(5), 681–688.

Kelling, G., & Coles, C. (1996). Fixing broken windows: Restoring order and reducing crime

in our communities. New York: Free Press.

Kirby, S., & Edmondson, A. (2012). The effectiveness of the ASBO–a practitioner

perspective. Safer Communities, 11(2), 96-104.

Koch, K., & Menezes, C. (2015). Virtue ethics: Beyond moral theory. South African Journal

of Bioethics and Law, 8(2), 48-49.

189

Korsgaard, C.M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Kukla, R. (2014). Living with Pirates. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 23(1), 75-

85.

Krueger, R. A., & Casey, M. A. (2000). Focus groups: A practical guide for applied research

(3rd ed.). London: Sage.

Kullberg A., Karlsson N., Timpka T., Lindqvist K. (2009). Correlates of local safety related

concerns in a Swedish Community: a cross-sectional study. BioMed Central

Public Health, 9(1), 221.

Le Sage, L., & De Ruyter, D. (2008). Criminal parental responsibility: Blaming parents on

the basis of their duty to control versus their duty to morally educate their children.

Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(6), 789-802.

Larkin, M., Watts, S., and Clifton, E. (2006). Giving voice and making sense in interpretative

phenomenological analysis. Qualitative Research in Psychology, 3(2), 102–20.

Laverty, S. M. (2008). Hermeneutic phenomenology and phenomenology: A comparison of

historical and methodological considerations. International Journal of Qualitative

Methods, 2(3), 21-35.

190

Lægaard, S. (2008). A Multicultural Social Ethos: Tolerance, Respect or Civility? Paper

presented at the UACES conference ‘Exchanging Ideas on Europe: Values and Ethos

in an Enlarging Europe: Multicultural Debates’. Edinburgh: UK.

Labour Party. (1995). A Quiet Life: tough action on criminal neighbours. London: Labour

Party.

Lent, A. (2008). A Crisis in Civility. Journal of Labour Politics, 16(3/4), 8-19.

Leonard, V. W. (1999). A Heideggerian phenomenological perspective on the concept of the

person. In Polifroni, E. C., and Welch, M. (Eds.). Perspectives on philosophy of

science in nursing: An historical and contemporary anthology (pp. 315-327).

Philadelphia: Lippincott.

Liberty. (2015). Campaigning against: Public Space Protection Orders. Retrieved from

www.liberty-human-rights.org.uk/campaigning/public-space-protection-orders-0.

Luco, A. (2014). The definition of morality: Threading the needle. Social Theory and

Practice, 40(3), 361.

Lopez, K.A. and Willis, D.G. 2004, Descriptive Versus Interpretive Phenomenology: Their

Contributions to Nursing Knowledge. Qualitative Health Research, 14(5), 726-735.

191

MacDonald, I. (2002). Anti-social behaviour orders: some current issues. Journal of Social

Welfare and Family Law, 24(2), 205-222.

Macdonald, S. (2006). A Suicidal Woman, Roaming Pigs and a Noisy Trampolinist: Refining

the ASBO's Definition of ‘Anti‐Social Behaviour’. The Modern Law Review, 69(2),

183-213.

MacIntyre, A. (1981). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London: Duckworth.

Mackenzie, S., Bannister, J., Flint, J., Parr, S., Millie, A. and Fleetwood, J. (2010). The

Drivers of Perceptions of Anti-Social Behaviour. Home Office Research Report 34.

London: Home Office.

May, T. (2010). Moving beyond the ASBO. Speech at the Coin Street Community Centre,

London, 28 July. Retrieved from

[http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/media-centre/speeches/beyond-the-asbo?version=1].

Maxwell. J. A. (2005). Qualitative research design: An interactive approach (2nd ed.).

London: Sage.

McRobbie, A., and Thornton, S.L. (1995). Rethinking ‘Moral Panic’ for Multi-mediated

Social Worlds. British Journal of Sociology, 46(4), 559-74.

Matthews, R. and Briggs, D. (2008). ‘Lost in translation: interpreting and implementing anti-

social behaviour policies’. In Squires, P. (ed.). ASBO nation: the criminalisation of

192

nuisance (pp. 87-100). Bristol: Policy Press.

McCarthy, D. J. (2011). Classing early intervention: Social class, occupational moralities and

criminalization. Critical Social Policy, 31(4), 495-516.

McDowell, L. (2004). Work, workfare, work/life balance and an ethic of care. Progress in

Human Geography, 28(2), 145-163.

McLaughlin, E., Muncie, J., & Hughes, G. (2001). The permanent revolution: New labour,

new public management and the modernization of criminal justice. Criminology &

Criminal Justice, 1(3), 301-318.

Michener, J. (2013). Neighbourhood disorder and local participation: Examining the political

relevance of Broken windows. Political Behavior, 35(4), 777-806. 

Miller, J. D., & Lynam, D. (2001). Structural Models of Personality and their Relation to

Antisocial Behaviour: A Meta-Analytic Review. Criminology, 39(4), 765-798.

Millie, A., Jacobson, J., McDonald, E. and Hough, M. (2005a). Anti-Social Behaviour

Strategies: Finding a Balance. Bristol: Policy Press.

Millie, A. (2006). Anti-social behaviour: Concerns of minority and marginalised

Londoners. Internet Journal of Criminology, 1-20.

193

Millie, A. (2008). Anti‐Social Behaviour in British Cities. Geography Compass, 2(5), 1681-

1696.

Millie, A. (2008). Anti-Social Behaviour, Behavioural Expectations and an Urban Aesthetic.

British Journal of Criminology, 48(3), 379–394.

Millie, A. (2009). Anti-Social Behaviour. Maidenhead: Open University Press.

Millie, A. (2009). Securing respect: Behavioural expectations and anti-social behaviour in

the UK. Bristol: Policy Press.

Millie, A. (2010). ‘It’s time to move beyond the ASBO’: The Coalition and Anti-Social

Behaviour. Howard League Early Career Academics Bulletin (6), 9–12.

Millie, A. (2010). Moral Politics, Moral Decline and ASB. People, Place and Policy

Online, 4(1), 6 – 13.

Millie, A. (2011). Value Judgments and Criminalization. British Journal of

Criminology, 51(2), 278-295.

Millie, A. (2016). Philosophical Criminology. Bristol: Policy Press.

Miner-Romanoff, K. (2012). Interpretive and Critical Phenomenological Crime Studies: A

Model Design. Qualitative Report, 17(54), 1-32.

194

Ministry of Justice (2011, October 13). Anti-Social Behaviour Order Statistics: England and

Wales 2009. Retrieved 12th November, 2015 from

https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/

116712/asbo10snr.pdf.

Ministry of Justice. (2012, October 18). Anti-social behaviour order statistics: England and

Wales 2011. Retrieved 12th November, 2015 from

https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/anti-social-behaviour-order-statistics-

england-and-wales-2011-2.

Ministry of Justice. (2013, October 31). Anti-social behaviour order statistics: England and

Wales 2012. Retrieved 12th November, 2015 from

https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/anti-social-behaviour-order-statistics-

england-and-wales-2012.

Moore, S., & Statham, E. (2006). Can Intergenerational Practice Offer a Way of Limiting

Anti‐Social Behaviour and Fear of Crime?. The Howard Journal of Criminal

Justice, 45(5), 468-484.

Morgado, A. M., & Vale-Dias, M. D. L. (2013). The antisocial phenomenon in adolescence:

What is literature telling us?. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 18(4), 436-443.

Morgan, D. L. (1998). Practical strategies for combining qualitative and quantitative

methods: Applications to health research. Qualitative Health Research, 8(3), 362-376

195

Neary, J., Egan, M., Keenan, P. J., Lawson, L., & Bond, L. (2013). Damned if they do,

damned if they don't: negotiating the tricky context of anti-social behaviour and

keeping safe in disadvantaged urban neighbourhoods. Journal of Youth Studies, 16(1),

118-134.

Nixon, J., Parr, S. and Sanderson, D. (2008). The Longer-term Outcomes for Families Who

Have Worked with Intensive Family Support Projects. London: Communities and

Local Government.

O'Connell, M., & Whelan, A. (1996). The public perception of crime prevalence, newspaper

readership and ‘mean world’ attitudes. Legal and Criminological Psychology, 1(2),

179-195.

Office for National Statistics. (2012). 2011 Census: Key Statistics for England and Wales,

March 2011. Retrieved 15th November, 2014 from www.ons.gov.uk.

Office of Deputy Prime Minister. (2003). Tackling Anti-Social Behaviour in Mixed Tenure

Areas. Housing Research Summary, 178. Wetherby: Office of the Deputy Prime

Minister.

Office for National Statistics. (2013). Crime in England and Wales, Year Ending September

2012. Retrieved 15th November, 2014 from http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons.

Office for National Statistics. (2013). Short Story on anti-social behaviour, 2011/12.

Retrieved 15th November, 2015 from http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons.

196

Office for National Statistics. (2015). Crime in England and Wales, Year Ending September

2014. Retrieved 24th November, 2015 from ONS http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons.

Onwuegbuzie, A. J., Dickinson, W. B., Leech, N. L., & Zoran, A. G. (2009). A qualitative

framework for collecting and analyzing data in focus group research. International

Journal of Qualitative Methods, 8(3), 1-21.

Palmer, M., Larkin, M., de Visser, R., and Fadden, G. (2010). Developing an interpretative

phenomenological approach to focus group data. Qualitative Research in Psychology,

7(2), 99-121.

Papps, P. (1998). Anti-social behaviour strategies—individualistic or holistic? Housing

Studies, 13(5), 639–656.

Parr, S. (20100. Family policy and the governance of anti-social behaviour in the UK:

Women’s experiences of intensive family support. Journal of Social Policy, 40(4),

717-737.

Payne, L. (2003). Anti‐social behaviour. Children & Society, 17(4), 321-324.

Pearson, G. (1983). Hooligan: A History of Respectable Fears. Basingstoke: Palgrave

Macmillan.

197

Pearson, G. (2009) A Jekyll in the classroom, a Hyde in the street: Queen Victoria’s

hooligans’. In: A. Millie (ed.). Securing Respect: Behavioural Expectations and Anti-

Social Behaviour in the UK (pp. 41-71).  Bristol: Policy Press.

Peters, D. A. (1993). Improving quality requires consumer input: Using focus groups.

Journal of Nursing Care Quality, 7, 34–41.

Peters, E. (2012). I blame the mother: Educating parents and the gendered nature of parenting

orders. Gender and Education, 24(1), 119-130.

Pietkiewicz, I., & Smith, J. A. (2012). A practical guide to using interpretative

phenomenological analysis in qualitative research psychology. Psychological Journal,

20(1), 7-14.

Pitts, J. (2001) The New Politics of Youth Crime. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

Piotrowska, P. J., Stride, C. B., & Rowe, R. (2012). Social gradients in child and adolescent

antisocial behavior: A systematic review protocol. Systematic Reviews, 1(1), 38-38.

Prior, D. (2009). The problem of anti-social behaviour and the policy knowledge base:

Analysing the power/knowledge relationship. Critical Social Policy, 29(1), 5-23.

Prior, D. and Paris, A. (2005) Preventing children’s involvement in crime and anti-social

behaviour: A literature review, Research Report No. 623, Nottingham: Department

for Education and Skills.

198

Powell, R., & Flint, J. (2009). (in)formalization and the civilizing process: Applying the work

of Norbert Elias to housing-based anti-social behaviour interventions in the UK.

Housing, Theory and Society, 26(3), 159-178.

Public Order Act 1986. Retrieved October 22, 2014 from

http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1986/64.

Ramsay, P. (2004). What is anti-social behaviour?. The Criminal Law Review, 908-925.

Respect Task Force. (2006a). Respect Action Plan. London: Home Office.

Respect Task Force (2006b) Family Intervention Projects: Respect Guide. London: Home

Office.

Robson, C. (2011). Real world research: A resource for social-scientists and practitioner-

researchers. 3rd edition. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

Rogers M., Smoak N.D., Liu J (2005). Self-reported deviant computer behavior: A big-5,

moral choice, and manipulative exploitive behavior analysis. Deviant Behavior, 27(3),

45– 68.

Rohloff, A., & Wright, S. (2010). Moral Panic and Social Theory Beyond the

Heuristic. Current Sociology, 58(3), 403-419.

199

Rose, N. (1996). The death of the social? Refiguring the territory of government. Economy

and Society, 25(3), 327–356.

Rose, N. (1999). Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Samuels, A. (2005). Anti-social behaviour orders: Their legal and jurisprudential

significance. Journal of Criminal Law, 69(3), 223-231.

Sadler, J. (2008). Implementing the Youth 'Anti-social Behaviour' Agenda: Policing the

Ashton Estate. Youth Justice, 8(1), 57-73.

Sayer, A. (2017). Responding to the troubled families programme: Framing the injuries of

inequality. Social Policy and Society, 16(1), 155-164.

Scott, S., & Parkey, H. (1998). Myths and reality: anti-social behaviour in Scotland. Housing

Studies, 13(3), 325-345.

Seale, C. (1999). Quality in qualitative research. Qualitative Inquiry, 5, 465-478.

Seidman, I. (2006). Interviewing as qualitative research: A guide for researchers in

education and the social sciences (3rd ed.). New York: Teachers College Press.

Sennett, R. (2003). Respect: The Formation of Character in an Age of Inequality. London:

Penguin Books.

200

Sherman, W. L., and Strange, H. (2004). Experimental ethnography: The marriage of

qualitative and quantitative research. Annals of the American Academy of Political

and Social Sciences, 595(1), 204-221.

Shoemaker, P.J., & Reese, S.D. (1996). Mediating the Message: theories of influences on

mass media content, New York: Longman.

Sim, J. (1998). Collecting and analysing qualitative data: issues raised by the focus

group. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 28(2), 345-352.

Skogan, W. (1990). Disorder and Decline: Crime and the Spiral of Decay in American

Neighbourhoods. New York: Free Press.

Skogan, W. G. (2008). Broken Windows: Why—And How—We Should Take Them

Seriously. Criminology & Public Policy, 7, 195–201.

Slemrod, J. (2007). Cheating ourselves: the economics of tax evasion. The Journal of

Economic Perspectives, 21(1), 25-48.

Smaling, A. (2003). Inductive, analogical, and communicative generalization. International

Journal of Qualitative Methods, 2(1), 52-67.

Smith, R. (2003) Youth Justice: Ideas, Policy, Practice. Cullompton: Willan.

201

Smith, J. A. (2003). Qualitative psychology: A practical guide to research methods. London:

Sage.

Smith, J.A. (2004) ‘Reflecting on the development of interpretative phenomenological

analysis and its contribution to qualitative research in psychology’. Qualitative

Research in Psychology, 1, 39–54.

Smith, J.A. (2007). Hermeneutics, human sciences and health: linking theory and practice.

International Journal of Qualitative Studies on Health and Well-Being, 2. 3–11.

Smith, J. A. and Eatough, V. (2006). Interpretative phenomenological analysis. In Breakwell,

G., Fife-Schaw, C., Hammond. S., and Smith, J.A. (Eds). Research methods in

psychology, 3rd edition (pp. 322-341). London: Sage.

Smith, JA. & Eatough, V. (2012). Interpretative phenomenological analysis. In G. M

Breakwell, J. A Smith & D. B Wright (Eds.) Research Methods in Psychology, 4th

Edition (pp. 439-461). London: Sage.

Smith, J., Flowers, P., and Larkin, M. (2009). Interpretative phenomenological analysis:

Theory, method and research. Los Angeles: Sage.

Smith, P., & Phillips, T. (2004). Emotional and behavioural responses to everyday incivility:

Challenging the fear/avoidance paradigm [paper in special issue: Fear and loathing in

the new century. Journal of Sociology, 40(4), 378-399.

202

Squires, P. (2006). New Labour and the politics of antisocial behaviour. Critical Social

Policy, 26(1), 144-168.

Squires, P. (2008) (ed.) ASBO Nation: The Criminalisation of Nuisance, Bristol: Policy Press.

Squires, P. and Stephen, D.E. (2005) Rougher Justice: Anti-Social Behaviour and Young

People, Cullompton: Willan Publishing.

Starks, H., & Brown Trinidad, S. (2007). Choose your method: A comparison of

phenomenology, discourse analysis, and grounded theory. Qualitative Health

Research, 17(10), 1372-1380.

Thompson, K. (1998). Moral Panics. London & New York: Routledge.

Tisdall, E. K. M. (2006). Antisocial behaviour legislation meets children's services:

challenging perspectives on children, parents and the state. Critical Social

Policy, 26(1), 101-120.

Tracy, S. J. (2010). Qualitative quality: Eight big-tent criteria for excellent qualitative

research. Qualitative Inquiry, 16(10), 837-851.

Tyler, T. R., & Darley, J. M. (1999). Building a law-abiding society: Taking public views

about morality and the legitimacy of legal authorities into account when formulating

substantive law. Hofstra Law Review, 28(3), 707.

203

Upson, A. (2006). Perceptions and experience of anti-social behaviour: Findings from the

2004/05 British Crime Survey. London: Home Office.

Varnfield, K. (2005). Vulnerable young people and the misuse of anti-social behaviour

orders. Safer Communities, 4(1), 33-37.

Waiton, S. (2005). ‘The politics of antisocial behaviour’. In C. O’Malley and S. Waiton

(eds.). Who’s Antisocial? New Labour and the Politics of Antisocial Behaviour.

Institute of Ideas Occasional Paper No. 2. London: Academy of Ideas Ltd.

Waiton, S. (2008). 'Asocial not Anti-social: The Respect Agenda and the Therapeutic Me', in

P. Squires (ed.). ASBO Nation: The Criminalisation of Nuisance. Bristol: Policy

Press.

Walsh, C. (2003). Dispersal of rights: a critical comment on specified provisions of the anti-

social behaviour bill. Youth Justice, 3(2), 104-111.

Wenham, A. (2017). Struggles and silences: Young people and the ‘Troubled families

programme’. Social Policy and Society, 16(1), 143-153.

Whitaker, R. C. (2003). Obesity prevention in paediatric primary care: four behaviours to

target. Archives of Paediatric & Adolescent Medicine, 157(8), 725.

White, C., Warrener, M., Reeves, A., & La Valle, I. (2008). Family Intervention Projects: An

evaluation of their design, set-up and early outcomes. Retrieved December 04, 2014

204

from https://www.gov.uk.

Whitehead, C.M.E., Stockdale, J.E. and Razzu, G. (2003). The economic and social costs of

anti-social behaviour, London: London School of Economics.

Whiteley, J.M. (1982). Approaches to the evaluation of character development. In: J.M.

Whiteley (Ed.) Character Development in College Students, (111–172). New York:

Character Research Press.

Wicherts, J. M., & Bakker, M. (2014). Broken windows, mediocre methods, and substandard

statistics. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 17(3), 388-403.

Wigzell, A. (2014). Moving beyond the ASBO? A review of the proposed anti-social

behaviour measures and their implications for children. Safer Communities, 13 (2),

73-82.

Wintour, P. (2005, May 18). Blair believes his agenda is a moral certainty. The Guardian,

p.1. Retrieved 10th December, 2014 from:

http://www.theguardian.com/politics/2005/may/18/uk.society.

Wood, M. (2004). Perceptions and Experiences of Anti-Social Behaviour: Findings from the

British Crime Survey 2003/04. Retrieved 24th October 2014 from

http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds.

205

Yan, Y. (2014). The moral implications of immorality. Journal of Religious Ethics, 42(3),

460-493.

York, J. (2006). Neighbourhood crime and anti-social behaviour: the Audit Commission

report. Safer Communities, 5(4), 17-23.

Young, J., 1971. The Drugtakers. London: McGibbon and Kee.

Appendix A

206

Summary Protocol for Using IPA with Focus Group Data

1. Objects of Concern and Experiential Claims

a. Pick out experiential claims and concerns as they appear in the transcript.

b. Summarise these, and sort into emergent patterns

2. Positionality

a. Explore the role played by facilitators, keeping track of questions, permissions,

encouragements, redirections, etc. (What is their perspective, stance, position?)

b. Explore the function of statements made by respondents. (What is their perspective,

stance?)

3. Roles & Relationships

a. Examine references to other people: What roles and relationships are described?

What sorts of meanings and expectations are attributed to these relationships?

b. What are understood to be the consequences of these?

4. Organisations & Systems

a. Examine references to organisations and systems: How are they described? What

sorts of meanings and expectations are attributed to these?

b. What are understood to be the consequences of these?

5. Stories

Examine the stories told by participants: look at the structure; genre; imagery and

tone. What does each story achieve? How do participants support or impede each

other to share their experiences? What temporal referents exist?

6. Language

Throughout stages 1–5, monitor language use, paying attention to use of metaphor,

euphemism, idiom, etc. Consider:

a. Patterns

Repetition, jargon, stand-out words and phrases, turn-taking, prompting – are these

identified in individuals or the whole group?

b. Context

Impact on language used; descriptions of feelings/emotive language; jargon and

explanation of technical terms; impact of facilitator.

c. Function

How/why is certain language being used? (e.g. to emphasise/back-up a point, to

207

shock, to provoke dis/agreement, to amuse/lighten the tone?)

7. Adaptation of Emergent Themes

Return to the emergent themes from step 1b. and adapt them according to the work

done subsequently. Answering the following questions will help:

a. What experiences are being shared?

b. What are individuals doing by sharing their experiences?

c. How are they making those things meaningful to one another?

d. What are they doing as a group?

e. What are the consensus issues?

f. Where is there conflict? How is this being managed/resolved?

8. Integration of Multiple Cases

Where more than one focus group has taken place, integrate work done with each to

build up an overall analysis of the topic under investigation. Data should be checked

to ensure sufficient homogeneity between focus groups to allow for successful

integration. To draw the analysis to completion:

a. Pick out commonalities and stand-out differences between groups drawing out

superordinate themes.

b. Frequently revisit the transcripts to check themes in relation to original claims

made to help ensure accuracy.

c. Consider the analysis in the wider context of existing relevant theories, models and

explanations.

See Palmer et al., (2010) for an in-depth detailed discussion of each step.

Appendix B

Consent Form

Study Title: Everyday Morality and Anti-social Behaviour

Name of Researcher:

208

Jan Adams. Email address: [email protected].

Mobile Number - 07919406540

Research Supervisor:

Professor Andrew Millie. Email address: [email protected]

Research University:

Edge Hill University, St Helens Road, Ormskirk, Lancashire, L39 4QP.

This focus group will investigate anti-social behaviour and everyday morality in modern society. The aim is to investigate how people perceive everyday morality and anti-social behaviour as two related or unrelated concepts. This will be achieved via your participation as an active member in a focus group. The focus group will be recorded for analysis purposes and to minimise interruptions during the discussion. In order to participate in this study, it is necessary that you give your informed consent. By signing this form you are indicating that you give your informed consent to partake in the research. You are also acknowledging that you understand what your role as a participant will involve, the nature of the study, and that you agree to this. Please consider the following points before signing the form: I understand that I am participating in criminological and philosophical research

regarding anti-social behaviour and everyday morality I understand that my identity will not be linked with my data, and that all information I

provide will remain confidential I understand that participation in the research is voluntary and that I may refuse to

participate without penalty I understand that I may withdraw my data up to 4 weeks following my participation I agree to the recording of the focus group and understand that this data will be

confidential, anonymous and stored securely I understand the data gathered in this project may form the basis of a report or other form

of publication or presentation I understand that any demographic information I provide will be treated with the strictest

confidentiality and will not be presented/used to identify me.

By signing this form, I am stating that I am over 18 years of age, and that I understand the above information and consent to participate in this study

Participants signature:……………………………………………………….Date……………Participants name (in capitals):………………………………………………………………...

Researchers signature………………………………………………………..Date……………Researchers Name (in capitals)…………………………………………………………………

Appendix C

Participant Demographic Information Sheet

Study Title: Everyday Morality and Anti-social Behaviour

209

This information sheet is to gather demographical information for your participation in the current research study. All information you answer on this form will be kept strictly confidential and anonymous. You do not have to complete this information to participate in the study if you do not wish to. This data will allow for further analysis and reflection on the data collected. All information provided will kept confidential and stored securely.

Participant Number:

Gender: Marital status:

Age Group (please tick as appropriate):

18-1920-2930-3940-4950-5960-6970+

Do you have children?

If you have children, do you currently have children under the age of 18?

Occupation (if retired please state last occupation prior to retirement):

Postcode: Homeowner / private tenant / social housing tenant:

Appendix D

Participant debriefing formStudy Title: Everyday Morality and Anti-social Behaviour

210

Thank you for participating in the present study regarding everyday morality and anti-social behaviour. The study aimed to discover your beliefs and views relating to whether everyday morality has a role in public perceptions of anti-social behaviour. The use of focus groups and your responses have facilitated the generation of data which was recorded. All data recorded from this interview and all information you have provided will be stored and maintained completely confidential. In addition, all data you have provided will be anonymised to prevent the identification of you or other participants. If you have any additional questions regarding the nature of this study or any general queries whatsoever you may utilise the contact details supplied below. If you desire to withdraw your data from the study this can be done during a four week period from the date of your participation.

In the event that your participation in the study has caused any distress or harm, including from topics discussed in the focus group, there are contact details provided below. There are also details provided for the Samaritans Helpline should you feel the desire to contact a professional counselling service to help with any issues raised in this study.Thank you for your participation in this study.

Researcher contact detailsResearcher’s name: Jan Adams. Email: [email protected]’s name: Andrew Millie. Email: [email protected]

Support contact 1Counselling and Supervisory ServicesThe Health and Well-being Centre, Milton House41 Ruff LaneOrmskirkL39 4QX.Telephone number: 01695650988Email address: [email protected]

Support contact 2 Support for individuals to any person in distressSamaritans helplineTelephone number: 08457909090Web address: www.samaritans.org

Appendices E

Interview ScheduleEveryday Morality and Anti-social Behaviour.

211

> TIMING GUIDE: 00:00

-Briefly explain purpose of the study, what is involved and put participants at ease.

Introduce Researcher

Hello and welcome. Firstly, I would just like to thank you all for coming today. This focus group will discuss anti-social behaviour and everyday morality in modern society. The focus group will be recorded for analysis purposes and to minimise interruptions during the discussion. There are no right or wrong answers to these questions and it is expected that there may be differences of opinion and beliefs. If there are differences please feel free to voice your individual opinions whether it is in agreement or different to any other views voiced in the study. [Go through the information sheet and pass copies round. Then ask participants to sign the consent form]

Are there any questions before we begin?

Section 1 – General/opening questions

Firstly, can we go around the group and just briefly introduce ourselves one at a time by giving your first name.

> TIMING GUIDE: 05:00

Section 2 -- Introductory questions

1. When you hear the term ‘Anti-social Behaviour’ what are your first thoughts?

2. When you hear the term ‘Morality’ what are your first thoughts?

3. What do you think ‘everyday morality’ might refer to?

4. Has anyone ever had any experience of, or witnessed, an example of something they considered to be Anti-social Behaviour?

5. How did this make you feel? In your view was this anti-social behaviour also morally wrong? Why?

6. Has anyone encountered any other everyday behaviour that they thought is morally wrong, or morally right, but which also seemed capable of being perceived as ASB?

> TIMING GUIDE: 20:00

Section 3 - Transition question

212

7. Can you give any three or four examples of everyday behaviours you would perceive as being anti-social? What makes these behaviours anti-social?

8. Can you give any three or four examples of everyday behaviours you would perceive as being morally ‘good’ and three or four that are morally ‘bad’? What makes these behaviours morally good or morally bad?

9. Why, in your opinion, may an individual or group participate in ‘moral’ behaviours?

10. What do you think about the relationship between an individual’s moral views or beliefs and how these may influence their everyday behaviour?

> TIMING GUIDE: 30:00Vignettes: Describe the scenarios to participants, provide sheets with the vignette scenarios detailed and describe one; then progress onto next vignette. Ask the group to explain their answers.

TIMING: approx. 4mins each

Scenario 1: Congregating youthsA bystander sitting at a bus stop has just witnessed a group of youths across the road congregating in a group. Whilst observing, he notices that these individuals are standing in the vicinity of multiple shops, and are causing other users of the public space to walk around them onto the adjacent road. Are these individuals engaging in an immoral act? Is it morally permissible for them to behave this way?Is anyone acting anti-socially? *Act of Distress here is congregating in public spaces*> TIMING: 34:00

Scenario 2: Illegal parkingAn individual is driving home in their car down a street. They arrive at their destination, only to find that someone has illegally parked. This illegal parking is blocking the path for pedestrians, but is also blocking the area designated for parking.Has the individual who has illegally parked behaved in an immoral way? Is this morally permissible?Has the illegal parker behaved anti-socially? *Act of ASB (but also criminal) = Illegal parking*> TIMING: 38:00

Scenario 3: Loud musicThere is a group of individuals who are having a party and playing music very loud. This is a common occurrence. It is causing local neighbours to get distressed and is affecting their

213

daily lifestyles and routines.Are the individuals causing the distress and annoyance through playing their music too loud behaving in a moral or immoral way? Is this morally permissible?Is playing the laud music anti-social? > TIMING: 42:00

Scenario 4: Benefit fraudAn individual has discovered that one of their neighbours has been committing benefit fraud. The neighbour in question has been behaving in this way for some time, and is not legally entitled to the financial support they are receiving.Is the individual behaving in an immoral or moral way? Can this behaviour be considered morally permissible?Is the individual’s behaviour anti-social? * economic crime/ASB?*> TIMING: 46:00

Scenario 5: LitteringA person witnesses another individual throwing some rubbish in an area that imposes fines for those who are caught littering. The person who has littered walks off, with no intention of picking this up. Is this person littering guilty of committing an immoral act? Is this behaviour morally permissible?> TIMING: 50:00

Scenario 6An individual discovers that someone they know has been dishonestly completing their tax reporting. Specifically, the person in questions has been declaring less income that they are actually earning and overstating deductions. Could this behaviour be considered moral or immoral? Is it morally permissible for the person to be falsifying their tax reports and continuing this behaviour?Is it anti-social behaviour?*Act of personal/individual ASB – Tax evasion, economic crime*> TIMING: 54:00

Section 4 – Final questions

11. In your own words, how would you actually describe and define anti-social behaviour?

12. How would you describe and define everyday morality?

13. Of everything discussed today, how would you sum up the links, if any, between everyday morality and anti-social behaviour? If in your opinion there is no links, then why not?

214

14. Is there anything anyone would like to add before we end the focus group?

Thank you for your participation in the group. If you have any questions after you leave you may contact either of the email addresses provided.

> TIMING: 60:00

215