17
Castillo 1 Neil Smith’s Uneven Development: the Capitalist Production of Space 1 Gerardo Castillo Guzmán [email protected] Capital creates a world after its own image. Communist Manifesto, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels Although the uneven character of capitalist development has received considerable attention within Marxist circles Amin, Aglietta, Furtado, Emmanuel, Mandel and Frank among others—Neil Smith‘s Uneven Development is a comprehensive and one of the most systematic inquires about the geography of capitalism. Part of the insightfulness of Smith‘s work is because it is not a mere exposition of the origins and patterns of the geography of capital. Uneven Development‘s final goal is to understand exactly how the production of space has contributed to the survival of capitalism.‖ (Smith 1984: 96), and with this aim in mind Smith advances good part of his hypothesis: capitalism does not only create uneven spatial patterns as a side-effect, but the production of space is essential for its own development. In one sense, the logic of the book reverses the process of appropriation from the abstract to the concreteof nature by capitalism. In consequence, it is organized into three major sections: the production of nature; the production of space; and the particular geography of capitalism or, more accurately, the ―…relationship between the production of nature and the unevenness of capitalist development.‖ (Smith 1984: 66) This logical approach, in turn, settles the basis for the understanding of capitalist spatial expansion and the resulting capitalist landscape. 1 Essay review prepared for the Seminar Geography of Capital directed by Don Mitchell at the Graduate Program of Geography at The University of Syracuse, December 2003.

Uneven Development-review(Neil Smith)

  • Upload
    garau0

  • View
    11

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Revista del libro de Neil Smith

Citation preview

  • Castillo 1

    Neil Smiths Uneven Development: the Capitalist Production of Space1 Gerardo Castillo Guzmn [email protected]

    Capital creates a world after its own image. Communist Manifesto, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels

    Although the uneven character of capitalist development has received

    considerable attention within Marxist circles Amin, Aglietta, Furtado, Emmanuel, Mandel and Frank among othersNeil Smiths Uneven Development is a comprehensive and one of the most systematic inquires about the geography of capitalism. Part of the

    insightfulness of Smiths work is because it is not a mere exposition of the origins and patterns of the geography of capital. Uneven Developments final goal is to understand exactly how the production of space has contributed to the survival of capitalism. (Smith 1984: 96), and with this aim in mind Smith advances good part of his hypothesis:

    capitalism does not only create uneven spatial patterns as a side-effect, but the production

    of space is essential for its own development.

    In one sense, the logic of the book reverses the process of appropriation from the abstract to the concreteof nature by capitalism. In consequence, it is organized into three major sections: the production of nature; the production of space; and the particular

    geography of capitalism or, more accurately, the relationship between the production of nature and the unevenness of capitalist development. (Smith 1984: 66) This logical approach, in turn, settles the basis for the understanding of capitalist spatial expansion

    and the resulting capitalist landscape.

    1 Essay review prepared for the Seminar Geography of Capital directed by Don Mitchell at the Graduate

    Program of Geography at The University of Syracuse, December 2003.

  • Castillo 2

    The production of nature at global scale and the creation of a world-system

    Smithss exposition begins with a somewhat abstract discussion of the ideological treatment of nature along history and the transformation of absolute space the primitive notion of space as a unity between nature-space-society-- into relative space the civilized conception of space that separates nature from space-- and social space. Amidst the atomistic and reifying bourgeois notions, the Marxist concept of production of nature and space seeks to reestablish the unity between nature, space and society, though not in its naturalistic forms but as a historical process of human creation:

    It is not just that space and society interact; a specific historical logic (that of

    capital accumulation) guides the historical dialectic of space and society. (Smith

    1984: 77)

    Space and nature, therefore, are no longer an accident of matter but a direct result of material production. (Smith 1984: 78) This shift, however, rather by the evolution of philosophical and physical thought has been achieved by the actual process

    of capital accumulation. The transformation of the notion, as well as the matter and

    substance-- of space has been driven by materials conditions. It is in this sense that the

    historical development of capitalism:

    entails the progressive universalization of value as the form of abstract labour. This involves not just the production of geographical space through the

  • Castillo 3

    development of transportation networks, but the progressive integration and

    transformation of absolute spaces into relative space. (Smith 1984: 82)

    Smith is here pointing to the progressive move from the creation of a world-scale

    mode of circulation a world-market-- to the creation of a world-scale mode of production. A clear understanding of this implication is central in Smiths thesis. He, very consequently with Marxs arguments in Capital, correctly establishes that mercantile money is not capital: profits from unequal trade do not generate surplus labor neither

    surplus value.2 Rather than the historical forms of articulation with pre-capitalist modes

    of production, Smith is concerned with a theoretical framework for the understanding of

    uneven capitalist expansion. In consequence, Smith argues that the contradictions leading

    to uneven development are not found in the sphere of exchange but in the premises of

    capitalist production: the opposite tendencies of equalization and differentiation inherent

    to capital expansion.

    The forces of equalization and univerlization emerge from the capitalist

    dogma of accumulation for accumulations sake, which lead to the spatial as well as social expansion of the domain of wage labor. In consequence, the universalization of

    wage labor frees not only working class but also capital from any inherent tie to absolute

    space. This process of universalization of relative space, however, encounters its opposite

    and, while:

    2 It could be perfectly possible to profit form other forms of exploitation (slavery or subjugation of peasant

    societies) but those are not capitalist relations of exploitation, which necessary imply the existence of wage labor and, thus, the separation of labor from the land.

  • Castillo 4

    social development leads to an increased emancipation from space in one direction, spatial fixity also becomes an increasingly vital underpinning to social

    development. (Smith 1984: 84)

    Once ended the partition of the globe by colonialism settling the limits of absolute geographical expansion--, production of space has been accomplished by the internal differentiation of global space, that is through the production of differentiated

    absolute spaces within the larger context of relative space. (Smith 1984: 88) The need for creating special kind of absolute spaces, certain spatial scales of social organization,

    has led to the formation of islands of absolute space in a sea of relative space. (Smith 1984: 87)

    The differentiation of geographical space in the last century is direct result of the

    inherent need to immobilize capital in the landscape as built environment. Thus, the

    contradiction between absolute and relative space is internalized within the space

    economy of capitalism itself. It is in this sense that geographical space has become an

    increasingly central concern regarding the survival of capitalism. Uneven development is

    nothing else but the concrete manifestation of the production of space under capitalism. (Smith 1984: 90)

    Uneven Development: universal or capitalist contradiction?

    At the basis of the uneven condition of capitalist development lies the unsolved

    contradiction between differentiation and equalization in the capitalist production of

  • Castillo 5

    space. On the one hand, inherent in the global production of relative space there is a

    tendency toward the equalization of the conditions of production and of the level of

    development of the productive forces. On the other, and in constant opposition, there is a

    tendency toward internal differentiation of geographical space into distinct absolute spaces, at different scales. (Smith 1984: 114) This tendency toward equalization and the resulting contradiction are the more concrete causes of uneven development.

    Mainly because of the highly abstract and long-term historic presentation of

    Smiths argument, there is the temptation of considering uneven development as the product of somewhat universal forces that arise from the early division of labor and

    territory between the town and the countryside. However, the author is clear in emphasize

    that the explanatory force that the contradiction between processes of equalization and

    processes of differentiation has for the understanding of spatial patterns of uneven

    development should be framed within the capitalist mode of production. In consequence,

    when analyzing Marxs insight about the historical foundation of capitalism upon the division between agriculture and industry, Smith states that this separation must be

    understood only under very specific circumstances: when the proletariat is free from the need and responsibility of producing their own means of subsistence. (1984: 109-110)

    Smith rejection of a universal and, in consequence, a-historical condition of unevenness does not mean he denies the possibility of uneven developments among pre-

    capitalists societies but simply that capitalism creates a very special kind of it. He notes

    that is not concerned with unevenness in general but with the specifically capitalist

    processes and patterns of spatial development. Although seemingly obvious, this remark

    is of major importance and serves to separate him from other Marxist authors as Ernest

  • Castillo 6

    Mandel. In fact, Smith accuses Mandel for inscribing uneven development into a

    universal law of human history3 and insists that it must be comprehended within specific forms of capitalist production of space. Thus, he declares that it is not the

    capitalist world system that:

    is a function of the universal validity of the law of unequal and combined development; rather, it is uneven development that is a function of the

    contemporary universality of capitalism. (1984: 98)

    Division of labor, territory and capital

    As mentioned above, Neil Smith roots the equalization and differentiation of capital --the

    fundamental motions of uneven development in the widespread emergence of the division of labor:

    The division of labor in society is the historical basis for the spatial differentiation

    of levels and conditions of development. The spatial or territorial division of

    labour is not a separate process but is implied from the start in the concept of

    division of labour. (Smith 1984: 99)

    A spatial division is already installed the sexual division of labor, the earliest form

    of division of labor. In addition, this division of labor is historically based upon

    differentiation of natural conditions:

    3 Accordingly to Smith, this approach would be, indeed, a hallmark of the bourgeois ideology and its

    tendency to universalize specific social forms under the capitalist mode of production into permanent, natural relations.

  • Castillo 7

    Given different natural conditions, the same expenditure of labour will result in

    different quantities of a given commodity, and this implies the possibility (but

    only the possibility) of surplus product in one place though not in other. (Smith

    1984: 99)

    It is in this line that qualitative differences in nature will be translated into

    qualitative and quantitative differences in societal organization: the societal division of labor expresses itself spatiality. (Smith 1984: 100)4 Consequently, spatial divisions could have emerged from natural differences but, with posterior economic development,

    they are the result of social dynamics. In fact, economic development becomes more and

    more untied to natural conditions in terms of distance and access to raw materials-- because of huge improvements in transportation and communication means as well as the

    increase of productive forces. This enlargement of productive forces means that raw

    materials are themselves a product of ever increasing previous labor processes and,

    therefore, there is separation between places of natural resources extraction and places of

    transformation and industrial production. Although increasingly a result of social and

    economic processes, these spatial differences are, however, ideologically naturalized.

    From a reading of Capital, Smith re-examines the relationship between the

    division of labor in its general, particular and specific aspects and the division of capital

    into the first department in charge of the production of means of productionand the second department concerned with production of means of subsistence. In a slight modification, Smith proposes a tripartite division of capital which parallels that one of

    4 The idea that spatial divisions derive from more general social differentiation was elaborated by Marx in

    terms of labor divisions, but also by Durkheim in terms of social solidarity and cohesion.

  • Castillo 8

    division of labor: departments, sectors, and individual units of property employed as

    capital. Folded together, capital and labor divisions operate at four scales where the

    process of differentiation takes place: i) the general societal division of labor and capital

    into different departments; ii) the division of labor and capital in different particular

    sectors; iii) the division of social capital in different individual capitals; and iv) the

    detailed division of labor within the workplace.

    Let us briefly examine the geographical implications of these divisions. First; the

    detailed division of labor within the workplace is crucial in explaining phenomena as

    improvements of labor productivity. However, Smith considers that except for the

    understanding of the highly structured spatial organization in the factory, for instance,

    this division contributes very little to the social differentiation leading to uneven

    development.

    Second; for some Marxists, the general societal division of labor and capital into

    different departments has been largely responsible of world-economy differentiation

    between centers of production and peripheries of consumption. This rough

    differentiation, however, makes little sense since peripheries also are regions of

    production (the industrialization of the Third World) and cores are, more than ever, the

    large centers of consumption.

    Third; the geographical correlation of the division of social capital among

    different individual capitals is the process of concentration and centralization in some

    places at expense of other places.

  • Castillo 9

    Fourth, and of major spatial importance, is the division of labor and capital in

    different particular sectors. For Smith, the division of the economy into specific sectors

    led to the differentiation of geographical space following the cycles of the rate of profit.

    Because of the process of equalization, sectors attracting capitals in their search for

    higher rates of profit tend to be young in the economy and, thus, it will coincide with the

    need of geographical expansion or relocation in order to supply the space for the

    burgeoning productive activities. The contrary would be equally possible and places

    where economic sectors loose large quantities of capital because of their low rate of

    profits, will suffer the drastic devaluation of their build environment.

    This issue has been introduced and studied by Harvey in The Limits of Capital

    when dealing with the geographical aspects of the third-cut of his theory of crisis. (1999:422-421) In Harvey, nevertheless, there is a subtler and more complex treatment of

    regional configurations. In fact, because capitalists have interest in different kind of

    capitals they tend to develop factional struggles. Thus, land owners, developers and

    builders, or the local government could build intra-class and, at some extent, inter-class

    alliances with workers in order to protect grounded capital from devaluation and external

    competition. As a result, urban or regional underdevelopment is not only strongly

    opposed but could more or less retarded and displaced.5 These political and class

    considerations, of course, do not invalidate Smiths argument but, however, show some of its limits and weakness. As we will observe below, this lack of connection with the

    political realm restricts, for instance, the understanding of capital behavior at the nation-

    state scale.

    5 Probably at the price of exacerbating the contradictions of the falling rate of profit and, thus, provoking a

    deeper and more violent crisis.

  • Castillo 10

    The see-saw theory of uneven development and its functioning at different scales

    In strict, what is behind the spatial pattern of uneven development is the oscillating logic

    driving capital or, in Smiths terms, the see-saw movement of capital. The see-saw theory of uneven development is making explicit the geographical implications of the

    connection between the logic of capital in its search for the highest rates of profit and the

    cyclical periods of capital expansion and crisis of over-accumulation proposed by Marx.

    Productive capital, and with it the build environment, expands and contracts cyclically

    and spatially creating in this movement the development and the underdevelopment of

    absolute places:

    The mobility of capital brings about the development of areas with a high rate of

    profit and the underdevelopment of those areas where a low rate of profit pertains.

    But the process of development itself leads to the diminution of this higher rate of

    profit. (Smith 1984:148-9)

    This see-saw theory, therefore, provides a powerful framework with which to understand the creation of uneven landscapes in capitalism rather than a historical

    account of specific uneven formations (de-industrialization northeast in the U.S. or the

    emergence of the New Industrialized Countries, for instance). Smith is more concerned

    with, on the one hand, the production of geographical space at world scale as relative

    space and, on the other hand, the creation of internal differentiations of geographical

    space into distinct absolute spaces, at different scales. (1984: 114) In consequence, his see-saw theory does not only illuminate the movement of capital in general but also

  • Castillo 11

    seeks to understand how it works at different scales. Smith proposes threes spatial scales6

    where to appreciate the effects of capital expansion and contraction: the urban, the global

    and the nation-state.7 As in the case of the division of capital and labor at different scales,

    let us highlight some notes about the scalar functioning of the see-saw theory.

    Academic research has devoted large attention to the city and, indeed, urban

    development is considered the locus where the centralization of capital finds its most

    accomplished geographical expression. As Smith correctly notes, the city is not only the

    space of production of commodities but also of consumption and reproduction of labor:

    The expansion of urban space [...] is not just a matter of increased centralization

    of the productive forces or the expansion of the scale at which the daily system of

    concrete labour takes place. It should be constructed, rather, as the expansion of

    the daily geographical sphere of abstract labour. (1984: 137)

    Urban development, therefore, results from the centralization of productive

    capital8 and it is managed through the ground-rent system. The ground-rent system

    homogenizes and levels urban space to the dimension of exchange-values but, at the same

    time, it leads to a process of differentiation and irrational speculation. In this sense, it is

    the scale of the urban space where the process of capital development and

    6 Smith does not regard these scales as something fixed and given for granted. They are, rather, fluid

    categories operating within dynamic processes. However, it is true that there is a major agreement in their use, mainly because they are expression of political and economic configurations historically developed within the limits of those levels. 7 There is also an intermediate and somewhat ambiguous regional scale that, in turn, could be divided into

    intra-national regions (i.e. the Sunbelt in the U.S.) and supra-national ones (i.e. the European Community). 8 In contrast with productive capital, the centralization of financial capital mainly managed by banks and

    circulating through electronic ordershas very little direct consequences in terms of spatial development.

  • Castillo 12

    underdevelopment has left its major imprint. Nonetheless, capital development could

    behave rather different in the case of the remaining scales.

    It is true that the internal differentiation of national territories into identifiable

    regions is the geographical expression of capital and labor concentration. The nation-state

    scale, however, possesses a key particularity. The sphere of the nation-state is a highly

    regulated area that imposes serious barriers to the free movement of capital and labor. To

    be sure, its borders are becoming increasingly porous to labor and capital mobility but,

    nonetheless, they still proof to be powerful leverages in the state attempts to avoid critical

    devaluations and protect national capital. Indeed, Smith argues that the condition of immobility of large amounts of the productive capital fixed capital in Harveys terms makes that it cannot be sent abroad and, thus, cannot circulate as commodity in the

    world-market. This capital, in consequence, is treated as national capital which must be protected against other capitalist states.9 This implies:

    the provision of various infrastructural supports and trade laws, the regulation of the reproduction of labour power, and support for the local money, all of which

    are necessary at the level of the collective capitalist rather than the individual.

    (Smith 1984: 142)

    In addition, there seems to be in place a functional relationship between capitalist

    growth and nation-state development. In fact, Smith considers that the fulfillment of the

    role of political controller over the working class is the reason explaining the deep

    9 In the spirit of Bukharins claim that the internationalization of capital meant simultaneously its

    nationalization, Smith asserts that the: division of the world economy at the scale of national capital is the necessary foundation upon which capital can launch its aspirations to universality. (1984: 144)

  • Castillo 13

    stability of the nation-state configuration. In our opinion, the implications of this

    reasoning are central: the economic logic of capitalist needs of stable political in terms of power correlationsarrangements for its reproduction and these arrangements are specific place-located. In a very consistent reading of Marx,10 Smith considers that the

    state is essential in disciplining the working class as well as the erratic and destructive

    behavior of individual capitalists. What is surprising, however, is his little attention paid

    to the also crucial role of the state in the building of fixed capital. The state is not only

    direct responsible of the construction of large-scale projects --such as railroads, harbors

    or highwaysotherwise difficult to assume by individual capitalists, but without the states coordinating role particularly through central banks-- it would very difficult to imagine the functioning of a complex banking and financial system, which in turn make

    possible the investment of enormous amounts of capital in the built environment. (Harvey

    1999: chapter 9)

    Up to this point is evident the necessity of a political system for the development

    of capitalism. However, it is not so clear why this system has to be placed at the scale of

    the nation-state.11 Smith provides some clues when maintains that the geographical extent

    of the nation-state:

    is constrained on the low end by the need to control a sufficiently large market (for labour and commodities) to fuel accumulation. At the high end of the scale, a

    10 In fact, in Capital, Marx recognizes that capitalism is an economic as well a political project and,

    therefore, the state must fulfill certain key functions necessary for capital development; namely, the preservation of market equality and exchange freedom, the protection of property rights, the enforcement of contracts, the minimization of the destructive aspects derived from competition, the mediation of among faction interests in order to preserve the capitalist class as a whole and, of course, the possibility of use of violence in case of threatening labor-class contestations, 11

    Not in historical but in structural terms.

  • Castillo 14

    nation-state that is too large finds it difficult to maintain political control over its

    territory. (1984: 143)

    At the face of recent history we should examine, for instance, the economic

    foundations of, on the one hand, processes of territorial disintegration12 or nationalist

    separation,13 and, on the other, of supra-national formations.14 We are simply suggesting

    that, despite of nation-state historical role in the development of the capitalist system,

    there is a never-solved tension between the mobility of capital and the territorial

    constituency of a political community. If the nation-state becomes dysfunctional for the

    cyclical but progressive movement of capital, it would be possible to imagine more

    suitable political platforms and, with this, we enter to the consideration of the global

    scale.

    Effectively, the global has been regarded both the most desirable scale for capital

    development as well as its geographical limit. Capitalism inherited the global scale in the

    form of a world-market built since early sixteenth century; but it needs to transform the

    world into a place of production. The capital expansion at the global scale would be,

    therefore, a movement toward equalization and univerzalition of the wage-labor

    relationship. Paralleling Marxs idea of a historical transition from the formal to the real subordination of labor to capital, Smith states that the territorial expansion of capital at

    global scale would be moving from the formal integration via exchange to the real

    integration via production of commodities. Through a successive process of cyclical

    12 As it would be the case of ex-Soviet and ex-Yugoslavian republics.

    13 This would be situation of the recently proclaimed state of East Timor or the current struggles maintained

    by the Frente Polisario in Western Sahara and the Bask movement in Spain. 14

    Most notably, the European Community.

  • Castillo 15

    crises, capitalist development would have transferred its inner contradiction of

    accumulation for accumulations sake to its final ground.15 In addition, the never-ending seek of capital for places and sectors with higher surplus value would be the fuel

    for the continuing creation of developed and underdeveloped places. In this line, Smith quoting Marx and Engelss Communist Manifestodeclares that there is nowhere clearer the fact that capital creates a world after its own image than in the geographical contradiction between development and underdevelopment where the over-accumulation

    of capital at one pole is matched by the over-accumulation of labour at the other. (1984:

    149) Capital, continues Smith, strives:

    to move from developed to underdeveloped space, then back to developed space which, because of its interim deprivation of capital, is now underdeveloped,

    and so on. (Smith 1984: 150)

    Historical evidence, however, does not portraits a real integration of the globe as a

    production place. Indeed, the capitalist world shows a highly stable feature, with

    endurable absolute places of production and consumption. At best, like Marx himself

    recognizes, the inner economic contradiction of capital --the fall of the rate of profit that mobilize capital around the globe, is a tendency. In real life, political decisions are

    more that epiphenomenal issues derived from class alliances dictated by capital. State

    forces, after all, are both controlled and controlling in its relation to the circulation of capital. (Harvey 1999: 324)16

    15 This is exactly what Lenin envisioned when labeling imperialism as the highest state of capitalism.

    16 Smith recognized the limits of the see-saw movement of capital, at least a national-state level, but

    confines the question to an empirical matter. (1984: 151) In summary, the see-saw theory works well for understanding urban development, presents mixed results for regional scale, and explains less at global scale. Smith argues that this is because the mobility of capital, and very especially of labor, is restricted by

  • Castillo 16

    As a way of conclusion

    Shaped by the finest Marxist tradition, Smith considers his work inscribed not

    merely in a philosophical debate but in a political economy that can inform activism and

    lead to changes. Because of the irrational character of capitalist development and its inner

    and unsolvable contradictions we would facing the hopeful disjunctive of falling into

    barbarism or advancing to socialism. There would be an opportunity for the solution of

    growing inner contradictions of the capitalist system.17 Thus, against the fragmentation

    imposed by capital, Smiths pleas for a global political alliance of the working class

    (1984: 153) After all, uneven development is nothing else that social inequality inscribed

    into the landscape and, simultaneously, the exploitation of that geographical unevenness for certain socially determined ends. (Smith 1984: 154) However, the remaining question is how to change an economic and naturalizedlogic determined by social relations. More than ever, it turns urgent to reconnect social needs with economic

    possibilities. To put this in Smith words:

    It is not that our goal is some rigidly conceived even development. This would make little sense. Rather, the goal is to create socially determined patterns of

    differentiation and equalization which are driven not by the logic of capital but by

    genuine social choice. (1984: 159)

    nation-state boundaries. In other words, the greater the scale of absolute space capital pushes for continuing accumulation, the greater the political resistance it will find. 17

    As Bond (1999) points out, unevenness derives from the transition from one declining mode of production to another rising, more progressive mode.

  • Castillo 17

    References

    Bond, Patrick. What is uneven development? P. OHara ed. (1999) The Encyclopedia of Political Economy. London: Routledge.

    Harvey, D. (1999) The Limits to Capital. London: Verso.

    Marx, K. (1992) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Vol. I. New York:

    International Publishers.

    Smith, N. (1984) Uneven Development: Nature, Capital and the Production of Space.

    Oxford: Basil Blackwell.