Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    1/47

    the author 2016

    Rawls, Piketty and the New Inequality

    Alan Thomas1

    Tilburg University

    Abstract

    The forty year period 1970-2010 saw two developments in the USA: first, at the level of theory,intense academic interest in the egalitarianism of John Rawls. Second, at the level of practice,fundamental changes in the institutions, policies and norms of US society that have led Gilens andPage [2014] to conclude that it has become an oligarchy de facto if not de jure. A central componentin that practical development is the tolerance of extensive inequality and the emergence of notmerely the 1 percent, but the elevation of an upper decile of wealthy individuals into a positionof economic and political dominance. In spite of pioneering work by Krouse, MacPherson andArneson, little academic attention has been paid to whether a political economy with roots inRawlss work might be the most effective response to these practical and institutional changes. Thatsituation may be about to change given the popular, as well as academic, response to Thomas

    Pikettys Capital in the Twenty-First Century. In this paper I will consider whether a form ofeconomic system described by Cambridge economist James Meade a common source for bothRawls and Piketty offers a feasible egalitarian ideal. It will be argued that the USA represents a"test case" for other advanced democracies faced with the challenge of a new form of patrimonialcapitalism. It is further argued that only a structural change to societys fundamental wage settinginstitutions, along the lines recommended by Meade and Rawls and implicit in Piketty, will bringabout the necessary structural change to implement a political economy for a just society.

    This paper takes as its starting point the conjunction of two striking facts: the first is that

    the last forty years has seen intense academic discussion of the work of John Rawls, but

    comparatively little discussion of what he called the choice of a social system. [Rawls,

    1971, p. 242] The second fact is that the last forty years has also seen marked changes in

    the economies of several Western democracies, but those changes are the most marked in

    the United States. I will elaborate on both points in turn.

    First, Rawlss work on domestic justice culminated in the arguments ofJustice as

    Fairnessin which the question of our choice of a social system plays a significant role in

    his discussion. Notably, he argued that liberal market socialism or a property-owning

    democracy were the only systems that could adequately specify his conception of justice

    as reciprocity. [Rawls, 2001] In particular, he dismissed welfare state capitalism the

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    2/47

    Draft Only 2

    predominant form of successful egalitarian societies in our own world on the grounds

    that it neglects the principle of reciprocity and is, therefore, structurally unjust. There has

    been some discussion of these claims in the voluminous secondary literature on Rawls,

    notably by Dick Krouse and Michael McPherson.2[Krouse & McPherson, 1986] But the

    comparative scale of this discussion, compared to such topics as Rawlss approach to

    public reason or religious accommodation, has been puzzlingly slight.3

    I turn now to the second starting point of my discussion, namely, the major

    economic changes in social democracies across the Western world. These changes are the

    most marked in the USA which is why European social theorists such as PierreRosanvallon and Thomas Piketty are drawn to study them. [Rosanvallon, 2013; Piketty,

    2014a] They are well illustrated in this table that I reproduce from Pikettys book Capital

    in the Twenty-First Century:

    Figure 8.5 Income inequality in the United States 19102010.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    3/47

    Draft Only 3

    My selective interest in this tabulated data is what it tells us about income inequality in

    the USA for the period 19702010. It shows us the extent to which the wealthiest 1 per

    cent and top 10 per cent of American citizens have pulled away from their fellow citizens

    over the last forty years. I will be concerned in this paper with some other phenomena

    associated with this development: the hollowing out of Americas middle class and

    stagnant incomes for those at the lower end of the income distribution. Relativeinequality

    has significantly widened caused by a hyperconcentration of gains at the top.4[Hacker

    & Pierson, 2010, p. 3]

    Further components of what Richard B. Freeman called the New Inequality

    5

    arethe distinctively American problem of the toleration of very high levels of executive

    remuneration; the emergence of very high rewards in the financial sector; the breakdown

    of Americas distinctive public-private partnerships when it comes to social insurance

    provision and, therefore, the exposure of many American on lower incomes to very high

    levels of risk. At the level of what one might call the background conditions to this

    inequality there has been a structural change in the US economy from manufacturing to

    services and the further weakening of organized labour as a countervailing force to all of

    the foregoing changes.6Some commentators, such as Jacob S. Hacker, Paul Pierson, and

    Sheldon Wolin take another key to these changes to be that which Wolin calls the

    political coming of age of corporate power in America. [Wolin, 2008, p. x]

    I am not an economist and am in no position to assess macro-economic

    arguments, but I note, for the sake of completeness, the claims of Joseph Stiglitz and

    James Galbraith that such levels of inequality in income and wealth are economically

    damaging. [Stiglitz, 2012; Galbraith, 2014] They contribute to an economy with

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    4/47

    Draft Only 4

    suppressed consumer demand and, in the absence of fiscal measures to reduce the

    comparative advantage of the wealthy, macro-economic policy can only stimulate growth

    in ways that exacerbate the tendency of a lightly regulated capitalism to inherent

    instability. [Stiglitz, 2012; Galbraith, 2014] We can reasonably predict an unstable series

    of boom and bust cycles that reproduce the pattern of events that lead up to the global

    financial crisis of 2008. These cycles are in no-ones interest, and the better off stand to

    lose just as the worst off do, but societys wealthiest people are the best placed to spread,

    and hence manage, their risks while the worse off are not.7 That places them in a

    comparatively better position to take advantage of deflated asset prices at the outset of arecovery: they lose less, they recover faster and, indeed, in doing so they consolidate their

    comparative advantage.8

    The post-2008 phenomenon of an economic recovery for the rich is therefore

    explicable as part of this self-reinforcing cycle and one we can expect to see repeated.9If

    those who hold capital assets have a significant influence on policy, then they will self-

    seekingly favour policies that set the goal of low inflation as a priority over other

    economic goals. They will, therefore, favour so-called austerity policies even in an

    economic downturn. The overall macro-economic effect is a set of policies that both

    increases the frequency of boom-bust cycles and causes the recessionary phase to last

    longer than they ought to do so in such cycles. All of this plays into what Robert D.

    Solow calls the rich get richer dynamic. [Solow, 2014]

    Returning from the economics to the politics of inequality, if concentrations of

    wealth and monopolistic control of capital have the political consequences that Rawls

    fears when he described his laws and tendencies of the social world, then that explains

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    5/47

    Draft Only 5

    why his two favoured forms of social system pre-emptively disperse capital holdings.

    Alternative political systems, such as the one currently dominant in the USA, may stand

    in a mutually reinforcing relation to high levels of inequality of income and wealth and

    produce a drift to oligarchy (to use Thomas Pikettys helpful phrase).10The central

    thesis of Jacob S. Hacker and Paul Piersons Winner-Take-All Politicsis that Americas

    wealthiest citizens have proved highly politically effective beyond their comparatively

    small numbers in a democracy and have, indeed, successfully won an ideological and

    political battle over the last forty years to cement their control of political and economic

    policy.To use Rawlss metaphor, the space of contested power is a limited space and

    inherently competitive. The very wealthy in American society collectively constitute an

    unusual powerful political actor that works to roll back the state, extend the scope of

    market provision, lower direct and indirect taxation and transfers, and conceptualise

    social programs as an inefficient form of insurance from which employers and wealthy

    individuals ought to withdraw. All of this is as a result of, and with the aim of

    consolidating, their monopolistic control of capital.11Political office need not be literally

    bought and sold if, in the inherently competitive space of politics, the wealthy are the

    most powerful political actor vis--vis other actors and able to exercise undue influence

    over democratic governance.12[Page and Winters, 2009; Gilens and Page, 2014]

    Indeed, Martin Gilens and Jeffrey I. Page made international headlines last year

    when they argued that the USA has become an oligarchy. They concluded that

    multivariate analysis indicates that economic elites and organized groups representing

    business interests have substantial independent impacts on U.S. government policy, while

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    6/47

    Draft Only 6

    average citizens and mass-based interest groups have little or no independent

    influence.13 The form and structure of democracy de jure co-exists with oligarchy de

    factoin the sense that the view of the majority of voters is epiphenomenal to the process

    of formulating and implementing policy.

    For radical critics the contribution of John Rawls to these economic and political

    changes was to play the fiddle while Rome burned; my aim in this paper is to convince

    you otherwise.14My goal is to show that Rawlss conception of justice as fairness, when

    fully specified as one kind of social system, is not only the most normatively desirable,

    but also the most realistically utopian, response to these changes changes that areobviously notbeyond the control of democratic politics.

    1 Rawls Fundamental Choice of Social System

    It is an open question how much my normative orientation differs from that of Rawlss

    own; my fundamental commitment is to a society free from domination and working out

    the consequences of that commitment has implications for the topic of material

    inequality.15My goal, shared with others such as James Bohman, is a society in which the

    material basis of domination is made structurally impossible. Bohman argues that

    republicanism assigns to citizens, jointly and severally, an achieved political status that

    makes it impossible to fall under the control of another.16 [Bohman, 2010, p. 436,

    emphasis added; see also Schuppert, 2013] The aim is so to re-structure material

    incentives that the capacity to dominate is taken away from any economic actor; we are

    not simply in the business of making domination costly to agents, some of whom might

    think that paying such metaphorical traffic tickets was worth it.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    7/47

    Draft Only 7

    This goal is realized by so pre-distributing capital that the context of market

    transactions is transformed. It is transformed so as to make their results fair in the only

    feasible way in which that can be achieved, namely, by patterning outcomes from the

    market. [Thomas, 2011, 2012] The proposal is to permit material incentives while

    constraining the inequalities that they generate to operation within a permissible range.

    [Rawls, 1999a, p. 74; Thomas, 2015] Both aims can be secured, I will argue, by attention

    to the issue of who holds capital. Addressing this question allows us both to focus on the

    structural basis of domination and to pre-distribute capital assets so as to harness the

    advantages of the market while patterning its outcomes as just.That aim is shared with Rawlss theory of justice as fairness; I take it the content

    of his principles of justice are familiar. Less familiar is his later claim that the underlying

    principle of reciprocity can only take a fully specified form in a property-owning

    democracy or a liberal market socialist system. Both involve a guarantee of the basic

    liberties, freedom of occupation, freedom to hold private property and a free market. Yet

    that which primarily distinguishes them, together, from other social systems is their

    sensitivity to who controls capital.

    I will not, in this paper, discuss the prospects for liberal market socialism and will

    focus here on property-owning democracy.17By the time he wrote Justice as Fairness,

    Rawls described a property-owning democracy as realiz[-ing] all the main political

    values expressed by the two principles of justice. [Rawls, 2001, p. 135] He explicitly

    states that it forms the institutional background to the realisation of the complete

    conception of justice as fairness from one generation to the next even if his discussion

    of it must remain, in his words, illustrative and highly tentative. [Rawls, 2001, p. 136]

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    8/47

    Draft Only 8

    Rawls focuses on the pre-emptive dispersal of the ownership of wealth and capital

    in a property-owning democracy, but for a specific political end:

    [T]o prevent a small part of society from controlling the economy and indirectly,political life as well . Property owning democracy avoids this, not be theredistribution of income to those with less at the end of each period . but ratherby ensuring the widespread ownership of productive assets and human capital (thatis, education and trained skills) at the beginning of each period, all of this against abackground of fair equality of opportunity. [Rawls, 2001, p. 139]

    This relatively compressed later discussion of a property-owning democracy focuses on

    the way it realises justice as fairness. In this respect, it contrasts with Rawlss earliestdiscussion of the idea in the first edition of A Theory of Justicein which there is a great

    deal more macro-economic detail. Rawls there states that:

    The aim of the branches of government is to establish a democratic regime in whichland and capital are widely though not presumably equally held. Society is not sodivided that one small sector controls the preponderance of productive resources.[Rawls 1971, p 280]

    If this economic system does indeed work well, then Rawlss ideal property-owning

    democracy envisages markets operating in a context structured pervasively so as to make

    their patterned effects fair. The state intervenes not only to supply public goods and to

    counter negative externalities, but also to impose adjusted procedural justice. In the first

    edition ofA Theory of Justice, Rawls states that steeply progressive taxes may very well

    be justified given the injustice of existing institutions. [Rawls, 1971, p. 279] But in his

    realistically utopian theory when justice has been more fully implemented, then the role

    of progressive taxation is significantly reduced. That reflects a general commitment to

    pre-distributive, as opposed to re-distributive egalitarianism. That choice of egalitarian

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    9/47

    Draft Only 9

    strategy, in turn, reflects a primary normative focus on underlying holdings of, and access

    to, capital. If we focus on the initial distribution of all forms of capital, human and

    physical, we have a reduced reliance on ex post income re-distribution.

    In order to explain why progressive taxation plays such a reduced role in the

    ideally just society, compared to our own, we need a better grasp on how a property-

    owning democracy is justified by Rawlss principles working as an interlocking group.

    Paul Smith noted that:

    The idea that the equalization of property ownership would transform the labourmarket, by equalizing bargaining power and eliminating the economic coercion to

    accept drudge jobs at low pay and thus forcing employers to make all jobsattractive, all things considered, is crucial to Rawlss idea that, in a competitivelabour market located in a just basic structure, income inequalities would tend justto compensate the costs of different jobs, that is, tend to equality, all thingsconsidered. [Smith, 1998, p.225]

    Smith believes that this explains some of the distinctive features of Rawlss egalitarian

    strategy (the strategy that we would now call predistributive a word that Smith does

    not use):

    Economic equalization is more likely and reliably to be effected, as Rawls thinks,by institutions and policies that equalize bargaining power than by an egalitarianethos restraining the exercise of unequal bargaining power (and egalitarianinstitutions and their distributional results are what, if anything, could produce anegalitarian ethos. [Smith, 1998, p. 227]

    This is the central idea of the New Keynesianism that Rawls inherits from Cambridge

    economist James Meade: we so structure the labour market that what looks like the

    introduction of special incentives under the difference principle works under a set of

    macro-economic arrangements that make such incentives tend to be merely

    compensatory.18 So the difference principle leads to inequalities that fall only within a

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    10/47

    Draft Only 10

    permissible range. Rawls argues that the scale and complexity of a modern economy

    forces the conclusion that the only way to implement principles of justice is by

    structuring the context in which market transactions occur. [Thomas, 2012]

    2 Rawls, Piketty and the Drift to Oligarchy

    We know that Rawls was aware of the work of economists contemporaneous to him, but

    we do not know how he came across the work of post-War British egalitarian James

    Meade. The context in which Meade formulated his ideas was as an adviser to the

    revisionists in the post-War British socialist (Labour) party. Meade believed that thestandard Labour Party procedure of strengthening the power of Britains labour unions

    when the socialists were in power, only to be met by a matching strengthening of the

    power of employers when they were not, generated a destructive and wasteful cycle of

    inflationary pressure and economic instability. His solution was a macro-level

    restructuring of the context in which labour and capital confronted each other: this re-

    structuring gave every citizen access to capital in order to reduce their dependence on

    income from labour with a transformatory effect on the economy as a whole.

    This work is the common source for Rawlss ideal of a property-owning

    democracy and a tradition within economics of politically engaged work on income and

    wealth that runs from Meade, via economist Anthony Atkinson, to Thomas Piketty.

    Pikettys contribution to the argument I am developing here is two-fold: first, he provides

    us with as comprehensive a data set as is feasible given that some information is

    unavailable and that information of this kind is politically contested (and often

    deliberately concealed). This is as complete a narrative as we are likely to assemble,

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    11/47

    Draft Only 11

    provisionally, for two and a half centuries of capitalism and the results are not

    encouraging for reasons that I will go into in more detail.

    Secondly, Pikettys more important contribution is to expose, and to critique, both

    a general and a special argument in defense of inequality that represents it as the result of

    the working out of an autonomous logic of capitalism. The belief that there is such a

    thing as an autonomous logic of capitalism is the first, general, argument; the more

    specific claim that the current inequality in the USA is the product of the opening of the

    US economy to global forces is a special instance of this more general claim.

    The aim, in both cases, is to imply that we face a choice between the prosperitythat results from the untrammelled operation of a free market that respects this

    autonomous logic, with unjust inequality as a regrettable side effect, or democratic

    interference with this logic that obstructs this prosperity. This line of argument hopes to

    show that the broadening and deepening of markets always makes them more efficient

    and is highly likely to improve wellbeing overall; capitalism is a win-win proposition

    for everyone, at least potentially, and the morally privileged institution of the market is in

    everyones interests. We will have to abandon the goal of regulating the top end of any

    distribution, but in Feldsteins memorable phrase only the spiteful egalitarian would

    reject Pareto improvements that benefit others on the basis of what Rawls calls a

    reasonable envy. [Feldstein, 2005]

    The globalization argument is a special instance of the more general argument:

    the autonomous logic of capitalism has always to be respected, and the New Inequality is

    produced by the exposure of the US economy to the forces of globalization. The

    hollowing out of the American middle class may be regrettable, but it is the downside

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    12/47

    Draft Only 12

    of economic changes that are more broadly to be welcomed.19This explanation fits easily

    with another: that the direct effect of globalization on the US economy is to place a

    premium on skills, particularly those connected to new technology: that explains why so

    many American citizens have lost out.20

    Piketty challenges both of these arguments. His more fundamental claims is that,

    with his historical narrative before us, we can see that they are both instances of Sartrean

    bad faith: as representing as beyond our democratic control that which is, in fact, the

    product of deliberate political choices. This instance of bad faith is, itself, in good faith at

    a deeper level for those who propose it: it represents the concern of those who benefitfrom these changes to represent them as both inevitable and irreversible and not subject

    to democratic choice.

    I think Piketty helps us to see why we need, now, to undertake a radical, structural

    reform of our central market institutions the kind of expanded economic basic

    structure represented by a property-owning democracy. This is for two reasons: the first

    is that the situation that we are facing is, if Piketty is right, historically unprecedented.

    The period between 1970 and 2010 has seen the return of capital, but Piketty knows

    that the nature of this society differs from the most radically unequal societies of the past.

    The composition of the top decile has changed. There is a greater amount of wealth in the

    top decile (the residual 9 percent) that is made up of income from labour, even if the

    top one percent still holds a disproportionate amount of equity. This is not, then, the

    society of the late nineteenth century rentier that was wiped out by the shocks to capital

    and periods of high inflation in the twentieth century. But the point is: that could be

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    13/47

    Draft Only 13

    about to happen particularly in the United States where inequality currently take an

    extreme form.21Piketty contrasts two forms of highly unequal society (in income terms):

    [T]here are two different ways for a society to achieve a very high inequality of top

    income . The first . is through a hyperpatrimonial society (or society ofrentiers): a society in which inherited wealth is very important and where theconcentration of wealth attains extreme levels . This is the pattern we see inAncien Rgime France and in Europe during the Belle poque. [Piketty, 2014a, p.264]

    That is an episode in the past of capitalism; however, the second form of unequal society

    is far more recent:

    The second way . is relatively new. It was largely created by the United Statesover the past few decades. Here we see that a very high level of total incomeinequality can be the result of a hypermeritocratic society (or at any rate a societythat the people at the top like to describe as hypermeritocratic) . The peak of theincome hierarchy is dominated by very high incomes from labor rather thaninherited wealth.22[Piketty, 2014a, pp. 264-5]

    But this over-simplifies the real issue:

    The stark contrast I have drawn here between two types of hyperinegalitariansociety a society of rentiers and a society of supermanagers is nave andoverdrawn. The two types of inequality can coexist: there is no reason why a personcant be both a supermanager and a rentier and the fact that the concentration ofwealth is currently much higher in the United States than in Europe suggests thatthat may well be the case in the United States today. And of course there is nothingto prevent the children of supermanagers from becoming rentiers. [Piketty, 2014a,p. 265]

    That, I take it, is the central issue that Piketty raises in the case of the USA, with the

    threat that it can generalise more widely across the jurisdictions that he studies: the two

    logics . may complement each other in the century ahead and combine their effects .

    The future could hold in store a new world of inequality more extreme than any that

    preceded it.23[Piketty, 2014a, p. 265]

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    14/47

    Draft Only 14

    Piketty is describing empirical tendencies and isolating them so that we may,

    collectively, take political action to redress them. In spite of his (perhaps unfortunate)

    name-checking of Marx in the title of his book, Pikettys thesis is not a prediction of

    some apocalyptic end for capitalism. Returns on capital will, indeed, diminish just as neo-

    classical theory predicts, but the key issue is imbalanced growth.24The New Inequality

    will provide the background conditions for an imbalanced development of capitalism if it

    is left unchecked by political action.

    In so far as Pikettys arguments are empirically grounded, then, new data or better

    explanations may undermine them. My point is that the truth of Pikettys key equation r

    > g is not imposed by some autonomous logic of capitalism, but by our political

    choices (as he emphasizes).25 This equation expresses the relation between returns on

    capital assets (r) and the rate of growth (g). Growth is slowing in our societies

    because they are already affluent, but if it is true that returns on capital will average 5 6

    percent a year while growth (determined by both population growth and technological

    innovation) will not keep pace, then we are facing the consequences of what could be a

    momentous social change. In particular, the role of inherited wealth will become

    disproportionately strong: to cite the phrase from the book most likely to stay in the

    minds of its readers the past tends to devour the future.26[Piketty, 2014a, p. 378]

    The benign post-war growth patterns captured by Simon Kuznets famous

    Kuznets Curve were taken to represent a normal phase in the development of capital,

    but Piketty argues that this phase was, in fact, historically anomalous. [Kuznets, 1953]

    Patterns of growth in capitalist societies are always shaped by political choices and if, in

    Pikettys narrative, the only countervailing forces to excessive inequality are the capital

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    15/47

    Draft Only 15

    shocks represented by World War, then we need to do better. We need to reconstruct, in

    so far as we can, the special political conditions that produced, economically, the trente

    glorieuses and, politically, the work of James Meade who was theorising these new

    conditions of capitalist society in medias res.27

    This leads on to the second reason why I think this data mandates that we adopt

    the radical strategies of Rawls and Meade. Pikettys data covers (primarily) the last two

    centuries including the emergence of welfare state capitalism in all its manifestations.

    Pikettys point is that social democratic politics has failed to prevent a return to extensive

    levels of capital based inequalities approaching their late nineteenth century precedentover the long run. Those capital based inequalities are dangerous for democracy given

    that those who benefit from the process of concentrated capital accumulation exert undue

    political influence to ensure that the rich get richer dynamic continues unimpeded.

    [Solow, 2014] The real challenge of Pikettys argument is that we have not yet imagined

    or implemented a political option that will solve the problem of preventing capital

    accumulation threatening the values of liberal democracy.28The relatively low rates of

    growth that feature in the problematic equation r > galso feature in Pikettys pessimistic

    account of the prospects for a social democratic politics founded wholly on an expanded

    role for progressive taxation and welfare state capitalism: we have tried this option, and it

    has not worked over the long run.

    Low growth rates in income mean that current electorates will not welcome a

    substantially higher tax burden; the latter has stabilized across the main jurisdictions that

    Piketty examines and for a good reason. [Piketty, 2014, p. 382] There is a jurisdiction

    relative cultural consensus on the role of the state and how extensive its provision of

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    16/47

    Draft Only 16

    services should be. There is going to be no expansion of the affirmative welfare state of

    the kind witnessed between 1930-1950 (from 10 percent to between 30 50 percent of

    national income) because that has already happened. No one realistically expects the

    process to develop until 70 or 80 percent of GDP is appropriated by the State.29We need

    new options in our egalitarian thinking for one very good reason: advanced democratic

    welfare state capitalism was already in place, but the return to our new Gilded Age in the

    period 1970 2010 was not prevented not even in the Nordic social democracies that

    do very well by redistributive measures, but less well by pre-distributive, capital based,

    measures. My interpretation of Pikettys data is that it demonstrates that egalitarians neednew, more radical, ideas; fortunately, Meade and Rawls are well placed to provide them.

    3 Two Kinds of Pre-distributionism versus Social Democracy

    The crux of my case for taking a property-owning democracy uniquely to be our best

    option as egalitarians is that its pre-distributive contextualization of the market patterns

    its outcomes as fair. This is not quite, however, what is meant by pre-distribution in the

    current debate over egalitarianism and that is why I would like to pursue a compare and

    contrast exercise with the views of Jacob S. Hacker, the leading pre-distributionist in

    this recent debate, and the views of Lane Kenworthy. As the title of Kenworthys book

    Social Democratic America makes clear his preferred option is a return to the social

    democratic traditions of the USA.30[Kenworthy, 2013a] While he has not considered the

    more radical views of Meade, Rawls and Piketty to date, we do have the benefit of

    Kenworthys thoughtful response to Hackers proposals. [Kenworthy, 2013b] I propose,

    as the litmus test for all three sets of proposals, examining how well they fare in

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    17/47

    Draft Only 17

    addressing the problem of the squeezed middle. The problem of the squeezed middle is

    that changes in the US economy over the last forty years have seen little change to the

    lives of the worst off they continue to do very badly. However, it has seen significant

    changes to the lives of the next category up the socio-economic ladder, namely, the

    working lower middle class. It is the income of this group that has stagnated.

    Pikettys historical research puts the fate of this class in an historical perspective:

    the growth of a true patrimonial (or propertied) middle class was the principal

    structural transformation of the distribution of wealth in the developed countries in the

    twentieth century. [Piketty, 2014, p. 260] He continues:[I]t is tempting to insist on the fact that wealth is still extremely concentrated today:the upper decile owns 60 percent of Europes wealth and more than 70 percent inthe United States. And the poorer half of the population are just as poor today asthey were in the past, with barely 5 percent of total wealth in 2010, just as in 1910.Basically, all the middle class managed to get its hands on was a few crumbs:scarcely more than a third of Europes wealth and barely a quarter in the UnitedStates . Nevertheless, the crumbs that the middle class have collected areimportant. [Piketty, 2014, pp. 261-2]

    This general pattern across the jurisdictions in Pikettys dataset is actually behind the

    curve when one examines the major structural changes in the US economy that has

    produced the phenomenon of the squeezed middle.

    The American middle class has fractured: those who have benefitted from these

    social and economic changes have been elevated into the lower 9 percent of the top 10

    percent. However, the lower middle class has seen its life prospects deteriorate

    consequent on the polarisation of the US workforce. [Stiglitz, 2012, p. 56] They have

    typically reacted by sending a secondary earner to work and working longer (often by

    combining separate jobs). They also face the consequences of a politically motivated shift

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    18/47

    Draft Only 18

    of personal risk on to themselves and their families even when their income has

    stagnated. (Hackers documentation of the great risk shift focuses on exposure to risk

    as the inverseof inadequate capital holding.) [Hacker, 2012] Americas squeezed middle

    class faces increased pressure to save to cover their individual risks while their income

    has not kept pace with these demands: it has remained, in real terms, virtually stagnant

    over a forty year period between 1970 and 2010.31

    This group is not in any Rawlsian blind spot: justice as fairness, as realised in

    an economic system, ties together the interests of all social groups.32If it is true that the

    worst off in our own society are the durably worst off in receipt of welfare payments,then Rawls took their claims to be the most morally urgent. But it would be very myopic

    to aim to lift the currently worst off into the position of the currently squeezed middle.

    Those who can fully participate in society via meaningful work would, nevertheless, find

    themselves exposed to risk and with stagnant income. If the choice is welfare dependency

    or the long and stressful hours of a typical family in the squeezed middle, then that is not

    an appealing structure of incentives. The contribution of the Meade-Rawls tradition in

    thinking about inequality is to direct our attention away from income inequality per se to

    the deeper inequalities in capital holding, control or access that serve to ground it.

    I suggest, then, that we draw on Meade and Rawls and the economic data

    supplied by Piketty to explain how we ought to realize the ambitious target of making

    unjust exploitation impossible. The way that this aim is realized is by adopting a system

    in which the relationship between income from capital and income from the marketing of

    labour is restructured at the macro-level of an expanded economic basic structure. This

    ambition is reflected in a wide range of policies: a free and high quality public education

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    19/47

    Draft Only 19

    system, wealth tax as well as progressive income tax, high levels of estate tax, the taxing

    of capital gains and capital gifts, and incentives for small savers.33More specific policies

    for the universal dispersal of capital include a society-wide unit trust made up of a

    portfolio of equity held for all citizens by the state, a sovereign wealth fund (where

    applicable) or some kind of demogrant scheme to encourage the individual, as well as the

    collective, holding of equity. If parts of this approach ought, in my view, to be

    constitutionally secured then there is one major issue that has to be the subject of

    democratic deliberation, namely, the relation between private and public debt. As Piketty

    points out, not only does the state in modern Western democracies typically not tax therich sufficiently, it actually borrows from them.34

    I think a return to this capital focused and pre-distributive tradition leads to

    significant differences of focus when we turn to policy choice. For example, I think their

    particular focus leads to some divergence from the policies of Jacob Hacker to whose

    pioneering work I am indebted. This point is worth developing as Hacker is usually

    interpreted as offering the distinctively pre-distributionist contribution in policy

    debates as to how to address the New Inequality. I think, in fact, that his policies are

    nowhere near radical enough they certainly do not compare to that which Meade and

    Rawls envisaged.

    Hacker pragmatically takes the preferred institutions of the social democratic Left

    to be working well and basically only in need of protection and expansion. [Hacker,

    2013] That is why, from the point of view of European social democrats already

    committed to welfare state capitalist institutions, Hackers message is keep what you

    have and avoid the Right-wing assault on pooled capital schemes. He aims to return

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    20/47

    Draft Only 20

    America to the goal of being an equality and opportunity society. This certainly

    corresponds to Rawlss goals as articulated in his first two principles that guarantee the

    equal basic liberties and fair equality of opportunity. However, nothing in this aspiration

    reflects the difference principle and that is an inadequate conception of justice.

    I think this difference is brought out by arguing that Hackers policies are not

    going to do well in dealing with the problem of the squeezed middle even though that

    was their avowed goal. This is because adopting the goal of an equality and

    opportunity society encourages meritocratic defences of inequality; defences that seem

    to play some role in explaining widespread tolerance of extensive inequality combinedwith reflective disapproval of this state of affairs.35Pikettys data shows that putatively

    meritocratic justifications have been given to justify some of the income inequality of

    the last forty years; he is sceptical about their factual basis. Admittedly, not even that

    meritocratic justification fully explains this inequality; unequal capital holding also plays

    an important role. But my point is that, for Rawls, meritocratic justifications are

    unacceptable from the perspective of justice even if their factual basis were correct.

    The ideology of meritocracy has certainly played some role in justifying the

    stagnant income position of the lower middle class the very sector that Hacker wants to

    help with a further expansion of welfare state commitments. Examples of the kinds of

    policies he favours are the extension of effective social insurance schemes on a

    stakeholder basis and the extension of transfer schemes like the working families tax

    credit. I do not think any party to this debate can believe in good faith that the current

    extreme inequality in capital holding and income has been shaped by free and open

    competition on a level playing field.36The great risk shift has taken place in a context

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    21/47

    Draft Only 21

    that was already unfair. My point is that if we make the playing field fair solely by

    realizing the goals of equal liberty and fair equality of opportunity, then there willstillbe

    a problem of the squeezed middle.

    This point is also made by Lane Kenworthy in his own assessment of Hackers

    pre-distributionism: if our goal is to solve the problem of the squeezed middle by

    finding high quality jobs for the highly educated middle class in a new knowledge

    economy, then this can hardly be expected to solve the problem for this entire class of

    people.37 [Kenworthy, 2013a; see also Turner, 2012, p. 86] It will, in fact, look like a

    retrospective vindication of meritocracy. That is why Kenworthy, even more thanHacker, pins his hopes on an expanded social democratic conception of the welfare state

    that he contrastswith a strategy that he labels pre-distributionism. [Kenworthy, 2013a,

    2013b]

    Kenworthy accurately identifies a bundle of Center-Left social democratic

    policies envisaged as paradigmatically pre-distributive in recent policy debate: more

    investment in education; an expanded manufacturing sector; stronger trade (labour)

    unions; minimum wage increases; the macro-economic goal of full employment;

    mandatory codetermination arrangements in large companies; profit sharing; increasing

    the number of workers in employment; finally, government intervention in the form of

    more public goods and services. [Kenworthy, 2013b]

    His evaluation of this raft of policies is ambivalent: some seem unrealistic, such

    as increasing trade union representation (down to 5% - 7% in the US private sector)38or

    expanding the manufacturing base. A realistic minimum wage or the goal of full

    employment seem unrealistic solely because of lack of political will39; by contrast, he

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    22/47

    Draft Only 22

    thinks that co-determination or profit sharing are good policies, but only work at the

    margins in developed economies. Together, they will have a limited effect on the

    problem of inequality.

    Kenworthy believes that we should resign ourselves to some of the social changes

    of the last forty years and aim further to increase the number of secondary earners in the

    workforce.40Everyones quality of life can be improved by the provision of more public

    goods, but the primary policy instrument we need is a working families tax credit: a

    conditional earnings subsidy.

    This is, obviously enough, a return to a traditional form of re-distributiveegalitarianism. Kenworthy is honest enough to admit that it produces its own moral

    hazard problem: if the general taxpayer funds this re-distributive subsidy, then the

    employers who have held wages stagnant for forty years face no pressure at all to change

    their policy. This kind of approach to the problem of the New Inequality contrasts with

    the kind of pre-distributionism I defend that is clearly more radical than the version that

    Kenworthy criticises. My objection to Hackers proposals is that they do not go far

    enough; my objection to Kenworthys revamped welfare state capitalism is that it leaves

    the fate of the squeezed middle at the mercy of democratic politics. They are to be

    assisted by re-distributive taxation so long as that political will exists. This is not a

    structural reform: it leaves the incentives of employers to underpay untouched. Indeed, it

    subsidises them to make that choice.

    This point, it seems to me, reinforces the fact that neither Hackers pre-

    distributionism nor Kenworthys re-distributionism is likely to be effective in addressing

    the problem of the squeezed middle. This is because neither of them aims at the

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    23/47

    Draft Only 23

    comprehensive re-structuring of the relations between labour and capital that is

    distinctive of Meades and Rawlss egalitarian property-owning democracies. Meade and

    Rawls demanded nothing less than the reform of the basic wage-setting institutions of

    society. Marginal changes brought about by a patchwork of particular policies will not

    add up to a change of the scale required. Only such a macro-level restructuring will

    provide an appropriate context for more local and restricted policies that may seem

    attractive as stand alone initiatives, but which can lead to a damaging policy of the

    second best if implemented piecemeal. In particular, Rawls makes the case that

    vindicating meritocracy cannot even be a part of our normative goals.

    41

    The aim is not toameliorate the conditions of those currently being harshly treated by the market, but to

    remove structural sources of unfairness. In the envisaged just society prosperity is

    diffused and no sector of society is squeezed at all because of a fundamental reform of

    the basic economic structure of our societies.

    I do not want to place any artificial distance between my view and Hackers. His

    goal is a fair distribution of income and opportunity alone. The former shapes his

    endorsement of a minimum wage; it is the latter that shapes his belief that increased

    public spending should be on education. However, Hacker also focuses on the big

    picture of encouraging macroeconomic stability overall, as he puts it, before the next

    asset bubble. [Hacker, 2013] That was Meades goal, too; I have emphasized how a

    property-owning democracy, combined with responsible attitudes to public debt and a

    rigorous regime of financial regulation smooth out boom and bust capitalist cycles in the

    economy.42

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    24/47

    Draft Only 24

    A crucial factor for Hacker is the loss of organised labour as a countervailing

    force in the market to organised controllers of capital. This is one of his three pillars of

    mid-twentieth century America prosperity: the first is a neo-Keynesian macroeconomic

    policy; the second a high quality education system; the third is the existence of the kind

    of public-private partnerships that shaped a distinctively American welfare state.

    However, the first two of those pillars remain even if the loss of the countervailing power

    of organised labour has contributed to the loss of the third pillar of prosperity, namely, its

    distinctive public-private partnerships at the service of social security, broadly

    conceived. In my view the situation facing current egalitarians takes us straight back toMeade and to Rawls: to a neo-Keynesian economic policy that targets underlying capital

    and a derivative focus on education and the development of human capital. In particular,

    an egalitarian strategy that does not focus solely on organised labour as its most effective

    political vehicle of social change has become relevant once more.

    I have throughout contrasted pre-distributive and re-distributive egalitarian

    strategies in general terms, but David Singh Grewal makes a specific point about our

    current circumstances with a direct bearing on this choice:

    The question of whether ex ante or ex post mechanisms are more efficient assumesthat both are politically feasible and it may be nave to assume that after lettingthe inequality-producing market runs its course there will be any agent left at theend of the process capable of demanding redistribution. Indeed, on a more path-dependent conception of political action, it may only be through structural changesto the economy which galvanize political coalitions while resurrecting distributivequestions that an electorate becomes capable of demanding higher tax rates.[Grewal, 2014, p. 665, emphasis added]

    I think it is undoubtedly true that, on this precise point, Grewal, Hacker and I are in

    complete agreement. The political changes of the last forty years have been deliberately

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    25/47

    Draft Only 25

    engineered to remove any agent for a redistributive politics, but the same is not true of an

    agent of pre-distributive politics. Meade thought that an egalitarianism driven by

    organized labour was counter-productive and so formulated a policy that made no such

    appeal; that helps to explain the relevance of this egalitarianism when such an agent is

    not even available.

    When Meade first formulated his revisionist proposals in the 1960s and 1970s

    they had some influence on Labour Party policy, but this was limited for two reasons.

    The first was that it represented a shift away from an appeal to organized labour that was

    difficult in a party created by the trade union movement. Secondly these policies could berepresented by political opponents as soak the rich policies that imposed taxes on

    wealth with no positive proposal as to how that transfer of wealth would inform an ideal

    of a just society. That was a misrepresentation at the time and it is a misunderstanding

    now: if we face, in Pikettys terms, a tipping point in the emergence of a new, capitalist

    form of feudalism in the guise of a society of unproductive rentiers whose interests lock

    in place a fixed structure of class based social relations, then we also face an historic

    opportunity to alter this course. Expanding the economic basis of citizenship for all

    citizens through a property-owning democracy is just, efficient, and stable. I turn, now,

    to the question of whether it is realistically utopian.

    Conclusion Two Cheers for Capitalism?

    This is, obviously enough, a large and complex subject and I can only end with some

    general remarks.43 My suggestion that a property-owning democracy is a realistically

    utopian egalitarian ideal is certainly open to misunderstanding: I am not suggesting that it

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    26/47

    Draft Only 26

    represents an individualistic ideal of self-sufficiency that suits an American society of

    conservative egalitarians (to invoke Jacobs and Pages well-known phrase). [Jacobs

    and Page, p. ix, pp. 234] That idea has been, indeed, the province of the Right wing

    version of the ideal that, far from inhibiting radical inequality, has played a role in

    generating it. 44 (That which distinguishes that version of the ideal is its moral

    individualism and its in principle anti-statism.)

    By contrast, the grounds I see for limited optimism are, first, that the tradition

    with which I am concerned here seems to me to have identified the correct targets and to

    have dispelled some crucial legitimating myths in this debate over the sources andremedies for inequality. By identifying the correct targets, I specifically mean directing

    our gaze away from high gains in the financial sector or executive remuneration: we

    know, collectively, how to deal with both even if in some jurisdictions political factors

    mean that we do not do so (such as in the USA). Products of political action, they can be

    reversed by political action: democratic determination of effective financial regulation

    and corporate governance, plus a very high rate of progressive income taxation, plus an

    acceptance that any financial institution too big to fail is too big to exist, ought to

    eliminate these problems. Piketty, for example, is comparatively relaxed about the issue

    of extensive rewards in the financial sector.45[Piketty, 2014b] It has its special features

    and it has certainly benefitted from regulatory drift from public policy being behind the

    curve of industry change but the percentage of economic activity reflected in these

    rewards is comparatively low.46 Focusing on hedge fund managers is as misleading as

    focusing on sports stars or entertainment celebrities: in all three cases we are not baffled

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    27/47

    Draft Only 27

    when it comes to a policy response. From being behind the curve taxation and regulation

    needs to be ahead of it.

    Piketty takes as his target the underlying distribution of who holds capital and the

    issue is not the current massive inequality in returns from income, but on what happens

    next in a society such as the USA. America has always tolerated inequality tied to

    individual circumstance, partly because it was assumed that it would dissipate over a

    limited period of a generation or so. That which Americans have always resisted is the

    recreation of an Old World neo-feudalism, with fixed relations of hierarchy based on

    static social relations, fixed social classes, unproductive activity, rent seeking and asignificant role for inheritance.47Yet that seems, if the historical pattern is not changed,

    to be where the bad faith putatively autonomous logic of capitalism is taking the

    USA over the next generation or so where todays personal fortune grounded on merit

    becomes someone elses unearned inheritance.

    When it comes to eliminating legitimating myths, I take it the real contributions of

    the Meade-Rawls-Piketty tradition is to expose any argument that defends either income

    or wealth inequality as a product of a fictional autonomous logic of capitalism or, for

    that matter, of pure meritocracy. If we thought that the benign development of post-

    War capitalism represented by the Kuznets curve was, in fact, an historical anomaly then

    the next question is how we can make this anomaly our new normal instead of the

    contrasting normal with which we seem to be stuck. [Galbraith, 2014] The particular

    version of the autonomous logic argument most cited in the recent literature is the

    claim that extensive inequality is a product of globalization: this is, for various reasons, a

    bad explanation.48There is no reason to believe that the global context has, in any

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    28/47

    Draft Only 28

    politically relevant sense, changed between 1970 and 2010 yet the US economy has

    radically diverged from other Western economies when it comes to inequality of wealth

    and income.

    This leads to the vexed question of the agents of any future change towards the

    implementation of a property-owning democracy. Here my view contrasts with that

    expressed in David Singh Grewal in his very insightful review of Pikettys book.

    Influenced by the neo-Marxist theorist Wolfgang Streeck and by the idea that political

    action is path-dependent Grewals policies for addressing the New Inequality do not

    aim to reconstruct the political conditions of the post-War neo-Keynesianism that formedthe context of Meades work. [Streeck, 2011, 2014; Grewal, 2014, pp. 664-667] Grewal

    accepts Streecks diagnosis that neo-Liberal political action has taken us to a situation

    comparable to the period before the trente glorieuses; it follow, then, by an argument

    from analogy that our current political remedies should be analogous to those applicable

    to the period before the exceptional times began. [Grewal, 2014, p. 665] These include

    general strikes and labor activism, experiments with new forms of cooperative industrial

    organization, and radical political and social movements. [Grewal, 2014, p. 665]

    I simply note that a striking omission in Grewals otherwise insightful review

    is that he does not place Piketty in the pre-distributionist, capital-egalitarian tradition of

    Meade and Rawls where he belongs; Grewal takes him to be an orthodox ex post factore-

    distributivist. 49 But I hope to have shown here that the twentieth century neo-

    Keynesianism of Meade and Rawls was considerably more innovative than that. I fully

    accept that the decline of organized labour was no co-incidence, but the result of political

    action, and any further strengthening of civic and organizational life will form part of a

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    29/47

    Draft Only 29

    solution to the problem of inequality. [Hacker and Pierson, 2010, pp. 127-132] However,

    as Kenworthy notes, that will not be enough in itself to reverse the changes of the last

    forty years. [Kenworthy, 2013a, p.4]

    But it is a resonant historical irony that Meade formulated his strategy to avoid

    dependence on the traditional resource of organized labour as the basis for a conventional

    form of social democracy: in his historical context he thought this would be counter-

    productive. That strategy remains available to us, not when this collective agency is not

    one that we elect not to use, but when it has been rendered unavailable even if only for

    a limited historical period. I have also noted that both Alperovitz and Grewal make thepoint that the conditions for capitals politically successful assault on labour are about to

    change: the shift in the basis of the US economy from manufacturing to services and the

    slowing of both immigration and population growth will see the return of labour.50

    In his own policy for the re-capitalising of American citizens Thad Williamson

    argues that, given that Americans have never had it so bad when it comes to inequality,

    this is an historically opportune moment to intervene to change the narrative.

    [Williamson, 2012] Williamson, like Alperovitz, thinks that community wealth building

    initiatives from the ground up are an appropriate path combined with political leadership

    to bring about the re-distribution of wealth. [Alperovitz, 2005] After all, whatever one

    might think of the justification for extensive wealth and inheritance taxes and steeply

    progressive income taxes, it can hardly be objected that the one percent are going to live

    substantially worse lives if this regime of taxation is implemented. We seem to be, then,

    living through a crucial historical juncture: whatever the outcome, my argument in this

    paper has been that we are not at a loss for a normative orientation for what ought to be

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    30/47

    Draft Only 30

    the outcome. In that sense, I think, we are entitled to a limited degree of optimism about

    the future.51

    List of Works Cited

    Alperovitz, Gar [2005] America Beyond Capitalism: Reclaiming Our Wealth, Our

    Liberty, and Our Democracy, John Wiley.

    Arneson, Richard [1986] Comment on Krouse and MacPherson, Ethics, vol. 97, no. 1,

    pp. 139145.Arneson, Richard [1999] Against Rawlsian Equality of Opportunity, Philosophical

    Studies, no. 93, pp. 11-112.

    Arneson, Richard [2011] Liberalism, Capitalism and Socialist Principles, Social

    Philosophy and Policy, vol. 28, issue 02, pp. 232-261.

    Arnold, N. Scott [1994] The Philosophy and Economics of Market Socialism: A Critical

    Examination, Oxford University Press.

    Atkinson, Anthony B., Piketty, Thomas and Saez, Emmanuel [2011] Top Incomes in the

    Long Run of History,Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 49, no. 1, pp. 371.

    Atkinson, Anthony B. [2015]Inequality: What Can Be Done?, Harvard University Press.

    Blyth, Mark [2015] Ending the Creditors Paradise,Jacobin, 27thFebruary.

    https://www.jacobinmag.com/2015/02/germany-austerity-blyth-speech-spd/

    Bohman, James [2011] Is Hegel a Republican?: Pippin, Recognition, and Domination in

    the Philosophy of Right.Inquiry, 53, pp. 435-49.

    Crosland, C. A. R. [1956/2006] The Future of Socialism, Constable & Robinson.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    31/47

    Draft Only 31

    DeLong, Brad [2006] The Primacy of Politics for Income Distribution? Grasping

    RealityBlog, August 20.

    http://delong.typepad.com/sdj/2006/08/the_primacy_of_.html

    DeLong, Brad [2014] Mr. Piketty and the Neo-classicists: A Suggested Interpretation,

    Grasping RealityBlog, August 20.

    http://www.bradford-delong.com/2014/05/the-honest-broker-mr-piketty-and-the-

    neoclassicists-a-suggested-interpretation-for-the-week-of-may-17-2014.html#more

    Dew-Becker, Ian and Gordon, Robert J. [2008] Controversies About the Rise of

    American Inequality: A Survey,National Bureau of Economic ResearchWorking Paper13982.

    URL: http://www.nber.org/papers/w13982

    Bourgoignon, Franois [2015] The Globalization of Inequality, trans. Thomas Scott-

    Railton, Princeton University Press.

    Feldstein, Martin [2005] Rethinking Social Insurance,American Economic Review, vol.

    95, no.1, pp. 1-24.

    Freeman, Richard B. [1996/97] Solving the New Inequality, The Boston Review,

    December/January issue.

    http://new.bostonreview.net/BR21.6/freeman.html

    Galbraith, James K. [2012]Inequality and Instability: A Study of the World Economy Just

    Before the Great Crisis, Oxford University Press.

    Galbraith, James K. [2014] The End of Normal: the Great Crisis and the Future of

    Growth, Simon & Schuster.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    32/47

    Draft Only 32

    Gilens, Martin and Page, [2014] Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest

    Groups and Average Citizens,Perspectives on Politics, vol. 12, no. 3, pp. 564581.

    Grewal, David Singh [2014] The Laws of Capital: Review of Thomas Piketty, Capital in

    the Twenty-First Century,Harvard Law Review, pp. 626667.

    Grusky, David B. [2012] What To Do About Inequality, The Boston Review,

    March/April.

    http://www.bostonreview.net/grusky-forum-inequality

    Grusky, David B. [2013] Taxing Away Inequality: A Conversation with Emmanuel

    Saetz, The Boston Review, February 28

    th

    .http://www.bostonreview.net/world-mccoy-family-center-ethics-society-stanford-

    university/taxing-away-inequality

    Guttman, Amy (ed.) [1988] Democracy and the Welfare State, Princeton University

    Press.

    Hacker, Jacob S. [2008] The Great Risk Shift: The New Economic Insecurity and the

    Decline of the American Dream, Oxford University Press.

    Hacker, Jacob S and Pierson, Paul [2010] Winner-Take-All-Politics: How Washington

    Made the Rich Richer--and Turned Its Back on the Middle Class, Simon and Schuster.

    Hacker, Jacob S. [2011] The Institutional Foundations of Middle Class Democracy

    http://www.policy-

    network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=3998&title=The+institutional+foundations+of+middle-

    class+democracy

    Hacker, Jacob s. [2013] An Interview with Jacob S. Hacker,Renewal, vol. 21, nos. 2/3.

    http://www.renewal.org.uk/articles/interview-the-politics-of-predistribution/

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    33/47

    Draft Only 33

    Heath, Joseph [2011] Three Normative Models of the Welfare State, Public Reason,

    vol. 3, no. 2 pp.1343.

    Hotelling, Harold [1929] Stability in Competition, The Economic Journal, vol. 39, no.

    153, pp. 4157.

    Jacobs, Lawrence and Page, Benjamim [2009] Class War? What Americans Really Think

    About Economic Inequality, University of Chicago Press.

    Kenworthy, Lane [2013a] Social Democratic America, Oxford University Press.

    Kenworthy, Lane [2013b] Whats Wrong with Predistribution?, Juncture, September

    20

    th

    .http://www.ippr.org/juncture/171/11298/whats-wrong-with-predistribution

    Krouse, Richard and McPherson, Michael [1986] A "mixed"-property regime: Equality

    and liberty in a market economy,Ethics, vol. 97, no. 1, pp. 119138 .

    Krouse, Richard and McPherson, Michael [1998] Capitalism, Property Owning

    Democracy and the Welfare State in Guttmann, A [1988] pp. 79-106.

    Krugman, Paul [2014] Why Were In a New Gilded Age, New York Review of Books,

    May 8.

    http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2014/may/08/thomas-piketty-new-gilded-

    age/?insrc=hpma

    Kuznets, Simon [1953] Shares of Upper Income Groups in Income and Savings, National

    Bureau of Economic Research.

    http://papers.nber.org/books/kuzn53-1

    Lind, Jo Thori [2005] Why is there So Little Redistribution?Nordic Journal of Political

    Economy, vol. 31, pp. 111125.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    34/47

    Draft Only 34

    Mankiw, N. Gregory [2008] The Wealth Trajectory: Rewards for the Few, New York

    Times, April 20.

    Meade, James [1993]Liberty, Equality and Efficiency, Macmillan.

    Meltzer, Allen H. and Richards, Scott F. [1981] A Rational Theory of the Size of

    Government, The Journal of Political Economy, vol. 89, no. 5, pp. 914927.

    Milanovic, Branko [2000] "The median-voter hypothesis, income inequality, and income

    redistribution: an empirical test with the required data, European Journal of Political

    Economy, vol. 16, pp. 367410.

    Milanovic, Branko [2014] The Return of "Patrimonial Capitalism": A Review ofThomas Piketty's Capital in the Twenty-First Century, Journal of Economic Literature,

    vol. 52, no. 2, pp. 51934.

    Naidu, Suresh [2014a] Notes from Capital in the Twenty First Century Panel, The Slack

    Wire Blog, April 20.

    http://slackwire.blogspot.com/2014/04/notes-from-capital-in-21st-century-panel.html

    Naidu, Suresh [2014b] Capital Eats the World,Jacobin, May 30.

    https://www.jacobinmag.com/2014/05/capital-eats-the-world/

    ONeill, Martin and Williamson, Thad [2012a]Property Owning Democracy: Rawls and

    Beyond, Wiley-Blackwell.

    Piketty, Thomas [2014a] Capital in the Twenty-First Century, trans. Arthur Goldhammer,

    Harvard University Press.

    Piketty, Thomas [2014b] An Interview with Thomas Piketty.

    URL: http://www.vox.com/2014/4/24/5643780/who-is-thomas-piketty#interview

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    35/47

    Draft Only 35

    Piketty, Thomas [2016] Capital, Predistribution and Redistribution, Crooked Timber,

    January 4.

    URL: http://crookedtimber.org/2016/01/04/capital-predistribution-and-redistribution/

    Rawls, John [1971]A Theory of Justice, first edition, Belknap Press.

    Rawls, John [1993]Political Liberalism, Columbia University Press.

    Rawls, John [1999]A Theory of Justice, second edition, Belknap Press.

    Rawls, John [2001]Justice as Fairness: A Re-statement, Harvard University Press.

    Rosanvallon, Pierre [2013] The Society of Equals, translated by Arthur Goldhammer,

    Harvard University Press.Rosen, Sherwin [1981] The Economics of Superstars, The American Economic Review,

    vol. 71, no. 5, pp. 845858.

    Ruggie, John Gerard [1982] International Regimes, Transactions, and Change:

    Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order, International Organization, vol.

    36, no. 2, pp 379415.

    Saez, Emmanuel and Zucman, Gabriel [2014] Wealth Inequality in the United States

    since 1913: Evidence from Capitalized Income Tax Data, National Bureau of Economic

    Research Working Paper Series, no. 20625, October.

    http://www.nber.org/papers/w20625

    Saez, Emmanuel [2015] Striking it Richer: The Evolution of Top Incomes in the United

    States (Updated with 2013 Preliminary Estimates), January 25.

    http://eml.berkeley.edu/~saez/saez-UStopincomes-2013.pdf

    Smith, Paul [1998] Incentives and Justice: G. A. Cohens Egalitarian Critique of Rawls,

    Social Theory and Practice, vol. 24, no.2, pp. 205235.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    36/47

    Draft Only 36

    Solow, Robert [2014] Piketty is Right: Review of Thomas Piketty, Capital in the

    Twenty-First Century, The New Republic, April 22.

    http://www.newrepublic.com/article/117429/capital-twenty-first-century-thomas-piketty-

    reviewed

    Stiglitz, Joseph [2012] The Price of Inequality: How Todays Divided Society Endangers

    Our Future, W. W. Norton and Company, inc.

    Streeck, [2011] The Crises of Democratic Capitalism, New Left Review, no. 71, pp. 5

    29.

    Streeck, Wolfgang [2014] The Politics of Public Debt: Neoliberalism, CapitalistDevelopment, and the Restructuring of the State, German Economic Review, vol. 15,

    issue 1, pp. 143165.

    Sunstein, Cass [2004] The Second Bill of Rights: FDRs Unfinished Revolution and Why

    We Need It More Than Ever, Basic Books.

    Taylor, Robert S [2013] Illiberal Socialism, unpublished ms.

    Thomas, Alan [2006/2010] Value and Context: the Nature of Moral and Political

    Knowledge, Clarendon Press.

    Thomas, Alan [2011] Cohens Critique of Rawls: a Double Counting Objection, Mind,

    vol. 120, issue 480, pp. 10991142.

    Thomas, Alan [2012a] Property-owning Democracy, Liberal Republicanism, and the

    Idea of an Egalitarian Ethos in ONeill, Martin and Williamson, Thad, Property-owning

    Democracy: Rawls and Beyond, Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 101128.

    Thomas, Alan [2012b] Rawls, Smith and and Argument fromComplexity toProperty-

    owning Democracy, The Good Society, vol. 21, no.1, pp. 420.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    37/47

    Draft Only 37

    Thomas, Alan [2013] Sen On Rawlss Transcendental Institutionalism: An Analysis

    and Critique,European Journal of Political Theory, vol. 13, no. 3, pp. 241263.

    Thomas, Alan [2015] Prerogatives and Incentives: A Reply to Brian Berkey,MindJuly.

    Thomas, Alan [2015] Rawls and Political Realism: Realistic Utopianism or Judgement

    in Bad Faith?,European Journal of Political Theory(forthcoming).

    Thomas, Alan [2016] Republic of Equals: Predistribution and Property-Owning

    Democracy, Oxford University Press (USA).

    Turner, Adair [2012]Economics After the Crisis, Oxford University Press.

    Williamson, Thad [2012a] Realizing Property-Owning Democracy: A Twenty YearStrategy to Create an Egalitarian Distribution of Assets in the United States, in ONeill

    and Williamson [2012] pp. 225248

    Williamson, Thad [2012b] Is Property-Owning Democracy a Politically Viable

    Aspiration?, in ONeill and Williamson [2012] pp. 287306.

    Winters, Jeffrey A. and Page, Benjamin I. [2009] Oligarchy in the United States?

    Perspectives on Politics, vol. 7. No. 4, pp. 731751.

    Wolin, Sheldon [2008] Democracy Incorporated: Managed Democracy and the Specter

    of Inverted Totalitarianism,Princeton University Press.

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    38/47

    Draft Only 38

    #Professor of Ethics, Tilburg University. [email protected] material in

    this paper re-capitulates some of the central arguments ofRepublic of Equals: Pre-

    distribution and Property-owning Democracy, to be published in 2016 by Oxford

    University Press.

    $Krouse, Richard and MacPherson, Michael [1998] Capitalism, Property Owning

    Democracy and the Welfare State in Guttmann, A [1988] pp. 79-106; Richard Arneson

    [1986]. See also Arneson [2011].

    3The publication of ONeill and Williamsons anthology [2012] may yet mark a change

    in the fortunes of property-owning democracy.4From 1979 until the eve of the Great Recession [2008] the top one percent received

    36 percent of all gains in household income . Economic growth was even more skewed

    between 2001 and 2006 the share of income gains going to the top one percent was

    over 53 percent . the top 0.1 percent one out of every thousand households received

    over 20 percent of all after-tax income gains between 1979 and 2005, compared with the

    13.5 percent enjoyed by the bottom 60 percent of households. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010,

    p. 3] Hacker and Pierson largely rely, in their 2010 book, on the data supplied by Piketty

    and Saez from 1913 up to 2007. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 14, p. 312, fn. 1] This is

    supplemented by data from the Congressional Budget Office. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010,

    p. 21] It is noteworthy that this is income data and that the wealth data is even more

    skewed. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 32] See also Atkinson, Piketty and Saez [2011];

    Saez and Zucman [2014]; Saez [2015].5

    [Freeman, 1996/7]%Regarding the latter, Hacker and Pierson argue that The precipitous fall in union

    membership occurred even though workers continued to voice strong and after 1984,

    increasing public support for unions and their goals. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 142]

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    39/47

    Draft Only 39

    &[T]he Great Recession has been particularly hard on those at the bottom, and even

    those in the middle, and this is typical: ordinary worker face higher unemployment, lower

    wages, declining house prices, a loss of much of their wealth. Since the rich are better

    able to bear risk, they reap the reward that society provides for compensating for the

    greater risk. [Stiglitz, 2012, p. 91, emphasis added]

    'As Hacker and Pierson memorably put it Recessions, it turned out, were for suckers,

    not bankers. [Hacker and Pierson, 2010, p. 292]

    (The rising share of national income captured by the richest Americans is a long-term

    trend . Moreover, that is not obviously related to either the business cycle or the

    shifting partisan occupancy of the White House. [Pierson & Hacker, 2010, pp. 17-18]

    #)

    Hacker and Pierson are also drawn to the metaphor of drift as government regulationand tax/transfer regimes fail to adapt to new economic realities step by step, as it were

    and leading to governmental sins of omission at the behest of special interests. [Hacker

    and Pierson, 2010, pp. 52-3]

    ##Two of the most insightful interpreters of Thomas Pikettys work, Brad DeLong and

    Suresh Naidu, argue that the major flaw in the argument of Capital in the Twenty-First

    Century is a lacuna on precisely this connection between wealth inequality and the

    politics of oligarchy. See DeLong [2014] and Naidu [2014a, 2014b] So extending the

    argument from neo-classical economics into political economy and back again greatly

    strengthens Pikettys conclusions. I defer a full examination of DeLongs and Naidus

    arguments to another occasion. That the equation r > g is meaningless in itself as a

    critique of inequality is acknowledged by Piketty in his recent [2016], but the relevant

    connection with the politics of oligarchy is, it seems to me, clearly present in Piketty

    [2014a].12Thus I agree entirely with Gar Alperovitz: until the foundational question of whether

    some other way to reduce inequality is confronted and resolved, it is unlikely that thedemocraticquestion of how to curb the influence of money in politics can be effectively

    dealt with. [Alperovitz, 2005, p. 52]13In particular, Gilens and Page falsify the median voter theorem [Hotelling, 1929]; that

    theorem has, as a corollary, Melzer and Richardss derived thesis that the median voter

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    40/47

    Draft Only 40

    will inhibit substantial inequalities. [Melzer & Richards, 1981] For some empirical

    assessments of the general Melzer and Richards model see Lind [2005] and Milanovic

    [2000]. The median voter theorem seems, in any case, currently to be empirically false

    for the USA.14It excerpts some of the central arguments of Republic of Equals: Pre-distribution and

    Property-Owning Democracyto be published in 2016 by Oxford University Press (USA).

    #*The extent to which the view I call liberal-republicanism is a friendly amendment to,

    or re-interpretation of, Rawlsian political liberalism is discussed in Republic of Equals

    chapter one.16As Bohman also puts it: Hegels claims about the modern state only make sense if it

    fulfills the central republican demand: that the capacity of others to dominate is not justcurrently absent, butstructurally impossible. [Bohman, 2010, p. 440, emphasis added]

    #&I argue that a property-owning democracy is normatively prior to liberal market

    socialism inRepublic of Equals, chapter 8, in partial agreement with the arguments of the

    arguments of Arnold [1994] and Bob Taylor [2013]. See also Thomas [2012].18 Although in theory the difference principle permits indefinitely large inequalities in

    return for small gains to the less favoured, the spread of income and wealth should not be

    excessive in practice,given the requisite background institutions, [Rawls, 1971, p. 536,

    emphasis added]

    #(One version of this argument is that the US paid the price of inequality for superior

    growth compared to, for example, European states. Hacker and Pierson effectively

    debunk that particular myth. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, pp. 26-7]

    $) Hacker and Pierson note the popularity of this argument with some US based

    economists: unfortunately, it fails to explain the pulling away of the very top and the

    effect of education is to avoid the devastatingly slow growth at the bottom. The

    economic impact of being a college educated knowledge worker are minimal.Furthermore, this explanation fails to generalize; why didnt workers in other advanced

    economies suffer the same fate? [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 35-7]

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    41/47

    Draft Only 41

    21The main consolation for those worried about this enormous concentration of power is

    that, like the rest of us, even these very privileged individuals will eventually die. But

    Pikettys point is that their fortunes dont. [Grewal, 2014, p. 641]

    $$Hacker and Pierson cite both Mankiw and DeLong as arguing that, since inequality in

    income is in pre-tax income, its explanation cannot significantly involve political factors,

    but it is the market bringing us the bad news. Hacker and Pierson point out that this

    argument ignores the political context of markets as well as the role played by tax and

    transfer policy in allowing these income inequalities to become wealth inequalities to

    help to convert these income inequalities into unproductive rent seeking. [Hacker &

    Pierson, 2010, p. 43-44, citing Mankiw, 2008; DeLong, 2006] 23

    Any Europeans who complacently think that Pikettys focus is the woes ofcontemporary America are right to a limited extent: he thinks that very high executive

    remuneration is a culturally explicable local phenomenon. However, on the issue of

    inheritance, European social democrats have more reason to be more concerned than their

    American counterparts. See Piketty [2014a], p. 378, 381. I think Brad DeLong is correct

    to note that, in spite of the unremitting hostility of North American commentators to

    Pikettys work, his primary focus is understandably not America, but France.

    [DeLong, 2014] For sympathetic treatments of Pikettys central argument see DeLong

    [2014], Grewal [2014], Krugman [2014], Naidu [2014], Milanovic [2014] and Solow

    [2014].24We have to multiply the capital-income ratio by the rate of return, and the same law of

    diminishing returns suggests that the rate of return on capital will fall. As production

    becomes more and more capital-intensive, it gets harder and harder to find profitable uses

    for additional capital, or easy ways to substitute capital for labor. Whether the capital

    share falls or rises depends on whether the rate of return has to fall proportionately more

    or less than the capital-income ratio rises. [Solow, 2013]25[O]ther advanced industrial countries with similar technology and per capita income

    differ greatly from the United States in inequality of pretax income (before transfers), in

    inequality of after tax and transfer income, in inequality of wealth, and in income

    mobility. These countries also differ greatly from the United States in the trendsin these

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    42/47

    Draft Only 42

    four variables over time. If markets were the principal driving force, why do seemingly

    similar advanced industrial countries differ so much? Our hypothesis is that market forces

    are real, but that they are shaped by political processes. [Stiglitz, 2012, p. 52, emphasis

    added] See also footnote 10.26 In strict logic, it could be otherwise, but the forces pushing in this direction are

    extremely powerful. The inequality r > g in one sense implies that the past tends to

    devour the future: wealth originating in the past automatically grows more rapidly, even

    without labour, than wealth stemming from work, which can be saved. Almost inevitably

    this tends to give lasting disproportionate importance to inequalities created in the past,

    and therefore to inheritance. [Piketty, 2014a, p. 378]27

    As Grewal notes, Crosland also wondered if these societies were indeed still accuratelyto be described as capitalist and his answer was no. [Grewal, 2014, p.657, fn, 103 ;

    Crosland, 2006, p. 46]28This is where the distinction becomes pertinent between ballooning executive pay and

    the workings of r > g; a return to a top rate of tax of over 80 percent solves the first

    problem as it was only a politically motivated departure from a high top progressive rate

    that incentivized bargaining for his executive remuneration. So that is one problem that

    social democratic politics had already solved before the UK and the US decided to

    unsolve it once again. See Piketty [2014], pp. 512-514.

    $(Lane Kenworthy, whose views I will discuss in the next section, proposes that the USA

    increase spending on social programs from 37% to 47% of its current ($17 trillion) GDP.

    [Kenworthy, 2013a, p. 11]

    +) Kenworthys relative optimism is grounded on his belief that Americans are

    pragmatists and they like institutions that work: the major institutions of the social

    democratic tradition dowork. [Kenworthy, 2013a, pp. 1213] (This represents the kind of

    efficiency argument, as opposed to redistributive arguments, for such institutionsdefended by Joseph Heath. [Heath, 2011]). A separate, and open, question is the

    historical success of this tradition in bringing inequality within a permissible range. Cass

    Sunstein, for example, argues that it was not Roosevelts New Deal that ended the

    economic depression of the 1930s, but WWII. [Sunstein, 2004] That is consonant with

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    43/47

    Draft Only 43

    Pikettys argument that the only effective shocks to capital that have prevented

    extensive wealth inequality is the experience of world war. These arguments are not

    encouraging for the social democrat.

    +#Virtually stagnant as the modest average gains per household are negated by the

    increase in hours worked by all the earners in a household. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, pp.

    22-3, p. 26] By comparison the household after tax income of the 0.1 percent rose from

    $4 m to $24.3 m between 1979 and 2005. [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 24]

    +$This reflects the importance to Rawls of his two claims that, in a just society, the

    expectations of all groups are both close-knit and chain-connected. If these two

    assumptions hold, then arguments grounded in justice and solidarity produce the same

    outcome as arguments grounded in efficiency, but the theory of justice cannot assumethat these exogenous assumptions are true. By implementing justice as an integrated

    whole we thereby make them true. I discuss this crucial argument inRepublic of Equals,

    chapter 2.33For the truly extraordinary story of Americas current capital gains taxation regime see

    Stiglitz [2012] pp. 713.

    +,This is, of course, one aspect of their undue influence on austerity policies part of

    that which Mark Blyth calls a creditors paradise of positive real interest rates, low

    inflation, open markets, beaten-down unions, and a retreating state. [Blyth, 2015]

    +*For a very helpful complementary discussion of changing attitudes to inequality see

    Adair Turner: If the worlds of celebrity, fashion and media generate very high pay, and

    if there are more highly paid corporate lawyers and investment bankers than there once

    were, and if there are some businesses (e.g. fashion retailing) in which a star CEO can

    make a big difference and get highly rewarded, thenthe sense among highly paid people

    of what is normal and justifiable shift. [Turner, 2012, p. 22, emphasis added] The

    superstar hypothesis a special version of the meritocratic argument that great gainsare going to the most talented in intense winner takes all competitions that have mass

    audience appeal (whether in sports or entertainment) may work well as a legitimating

    myth, but as Hacker and Pierson, Rosanvallon and Piketty all note, sports stars and

    celebrities form only a small percentage of the very wealthy (Hacker and Pierson put the

  • 7/25/2019 Thomas: Rawls Piketty and the New Inequality (2016)

    44/47

    Draft Only 44

    figure at 3%). [Hacker & Pierson, 2010, p. 45; Rosanvallon, 2013, pp. 241-2] The classic

    paper on the economics of superstars is Rosen [1981]. As Dew-Becker and Gordon

    point out: superstars and other market-driven occupations have their incomes chosen by

    the market, whereas CEO compensation is chose