theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    1/16

    The Aristotelian Society and Wileyare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the

    Aristotelian Society.

    http://www.jstor.org

    Theories of Knowledge: An Analytic FrameworkAuthor(s): Susan HaackSource: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 83 (1982 - 1983), pp. 143-157Published by: on behalf ofWiley The Aristotelian SocietyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4544996Accessed: 27-08-2014 01:14 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aristotelianhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4544996http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4544996http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aristotelianhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    2/16

    IX*-THEORIES

    OF KNOWLEDGE:

    AN

    ANALYTIC

    FRAMEWORK

    by Susan Haack

    Contemporary epistemology

    must choose between the

    solid security of the ancient foundationalist pyramid and

    the risky adventure of the new coherentist raft. (Sosa')

    One seems forced to choose between the picture of an

    elephant

    which rests on a tortoise

    (What supports the

    tortoise?) and the picture

    of a

    great Hegelian serpent of

    knowledge

    with

    its

    tail

    in its

    mouth

    (Where

    does

    it

    begin?).

    Neither will

    do. (Sellars2)

    It is commonly supposed that

    one

    is

    obliged

    to

    choose, in the

    theory

    of

    knowledge,

    between

    two, fundamentally opposed

    models:

    the

    foundationalist, according

    to

    which

    the rest of our

    knowledge is supported by the foundation of a relatively small

    class

    of

    epistemically privileged beliefs, and the coherentist,

    according

    to

    which the

    various

    parts

    of

    our

    knowledge are

    mutually supportive.

    But it is

    rarely spelled

    out3

    what the

    characteristic

    features of foundationalism and coherentism

    are,

    or

    why they

    should be

    thought

    to

    be the only feasible

    options.

    My

    first

    object,

    in

    this

    paper,

    is

    to construct

    a scheme of

    classificationwithin which one can locate two extreme kindsof

    theory,

    which

    I

    will

    call

    'Pure Foundationalism'

    and

    'Pure

    Coherentism',

    and

    a whole

    range

    of intermediate

    kinds of

    theory

    in between.

    My

    second

    object

    is

    to

    examine,

    in

    the

    context

    of this

    framework,

    the

    arguments

    which have dominated the debate

    between

    foundationalism

    and coherentism.

    This

    discussion

    will,

    I

    believe,

    indicate that there are two

    intermediate

    types

    of

    theory capable

    of

    withstanding

    the

    arguments

    of both

    sides.

    I

    shall make it clear which of these I favour;but spacewill permit

    me

    only

    to hint

    at

    the reasons for

    my preference.

    *

    Meeting

    of

    the Aristotelian

    Society

    held

    at 5/7 Tavistock

    Place,

    London

    WC1,

    on

    Monday,

    14

    March,

    1983 at

    6.00 p.m.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    3/16

    144 SUSAN

    HAACK

    I

    Let me acknowledge,at the outset, that therewill ofcourse be an

    element of arbitrariness

    n

    the

    characterisations

    I

    shall

    give.

    But

    I

    hope

    that

    the

    characterisations

    given

    here

    will

    at

    any

    rate serve

    adequately

    to

    bring

    into focus

    the

    issues

    that have

    been

    debated

    between those who call themselves

    'foundationalists'

    and those

    who call

    themselves

    coherentists',

    without

    distorting

    the

    history

    of

    this debate

    any

    more than is unavoidable. The use of

    the

    terms 'foundationalism'

    and 'coherentism' in

    the

    literature

    has,

    however, been ill-defined and shifting to such an extent that I

    doubt that

    any

    characterisation could

    square

    with all of

    it.

    All

    the theories to be characterised

    in

    this

    section-Pure

    Foundationalism,

    Pure Coherentism

    and the

    intermediate

    theories-share

    the

    assumptions

    that we do

    have

    knowledge,

    and that

    our

    having knowledge requires

    (at least)

    our

    having

    beliefs

    which

    are

    justified

    as well

    as

    true;

    where

    they

    differ

    is

    on

    how our justified beliefs

    get

    their

    justification.

    By 'Pure

    Foundationalism'

    I

    shall

    mean

    any theory

    according

    to

    which:

    (PF1)

    Some beliefs

    are,

    epistemically,

    absolutely

    secure

    and:

    (PF2)

    All

    beliefs

    which

    are

    justified, but not absolutely

    secure (in the sense of (PFI)) are justified wholly by the

    support,

    direct

    or

    indirect,

    of

    these

    absolutely secure

    beliefs.

    I

    shall

    call

    (PF1)-without

    pejorative

    intent-'Dogmatism

    '4

    I

    have stated

    Dogmatism

    in

    a

    very general

    way,

    because

    I

    intend

    it to cover not

    just one,

    but a

    range

    of

    views.

    All

    Dogmatists

    hold

    that there are some

    privileged

    beliefs

    which

    enjoy immunity to

    certain kinds of epistemic defect; they differ, however, with

    regard

    to

    the kind of

    epistemic

    defect

    they

    have in

    mind. For

    example,

    some have

    in

    mind

    immunity

    to

    error

    (the privileged

    beliefs

    are

    'certain',

    that

    is, roughly,

    it

    is

    impossible

    that

    they

    should be

    mistakenly held);

    some,

    immunity

    to

    unwarranted-

    ness

    (the

    privileged

    beliefs

    are

    'self-warranting',

    hat

    is, roughly,

    it is

    impossible

    that

    they

    should be

    unjustifiedlyheld); some,

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    4/16

    THEORIES OF

    KNOWLEDGE: AN ANALY'I'IC FRAMEWORK

    145

    immunity

    to ignorance (the privileged

    beliefs are

    'self-

    manifesting',

    that is, roughly,

    it is

    impossible

    that

    they

    should

    fail to be believed when they are true); others, again, hold that

    there are privileged

    beliefs

    which

    enjoy some two,

    or

    even

    all

    three,

    kinds

    of

    immunity.

    (Here, even

    in the

    remarks

    in

    which

    I

    elaborate on my

    original, vague

    statement,

    I

    am,

    of

    course, greatly simplifying

    an

    extremely complex

    matter;

    a full account would

    call for

    careful

    textual analysis

    of what has been meant

    by saying

    that some

    beliefs

    are

    'indubitable', 'incorrigible',

    'directly evident',

    'self-

    evident', etc., etc.)5

    According

    to

    (PF2)

    the

    justification

    of

    each

    justified

    but

    unprivileged

    belief

    depends

    on the

    support

    of

    some

    privileged

    belief

    or

    beliefs:

    either

    directly (privileged

    beliefs

    justify

    the

    unprivileged

    belief in

    question)

    or

    indirectly (privileged

    beliefs

    justify unprivileged

    beliefs,

    . . . which

    justify

    the

    unprivileged

    belief

    in

    question).

    The crucial

    point

    is that

    all the

    justification

    of

    any justified

    but

    unprivileged

    belief

    derives, strictly

    linearly,

    from

    the

    support

    of

    privileged

    beliefs.

    So

    I

    shall call (PF2)

    the

    'Strong

    Thesis

    of One-Directional

    Justification'.

    (PF1) does

    not entail

    (PF2);

    it

    could be that, though there are

    absolutely

    secure

    beliefs, they

    do not

    serve

    to

    support the

    rest of

    our

    knowledge.

    Neither does

    (PF2),

    by itself, entail (PFI);6

    together

    with

    the

    assumption

    that there

    are

    somejustified beliefs,

    however,

    it

    does.

    The negation of (PF1) is:

    (NPF1)

    No

    beliefs

    are, epistemically,

    absolutely secure.

    I

    shall

    call

    (NPF1)

    'Fallibilism'.

    Like

    'Dogmatism', 'Fallibilism'

    refers

    to

    a

    family

    of

    views,

    rather than

    to

    a

    single thesis.

    While

    each

    form of Fallibilism

    is

    incompatible

    with

    the

    corresponding

    form

    of

    Dogmatism,

    Fallibilism with

    regard

    to

    one concept

    of

    epistemic privilege is compatible with Dogmatism with regard

    to

    another.

    The

    negation

    of

    (PF2) is:

    (NPF2)

    Not all beliefs which

    are justified, but

    not

    absolutely secure, are justified

    wholly by the support

    of

    absolutely

    secure

    beliefs.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    5/16

    146

    SUSANHAACK

    Any theory

    which

    accepts (or

    entails)

    either

    of (NPF1) or

    (NPF2)

    is

    incompatible

    with

    Pure

    Foundationalism

    (a qualifi-

    cation with respectto the kind ofepistemic privilegeconcerned

    is

    understood here).

    By

    'Pure

    Coherentism'

    I

    shall

    mean

    any theory according

    to

    which:

    (NPF1) (Fallibilism)

    (PC1)

    No belief

    is,

    in and

    of

    itself, epistemically more

    secure

    than

    any

    other

    and:

    (PC2) Any

    belief that

    is

    justified

    is

    justified wholly in

    virtue of

    its

    belonging

    to

    some set

    of beliefs which has

    certain

    properties

    (consistency, comprehensiveness).

    I will call

    (PC1) 'Epistemic Egalitarianism'.

    Like

    'Dogmatism'

    and 'Fallibilism', 'Epistemic Egalitarianism'refers to a classof

    views, differing

    with

    respect

    to

    the

    particular interpretation

    given

    to

    'epistemically

    secure'.

    I will call

    (PC2)

    the 'Thesis

    of Mutual

    Justification'.

    It is

    necessary

    to

    stipulate

    Fallibilism, separately,

    as a

    characteristic

    thesis

    of Pure

    Coherentism,

    because

    Epistemic

    Egalitarianism

    s

    compatible,

    strictly speaking,

    with

    Dogmatism

    as

    well as

    Fallibilism

    (but

    on the

    Dogmatist assumption

    that

    some beliefs

    are

    absolutely

    secure, Epistemic Egalitarianism

    would

    lhave

    the

    very peculiar consequence

    that

    all beliefs

    are

    absolutely secure). However,

    Fallibilism with

    respect

    o

    warrant-

    orientedprivilege

    s

    actually

    a

    consequence

    of

    the Thesis of

    Mutual

    Justification,

    since if

    all

    justified

    beliefs

    get

    their

    justification in

    the

    same

    way, purely by

    means

    of

    mutual

    support, none are

    privileged

    with

    regard

    to

    justification.

    It is obviousthatPureCoherentism,asI havecharacterised t,

    is

    incompatible

    with

    Pure

    Foundationalism.

    For, first,

    it is

    committed

    to

    Fallibilism.

    And,

    second,

    on

    the

    assumption

    that

    there are

    justified beliefs, (PC2)

    entails

    (NPF2); indeed,

    that

    all

    justified

    beliefs

    are

    justified wholly by

    mutual

    support

    entails

    not just

    that

    not

    all,

    but that no

    beliefs are

    justified

    in

    the way

    claimed

    by (PF2).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    6/16

    THEORIES

    OF

    KNOWLEDGE:

    AN ANALYTIC FRAMEWORK

    147

    In fact Pure

    Coherentism,

    as this

    suggests,

    is a

    particularly

    strong

    rival

    of

    Pure

    Foundationalism.

    For, first,

    it

    rejects

    both

    he

    characteristictheses of Pure Foundationalism.And, second, its

    denial of each characteristicthesis of Pure

    Foundationalism

    is as

    strong

    a denial

    as it could be: not

    only

    are there no beliefs

    which

    are

    epistemically

    privileged,

    there

    aren't even

    any

    beliefs

    which

    are at least

    epistemically

    better off than

    others;

    and

    not

    just

    not

    all, but no justified beliefsget theirjustification in

    the

    way

    the

    Pure

    Foundationalist

    claims.

    So we can

    expect

    there

    to be

    other, intermediate kinds of

    theory which are rivals both of Pure Foundationalism and of

    Pure CoherentiSM.8

    Among

    the intermediate

    theories,

    I

    shall

    distinguish

    two

    categories:

    those

    which

    retain

    (PFI)

    but

    reject

    (PF2),

    and those

    which

    (like

    Pure

    Coherentism) reject

    both.

    (Since,

    on the

    assumption

    that there are

    justified beliefs, (PF2)

    entails

    (PF1),

    there are

    no

    (non-sceptical)

    theories

    which

    retain

    (PF2)

    but

    reject (PF1).)

    In the firstcategory fallsthe

    type

    of

    theory

    I

    shall call

    'Impure

    Foundationalism',

    and

    characterise

    as

    holding

    both:

    (PF1) (Dogmatism)

    and:

    (IPF2) All beliefs which are justified but not absolutely

    secure are justified

    at least

    in

    part by the

    support of

    absolutely

    secure

    beliefs;

    some are also

    justified

    in

    part by

    mutual relations of

    support among

    themselves.

    Like the Pure

    Foundationalist,

    the

    Impure

    Foundationalist

    requires

    that

    every

    unprivileged

    but

    justified

    belief derives

    from

    some

    privileged

    belief(s);

    unlike the

    Pure

    Foundationalist,

    however, he does not require that the justification for any

    justified

    but

    unprivileged

    belief

    derive

    exclusively rom

    privileged

    beliefs. For

    this

    reason,

    I

    shall

    call

    (IPF2)

    the

    'Impure Thesis of

    One-Directional

    Justification'

    (or perhaps 'Thesis

    of One-

    Directional Justification with

    Twiddle' would have been more

    perspicuous,

    if

    less

    elegant).

    Impure Foundationalism still allows that

    epistemically

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    7/16

    148

    SUSAN

    HAACK

    privileged beliefs play

    a

    specially

    important

    role in the

    justification

    of other beliefs.

    But there is

    another

    possible type

    of

    position according to which, while there are epistemically

    privileged

    beliefs,

    their

    support

    is not essential to the

    justifica-

    tion

    of

    other

    beliefs:

    (PF1) (Dogmatism)

    (NPF2*)

    No

    beliefs

    which

    arejustified but

    not

    absolutely

    secure

    are

    justified

    even

    in

    part by the support of

    absolutely

    secure beliefs.

    ((NPF2*) is,

    of

    course, incompatible

    with

    (IPF2) as

    well as with

    the stronger (PF2).)

    I

    shall refer

    to this as the 'Idle Epistemic Wheels' view. (I say

    'view' because,

    since

    it is

    characterisedonly negatively,

    it seems

    inappropriate

    to call

    it

    a theory.)

    Theories

    in the second

    category

    (rejecting (PF1) as well as

    (PF2)) deny

    that there are

    any

    absolutely secure beliefs.But

    it

    is

    possible to do this, to be a Fallibilist, without accepting

    Epistemic Egalitarianism.

    Fallibilism is

    quite

    compatible, also,

    with

    the

    thesis that

    some

    beliefs

    are

    more secure

    than others,

    'Epistemic

    Inegalitarianism';

    this

    is:

    (NPC 1)

    Some beliefs

    are,

    in

    and of themselves,

    epistemi-

    cally

    more

    secure

    than

    others.

    I shall

    distinguish

    three

    types

    of

    Inegalitarian intermediate

    theory.

    One

    type

    sees

    justification

    as

    essentiallyone-directional,

    from

    the

    relatively

    secure

    to the

    relatively insecure.

    I

    will referto

    this

    as 'Weak

    Foundationalism',

    and

    characterise

    it

    as the

    conjunction

    ofi

    (NPF1)

    (Fallibilism)

    (NPCI) (Epistemic Inegalitarianism)

    and:

    (WF2)

    The

    justification

    of less

    secure beliefs always

    depends upon

    the

    support

    of

    more secure

    beliefs, and not

    vice-versa

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    8/16

    THEORIESOF KNOWLEDGE:

    N

    ANALYTIC

    FRAMEWORK

    149

    which

    I

    shall call (noting

    that

    (PF2) implies (WF2), but not vice-

    versa)

    the 'Weak Thesis of

    One-Directional Justification'.

    The two other types of Inegalitarian theory reject this linear

    conception

    of

    justification,

    seeing

    it

    as, rather,

    a matter of

    mutual

    support.

    The difference between them is that

    one,

    like

    Pure Coherentism, requires

    that

    justification

    be

    wholly a

    matter

    of relations

    among

    beliefs, while the other, like

    Foundationalist

    theories,

    does not. The first

    type

    I shall call 'Weak

    Coherentism',

    and characterise

    as

    the

    conjunction of:

    (NPF1) (Fallibilism)

    (NPC1) (Epistemic Inegalitarianism)

    and:

    (WC2) Any

    belief that

    is

    justified

    is

    justified wholly

    in

    virtue

    of

    its

    relations

    to

    other

    beliefs,

    the

    justification of

    more secure

    beliefs

    possibly depending upon

    the

    support

    of

    less secure

    beliefs,

    as

    well as vice-versa

    which

    I

    shall call

    the 'Thesis

    of

    Weighted

    MutualJustification'.

    The last

    type

    of

    theory

    to

    be

    characterised is,

    as

    it

    were,

    intermediate

    between Weak Foundationalism

    and

    Weak Co-

    herentism,

    so

    I

    shall call

    it

    'Foundherentism';

    (NPF1) (Fallibilism)

    (NPC 1) (Epistemic Inegalitarianism)

    and:

    (FH2)

    The

    justification

    of

    more secure beliefs

    may

    depend upon

    the

    support

    of less

    secure

    beliefs, as well as

    vice-versa.

    I will

    refer to

    (FH2)

    as

    'Up-and-Back-ism'. (I note that (WC2)

    implies (FH2),

    but not the other

    way around.)

    My

    classification

    of

    types

    of

    epistemic theory

    is

    not

    exhaustive,

    and

    it is

    exclusive

    only

    in

    a rather

    restricted sense.

    It is not

    exhaustive,

    because the

    types of theory sketched all

    share two

    assumptions:

    that

    we

    do have

    knowledge,

    and

    that

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    9/16

    150

    SUSAN HAACK

    knowledge

    is

    (at least)justified,

    true belief. So

    sceptical theories,

    and

    theories which

    reject

    this kind of definition

    of

    knowledge,

    fall outside its scope.9 (Nor do I claim to have characterised

    every possible type

    of

    theory

    between

    my two extremes, though

    of course

    I

    hope

    I

    have

    characterised

    the

    most

    serious

    options.)

    The classification

    s

    exclusive

    in this

    sense: each of the types of

    theory

    I

    have

    sketched

    is

    incompatible

    with

    each of the others

    with respect to any one conception of epistemic privilege, and

    with respect to the same class of beliefs.

    The former qualification

    is

    needed

    because,

    as

    I

    have

    emphasised, there is more than one conception of epistemic

    privilege (certainty, self-warrant, etc., etc.),

    and

    it

    is

    consistent

    to subscribe to different types

    of

    theory

    with

    respect to different

    conceptions

    of

    epistemic privilege.

    The latter

    qualification

    is needed

    because,

    on the

    assumption

    of,

    for

    example,

    a radical distinction between

    logical

    and

    empirical knowledge,

    it would be consistent to subscribe to

    one

    type

    of

    theory

    with

    regard

    to the

    one,

    and another with

    regard

    to

    the other.

    It

    might

    be

    useful,

    in

    view

    of

    this,

    to

    distinguish

    between

    local

    and

    global epistemic

    theories-the latter

    but not the

    former

    aspiring

    to

    apply

    to all human

    knowledge.

    And with

    this

    distinction

    in

    hand,

    it would

    be

    possible

    to

    characterise

    'Contextualism ?

    as

    a form

    of

    local

    foundationalism: withina

    context

    'form

    of

    life', society

    or

    whatever)

    there are

    privileged

    beliefs and

    justification

    is

    one-directional.

    II

    Perhaps

    Pure

    Foundationalism and Pure Coherentism, as I

    have characterised

    them,

    are so

    extreme

    that no philosopher has

    ever

    seriously

    held either

    position.

    But the

    extreme theories are

    nonetheless

    important

    to

    an

    understanding of the arguments

    traditionally deployed in the debate between 'foundationalism'

    and 'coherentism'.

    (This

    debate

    has,

    of

    course, been conducted

    without benefit of the scheme

    of classification

    I

    have just offered;

    so,

    in

    what

    follows, my

    use of the

    terms 'foundationalism' (with a

    small

    'f)

    and 'coherentism'

    (with a small 'c') should not be

    understood as

    presupposing

    that

    scheme.)

    Unless

    foundationalism

    is

    true,

    its

    sympathisers sometimes

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    10/16

    IDLE WHEELS VIEW

    SCEPTICISM

    (PF1) Dogmatism

    NON-JUSTIFICATION

    (NPF2*)

    No beliefs are

    DEFINITIONS

    OF

    justified

    as

    in

    (PF2)

    KNOWLEDGE

    PURE

    IMPURE FOUNDHERENTISM

    W

    FOUNDATIONALISM

    FOUNDATIONALISM

    (NPFI)

    Fallibilism (N

    (PF1) Dogmatism

    (PFI) Dogmatism

    (NPCl) Epitemic (N

    Some

    belief's are

    absolutely

    NPI

    ptei(PC)Esem

    Someurellef

    are

    absotutely

    (IPF2) ImpureThesisof One- Inegalitarianism

    DIrectional

    _ustifica-

    (FH2)

    Up-and-Backism

    So

    (PF2) Strong,

    Thesis

    of

    One-

    hlon

    . .

    tha

    Directional

    Just~fication

    All beliefs

    which are

    justified

    beliefs

    may depend

    on less

    (W

    All

    beliefs

    which

    arejustified

    but not

    absolutely

    secure

    are

    seluebi as well as v

    but

    not

    absolutely

    secure are

    Justifiedat leastin

    part

    by

    the c

    ii

    bustifiewholybotorof spportofabsolutelysec

    An

    justified

    wholly

    by

    support

    of

    support

    of

    absolutely

    securewhlybmualspot

    aboueyscr eiE eiEbsm loi atb

    wh

    absolutely

    secure beliefs

    beliefs;

    some

    also in

    part

    by

    mo

    mutual

    support

    les

    WEAK

    FOUNDATIONALISM

    (NPFI) Fallibilism

    (NPC1) EpistemicEgali-

    larianism

    (WF2)

    Weak Thesis

    of

    One-

    Directional

    ustifica-

    lion

    Justification of less secure

    be-

    liefs

    always depends

    on

    more

    secure, not v-v.

  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    11/16

    152

    SUSAN

    HAACK

    argue,

    there

    is no

    way

    in

    which

    our beliefscould

    bejustified,

    and

    we should have

    no

    knowledge. Foundationalism must

    be

    accepted, because the only alternative is a surrender to

    scepticism.

    I

    will call

    this

    the

    'No

    Tolerable Alternatives

    Argument'.

    Of course,

    the

    argument

    depends upon

    the

    assumption that

    scepticism

    is

    intolerable.

    But I shall leave aside the issues raised

    by

    this

    assumption,

    to concentrate

    on the claim that foundation-

    alism

    is the

    only

    alternative

    to

    scepticism.

    The claim is that foundationalism offers

    the

    only possible

    account of how a person'sbeliefscould bejustified. Suppose, the

    argument goes,

    someone believes

    something

    on the

    basis

    of

    certain other

    things

    he

    believes,

    and that

    he

    holds these beliefs

    on the

    basis

    of certain further beliefs,

    . . .

    and

    so

    on.

    If

    this

    process eventually ends

    with

    beliefs

    which

    do

    not

    themselves

    depend

    on further

    beliefs,

    and

    yet

    which are themselves

    secure,

    the original

    belief can be

    justified.

    But

    not

    otherwise;

    not

    if

    the

    process comes to an end

    with

    'terminal'

    beliefs which are

    insecure,

    or if it does not come to an end at all, but

    goes

    round in

    a

    circle,

    with

    one belief

    supported

    by

    others to

    which,

    in

    turn,

    it

    lends

    support.

    Now, first, the

    sort

    of epistemic privilege

    in

    the terminal

    beliefs

    which is

    called for

    by

    this

    argument must, surely,

    be

    warrant-oriented.

    he

    plausible

    assumption implicit

    in the

    argument

    is

    that

    a person

    cannot

    be

    justified

    in

    believing

    something if he believes it on the basis of somethingelse he isnot

    justified

    in

    believing.

    More particularly,

    second, what

    the

    argument requires s that

    there

    be terminal

    beliefs which are

    justifled,

    but not

    ustifed by the

    supportof

    other

    beliefs.

    For unless the

    process

    of

    justification

    eventually

    reaches

    beliefs which are not

    dependent

    on

    further

    beliefs,

    it has not

    come to an end.

    So

    what the

    No

    Tolerable

    Alternatives

    Argument

    requires

    is

    that there be

    some beliefs

    which are, as I shall say, 'independently warranted'.

    Some foundationalists

    have,

    I

    think, had

    in

    mind

    that

    experiential

    beliefs

    have this status:

    they

    are

    justified,

    not

    by

    the

    support

    of other

    beliefs,

    but

    by experience. Other foundationa-

    lists,

    of

    a

    less

    empiricist11

    tripe, have offered other candidates.

    'Justified,

    but not

    by

    the

    support

    of

    other beliefs'

    is

    how I

    would

    make sense

    of the

    prima

    facie

    rather

    puzzling claim

    that

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    12/16

    THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE: AN ANALYTIC FRAMEWORK

    153

    some

    beliefs are

    'self-justifying'.

    It is also

    a

    possible

    interpreta-

    tion

    of

    the

    suggestion

    that

    some beliefs 'do not stand in

    need of

    justification': they do not need justification by other beliefs,

    since they

    get

    their

    justification

    elsewhere.

    (I

    suspect,however,

    that if, at times, the

    claim

    that

    purely

    experiential beliefs do not

    stand

    in need

    ofjustification

    has

    been meant more

    literally

    than

    this,

    it has been because of a confusion

    between

    an

    experience

    itself,

    and a

    belief

    about

    the

    experience.)

    Beliefs

    which have some other kind of

    epistemic

    privilege,

    but

    are

    not

    independently

    warranted,

    may

    be

    epistemically

    Idle

    Wheels. (I do not want to enter, here, into the very complicated

    considerations involved

    in

    the

    question

    of

    the

    logical relations

    between

    independent

    warrant

    and other

    forms of

    epistemic

    privilege.

    It will

    suffice

    to

    point

    out

    that

    if,

    if

    a

    belief

    is

    independently

    warranted,

    it

    follows

    that

    it

    has some

    other

    type

    of

    epistemic

    privilege,

    the weaker

    type

    of

    privilege is,

    so to

    speak,

    implicitly required

    by

    the No Tolerable

    Alternatives

    Argument;

    but

    if,

    if a belief

    has

    some other

    type

    of

    privilege,

    it

    follows

    that

    it

    is

    independently

    warranted,

    the

    stronger

    type

    of

    epistemic

    privilege

    is

    not

    required, even

    implicitly, by the No

    Tolerable

    Alternatives

    Argument.)

    The

    No

    Tolerable Alternatives

    Argument

    simply

    dismisses

    out

    of hand the

    idea that

    the

    process

    of

    justification

    might 'go

    round

    in

    a circle'.

    Sympathisers

    with

    coherentismmight

    protest

    that

    they propose

    nothing

    so

    crass as

    one

    belief's

    being justified

    by the support of another, which depends on a further

    belief,

    . . .

    which

    depends

    on

    the

    first;

    he

    'mutual

    support' they

    envisage,

    to which the

    foundationalist

    disingenuously

    refers as

    'going

    round

    in

    a

    circle', is,

    rather,

    a

    matter

    of beliefs

    deriving

    their

    justification

    from

    the

    fact

    that

    they

    belong

    to

    a

    suitably

    cohesive and

    comprehensive

    set

    of

    beliefs.

    The

    second

    argument

    I

    want to

    consider

    is

    an

    explicit

    critique

    of this

    proposal.

    The

    coherentist,

    the

    argument

    goes, tries

    to

    give an

    account of

    justification purely in terms of the relationsamong a person's

    beliefs,

    with no

    reference

    to

    anything

    external,

    over

    and

    above

    the

    beliefs themselves. But this

    simply

    cannot

    be

    done;

    for

    no

    such

    internal

    relationswithin a

    set

    of

    beliefs

    could be

    sufficientto

    show them to be

    justified.

    There are

    too

    many

    'coherent'

    belief

    sets,

    and the coherentist

    is

    quite

    unable to

    discriminate

    among

    them.

    (In

    what

    I

    regard

    as

    its

    most

    plausible

    form,

    this

    argument

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    13/16

    154

    SUSAN HAACK

    points out,

    in

    particular,

    that the coherentist has to allow that

    a

    person might bejustified

    in beliefswhich are

    wholly

    disconnected

    from his sensory experience, provided only that they cohere

    internally

    in an

    appropriate way.)

    I will call this the

    'Drunken

    Sailors

    Argument' (justification,

    in the coherentist

    account,

    is

    like

    two

    drunken

    sailors back

    to

    back-what are

    they standing

    on?).

    This makes explicit what,

    as I

    suggested,

    was

    implicit

    in

    the

    No Tolerable

    Alternatives

    Argument:

    that an

    acceptable theory

    of

    justification

    must make

    reference to

    something beyond

    a

    person'sbeliefs.

    Neither a Pure

    nor

    a Weak Coherentist

    theory can allow

    such

    a

    reference.

    Foundationalist and

    Foundherentist

    theories, however, can

    allow

    it;

    and those

    which

    spell

    out the

    notion of

    (absolute

    or

    relative) epistemic privilege

    in

    terms of

    independent warrant

    do, implicitly, appeal

    to

    something

    outside one's

    beliefs.

    Neither of the arguments considered here, however, shows

    that an acceptable theory must admit absolutelyprivileged

    beliefs.

    One may,

    I

    take

    it,

    be more or

    less

    justified

    in

    believing

    something.

    The No Tolerable Alternatives

    Argument

    does not

    establish

    that

    there must be

    terminal beliefs

    which

    are

    absolutely secure,

    in the

    sense of

    completely justified, in-

    dependently

    of

    the

    support

    of

    furtherbeliefs.

    Generally,

    I

    take it,

    justification is,

    so to

    speak,

    'diluted' as

    one

    passes from

    supporting

    beliefs

    to

    the beliefs

    they support;

    I

    mean, that even

    if

    one

    is

    completely justified

    in

    some initial

    beliefs,

    one

    will

    usually

    only

    be

    justified

    to some extent in the

    further

    beliefs

    one holds on

    their basis.

    Now,

    if it

    were

    required

    that in

    order for a belief to

    count as knowledge

    one

    should be completely justified in

    holding it,

    then

    only epistemically privileged

    beliefs

    would

    qualify

    as

    knowledge anyway,

    and

    the

    foundationaliststructure

    ofjustificationwould be simply irrelevant.If,on the otherhand,

    it is

    required only (as seems more plausible) that, in order for a

    belief

    to

    count as

    knowledge, one must have sufficient ustifica-

    tion

    for

    holding it,

    then

    it

    is

    not

    necessary

    or the

    terminal beliefs

    to

    be

    completely justified independently

    of

    the support of other

    beliefs;

    it is

    necessary only

    that

    they

    be

    justified enough to pass

    on sufficient

    justification

    to

    the rest.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    14/16

    THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE: AN

    ANALYTIC

    FRAMEWORK

    155

    And

    it

    would

    be

    sufficient,

    to

    meet the

    Drunken

    Sailors

    Argument, to

    allow

    that there

    are

    some beliefs

    which are at

    least

    partially justified otherwise than by the support of further

    beliefs;

    it is

    not

    necessary

    that

    there

    be beliefs

    which

    are

    completely justified

    in this

    way.

    So if

    these two

    arguments

    are

    accepted,

    they

    leave

    some

    Inegalitarian

    theories

    (Weak

    Foundationalism

    and

    Found-

    herentism) as well

    as the

    Dogmatist

    theories

    (Pure and

    Impure

    Foundationalism)

    in

    the

    field.

    Let me next consider an

    argument

    used

    by

    sympathiserswith

    coherentism.Foundationalism, it is sometimesargued, requires

    there

    to be

    beliefs

    which

    are both

    secure,

    and

    at the

    same

    time

    rich

    enough

    in

    content to

    be

    capable

    of

    supporting

    the rest

    of

    one's

    knowledge.

    But no beliefs

    could

    be

    both

    secure

    enough

    and

    rich

    enough;

    if

    any

    are

    absolutely

    secure,

    it

    can

    only

    be

    because

    they

    have been so

    stripped

    of content

    as to

    take no

    epistemic

    risk,

    and such

    beliefs

    would be

    quite

    incapable

    of

    serving

    as

    the

    foundations for the rest of

    one's

    knowledge.

    I

    shall call

    this

    the

    'Swings and Roundabouts

    Argument'

    (what

    you gain

    on

    the

    swings

    of

    security you

    lose

    on

    the

    roundabouts

    of

    content).

    Though

    it

    is

    vaguer

    than

    one

    would like

    as

    to

    exactly

    what

    the

    relation is

    between

    security

    and

    content, still,

    I

    think, this

    argument

    has

    some

    plausibility

    (especially,

    perhaps,

    in

    view of

    the

    tendency

    for

    foundationalists to

    restrict

    the

    content of

    their

    basic

    beliefs when their

    claim

    to

    security

    is

    under

    threat).

    The

    chief point I want to make about the argumenthere is a simple

    one: that

    it is

    the more

    plausible

    the

    more

    secure the

    privileged

    beliefs are

    supposed

    to

    be,

    and

    the

    greater

    the

    burden

    of

    the

    support

    of

    unprivileged

    beliefs

    they

    are

    supposed

    to

    bear. This

    means that

    it is

    most

    persuasive

    against

    Pure

    Foundationalism,

    which

    requires

    its

    privileged

    beliefs to

    be both

    absolutely

    secure

    and

    wholly responsible

    for

    the

    justification

    of

    other

    beliefs. It is

    not

    quite

    so

    persuasive

    against

    Impure

    Foundationalism,

    which,

    though it requiresits privilegedbeliefsto be absolutelysecure,

    does not

    require

    them to

    be

    quite

    wholly responsible

    for

    the

    support

    of

    other beliefs.

    And it

    need not

    be

    a serious

    threat to

    Weak

    Foundationalism,

    which,

    not

    requiring

    absolute

    security,

    can start with

    more

    content in its

    basic

    beliefs

    than

    either

    the

    Pure or the

    Impure

    forms.

    So,

    of

    the

    types

    of

    theory

    I

    have

    characterised,

    it

    looks as if

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    15/16

    156

    SUSAN

    HAACK

    two-Weak

    Foundationalism

    and

    Foundherentism

    (both:

    with

    respect

    to independent

    warrant)-may

    be able to

    survive

    the

    arguments of both sides in the traditional debate between

    foundationalism

    and

    coherentism.

    Of these

    two

    types

    of

    theory,

    I

    regard

    Foundherentism

    as the

    more

    plausible.

    Central

    among my

    reasonsfor this

    preference

    is that

    this

    kind

    of

    theory

    seemsto me able

    to offer

    a better account

    of the role

    of

    experience

    in

    justification.

    Like

    Quine

    (and

    before

    him, Dewey

    and

    Peirce),

    I

    conceive

    of

    the theoryof knowledgenaturalistically,as centrallyconcerned

    with

    the

    ways

    in which human

    beings

    learn about the world

    by

    means

    of their

    interactions

    with

    it.

    And,

    like

    them,

    I

    think

    of

    experience

    as

    playing

    an

    important

    role

    in

    the

    justification

    of a

    person's

    beliefs.

    The

    human

    subjecthas experiences,

    and

    in the light of those

    experiences

    he

    modifies

    his beliefs.

    Some of his beliefs

    depend

    largely

    upon

    experience,

    some

    largely upon

    other beliefs of

    his.

    But none

    depend

    solely

    on

    experience;

    for the beliefs he

    already

    has

    affect

    what beliefs

    he

    acquires

    as

    a

    result

    of

    experience.

    Weak Foundationalism,

    like

    Foundherentism,

    is

    Inegalitar-

    ian,

    and

    so allows

    that some beliefs

    get more

    of their

    justification

    than others

    from

    experience.

    Weak Foundationa-

    lism,

    again

    like

    Foundherentism,

    is

    Fallibilist,

    and so denies that

    any

    beliefs

    are

    completely

    justified

    by

    experience

    alone. But

    while Foundherentism

    can

    explain

    that

    this

    is

    because even

    beliefs very

    close

    to

    experience depend

    in

    some small measure

    upon

    the

    support

    of

    more

    'theoretical'

    beliefs (e.g.,

    about

    the

    conditions

    of

    perception),

    Weak Foundationalism

    cannot;

    which

    is

    a

    reason

    to

    prefer

    Foundherentism.This, of

    course,

    cuts

    a

    very long story very

    short

    indeed;

    but

    a

    comprehensive

    defense

    of

    Up-and-Back-ism

    is

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of this

    paper.12*

    *

    The final version ol

    this

    paper

    was

    written

    up

    while

    I

    was a

    Visiting

    Fellow

    at the

    Australian National University.

    I

    am

    very grateful

    to

    Howard

    Burdick for

    detailed

    comments on

    a draft.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Wed, 27 Aug 2014 01:14:55 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 theories of knowledge an analytic framework.pdf

    16/16

    THEORIES OF

    KNOWLEDGE: AN

    ANALYTIC

    FRAMEWORK

    157

    NOTES

    'Sosa, E,

    'The

    Raft and the

    Pyramid',

    in MidwestStudies n

    Philosophy, ,

    ed.

    French,

    P. et al., Minnesota UP, p. 3.

    2Sellars,

    W.

    'Empiricism

    and the

    Philosophy

    of

    Mind',

    in

    Science, erception

    ndReality,

    RKP, 1963, p. 170.

    'But

    cf.

    Sosa, op. cit.,

    and

    Pollock, J.,

    'A

    Plethora

    of

    Epistemological Theories', in

    Justification

    nd

    Knowledge,

    d.

    Pappas, G., Reidel, 1979,

    93-113.

    4A

    usage

    I

    derive

    from Peirce.

    5Cf.

    Alston, W. P., 'Varieties of Privileged Access',Americanhilosophical uarterly,,

    1971, 223-41.

    6Taking

    the 'all'

    as

    in the

    predicate

    calculus.

    'In 'Fallibilism and Necessity', Synthese, 1, 1979, 37-63,

    without

    benefit of this

    framework,

    I

    used the term

    'fallibilism'

    to

    refer to

    one member of this family.

    'Any

    Egalitarian theory

    which held that

    all beliefsgot theirjustification

    in

    some other

    way than

    that

    specified by (PC2)

    would

    be

    a rival

    of Pure

    Foundationalism as strong as

    Pure Coherentism;

    but I know of no serious candidate.

    'See e.g., Goldman, A.,

    'A

    Causal

    Theory

    of

    Knowing',

    Journal

    of Philosophy,

    4,

    355-372.

    Popper

    would be another

    example

    of a writer who

    rejects

    the

    justification

    requirement; he is a sceptic with respect to justification, but not with respect to

    knowledge.

    '0See e.g., Wittgenstein, L.,

    On

    Certainty, lackwell, 1969;Annis, D., 'AContextualist

    Theory of Epistemic Justification', American hilosophicalQuarterly, 5, 1978, 213-9.

    I

    would not want

    this

    to

    suggest

    that

    I

    regard

    the

    distinction

    between 'empiricist'

    and 'rationalist'

    approaches

    as

    unproblematic;

    it

    might possibly

    be

    amenable

    to

    a

    treatment roughly analogous

    to the

    one

    I

    have

    employed

    in

    part

    I

    of this paper, with

    approaches according

    to

    which

    all

    knowledge

    derives from

    experience

    at one extreme

    and

    approaches according

    to

    which

    all

    knowledge

    derives from reason at the other.

    12

    I

    have discussed

    this matter in much

    more detail in two unpublished papers,

    'Taking Away the given ' and

    'An

    Empire State Building Made Out of Toothpicks'(a

    critique of C. I. Lewis's Impure Foundationalism).