25
1 THE MADHYAMAKA CONTRIBUTION TO SKEPTICISM Georges Dreyfus Williams College and Jay L Garfield Smith College Harvard Divinity School Central University of Tibetan Studies University of Melbourne Introduction Skepticism is often seen as a specifically Western development. In this essay, we will show that this ethnocentric attitude is seriously mistaken. Skepticism was alive and well in ancient India as well. In fact, it is quite possible that Pyrrho of Elis developed his skepticism in conversation with philosophers in India, and hence that it is that country that should be credited as the fountainhead of the skeptical tradition, and its source may perhaps be in the early Buddhist ideas that gave rise to Madhyamaka. The sayings attributed to Pyrrho by Diogenes Laertius are redolent of Prajñāparamitā language, and at least raise this possibility. 1 In this essay, we argue not simply that skepticism is part of the Indian tradition, but that Madhyamaka skepticism offers important resources for interpreting skepticism and for bringing it into meaningful dialogue with other philosophical positions. The Madhyamaka school was founded by Nāgārjuna, an Indian philosopher (c 2 nd C CE) whose masterwork, the Mulamādhyamikakārikā (Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way, henceforth MMK), revolutionized Indian Buddhist philosophy. Its central claim is that all phenomena are empty (śunya), that is, lack svabhāva. This term has been translated into English in a number of ways: own-being, essence, inherent existence, intrinsic nature, true nature, real existence, substance, thing-in-itself, etc. Although some of us prefer intrinsic nature, the range of options indicates its complex semantic range. The central Madhyamaka insight is that all things lack intrinsic nature: nothing has an essential characteristic in virtue of which it is what it is; nothing exists independently of a manifold of causal relations 1 See C. Beckwith (2015), McEvilly (2012), Kuzminsky (2008) and Garfield (1990).

THE MADHYAMAKA CONTRIBUTION TO SKEPTICISM Georges … · The Madhyamaka school was founded by Nāgārjuna, an Indian philosopher (c 2nd C CE) whose masterwork, the Mulamādhyamikakārikā

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    8

  • Download
    2

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

1

THEMADHYAMAKACONTRIBUTIONTOSKEPTICISMGeorgesDreyfusWilliamsCollege

andJayLGarfieldSmithCollege

HarvardDivinitySchoolCentralUniversityofTibetanStudies

UniversityofMelbourne

Introduction

SkepticismisoftenseenasaspecificallyWesterndevelopment.Inthisessay,we

willshowthatthisethnocentricattitudeisseriouslymistaken.Skepticismwasaliveand

wellinancientIndiaaswell.Infact,itisquitepossiblethatPyrrhoofElisdevelopedhis

skepticisminconversationwithphilosophersinIndia,andhencethatitisthatcountrythat

shouldbecreditedasthefountainheadoftheskepticaltradition,anditssourcemay

perhapsbeintheearlyBuddhistideasthatgaverisetoMadhyamaka.Thesayings

attributedtoPyrrhobyDiogenesLaertiusareredolentofPrajñāparamitālanguage,andat

leastraisethispossibility.1Inthisessay,wearguenotsimplythatskepticismispartofthe

Indiantradition,butthatMadhyamakaskepticismoffersimportantresourcesfor

interpretingskepticismandforbringingitintomeaningfuldialoguewithother

philosophicalpositions.

TheMadhyamakaschoolwasfoundedbyNāgārjuna,anIndianphilosopher(c2ndC

CE)whosemasterwork,theMulamādhyamikakārikā(FundamentalVersesontheMiddle

Way,henceforthMMK),revolutionizedIndianBuddhistphilosophy.Itscentralclaimisthat

allphenomenaareempty(śunya),thatis,lacksvabhāva.Thistermhasbeentranslatedinto

Englishinanumberofways:own-being,essence,inherentexistence,intrinsicnature,true

nature,realexistence,substance,thing-in-itself,etc.Althoughsomeofuspreferintrinsic

nature,therangeofoptionsindicatesitscomplexsemanticrange.ThecentralMadhyamaka

insightisthatallthingslackintrinsicnature:nothinghasanessentialcharacteristicin

virtueofwhichitiswhatitis;nothingexistsindependentlyofamanifoldofcausalrelations

1SeeC.Beckwith(2015),McEvilly(2012),Kuzminsky(2008)andGarfield(1990).

2

andpart-wholerelations;nothinghasanykindofrealitythatdoesnotinsomewaydepend

onconventions.

Thisisbothanontologicalandanepistemologicalclaim.Ontologically,itisthe

claimthatnothinghasintrinsicnature;epistemologicallyitmeansthatwhenweanalyse

phenomenatodeterminewhattheyare,wefindnothing;wecomeupempty.Thislackof

findabilityconcernsthewaythingsare(or,rather,howtheyarenot)butalsoinvolvesour

waysofunderstandingtheworld.Thisepistemicsenseisallthemoreimportantgiventhat

itsrefutationisnotmeanttobejustatheoreticalenterprisebuttoentailacognitive

transformationofthewaysweconceiveofandexperienceourselvesandtheworld,aswe

willseelater.

Nāgārjunaarguesthatitnothinghassvabhāva.Thatis,everythingisemptyof

intrinsicnature.Butwhataboutthelackofsvabhāvaitself,thefactthatphenomenadon’t

haveatruenature?Isthislackoftruenaturetheirtruenature?Isthishowthingsarein

reality,namelythattheylackanytruenature?Andifthisisso,isn’tthistheirtruenature?

Indeed,theΑṣtahaśrika-prajñāparammīta-sūtrasaysthat“allthingshaveonenature—that

is,nonature.”Thisisobviouslyparadoxical.Thisparadox(whichGarfieldandPriest

(2003)call“Nāgārjuna’sParadox”isneitheraccidentaltoNāgārjuna’sphilosophynor

unnoticedintheMadhyamakatradition—ancientandmodern.

Therearemanyresponsestothisparadox,reflectingavarietyofinterpretive

choicesmadebycommentatorsandthecomplexityandambiguitiesofNāgārjuna’scorpus.

Somecommentatorschoosetoembracethemoreparadoxicalandradicallyskeptical

passagesinNāgārjuna’sworks,particularlytheonesconcerningthesislessnessandthe

repudiationofallviews.Othersattempttodefusetheparadoxesandtofindconsistent

readings.Thisistruebothofcanonicalandcontemporarycommentators.(See,

Tsongkhapa(2006),Garfield(2015),GarfieldandPriest(2010),DeguchiGarfieldand

Priest(2008;2013).

Tsongkhapa(1357-1419)presentsanimportantcanonicalnon-skeptical

interpretationofNāgārjuna.Hearguesthattheassertionthatthingslackintrinsicnatureis

meantsimplytounderminethetendencytoreifyrealityandtopresentapositivetheoryof

3

thenatureofthings,viz.,thattheylackintrinsicexistence;thattheyexistaselementsinthe

webofinterconnectedcausesandeffects.(Tsongkhapa2002&2006).Onthis

understanding,theclaimthatemptinessistheultimatetruthisnotmerelytherefusalto

acceptanyintrinsicnature;itisalsotheassertionthatthingsexistinaparticularway.

(Whetheritispossibletoevadeparadoxthiswayisanothermatter,oneaddressedby

DeguchiGarfieldandPriest(2003)andbyGarfieldandPriest(2003)).Thisinterpretation

hastobetakenseriously,for,whileNāgārjuna—atleastaccordingtohisinterpreterswho

followCandarakīrti—usesreductioargumentstodemonstratethathisopponents’

positionsareincoherentbytheirownlights,thisdoesnotprecludehisarguingforhisown

position,namely,thatthingslacksvabhāva.

Ontheotherhand,onamoreskepticalinterpretation,wemightthinkthatthis

realizationcanneverbecashedoutasadefinitiveunderstandingofhowthingsreallyare.

Whenwelookforhowthingsare,wealwayscomeupempty.Wecanneverreachtheir

truenature.Allwhatwecandoistousevariousformulationsthatwillhelpusto

relinquishtheinstinctivecommitmenttotheideathattheremustbeawaythatthings

reallyare,andthisisthefreedomfromviewsrecommendedbytheearlycanon(Majjhima

Nikāya,Sutta72).ThismaybewhatNāgārjunameanswhenhesaysthatemptinessisthe

rejectionofallviews,andthatoneforwhomemptinessbecomesaviewisincurable.(MMK

Xiii.8)Candrakīrtiputsthispointnicelyinhiscommentary,whenhecomparessomeone

accordingtowhomemptinessisthefinalnatureofthingstosomeonewho,whentoldthat

ashopkeeperhasnothingtosell,askstobuysomeofthatnothing.(Prasannapadā83b,

quotedinTsongkhapa2006,p.299)

Whenviewedinthisperspective,webelievethatMadhyamakaisbestunderstood

assimilartoPyrrhonianskepticismratherthanmodernepistemologicalskepticismof

Descartes.(SeeGarfield1990andCowherds2005,chs6and7forasustaineddefenseof

thisposition.)HereweexplorethewaysinwhichtheMadhyamakadoctrineofthetwo

truthscanprovideresourcesforrespondingtosomechallengesthatskepticismfaces.We

thenaskwhichofthetwoprincipalinterpretationsofMadhyamaka—Prāsaṅgikaand

Svātantrika—providesthebestresourcesfortheexplanationoftheutilityofpractical

knowledgewithintheskepticalperspective.Wehopethatthisexplorationgives

4

philosophersinterestedinskepticismareasontolookbeyondGreeceandtoopentheir

eyestotheresourcesprovidedbyMadhyamakafortheskepticaltradition.

Havingnotedthattherearenon-skepticalreadingsofNāgārjuna’sMadhyamaka,we

nowsetthemasidetoexplorewhatwecanlearnfromreadingNāgārjunaasaskeptic.But

weadvisethereadertokeepinmindthatthisisonlyonlyonestrandofMadhyamaka

interpretation.Ontheotherhanditisaveryimportantone,probablyeventhemainone

followedbythemajorityoftraditionalIndianandTibetancommentators,andsoour

attentiontoitisjustified,notonlybyitsphilosophicalimportance,butalsobyits

prominenceintheBuddhisttradition.

1.MadhyamakaandSkepticism

Manycontemporaryphilosophersunderstandbyskepticismthemodernskepticism

introducedbyDescartes:theviewthatweshouldrefusetoassenttoanyclaimofwhichwe

cannotbecertain,andwherecertaintyentailstheeliminationofallpossibilityoferror.This

isverydifferentfromanyformofclassicalskepticism,whetherAcademicorPyrrhonian.It

isbothmorelimitedinitsscope,andmoremethodologicalandtheoretical;Pyrrhonian

skepticismisuniversalinitsreach,andhasprofoundimplicationsforhowweunderstand

ourcognitiverelationtotheworld,includingtoourselves.

Pyrrhonianskepticismhasaverydistinctivestructure,includingbothanegative

andapositivephase.Pyrrhonianskepticismalwayssituatesitselfasakindofmiddlepath

inasubstantivephilosophicaldebate,butamiddlepathofaveryparticularkind,

essentiallyinvolvingthedialecticaldeviceofepochē.Theskeptic,whensheencountersa

debatebetweentwodogmaticextremes—areificationistandanihilistposition—identifies

thesharedpresuppositionatthecoreofthedebate,andrejectsit,suspendingtheentire

debateassenseless.Thissuspensiondoesnotconsistinsaying“maybethissideisright;

maybethatside”;nordoesitinvolvetakingsomekindofcompromiseposition.Instead,it

rejectsbothpositionsnotasfalse,butassenseless,andtheentiredebateasmeaningless,to

besuspended.

Forexample,onemightimagineadebateregardingtheexistenceoftheexternal

world.Thereificationistarguesthatourwaysoftalkingabouttheexternalworld

5

(includingtheassertionoftheexistenceoftheobjectsofperception)arejustifiedbecause

wehavedirectperceptualevidencethatitexists;thenihilistarguesthatnoneofour

evidenceisdirectandallweperceiveareoursensations,andsoourdiscourseaboutthe

externalworldisentirelyunjustified.ThePyrrhonianskepticarguesthatnoneofthis

makesanysense.Shearguesthatdespitethefactthatthereificationistandthenihilist

appeartodisagreecompletely,theyagreeabouttheonlythingthatmatters—thatour

conventionsarejustifiedif,andonlyif,wehavedirectaccesstoanindependentexternal

world.Instead,inamovethatGarfield(1990)hascalledthe“skepticalinversion,”the

skepticarguesthatnothingindependentofourconventionscouldeverjustifythose

conventions,andthatourconventionsthemselvesconstitutetheexternalworldforus;that

thereisnobedrockthatcouldgroundourepistemic,oranyotherpractices.

ThisistightlyboundupwithwhatSextusEmpiricuscalled“theproblemofthe

criterion.”Hearguedthatanyattempttogroundconventioninanindependentreality—

anysearchforepistemicfoundations,foundersontheimpossibilityofsecuringacriterion

forvalidity:ifacriterionisneeded,thenacriterionisneededforthevalidationofthe

criterion,leadingtoacircleortoaregress.

Skepticismsofarseemsentirelynegative,tobethepositionthatwecanneverhave

justificationforwhatwesay,whatwedo,orhowweleadourlives;thatnothingwesayhas

anyground.ThepositivesideofskepticismemergesfromwhatSextuscalled“thefourfold

prescription.”Sextusurgedthattheskepticleadslifeinaccordancewithournatural

instincts;thewaythingsappeartooursenses;thecustomsofourculture;andthe

instructionoftheartsandcrafts.

Holdingtoappearances,then,welivewithoutbeliefsbutinaccordancewiththeordinaryregimenoflife,sincewecannotbewhollyinactive.Andthisordinaryregimenoflifeseemstobefourfold:oneparthastodowiththeguidanceofnature,anotherwiththecompulsionsofthepathé,anotherwiththehandingdownoflawsandcustoms,andafourthwiththeinstructioninartsandcrafts.Nature’sguidanceisthatbywhichwearenaturallycapableofsensationandthought;compulsionofthepathéisthatbywhichhungerdrivesustofoodandthirstmakesusdrink;thehandingdownofcustomsandlawsisthatbywhichweacceptthatpietyintheconductoflifeisgoodandimpietybad;andinstructioninarts

6

andcraftsisthatbywhichwearenotinactiveinwhicheverweacquire.Andwesayallthesethingswithoutbelief(I:23-24).

Thesefourdeterminantsofpracticegiveusallofthejustificationweeverneedor

couldeverhaveforourordinarypractices,includingmoralandscientificdiscourse.The

skepticthinkswegowrongnotwhenwetalk,notwhenweassenttothings,butrather

whenwethinkthatthattalkorassentisgroundedoutsideofhumanconvention.(See

Mates1996,Hallie1985,Garfield1990formoredetailonthestructureofPyrrhonian

skepticism.)

ThereisonelastpointweshouldmakeabouttheclassicalGreekskepticaltradition

beforewereturntoMadhyamaka,andthatisthedistinctionbetweenAcademicand

Pyrrhonianskepticism.ThesewerethetwoskepticalschoolsactiveintheHellenistic

period,andSextus,forgoodreason,defendsthePyrrhonianapproach.Thedifferenceis

this.TheAcademicskeptictakestheargumentsforskepticismitselftobecompelling,and

henceforskepticismtobeclearlywarrantedasanepistemologicalposition.Thismight

appeartobeasradicalasonecouldgetintherefutationofdogmatism.Butitisnot,andit

isanunstablestoppingpoint.ThePyrrhoniangoesonestepfarther,applyingskeptical

argumentsreflexivelytoskepticismitself,andarguingthatskepticalcritiqueandpractice

itselfcanneverbeanymorethanonemorecustom.Ifitdoesbecomemorethanthis,it

becomesonemoredogma.SextususesthemetaphorofalaxativeinOutlinesof

Pyrrhonism:ifthelaxativedoesnotpurgeitselfaswellasthematerialinthebowel,it

becomesonemoredisease.Interestingly,Candrakīrtiquotesexactlythesamemetaphorin

hiscommentaryonxiii.8ofMūlamadhyamakakārikā.Thepassageisdrawnoriginallyfrom

theKaśyapa-parivarta-sūtra.(SeeTsongkhapa2006,p.300.)

WearenotthefirsttolinkMadhyamakaandGreekskepticism.B.K.Matilal,for

example,understandsNāgārjunaasofferingaskepticalargumentagainsthisHindurealist

adversariesandtheirepistemology(Matilal1986:46-68).Matilalarguesthatskeptical

argumentrestsontheproblemofthecriterion.Ourepistemicpracticesarebasedon

criteriarespondingtostandardsofproof.Wedonotjusthaveimpressionsaboutreality

butholdtheseimpressionstobetrueinrelationtosomecriteria,whichinturncanbe

assessedinrelationtosomestandardsofproof.Butthesecriteriabothdemand

7

justificationandcannotbejustifiedindependently;theyhenceshouldberejectedbythe

rationalperson.

IntheIndiancontext,MatilalfindssuchepistemologicalskepticisminNāgārjuna’s

Vigrahavyāvartanī,asustainedcritiqueoftheHindurealist(theNyāya)epistemology

accordingtowhichourepistemicpracticesrequirethesupportofwarrantingepistemic

instruments(pramāṇa).2ForNāgārjuna,thisisimpossiblesinceiteitherbegsthequestion

(presupposingtheverystandardsthatitseekstoestablish)oritleadstoanunacceptable

infiniteregressinwhicheveryappealtosomestandardpresupposesanotherstandardof

justification.ThisispreciselySextus’critiqueofthecriterion.Matilalunderstands

Nāgārjunatoconcludethatitisincoherenttorequireeveryepistemicepisodetobe

supportedbysomewell-establishedmeansofreliablecognition.Weshoulddispensefrom

thisrequirementandrealizethatwedonothavehardcriteriatodistinguishveridicalfrom

non-veridicalcognitions.Nāgārjuna,onthisview,isaskepticalcoherentist.

Nāgārjuna’srefutationraisesanimmediateobjectionfromhisrealistopponent

(Matilal1986,64).Iftherearenowell-establishedmeanstodistinguishreliablefrom

unreliablecognitions,whatisthentheepistemicstatusofthisrefutation?Isititself

reliable?Ifitis,itshouldbesupportedbysomewell-establishedmeansofreliable

cognitioninflagrantcontradictiontotheskepticalthesis.Ifitisnotreliable,whyshould

wegiveitanycredence?Againstthisaccusationthathisrefutationisself-stultifying,

Nāgārjunagivesthisfamousanswer:

IfIhadanyposition,Itherebywouldbeatfault.ButsinceIhavenoposition,Iamnotatfaultatall.3

2Pramāṇaisoftentranslatedas“validcognition,”“epistemicwarrant,”“epistemicinstrument,”“meansofreliablecognition”orsimplyas“reliablecognition.”Wewillusetheterm“epistemicinstrument”whenreferringtopramāṇaasameansofacquiringknowledge,and“epistemicwarrant”totranslatethetermwhenitreferstoavalidatororknowlege.Thesetranslationshavetheadvantageofavoidingjargonwhileatthesametimecapturingthereliabilistviewofknowledge,orrather,itsroughIndianequivalentpramāṇa,thatBuddhistthinkersshare.ForatranslationofNāgārjuna’swork,seeBattacharya(1978,1986).ForadiscussionoftheNyāyaepistemology,seeMatilal(1971)&(1985).SeealsoCowherds(2005)andGarfield(2015).3Någårjuna,VV29quotedbyPatshab(2006):49.Forathoroughexaminationofthisstatement,see.D.Ruegg(2000).AsimilarpointismadeinYSV50-51.SeeScherrer-Schaub(1991):294-296.

8

Atfirstssight,thisparadoxicalanswercanseemaglibwayforNāgārjunatogetout

ofatrickysituation.Thisisinfacthowmanyauthors,traditionalandmodern,have

understoodthisstatement,whichtheyseeasanillustrationofthesophistry(vitanda)that

theyseeasbeingattheheartofhisphilosophy(Robinson1972&Hayes1994).Butthis

dismissalmissesthekeypointmadebyNāgārjuna,forthisispreciselywhereNāgārjunais

clearlyalignedneitherwithmodernnorwithAcademic,butwithPyrrhonianskepticism.

NāgārjunaisnotjustquestioningtheNyāyaclaimsinrelationtowell-establishedstandards

ofproof;heisreflexivelyapplyingtheskepticalargumenttohisownposition,affirming

thatthereisnoconvention-independentArchimedeanepistemicfulcrum,andthathe

claimsnoneforhimself.

Nāgārjuna,thatis,rejectstheveryideaofappealingtoindependentstandardsof

prooftoestablishanything,includingthat.(SeeGarfield1996,2010)Accordingto

Nāgārjuna,Mādhyamikasarenotinthebusinessofdefendingtruepositionsaboutthe

natureofreality.Thisiswhyhesays(MMKXXII:11)

Wedonotassert“Empty.”Nordoweassert“Non-empty.”Weneitherassertbothnorneither.Theyareassertedonlyforthepurposeofdesignation.

Inthispassage,Nāgārjunaisexplicitabouthisskepticism.This“thesislessness,”i.e.,

ofcompletesuspensionofassertionwasalsoclaimedbyPyrrhoinhisremarks,“Iassert

nothing”(I:192-194)“Ihavenoposition”(I:197).

Nāgārjuna’smethodis,however,differentfromthatofPyrrhonism,whichseeksto

reachasuspensionofbeliefbyoutliningtheargumentsforandagainstathesis.The

Madhyamakamethoddoesnotusethismethodofequipollence,butinsteadapplies

reductioargumentstoeachdogmaticposition.Hence,insomeways,itsargumentform

goesfurthertheGreekmethodofequipollence,andwecouldsaythattheMadhyamaka

reductiomethodisagreatcontributiontotheskepticaltradition.Despitethese

differences,itisclearthatPyrrhonianskepticismandMadhyamikadobelongtothesame

skepticalfamily.

9

2.MadhyamakaandtheTwoTruths

IfitistruethattheMādhyamikaskepticaimstorejectallviews(anyoneforwhom

emptinessbecomesaviewisincurable;IprostratetoGautama,thebestofallteachers,who

taughtthesupremeDharmathatleadstotherelinquishingofallviews…)andnotjust

questionthereliabilityofourknowledge,shouldn’tsherejectallviews,eventhose

concerningtransactionalreality,andevenherown?Thisobjectioniswell-knownandhas

beenraisedagainstPyrrhonismanditsfounder,PyrrhoofElis.Thisobjectionraisesan

importantquestion:cantheskeptics’commitmenttothesuspensionofbeliefsavoid

includingthatofbeliefsconcerningeverydaylife?OurthesisisthattheMadhyamaka

schemaofthetwotruthscanexplainhowtheskepticcanrespondtothischallenge.

ThetwotruthsschemeisarticulatedindifferentwaysinthehistoryofBuddhist

philosophy,butitplaysadistinctiveandcentralroleinMadhyamaka.(SeeSiderits1980,

1981,Garfield1995,2015)Nāgārjuna,forinstancesassertsthat

TheBuddha’steachingoftheDharmaIsbasedontwotruths:Atruthofworldlyconvention,Andanultimatetruth.(xxiv.8)

Candrakīrtri,inglossingthisverse,emphasizesthatthetwotruthsreflecttwo

naturesthateveryentityhas—aconventionalnatureasadependentlyoriginated,

perceptibleobjectandultimatenatureasempty.[Madhyamakāvatāra-bhāṣya253a]But

thesetwonatures—althoughtheyaretwonaturesofanobject,aredefinedwithrespectto

theperspectivesofthesubjecttowhomthoseobjectsappear.Conventionaltruthis

constitutedbyourordinaryperceptualandconceptualprocesses,andbyourlinguistic

conventions.Itisthewaythingsareaccordingtoourordinaryexperienceandasconfirmed

byourconventionalinvestigativetechniques,includingscience.Buteventotheextentthat

wegetitrightontheseterms,conventionaltruthisdeceptive:thethingsthatare

conventionalrealappeartousasthoughtheyhaveagreater,adeeperrealitythanthat—

theyappearasconvention-independentrealities.

Infact,however,theyareemptyofthatkindofexistence,andthisistheirultimate

truth.Thisishowtheywouldappeartoanawakenedconsciousness.Formthisstandpoint,

theyhavenoindependentnature;nothingcanbesaidaboutthemexceptthattheyare

10

emptyofanyintrinsicnature,evenofthatemptiness.(SeeGarfield1995,2015,Garfield

andPriest2003.)Thesetwostandpointsenableadistinctionbetweentwosortsof

statements,thosethataretrueconventionallyandthosethatareultimatelytrue.This

distinctioninturnenablesadistinctionbetweentwolevelsofreality:ultimatetruth(the

objectsthatmakeultimatelytruestatementstrue)andconventionaltruth(theobjectsthat

makeconventionallytruestatementsconventionallytrue).

ItmayseemoddinEnglishtocallpotsandpansconventionaltruthsasweareused

tolimittheapplicationoftheconceptoftruthtotruthbearers,entitiessuchas

propositions,statements,sentences,thoughts,etc.TheIndiantraditiondoesnotsharethis

restrictionanduseliberallytheideaoftruth(satya)asreferringtobothstatementandthe

objectsofthestatement.TheSanskritsatmeansrealasmuchasitmeanstrue.So,wecan

thinkofitaspickingupthemeaningoftrueasitoccursinphraseslikeatruefriend,ortrue

coinoftherealm.Itmeanstobenondeceptive(andindeedfalsityisglossedbyNāgārjunain

MMKxiii.2intermsofdeceptiveness).Wecanthusseethecommonuseoftrueasapplying

onlytosentencesorbeliefsasderivativefromthemorebasicuseoftrueascognatewith

trust:thingsaretruetotheextentthatwecantrustthem;totheextentthattheydonot

deceiveus.Ifweunderstandthetermthisway,thereisnothingoddabouttranslatingsatya

astrue.Truesentencesliketruewaterarenon-deceptive;falsesentenceslikethefalse

waterinamiragearedeceptive.

IntheAbhidharma,thedistinctionbetweenthetwotruthsismereological.

Compositephenomenaareconventionaltruths,whereastheirultimatepartless

componentsareultimatetruths.Thisconceptionofthetwotruthsdifferentiatetwoclasses

ofphenomena:thosethathaveacertainamountofsubstantialreality(dravyasat)and

thosethatexistonlyasdesignations(prajñāptisat)orconstructionsonthebasisofreally

existentelements.

TheMadhyamakadoctrineofthetwotruthsisrelatedtothatoftheAbhidharmabut

doesnotinvolveatwo-tierontology.ThedecisivepassageoftheMMKisfoundinthe

XXIVthchapter.NāgārjunarespondstohisAbhidharmaopponent,whoarguesthatifall

thingslacktrueexistenceandeverythingisonlyconventionallyreal,wecannotmake

11

ethicaldistinctionsbetweentheobstaclesthatneetobeabandonedandthevirtuesthat

needtobedeveloped.Againstthischargeofrelativism,Nāgārjunarespondsthatthe

opponenthasfailedtounderstandthescopeoftheMadhyamakaapproach.The

thoroughlydeconstructiveapproachadvocatedbyNāgārjunaconcernsonlyontological

notionssuchascausality,movement,fournobletruths,dependent-arising,etc.Itisan

inquiryintohowthingsreallyareanddoesnotaffectsthepragmaticconceptsthatweuse

indailylife.Thoseareconventionalortransactionaltruths,thatis,theyareonly

conventionallyortransactionallyreal.Theydon’thaveanyrealexistenceoutsideoftheir

beingusedinthepracticeswithoutwhichlifeinthisworldwouldbeimpossible.

Buteventhoughthismightappeartobeareaffirmationofthetwo-tieredapproach

tothetwotruthscharacteristicoftheAbhidharma,afewverseslaterNāgārjunapullsthe

rugoutfromunderthatreadingbyaffirmingtheontologicalidentityofthetwotruths:

“Whateverisdependentoriginationweexplaintobeemptiness.That,beingadependent

designationisitselfthemiddleway.”(xxiv.18)AsTsongkhpaputsit,thetwotruthsare

intensionallydistinct,butextensionallyidentical.UltimatetruthonNāgārjuna’sview

consistsnotinintrinsicallyrealpartlessmomentaryparticlesbutinemptiness(śunayatā),

thatis,theabsenceofanyintrinsicreality.Thislackoftruenatureistheultimatetruth,not

inthesensethatitissomekindofsuper-reality,butinthesensethatitiswhatthe

ontologicalanalysiscomesupagainstultimately:nothing.Hence,ultimatetruthshould

notbehypostatizedintoarealentity,forthelackoftruenatureitselflacksitselfanytrue

nature.Emptinessitselfisempty.Statementsabouttheemptinessofthingsshouldnotbe

understoodasrevealingtheirtruenature,but,rather,asstatementsthattheyhaveno

naturetoberevealed.(SeeGarfield2014)

Manyhavenotedthatthisisparadoxical:emptinessistheultimatenatureofthings

anditistheabsenceofanynature.(GarfieldandPriest).Indiancommentatorswrestled

withthisparadox.Bhāvivekaarguesthatsuchastatementshouldbeunderstood

rhetorically.Itislikesomebodywishingtopreventnoisesaying“quiet”.(Katsura&

Siderits,248)Thisisaperformativeutterancethatismeanttointerveneinpracticeand

thisishowMadhyamakastatementsaboutemptinessbeingtheultimatetruthhavetobe

understood.Theyarenotdescriptionsofhowthingsare,nordotheyrefertosomekindof

12

mysticalabsolute(asitmaybeforaschoollikeVedānta)orarockbottombasisofreality,

asitisfortheAbhidharma.Candrakīrti,ontheotherhand,isamorePyrrhoniangesture,

usesthesimilesoftheshopkeeperwithemptyshelvesandthelaxativetoarguethatwe

shouldunderstandtheseassertionsreflexively,asapplyingtothemselvesaswellas

anythingelse,followingthePyrrhonianmodelofskepticaldiscourse.

Thenotionofconventionaltruthcanbemuchmorecomplexthanthatofthe

ultimatetruth.(SeeCowherds2005,2010).Candrakīrtidevotesagreatdealofhis

philosophicalefforttoexplicatingthisidea.Thisishowheexplainsthetwotruths:

Allthingsbeartwonaturesthroughcorrectandfalseviews.Theobject(viṣaya)ofthosewhoseecorrectlyissaidtobe“reality”(tattva)andtheobjectsofthosewhoseefalseissaidtobe“conventionalexistence”(saṃvṛtisatya).(fromMadhyamakāvatāra-bhāṣya253a,quotedatCowherds205,p.9)

ForMādhyamikas,theconventionalnatureofobjectsdoesnotconsistjustoftheir

beingtheobjectsoftheconventions(agreementsinpractice)weengageinforthesakeof

convenience,astheyareunderstoodbytheAbhidharma.Theirbeingconventionalalso

entailsthattheyaretheobjectsconstructedbythedistortionscreatedbytheignorance

afflictingsentientbeings.Contrarytowhatthenaïverealistbelieves,wedonotseethe

worldasitis;weengageinaconstantconstructionoftherealitiesweencounter.Indoing

so,wesuperimpose(samāropa)intrinsicidentityinsteadofseeingtheworldasawebof

inter-relations.4Thus,conventionalrealitiesaretobethoughtnotjustastheentitieswe

engagewithinpracticaltransactions,theyarealsotheentitiesthatweconstructusingour

innateperceptualandcognitiveapparatus,modulatedbyourculturallyacquiredconcepts

anddispositions,andmistakenlytakentobeobjectsperceiveddirectly,justastheyare

independentlyoftheirmodeofapprehension.

Candrakīrticapturesthiscomplexitywhenhedistinguishesthreemeaningsofthe

termsaṃvṛti.Thetermcanmeandependentarising(pratityasamutpāda)inthesenseof

4TillemansclaimsthatMādhyamikassimplypostulatethatbeingsreifyrealitywithoutofferinganyproof(Tillemans,33).WhetherornotclassicalIndianBuddhistargumentsfortheomnipresenceofreificationarecompelling,however,contemporarycognitivescienceprovidesampleevidencetofillthegaps.

13

mutualdependenceincludingcausal,mereological,andimputationaldependence..Itcan

alsorefertoexistenceinvirtueoftheordinarymundaneconventions(lokavyavahāra)in

whichweengageindailylife,ormoresimply,ordinariness.Thesemeaningsitshareswith

theEnglishwordconventional,giveortakeabit.Butsamvṛticanalsomeanconcealment,

indicatingthefactthatourhabitsofreificationandoftakingwhatweperceivetobegiven

directlytousthroughtransparentperceptualprocessesconcealtherealwayinwhichthey

exist.(Cowherds2005,13;Garfield2015)

Webeganthissectionbysuggestingthatthedoctrineofthetwotruthscansolvea

problemforskepticism:howcantheskepticrespondtothechallengethatherskepticismis

cripplinginthatitpreventsherfromformulatingaconstructiveaccountoftheordinary

worldthatsupportsthedistinctionsnecessarytoordinarylife?Canthedoctrineofthetwo

truthsprovidesuchaprincipledway?Inparticular,doesthedoctrineallowsfora

sufficientlyrobustaccountofconventionaltruthtogroundtherationalityundergirding

ordinarylife?Itistothatquestionthatwenowturn,andwewillexamineitthrougha

doxographicrubricintroducedbyTibetanphilosopherstosystematizecommentarial

debatesinIndiaregardingtheproperunderstandingofMadhyamaka:thedistinction

betweenrangrgyud(Svātantrika/proponentsofindependentarguments)andthal‘gyur

(Prāsaṅgika/wieldersofreductioarguments).

3.SvātantrikaandPrāsaṅgika

Adifferenceamongcommentatorsemergedduringadisputeontheinterpretation

ofNāgārjuna’sMMK.Bhāvivekaarguedthatanearliercommentarywrittenby

Buddhapālitawasafailedcommentaryinthatitdidnotglossargumentspresentedinthe

textasautonomous(svatantra),thatis,probativearguments(prayoga)establishingthe

emptinessofallphenomena.CandrakīrtirespondedbydefendingBuddhapālita,arguing

thatMādhyamikasshouldnotprovideprobativearguments,andcriticizingBhāvivekafor

doingso.Thisessayisnottheplacetoexplorethisextremelycomplexissue.(SeeDreyfus

andMcClintockfordetails.)Hereweemphasizethatthisdifferencealsoconcernswhether

aMādhyamikacanclaimtohavenoviewwhileformulatinganaccountofconventional

truththatrespondstothechallengefacedbytheskeptic.

14

Bhāvivekatakesamoderateapproach,arguingthattheclaimtopositionlessness

cannotbetakenatfacevalue,thatweneedsomewaytomodify,or,atleast,reducethe

scopeoftheapparentlyparadoxicalclaimsoastomakeMadhyamakasafeforphilosophical

discourse.Andhedoessobyappealingtoastrongdistinctionbetweentheultimateand

conventional.Candrakīrtidisagreesvehementlywiththisstrategyandarguesforamore

radicalstancethattakesNāgārjuna’sstatementofthesislessnessmuchmoreliterally.

Tibetancommentatorsseethisdebateasdefiningtwolinesofinterpretationof

Nāgārjuna.FollowingTsongkhapa,theyarguethatthisdifferencedoesnotconcernjustthe

waysinwhichMādhyamikasdeployargumentstoestablishemptinessbuthasalso

importantimplicationsforhowtounderstandthetwotruths.Hence,theyseethis

differenceasseparatingtwosub-schoolsofMadhyamaka:thosewhofollowBhāviveka

accepttheuseofautonomousargumentsinestablishingemptinesstheycallSvātantrikas;

thosewhofollowCandrakīrti’srejectionofthistypeofargumentandwhoofferonly

reductioarguments(prāsaṅga)theycallPrāsaṅgikas.(Nonetheless,althoughtheyagreeon

theimportanceofthisdistinction,Tibetancommentatorsdisagreeonhowtounderstand

thescopeofthisdifferencebetweenSvātantrikasandPrāsaṅgikas(Dreyfus2003).)

Tsongkhapaarguesthatthisdifferenceconcernsnotjustthewaytounderstand

conventionaltruthbutalsohowtounderstandultimatetruth.Hearguesthatthe

SvātantrikaoffersaninferiorinterpretationofMadhyamakawhichdoesnotgofarenough

initsdeconstructionofoursenseofwhatitmeansforsomethingtobereal.Weshould

note,however,thatTsongkhapa’sinterpretationofthePrāsaṅgikaviewraisesimportant

questionsforsomeofhisothercommitments,andinparticularhisendorsementofthe

rationalanalysisoftheultimate(Dreyfus2003).Hence,Tillemansisquiterightincalling

himan“atypicalPrāsaṅgika”.(Tillemans2016,5)Non-GelukthinkerssuchasMipham,

havenoticedthisambiguityandhaverejectedTsongkhapa‘sinterpretationofthe

difference.Fortheseinterpretersthereisnodifferenceintheviewofemptinessbetween

SvātantrikasandPrāsaṅgikas.Thedifferenceonlyconcernsthewayweshouldapproach

thisviewandtheimplicationsthatthishasasfarashowweunderstandwhatitmeansfor

somethingtobeconventionallyreal.

15

AccordingtoSvātantrikas,Mādhyamikasmustdrawaprincipleddistinction

betweenultimateandconventionaltruths.Withoutsuchdistinction,theyargue,

Nāgārjuna’sdialecticdescendsintoanincoherentpositioninwhicheverythingcanbe

equallynegatedoraffirmed,whatTillemanshascalled“thedismalslough”ofrelativism.

(Cowherds2005)Toavoidthisdanger,SvātantrikasrecommendthatNāgārjuna’s

positionlessnessbeunderstoodasconcerningonlytheultimate.Mādhyamikas,theyagree,

shouldnotholdanypositionabouthowthingsareinreality,sinceanyattempttohold

Madhyamakastatementsabouttheultimateisboundtoreifyphenomenabyattributing

themapositiveornegativeintrinsicnature.Therefore,theyargue,thebestthat

Mādhyamikascandoistomakestatementsthatapproximatetheultimatewithoutever

claimingtograspitfully.

This,then,iswhatSvātantrikastakeMadhyamakaargumentstobeallabout:using

theconventionaltobringopponentstoprovisionalconclusionsthatwillleadthemto

understandtheultimate.Thisconceptualunderstandingisnot,however,afullyaccurate

realizationoftheultimatebutmerelyanunderstandingoftheultimatethroughconcepts.

Hence,inasmuchasitistakentobetheultimate,theobjectofrealizationcanbeonlythe

represented,orcategorized,ultimate(rnamgrangspa’idondam).Theactual—non-

represented,non-categorized—ultimate(rnamgrangsmayinpa’idondam)isbeyondthe

reachoflanguageandthought,whichimplicatethedualitiesthataretobetranscendedat

theultimatelevel(Eckel1987,71-75).

TheseSvātantrikaargumentsarebasedontheassumptionthatwhilewecannot

findanyultimateintrinsicnature,wecanstillmakeconventionaldistinctions.Ifweanalyze

thingsastheyaretakenconventionally,wewillfind,inourconventions,enoughresources

todelineatesetsofnecessaryandsufficientconditionsfortheiridentities;ifweaskabout

thenatureofourconventions,wewillfindatsomepointdefiniterulesthatdetermineour

practices.Philosophicalanalysesoftheconventionalworld,onthisview,yieldsresults,

albeitprovisionalones.Thereare,forexample,principleddistinctionsthatcanbemade

betweenwhatisconventionallyrealandwhatiscompletelyimaginedandhencehasno

realitywhatsoever(Eckel1987,75-80).

16

AsMādhyamikas,Svātantrikasdenythatanyofwhatthisconventionalphilosophical

analysisyieldssurvivesultimateanalysis.Thecriteriathatwefindinourconventional

analyses,theyconcede,donotapplytoanythingindependentlyofourpracticesand

schemata;instead,theyareusefulonlywithinthecontextofthesepractices.Forinstance,

whenwesaythatthingsareproducedindependenceofcausesandconditions,wearenot

attemptingtocapturehowthingsreallyare,butmerelydescribehowtheyappeartous.We

arethekindofbeingswhocanonlyorganizeourexperiencesthroughaschemasuchas

causality.Hence,wearejustifiedinclaimingthatthingsareproducedconditionally,but

onlyconventionally,thatis,withinthecontextofourownpracticesandschemata.

PrāsaṅgikasvigorouslyrejectthisSvātantrikapositionasareintroductionthrough

thebackdoorofthenotionoftherealintrinsicnaturethatNāgārjunathrewoutofthefront

door.AccordingtothePrāsaṅgikainterpretation,Madhyamakaisincompatiblewithany

commitmenttotheexistenceofindependenttruthmakersforourassertions.Svātantrikas,

theyargue,eventhoughtheytakethetruthmakerstheyposittobemerelyconventionally

existent,insistthatourordinaryconventionspresumethattheseentitieshavethenatures

thattheydoindependentlyofourconventions,andsoconstituteanindependentstandard

oftruthorfalsity.

ThisisthesenseinwhichPrāsaṅgikaschargeSvātantrikaswithpositingintrinsic

natureconventionally,evenifnotultimately.Prāsaṅgikas,ontheotherhand,arguethat

thisamountstothepresuppositionthattheobjectsofsomestatementsconstitute

standardsfortruthandso,atleastconventionally,haveintrinsic,notrelationalor

dependent,identities.Theyclaimthatthisapparentrationalreconstructionordinary

practiceascribestoordinarypeopleametaphysicalcommitmentneitherrequirednor

presentinoureverydayconventions.(CompareWittgenstein’scritiqueoftheideathatour

useofwordspresupposesthatwehavenecessaryandsufficientconditionsfortheircorrect

applicationinmind.)Thisradicalpositionraisesdeepquestionsaboutconventionaltruth.

WhataretheimplicationsofthePrāsaṅgikaembraceofNāgārjuna’sthesislessnessfor

understandingtheconventional?Shouldn’tonebeabletomakedistinctionswithinthe

realmofconventionaltransactionalrealitybetweentrueandfalsestatements?Shouldn’t

weabletosaythattheaffirmationthattheearthisflatissimplyfalse?

17

Itisherethatinterpretationsdiverge.PatsabNyimadrak,the11thcenturyTibetan

translatorofCandrakīrtiandtheintroducerofhisideasinTibet(Dreyfus2003),rejectsthe

veryideaoftruthintheconventionalrealm.HearguesthattheroleofMadhyamaka

argumentsisnottoestablishtruth—orevenfalsity—butrathersimplytodebunkthenaive

viewthatthingsexistthewaytheyappeartous.TheMadhyamakarefutationoftherealist

is,fromthisperspective,notintendedtoprovidesomehighertruth,buttogetusoutofthe

gameofascribingtruthandfalsity,andtodosowithoutcommittingourselvestoany

standpoint,positiveornegative,onthegroundsthatanycommitmenttotruthandfalsity

aspolarsemanticoppositesleadsustocontradiction.Thus,accordingtoPatsab,eventhe

claimthatallphenomenaareemptyisnotaconclusion,evenonederivedfromthe

contradictionsentailedbytheiropponents’viewsthatthingsarenon-empty.

OnPatsab’sview,itismerelyarhetoricalstance,akindofsloganusefulinshowing

opponentsthewaytogetoutofthecontradictionsentailedbytheirowncommitments;the

Mādhyamikadoesn’tevenactuallysaythathehasnoposition,andevenhisprofessionsto

accordwithmundaneconventionaretobedistrusted.Patsabclaimsthatthedoctrineof

thetwotruthsismerelyawaytotakeintoaccountthewaysoftheworldandshouldnot

thoughttohaveanyconstructivephilosophicalvalue.Madhyamakashouldaimfora

completesuspensionoftruthandfalsityandusesconventionsonlyasawaytoleadbeings

outoftheirmiseries.ThisviewisechoedbytheSakyascholarTaktshangLotsawainhis

critiqueofTsongkhapa’suseofreasoningtoinvestigateultimaterealityandof

Tsongkhapa’scommitmenttostandardsoftruthwithinconventionalreality.(SeeGarfield

inpress.)

ButPatsabseemstogetCandrakīrtiwrong(asdoesTaktshang).Candrakīrtidoes

claimthatnoassertionsarepossibleregardingtheintrinsicnatureofthings.Buthedoes

notgoasfarasPatsab:heishappytodistinguishtruthfromfalsitywithinconventional

reality,andinglossingtruthasnondeceptiveness,hearguesthatconventionalphenomena

maydeceiveusregardingtheirultimatenaturewithoutdeceivingusregardingtheir

conventionalnature.(Cowherds2015)Moreimportantly,hedefendsthismethodology

extensivelyandcriticizesBhāvivekaforadvocatingadifferentargumentativemethodology,

theuseofautonomousreasonings(PP12-38)onthegroundsthatBhāviveka’s

18

methodologyreintroducesintrinsicnatureconventionally,andsoseeksastandardoftruth

andfalsitymorerobustthanmereconvention.Hence,hisclaimsandargumentshavetobe

understoodasbeingsomethingmorethanmereslogansorconcessionstotheworld,as

Patsabunderstandthem.

Moreover,Candrakīrtiendorsestheuseofconventionalepistemicinstruments,and

thenormativestatusofconventionalepistemicwarrants.HefaultstheBuddhist

epistemologists,particularlyDignāga,forofferinganoverlypareddownepistemologyand

arguesthatinthesemattersweshouldfollowcommonsenseratherthanarevisionist

epistemologicalprogram.Inthisperspective—onethatechoesSextus’fourfold

prescription—epistemicpracticesarenottoberejected;theyaresimplytobeunderstood

descriptivelyasthewaysweinfactleadourepistemiclives;asconventionstobefollowed,

becausethatishowhumanlifeworks.Onthisview,epistemologyandontologyaremore

anthropologicalthantranscendentalpursuits,revealingourconventionsregardingwhat

wetaketoberealandwhatcountsaswarrant,notanyindependentstandardthatgrounds

orfailstogroundthoseconventions.Hence,CandrakīrtiisquitehappytoaccepttheNyāya

epistemologyasreflectingthewaysinwhichweusetheconceptofknowledgeindailylife.

(SeeCowherds2015andSiderits1980and1981)

Svātantrikasaredistinctivelyunhappywiththisminimalistepistemology.Whileas

Mādhyamikas,theydonotarguethatMadhyamakareasoningscancaptureultimatereality

andprovideatruedepictionofhowthingsreallyare,theydoseektoreininthe

paradoxicalnatureofMadhyamakasoastoresolve,oratleast,attenuatethefundamental

tensionthatisattheheartofthistradition.Theywanttomakesenseofadoctrinethat

claimstoshowthatitmakesnosensetotalkabouthowthingsreallyarepreciselywhile

preservingrobustwaystomaketransactionaldistinctions.AccordingtotheSvātantrikas,

thetensioncanberelievedbyarguingthatMadhyamakareasoningsdonotaimat

providingatruedescriptionofrealitybutasprovidingthemostjustifiablewayofthinking

aboutreality,theonethatisleastmisleadingandmostlikelytofosterahealthyattitude

towardpracticewhilepreservingthepossibilityofprovidingprincipleddistinctions

informingsuchpractice.

19

4.Prasaṅgika,SvātantrikaandSkepticismTheSvātantrikapositionseeksaplaceforconstructivephilosophy,andworriesthat

Prāsaṅgikahaseliminatedanysuchspace.Itdevelopsthisconstructivepositionby

providingarobustdistinctionbetweenthewaysinwhichskepticismoperatesregarding

theultimatetruthandhowitoperatesinthedomainofpracticallife,theconventionaltruth

ortransactionaldomainofobjectsofpracticalinquiry.

IntheIndiancontext,thisrequiresarobustaccountofepistemicwarrantinthe

conventionalrealm.PatsabrejectsthispossibilityentirelybutCandrakīrtidoesnot.The

issuehereconcernswhetheranaccountofconventionaltruthandconventionalepistemic

warrantthatismerelyanthropologicalcanhavesufficientbitetoconstituteandtoexplain

genuinenormativeforce.ForPatsab,noepistemicpracticescansurvivethedeconstructive

Madhyamakaanalysisandhenceitmakesnosensetoattempttodistinguishwarranted

fromunwarrantedepistemicpractices,evenattheconventionallevel.Suchdistinctionis

merelyaconcessiontotheworldwhichtheBuddhistsshouldnotpaytoomuchattention

to.Instead,theyshouldrelyontheonlyvalidsourceofguidance,thewordsofthe

Buddha.CandrakīrtiislessextremeinthatheishappytoaccepttheNyāyacatalog

ofpramāṇasasadescriptionofordinaryepistemicpractices,butherejectstheideathat

this,oranysetofepistemicpracticeshasanythingbeyondcustomtorecommendit.So,he

argues,knowledgeissimplyopinionvalidatedbytheepistemicpracticesacceptedbythe

world.ButaccordingtoSvātantrikas,thisconventionalismdegeneratesintoarelativism

accordingtowhichconventionaltruthiswhatevertheworldaccepts.(SeeCowherds2005,

c.9).Ifthisistobeanadequateepistemology,itmustprovideaprincipledaccountofhow

pragmaticdistinctionscanbepreservedandexplainedthatgoesbeyondmerelysaying

“thisiswhatwedo.”Andindeed,Candrakīrtidoesnotdoso.

Aswenotedabove,Candrakīrti’spositionresemblesthatSextusEmpiricus’account

foundintheFourfoldPrescriptionpresentedinOutlines(hencethekinshiptoskeptical

positionsintheWestadoptedbyHumeandWittgenstein).Sextusaskshowtheskepticisto

livehisskepticism,andrepliesthattheskepticfollowshisappetites,appearances,thelaws

andcustomsofhisculture,andtheinstructionsofthearts.Sextus’deepinsightisthatallof

thisispractice,andnoneofitinvolvescommitmenttodeepthesesaboutthenatureof

20

things.(SeeespeciallyI:18.)Thefourfoldprescription,aswehavenoted,isthepositive

sideofPyrrhonianskepticism,anditisimportanttoSextusthatitispossibletofollowthis

prescriptionwithoutfallingintodogmatism,withoutmakingassertions,intherelevant

sense;withouttakingpositions,intherelevantsense.

Buthowisthispossible?ManyfindSextus’ownaccounttooweaktoprovidea

philosophicallysatisfyinganswertothechallengefacingskepticism.Wearenottoldhow

orwhythisprescriptionistooperate,orwhatitsbenefitsare.Wearealsonottoldhowthe

listismade.Isitexhaustive?Onwhichbasisisitmade?Thisispartofthemotivationfor

the17thand18thcenturyattemptsofBacon,Mandeville,Humeandotherstodefendthe

normativeforceofcustom,astrategywhichremainscontroversial.(SeeGarfield20xx).Can

theSvātantrikaapproachdobetterandprovideamoreprincipledaccountofconventional

truth?The8thcenturyphilosopherJñānagarbhaarguesthatMādhyamikascanmeetthe

challengethatitfacesbymakingadistinctionbetweencorrect(satya)andincorrect

(mithyā)conventionaltruths.Hesays:

Amerething(vastu-mātra),whichisnottobeconfusedwithanythingthatisimaginedandarisesdependently,isnotknownascorrectrelative[truth].(Eckel1987,75).

AccordingtoJñānagarbha,thedistinctionthatcansaveMadhyamakafrom

descendingintorelativismistobefoundonthebasicBuddhistdoctrineofdependent

arising(pratityasamutpāda).Whatweneedtodistinguisharetheappearancesthatare

illusoryaccordingtotheworld(likemirages,theobjectsofdreams,etc.)fromtheonesthat

arecorrect(liketheappearancesoftheheatproducedbyfire).Thoseappearancesare

producedindependenceoncausesandconditions,andhencecanbeestablishedas

conventionallyreal.Inthisway,theMādhyamikacanclaimtohaveprovidedaprincipled

waytopreservetheintegrityoftheobjectsthatourpracticespresupposewithoutreifying

themintohypostatizedentities.

ThiswayofarguingforMadhyamakastartsbytakingtheideaofconventionaltruth

veryseriously.Itisnotjustthewaydeludedbeingsconceiveofreality(asPatsabthinks)

or,even,akindofconcessionthattheskepticmakestoparticipateintheconversation

accordingtotheconventionsoftheworld(asCandrakīrtimaythink),butanarticulationof

21

thepresuppositionsofourpractice.Obviously,suchanarticulationdoesnotaimtoprovide

adescriptionperimpossibleofhowthingsreallyarebutjustofhowweassumethemtobe

whenweengagetheminourpractices.Hence,thisarticulationismerelyconventionaland

istobesetasidewhenweattempttothinkhowthingsreallyare.

Nonetheless,suchastrategymuststartfromtheprovisionalknowledgethatwe

haveoftheworldasassumedbyourpractices.Theworldweexperiencedoesnotexist

outsideofourinterestsandconventions,butisalsonotcompletelydeterminedbythese

considerations.Ourassumptionsaboutrealityarealsolargelydeterminedbyour

embodiedcondition.Weseetheworldofexperienceincertainwaysnotjustbecauseofour

interestsandconventionsbutalsobecauseofthekindoftheperceptualapparatusthatwe

have.Itappearstousthatourexperiencesandtheobjectsoftheworldareproducedin

dependenceoncomplexcausalnexes.Whetherornotoriginationisnotbuiltinthefabric

oftheuniverse,itiscertainlyaubiquitousfeatureoftheworldappearance.Thisiswhy

Jñānagarbhaasserts:[T]hisiswhy[theBuddha’s]teachingisbasedonappearances.”

(Eckel1987,89)Andevenifdependenceoncausalityismerelyofthedomainof

appearance,wearenotfreejusttodispensefromitandestablishedsetsofconventionthat

wouldnegatecausaldependence.

Hence,ourembodiedandtheperceptualapparatusthatthisentailssignificantly

constrainthekindofconventionsthatwecancomeup,andthusoffersabasisfora

principledaccountofconventionaltruthbasedontheconceptofdependentarising,

understoodnotasanontologicalconceptbutasprovidinganaccountofthefundamental

perceptualconstraintsofourexperienceandtheobjectsthattheyyield.

Thisissonotbecausetheobjectsgiveninperceptionexistinrealityjustasthey

appear,butbecausetheyreflectourmostfundamentalmodesofinteractionwiththe

world.ItisonthisbasisthatMādhyamikascanthenproceedtoshowtheirfundamental

pointthatitmakesnosensetothinkofrealityinabstractionofourmodesofinteraction

withtheworld,asifwecouldtaketheviewfromnowhere.Thisconclusionmaynotstrictly

correspondtorealitybutisthebestway,themostusefulandleastdeceptive,wayof

thinkingaboutreality.

22

Onceweadoptthishealthyskepticismtowardanyattempttocharacterizehow

thingsreallyareinabstractionfromourinteractionswiththem,wecometorealizethatall

whatwehavearewhatisprovidedbyourinteractionswiththeworld.OnthisSvātantrika

view,thisiswhatconventionalrealityisabout,andweneedtorealizethatthisisallthat

wehave.Thisdoesnotmean,however,thatouraccountofthislevelofrealityisarbitrary.

Therearewaysinwhichourexperiencesaresignificantlyconstrainedbyourembodiment

andbytheworld.

TheSvātantrikapositionsuggeststhatwemaybewisetostartfromthis

conventionalbasistoshowhowwearejustifiedtogofromtheretothefundamental

Madhyamakainsight.Thissuggestionalsoprovidesaresponsetothechallengefacing

skepticism.Althoughinquiriesintohowthingsexistaretobesuspendedastheyleadto

unsolvablecontradictions,theinvestigationsintohowthingsarewithinthecontextofhow

thingsappeartousaretobewelcomed.Itmaybeimpossibletoestablishahardline

dividingwhichkindofinquiryisallowableandwhichisnot,buttherelianceondependent

arisingdoesprovideaguidelinesufficientlyrobusttorespondtothechallengefacing

skepticism.

Inquiriesbasedoncausality(andinamoderncontextonprobability)canbetaken

asprovidingtheprovisionalbedrocksonwhichtobaseourconventionaldistinctions.Ina

moderncontext,thismeansthatwecantakethewell-establishedscientificfindingsas

basestoestablishthekindofdistinctionsthatweneedtosurviveonthisplanet.Hence,we

donotneedtofearthatskepticismmayunderminetherelianceoncausalorprobabilistic

regularitiesestablishedbyscienceaslongasweunderstandthatalthoughthosearenot

arbitrarytheyarealsonothowthingsareinrealitysincetheyareofthedomainofthe

appearances.

Inthisway,Nāgārjuna’sinsightthatitisimpossibletomakesenseofhowthingsare

inrealityispreservedandmadecompatiblewithamoreconstructiveapproachto

knowledgeingeneralandphilosophyinparticular.ThePrāsaṅgikaprojectofgrounding

everythinginconventionmaybepossible;butthisrequiresanaccountofconvention

sufficientlyrobusttoinducethegenuinenormativitypresupposedbyideassuchastruth

23

andknowledge.Alternatively,theSvātantrikaproject,withitscommitmenttoconventional

intrinsicnaturesmaybeabetterarticulationoftheskepticalprogram,Insettingoutthis

dilemma,theMadhyamakatraditionenrichesourunderstandingofskepticism.And

whicheverway,onegoes,theMadhyamakatraditionindicatesawayofresolvingskeptical

problemsnotanticipatedinWesternskepticalthought.Thesearecontributionsthat

Westernphilosophersinterestedinskepticismshouldtakeseriously.

ReferencesBeckwith,C.(2015)GreekBuddha:Pyrrho’sEncounterwithEarlyBuddhisminCentralAsia.

Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.

Burneyat,M.(1983a)“CanTheSkepticLivehisSkepticism?”inBurneyat,M.TheSkepticalTradition.Berkeley:UniversityofCalifornia,117-148.

Burneyat,M.(1983b)TheSkepticalTradition.Berkeley:UniversityofCalifornia.

Burton,D.(1983)EmptinessAppraised:ACriticalStudyofNāgārjuna’Philosophy.London:Curzon.

Carpenter,A.(2014)IndianBuddhistPhilosophy.Durham:Acumen.Cowherds(2010).Moonshadows:ConventionalTruthinBuddhistPhilosophy(withthe

Cowherds,OxfordUniversityPress.

Deguchi,Y.,J.GarfieldandG.Priest.(2008).“TheWayoftheDialetheist:ContradictionsinBuddhistPhilosophy”(withGrahamPriestandYasuoDeguchi),PhilosophyEastandWest58:3,pp395-402,2008.

Deguchi,Y,J.Garfield,andG.Priest.(2013).“HowWeThinkMādhyamikasThink:ReplytoTillemans,”(withYDeguchiandGPriest),PhilosophyEastandWest63:3,427-436,2013.

Dreyfus,G.(2003)“WouldtheTruePrāsaṅgikaPleaseStand?”Dreyfus,G.&

Dreyfus,G.andJ.Garfield.(2010).“MadhyamakaandClassicalGreekScepticism”,inCowherds,Moonshadows:ConventionalTruthinBuddhistPhilosophy.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress,115-130.

Eckel,D.(1987)Jñānagarbha’sCommentaryontheDistinctionBetweentheTwoTruths.Albany:Suny.

Garfield,J.(1990).“EpochéandSunyatā:ScepticismEastandWest,”PhilosophyEastandWest40,no.3,1990,pp.285-307,

Garfield,J.(1994).“DependentCo-originationandtheEmptinessofEmptiness:WhydidNāgārjunabeginwithCausation?”PhilosophyEastandWest44,1994,pp219-250.

Garfield,J.(1995).FundamentalWisdomoftheMiddleWay:Nāgārjuna'sMūlamadhyamakakārikā.OxfordUniversityPress,NewYork,1995.

24

Garfield,J.(1996).“EmptinessandPositionlessness:DotheMādhyamikaRelinquishallViews?,”JournalofIndianPhilosophyandReligion1,1996,pp1-34.

Garfield,J.(2002).EmptyWords:BuddhistPhilosophyandCross-CulturalInterpretation.OxfordUniversityPress,NewYork.

Garfield,J.(2010).“AuthorityabouttheDeceptive:WhatisTrueaboutConventionalTruth?,”PhilosophyEastandWest60:3,pp341-354(2010.

Garfield.J.(2014).“MadhyamakaisnotNilihism,”inJeelooLiued.,MuchAdoAboutNothing:TheoriesofNothingnessinAsianandWesternPhilosophy.London:Routledge,pp.44-54.

Garfield,J.(2015).EngagingBuddhism:WhyDoesBuddhismMattertoPhilosophy?NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Garfield,J.(20xx).TheConcealedInfluenceofCustom:Hume’sTreatiseFromtheInsideOut.(underreview)

Garfield,J.andG.Priest,(2003).“NāgārjunaandtheLimitsofThought”(withGrahamPriest),PhilosophyEastandWest53:1,2003,pp1-21.

Garfield,J.&VanNorden,B.“IfPhilosophyWon’tDiversify,Let’sCallItWhatItReallyIs”inNewYorkTimes,May112016.

Hallie.M.(1985).SextusEmpiricus:SelectionsfromtheMajorWritingsonScepticism,Man,andGod.Indianapolis:Hackett.

Kuzminski,Adrian.2008.Pyrrhonism:HowtheAncientGreeksReinventedBuddhism.Lanham,MD:LexingtonBooks.

Mates,B.(1996).TheSkepticWay.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Matilal,B.K.(1986)Perception.Oxford:Clarendon.McClintock,S.eds.TheSvātantrikaPrāsaṅgikaDistinction.Boston:Wisdom.

McEvilley,Thomas.2012.TheShapeofAncientThought:ComparativeStudiesinGreekandIndianPhilosophies[eBook].NewYork:AllworthPress.

Newland,G.&Tillemans,T.“AnIntroductiontoConventionalTruth”inTheCowherds.(2011)Moonshadows:ConventionalTruthinBuddhistPhilosophy.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Siderits,M.(1980)“TheMadhyamakaCritiqueofEpistemologyI”inJournalofIndianPhilosophy9:307-335.

Siderits,M.(1981)“TheMadhyamakaCritiqueofEpistemologyII”inJournalofIndianPhilosophy9:121-160.

Siderits,M.&Katsura,S.transl.Nāgārjuna’sMiddleWay:MūlamadhyamakaKārikā.Boston:Wisdom,2013.

Striker,G(1983)“TheTenTropesofAenesedimus”inBurneyat1983b:95-116.Tillemans,T.(2016)HowDoMādhyamikasThink?Boston:Wisdom.

25

Tsongkhapa.(Garfield,G.&Samten,Ngawang,transl.)(2006)OceanofReasoning.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Westerhof,J.(2009)Nāgārjuna’sMadhyamaka:APhilosophicalIntroduction.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.