The Future of Beauty

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    1/30

    The Future of Beauty

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    2/30

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    3/30

    The Future of Beauty

    in Theatre, Literature and the Arts

    Edited by

    Daniel Meyer-Dinkgrfe

    CAMBRIDGE SCHOLARS PRESS

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    4/30

    The Future of Beauty in Theatre, Literature and the Arts, edited by Daniel Meyer-Dinkgrfe

    This book first published 2005 by

    Cambridge Scholars Press

    15 Angerton Gardens, Newcastle, NE5 2JA, UK

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data

    A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

    Copyright 2005 Daniel Meyer-Dinkgrfe and contributors

    All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or

    otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.

    ISBN 1-904303-59-5

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    5/30

    CONTENTS

    Chapter One: John Danvers,

    In Beauty I Walk: Beauty, Nature and the Visual Arts ........................................1

    Chapter Two: Jos Manuel Marrero Henrquez,Poetics of Beauty in a Virtual Millenium............................................................12

    Chapter Three: Amy Ione

    Is Plato's Philosophy Relevant Today?

    Mimesis to Virtual Reality ..................................................................................18

    Chapter Four: Maurizio Vito

    Does Beauty have a future?.................................................................................32

    Chapter Five: Marcus Verhaegh

    A Defense of Kants Beauty Centered Account of Art .......................................45

    Chapter Six: Steve Mason

    On Fractal Logic, and the Fractal Aesthetic ........................................................70

    Chapter Seven: Harold Schweizer

    The Future of the Aesthetic in the Particular:Reflections on Elizabeth Bishop's Poem..........................................................91

    Chapter Eight: Brian Martin

    Corporal Affairs: French Military Fiction

    and Masculine Beauty, 1870-1918 ....................................................................103

    Chapter Nine: Jennifer Walden

    Its extraordinary, how beautiful your skin is ...............................................123

    Chapter Ten: Yana Meerzon

    Hamlet as Beauty ..............................................................................................131

    Chapter Eleven: Daniel Meyer-Dinkgrfe,

    The Future of Beauty in Theatre .......................................................................146

    Chapter Twelve: Sreenath Nair

    Saundarya: the Concept of Beauty in Indian Aesthetics....................................154

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    6/30

    Contentsvi

    List of Contributors ...........................................................................................164

    Index..................................................................................................................167

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    7/30

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

    This collection of essays took its origins as a workshop / panel at the 7 th

    International Conference of ISSEI (International Society for the Study of European

    Ideas), held in Bergen, Norway, in August 2000. Ione, Verhaegh, Mason, Nair and

    Gritzner wrote their chapters specially for the book. Harold Schweizers essay WithSabbath Eyes: The Particular and the Claims of History in Elizabeth Bishops

    Poemwas previously published inJournal of Modern Literature28. 2 (Summer

    2005).

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    8/30

    INTRODUCTION

    Much of what is going on in the arts and in literature is not what I would call

    beautiful. I find the heritage of realism and naturalism of the 19th century

    problematic if it inspires yet another delving into the abyss of human

    psychopathology. To argue with German theatre director Grndgens: it is

    eminently easy to write, direct, and perform in such a way that it is ugly, or that it

    causes a scandal. Grndgens words about the theatre are true also for the other arts

    and literature. This is a personal, subjective view, and there is a problem here,

    which boils down to the catch phrase beauty is in the eyes of the beholder:

    beauty is somehow intangible, very subjective, beyond objective (and that means,scientific) means of gaining knowledge which dominate, and are thus favoured by,the current (western) mind-set.

    This mind-set, however, shows indications of change: in the booming debate on

    human consciousness, for example, an Internet-based seminar, extending over two

    weeks, and generating some 500 pages of text in printout, was specifically devoted

    to establishing ways of dealing scientifically with the subjective realm of the

    emotions, and there is basic research into neurophysiological correlates of beauty

    (i.e., changes of neurophysiological parameters when a subject is shown pictures

    deemed beautiful or not by the experimenters). Research has also shown thatregarding the beauty of faces, universal patterns seem to exist: statistically

    speaking, we tend to agree overall whether a face shown to us at random is

    beautiful or not, independent of our own age, gender, race, culture, etc., or that ofthe individuals on the photos.

    Common sense would suggest that although beauty is predominantly associated

    with things we see, it is not limited to that one sense, or sensual experience

    altogether. We may well describe sounds as beautiful (classical music, for

    example), or the smell or taste of a favourite meal, or the touch of a specific fabric.

    For some of those, most languages have developed more sense-specific terms, sucha delicious for taste, but the ultimate characteristic implied by those terms is the

    same. Intellectual stimulation can be called beautiful, or the creative acts, say, of

    writing a paper, a poem, or play, or of composing, painting, etc. Beyond all those

    manifest objects of beauty, Plato would locate the form of beauty, beauty as such.

    It is beauty itself, of itself, with itself, uniform, and of eternal being. All

    expressions of beauty have part in this form of beauty, and all expressions of

    beauty exist to enable the direct experience of the form of beauty, as the ultimate

    goal. Is Platos philosophy relevant for us today, does it have a role in the future?

    The majority of chapters in this book are based on papers presented at theseventh international conference of ISSEI (International Society for the Study of

    European Ideas), held in Bergen in August 2000. The remit of the panel on The

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    9/30

    Introduction ix

    Future of Beauty in the Arts and Literature was to provide a broad basis for a

    thorough reassessment of the European traditions of beauty in the arts (fine arts,

    performing arts, media arts), and in literature, not as a return to some distant, and

    allegedly ideal past, but as a constructive means of realising the potential of the

    arts for the 21st century.

    John Danvers considers beauty as a mode of engagement, a function of a

    particular kind of relationship between subject and object, rather than as a qualityinherent in particular objects or as a transcendent ideal. His paper comprises two

    parts: the first consists of notes about beauty grounded in the processes and

    structures of experience, perception and nature; the second, employs a more poetic

    discourse to explore similar territory. Instead of stepping back from beauty to

    define or categorise it, Danvers tries to explore qualities of beauty from a close

    vantage point. In a small way he suggests a revisioning of beauty as a mode ofbeing and doing, rather than as an aesthetic category, or mode of passive reception.

    This reconfiguring of the meanings of beauty and the beautiful should be seen as

    arising from his reflections as an art practitioner rather than as a theoretician.

    Jos Manuel Marrero Henriquez provides a brief survey of ideas about

    beauty from Plato via the Romantics to G.M. Hopkins, concluding that there

    should be a new place for beauty in discussing literature, enabled by approaches

    that acknowledge that beauty may never be measurable through scientific

    procedures. Amy Ione takes the discussion of Plato further: she first engages with

    the question of why, despite his own artistry, Plato questioned the value of artisticcontributions. The discussion then counterpoints Platos view with contemporary

    art projects that deal with beauty, emotion, illusory reality and other forms ofdeception. Widening the debate to include not only Plato but also Kant, Maurizio

    Vito first of all provides a very short background about beauty in Platonic and

    Kantian philosophy; he then draws some extreme consequences of that history as it

    developed over the last century, understood from an aesthetical viewpoint. On that

    basis Vito examines some changes beauty has assumed according to how three

    modern artists (Jorge Luis Borges, Marcel Duchamp, and John Cage) managed it;

    this section deals with the peculiar features Music, Literature, and Paintingacquired in the last century, pointing out their new relationships with beauty, and

    asks whether or not it survives. In his defence of the Kantian approach to art ,Marcus Verhaeghargues that good art must be beautiful art, in Kants sense of

    the beautiful. His focus is twofold: showing the roominess involved in Kants

    account of beauty; and suggesting that art which falls outside this extraordinarily

    roomy conception will be tasteless, dull, and awful. This dual project leads him to

    criticize readings of Kant that paint him as offering an overly-formalistic

    aesthetics, such that a Kantian is left unable to explain the artistic value of works

    that violate traditional Western expectation concerning proper sources of aestheticpleasure. He concludes that our positive aesthetic reactions to art-objects can

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    10/30

    Meyer-Dinkgrfex

    always be considered to involve judgments of beauty, where this perspective upon

    the reaction has a definite explanatory power, in that it places the function of art

    within Kants general and quite powerful account of the proper uses of the

    theoretical and moral faculties. Steven Mason describes the complexity of

    enduring works of art in terms of their inherent fractality. Fractal logic is

    epistemologically prior to general rationalization, insofar as it operates beyond

    dichotomous semantics. Thus Mason posits fractal logic as a connexion ofnonlinear processes, a methodology, rather than a theoretical structure to which the

    complexity of natural phenomena is readily attributed. The future of aesthetics, like

    its past, is beset by the problem of presupposition. By exhibiting those

    presuppositions inherent in its very discourse, we can at least begin to articulate

    modes of aesthetical concepualization beyond dichotomous interpretation -

    conceptualization that mirrors the very complexity found in other non/humanrealms. With Harald Schweizers essay, we move from the broad field of the fine

    arts to literature. When the German philosopher Theodor Adorno wrote in one of

    his aphorisms in Minima Moralia: The whole is the false (1974, 50), he

    expressed his increasing disenchantment with the totalitarian claims of what he

    called the moral terrorism of politically motivated art (1990, 98). No gaze

    attains beauty, he adds in another aphorism, that is not accompanied by

    indifference, indeed, almost by contempt, for all that lies outside the object

    contemplated (1974,76). The particular object is dialectically opposed to all that

    lies outside. All that lies outside is the whole that is false. Schweizerdemonstrates that Elizabeth Bishops aesthetic exemplifies both Adornos

    scepticism about totalitarian claims and his advocacy for the particular object.

    Brian Martin writes about the militarization of France between the Franco-

    Prussian War in 1870 and the beginning of the First World War in 1914, which

    produced a new kind of uniform manhood, where every male citizen-soldier

    possessed a strong muscular body and a fierce patriotic loyalty to his comrades and

    nation. But this new military masculinity could neither protect the bodies of French

    soldiers from the ravages of newer and deadlier technologies, nor prevent their

    affections from developing into homosocial intimacies with their fellow soldiers.French literary representation from Zolas La Dbcle to Prousts Le Temps

    retrouv confirms that militarization ironically brings the simultaneous

    development of male beauty and destruction, masculine hatred and love. Attempts

    to clothe the male body in the illusion of muscular strength will not prevent it from

    mutilation and death. Similarly, many men who are trained to kill an enemy will

    displace the horror of such violence onto the desire to love a comrade. Of course,

    these lessons are not new; they can be traced in the French literary tradition back to

    the twelfth-century Chanson de Roland, and in the Western literary tradition back

    to the Iliad. But as the world enters a new period of global violence andmilitarization in this opening decade of the twenty-first century, these lessons and

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    11/30

    Introduction xi

    texts demand repeating and rereading. If not, they will soon be echoed by future

    texts on the destruction of life, beauty, and human relationships by new military

    technologies and even more violent wars.

    Jennifer Walden addresses beauty in film, with reference to touch displacing

    vision in Alain ResnaisHiroshima mon Amour. Marguerite Duras, who wrote the

    screenplay, stated in the scenario to the film, that one of its principal goals is to

    have done with the description of horror by horror, for that has been done by theJapanese themselves, but to make this horror rise again from its ashes by

    incorporating it in a love that will necessarily be special and wonderful, one that

    will be more credible than if it has occurred anywhere else in the world, a place

    that death had notpreserved.

    The final three chapters deal with beauty in theatre. Yana Meerzon focuses on two

    aspects of the 1911 Moscow Art Theatres staging of Hamletdirected by GordonCraig, with Vasily Kachalov as Hamlet, as they came to be the defining

    characteristics of the 1998 Peter SteinsHamlet, presented in Moscow with Evgeny

    Mironov as the protagonist. In both productions, one at the beginning and the other

    at the end of the 20th century, the directorial treatment of the literary text and

    approach to the image of Hamlet reflect thedichotomy of Plato-Aristotelian views

    on beauty in its aesthetic function as beauty of form, and in its ethic function as

    beauty of good.Accordingly, Meerzon considers the aesthetic function of Hamlet

    embodied in the notion of beauty of text, represented by visual effectsin its 1911

    staging and by word as actionin the 1998 one, as Aristotelian. She associates theRussian ethic vision of the figure of Hamlet as a tormented, suffering intellectual,

    going through a spiritual journey in order to set right the time that is out ofjoint, as Platonian. This Hamlets inner journey is the essence of the spiritual

    beauty of each Hamlets stage figure discussed here, from Vasily Kachalov (1911)

    to Evgeny Mironov (1998). Daniel Meyer-Dinkgrfe finally addresses general

    issues concerning the future of beauty in the context of theatre, while Sreenath

    Nair provides am analysis of the origin, development, understanding and

    contemporary practice of the term Saundaryain Indian aesthetics.

    Bibliography

    Adorno, Theodor. W. 1974. Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life.

    Trans. E.F.N. Jephcott. London: New Left Books.

    ---------. 1990. Commitment. In Literature in the Modern World. Ed. Dennis

    Walder. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1990.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    12/30

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    13/30

    CHAPTER ONE

    JOHN DANVERS

    INBEAUTYIWALK:BEAUTY,NATURE AND THE

    VISUAL ARTS

    INTRODUCTION

    In this paper my approach is to consider beauty as a mode of engagement, a

    function of a particular kind of relationship between subject and object, rather than

    as a quality inherent in particular objects or as a transcendent ideal. The paper

    comprises two parts: the first consists of notes about beauty grounded in theprocesses and structures of experience, perception and nature; the second, employs

    a more poetic discourse to explore similar territory. Instead of stepping back from

    beauty to define or categorise it, Im trying to explore qualities of beauty from a

    close vantage point. In a small way Im suggesting a revisioning of beauty as a

    mode of being and doing, rather than as an aesthetic category, or mode of passive

    reception. This reconfiguring of the meanings of beauty and the beautiful should be

    seen as arising from my reflections as an art practitioner rather than as a

    theoretician.

    PART I

    I am very glad, said Aristo laughing, that at last you have come to the proper

    conclusion and that you are satisfied to admire what at first you wanted to

    understand. Take my advice, he added, and let us stop without saying anythingfurther about a thing which continues to exist only because no one can say what it

    is Dominique Bouhours (in Kirwan 1993, 120)

    The history of aesthetics is littered with attempts to rationalise and systematise

    beauty. Most, if not all, have been either misguided or deeply flawed, usually

    because they ignore the ineffable and concrete nature of beauty as an experience.

    Likewise attempts to define beauty have ended in blind alleys, false certainty or

    futility. Most of these attempts have grown out of a reductive search for a universal

    constant or an essence which inevitably tends to reify beauty, freezing a fluid,complex and often fleeting experience.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    14/30

    Chapter One2

    Luc Ferry, inHomo Aestheticus: The Invention of Taste in the Democratic Age

    (1993, 40), emphasises the importance of the irrational and ineffable aspects of

    beauty. He quotes Philanthe: the heart is more ingenious than the mind and

    points to the importance of equivocal metaphors when discussing beauty. The

    resistance of beauty to linguistic analysis is a recurring theme of Ferrys writing

    and he frequently echoes Bouhours advice that we would do well to be satisfied to

    admire what at first we wanted to understand. As Bouhours suggests, the veryexistence of beauty may depend on the fact that no one can say what it is (in

    Kirwan, 1993, 120).

    Developing these ideas of the indefinable nature of beauty James Kirwan

    describes it as a kind of yearning without object, combined with a sense of

    ineffable meaningfulness (1999, 47). Kirwan seems to be making a case for

    beauty as a psychological state, a condition to which we are all prone. While wemay not agree with the romantic love-torn emphasis on yearning, the idea that

    beauty is an ineffable and fleeting experience without a fixed object seems to me to

    make sense and to avoid some of the problems associated with other analyses. For,

    though it may be difficult and probably impossible to define beauty, there is no

    doubt that we can, and do, experience it. And experiences of beauty can be

    described, evoked and investigated. We can also acknowledge that the experiences

    of what we call beauty are energising and revitalising, making us feel, however

    briefly, more alive. These are moments of intense pleasure and vivacity. They have

    autonomous value and they can be reclaimed, remembered and invoked in a waythat is enriching and sometimes poignant. Often there is an unpredictability to

    experiences of beauty. They can rarely be predetermined let alone dictated. Wecant prescribe conditions or experiences of beauty, for ourselves or for others.

    This mix of complexity, unpredictability and life-enhancing power contribute to

    the significance of experiences of beauty, and it is not surprising that we celebrate,

    attempt to engender and reflect on them through the making of art, philosophy,

    literature and performance.

    Instead of discussing the epistemological implications of beauty I propose to

    explore some of its ontological qualities and related issues.

    Beauty and Being

    We have already established that whatever doubts surround particular

    rationalisations or definitions of beauty most of us recognise certain kinds of

    experience signified by the term. The presence of beauty as an experience or mode

    of being is distinctive and memorable even if it is hard or even impossible to pindown. Indeed the experience of beauty could be considered as a non-linguistic or

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    15/30

    Danvers 3

    pre-linguistic mode of being in the phenomenological sense, a concrete resonant

    experience that is ineffable, evanescent and resistant to conceptualisation. As

    Scarry puts it: Beauty causes us to gape and suspend all thought (in Nehamas

    2000, 24). This resistance to objectification and analysis can lead to a sense of

    otherness, and may account for the ideas and metaphors of transcendence often

    introduced into discussions of beauty. Experientially beauty is often characterised

    by, or associated with, a sense of well-being, coherence, wholeness, integration andvibrant equanimity, and in many cases with a feeling of expanded consciousness

    and even liberation from ego or self. Nehamas comments: To find beauty where

    one hadnt seen it before is to look at the world with new eyes, and that is an

    expansion of the self (2000, 24). Our experience of beauty can involve what

    Scarry calls a radical decentring.

    It would be wrong to consider experiences of beauty as primarily aesthetic. Theexperience may, or may not, have an important aesthetic dimension, but it usually

    comprises a multitude of meanings, sensations and ethical dispositions.

    Experiences that are life-denying or detrimental to the quality of living are unlikely

    to be constituent strands of the experience of beauty - which is fundamentally life-

    enhancing. An aestheticism projected on to suffering or poverty, or that has no

    moral dimension, should be distinguished from the view of beauty being explored

    here.

    Some individuals and cultures place particular emphasis on the path of beauty,

    the cultivation of the experience of beauty as a way of healing, establishingwholeness and goodness, and dissolving the linguistic or conceptual boundaries

    between self and non-self, observer and observed, subject and object. Many peoplein their experiencing of beauty have a sense of engagement and participation which

    dissolves boundaries, a fleeting experience of undifferentiated unity. This quality

    may account for the close association between descriptions of mystical

    experience and the descriptive vocabularies of beauty and love.

    The Way of Beauty

    The Navaho place the way of beauty at the centre of their religious life. The

    Night Chant(Rothenberg 1969, 81), one of the most important rituals of the year,

    includes the following passage: In beauty I walk / With beauty before me I walk /

    With beauty behind me I walk / With beauty above me I walk / With beauty above

    & about me I walk / It is finished in beauty / It is finished in beauty. This is both a

    poetic utterance ascribed to Bitahatini, The Visionary, (who was carried off by the

    gods and returned with the rituals and songs that form the Night Chant), and a

    statement of spiritual intent to walk the path of beauty and to cultivate theexperience of beauty, whether as a maker (of songs, dances, food or artefacts), as a

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    16/30

    Chapter One4

    participant in ritual, or as an experiencing being in everyday life. We can trace a

    connection here, in intention if not method or cultural context, with the ideas of

    John Cage and Joseph Beuys to establish the sensibility of the artist as a mode of

    living for everyone in everyday life. Certainly Cage and Beuys were great

    proselytisers for the path of beauty, and both urged us to recognise the importance

    of beauty (viewed in the way that Ive tried to describe here) for an enriched and

    empowered life. Both artists pursued this egalitarian approach, and both werecritical of the exclusivity often associated with beauty as a special experience

    closely linked to the taste of a social/cultural elite. In Cages view beauty can be

    thought of in a more inclusive way as the experience of suchness (tathata),

    things-in-themselves the beauty of the ordinary, the specialness of the everyday.

    Yet always there is the question: are we talking about the experience of beauty

    or the beauty of experience? Ultimately experiencing beauty may be synonymouswith experiencing being itself, something Euripides affirms: For only to be alive

    and to see the light / Is beautiful. Only to see the light, / To see a blade of young

    grass, / Or the grey face of a stone. (in Walker, 1988)

    Beauty and Nature

    Looked at from a slightly different angle the view of beauty being outlined here

    suggests that the ultimate model or template for the beautiful is nature and itsconstituent processes. Cage, paraphrasing Coomaraswamy, suggests that the aim of

    art is to approximate to Nature in her manner of operation. Beauty, as aparticular mode of engagement with reality, is probably wired into us in a

    biological evolutionary sense. Our notions of what (or who!) is beautiful arise from

    the evolutionary reproductive drive to find the best mate with whom to perpetuate

    and strengthen our genetic line. It may be that this is a biological reason for the

    close association between beauty and goodness or truth. This model of beauty is

    rooted in the processes and imperatives of nature. Beauty in this sense is not a

    decorative flourish but a fundamental experience upon which particular culturalideas and forms are built. The fact that experiences of beauty can arise in the most

    unlikely of circumstances (eg. accounts of prisoners, of victims of war, poverty and

    other catastrophes) suggests the centrality of these experiences to our lives. It

    might not be an exaggeration to suggest experiences of beauty are important

    drivers for living, beacons that light our lives and ensure our survival.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    17/30

    Danvers 5

    Beauty and the Beautiful

    Particular attempts to define the beautiful in terms of characteristics or qualities

    of objects are as doomed to failure as attempts to rationalise the experience of

    beauty. If beauty is a kind of experiencing the function of a particular sort ofrelationship between subject and object, which, in its most intense form, burns

    away this duality then it may not be dependent upon particular qualities of

    objects. It is the quality of the mode of attention that is crucial, not the quality of

    the thing or event in the world. This accounts for how we can develop our sensing

    of beauty, how we can cultivate, expand and open out our experience, or,

    conversely, how we can narrow it down. Without exercise of the mode of attentionour capacity to experience beauty can shrink and atrophy.

    So what is the relationship between beauty and the beautiful, between

    experiencing beauty and beauty objectified? First of all Im not sure beauty is, or

    can be, objectified. Beautiful objects and events are objects and events

    associated with experiences of beauty either because theyre considered as likely

    to stimulate such experiences directly, or because theyre likely to evoke, echo or

    bring to mind such experiences less directly (for instance by remembering them).

    Or maybe the distinction should be between those objects that bring beauty to mind

    (directly experienced, remembered or re-presented) and those that remind us ofmoments of beauty lost or no longer experienced. There are also those kinds of

    objects/events that stimulate beauty in others, but not in us. Museums, theatres,galleries and concert halls are full of things that embody or stimulate experiences

    of beauty for others and/or for ourselves.

    Different cultures of beauty arise out of the infinite kinds of experiences of

    beauty. Artefacts within these cultures are associated with these experiences and

    become codified as objects of beauty, even though beauty as an experience

    cannot be objectified. The confusion over this process of encultured objectification

    leads to a false debate about competing qualities or characteristics ofobjects/events/artefacts, when a more productive debate would be about the

    qualities of experience.

    Moments of Beauty

    A few examples are given below to illustrate the specificity of moments of

    beauty embedded within a continuum of experiences.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    18/30

    Chapter One6

    Agnes Martinmakes work from a position as a classicist and idealist. These

    paintings, in my experience, generate the kind of ineffable, vibrant resonance that

    is symptomatic of beauty. With extremely reductive formalism, a narrow chromatic

    range, and repetitious configurations of lines within a usually square pictorial field,

    each painting invites an intense scrutiny that yields a rich array of sensations.

    There is a surprising immediacy to the work. Our sensory systems are activated in

    ways that belie the simplicity of means employed. I experience a kind of confusionof perception that precludes immediate conceptualisation. There is an excitation of

    the senses accompanied by a sense of integration, coherence and fulfilment. It is

    probably no coincidence that the paintings are almost unreproduceable. Martin

    argues eloquently for an essentialist theory of transcendent beauty far removed

    from the case Ive been making. She was very clear about her position: Classicists

    are people that look out with their backs to the world.All art work is aboutbeautythe awareness of perfection. (Haskell 1992, 15) Of course there are many

    who walk into a Martin show and wonder what all the fuss is about! Surrounded by

    low-key variations on a not very interesting theme they are quickly bored,

    perplexed and dissatisfied. The experience of beauty is not a function of the object

    alone it is a vibrant manifestation of particular kinds of relationship and

    interaction.

    In Tree of Life (1977) Bill Viola illuminated an oak tree with a powerful

    spotlight from late afternoon (when it was still light) until several hours after

    sunset. This simple act of drawing attention to one tree out of many, on one day outof many - using a spotlight which has no noticeable effect while the sun is out, but

    becomes a sun as it gets darker all around is recorded in a few memorablephotographs. We attend to the tree as if its on fire. Our peripheral awareness of the

    abstract generality of trees is briefly replaced by a single entity. And the

    illumination makes us aware of the tree as a field of energy and as an organic

    processor of light. The image of the spotlighted tree has great beauty, as has the

    idea of the event.

    Anish Kapoormakes work that arises out of a distinctive fusion of Hinduism,

    phenomenology and European modernism. The works have a tendency to induceperceptual disorientation, to challenge our sense of how we experience space and

    to raise uneasy feelings of doubt about who we are, and how and what we know.

    Kapoor makes use of many sculptural materials in conjunction with chromatically

    saturated dry pigment. We approach dense fields of black or blue, unable to tell

    whether we are gazing at a flat, concave or convex surface. Often, even close-to,

    we cant make out if we are encountering a deep hole or a shallow depression. A

    sense of vertigo often arises a powerful engagement with a void. The complex

    interaction of sometimes ambivalent qualities and responses provides a rich

    generative field within which experiences of beauty can arise.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    19/30

    Danvers 7

    In engaging with the very different works of Cage and Beuys we also

    encounter experiential fields in which beauty arises, often unexpectedly. Within the

    noisy indeterminacy of Cages Fontana Mix we can experience not only the beauty

    of dissonance and diversity but also re-engage with the wider auditory environment

    in a revitalised manner. Likewise many of the drawings of Beuys give rise to a

    beauty of fragmentation, a scratchy kind of beauty that is in stark contrast to the

    experience of a work by Martin or Kapoor. And even in photographic form actionsby Beuys can generate great beauty out of a concatenation of ideas, aspirations,

    materials, iconic and symbolic forms, deployed in surprising but convincing ways.

    Then again there are those who only experience ugly noise in Cage, and histrionic

    melodrama in Beuys. The artists only provide a field of potentiality within which

    we may, or may not, experience beauty.

    PART II

    In Other Words

    Empty & Uncertain Dust in the Light

    Were not certainties or absolutes

    were conditional, improvised,

    speculative fields

    fluid streams

    a dance of

    perception, cognition &

    representation

    appearances in space

    inscribed with history

    a continuum

    of might bes

    experience the world

    encode that experience

    in the world, grounded,

    making sense,

    making ourselves,

    we are smudges

    in a shimmering field

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    20/30

    Chapter One8

    the object is never, is always

    certainty is never always

    we are always, never

    art inhabits self

    weaving & unravelling identity

    making, composing

    scattering

    moments of beauty

    the physicist is where

    beauty happens

    in charged atoms of insight

    ideas & regimes

    changes in perspective & rationality

    small histories of seeing

    - all cast shadows

    & obscure what light there is

    look at experience

    experience experience

    feel gentle chaos

    experience is pure, is dumb wisdom

    world is Lila

    & we are mirageson the horizon

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    21/30

    Danvers 9

    of mind

    agents of self

    trading words

    one minute of stars

    - a lifetime of wonder

    small dazzle of butterflies

    left Neruda dazed

    naming, naming is always

    too much

    drift nets lost

    in a sea of verbs

    forget names, find beauty

    naming maiming

    Meng Chaio wrote:

    beauty too close

    will ruin your

    life

    Kevin Spacey in American Beauty

    showed us how

    yet to aspire

    to beauty

    is to meet the world

    on easy terms

    Cage realised he couldnt change

    the world but he could

    change his outlook on theworld

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    22/30

    Chapter One10

    practice this alchemy

    & know delight

    what can we say of being?only that we are, and that it feels

    like this

    fleeting metaphors of unfolding

    there is a necessity to beauty

    commonplace moments

    ebb & flow of mind

    self-contained transparency of passing ecstasy

    foggy morning & burning bush

    & yet in unknowing

    is revelation

    & there can be no possession

    & no dissection

    Hume speaks of being blind but sure

    what is beautiful strikes me

    I cannot grasp itor predict it

    in mind out of thoughtthere is what is before

    it is somethingelse

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    23/30

    Danvers 11

    we all aspire to the condition of light

    beauty is empty-handed being

    or being

    empty-handed

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Ferry, L. 1993.Homo Aestheticus: The Invention of Taste in the Democratic Age.

    Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Haskell, B. 1992. Agnes Martin. New York: Whitney Museum of AmericanArt/Abrams.

    Kirwan, J. 1999.Beauty. Manchester: Manchester University PressNehamas, A. 2000.Not Rocket Science, London Review of Books, Vol. 22 No. 12,

    22 June 2000

    Rothenberg, J. 1969. Technicians of the Sacred. New York: Anchor Books.

    Scarry, E. 1999. On Beauty and Being Just, reviewed in Nehamas, A. 2000. Not

    Rocket Science, London Review of Books, Vol. 22 No. 12, 22 June 2000

    Walker, R. 1988. Painters in the Australian Landscape. Sydney: Hale and

    Iremonger Pty Ltd.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    24/30

    CHAPTER TWO

    JOS MANUEL MARRERO HENRQUEZ

    POETICS OF BEAUTY IN A VIRTUAL MILLENIUM

    The idea that the true nature of art is intransitive and non instrumental has

    dominated in modern criticism and theory. Carried to its extreme, this conceptionof art allowed Valry to relate poetry to dancing and prose to walking, forwalking, like prose, has a definite aim, [...] it is an act directed at something wewish to reach, while dancing is a secondary use of [...] movement [that] admits ofan infinite number of creations and variations of figures (1958, 70).Considerations similar to these are behind the analytical procedures of the Russianformalists and of the American new critics, and they have formed the base to createa science of literature in which the first postulation is always the same: poeticalfunction is the one that calls attention to the message, as Tzvetan Todorov hasalready pointed out (1982).

    Lyrical poetry is considered the most literary and artistic of the genres ofliterature as a consequence of the decay of the Aristotelian conception of art thatkept mimesis as a fundamental reason to have tragedy as the best and mostexemplary of the genres until the emergence of Romanticism. Renaissance andBaroque efforts of scholars such as Minturno, Escaligero or Cascales to introduce anon-mimetic genre as lyrical poetry within Aristotles Poetics ended updiminishing the power of mimesis to justify what makes a text artistic. On the wayto consider art as an expression of a subject and as a sublime experience, mimeticcriteria lost its authority. Grard Genette (1982) and, most recently, GustavoGuerrero (1998) have shown with great clarity this process of forcedmisinterpretation of AristotlesPoetics.

    During the 18th century a new conception of literariness began to dominate.John Dennis, for example, in The Grounds of Criticism in Poetry(1704), classifiedthe most elevated poetry in the epic, the tragic and the great lyrical, and erasedcenturies of Aristotelianism when he affirmed that a poet ought to contrive everything in order to the moving of Passion, that not only the Fable, the Incidents andCharacters, but the very Sentiments and Expressions, ought all to be designed forthat (1999, 338). And a few years later, Joseph Trapp, in his Lectures on Poetry

    (1711), affirmed, as to the Nature of the Lyrical Poem, it is, of all kinds of Poetry,

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    25/30

    Marrero 13

    the most poetical, and is as distinct, both in Style and Thought from the rest, asPoetry in general is from Prose (1711, 303).

    By the end of the 18thcentury, and with the complicity of one of the ancients,Longinus On the Sublime(first century A.D.), this new conception of literarinessis so powerful that it will become necessary to justify, not the lyrical poetry, butthe Aristotelian theory, for, as William Jones pointed out in On the ArtsCommonly Called Imitative (1772) the assertion of Aristotle that all poetryconsists in imitation [...] has been so frequently echoed from author to author, thatit would seem a kind of arrogance to controvert it (1777, 191). From King Davidto Petrach, Jones considered that the true poetry had always been an expression of

    passions, that the true poetry had always been lyrical, for the finest parts ofpoetry, music and painting are expressiveof thepassionsand operate on our mindsby sympathy [...and] the inferieurs parts of them are descriptiveof natural objectsand affects us chiefly by substitution (1777, 207). Romantic subjectivityexpressing its passions gave way to a new conception of literariness in which theexpression found a reason to be in its own right. By stressing the interplay of wordswithin the page, the subject was left behind, and the text became an autonomousobject of art. Stphane Mallarm, for example, broke with Romantic expressivismand he was also far from considering poetry as imitation. Reality was in the poemitself, it may exist in a piece of paper. Beyond the author, lyrical poetry ledthrough French symbolism to the contemporary idea of the objective nature of the

    poem in much of the twentieth-century criticism.Far from the subject, far from reality, literature has ended up forming a reality

    apart from reality, a virtual reality, and one more virtuality among the virtualrealities humankind has been surrounding itself with. Jean Baudrillard hascommented on this cultural situation as an emptying process of the referentialcontents of the images, from the image that reflects a basic reality to the image thatbears no relation to any reality whatever: [the image that...] is its own puresimulacrum (1988, 170). Reality is at stake, affirms Baudrillard, and abstractionis no longer that of the map, the double, the mirror or the concept [...] it is the

    generation by models of a real without origin or reality: a hyperreal (1988, 166).It is necessary to preserve the abstractions magic to save reality from oblivion.

    For it is the difference between the real and the simulation models what forms thepoetry of the map and the charm of the territory, the magic of the concept and thecharm of the real (1988, 166-67). In a hyperreal environment, reality and poetryneed each other to exist, and bringing the Platonic idea of Beauty back into literarycriticism clearly contributes to the survival of both.

    Perception of Beauty in literature is not a solipsistic act, it depends to a largeextent on the emotive, referential and utilitarian aspects of everyday languages and

    lives, and it was no frivolity that Plato in his Hipias Major linked the idea ofBeauty to the idea of Good, and also to the idea of Will. A worthy space to

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    26/30

    Chapter Two14

    transitivity as an aesthetic category should be open. Entering a new millennium,full of virtual realities, the deep values shaping both Classical rhetoric and theHumanist idea that grew from it deserve the intent.

    If literature is linked to Beauty, its analysis and interpretations have to take intoaccount not only styles, figures and generic structures, but also moral,

    psychological, ideological, historical, political and sentimental factors, all of themdifficult to measure, but without doubt bearers of aesthetic meaning. Theconfluence of agents that take part in the perception of Beauty is so overwhelmingthat Socrates himself failed to define it.

    TheHipias Majordialogue enhances the Socratic search of the idea of Beautythat is present in all things that are perceived as beautiful. But after a long andsubtle conversation, no conclusion is reached; rather, the proverb all that is

    beautiful is difficult is brought to light. That is the result of the inquisition aboutBeauty.

    Located at the end of the Hipias Major, such proverb is not a simpleconsolation, nor is it a frivolous way of hiding an obvious failure, but praise of thewill that any person wishing to reach a certain grade of excellence must have.

    Will is also one of the basic topics in The Symposio, where it appears under thename of Love. Love is the impulse toward the perpetual possession of Good, animpulse different from its own finality but, at the same time, and in the light of

    Hipias Major, part of it. For in Love there are involved intellectual and spiritual

    motives that are far away from the mere physical beauty of things, and close to thebeauty that exists in sublime activities, institutions, feelings and ideas.

    Will (or Love) is the impulse, and Beauty (or Good) its final goal. Will is thereflection of Beauty that is in any human being that is seriously engaged in theapprehension of the Ideas. Apprehending and searching are beautiful actions withethical and moral consequences, for they contribute to the healthy development oftheRepublic.

    In 1865 G. M. Hopkins wrote a platonic dialogue devoted to the idea of Beauty.Here it is not a proverb that forms the resigned final solution to the enigma. In

    contrast to Socrates, the master in Hopkins dialogue succeeds in describing someof the characteristics of the beautiful objects of nature and the arts. Features suchas numerical symmetry of elements, or gradation in colours, define Beauty. Themaster goes on from symmetry to regularity, from regularity to irregularity andtheir combination, to conclude that Beauty results in a relation, and its perceptionimplies the apprehension of a comparison. In brief, Beauty involves the idea ofelements in harmony in the frame of a composition.

    However, none of the speakers in the dialogue is satisfied with the abstractionsthat the master uses to expose what the nature of Beauty and the conditions of its

    perception are. Criticism, particularly that of poetry, cannot be judicial --degustibus non est disputandum-- nor should it be reduced by logic or common sense.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    27/30

    Marrero 15

    There is a plus, a mystical plus located beyond poetry considered as amathematical thing, measured by compasses, that keeps awaitingcomprehension. Questioned about this plus, the master calls the attention of thespeakers to the tea, and all of them enter to have a cup. That is the end of thedialogue. This plus keeps reverberating as an interrogation. Hopkins called itmystical, but it could have also been called lyrical, transcendent,symbolic; and, if following Socrates moral approach to Beauty, it could havealso been called engaged, social or realist.

    If related to the nature and perception of Beauty, Valrys opposition betweendancing and walking, poetry and prose, Jones opposition between thesuperior expression of passions that operates by sympathy and the inferiordescription of natural objects that operates by substitution, Mallarms opposition

    between the piece of paper and the world, and the oppositions between thewords mystical, lyrical, transcendent, symbolic, poetical and the wordsmaterialist, comic, determinist, realist, prosaic vanish. Perception ofBeauty in literature is influenced by such a multitude of factors and of such variedand obscure affiliations, that any literary criticism with scientific goals has no otherchoice than to ignore Beauty or dump it in a dark shed with all that offersresistance to be measured.

    As a beautiful experience, the experience of literature is an inexplicablephenomenon, far more complex than any intent to reduce it to any mystical,

    structural, symbolic, realist or engag approach. Lyrical experience of literatureitself is beyond the so called lyrical genres and the structural and stylistics featuresof lyricism. And social experience of literature is beyond the narrative genres andthe structural and stylistic features of Realism. As much as it is an obstacle to anyscientific enquiry about literature, Beauty is also an obstacle to any theory ofinterpretation that bases the literary prestige of texts exclusively on their higheranagogical interpretations. Reasons enough had Socrates to link the idea of Beautyin the forms of handicrafts, nature, feelings and institutions to the idea of Good,and also to the ideas of Will and Love.

    Nothing should be an obstacle in reorienting literary criticism to the possibilityof opening an honourable space to transitivity as an aesthetic category. For in anywriting there is an aesthetic motivation that can be understood as the unavoidabletransitivity by means of which writing refers to itself while referring to the world.It could also be affirmed that in writing there is nothing but transitivity, a directone, the one that by saying of the world says of itself, and an indirect one, the onethat by saying of itself says of the world. It could even be affirmed, taken suchcontradiction to an extreme, that whenever a text says more of itself it is sayingmore of the world, and when it says more of the world, more it is saying of itself.

    At orienting the message on the emissary letting the receiver know about him,poetical function cannot avoid being emotive, nor can it avoid being connative

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    28/30

    Chapter Two16

    when orienting the message on the receiver implying him in the message, norreferential, when orienting the message on the reality, nor phatic, when orientingthe message on the canal of transmission (purifying it of noises), normetalinguistic, when orienting the message on the code to clarify its peculiar rules.If poetic function is understood this beautiful way, criticism, that can do little morethan concentrating its attention on the text, has no obligation to dissociate languagefrom its human condition to satisfy the necessity of having an object of linguisticresearch, nor has it to assume such a plain consideration of literature that makes ofthe texts not objects of beauty, consolation, pleasure, commitment, evasion ormeditation, but lab entities or bones to apply carbon-14 dating.

    Beauty and Will are unstable concepts and both have been ruled out of theworks that intend to determine textual and human behaviours. But if being humanis a linguistic condition more than a biological or zoological one, Beauty and Willmust go hand in hand in an aesthetics of transitivity, since transitivity meanscritically linking literature with its human condition to constantly remind thatlanguage, once emptied of its human content, is merely senseless jangle in a void.

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Aristteles. 1981.El Arte Potica. Mxico: Espasa Calpe.Baudrillard, J. 1988. Selected Writings. Poster, Mark (ed.). California:

    Stanford University Press.Dennis, J. 1939. Critical Works. Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press.Genette, G. 1982.Figures of Literary Discourse. New York: Columbia University

    Press.Guerrero, G. 1998. Teoras de la lrica. Mxico: Fondo de Cultura Econmica.Hopkins, G. M. 1985. On the Origin of Beauty: A Platonic Dialogue.Poems and

    Prose. London: Penguin Books, 92-104.Jones, W. 1777. On the Arts Commonly Called Imitative. Poems Consisting

    Chiefly of Translations from Asiatick Languages. London: W. Boyer and J.Nichols.

    Mallarm, S. 1956. The Book: A Spiritual Instrument.Mallarm: selected Prose,Poems, Essays, and Letters. Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press.

    Platn. 1986.Dilogos I. Apologa. Critn. Eutifrn. In. Lisis. Crmides. HipiasMenor. Hipias Mayor. Laques. Protgoras.Madrid: Editorial Gredos.

    ---. 1989.Dilogos III. Fedn, Banquete, Fedro.Madrid: Editorial Gredos.Todorov, T. 1982. The Poetics of Prose. Ithaca and London: Cornell University

    Press.Trapp, J. 1747.Lectures on Poetry. London: Printed for C. Hitch and C. Davis

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    29/30

    Marrero 17

    Valry, P. 1958. The Collected Works of Paul Valry. Vol. vii. Princeton:Princeton University Press.

  • 8/13/2019 The Future of Beauty

    30/30

    CHAPTER THREE

    AMY IONE

    IS PLATO'S PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TODAY?

    MIMESIS TO VIRTUAL REALITY

    [i]f one attempted to belittle the arts by saying that, in creating, they imitate nature,the answer should be that . . . the arts create many things by themselves. Where

    something is lacking, they supply it, because they own beauty.

    Plotinus, The Enneads(Plotinus, 1991, V: 8. 1)

    PLATO'S VIEW OF ART

    The late dean of art history, E.H. Gombrich began his last book, The Preference

    for the Primitive, with the thought:

    The well-known dictum by the philosopher Alfred N. Whitehead, that the whole

    history of Western philosophy is but a series of footnotes to the writings of Plato,

    applies with special force to the philosophy of the arts . . . [Plato believed that] art

    can only flatter and deceive the senses and seduce the mind to feed on phantoms.

    (2001, 11)

    Gombrich's words are particularly thought provoking when we consider whether

    Plato is relevant today. Popular culture abounds with references to Plato's writings,

    elevating connections far beyond the philosophy of the arts per se. Paralleling thetwo domains it is worth noting that contemporary testaments to Plato's influence

    have a propensity to misrepresent some of his primary philosophical concerns. For

    example, in the early 1990s Dan Sandin, Thomas DeFanti, and Carolina Cruz-

    Neira introduced an immersive environment technology they termed the CAVE.

    Their 1993 article "A Room with a View," explains that the CAVE acronym,which stands for Cave Automatic Virtual Environment, is intended as an illusion to

    the Allegory of the Cave found in Plato's Republic. According to this article, "the

    Greek philosopher explored the ideas of perception, reality, and illusion using the

    analogy of a person facing the back of a cave alive with shadows that are his onlybasis for his ideas of what real objects are." (Sandin 2001, 268). Their summation,