The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    1/35

    THE BEHAVIORAL REVOLUTION? A GENEALOGY OF A CONCEPT

    Josh BerkenpasWestern Michigan University

    ABSTRACT

    For this article, I ask the question where is the behavioral revolution? My aim is to

    illuminate the discursive evolution of the behavioral revolution in American political

    science through a non -rhetorical history of the behavioral revolution (Schmidt 1998,

    11). I examine the way the analytic construct of the behavioral revolution evolved in the

    discourse of the discipline over time. I begin with an illustrative example drawn from

    contemporary reference material and then turn to an analysis of the writing of

    behavioralists authors in the 1950s and early 1960s: Robert Dahl, Heinz Eulau, and David

    Easton. I then discuss the emergence of the behavioral revolution in the discourse of the

    discipline more generally and contrast a proponent of behavioralism (Easton 1968) with

    a critic (Wolin 1969). I end the article with a discussion of the way that contemporary

    disciplinary historians understand the behavioral revolution. While the importance of the

    concept of the behavioral revolution is shown to be ongoing, the origin of the

    conventional use of the behavioral revolution is traced to the late 1960s.

    SEARCHING FOR THE BEHAVIORAL REVOLUTION

    In this article, I ask the question Where is the Behavioral Revolution? Not wither the

    behavioral revolution, but where did it first appear and subsequently proliferate in the discourse of

    the discipline? The debate continues over the precise origins of behavioralism in political science.

    As the disciplinary historian John Gunnell points out in the Oxford Handbook of Political Ideology ,

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    2/35

    2

    it would be difficult to determine when the first shot was fired in what came to be called, by all

    parties, the behavioral revolution (2013 a, 82; see also 2013b, 191). A common understanding

    of the behavioral revolution is found in another contemporary reference work. The political

    scientist Clyde Barrows entry on Political S cience in the International Encyclopedia of Social

    Sciences summarizes the history of the discipline. B arrow states that during the 1920s, political

    science began a paradigm shift that culminated in the behavioral revolution of the 1950s (2008,

    312). The mention of the behavioral revolution is immediately placed in the context of a

    transformation in the disciplines understanding of the scientific enterprise, which made the

    science in political science positivist in the sense that political scientists increasingly came to believe that there is a single scientific method that starts with the formulation of a hypothesis,

    followed by empirical observation or experimentation, which leads to falsification or verification

    of the initial hypothesis (312).

    By the 1950s, the positivist movement had culminated in the rise of behavioralism and the

    behavioral revolution in political science. This revolution is considered by Barrow to be a

    Kuhnian scientific revolution (312). Following the publication of Kuhns The Structure of

    Scientific Revolutions in 1962 it quickly became de rigueur in American political science to speak

    of the history of the discipline in the Kuhnian terms of normal science, paradigm shift, and

    scientific revolution (Ricci 1977). By 1965, the language introduced by Kuhn to explain changes

    in dominant scientific paradigms had entered the mainstream. This is reflected, for example, in

    David Truman s 1965 APSA Presidential Address (1965, 865). Barrow understands the

    behavioral revolution in Kuhnian terms of a scientific revolution because the organizing paradigm

    of the discipline shifted from a focus on the state in the German tradition of Staatswissenschaft to

    the political system , and because the reorientation of methodological focus to behavioral

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    3/35

    3

    methods borrowed from the physical sciences. The first aspect of this paradigm shift, Barrow

    describes the transition from positivism to behavioralism, was a redefinition of the meaning of

    science [along] the same methodological foundations as the natural sciences (312). In

    Bar rows narrative, the positivist movement of the 1920s was spearheaded by efforts at the

    University of Chicago and especially the foundation of the Social Science Research Council and

    the work of Charles Merriam. 1

    Barrows entry is a textbook example of a political scientist using a form of historical

    narrative to convey the triumphal and rapid transformation of the discipline after the behavioral

    revolution. But how did we get here? When did political scientists first begin to incorporate theconcept of the behavioral revolution in their discussions of the disciplines past ? When was the

    concept invented and how have prominent political scientists used it over time? To continue this

    inquiry into the discursive origin of the phrase the behavioral revol ution, I now turn to the

    literature of the behavioralists themselves. What better place to look for the behavioral revolution

    than in the written works of the actors during this period? As we shall see this approach is useful

    in only a limited way. After a review of behavioral period literature, I turn to two examples of

    authors using the behavioral revolution in their writing. I then review the way contemporary

    disciplinary historians use the concept in their writing. In conclusion I argue that the behavioral

    revolution should not be understood as an event that can be given a precise dating . It is better

    to understand the behavioral revolution as a discursive object created in the discourse of political

    scientists writing in the past. This understanding allows one to see how the language of

    revolution is misleading when discussing the discursive history of political science.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    4/35

    4

    THE BEHAVIORAL PERIOD

    In his 1991 Study of Electoral Behavior, Jack Dennis discusses the behavioral

    revolution in terms of a movement which began to emerge and to change the intellectual

    concerns of political scientists by the late 1940s and early 1950 (1991, 54). Dennis is a prominent

    behavioral scholar and a former student of one of the founders of behavioralism, David Easton

    (Easton 1965, note 11). In his discussion of the behavioral revolution, Dennis cites three prominent

    behavioralist works: Robert Dahls 1961 American Political Science Review ( APSR) article The

    Behavioral Approach in Political Science ; Heinz Eulaus 1963 The Behavioral Persuasion in

    Politics; and David Eastons 1965 A Framework for Political Analysis . Dennis describes the

    behavioral revolution in particularly Dahlian terms as a new mood, style and focus of political

    inquiry and one where the study of voting behavior became the subfield par excellence for

    scientific applications to the study of human behavior (1991, 54; cf. Dahl 1961; Easton 1965,

    165).

    In this section, I interrogate the citations Dennis provides for his discussion of the

    behavioral revolution , and see if I can discover any clues as to when that phrase was first used,

    or perhaps more realistically when the phrase first began to enjoy a wide currency in the discourse

    of the discipline. Of course this investigation takes us a full sixty years back in time, so it is

    reasonable to expect that the phrase the behavioral revolution will not yet be in wide circulation.

    If this is the case though, why does Dennis cite these three pieces together by way of substantiating

    his brief definition of the behavioral revolution? Might the origin of the behavioral revolution be

    found in these early writings of three prominent proponents of behavioralism in political science?

    In Dahls classic APSR article, The Behavioral Approach in Political Science: Epitaph for

    a Monument to a Successful Protest, he begins by noting that there is no consensus concerning

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    5/35

    5

    the nature and origin of the term behavioral. 2 It is much easier to identify the concept in terms

    of what it is not, and for Dahl, the behavioral approach to political science is not the same as that

    of the speculative philosopher, the historian, the legalist, or the moralist (1961, 763). 3 In

    beginning his investigation, Dahl identifies the first use of the phrase political behavior in the

    literature of American political science following the First World War. 4 Dahl identifies six

    stimuli that helped establish the behavioral approach in American political science: (1) the early

    work of Charles Merriam at the University of Chicago and the flowering of behavioral political

    science at the University of Chicago in the 1920s and 1930s, (2) the influx of German migr

    scholars in the 1930s, (3) the Second World War and the experience of the war generationsconfrontation of theory and reality, (4) the establishment of the Social Science Rese arch Council,

    (5) the development of the social scientific survey at the University of Michigan and Columbia

    University, (6) the impact of the great philanthropic foundations in Carnegie, Rockefeller, and

    Ford (1961, 763-765).

    In opening his essay, Dahl de votes considerable attention to David Trumans 1951 article

    written for the Social Science Research Council titled, The Implications of Political Behavior

    Research. 5 Dahl s narrative continues, and he mentions who he understands to be founders of

    behavioralism: Charles Merriam, Harold Lasswell, David Easton, V.O. Key, Jr., Herbert Simon,

    Pendleton Herring, and Gabriel Almond. Dahl also discusses the importance of institutional

    support from the University of Chicago and Columbia University, the Social Science Research

    Council and its Committee on Political Behavior, the Survey Research Center and the Bureau of

    Applied Research at the University of Michigan, the support of philanthropic foundations like the

    Ford Foundations Behavioral Science Program, and stemming from this last effort, the Center for

    Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Stanford University.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    6/35

    6

    By the second section of his essay, Dahl is ready to define the behavioral approach as a

    protest movement within political science which:

    Through usage by partisans, partly as an epithet, terms like political behavior

    and the behavioral approach came to be associated with a number of political

    scientists, mainly Americans, who shared a strong sense of dissatisfaction with

    the achievements of conventional political science, particularly through

    historical, philosophical, and the descriptive-institutional approaches, and a

    belief that additional methods and approaches either existed or could be

    developed that would help to provide political science with empirical propositions and theories of a systematic sort, tested by closer, more direct and

    more rigorously controlled observation of political events (1961, 766).

    By the third section, Dahl flatly equates the behavioral mood with the scient ific

    outlook, and he transitions to using the later term in place of the former. By the time he concludes

    his essay, the behavioral approach has disappeared altogether. For example, Dahl closes his study

    with a reminiscence of how from time to time in the past the study of politics has been altered,

    permanently, by a fresh infusion of the spirit of empirical inquiry by, that is to say, the scientific

    outlook ( 772). In effect, Dahl views the behavioral approach to the study of American politics as

    a mood , which is characterized by the effort to be more empirical in the scientific sense

    imported from the physical sciences (i.e. positivist inspired scientific method ). Once again, Dahl

    is asserting a basic equivalence between behavioralism and the scientific outlook.

    Where is the behavioral revolution in Dahls essay and why does Dennis (1991) cite this

    article in his discussion of it? Even though Dahl does not use the concept behavioral revolution ,

    the idea is already there in his writing on the subject of behavioralism and the scientific outlook

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    7/35

    7

    in political science. He comes closest to mentioning the behavioral revolution at the end of section

    one and the beginning of section five. In closing section one, Dahl refers to the radicals and the

    revolutionary sectarians who first initiated the behavioral approach in the 1920s and 1930s at

    the University of Chicago. The justification for the use of this language is not offered by Dahl.

    Presumably t he sectarians of the behavioral approach were radical and revolutionary

    because they represented a new mood or outlook in the discipline which was markedly different

    than what had come before. In section five, Dahl refers to the behavioral approach variously in

    terms of a revolt and a protest against the traditionalists in the discipline.

    Dennis also cites Eulaus 1963 The Behavioral Persuasion in Politics , but does Eulaumention the behavioral revolution in this work? Like Dahl, Eulau begins with the q uestion what

    is political behavior? In his search for the meaning of behavioralism, Eulau famously

    characterizes the behavioral approach in American political science as the behavioral persuasion

    (1963, 4). For Eulau, the behavioral persuasion in pol itics is a return to a tradition of research

    beginning with ancient authors in Greece and neglected by modern researchers. In making this

    presentist point, Eula u notes how behavioralist make use of techniques of research that the

    classical writers woul d have used had it been available to them (Eulau 1963, 32). Similar to the

    great scientists of the ancient world, the behavioral researcher eschews mythologies and normative

    theories and instead focuses on what people do and what beliefs they understand to be motivating

    their actions (7). In returning to man as the root of politics, says Eulau and echoing Dahl, the

    behavioral persuasion reveals itself as a radical orientation in the study of politics (10). By

    radical Eulau is referring to the etymological meaning of going to the root of something (the

    title of the chapter is The Root is Man after all). More specifically, Eulau means to highlight

    the Popperian criterion of validity or falsificationism since the behavioral persuasions

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    8/35

    8

    radi calism stems from the conviction that a proposition may be worn out when, on being tested,

    it can be disproved ( 10-11). 6

    Although there are many individual differences among practicing behavioralists in

    American political science in the early 1960s, Eulau identifies four areas where a broad consensus

    exists. First, there is widespread agreement on the appropriate units of analysis. Echoing other

    behavioralists, Eulau emphases that the core of the approach is the focus on the individual person

    as the empi rical unit of analysis (1963, 13). Second, the common agreement that research must

    engage all realms of discovery relevant to political behavior whether social, economic, or cultural.

    This acknowledgment of the necessity of approaching phenomena from multiple levels of analysisnecessitates an interdisciplinary approach. Third, the interdependence of theory and research;

    where by theory , Eulau means the theoretical activit y which postulates and ultimately

    presupposes a framework or model for analysis ; and by research he means the activity of

    formulating testable hypotheses and then testing them using empirical data (e.g. voting or other

    decision-making phenomena).

    The fourth area of general consensus is an agreement on the utility of behavioral methods

    for the analysis of political phenomenon. Here Eulau makes near explicit use of the phrase the

    behavioral revolution. Eulau is discussing the methods and/or techniques of behavioral political

    science and, similar to Easton (discussed below), he states that the revolution in the behavioral

    sciences has been predominantly a technological revolution (1963, 31) . Unlike Easton, Eulau is

    adamant that the revolution is not a revolt against classical or traditional theory. 7 In his telling,

    the beh avioral persuasion represents what one might call the coming of age of social science .

    Among the techniques that Eulau singles out are the probability survey sample, the use of

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    9/35

    9

    panels of informants, the invention of metric techniques such as scalogram and factor analysis,

    and the analysis of political group behavior (1963, 33 -34). 8

    In an oral history, Eulau registers his opinion that there really never was a behavioral

    revolution (Baer et al. 1991). In his account and similar to other behavioral founders accounts of

    the disciplines past, two key moments stand out in the early emergence of the behavioral

    revolution in the discourse of political science: Trumans 1955 article for the Social Science

    Research Article, titled The Impact on Political Science of the Revolution in the Beha vioral

    Sciences, and the publication of Thomas Kuhns 1962 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions .

    Eulau remarks that the origin of the phrase the behavioral revolution probably came fromTruman s 1955 article (Baer et al. 1991, pp. 193 -194). 9

    Despi te Eulaus reference to Truman (1955), there is no explicit mention of the behavioral

    revolution. Truman opens his article by asking what is the nature of the alleged revolution

    marked out by himself in his title (1955, 202). For Truman, the behavioral sciences may be

    defined in the special sense of academic departments in social science that provide or aspire to

    provide verified principles of human behavior through the use of methods of inquiry similar to

    those of the natural sciences (1955, 203). In 1955, these departments are overwhelmingly to be

    found in psychology, sociology, and anthropology (203). Truman (1955) goes on to

    conventionally relate all the advances in technique and/or method which would in just a few short

    years become the focus of tremendous controversy (e.g. see Barber 2006). There is no sense in

    Trumans remarks that anything he is saying is controversial. From the perspective of the present,

    his naivety (or perhaps his political astuteness?) is a consequence of the fact that the impact of

    Kuhns 1962 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions had yet to be felt in the sociology of

    knowledge. Truman is decidedly not a partisan of any revolution, and he preaches caution

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    10/35

    10

    admonishing the Young Turks not to lose sight of the political aspect of their vocation or fail to

    recognize the limited applicability of behavioralism to the larger and more complex arena of

    politics and human governance. He identifies the core of what political scientists do as the

    description of institutions, how they operate, and the consequences for the life of the citizen. In

    the end, although he is sympathetic to the call for more systematic and empirical theory in political

    science research, he is still skeptical that a revolution in theory and method along behavioral lines

    will improve the discipline as a whole. 10

    Dennis also cites David Eastons 1965 book , A Framework for Political Analysis , but

    where is the behavioral revolution in this work?11

    Easton begins his preface by mentioning that Framework is a follow-up to his now more well-known The Political System (1953). The book is

    an elaboration of what Easton calls systems theory and an inquiry into the way the entire political

    system can be mapped in a logico-functional manner. Although this is a somewhat antiquated

    approach to political analysis, it is interesting for its importance in the historiography of the

    discipline (Gunnell 2013b, 2014). For my purposes, the relevant portions of Eastons text come

    primarily from Chapter One, Theory and Behavioral Research, previously published in 1962 as

    The Current Meaning of Behavioralism in Political Science.

    My emphasis is on finding the behavioral revolution in Eastons work. Why does Dennis

    cite this work in reference to the behavioral revolution? Like Dahl and Eulau, Easton has trouble

    providing an unequivocal definition of behavioralism (1965, 4). For Easton, like Eulau, what is

    afoot is a conceptual revolution in the discipline which is a remaking of the meaning of theory

    in modern political science (1965, 2). Also like Dahl and Eulau, in this chapter Easton comes very

    close to describing the period in terms of a behavioral revolution. The first section of the chapter

    is called The Revolution in Political Theory. Easton refers to a revolution in the manner of

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    11/35

    11

    thinking about political theory that he hopes will come to predominate in the discipline. Easton

    already rejected traditional political theory (historical, institutional, moral, etc.) in his 1951

    article The Decline of Modern Political Theory and in his 1953 book, The Political System .

    Moving beyond these criticisms, Easton is now ready to describe the theoretical framework which

    he hopes will serve as a basis for modern empirical political theory. In a point I return to in a

    moment, Easton emphasizes that this intellectual revolution and upheaval is in large part due

    to the interdisciplinary nature of the behavioral approach to political analysis (1965, 3). 12

    Easton goes on to do his best to give a comprehensive account of the assumptions and

    objectives which loosely c haracterize the behavioral credo of behavioral researchers in thediscipline (7). These assumptions and objectives are: (1) the search for regularities or patterns in

    political behavior, (2) the use of a verification principle such as hypothesis testing, (3) an emphasis

    on methodological technique , (4) quantification , (5) the separation of values from facts in an

    analytic fashion, (6) the systematization of both theory and practice, (7) pure science in the sense

    that theory precedes application, and (8) integration in the sense that political behavior research is

    interdisciplinary (7; emphasis in original).

    Easton sets out to better delimit the meaning of the behavioral approach which, echoing

    other period authors, has come to mean about as many things as are commentators (1965, 8).

    The diversity of definitions has at least a common goal a science of politics modeled after the

    methodological assumptions of the natural sciences ( 8). Here, in a nutshell, is what the behavioral

    movement came to mean to later political scientists (recall Barrows 2008 definition above). Even

    so, the goal of making the study of politics more scientific has been discussed for much longer

    than the behavioral period in the US (see Lepawsky 1964; Dryzek 2006). New here is the

    additional sentiment of a disdain for tradition , and a concomitant dismissal of classical political

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    12/35

    12

    theory. For Easton the behavioral approach signifies far more than a new methodological

    orientation or mood in American political science. Thus, Easton argues, by the adoption of this

    name by the various foundations, institutes, and departmental programs at universities, the idea of

    behavioral science is applied to any social research concerned with a scientific understanding of

    man in society, regardless of the disciplinary umbrella under which it may find shelter (1965, 12 -

    13; see also Hauptmann 2012, 22). In what amounts to a common theme among the founders of

    behavioralism, t raditional or classical political theory is dismissed in favor of empirical

    political theory. The behavioral approach is largely the offspring of this revolution which can

    be understood as the new kind of theory in political science that has been struggling thr ough adecade of parturition and that is just now beginning to take on a life of its own (1965, 3). In

    addition, reports Easton, the new name of behavioralism signals that the science of politics

    aims to ally itself with trends in other social science disciplines (1965, 9). This theme of

    interdisciplinarity and the interconnection of the social sciences is repeated often in the context of

    narratives about the foundation of behavioral political science.

    The point that Easton belabors is that the behavioral approach is more than a new emphasis

    on the application of the scientific method. Historically there have been a number of name

    changes as science slowly evolved into specialized branches. Whereas once there was philosophy;

    slowly there appeared moral and natural science, followed later by the full modern repertoire

    of biology, physics, and astronomy , etc. (1965, 11). Although there has long been a focus

    on modeling political science on the physical sciences it was only since the 1950s that the name

    behavioral science came into use (1965, 9). More recently, the emergence of behavioral as

    opposed to social science may be attributed to the creation of the National Science Foundation

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    13/35

    13

    in 1950 and social scientists efforts to disassociate themselves from any sort of socialist science

    (1965, 12; see Easton 1985, 139-140). 13

    Behavioralists have been in agreement in what they are not: i.e. not confined to one

    discipline, not restricted to the study of institutions, not adverse to the application of the scientific

    method to social and political problems. At the same time, behavioralists have failed to consider

    the newness of the emergent behavioral or empirical theory. As I mentioned earlier, Easton

    believes that the behavioral movement represents more than a new focus on method (1965, 17,

    21). Instead, the principal feature that distinguishes the traditional from behavioral political

    science is the form of empirical theory that Easton champions throughout his career. Newtheory, for Easton, tends to be analytic, not substantive, explanatory rather than eth ical, more

    general and less particular (1965, 22). When aligned with advanced technical means of research,

    the new empirical theory promises to reveal the full meaning and significance of the behavioral

    approach in political science (1965, 22). 14

    Where is the behavioral revolution Eastons 1965 book? The behavioral sciences represent

    a new turning in the road and the beginning of a new direction . Similar to Truman (1955),

    this language is making use of the imagery of revolution, even as the metaphor is far from explicit

    (1965, 13). In part, Easton argues that the behavioral approach is an ideological weapon lending

    color and vigor to the movement of a diffuse and informal group of academic rebels against

    traditions (1965, 10). Easton wishes to be more specific and analytically distinguishes two

    revolutions that are occurring simultaneously in American political science: (1) a technical

    revolution, and (2) a theoretical revolution. 15 First, the technical revolution which began in the

    1920s and flourished after WWII political analysis developed the following scientific techniques:

    interviews, survey research, technical methods for measurement, [t]he formalization of analysis

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    14/35

    14

    in logica l and mathematical symbols the widespread introduction of the scope and method of

    political science and training in the use of mechanized procedures for recording and analyzing

    data (1965, 18). Next, Easton turns to a second, theoretical revolution , which he feels needs to

    be acknowledged in order to understand the nature of behavioralism for American political

    science. Although Easton does not use the phrase the behavioral revolution , he does observe

    that the behavioral movement is marked by a second revolution, which ha s transformed other

    social sciences into behavioral disciplines (1965, 18 -19 ). This revolution, Easton continues,

    has involved the sharp consciousness that without a far more concentrated effort on empirical

    theory our tech nical resources would be squandered (1965, 19). So although Easton is notexplicit here, like the other behavioralists discussed above, he is clearly gesturing toward the

    phrase the behavioral revolution.

    Whether considered a mood (Dahl) or an orientation (Easton), all the authors covered

    would agree with Eulau (1963) when he says the behavioral persuasion in politics is concerned

    with what man does politically and the meanings he attaches to his behavior (5). In all these

    period pieces (1955-1965), the authors allude to the concept of the behavioral revolution , but in

    no case do they actually make use of the phrase. Why did Dennis, writing thirty years later, choose

    to cite Dahl, Easton, and Eulau to back up his condensed definition of the so- called behavioral

    revolution? How do these pieces help us understand the origin of the concept? The empirical

    question remains when did the phrase the behavioral revolution enter into the literature of

    American political science and perhaps more importantly when did its use become commonplace?

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    15/35

    15

    THE BEHAVIORAL REVOLUTION APPEARS

    In my search for the behavioral revolution, I now contrast a proponent and a critic of

    behavioralism using the phrase the behavioral revolution in the late 1960s : Easton (1968) and

    Wolin (1969) respectively. Easton stands as a proponent of behavioralism and as one of the first

    to explicitly mention the behavioral revolution in their writing, while the political theorist Sheldon

    Wolin stands as a critic of behavioralism in political science (Wiley 2006). In retrospect, it appears

    that the late 1960s was a turning point in the disciplines acceptance and use of the behavioral

    revolution. The late 1960s also represents a crisis period in the identity of political science, which

    had enjoyed a long period of behavioral dominance. It seems that 1968 was somewhat of athreshold year for the emergence of the phrase the behavioral revolution in the writing of

    American political scientists. For example, in Maria n Irishs 1968 edited volume, Political

    Science: The Advance of the Discipline , there are two uses of the phrase the behavioral

    revolution. The first is found in William Keech and James W. Protheros article American

    Government the authors speak of the behavioral revolution using quotation marks. In Neil

    McDonald and James Rosenaus contribution, Political Theory as Academic Field and

    Intellectual Activity, the phrase the behavioral revolution appears without quotation marks

    seven times. It seems that as challenges to behavioral dominance mounted in the late 1960s, the

    concept of the behavioral revolution came to be used by critics and defenders of behavioralism in

    their writing.

    One of the earliest mentions of the phrase the behavioral revolution I found is in Easton s

    1968 International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences entry on Political Science. Easton is

    writing as a disciplinary historian and he opens his encyclopedia entry by noting that political

    science in mid- twentieth century is a discipline in search of its identity (1968, 282). This identity

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    16/35

    16

    crisis has been precipitated by a profound revolution in the discipline since WWII (1968, 282).

    Easton goes on to catalogue traditional means of organizing political phenomenon such as

    institutions, the state, power, and of course, he gives special attention to his concept of the

    political system. Next , Easton catalogues the various content areas that he sees as being at the

    core of political sciences over the millennia: universalism (ancient Greek thought through the 19 th

    century), legalism (late into the 19 th century), realism (through WWII), and behavioralism (after

    WWII).

    The bulk of Eastons article is devoted to the behavioral period. According to E aston, the

    behavioral movement in political science came into full bloom after WWII (1968, 291). As withhis 1965, A Framework for Political Analysis , Easton identifies two distinct revolutions

    simultaneously at work in contemporary political science in the US: the technical/methodological

    and the theoretical revolutions. Unlike his earlier work, the concept of the behavioral revolution

    is mentioned four times. Discussing the advance of the theoretical revolution in American political

    science, Easton says, the behavioral revolution has stimulated the formulation of empirically

    oriented theory (1968, 294). 16 In a section titled Method and Theory, Easton discusses how the

    discipline has been reshaped by the revolution in techniques or methods of analysis. The new

    political science has turned toward method and technique in the wake of a major revolution and

    by the 1960s the methods of modern science had made deep inroads into political research, under

    the rubric of the study of political behavior. This behavioral revolution has permanently changed

    the methodological and technical face of political science (295).

    Easton continues discussing how modern political science went through an arduous

    learning process as it worked to throw off the heavy yoke of the Greek classical tradition (296).

    The behavioral revolution in political science after World War II stands as a summary label for

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    17/35

    17

    the consequences of the full reception of scientific method (296). The use of quotation marks in

    this instance ought to signal that the author is uncomfortable with the usage or that he or she is

    quoting another author. Neither of these traditional interpretations makes sense in this case.

    Easton is not quoting any author in this use, but clearly he is com fortable with the phrase the

    behavioral revolution since hes already used it without qualification twice, and in the very next

    paragraph he uses the phrase without quotation marks. 17 If we disregard particulars for the

    moment, what stands out with brilliant clarity in the behavioral revolution in political science is

    the final and complete acceptance of the idea that methods of investigation, in all their aspects, are

    problematic and, accordingly, merit special, concentrated attention (1968, 296). Throughout thisarticle there is no sense that the use of the phrase is in anyway problematic, despite the one strange

    occurrence of the phrase in quotation marks. 18

    By the end of the 1960s, the concept of the behavioral revolution is also in use in the

    subfield of political theory. The political theorist Sheldon Wolin can frame his APSR article,

    Political Theory as a Vocation, around a critique of the so-called technological and/or

    methodological advances represented by behavioralism in American political science. In sharp

    contrast to the behavioralists like Easton, Wolin insists that theory is not method and in fact these

    two activities represent very different ways of life: the bios theoretikos and the vita methodica

    respectively. 19 Wolin juxtaposes the vocation of what he calls the epic political theorist and the

    scientific theorist (1969, 1080). Wolins work aims to restore the dignity and legitimacy of

    traditional or classical political theory since behavioral empirical political theory as Dahl, Easton,

    and Eulau understood it, has impoverished the long tradition of political thought. 20

    The reduction of the rich tradition of western political theory into the narrow confines of

    scientific method is lamentable. Like the migr scholars Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    18/35

    18

    (although with different emphases), Wolin is concerned with the big picture and with

    understanding how it is that traditional or classical political theory could come to be so maligned

    even to the point of being declared dead or dying even by its defenders? 21 His answer is revealed

    at the end of his essay: the Western world as it existed in 1969 is productive of a methodological

    and scientific mentality. The technical and ideological imperatives of late capitalism in the West

    have created methodological technicians and it is no wonder that social and political scientists

    have found behavioral methods congenial (Rothsetin 2005). 22 This is very much like a scenario

    Max Weber might have had in mind when he wrote of the polar night of icy darkness and

    hardness, referring then to the dystopian possibility of a fully-rationalized society (Wolin 1969).Since citizens are trained from early childhood to think in methodological and scientific terms it

    is no wonder that they behave in rational and predictable ways (Arendt 1958).

    So where is the behavioral revolution in Wolins article? The phrase the behavio ral

    revolution is clearly and conventionally used by Wolin to refer to the behavioral period in the

    disciplines past. By 1969, the nature of the so -called revolution is well establi shed. W hatever

    ones assessment of the behavioral revolution, says Wolin, it clearly has succeeded in

    transforming political science. What is less clear is the precise nature of that revolution (1062).

    Yet, most practitioners today would probably accept the common story of the behavioral

    revolution as the period between 1950 and 1970 in which American political science became a

    real science modeled after the methodological assumptions and technical innovations of the

    modern physical and biological sciences.

    Wolin also criticizes proponents of behavioralism in American political science, when he

    says the idea of method is the central fact of the behavioral revolution ( 1063). Wolins critique

    is summarized as a rejection of the behavioral vita methodica or the dogmatic adherence to the

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    19/35

    19

    ethic of science: objectivity, detachment, fidelity to fact, and deference to intersubjective

    verification by a community of practitioners (1969, 1064). Wolin remarks how th is change in

    the mentality of the ave rage political scientist may mark the significance of the behavioral

    revolution (1969, 1064). Wolin rejects the proposition that the behavioral revolution was a

    scientific revolution on the order that Kuhn identified occurring in the history of the physical

    sciences (Kuhn 1962). Despite this fact, he does finds that there has been a certain revolution in

    political science, and one characterized by the behavioral movements presupposition that the

    fundamental purposes and arrangements served by its te chniques have been settled (1969, 1063).

    Thus, according to Wolin, a dominant paradigm has emerged , but not because of any anomaliesin traditional political theory. This shift has been made possible by external changes in the world

    of human affairs following the world wars and new challenges to democracy and human dignity

    (1081-1082; cf. Brown 2002).

    DISCIPLINARY HISTORY

    Disciplinary history has been developing since the early 1960s, and is now sub-genre in its

    own right. By the late 1980s, it would not be an exaggeration to suggest that the history of

    political science is on the threshold of becoming a distinct research specialty (Gunnell 1985, 16;

    Farr 1988). Now that I have identified the year of the initial diffusion of the concept of the

    behavioral revolution in 1968, I turn to the work of the disciplinary historians in order to see how

    this concept has been used to the present day.

    Among the first works devoted exclusively to discussing the history of the discipline of

    political science were Bernard Crick (1959), and Albert Somit and Joseph Tanenhaus (1967). I

    have not found the phrase the behavioral revolution in either of these foundational texts in the

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    20/35

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    21/35

    21

    concept. Debates about the significance of behavioralism and whether the movement was truly

    revolutionary have also exacerbated ongoing crises of identity in the discipline. As Gunnell points

    out in 2004, telling the story of political science has always been a crucial element in both the

    disciplines internal rhetoric of inquiry and its search for identity ( 47). Early in the new millennia,

    Gunnell finds the phrase the behavioral revolution to be an inappropriate usage given that its use

    since the 1960s was based in part on the theory of scientific revolution forwarded in Kuhns The

    Structure of Scientific Revolutions . Gunnell argues that there has only been one scientific

    revolution in the sense of a discipline-wide paradigm shift and this occurred in the 1920s. This

    earlier positivist revolution was characterized by a shift from state-based political science to afocus on the integration of positivism into mainstream political science through the aegis of

    pluralist theory a movement that was complete by the mid -1930s (Gunnell 2004, 48; see

    Barrow 2011, 82). This implies that the story of t he behavioral revolution is inaccurate at least

    in so far as it purports to be a Kuhnian scientific revolution.

    In Gunnell (2004), the behavioral revolution was far from a revolution in the Kuhnian

    sense (2004, 48 -49). Instead the movement is unders tood in terms of a reformation of the

    positivist revolution of the 1920s and 1930s, buttressed by the influx of migr scholars who

    became the epistemological other of the mainstream in American political science (2004, 49; see

    also Gunnell 1993, Gunnell 2007). From this perspective, the behavioral revolution becomes a

    conservative movement which sought to bolster and defend the mainstream from the assaults of

    their critics in political theory and elsewhere (2004, 49). Gunnell characterizes the behavioral

    movement as a reaffirmation of the pluralist revolution of the 1920s and 1930s which was in

    part a defense against the new and unprecedented attack on the idea of a science of politics, but it

    was also a response to a context that valorized pure science and funded quantitative research

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    22/35

    22

    (2004, 49). For Gunnell, then, the discourse about the behavioral revolution is clearly

    mythological. Gunnells article works to debunk the myth of the behavioral revolution by arguing

    that the movement was not in fact revolutionary at all.

    The political theorist and disciplinary historian John Dryzek discusses five potentially

    revolutionary moments in the history of American political science (2006, 487). In succession

    these were: the statist founders in the late 19 th century, the pluralist moment in the early 20 th

    century, the behavioralist period of the mid-20 th century, the Caucus for a New Political Science

    in the late 1960s, and finally the Perestroika movement in the early 21 st century. It is notable that

    Dryzek finds only two of these moments to be truly revolutionary. Only the statist and the behavioralist ones were revolutionary, in the sense that they were able to rese[t] the disciplines

    agenda from what came before (2006, 487).

    As the title of his article makes clear, Dryzek argues that these were the only revolutionary

    moments in the disciplines history since they were able to change the agenda of the discipline and

    because they did not encounter strong resistance from practitioners in the field. Thus for Dryzek,

    Gunnell s interpretation that there was only one revolutionary moment in the history of the

    discipline is incorrect. Moreover, the idea that the pluralist movement was revolutionary is

    incorrect, since the rise of pluralist theory was met with resistance and did not displace older statist

    forms of analysis (2006, 488). In fact, the recognition of a pluralist moment in American political

    science does not even count as a revolution in Dryzeks analysis . Statism and behavioralism, on

    the other hand, counted as revolutionary because there was no opposition and so they were able to

    shift the agenda for the entire discipline.

    It seems that the behavioral revolution is a true revolution since it reset the agenda for a

    large number of scholars in the field. As Dryzek summarizes, it represented a selective

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    23/35

    23

    radicalization of exis ting disciplinary tendencies leading to more survey research being funded

    and published, an increase in the relative frequency of quantitative studies in the disciplines top

    journals, and a relative decline in work addressed to public policy (2006, 490). Again, the point

    is that for Dryzek behavio ralism is a revolution without enemies and succeeded in resetting the

    research agenda of the discipline not because it was completely new and fought a battle with the

    mainstream, but because it grew out of the mainstream and did not encounter much resistance from

    the disciplines intellectual and institutional configuration at the time.

    In disciplinary history, then, there appears to be a movement toward a more critical

    awareness about the behavioral period and whether or not it counts as a revolution or not.Whether understood as a political, intellectual, or Kuhnian scientific revolution, historians of the

    discipline have started to question whether and how the behavioral revolution was revolutionary .

    CONCLUSION

    In this paper, I located the emergence of the phrase the behavioral revolution in the

    writing of political scientists. I traced its conventional use to sometime around the year 1968. I

    also found that authors writing prior to 1968 come close to using the phrase and that it is most

    commonly used in narratives about the disciplines past and often in connecti on with Truman

    (1951, 1955) and Kuhn (1962). Along with Trumans 1955 article, Kuhns 1962 classic seem like

    possible explanations for the beginnings of the wide-spread use of t he language of revolution in

    describing the behavioral period in political science. But is still an open question why it would

    wait until the late 1960s for the phrase the behavioral revolution to find its way into the discourse

    of the discipline in a major way.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    24/35

    24

    Although it is probably too late, I propose that the language of revolution is misleading

    when talking about the history of political science. In my view, both the discipline and the

    profession of political science are in a constant state of change. 23 Academic ideas and institutions

    evolve over time and it simply doesnt make sense to speak of intellectual and structural change

    in terms of political, social, or scientific revolutions. Instead both our professional and disciplinary

    configuration changes slowly over time reflecting the development of institutions as well as the

    input of generation after generation of new political scientists. New political scientists are trained

    in institutions and come to confront a political system that is fundamentally different than that of

    previous generations. It is no wonder, then, that there is going to be a division of labor where onegroup continues with basic research on more traditional problems, while another group commits

    itself to criticizing these authors for their failure to consider the normative implications of their

    basic assumptions, and finally another which would seek to make political science something other

    than what it has been in the past. In every era in the development of American political science,

    one can find examples of all three tendencies. In retrospect, every era has its dominant trends in

    research and ideological commitments. I propose, however, that these three research groups are

    engaged in a great conversation which ultimately produces and reproduces the present ideological

    and institutional configuration of the discipline . There has been no revolution in American

    political science but rather the genealogical record reveals an ongoing process of disciplinary and

    professional continuity and innovation over time. 24

    It seems to me that the recognition of an ongoing evolution in political science is the best

    way to understand the history of the discipline over time. There has never been, I submit, a single

    coherent and dominant paradigm that took hold of the discipline. More importantly there was

    not an abrupt change from a before to an after state where tradition was suddenly supplanted by

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    25/35

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    26/35

    26

    NOTES

    1 For a detailed discussion of early founders in American political science see Bernard

    Cricks 1959 The American Science of Politics: Its Origins and Conditions . Crick gives

    extended attention to A.F. Bentley, Charles Merriam, and Harold Lasswell.

    2 Dahls paper was first presented at the 5th World Congress of the International Political

    Science Association, Paris, September 26, 1961 (Polsby et al. 1963, 15).

    3 As Somit and Tanenhaus point out, the term behaviorism was commonly used prior to

    the 1960s when the term behavioralism came to be the predominate usage (1967, 183).

    See also Easton 1985, p. 137.4 Curiously, Dahl cites David Eastons 1953 The Political System as evidence that the term

    has been in use since WWI. I say curious since an earlier citation would seem more

    appropriate. Later, Dahl also gives credit to Frank Kent, an American journalist who

    published Political Behavior in 1928 and to Herbert Tingstens 1937 Political Behavior .

    See also James Farr (1995) on Dahl s 1961 article.

    5 I discuss another important article by David Truman below.

    6 See Karl Popper (1962); Ricci (1977).

    7 Which is not to say that Eulau withholds from criticizing traditional political theory along

    the same lines pursued by Dahl and Easton. According to Eulau, much traditional

    political inquiry has been purely formal in the sense that is was limited to the observation

    of patterns and took the meaning content of behavioral for granted. Political institutions

    or constitutions were described and their formal similarities and differences were noted,

    but what these patterns meant to the people involved was not investigated. Rather

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    27/35

    27

    meanings were ascribed, usually on the basis of the observers cultural understandings

    (1963, 69).

    8 In Chapter Five, Eulau discusses some behavioral dilemmas. Eulau begins by noting

    that the behavioral persuasion in politics is difficult to live by. Behavioral practitioners

    make exacting scientific demands on themselves (1963, 110). This persuasion is

    difficult to live by since it aspires to the status of science and since Eulau takes it for

    granted that a science of politics is both possible and desirable, and I shall start from

    there (1963, 111).

    9

    Recall that Dahl cited Truman s earlier 1951 article . Truman (1951) is a book chapterappears in Research Frontiers in Politics and Government which was produced for the

    Brookings Institution. Other notable behavioralists who have chapters in this book are

    Herbert Simon, Robert Dahl, and Alfred de Grazia.

    10 There seems to be somewhat of a consensus around the idea that the behavioral

    revolution was hardly a scientific revolution as described by Kuhn (1962): see for

    example Eulaus 1991 APSA oral history; Farr 1995; Gunnell 2004; and Dryzek 2006).

    11 Easton acknowledges Jack Dennis in his preface as one of many graduate students who

    helped in some way contribute to the book (1965, xiii).

    12 Judging from Eastons remarks in 19 85, his efforts were an overwhelming success. In his

    Political Science in the United States: Past and Present, Easton says of the behavioral

    period that if there was any single comprehensive description of the subject matter of

    political science it was to be found in the notion that it studied the authoritative allocation

    of values for society. This was the conception that I had put forward in my book, The

    Political System , in 1953, and it had found widespread acceptance (1985, 144). For

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    28/35

    28

    more on the success of empirical theory see Contemporary Empirical Political Theory ,

    Kristen R. Monroe, Ed. (1997).

    13 Easton also mentions the influence of the Ford Foundation (established in 1936) as a

    factor in the name change from social to behavioral science. On foundation influence

    and the rise of behavioralism, see Hauptmann 2006 and Hauptmann 2012.

    14 On Eastons efforts to establish a general form of empirical theory, see Adcock (2007);

    Gunnell (2013b).

    15 For another treatment of Eastons impact on the behavioral rev olution, see Adcock

    (2010).16 For Easton empirical theory is tantamount to behavioral theory. The ancient desire

    to understand the nature and origin of political systems or regime types expanded after

    World War II to become empirically oriented, or b ehavioral, theory (1968, 293).

    17 In my reading the alternating usage of the quotation marks indicates that political

    scientists are not yet convinced that the phrase is wholly unproblematic and ready for use

    without the qualification.

    18 This unqualified use is particularly remarkable given that just a year later Easton would

    declare the end of the behavioral revolution and the beginning of the post -behavioral

    revolution. See his 1969 APSA presidential address The New Revolution in Political

    Science.

    19 Of course, not all political scientists started doing behavioral research. According to

    James Farr, numerically, nonbehavioralists represented the majority of practicing

    political scientists and theorists (2003, 322).

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    29/35

    29

    20 Wolin characterizes the crisis in the tradition of political theory in the following terms:

    there is widely shared belief that the tradition was largely unscientific where it was not

    antiscientific and that the defining characteristic of a scientific revolution is to break with

    the past (1969, 1068). On traditional political theory see also Hauptmanns 2005

    Defining Theory in Postwar Political Science. For a critique of the idea of a long -

    tradition of political thought, see Gunnell 1978, 1984.

    21 The vocation of the traditional or epic political theorist is characterized by Wolin in the

    following terms: Here lies the vocation of those who preserve our understanding of past

    theories, who sharpen our sense of the subtle, complex interplay between politicalexperience and thought, and who preserve our memory of the agonizing efforts of

    intellect to restate the possibilities and threats posed by political dilemmas of the past

    (1969, 1077).

    22 There is not space here to dive deeply into these epic issues and Ive dealt with them in

    more detail elsewhere (Berkenpas 2009).

    23 According to Easton our discipline refers to our intellectual enterprise; our profession to

    the trained and expert scholars who participate in the discipline (1969, 1059). Cf. John

    Gunnell 2006.

    24 For an analogous skeptical treatment of the behavioral movement in political science see

    Adcock 2007 Interpreting Behavioralism.

    25 On the relationship between disciplinary history and professional identity see Dryzek and

    Leonards 1990 History and Discipline in Political Science.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    30/35

    30

    REFERENCES

    Adcock, Robert. 2007. Interpreting Behavioralism . Modern Political Science: Anglo-

    American Exchanges Since 1880 . Robert Adcock, Mark Bevir, and Shannon C.

    Stimson, Eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    . 2010. XX.

    Almond, Gabriel A. 1966. Political Theory and Political Science. The American Political

    Science Review , Vol. 60, No. 4, pp. 869-879.

    Baer, Michael, A., Malcom E. Jewell, and Lee Sigelman, Eds. 1991. Political Science in America:

    Oral Histories of a Discipline . Lexington, KY: University of Kentucky Press.Barber, Benjamin R. 2006. The Politics of Political Science: Value -free Theory and the

    Wolin-Strauss Dust- Up of 1963. American Political Science Review , Vol. 100, No.

    4, pp. 539-545.

    Barrow, C lyde W. 2008. Political Science . International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences .

    William A. Darity, Jr., Ed.

    . 2011. Politics Denied: Commen ts on Waismel- Manor and Lowis Politics in Motion.

    New Political Science . Vol. 33, No. 1, pp. 79-86.

    Berkenpas, Joshua R. 2009. The Ongoing Revolution in American Political Science. Masters

    Thesis, Western Michigan University.

    Brown, Wendy. 2002. At the Edge. Political Theory , Vol. 30, No. 4, pp. 556-576.

    Crick, Bernard. 1959. The American Science of Politics: Its Origins and Conditions . Berkeley

    and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Dahl, Robert. 1961. The Behavioral Approach in Political Science: Epitaph for a Monument

    to a Successful Protest. American Political Science Review . Vol. 55, No. 4, pp. 763-772.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    31/35

    31

    Dennis, Jack. 1991. The Study of Electoral Behavior. Political Science: Looking to the

    Future. Volume III: Political Behavior . William Crotty, ed. Evanston, IL: Northwestern

    University Press.

    Dryzek, John S. 2006. Revolution s Without Enemies: Key Transformations in Political

    Science. American Political Science Review . Vol. 100, No. 4, pp. 487-492.

    Dryzek, John S. and Stephan T. Leonard. 1988. History and Discipline in Political Science.

    American Political Science Review , Vol. 82, No. 4, pp. 1245-1260.

    . 1990. Can Political Science History be Neu tral? The American Political Science Review ,

    Vol. 84, No. 2, pp. 587-607.Easton, David (1951) The Decline of Modern Political Theory The Journal of Politics , Vol.

    25, No. 3.

    . 1953. The Political System: An Inquiry into the State of Political Science . NY: Alfred

    Knoph.

    . 1962. The Current Meaning of Behavioralism in Political Science. The Limits of

    Behavioralism in Political Science. James C. Charlesworth, Ed. Philadelphia: The

    American Academy of Political and Social Sciences.

    . 1965. A Framework for Political Analysis . Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    . 1968. Political Science . International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences . David

    Sills, Ed.

    . 1969. The New Revolution in Political Science The American Political Science

    Review, Vol. 63, No. 4.

    . 1985. Political Science in the United States: Past and Present . International Political

    Science Review , Vol. 6, No. 1, pp. 133-152.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    32/35

    32

    Easton, David, John G. Gunnell, & Luigi Graziano eds. (1991) The Development of

    Political Science: A Comparative Survey . NY: Routledge.

    Eulau, Heinz (1964) The Behavioral Persuasion in Politics . Stanford University Press.

    Farr, James. 1988. The History of Political Science. American Journal of Political Science .

    Vol. 32, No. 4, pp. 1175-1195.

    . 1995. Remembering the Revolution: Behavioralism in American Political Science.

    Political Science in History: Research Programs and Political Traditions . James Farr,

    John S. Dryzek, and Stephan T. Leonard, Eds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    . 2003. Political Science. The Cambridge History of Science, Vol. 7: The Modern SocialSciences . Theodore M. Porter & Dorothy Ross, Eds. NY: Cambridge University Press.

    . 2008. The History of Political Thought as Disciplinary Genre. The Oxford Handbook of

    Political Theory . John Dryzek, Bonnie Honig, & Anne Phillips, Eds. NY: Oxford

    University Press.

    Farr, James & Raymond Seidelman, eds. 1993. Discipline and History: Political Science in the

    United States . Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Farr, James, John Gunnell, Raymond Seidelman, John S. Dryzek, and Stephen T. Leonard. 1990.

    Can Political Science History Be Neutral? APSR, Vol. 84, No. 2, pp. 587-607.

    Gunnell, John G. 1978. The Myth of the Tradition. American Political Science Review , Vol.

    72, No. 1, pp.122-134.

    Gunnell, John. 1983. Political Theory: The Evolution of a Su b-Field. Political Science: The

    State of the Discipline . Ada W. Finifter, ed. Washington, D.C.: The American Political

    Science Association.

    . 1991. The Historiography of American Political Science. The Development of Political

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    33/35

    33

    Science: A Comparative Survey . David Easton, John G. Gunnell, & Luigi Graziano,

    Eds. NY: Routledge.

    . 1993. The Descent of Political Theory: The Genealogy of an American Vocation . Chicago:

    The University of Chicago Press.

    . 2004. The Real Revolution in Political Science. PSOnline , January, pp. 47-50.

    . 2006. The Founding of the American Political Science Association: Discipline,

    Profession, Political Theory, and Politics. American Political Science Review , Vol. 100,

    No. 4., pp. 479-486.

    . 2007. Making Democracy Safe for the World: Political Science between the Wars. Modern Political Science: Anglo-American Exchanges Since 1880 . Robert Adcock, Mark

    Bevir, and Shannon C. Stimson, Eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    . 2013a . Behavioralism in American Political Science. The Oxford Handbook of Political

    Ideologies . Michael Freeden, Lyman Tower Sargent, and Marc Stears, Eds. NY: Oxford

    University Press.

    . 2013b. The Reconstitution of Political Theory: David Easton, Behavioralism, and the Long

    Road to System. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences , Vol. 41, No. 2, pp.

    190-210.

    Greenstein, Fred I. & Nelson W. Polsby eds. (1975) Political Science: Scope and Theory.

    Handbook of Political Science, Vol. 1 . Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Hauptmann, Emily. 2005. Defining Theory in Postwar Political Science . The Politics of

    Method in the Human Sciences: Positivism and Its Epistemological Others . George

    Steinmetz, Ed. Durham: Duke University Press.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    34/35

    34

    . 2006. From Opposition to Accommodation: How Rockefeller Foundation Grants

    Redefined Relations between Political Theory and Social Science in the 1950s. The

    American Political Science Review , Vol. 100, No. 4., pp. 643-649.

    . 201 2. The Ford Foundation and the Rise of Beh avioralism in Political Science. The

    Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences , Vol 48, No. 2, pp. 154-173.

    Irish, Marian D. 1968. Political Science: Advance of the Discipline . Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

    Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Kuhn, Thomas (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions . Chicago: The University

    of Chicago Press.Lepawsky, Albert. 1964. Summary of Proceedings of the Western Political Science

    Association: The Politics of Epistemology. Political Research Quarterly , Vol. 17, No.

    21, pp. 21-52.

    Monroe, Kristen M. (1997) Contemporary Empirical Theory . Berkeley and Los Angeles:

    The University of California Press.

    Popper, Karl. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge . NY:

    Basic Books.

    Ricci, David. 1977. Reading Thomas Kuhn in the Post -Behavioral Era. The Western Political

    Quarterly , Vol. 30, No. 1, pp. 7-34.

    Somit, Albert and Joseph Tanenhaus. 1967. The Development of American Political Science:

    From Burgess to Behavioralism . Boston: Allyn and Bacon, Inc.

    Truman, David B. 1955. The Impact on Political Science of the Revolution in the Behavioral

    Sciences. Research Frontiers in Politics and Government . Washington, D.C.: The

    Brookings Institution.

  • 8/12/2019 The Behavioral Revolution? A Geneaology of a Concept

    35/35

    . 1965. Disillusion and Regeneration: The Quest for a Discipline. The American

    Political Science Review , Vol. 54, No. 4, pp. 865-873.

    Wiley, James. 2006. Sheldon Wolin on Theory and the Political. Polity , Vol. 38, No. 2, pp. 211-

    234.

    Wolin, Sheldon. 1969. Political Theory as a Vocation The American Political Science Review ,

    Vol. 63, No. 4, pp. 1062-1082.