60
Could you find yourself one morning in a different body? How far can legal paternalism go? Is Satan a viable alternative to God? All philosophers ranked, even by facial hair FEATURE ARTICLE Can we support our superiority? THE AXIOM ABINGDON SCHOOL'S PHILOSOPHY MAGAZINE SUMMER ISSUE 3 WITTGENSTEIN • JOHN NASH: GAME THEORY • A CASE FOR LEGAL PATERNALISM • DOES SATAN OFFER THE ANSWERS? • A STUDY OF TRIALISM • ARE ANIMALS SUB-HUMAN? • COULD YOU WAKE UP IN A DIFFERENT BODY? • DEFINING THE A-PHYSICAL • JOIN PYTHAGORAS TODAY! • PHILOSOPHER TOP TRUMPS • EXISTENTIAL COMICS

The Axiom - Issue 3

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

 

Citation preview

Page 1: The Axiom - Issue 3

Could you find yourself one morning in a different body?

How far can legal paternalism go?

Is Satan a viable alternative to God?

All philosophers ranked, even by facial hair

FEATURE ARTICLE

Can we support our superiority?

THE

AXIOMABINGDON SCHOOL'S PHILOSOPHY MAGAZINE

SUMMER ISSUE 3

•WITTGENSTEIN•JOHNNASH:GAMETHEORY•ACASEFORLEGALPATERNALISM•DOESSATANOFFERTHEANSWERS?•ASTUDYOFTRIALISM•AREANIMALSSUB-HUMAN?•COULDYOUWAKEUPINADIFFERENTBODY?•DEFININGTHEA-PHYSICAL•JOINPYTHAGORASTODAY!•PHILOSOPHERTOPTRUMPS•EXISTENTIALCOMICS

Page 2: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 3: The Axiom - Issue 3

1

Letter From the Editor

This is the last issue of this academic year, and the last of which I am editor. Our own Blake Jones, of course, has done a great majority of the work for this issue, even persisting during his exams; and I am very

much in debt to him for all the great work he has put into keeping the Axiom going, and taking it on to new and greater things. It is with great pleasure that I leave the editorship of the magazine to him, and hope that he gets as much pleasure out of working on the Axiom as I have - I am more than sure he is up to the task!

The changing of hands puts one in mind of cyclical philosophies - those which try to draw broad conclusions about a method or trend throughout history, which can be seen in any culture or any system of thinking. For example, the concept of a thesis, an antithesis, and finally a synthesis, is oft attributed to Hegel as a characterisation of a superior method, which may be turned to any problem. The Myth of Er, pinned to the back of Plato’s Republic, talks of rebirth as a symbol of rending the just. Further, the inevitable political cycles in the same work, moving from autocracy, timocracy, oligarchy, democracy and tyranny, give us another example of the historical inevitability of cycles.

The common thread, of course, is worth remembering in a rather unphilosophical way - this is the only time I will promote such cod philosophy! Everything changes, in shape, form, and content. It might be viewed as one of the inevitabilities of history. The recent break has given me some time to accomplish some long needed reading on the matter. Norman Davies’ ‘Europe’, which I encourage everyone no matter their subject preference to read, gives us a broad view of change and continuity. From the roman appropriation of audacious corinthian architecture, to the relatively recent emergence of ‘retro’ culture, continuity, as well as change, is present. That is what I hope the Axiom will go on to be - an invention, a constant flux, changing with the tastes and opinions of its Editor and writers; but all the while sitting on solid stone, keeping with its original aims until the last. May it always be a place for philosophers to talk about what they love.

My deepest thanks to Blake, Miss Holt, Tom, and all contributors; and most of all to all those reading,

Tomas Brown

Page 4: The Axiom - Issue 3

2

Contents

WITTGENSTEIN 5JOHNNASH:GAMETHEORY 8THELIMITSOFTHELAW 14DOESSATANOFFERTHEANSWERS 20ASTUDYOFTRIALISM 25AREANIMALSSUB-HUMAN 29COULDYOUWAKEUPINADIFFERENTBODY? 33DEFININGTHEA-PHYSICAL 40

JOINPYTHAGORASTODAY! 47PHILOSOPHERTOPTRUMPS 49EXISTENTIALCOMICS 53

CONTRIBUTORS 56

Page 5: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 6: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 7: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Axiom

5

WITTGENSTEINWords by Tomas Brown

Page 8: The Axiom - Issue 3

Wittgenstein

66

Wittgenstein is famous for his incomprehensibility. Throughout his life, the man was famous for being misunderstood. Which is not surprising; on one level, his medium in his early career is a mix of succinct but unclear sentence long propositions, attempting to express momentous ideas; on another, Wittgenstein was talking about how misconceptions were the essence of all philosophical questions. There is, of course, a pinch of salt which must be taken when reading any of his work; Wittgenstein is practically a different person in his early period and his late.

Page 9: The Axiom - Issue 3

7

Wittgenstein

Wittgenstein’s early philosophy has been described most famous-ly as crystalline, a hard and cold mix of logic and mathematics, which is bound up near exclusively in the 20th century exactness of

Vienna culture and Modernism itself. Before anything else, Wittgenstein was a mathematician, his first degree being one in aeronautics from Birmingham uni-versity. It was one of the qualities that Bertrand Russell was looking for in his undergraduates at the time, a quality of ‘mathmaticy’ and ‘scientism’ he thought he found in the ‘queer german lad’ who would follow him back to his rooms. Wittgenstein wrote his first notable work in this period, finished only while in the Austrian army - the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus, a mathematical work which looked to solve all of philosophy in one fell swoop.

The work divides the world into three parts; the world of binary logical facts, the world of thought, and the world of expression, loosely similar to the ontol-ogy of Popper to emerge 50 years later. Every one reflects another, so broadly, once you have the structure of one world down, you have that of all three. The world, Wittgenstein says, splits into ‘simple’ and ‘complex’ facts. Complexes are arrangements of simples; ‘the sky is blue’ for example, is an arrangement of the simple facts of sky and blue. The set of all simples he says make up the ‘facts of the world’; a set of binary facts which can have the value of true or not true and be effective. The notion of truth here relies upon the reflection between the world of expression and the world of facts; a thing is true if it paints a logically valid picture of the facts of the world as they are, like how a score for a film is right if it notes all the music down in the right tone and the right beat. Truth for Wittgenstein is however not so much about relation; it isn’t asking ‘is this the case or not, this individual fact?’ but rather about asking if the situation holds true, if the arrangement reflects the facts of the world; does the music sound right, in other words?

This of course leads him to make statements about the kind of things we can say with this theory of language and this theory of truth. Can we really talk about the way propositions work? No! Because the way propositions work isn’t an arrangement of things propositions can be the subject of, persay. It is like trying to depict how the music score relates to the piece of music by using musi-cal notation again, you just end up repeating yourself. Communication of some things, for Wittgenstein is not about ‘saying’ - it isn’t about saying that you mean things are one way and that is ontologically how they are - it is about ‘showing’ the relationship between certain facts, showing how the bits relate together which allows us to communicate.

Of course, this really leads us into tricky territory for the purpose of the book; what Wittgenstein has been trying to do for us is lead us up and talk about how propositions relate to things! Of course, this is why Wittgenstein ultimately finds his victory over philosophy uncomfortable - the book is a ‘ladder’ to be climbed and thrown away when you realise what tosh it is. All this is complicat-ed by the fact that Wittgenstein is not making an argument in the Tractatus by any stretch of the imagination; he makes a broad system of unsupported state-ments to do with the nature of the world, which he just expects us to accept.

This doesn’t stop it from being one of the most complicated works in any language. Constant germanicisms, redefinition every second page, and a strik-ingly unconventional layout borrowed from Spinozia all make the work hard to read. But, well rewarding for anyone who wants to get past the first page, and especially so considering the first words Wittgenstein spoke when he put the work forward to be judged for his doctorate. He simply clapped Moore and Russell on the back, and shouted ‘Don’t worry Gentlemen, you will never un-derstand it!’

Page 10: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Axiom

8

JOHN NASH: GAME

THEORYWords by Blake Jones

Page 11: The Axiom - Issue 3

9

John Nash: Game Theory

American mathematician

John Nash sadly died on May 23 2015. Nash

was notably an essential contributor to game theory

and he wrote papers on Equilibrium Points in N-person Games, The

Bargaining

Problem, Non-cooperative Games and Two

Person Cooperative Games. His theory of the Nash Equilibrium led to him being awarded the

Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences in

1994. Nash also came to

popular fame after the 2001 film

A Beautiful Mind was released which was based

on him. In this article I will outline the Nash

Equilibrium and other aspects of game

theory.

Page 12: The Axiom - Issue 3

John Nash: Game Theory

10

GO STOP

GO Ten minutesTen minutes

No time,Ten seconds

STOP Ten seconds,No time

Fifteen seconds,Fifteen seconds

The Nash Equilibrium can be defined as ‘a situation where the op-timal outcome of a game is one where no player has an incentive to deviate from his or her chosen strategy after considering an op-

ponent's choice. Overall, an individual can receive no incremental benefit from changing actions, assuming other players remain constant in their strategies.’ In more simplistic and applied terms, the Nash Equilibrium is ‘a situation where a law would be followed even if it was not enforced’. The Nash Equilibrium points to a time where people would cooperate by their own choice because it has the best outcome for them.

A common example of this is following traffic lights. When there is an inter-section of two roads and a car is driving down each road, the cars will generally wait at the traffic lights if they indicate that they need to do so. Whilst cars can receive tickets for not following this, it is not strongly enforced for people to follow and even without it being law most people would listen to it. This is because of the simple reason that the cars would crash if they went at the same time and they would waste time if they both waited. Therefore it makes sense to cooperate to find the best solution. The table below demonstrates this with roughly how much time they would waste.

Though this table is only a rough estimation to how much time would be taken, it shows that one car waiting whilst one car goes creates the best out-come for both cars. This option is also what traffic lights try to enforce, with GO on one side and STOP on the other. Obviously both cars would not go at the same time since it would cause a crash and time would be wasted by giving insurance details. If both cars were to stop they would then see that the other was waiting and then restart their car and slowly make the cross. Ergo is they cooperate one car is agrees to wait a few second so that the other car can go straight away - the best outcome is produced for everyone.

This traffic light situation follows the Nash Equilibrium for the two cars lis-tening to the traffic lights. Going back to the definition, here the two sides have considered what the other car will choose and how what they do is affected by that and once they have made their decision it would be pointless for them to change it. However the Nash Equilibrium can only be used a limited amount because it is rarely the case that individuals come off best when they cooperate with others.

The opposing situation to the Nash Equilibrium is the Prisoner’s Dilemma. In this situation one will always be better off if they chose the option which benefits them and harms another.

Page 13: The Axiom - Issue 3

11

John Nash: Game Theory

Two people are caught doing a small scale crime together and arrested by the police. That night there was another crime on a larger scale which happened which the police suspect the pair were involved in, but they have no evidence. Therefore the two prisoners are questioned individually. The police offer the same choice to the two of them: say nothing and receive their sentence for the small crime or testify that their partner committed the larger crime and they will be pardoned for the smaller crime and set free. Added to this, if one of the prisoners is accused of the larger crime they will have a larger sentence. If they both accuse each other, they will both have longer sentences, but they would shorter than the sentence if they were solely blamed. The two prisoners are held in separate cells and cannot communicate with each other. The number of years in jail they would receive can be shown in the table below.

COOPERATE DEFECT

COOPERATE 1 year1 year

Set free3 years

DEFECT 3 yearsSet free

2 years2 years

Page 14: The Axiom - Issue 3

John Nash: Game Theory

12

The fundamental difference to the Nash Equilibrium here, is that is better for the individual to go for the selfish option. If the partner has decided to cooper-ate, that decision is fixed and since they cannot communicate what you do does not affect their decision. Therefore you can cooperate and get one year in jail, or defect and get set free. On the flip side, if the partner is going to defect and there is little which can be done about that you can cooperate and get three years in jail, or defect and get two years. Whatever the situation it is best to defect be-cause that will always bring the shortest time. Yet if one compares total years in jail, both cooperating has two, one cooperating and one defecting has three and both defecting has four. Thus on balance the two prisoners may go for the more utilitarian approach.

The Prisoner’s Dilemma is also a much more relevant model to the real world in which there is competition in many aspects of life. The most obvious

Page 15: The Axiom - Issue 3

13

John Nash: Game Theory

A:NOADVERTISING A:ADVERTISING

B:NOADVERTISING

A: 500 x £1 = £500B: 500 x £1 = £500 Total: £1,000

A: (800 x £1) - £200 = £600B: (200 x £1) = £200 Total: £800

B:ADVERTISING

A: (200 x £1) =£200B: (800 x £1) - £200 = £600Total: £800

A: (500 x £1) - £200 = £300B: (500 x £1) - £200 = £300Total: £600

area is economics and the world of business. The Prisoner’s Dilemma can serve as a stripped down example of competition between companies and their ap-proaches to matters. For example, in advertising the same situation can occur. If we take simplistic approach of a real situation, there are two chocolate pro-ducing companies in a town of 1,000 people. The chocolate bars they produce are practically the same and if they were to just sell both of them as they were, 500 would buy from ‘Chocolatiers’ and 500 would buy from ‘Dairy Dunk’. Here both sides would make equal amounts of money. However, the two companies have the option of spending money on advertising and increasing the popularity of their chocolate, creating a greater turnover. This of course would take away customers from the other company, so that company may feel the need to invest in advertising as well. If one chocolate bar cost £1 and adverting costs £200, the situation below arises.

This table demonstrates a similar situation to the Prisoner’s Dilemma. ‘De-fecting’ or advertising in this situation will always create a better outcome for the individual. They can choose to have £600/£300 or have £500/£200, with the other company’s decision fixing whether or not you have the larger amount. Nevertheless, the two companies are in the best overall position if they both choose to not advertise.

The Nash Equilibrium and the Prisoner’s Dilemma are two models which are both relevant to our lives. It would be good if we could live in a world of Nash Equilibriums and we could always cooperate to have the best outcome. Yet unfortunately we often have to deal with Prisoner’s Dilemmas. The fun-damental difference is that we can communicate with other parties. We can negotiate to try and work out the best outcome. We are not robots who will always do what is best for just us; we can take into account the effect we have on other people. Therefore whether we are the kind of people to defect or not, understanding these two examples and the long term consequences connected to them informs us to help us make the right decisions.

Page 16: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Axiom

14

THE LIMITS OF THE

LAWWords by Giannis Giortzis

Page 17: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Limits of the Law

15

Discussion One:A Case for Legal Paternalism

What are the limits of the Law? Which principle should guide Government intervention in our everyday lives, and where is it necessary to draw the line? In these discussions, we will aim to exhibit some of the key philosophies which attempt to answer the above questions, introducing the arguments in favour and against each theory.

Page 18: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Limits of the Law

16

The Oxford Companion to Philosophy defines paternalism as “the power or authority one person or institution

exercises over another to confer benefits or prevent harm for the latter regardless of the latter’s informed consent.” Seeing that this is an extremely vague definition, those attempting to use the term more precisely have, in essence, formed a spectrum with different variants of the notion used in specific circumstances. These include soft versus hard, broad versus narrow, weak versus strong, pure versus impure, mor-al versus welfare, and old versus new. Within these variants, the threshold above which the state should act is entirely debatable, especially in cases where scientific evidence either for or against is inconclusive.

Distinction is made between the people af-fected by paternalist action and the aspect of their welfare that is to be affected. Paternalism’s target(s) can be divided into two categories – pure and impure – where “pure” paternalism is supposed to benefit the person restricted or reg-ulated under the law (such as a ban on underage alcohol and tobacco use that benefits the con-sumers themselves), whereas “impure” refers to situations where individuals other than those who are controlled are benefitted by this mea-sure (such as mandatory licensing of medical practitioners that benefits future patients). Sim-ilarly, theorists also attempt to distinguish be-tween moral and welfare paternalism, where the moral side focuses on the public’s moral welling being, whereas the welfare side is directed to-wards improving the material, or physiological, aspect of our lives. The two often complement each other – a ban on prostitution could be made on the grounds that an escort undermines his/

her mental health and self-respect by selling his/her body, whereas sexual intercourse may also lead to physical abuse or sexually transmitted diseases being transferred from one participant to the other. A ban could therefore be warranted under both variants.

Variations of PaternalismSoft paternalism, for starters, is the belief that the state should only be able to intervene in af-fairs if the affected individual is involuntarily misinformed or ignorant on the matter. Hence, intervention is justified by the fact that the state is, ideally, protecting the individual from a harm that he/she didn’t know and most certainly did not consent to. On the contrary, “hard” pater-nalism involves an action even if the person is acting knowledgably, perhaps because the state considers itself more informed or accurate in the given field and/or wishes to avoid harm to come to its citizens at all costs. Examples could include the outlawing of physician-assisted sui-cide or the enforcement of the wearing of seat belts in vehicles.

As for weak/strong paternalism, it eventual-ly boils down to the means versus ends debate. “Weak” paternalists would advocate a restric-tion of access to means through which an in-dividual can eventually realise his end goal, if they are known to be ineffective if used for that purpose. This is backed up by the simple be-lief that an institution whose role is to improve the individual’s well-being would use the most effective means possible simply for the sake of maximising its efficiency and economising on time and resources. If the end result is deemed acceptable, then it could be argued that there should be nothing impeding progress towards

53921 93901 69044 67224 39733 68770 64579 43679 15843 44429 94727 94609 36250 96255 12982 47823 57845 73105 57062 43933 60651 78915 81461 01769 15741 71556 37896 69760 40534 14369 79289 57675 03344 91135 57342 61575 87929 22990 67778 23446 53107 06385 85039 30393 85893 26581 79631 90579 63315 64359 02318 30385 39755 82018 82890 12767 71392 51687 23843 72122 44647 69524 27461 26747 42197 45959 08275 10898 84404 80606 70193 86329 31642 78436 44788 17775 71884 94074 10951 54323 55492 62907 22200 35230 81758 21183 35127 34939 87167 48811 42173 52765 91870 23054 77013 05241 66161 60839 46609 79366 60668 79638 53287 61518 46952 32520 62920 49290 00525 96224 82521

24947 73800 67013 22247 75838 25476 64051 92535 44010 79958 29902 10309 36080 29565 65805 59610 04761 31215 55730 58464 90245 42650 47654 19020 97669 79058 27672 54479 29026 15806 67487 15669 67166 87781 57814 83854 68287 40682 13904 67694 27809 51774 59820 81094 86314 67725 76296 25700 34225 39582 11451 17842 91740 45553 09456 56656 94021 03759 68977 73451 04671 90634 46067 80985 34559 34820 44157 14816 57162 38608 28858 17169 58496 15443 47147 17468 37130 67595 48487 67748 85808 57871 52804 52544 45185 14554 00990 77754 62950 81187 75475 30309 83715 00921 63396 73550 74023 20792 65361 38198 56821 64290 88393 77520 34003 89763 76817 57525 73830 19258 20025 81510 26027 05890 15776 50741 43699 96094 31568 75063 73190 13957 51137 39703 54348 50125 49547 23327 01638 55657 41076 13665 71062 37313 81467 23947 48016 44140 19101 17652 51658 04943 86331 54249 62629 14669 95839 17451 38490 99874 71792 19924 10890 08377 21531 72208 39399 15256 26033 08218 86493 76486 29057 95218 59625 40238 05015 74916 87847 49595 14067 79716 41442 56177 00893 14434 31033 74926 49945 42376 05488 47535 72035 26522 45033 22204 06079 81403 63983 02277 61020 68141 50686 48044 14240 60444 06283 01398 64769 78379 87206 77957 75093 73326 18306 88079 82986 41139 82175 45839 62020 38076 38912 47662 14024 75684 74970 96215 51877 76519 38293 93829 16289 70249 27861 35251 47577 79950 57624 30296 43554 45908 07280 68740 85602 14543 84040 25497 68674 36610 61273 16136 87598 96159 56528 42717 90118 81855 20030 27876 63574 14244 48193 15465 81365 97545 26948 00024 72273 60759 69740 25941 32640 07957 87636 47625 72106 73953 32727 35323 67734 37482 19929 34353 33570 60205 44225 60727 55269 17620 69944 62858 63033 62376 58179 19922 94687 74606 54079 39081 00678 46811 45451 00140 77359 59030 82174 66081 91617 57146 32510 66116 02434 73929 52411 31428 23141 78142 01482 91477 44880 96088 28685 48764 37625 41174 25032 16172 79213 37680 27111 83068 26615 37800 60583 71192 08568 15305 35668 98368 07610 51991 79393 46318 22097 57424 53436 75856 13835 07837 86370 00208 23013 21031

Page 19: The Axiom - Issue 3

53921 93901 69044 67224 39733 68770 64579 43679 15843 44429 94727 94609 36250 96255 12982 47823 57845 73105 57062 43933 60651 78915 81461 01769 15741 71556 37896 69760 40534 14369 79289 57675 03344 91135 57342 61575 87929 22990 67778 23446 53107 06385 85039 30393 85893 26581 79631 90579 63315 64359 02318 30385 39755 82018 82890 12767 71392 51687 23843 72122 44647 69524 27461 26747 42197 45959 08275 10898 84404 80606 70193 86329 31642 78436 44788 17775 71884 94074 10951 54323 55492 62907 22200 35230 81758 21183 35127 34939 87167 48811 42173 52765 91870 23054 77013 05241 66161 60839 46609 79366 60668 79638 53287 61518 46952 32520 62920 49290 00525 96224 82521

24947 73800 67013 22247 75838 25476 64051 92535 44010 79958 29902 10309 36080 29565 65805 59610 04761 31215 55730 58464 90245 42650 47654 19020 97669 79058 27672 54479 29026 15806 67487 15669 67166 87781 57814 83854 68287 40682 13904 67694 27809 51774 59820 81094 86314 67725 76296 25700 34225 39582 11451 17842 91740 45553 09456 56656 94021 03759 68977 73451 04671 90634 46067 80985 34559 34820 44157 14816 57162 38608 28858 17169 58496 15443 47147 17468 37130 67595 48487 67748 85808 57871 52804 52544 45185 14554 00990 77754 62950 81187 75475 30309 83715 00921 63396 73550 74023 20792 65361 38198 56821 64290 88393 77520 34003 89763 76817 57525 73830 19258 20025 81510 26027 05890 15776 50741 43699 96094 31568 75063 73190 13957 51137 39703 54348 50125 49547 23327 01638 55657 41076 13665 71062 37313 81467 23947 48016 44140 19101 17652 51658 04943 86331 54249 62629 14669 95839 17451 38490 99874 71792 19924 10890 08377 21531 72208 39399 15256 26033 08218 86493 76486 29057 95218 59625 40238 05015 74916 87847 49595 14067 79716 41442 56177 00893 14434 31033 74926 49945 42376 05488 47535 72035 26522 45033 22204 06079 81403 63983 02277 61020 68141 50686 48044 14240 60444 06283 01398 64769 78379 87206 77957 75093 73326 18306 88079 82986 41139 82175 45839 62020 38076 38912 47662 14024 75684 74970 96215 51877 76519 38293 93829 16289 70249 27861 35251 47577 79950 57624 30296 43554 45908 07280 68740 85602 14543 84040 25497 68674 36610 61273 16136 87598 96159 56528 42717 90118 81855 20030 27876 63574 14244 48193 15465 81365 97545 26948 00024 72273 60759 69740 25941 32640 07957 87636 47625 72106 73953 32727 35323

46154 52475 87872 93124 04223 29024 37826 12601 80742 63656 97274 31587 03580 08245 79121 64478 19612 94753 86831 22108 05088 16012 33619 85940 89142 72389 43501 19900 33883 94251 63180 56833 20930 01387 32083 51546 99724 14328 75483 60267 01252 39211 50534 45547 86819 54002 72761 50302 13900 34092 79286 40314 06874 54002 68731 48480 31274 60774 73949 53736 55469 46354 22515 81794 13456 25887 66249 80466 78916 12504 76452 11068 96276 96248

The Limits of the Law

17

it. An oft cited example refers to how a medical institution will advise, if not force, a patient to not use a certain drug which has already been proven will not cure him. The debate here lies at which the Government judges intervention to be necessary. To illustrate: should the Govern-ment actively prevent us from taking sugar pills to cure cancer, because it is empirically compre-hending the gravity of the situation better than the patient? Should it just inform us on how they (fail to) work, explain the placebo effect and let us move on with our lives, respecting our per-sonal convictions more than our health? Should it take no measures at all and let us research our treatment at our own will and expense?

Meanwhile, “strong” paternalists pride themselves in interfering with peoples’ ends, if they are thought to not be acting in a rational way in striving for them. An example could be the censorship of pro-suicide media, by assum-ing that no rational human would pursue suicide without having first been influenced in part by external factors highlighting the existence or benefits of such an option. Advocates sneer at the “slippery slope” argument where the oppo-sition asks whether it’s appropriate to potential-ly blow something out of proportion in order to bring conformity (such as the NHS’s gruesome advertisements against smoking): for them, the ends usually justify the means, and shocking the target individuals is the only way to overcome denial.

Unfortunately, scenarios like these are high-ly contentious and too broad to be generalised, especially when sentimentality and personal experience enter the debate. To provide anoth-er scenario, what happens when someone suf-fering from a terminal illness under great pain

wishes to commit suicide? Has the meaning of life, which is so extraordinarily unique and valu-able in the eyes of greater society, been lost after years of suffering? Whose role is it to determine who decides the outcome of such an important decision, with profound personal, religious and political effects? At this stage, an observer would just have to agree that with something rather shocking for philosophy: that one size fits none and that no number of theories on human ratio-nale can possible begin to comprehend the com-plexity of each individual situation.

CriticismIn our increasingly liberal western democracies, it really is no wonder that paternalist policies, especially when involving legal coercion, are of-ten divisive.

One of the most prominent arguments against the “nanny-state” is Mill’s First argu-ment, which, consistent with his liberal ideals, is largely of a consequentialist nature. In his trea-tise “On Liberty” (1859), he argues that the max-imum possible utility (satisfaction) arises from when an individual has the freedom to carve his own path in life, achieving his goals in the way that he/she best sees fit. Other philosophers, such as Feinberg, also utilise similar ideas of ma-turity, personal sovereignty and autonomy when attacking aspects of Paternalism. Coupled to this concept of rightness of action is that, by doing so, a person will be able to develop his own sense of moral and cultural autonomy, rendering him more responsible (and hopefully also allowing him to learn from his mistakes). However, this argument makes a critical assumption that does not always apply in the real world – that all hu-mans are experts in every field that is relevant to

Page 20: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Limits of the Law

18

their lives. If that was so, there would be little demand for lawyers, or doctors, or teachers, or any other profession whose role it is to advise or teach the in-dividual in order to directly or indirectly improve his well-being! Additionally, we could consider the fact that life is to short and unique to waste “learning from past mistakes” (or missed opportunities), especially when they may have a long-lasting effect on our lives and, in the long run, have a detrimental effect on out utility. Knowingly allowing others to make them, in the eyes of paternalists, is unacceptable when we have an opportunity to intervene and share our own acquired knowledge on the issue. This claim, however, raises even deeper philo-sophical questions about fate and if we can avoid or alter it. Should a third party be making that decision for us without our say?

In response to the argument above, Goodin raises the question of current vs. future self. Under his proposition, the state should reserve the right to in-tervene where people’s preferences are short-lived or temporary, rather than permanent (or “settled”). According to this principle, some activities, such as the habitual consumption of alcohol or illegal drugs, induce a temporary sense of utility, which, however, is most definitely inverted as the person grows older and starts to suffer from the negative impacts of the substances, notably health issues and social isolation. By this logic, Government regulation is justified by asserting that someone’s future self would be more satisfied with the outcome if he was prevented from going down this road in the first place, if the utility lost in the future outweighs the satisfaction gained in the present. But, surely, all in-dividuals must be rational and understand the consequences of their actions in

Page 21: The Axiom - Issue 3

19

The Limits of the Law

the first place? Not necessarily, as a lack of education on the matter, poor living conditions, peer pressure, denial, the status quo bias, and a plethora of other reasons may lead to a person indulging in activities which grant him short-term pleasure regardless of possible future dangers. Since these become increasingly incurable and irreversible as time goes by, Goodin advocates both “soft” and “hard” rapid paternalist action in order to prevent this process of gradual decay from starting in the first place, which, we can extrapolate, would have a net utility loss on the individual.

Further arguments against paternalism include the so-called “moral haz-ard”, where one party involved in a transaction is prepared to take more risks, knowing in advance that these will impact the other. Critics of paternalism use the example of someone taking less care of his property if he is legally obliged to fully insure it, as he knows that the insurance company will eventually foot the bill. Even though this does seem compliant with human nature, nowadays, this is becoming a non-issue in the real world, as companies engage in stringent checks and offer full reimbursement only under certain conditions to prevent people from exploiting the system, which links to the conditionality of welfare as mentioned above. Besides, the satisfaction gained from getting reimbursed (and cheating the system) may not always compensate for that lost during the period which your property is damaged.

Finally, opponents of this public policy are quick to remind us that the state is a large, anonymous institution which in no way knows what will give you the most satisfaction. As obvious as that may sound the first time, the state does in fact know, and in a relatively objective manner (through statistics and polls), what the most important nationwide aggregate problems faced by the populace are. But, unlike many individuals, paternalists see the state as actually having the power and clout to deal with them. It may introduce, for instance, a junk food tax and public information campaigns in order to reduce obesity levels, or it may impose an income management scheme to ensure that all parents are providing as much as needed for their children in response to rises in child de-linquency or abuse. Such general concerns of the electorate are therefore often reflected and (re)acted upon at the highest echelons of power, even if relying solely on a possibly inefficient or corrupt administration to cater for one’s needs is naïve, considering the fact that government policy does not always benefit the majority or address smaller local issues.

In conclusion, liberal democracies have certain preconceived notions, such as that human dignity is to be respected, that all humans should have the right to life and good health, and that unemployment is a negative which should be minimised. It is also reasonable to consider that someone will gain more utility in the long term by having a stable source of income, high job satisfaction, social links with friends/family, a roof over his head, good health, and a vision for the future. Therefore, if the government uses legal paternalism responsibly as part of a public policy in order to realise these aims and deliver a higher standard of living to its peoples by accounting for all of the aforementioned issues, then its policies seem to be justified both economically and psychologically.

After all, satisfaction may just equally arise from living a comfortable, safe, promising life.

This series will be continued in the next issue of The Axiom, by exploring the argu-ments for and against Mill’s Harm Principle.

Page 22: The Axiom - Issue 3

The Axiom

20

DOES SATAN OFFER

THE ANSWERS?

Words by Blake Jones

Page 23: The Axiom - Issue 3

21

Does Satan Offer the Answers?

Do you believe in God? Do you believe in the Devil? Two separate questions which commonly have two different answers. Belief in God could come about because of the prejudices we have of the world, but by that standard, belief in Satan is much more likely and would be much more dominant. Humans regard God and Satan in two different ways, but they suggest that humans are so desperate for Satan to exist. One can say that the idea of God came about from the need to avoid responsibility, the way to control the people, the vessel for human qualities and the explanation of why the universe was created. However after all of those factors, why didn’t we think of the Devil?

Page 24: The Axiom - Issue 3

Does Satan Offer the Answers?

22

Sigmund Freud wrote in The Future of an Illusion, ‘the gods retain their threefold task: they must exorcise the terrors of nature, they must reconcile men to the cruel-

ty of fate, particularly as it is shown in death, and they must compensate them for the sufferings and privations which a civilized life in common has imposed on them.’ Freud was amongst many who felt that the belief in God was something which naturally came about due to the need humans have to be-lieve in a Holy Being. Yet he disagreed. This is used as a criticism of theism due to the idea that faiths came about because we want-ed to have a God.

However, whilst there may be good reason to suggest this, it comes more naturally to believe in the Devil than God. If one was to survey the world, there would be more people believing in God than in the Devil, though plenty believe in God. The Devil is a horrible figure and obviously should never be worshipped, but the simple belief in Satan is a more natural one and is a more ap-pealing one to humans. Thus Freud’s argument becomes redun-dant.

Belief in Satan or Iblis often comes as a consequence of belief in God, particularly in Christianity and Islam. However, there are plenty of Christians who avoid believing in the Devil and both the ideas of Demons and God come from different places, long before Christianity. All the same, the way Christians look at Satan and God reveals what our attitudes are really like. The Christian view of God predominantly comes from the Bible. Christians think of God as the All-powerful, All-loving and All-knowing Being and the image of Him and His qualities are nearly always the ones de-scribed by Jesus and other Biblical prophets. Very few Christians think of God as the bearded man on the fluffy white cloud, which is how human art and popular culture has described Him.

Compare this to the Devil, whom is immediately thought of and commonly believed to be the horned red figure holding a pitchfork. Christians who believe in the Devil may believe that he is the cherub-like figure, or the serpent in the Garden of Eden, or the creature who had a wager with God, but those are not the most central ideas about Satan, even if they are the main ideas from the Bible. The more common Christian beliefs of Sa-tan come from John Milton’s Paradise Lost and the artwork of William Blake. The view of the Devil has a much greater human influence leading to the image of the winged beast with a tail. Therefore, the beliefs in the Devil come from human ideas and feelings much more than beliefs about God do. This means that the idea of Satan is controlled more easily by what humans want and thus the entire idea is reflective of human’s preconceived notions and what they want to believe in

However the most significant question is ‘why do we want to believe in Satan?’ One can take any reason why someone would want to believe in God or even impose the belief in God, without actually knowing God existed, and by that same reason believing in Satan is even more compelling. Sigmund Freud suggested that belief in God was a way to avoid responsibility for our actions. We are able to not worry about the future since someone else is in

Page 25: The Axiom - Issue 3

23

Does Satan Offer the Answers?

control and God will look after us. Whilst this may be something which has increased belief in God, belief in Satan is the ultimate way of avoiding responsibility. We do not need to take responsi-bility for our actions since they were right and good, or the Devil is the reason why we did wrong. This frees us from all responsi-bility and lets us keep avoiding the harsh realities of life, since we can blame it all on one figure.

Civilisations can be criticised for using God as a way to con-trol the people. If laws such as “thou shalt not kill” and “thou shalt not steal” are in place and have an eternal consequence if they are broken, people are much more likely to follow them. However the Devil or negative reinforcement has always been a way of controlling people. From a young age we were told stories of the bogeyman and the horrible things that would happen to us if we were naughty, and it worked well. In contrast to positive re-inforcement, children are told that Father Christmas will reward them if they are good, but this is a less effective system. Children are not good to get presents at Christmas, instead presents are just expected at that time of year. In a larger scale, belief in God to make people do good becomes less effective, since going by Christian doctrine on the Atonement of Christ, there is no lon-ger a need to do good. Instead using the fear of the Devil taking your soul and you becoming prisoner to him if you submit to his temptation, controls the people much better. Therefore if peo-ple were looking for a supernatural idea to control the people, it would make much more sense to go to an evil one and thus Satan is more likely to be created than God.

Furthermore, God can be seen as the best and most desir-able qualities we have put into an Entity. We take the idea that humans are loving and make God All-loving. Our hope for these qualities leads us to create God who amplifies these traits and helps us in our hope to reach them. Yet in the same way we put our worst qualities into the figure of the Devil. He personifies de-ceitfulness, temptation and chaos, all of which we want to avoid. In Buddhism the closest figure to Satan is Mara, whose main traits are unwholesome impulses and unskillfulness. Again what we fear or want to avoid is put into this figure. This is demon-strated by the different ways God and Satan are described. God is someone very close to humans, His Son lived in a human body and humans receive part of God inside us through the Holy Spir-it. Satan however is a serpent, lying in the dirt amongst the oth-er beasts, and when he contacts us it is just through thoughts or ideas suggested to us, or often through other ways in the physical world. This underlines how humans have put their best and most hopeful side into God and allowed the very worst of us to be con-sumed by Satan.

This is because we can have a source of these qualities to blame for them appearing in us. More importantly though, Satan is more effective than God in this incidence, for rather than have a Being who can help us as we work towards being like Him, we have an enemy to fight, who we have to do all we can to be the opposite of. Ergo, regarding human hopes effecting what we believe in, the hu-man desire for an enemy is what endures and that is why humans

Page 26: The Axiom - Issue 3

“Man is the cruelest animal. When gazing at tragedies, bull-fights, crucifixations he hath hitherto felt happier than at any other time on Earth. And when he invented Hell...lo, Hell was his Heaven on Earth"; he could put up with suffering now, by contemplating the eternal punishment of his oppressors in the other world.”

- Nietzsche

Does Satan Offer the Answers?

24

are more likely to create Satan than create God.Finally, it is commonly said that people believe in

God since we wanted an explanation as to why we are here and how it could be done. We are said to have gone to God for this explanation, and now as science offers other reasons atheism grows. However why would we think that it was God who created us, since that has the underlying assumption that the creation of the world was a kind thing. I personally am grateful that we ex-ist rather than not exist, yet if one was to look at the majority of the world, there would probably be a pref-erence for the world never being created. Therefore it makes much more sense that humans would assume that an evil being in the form of the Devil created this world as a way of inflicting pain on us, not the All-lov-ing God in order to give us a gift. As a result of this, the ancient tribe would have created demons to hate and blame for bringing us here; God would have nothing to do with it.

In conclusion, whilst humans could have created God as a way to cope with whatever challenges they were facing, it is much more likely that the Devil would have been created from this. Human nature tends to-wards believing in Satan before others, yet this is not the case. Therefore the idea that we believe in God as a response to the world we live is invalid. If our be-liefs were truly based on instinctive human nature, we would have religions based on the Devil and not God. Thus the idea of God could not simply come about because human nature required it; at heart humans would require a belief in Satan instead.

Page 27: The Axiom - Issue 3

25

The Axiom

A STUDY OF TRIALISM

Words by Tomas Brown

Page 28: The Axiom - Issue 3

A Study of Trialism

26

We were recently priv-ileged enough to hear John

Cottingham speak for the school’s Edmund society; but what was this trial-

ism he talked about? Is it really legitimate to say that the mind is split into three separate

parts? Does it solve the problem of mind body interaction, does it even sort out the prob-

lems that it sets out to? Here I provide a brief expose for the new awkward

dualist on the topic.

Page 29: The Axiom - Issue 3

27

A Study of Trialism

‘Nature also teaches me by these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst etc., that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am very closely united to it.’ In 1985, Cottingham published

an article in the journal MIND, tackling the two main problems with Cartesian dualism;

These problems had led Descartes to some very tricky positions. He for exam-ple was forced to consider animals as having no sensations and being just au-tomatons, because he ascribed to the categorization of sensations as a kind of thinking, and he didn’t want animals to think in the same way as humans. Per-haps introducing a third category of substance, a completely new kind of being, can avoid the problems which arise when we try to jam matter into either a mental or physical type of thing?

Trialism essentially attempts to solve this by sprinting all the substances in the world into three domains. Traditional Cartesian dualism invokes the con-cept of body, an extended, changing, and unthinking substance, which is com-pletely separate from the second substance of the Mind, the unextended, think-ing substance. Imagine, for example, a mouse; a mouse has a body - a tail, claws, a pair of whiskers, and so on. It also has the thing which tells the mouse what to do, sees where the cheese is, moves the legs in a scampering motion and so on. This dualistic theory has a big problem; what happens to the parts of us which ‘bridge the gap’?

Does this solve our two problems? Firstly, can it counteract the challenge that it is impossible for mental operations to ‘not require any place or depend on any material thing’? Certainly. The doctrine places the sensation as a class of it’s own, between the physical and the mental, at once relying on physical causes - Descartes describes sensation as being dependent upon things outside himself - and a mental event. Trialism gives a physicalist basis for thought and sensation, while retaining the central quality of dualism between a mental and physical realm - in other words, trialism gives an avenue for solving this problem which is not reliant on the reductionist methods of behaviourists or identity theorists.

Secondly, can it counteract the problem of what we consider physical sen-

(1) the challenge that it is impossible for mental operations to ‘not require any place or depend on any material thing’

(2) the problem of what to consider sensations to be; are they part of the mind or are they a physical product of the body.

If I sit down in a car, there are a number of things informing me. While I have purely mental thoughts, like ‘I am going to sit in this chair’, there are a number of mental entities, sensations, which aren’t just mental. I feel the heat of the car heat-er, the hardness of the seat below me, I feel the texture of the upholstery and so on. The doctrine of trialism solves this problem by making sensation a completely separate substance, something which is independent on it’s own, neither physical nor mental, but acting as a separate, smaller cog between the two realms of mental and physical.

Page 30: The Axiom - Issue 3

A Study of Trialism

28

sations to be? As we saw with the ani-mal example, this lead Descartes into trouble concerning animals and their autonomy. It is further clear that they are problematic, as sensations appear to be mental events - I feel something burn me, for example - but are actu-ally able to enforce themselves on us against our volution in ways mental thoughts generally should not be

able to. Again, we find this problem solved; by conceiving of sensation as ‘bridging the gap’ we might see that it is a process of causation, or some-thing that presents itself to us in ways which are completely apart from the mental sensations we have every day. This objection is, in short, a category mistake; sensations may not strictly be a thing.

In conclusion, we find that Trial-ism, despite what may be a precarous position when read into the texts of Descartes, allows us to circumvent both of the great problems posed by Cottingham in the opening to his pa-per. I would advise anyone who wish-es to engage in further reading to dip into Cottingham’s brilliant book enti-tled ‘The Rationalists’.

Page 31: The Axiom - Issue 3

29

Header

INSERT A GOOD TITLE HERE

Words by Tomas Brown

The Axiom

29

ARE ANIMALS

SUB-HUMAN?Words by Richard Ainslie

Page 32: The Axiom - Issue 3

3030

It seems now that human beings treat animals as very much a sub-genus to humans, one that is more there to fulfil our needs for food, pets, sport hunting and other sorts of hobbies and uses. But a question that might be dismissed by many as the ramblings of vegetable-fuelled activists from PETA is whether animals should be treated as sub-human and below us or whether we need to treat them with equal respect as we treat each other.

Are Animals Sub-human?

Page 33: The Axiom - Issue 3

Are Animals Sub-human?

31

The central definition of this issue is how we define humanity. Do we say that humanity is having intelligent thought? Emotions? Morality/choice? In this article I will address these options and also whether there

is something else that is a defining factor that splits or unites our species. First of all let it be said that biologically/evolutionarily speaking we are of course just a higher evolved creature that is only that, just a more complex brain that can pro-duce more complicated thought processes, combined with opposable thumbs and a more sophisticated voice box which allow us for using tools and using complex language. But when we come to the more developed questions in metaphysics and meta-ethics, this is why we might ask the question ‘Are animals sub-human?’, for while animals concern themselves only with base needs of eating, sleeping etc. we seem to concern ourselves with questions on finding higher meaning in life. This is the distinction that I would like to focus on in this article.

So first perhaps it could be considered that it is intelligence which gives us our humanity and that our ability to rationalise and logically reason gives us the superior aspect. At first it does seem that this facet that has given us technolo-gy, mastery of the natural world and all our infrastructure seems like something that elevates us. However, we have seen over the years that animals display in-telligence or intelligence-like behaviour. The example that is a key in this is the famous Koko the gorilla who learned a reported 1000 signs and was able to con-verse, admittedly fairly basically, seem emotive and display greater capacity for relating ideas than monkeys had before. Koko not only could interact with her owner and strangers but she could mention in ‘conversation’ objects that were absent (displacement), recognise herself in a mirror, report memories she has, talk about language itself, invent new signs for other concepts (for example while Koko did not know the sign for ‘ring’ she started calling it ‘finger bracelet’, com-bining these two ideas) and using counterfactual statements for humour, which suggests an understanding of other minds. While it is only monkeys who can show this level of sophistication of thought, other animals also show varying de-grees of intelligence. There are many species of animals that can learn to navigate mazes, Gordon setters can remember where they found dead animals up to a year afterwards and elephants can associate names with people. So in fact intelligence is not a wholly unique human quality and we must look elsewhere.

So perhaps then it is our emotions that define us as a species. We do seem to have much more complex emotional responses to others ranging from basic ones such as happiness, sadness and embarrassment to complicated ones such as love, schadenfreude and deep empathy. This huge range of emotions at face value do seem exceptional when we compare it to animals. However, another remarkable aspect of Koko is that she showed a desire to have a pet and then, having chosen a pet cat, she cared for it as if a baby gorilla and she was very loving towards it. When the cat got run over and Koko was told about it, she signed ‘bad sad frown cry cry sad’. Other animals show huge devotion to their family group and dogs have been known to lay down their lives for their owners. So once again emotion and complex emotion is not unique to us.

Finally when we examine our sense of morality and choice it appears we have found a much more convincing candidate. Our perceived sense of what is right and wrong and how we largely subscribe to these, as well as how we choose de-cisions freely. These are in fact things that we have and animals don't as animals don't stop to consider whether they should or shouldn't kill the gazelle in front of

Page 34: The Axiom - Issue 3

32

Are Animals Sub-human?

them because it may be morally dubious. Neither will an animal choose to oppose the mass consensus of its family group/pack and go it alone whereas humans may well do this. The issue here may not be whether our morality and choices make us different from animals but whether we have these at all. Firstly because mo-rality certainly does not seem objective as it is so varied from culture to culture which suggests that it is a purely human social construct, perhaps to enforce law and keep people in check, after all society would dissolve if no one had a problem with killing each other. Also, our choices, as many psychologists would argue, are so influenced by our social groups and our surroundings that most of our choices are determined by others anyway and our idea of free will is not really real. While I do not want to be weighing the validity of determinism or moral objectivity it must be considered that these are not actual higher functions that humans hold at all, they are just extensions of the social structures that animals have, much as a wolf will be chastised for not helping the group, if we choose ‘morally wrong’ actions then we are chastised.

Therefore, it seems that in conclusion we must look back to the cold evolu-tionary view that we really are just another species of monkey whose brain is a bit better at processing and that there is not objective standard by which we can judge our species as superior, and that we can say ‘animals are sub-human’ as ‘human’ is nothing too special at all. But before we cast our sense of value into the abyss and settle for a very nihilistic depression, it might be considered that while there is nothing objectively superior about humans, it is our subjective values and opinions which are able to give more meaning to our lives. This I feel is what gives us greater value, our ability to place more than just scientific value on our ideas and beliefs which can mean more to us than just cold hard facts and it is these ideas which allow us to find higher meaning in life, something which animals just don't have.

Page 35: The Axiom - Issue 3

33

The Axiom

COULD YOU WAKE

UP IN A DIFFERENT

BODY?Words by Tomas Brown

Page 36: The Axiom - Issue 3

34

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

‘One morning, when Gregor

Samsa woke from troubled dreams,

he found himself transformed in his bed

into a horrible vermin. He lay on his armour like back, and

if he lifted his head a little he could see his brown belly,

slightly domed and divided by arches into stiff sections.’

-Kafka, Metamorphosis

Page 37: The Axiom - Issue 3

35

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

For Gregor Samsa to retain his identity for us to call him ‘Gregor Samsa’ and for him finding himself in a different body to be feasi-ble there are two necessary conditions: (a) that the subject (Samsa)

retains a constant identity which we can refrence him by before and after his transformation and (b) that the subject’s physicality changed independent of this constant identity. Broadly, in any transformation there must be ‘identity’, which is transitive1 over time and does not change ensuring ‘you’ stay ‘you’; and ‘body’, which is what transforms independently of identity.

We wake up unwittingly to find ourselves in different bodies every morn-ing under these principles; a day sees a turnover of at least 170,000 cells. We incrementally change physicality constantly, so if we make identity or the ‘self ’ distinct from physicality, the approach of a substance dualist and the view the question presupposes then we find ourselves waking up in a different body every morning2 . In the following, I consider the critiques of such a dualist ap-proach to identity.

If we adopt a dualist approach, we must specify how identity is attached to the self. Locke approaches this by attaching ‘identity’ to the concept of memory or consciousness of experience. He tells the story of a Prince who has his soul swapped with a Cobbler; his experiences and his memories transferred into the Cobbler’s body. According to Locke, X at T2 is the same person as Y at T1 if X is able to have consciousness of Y’s experiences/memories. Therefore as X (the Cobbler) has the same experiences and memories as Y (the Prince), the Prince has retained his identity though he is in the Cobbler’s body, as he has his past experiences, memories and awareness. Here both the original criteria of (a) and (b) we established are satisfied, as the subject has retained a constant identity, and has changed physicality independently of this identity. Therefore, under Locke’s scheme, it is possible to wake up in a different body, given that we retain consciousness of experiences and memories.

One objection to identity being attached to mental ‘consciousness of ex-perience’ extends from Thomas Nagel’s ‘What is it Like to be a Bat?’. It is impossible, he says, to know what it is like to be another thing if we don’t have identical consciousness of experiences this, for example, is why we can’t know what it is like to be a bat, as we are not aware of what the use of echolocation is like or a bat’s other experiences. Should we attempt to know batness, say, by slowly metamorphosing ourselves into a bat, by the end of the process we would not have the same conscious experiences which iden-tify us with ourselves; rather we would have a bat’s. Here Locke’s theory is challenged. Even if our mental selves were transferred into a different body, we could say that we are not the same ‘us’. The difference in what experi-ences we are conscious of ( just as a seeing man might be aware of colour in a way a blind man might not be) would render us subtly different people just as we are not the same person mentally after we metamorphosize into the

1 Transitivity being the principle iff X = Y and Y = Z, then Z = X, so if Gregor’s identity at time T1 is the same as time T2, and at T2 is the same as T3, then Gregor’s identity at time T1 is retained through to time T3.2 Assuming the ‘strict and philosophical’ qualitative view of identity taken by Joseph Butler and RoderickChisholm, where a thing has continuous identity iff X at time T1 has the same properties as X at time T2.

Page 38: The Axiom - Issue 3

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

36

mind of a bat. Therefore, we can’t keep identity as constant on the basis of consciousness of experiences, as we find that there is a link between what we experience from our physicality and who we are.

A further criticism extends from Locke’s linking of memory to constant identity. If the Cobbler can refer to the same memories as the Prince, he argues, he must be the same mental individual. Reid provides retort to this with his ‘Brave Officer’ example. If an Officer remembers a whipping he had as a Boy, we may say under Locke’s principle that him and the Boy are the same. If an old General remembers his career as an Officer, we may say also that he and the Officer are the same person. However, if the old General can’t recall the beat-ing he had as a Boy, we can’t say that he is the same person, and this weakens memory as a principle of constant identity. Identity is not in Locke’s scheme transitive over time, as if the General has no shared memory with the boy, they can’t have the same identity. If identity can’t be transitive, relating consistently to all points, it can’t be a basis for a constant identity to retain being ‘us’ after waking up in a different body.

Having explored Locke’s idea of attaching a constant identity to either mem-ory or conception of experience (and found it unfruitful), we shall now explore whether there is even a ‘self ’ to attach identity to or transfer to a different body. Let us engage in a thought experiment to pursue this, and produce a synopsis of ourselves. For example:

First, strip away our likes or dislikes, as they are not us ourselves, merely things that ‘selves’ participate in:

Second,strip away our physical position, since we are attempting to find our purely mental self:

Third, strip away our emotional quality and dispositions, since emotion is some-thing we participate in, not something which I myself am.

(i) ‘I am Tomas Brown, I’m a sixth form student who enjoys philosophy and debating - I consider myself a calm person’.

(ii) ‘I am Tomas Brown, I’m a sixth form student who enjoys philosophy and debating - I consider myself a calm person’.

(iii) ‘I am Tomas Brown, I’m a sixth form student who enjoys philosophy and debating - I consider myself a calm person’.

(iv) ‘I am Tomas Brown, I’m a sixth form student who enjoys philosophy and debating - I consider myself a calm person’.

Page 39: The Axiom - Issue 3

37

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

The synopsis of the self we are left with is ‘I am Tomas Brown’ does not express anything about the self, given that it is only another term of reference for my-self3 . From this and similar attempts, we may find that the ‘self ’ is inexpress-ible. Russell affirms a similar view that we aren’t acquainted with our actual mental self, only our sensations and thoughts. It becomes evident, due to it’s inexpressibility, that we might question its existence at all. A verificationist ap-proach affirms that we can’t have positive or negative verification for a mental self (as we can’t be acquainted with it directly), it must be a meaningless and unrealisable concept. From this point, we question if it is possible for us to find ourselves in a different body if there is no self to fulfil our first criteria of (a) and be a constant point of identification in both our initial and our different body. Without a constant identity, we could not possibly wake up to find ourselves in a different body.

A retort to be made of this view might be that we feel emotions that per-tain to a self, and we have the concept of ownership of one’s body, pertaining to a self. In the opening quote of this essay, Samsa clearly sees his brown belly, and his armour like back. We however would reply that the mental concept of the self is merely an illusion as it derived from our physical concept of the self, and therefore can’t constitute a literal ground for transferring identity from one body to another. We always have immediate evidence for the conception of my physical self; I look down at my legs, and I know that they are mine; I can feel the keys of my laptop under my fingers; I am aware of them in space and their

3 Given a minimalist scheme of reference where X = Y iff X is the same as Y.

Page 40: The Axiom - Issue 3

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

38

location in relevance to me. I am aware broadly of the physical thing that is me, and can give an accurate description of what it is to be me down to the atomic level. In reference to this, it is proposed, the term ‘self ’ was created with defi-nite intent to our physicality.

The concept of a mental self arguably comes from an extension of this con-cept into the mind. As I know I have legs, arms in the physical world, I assume that I have some sort of equivalent in the mental world the self. However, we already know from our thought experiment, that we don’t have any immediate evidence for the concept of the self we can’t be acquainted with it, only thought and sense we find it impossible to directly describe it at all. Therefore, as we don’t have the same relation to the mental self as the physical self, the mental self becomes a referenceless condition, corresponding to nothing. When we say ‘I woke up in a different body’, what we are saying is meaningless, as ‘I’ is refer-enceless, and as such we find no constant identity that we can be taken from the

first body to the body we transfer into.However, some may counter the possibility that a physi-

cally based identity can still be transferred into a different body by abandoning the dualist approach. The paradox of the ship of Theseus, when tackled from the point of perdurantism (specifically stage theory), demonstrates

how an object, although it may change its physicality, can maintain its identity without resorting to untenable dual-

ism. It proceeds as such. The ship of Theseus is to be pre-served for a thousand years via the progressive

renovation of one plank per year. By the end of the thousand years, the ship will have none of its original physicality left, consisting of only renovated planks. Stage theorists such as Tim Sider argue that despite this change in physi-cality, the ship is still the ship of Theseus, be-cause the ship is composed of temporal parts, which extend across the fourth dimension of time. Working under the principle of numeri-

cal identity4, Sider argues if we examine slices of time between the renovation of each plank,

we will find the ship numerically identical to how it was last year, although it’s physicality has changed. Therefore, it is possible to have a changing physicality but still retain a constant

identity.Applying this to the possibility of being

able to wake up in a different body, we may find that it is indeed possible. While

we must cede that waking up in an en-tirely different body, as Samsa does in

Metamorphosis, is not possible as our current body is not numerical-

Page 41: The Axiom - Issue 3

39

Could You Wake Up in a Different Body?

ly identical to a beetle’s and thereby can’t transfer identity, we may say that the gradual biological turnover of cells allows us to wake up in a ‘different body’ while retaining our concept of identity. As with the ship of Theseus, where a ship is numerically identical despite changing physically because it retains its planks at all times, we may say that our physical self is numerically identical despite changing our physicality over time, and becoming a ‘different body’ in constitution but not form. Therefore, we may say that in this strict sense, it is possible to wake up in a different body while retaining our identity.

In conclusion, the possibility of being able to wake up in a different body ne-cessitates two things: (a) that there is constant identity which we can reference someone by before and after their metamorphosis and (b) that the subject’s physicality changes independent of this constant identity. We have found that the possibility of a self in the terms of substance dualism, that might transfer between bodies is improbable, and even granted its existence, carrying identi-ty on basis of mental memories and consciousness of experience is impossible. However, the physical self we find can provide a consistent identity as it may withstand physical change if it is numerically identical with it’s past selves. This change we must be gradual however, and we find that while we wake every morning with a different cellular body, we may sleep sound knowing we can’t wake a beetle.

4 Objects A and B are numerically identical if there is only one thing variously called ‘A’ and ‘B’.

Page 42: The Axiom - Issue 3

40

The Axiom

DEFINING THE

A-PHYSICALWords by Blake Jones

Page 43: The Axiom - Issue 3

41

Defining the A-physical

Physical: relating to the body as opposed to the mind; relating to things perceived

through the senses as opposed to the mind; tangible or concrete. What is

the a-physical? It would be completely separate from the body or senses, yet does this mean it would be the mind or spirit?

Can we ever have anything completely separate from the body and thus is it

possible or the a-physical to exist and if so what would it be?

Page 44: The Axiom - Issue 3

Defining the A-physical

42

The a-physical by my definition is something which is totally dis-connected from the physical world and exists on its own without any influence from that which is tangible or concrete. To discover

whether this axiom is possible, one must reflect on what already exists. For the sake of this article the body and the physical exist, and our perceptions of them are valid. In addition, the mind exists. Following Descartes’ ‘cogito ergo sum’ (I think therefore I am), there is a spiritual element to this world as well; which I know exists since I can experience. However, does the mind count as something a-physical?

The brain has neurones and nerves send impulses throughout it, caus-ing the different thoughts we have. This suggests that the mind itself is only brought about by the physical and is just another process of the body. Yet, the mind could be more independent than that. The mind may act upon the physical world through nerve impulses, but the mind can still be free from control from the brain. The mind exists in a separate realm to the physical world, where it acts separately from the body. Then for the mind to have effect in this realm, the thoughts and decisions of the mind are sent to the brain so that they can take place in the physical world. This would allow the mind to be a-physical.

However, the mind is made up of thoughts. Can any thoughts be a-physi-cal? Some thoughts such as remembering what a house looked like or think-ing about something soft are physical. They exist as a result of physical ob-jects and physical experiences, thus cannot escape their physical nature. The thoughts of them may be of the mind, yet this is combined with the physical. As a result of this, the mind cannot be a-physical. It may not be solely physical, but it experiences physical things and holds physical based thoughts, mean-ing that it is part physical and part spiritual, but never a-physical. Neverthe-less, there could be some thoughts or ideas which are a-physical, allowing the a-physical to exist.

We can try to find a-physical ideas, yet they all eventually have a connec-tion to the physical. 2+2=4 is considered to be an innate and eternally true idea, which is of the mind and not physical. However, 2+2=4 has a physical root. That idea and the rest of maths itself comes from observation of the physical world. It may transcend the physical and be able to be applied to all situations both in the physical and spiritual worlds, yet its origin is physical. 2+2=4 first comes from observation of physical things and realising that the statement is true. Whilst this can be proved by non-physical means, numbers themselves come from the physical. We first observed physical things and re-alised that we could give value to them, hence numbers arose. Today, we can think about numbers in a non-physical way, yet these thoughts come from and make up the physical world, and they cannot escape their slightly physical nature. Ergo, 2+2=4 and other ideas about numbers are all at heart physical based ideas. Or at least, they are too connected to the physical world that they cannot be described as a-physical.

One potential a-physical idea is the idea of a perfect circle. Unlike other ideas which can only have a physical influence to exist. The perfect circle only exists in the physical world because humans and their minds created it. The perfect circle does not come about from nature and instead we have to think about it for it to exist. The perfect circle was originally a solely spiritual idea; the fact that it exists as a physical object is irrelevant since it was created later

Page 45: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 46: The Axiom - Issue 3

44

Defining the A-physical

due to the idea being inside our minds. However, the idea of the perfect cir-cle comes from the idea of the physical circle which may not be perfect, but still exists and prompts this idea. Whilst the idea alone of a perfect circle is a-physical, when I think of the perfect circle I am partly thinking about non perfect physical circles which I have seen, allowing this idea to be prompted. Therefore the perfect circle is not a-physical.

A conversation could be called a-physical. If two people are discussing something, the words they speak are not physical things. The sounds repre-senting them may be physical vibrations and they may be made and heard in physical ways, the idea of those words is not physical. The thought of ‘hello’ is not a physical one. It does not necessarily mean a greeting to a physical person nearby, but instead is the idea of one mind meeting another.

‘Hello’ is the closest idea we have to the a-physical, yet it cannot escape the physical. It is thought of in the mind which is closely connected to the physical. It is learnt through physical interactions or someone being taught it through physical means (talking, sound waves and hearing). It can only be used correctly if one knows the physical situation they are in (greeting an-other mind inhabiting a body), and we know to say or think this based on observing the world with physical senses and knowing that someone is there.

In conclusion, we cannot properly define the a-physical, since examples of it cannot be given. We know of nothing which is truly a-physical thus we are not able to give an example of it. The a-physical could exist, but humans are not a-physical beings and do not have an a-physical part of ourselves either. Therefore we are unable to observe the a-physical and cannot know if it ex-ists. The moment we observe or understand an a-physical idea it is no longer a-physical since it is used in a physical way.

So what do we have? In Cartesian trialism it is suggested that we have the mind, the body and a side which combines the mind and body – for example the sensation of hunger. Yet if we cannot experience the a-physical, we only have the body and the rest is a combination of the body and mind at different ratios.

Karl Popper suggested that the universe was made of three worlds. World 1, the world of material things (the pages of a book or a human hand); world 2, the subjective world of minds (memories or cognition); world 3, the world of objective knowledge or culture and ideas (art, ethics or language). How-ever the issue with this is that whilst world 3 is the predominant world of combining the physical and spiritual, world 2 is still a world featuring this combination, just to a lesser extent. Memories contain the combination of the physical and mental just as much as language does. Thus the three worlds are in truth two worlds.

In conclusion, the a-physical cannot be defined since as physical beings we are unable to appreciate it. Instead there is the solely physical realm which exists; in addition there is a spiritual side to the universe. We have the phys-ical, then everything else is a combination of the physical and spiritual, all to different extents. In this universe we cannot say that there is one solely phys-ical world, or that it is made to two or three realms involving the physical and spiritual. There are an infinite number of realms or levels with increasingly less physical influence on them. This may lead eventually to the a-physical world, as the ultimate level, but we cannot understand it. Yet we live as phys-ical beings in these many worlds or realms of the physical united with the spiritual.

Page 47: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 48: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 49: The Axiom - Issue 3

47

The Axiom

JOIN PYTHAGORAS

TODAY!Words by Tomas Brown

Page 50: The Axiom - Issue 3

Join Pythagoras Today!

48

Do YOU know just how much of a menace beans are to our society? Do YOU know that picking up things off of the ground is dirty and wrong and intellectually degrading? Do you want to become a mathematikos, joining an organisation which broadly makes you sound like

you are a particularly nerdy fish?

Well then my cult is sure as beans are from the pits of hell for you! Here in our triangle themed paradise, we live in freedom from such daily dystopian dilemmas as having to eat from whole loaves of bread, or having an outburst of flatulence ruin your voting procedures! I have found and practiced many of the ancient techniques from totally not the seediest of the Egyptian cults you have ever seen, spending 22 years of my life thinking about the essential triangular centers of all our religious lives; the Pyramids! Today, I offer this knowledge to you, for little else than all your worldly and intellectual possessions!

Of course, you might ask “What is in it for me, apart from eternal freedom from beans and a life in our utopian triangular paradise?”. Well, you get, and get this, an entire fantastic life of cheese and pastry! We have an eternal pythagorean party happening 20-4-7 over in Pythagoras land! Cheese guys! Who doesn’t like cheese!

Well, for the small price of only 40 drachma per day in advance to your re-beanalising and fantastically mathematical stay, you too can take on the title of mathematikoi, and join me, Pythagoras, in triangle heaven. Free cheese included.

Page 51: The Axiom - Issue 3

49

The Axiom

PHILOSOPHER TOP TRUMPS

Words by Tomas Brown

Page 52: The Axiom - Issue 3

Philosophers Top Trumps

50

Russell

Insanity 2Facial Hair 0Controversy 3Renown 9Beauty Score 4

Diogenes

Insanity 10Facial Hair 6Controversy 10Renown 6Beauty Score 8

Plato

Insanity 4Facial Hair 7Controversy 3Renown 10Beauty Score 3

Hume

Insanity 6Facial Hair 0Controversy 3Renown 9Beauty Score 1

Wittgenstein

Insanity 9Facial Hair 1Controversy 10Renown 10Beauty Score 10

Moore

Insanity 1Facial Hair 0Controversy 1Renown 7Beauty Score 4

Spinoza

Insanity 4Facial Hair 0Controversy 3Renown 6Beauty Score 5

Popper

Insanity 3Facial Hair 0Controversy 4Renown 7Beauty Score 4

Hegel

Insanity 3Facial Hair 0Controversy 4Renown 8Beauty Score 1

Page 53: The Axiom - Issue 3

51

Philosopher Top Trumps

Gettier

Insanity 1Facial Hair 0Controversy 7Renown 10Beauty Score 3

Frege

Insanity 4Facial Hair 7Controversy 7Renown 6Beauty Score 5

Kant

Insanity 7Facial Hair 0Controversy 4Renown 10Beauty Score 7

Nietzsche

Insanity 10Facial Hair 10Controversy 10Renown 7Beauty Score 3

Kierkegaard

Insanity 9Facial Hair 0Controversy 5Renown 10Beauty Score 7

Pythagoras

Insanity 10Facial Hair 10Controversy 9Renown 10Beauty Score 3

Descartes

Insanity 3Facial Hair 5Controversy 8Renown 8Beauty Score 6

Sartre

Insanity 4Facial Hair 0Controversy 5Renown 9Beauty Score 4

Leibniz

Insanity 2Facial Hair 0Controversy 3Renown 6Beauty Score 10

Page 54: The Axiom - Issue 3

52

Philosophers Top Trumps

Camus

Insanity 4Facial Hair 0Controversy 5Renown 4Beauty Score 10

Barnes

Insanity 10Facial Hair 10Controversy 10Renown 10Beauty Score 10

Hobbes

Insanity 8Facial Hair 4Controversy 7Renown 6Beauty Score 3

Locke

Insanity 2Facial Hair 0Controversy 4Renown 6Beauty Score 3

Page 55: The Axiom - Issue 3

53

The Axiom

EXISTENTIAL COMICS

Page 56: The Axiom - Issue 3

Existential Comics

Page 57: The Axiom - Issue 3

Existential Comics

Page 58: The Axiom - Issue 3

56

THE

AXIOMISSUE No.3

Contributors

Tomas Brown Blake Jones Giannis Giortzis Richard Ainslie Tom Davy

Comic by Existential ComicsDesign by Blake Jones & Asten Yeo

"The Axiom is a publication wholly produced and owned by Abingdon School, a company limited by guarantee and a regis-

tered charity (Charity No. 1071298). Copyright in all articles and images remains with the creators and owners of those works.

Previously published images and quotes or other excerpts from published works are used either by explicit permission or under

the terms of Fair Use or a Creative Commons licence."

Page 24: "I was walking among the fire of Hell" courtesy of flickr user gags9999 is liscensed under CC BY-NC-SA 2.0

Page 30: "Captive Cat" courtesy of flickr user Faris Algosaibi is liscensed under CC BY-NC-SA 2.0

Page 59: The Axiom - Issue 3
Page 60: The Axiom - Issue 3

THE AXIOMNo.32015