Surface Effects

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    1/36

    Surface effects: Borromini,Semper, Loos

    Andrew Benjamin University of Technology, Sydney, Australia

    The argument in this paper is that surface should be understood neither as a merely struc-

    tural, nor as a merely decorative aspect of building. Rather, the creation of surfaces (interiorwalls or facades and so on) organises a programme which allows for a reading of the space

    of architecture. The latter formulationthe space of architecturehas a double register. On

    the one hand, it refers to the specific architectural works, to particular buildings, and how

    they effect and affect the subject. On the other hand, it makes a broader, theoretical

    point about the way that architecture is conceived as an effect of the possibilities inherent

    in the materials used in the making of surfaces. The argument is advanced through an

    engagement with work by Borromini, Semper and Loos.

    Surface/theory

    Within architecture, the surface figures as both an

    historical and a theoretical concern. As an intro-

    duction to the specific engagement with Borro-

    mini, Semper, and Loosall of whose work will

    play a pivotal role in this recasting of the surface as

    a concept within architectural theorya more

    detailed consideration needs to be given to a

    concern with the surface in the context of architec-

    tural theory.1 Three elements guide this approach to

    the relationship between theory and the surface. All

    are integral to the operation of the architectural.

    In the first place, there is the definition of architec-

    tural theory. It needs to be understood as an

    engagement with issues arising from the practice

    of design. Practice has to be given as great an exten-

    sion as possible running from issues delimited by

    pedagogy to those whose concern is with the

    detail of structures and the nature of research.

    Within practiceunderstood in this extended

    sensethese specific issues will have autonomy

    because of such a positioning. Secondly, integral to

    a theoretical engagement with architecture as a

    practice is the recognition that architecture is

    necessarily bound up with its means of represen-

    tation. (These means figure as much in the pro-duction of images as they do in form creation

    itself.) This does not entail that architecture is iden-

    tical with the image of architecture. Indeed the

    opposite is the case. What it does mean however

    is that drawings, diagrams, computer images,

    three-dimensional print outs, models, etc., all form

    part of the focus of architectural theory. To the

    extent that the means of representation change

    there will be subsequent changes in how the prac-

    tice of architectural theory works. There needs to

    be a certain reciprocity since moves within the

    means of representation should be accompanied

    by changes, or the very least accommodations, on

    the level of theory. (For example, theory cannot

    remain indifferent to the move from Cartesian

    based CAD systems to animation software programs

    such as Maya.)2

    The final element concerns the relationship

    between theory and history. The conjecture here is

    that there is an important difference between the

    1

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

    # 2006 The Journal of Architecture 13602365 DOI: 10.1080/13602360600636099

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    2/36

    objects that comprise the history of architecture and

    the presence of the same objects within architec-

    tural theory. While there will be an important

    relationship between history and theory, the signifi-cance of this distinction should not be overlooked.

    What is at issue is the possibility of the history of

    architecture having a productive presence within

    the practice of design. Again, the argument will

    be that it is only by construing the history of archi-

    tecture theoretically that it will then become poss-

    ible for that history to play a role in particular

    modalities of practice. In regard to this final point

    it will be essential to distinguish between history

    as a specific discursive activity and what will be

    called a theoretical history. The details of theseelements need to be taken up. While there is the

    temptation to treat each separately there are

    important connections between them. The point

    of departure however has to be with the definition

    of architectural theory.

    If the theoretical is defined as an internal

    conditioninternal to architectural practicethen

    it cannot be readily separated from the possibilities

    that obtain for form creation. There are different

    ways in which it can be engendered. As an activity,

    form creation can be guided, for example, as

    much by programme as it can by the abstract activity

    in which volume (or form) is the consequence of the

    deformation of a grid. Equally, form creation will

    always be connected to what a certain set of

    materials will allow and what others will preclude.

    To the extent that form and materials are involved,

    then the geometries within which they are articu-

    lated are also central. Once it can be assumed that

    the relationships between materials, geometries

    and forms are not given in advance, then this has

    the twofold effect of delimiting a space in which

    architectural research can be done. At the same

    time it begins to define the ambit of that research.In addition, and this is the second point, it locates

    not just the space of theory but more significantly

    its necessity. Precisely because relationships have to

    be established and decisions made, this opens up

    the need for forms of deliberation that are continu-

    ally informed. What occasions the introduction of

    theory is the presence of a space opened by a

    relationship whose formal presence cannot be deter-

    mined in advance.

    History, as generally understood, involves the

    location of an object within a field of activity inwhich the object has meaning because of that

    context.3 Writing history involves showing in what

    way the field individuates the particular object;

    although equally, it is concerned with the way the

    field is maintained by the particulars reference to

    it. As such, history can only insist on particularity

    to the extent that what continues to be held in

    place is the network or field. This field occasions

    the objects meaning (and thus the objects presence

    as a cultural or historical sign). While such a position

    enables an account of innovation to be given, and

    thus an account of how an object may interrupt a

    field of activity, perhaps to the point of redefining

    it, what cannot be given within such a setting, is

    an account of the object that insists both on the cen-

    trality of innovation and on the object of innovation

    as able to cause an iterative reworking of the

    elements of history. The historical question does

    not concern the possibility of another form of inno-

    vation, or a reworking of the given, in order that

    2

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    3/36

    a further innovative potential be released. The latter

    possibilitythe destruction of the field of meaning

    in order to occasion innovationbecomes the defi-

    nitional concern of theory. The preoccupations oftheory, in such a context, are with the effectuation

    of the particular as architecture. In regard to the

    objects of history what this means, as has been indi-

    cated, is their capacity to be given another context

    in order that a potentialunrecognised by the

    founding contextcan play a productive role in

    form generation. This is a possibility that emerges

    if the hold of historyas defined by a strict

    contextualismis released.

    The immediate question that has to be addressed

    is the position of the surfacethe surface both as anexisting architectural reality and as a theoretical

    conceptwithin these large formulations of the

    concerns of architectural theory. To ask the ques-

    tionwhat is a surface in architecture?is to ask

    as much about the practical implications of how

    surfaces are used and materials are deployed to

    create them, as it is to ask about the generation of

    surfaces on computer screens. This latter possibility

    means that surfaces can be granted complex his-

    tories internal to the construction of the surface

    itself. More significantly, it will allow for the logic

    that generates the surface and the one that

    enables change to be registered to be one and the

    same and thus internal to the surface as an operative

    field. The key move here however, and it is the one

    that necessitates that a theoretical history of the

    surface be writtenthis essay being a contribution

    to that historyis that such a form of production

    will give rise to a conception of the surface as that

    which will have an effect rather than simply being

    the consequence of the process of its creation.

    Once a surface can effectie, it can bring

    something aboutthen it can be understood as

    that which works to distribute programme. Theeffect will not be instrumental; rather it will be

    inherent in the operation of the surface itself. (This

    will, of course, transform the way the term

    surface is understood.) Once the surface can be

    construed either as that which distributes program-

    mable space, or functional concerns, or the

    elements of architecture (eg, walls and columns),

    then what is at work is a form of production;

    hence the surface effect. While such a conception

    of the surface has only arisen since the use of

    animation software in the design process, it willallow a history of the surface effect to be con-

    structed. Such a project would have the salutary

    effect of robbing the present of its claim to pure

    novelty by allowing a retroactive history to be

    constructed. It will be a history of the surface

    written fromindeed made possible bythat

    which occasions and defines the present. This

    occurs in the precise sense that the moments

    within this retroactive history are given coherence

    by the concerns of the present and those concerns

    are the issues that arisetodayfor and from

    the practice of design. While the nature of this

    conception of the historicaldecontextualisation

    allowing for a theoretical historydemands further

    clarification, at the very minimum what has been

    provided is a point of departure.

    Procedurally what will be argued is that the roles

    of the surface in Borrominis San Carlo alle Quattro

    Fontane, in Sempers writings on cladding as well

    as his discussion of antiquities especially Trajans

    3

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    4/36

    Column and finally in Adolf Looss Haus Muller, while

    at one level having little in common, on another level

    have an important affinity. That affinity is con-

    structed retrospectively. It has to do with the wayeither the writings or specific buildings are con-

    cerned with the surface. What is important there-

    fore is to begin to establish how each of these

    moments, when run together, creates part of the

    history of the surface effect. The lack of immediate

    similarity marking each of these domains means

    that a different way into the question at hand

    the surface that effectshas to emerge in each

    case. In regards to Borromini what will become

    important is the way that the move from an exter-

    nally regulated systemin this instance the onegiven by the analogy between the body and the

    buildingto one whose regulation is internal

    marks the presence of the surface effect. The

    move to the surface will be accompanied by a

    decontextualising move in which both the internal

    and external aspects of the building as well

    as certain drawings by Borromini come to be

    repositioned as objects within a theoretical history.

    In the case of Semper the key opening moment,

    at least for this project, is his discussion of the wall

    in The Four Elements of Architecture.4 If the walls

    original meaning is identified as spatial enclosure,

    it is then possible to distinguish between a structure

    that is simply load bearing and the wall. (The former

    may be no more than that which supports the realis-

    ation of spatial enclosure.) Once this conception of

    the walltransformed into a concern with the

    surfaceis interarticulated with Sempers refusal

    of the distinction between ornament and structure,

    then surface can begin to be identified with

    concerns delimited by programme and function. At

    the minimum it allows the elements of architec-

    turewall, floor, column, corner, etc.to be an

    effect of an operative or generative conception ofthe surface. (Hence a surface defined in terms of

    potentiality rather than simple literal presence.)

    This positioning of Semper will take place in terms

    of an initial juxtaposition with Ruskin for whom

    architecture is the adornment on any edifice. It

    is not as though Semper returns to the edifice by a

    refusal of the identification of architecture and orna-

    ment. His position is far more radical. What will be

    argued is that he refuses the terms set by the oppo-

    sition.5 As a result architecture can be thought

    beyond the opposition structure/ornament. Thisrefusal should now be seen as a radical opening in

    architectural thinking, one resisted by so-called

    post-modern architecture whose aims were for the

    most part explicable in terms of a reintroduction of

    that very distinction.

    Looss significance, initially, can be detected in

    those writings which try to identify the futility of

    ornamentation. The distancing of ornamentation

    needs to be read, at least in part, as a move to the

    centrality of the surface. With Looss there is an

    important addition. Programmatic concerns are

    brought about by the interrelation of surface and

    volume. Starting with Sempers redefinition of the

    wall as that which effects spatial enclosure, the

    project is then to establish in what way the cladding

    within Looss Haus Muller, moves the wall away from

    reductive identification with the literal wall.6 More-

    over, when it becomes possible to locate the actual

    functional operation of the building in the cladding

    (Bekleidung), cutting the Raumplan in order to

    4

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    5/36

    allow for circulation and programme, then it is

    equally possible to allow for the presence of the

    effect of the wall without there having to be a

    literal wall.7

    Even though Looss claim that theinterior of the house should reveal all, while the

    exterior remain mute, is well known, the force,

    perhaps the potential created by the Haus Muller,

    cannot be reduced to this one authorial comment.

    The silence of the exterior cannot be enforced. It

    has an ineliminable potential. (A potential that

    decontextualisation can release.) What this means

    is that the interiors presence can be described as

    functionally indifferent to the exterior of the build-

    ing. Not only does this create two different sur-

    facessurfaces held by the literal wall though notreducible to itit also allows those surfaces

    programmatic possibilities that are capable of a

    relationship of indifference. (The literal wall would

    then need to be understood as that which carried

    two surfaces.) Freed from their initial structural or

    tectonic constraints actual walls are able to function

    as surfaces that effect. In other words, they are able

    to work as distributors of programme rather than as

    markers of putatively neutral spaces. As a conse-

    quence wallsnow as surfacescan become

    effects of the surface.

    In sum, what Loos achieves is a practical and

    workful conception of the surface, by having

    freed the surface from its reduction to the literal

    wall (even if it is one whose potential was not

    fully explored in his actual buildings). Nonetheless,

    there is a significant opening. From within the

    purview of this argument the vocabulary of walls

    and floors has to be reworked such that what is

    given central place is the surface. Whether a

    surface is also a wall or a floor becomes a consider-

    ation that has to be integrated into its presence as a

    surface. They become moments of fixity on a

    surface, moments that are usually the consequencesof programmatic constraints. Instead of its being

    attributed a static quality, the surface will henceforth

    have a dynamic one. While this can be generalised in

    terms of the surface effect, the details will always

    need to be examined. Only then is it possible to

    occasion that move in which what becomes import-

    ant is the surface as a process and therefore as a

    locus of activity. Process and activity will always

    work to displace the surface from an historically

    determined context.8

    Once it can be argued therefore that, from theposition of theory, Loos allows for the intersection

    of surface and volume to distribute programme,

    the surface takes on a particular quality. It becomes

    the abstract or diagrammatic presentation of that

    which opens up fields of activity. The productive

    sense of the surface gives rise to a range of research

    projects that are determined by the nature of the

    relationship between the diagrammatic and its

    ensuing architectural representation. From within

    this framework the surface will remain an abstract

    possibility. The release of the potential that abstrac-

    tion contains, and the manner in which that release

    occurs, or more problematically is occluded, is the

    act of realisation.

    Opening: the body

    Architecture has relied on models or analogies in

    order to define its activity or delimit its field of oper-

    ation. From Vitruvius up until the recent past one of

    the most pervasive analogies has been the body.9

    5

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    6/36

    What will be suggested here, in order to open up the

    place of the surface, is that not only have develop-

    ments in architecture overcome the hold of that

    analogy, but also that freedom has allowed areturn to earlier architectural forms. Such a return

    means that these forms can be reinterpreted. In a

    sense architecture can develop another relation to

    the body by its having been freed from a relationship

    based on an analogy between the building and

    the body. Consequently, it is possible to take up,

    from within architecture, issues that pertain, for

    example, to the disabled body or the gendered

    body precisely because issues that relate to embo-

    died existence are no longer positioned by the

    analogy between the built and the body. The bodyhas not been reconfigured and the nature of the

    analogy changed. Rather, the body can be reconfi-

    gured because the analogy has been overcome.

    Part of the move to the surface accompanies this

    repositioning of architectures relationship to the

    body.

    Of the many formulations of the relationship

    between body and architecture the one found in

    AlbertisOn the Art of Building captures the nature

    of what is involved.10 It is not just that beauty is

    defined in terms of the internal adequacy of pro-

    portion, the internal divisions of the human body

    also provide the measure for the building. Of the

    many passages that could be cited one of the

    more apposite is the following:

    The shapes and sizes for the setting out of

    columns, of which the ancients distinguished

    three kinds according to the variations of the

    human body, are well worth understanding.

    When they considered mans body, they decided

    to make columns after his image. Having taken

    the measurements of a man, they discovered

    that the width, from one side to the other, was

    a sixth of the height, while the depth from navelto kidneys was a tenth.11

    What is important in this passage is twofold. Not

    only is there the strength of the analogy, moreover,

    measurement and the geometry of proportion are

    structured by it. Measure is always defined exter-

    nally. Not only is the body a given, it provides

    accepting a symbiosis between building and

    bodythe ground of construction and evaluation.

    Part of the force that can be attributed to the

    analogy is this structuring potential. Fundamental

    to the process was an essential anthropocentrism.This is not merely the pursuit of humanistic

    valuesalthough that may have been the case

    but the identification of the generative element of

    design within an analogy in which architecture was

    always determined externally. When architecture

    moves to the modern perioda movement, which,

    as is being suggested, sanctions a retrospective

    reinterpretation of the traditionthen the external

    control will have vanished. The body has not been

    deferred if only to be reincorporated as a concern

    within architecture, more significantly an external

    control, a control structured by analogy (an instance

    of which is the body), has given way to a funda-

    mentally different way of construing the generative

    dimension of architecture. That dimension has

    become internal to the object. The object is rede-

    fined in terms of its self-effectuation as architecture.

    A clear example, as has already been suggested, is

    the way that the Raumplan intersects with the role

    of cladding in Looss Haus Mullerto construct the

    6

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    7/36

    object as architecture. (This is, of course, a position

    that will be pursued in greater detail.)

    If architecture has been freed from the analogy of

    the body, how then does this freedom open up theconcerns of the history of architecture? Surely it

    could be argued that while this freedom may have

    some impact on future projections, the conceptions

    of symmetry that appeared in earlier buildings, or

    plans, defined symmetry in terms of the order of

    the body, or if not the body then nature. (In both

    instances what determined symmetry was external

    to built form.) Even if that argument could be sus-

    tained there is no need to limit interpretations in

    this manner. To the extent that elements of the

    history of architecture can be differentiated fromtheir insertion into a given history, the possibility of

    reinterpretation and thus reactivisation occasions

    the emergence of another object. As has already

    been indicated, such a connection is only possible

    because the objects potential will not allow the

    insistence of history to still that possibility.

    In order to trace the potential in the work of the

    surfaces comprising Borrominis San Carlo alle

    Quattro Fontane (16381682) a detour will be

    taken.12 Instead of proceeding directly to the detail

    of Borrominis work, two sculptures by Bernini will

    set the scene. The second, David (1623) is by far

    the more significant. Nonetheless, the move from

    the slightly earlier sculpture to this one needs to be

    understood as the move from a work defined by a

    clear sense of front and therefore of sides and

    behind, to one that resists all the dimensions of fron-

    tality by working as a continual surface. In architec-

    tural terms, the possibility demanded by Palladio, in

    which, if the Villa Rotondabegins to define an ideal

    and where part of the ideal is the symmetry of the

    front, would cede its place to an internally genera-

    tive system in Borromini. This movement is present

    within the Bernini sculptures. Frontality is overcomeby an internally regulated system that individuates

    specific elements. They are the after-effects of a

    system, rather than being incorporated into a total-

    ity whose organisational logic leads in a different

    direction; ie, to the object as symbol. While symbo-

    lism, both in architecture and sculpture, is almost

    impossible to avoid, there is a real difference

    between the attribution of a symbolical quality and

    the necessity of a symbolic presence derived from

    the objects relationship to an external order of

    organisation. The argument is not that sculptureopens up architecture. Rather, in holding to the

    specificity of sculpture it then becomes possible to

    examine how a distinction between stasis and move-

    ment is at work within this particular field. As such,

    what can then be asked is what the architectural

    correlate to this distinction would be like.

    Bernini. The processDavidDavid

    As a point of departure it should not be forgotten that

    withDavidwhat is at work is a body (Fig. 1). A sculp-

    tured body, and yet as sculpture it can be interpreted

    as the move from the body understood as proportion

    towards a body understood as a dynamic process

    of internal relationships. Moreover, it is a dynamic

    process that is neither one of simple movement nor

    one of unending oscillation. What is at work is the

    movement of what will be called the material infinite.

    While this term will need to be clarified, at this stage it

    should be understood as identifying a process in

    which finite moments are the effect of the process;

    7

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    8/36

    a process that is potentially infinite. As such materiality

    has a certain immateriality as its condition of existence.

    This sculpture involves a marked development

    from earlier works such as The Rape of Proserpina

    (16212). What defined that particular work was

    its static quality. That quality is brought about by

    the relationship between the planted left leg of

    Pluto and the force of Proserpinas left hand against

    his face. The skin above her abductors left eye is

    being forced up while all the weight is borne by his

    left leg. Therightleg is raisedindicating thepossibility

    of movement and yet the relationship between the

    eye and the left leg indicates a stationary position.

    All that is being marked is the moment. Ovid insists

    on the simultaneity of seeing, loving and abducting

    (Metamorphoses, V.395). The sculpture is of thatpoint in time. The movement of hand, facial skin

    and legs involves a careful balance. As such it is

    mannerist in orientation, although more importantly

    as a work it can be said to be defined by the tem-

    porality of the instant. What is seen is that

    particular instant. Each of the elements comprising

    the relationhips that define the sculpture can be

    viewed. There is a real extent to which the work is

    complete in itself. The completion delimits what

    is seen. The relationship between presentation and

    the instant defines the work in terms of both rep-resentation and expression. Neither claim can be

    made of David. This will be the reason why David

    is an architecturally more interesting sculpture.

    Moreover, although this is a contention to be

    argued,David, in procedural terms, opens the way

    towards Borrominis extraordinary facades and

    interiors. More, particularly David, despite being a

    body, leads away from the analogy between body

    and building. Even though there is a body, at work

    here is a conception of form that is no longer

    anthropocentric in nature.

    What marks out David as a site, and therefore

    what delimits its particularity, has initially to do with

    a conception of relatedness that is no longer held

    by the instant. Time figures in a different way. The

    insistence of theinstantcedesits place to thetempor-

    ality of process. What this conception of time brings

    with it is work. Work is both object and activity. Once

    the temporal and active dimension comes to define

    the ontology of the object, then while a work is

    8

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

    Figure 1. David,

    Bernini, (1623), marble.

    (Rome, Galerie

    Borghe` se). From Bernini

    Toutes Ses Oeuvres auMonde, Figure 4, 4th

    edition (Rome, Fratelli

    Palombi srl, 1998).

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    9/36

    present, the presentation has to be defined in terms

    of an interiority that eschews any reduction to the

    instant. In other words, it is defined in terms of a

    set of internal relations whose work comprises thework. While those relationships have exteriority

    insofar as the object has material presence, the

    exterior is the presentation of pure interiority. And

    yet, the relations comprising this interiority have to

    be defined in terms of dynamic relations rather

    than the interconnection of static points. What will

    emerge therefore is another way of construing

    internal relationships.

    One of the most remarkable qualities of the sculp-

    ture is the impossibility of standing in front of it as

    opposed to behind it. Equally, it is not possible tostand to one side and see it from that side rather

    than being either in front or behind. No matter

    where the viewer stands the sculpture stands before

    the eye. In a sense this is because Davids body

    is turned such that in being ready to release the

    catapulta rope containing a stone stretched

    between his handsa circle has been constructed.

    What is viewed is that circle. However, to insist on

    the formal circularity of the object would be to

    miss both the counter balancing of forces as well

    as the dynamic relationships that the circle con-

    structs (or equally, of which the circle is the effect).

    While it may be necessary to provide a semiology

    of the sculpture in which the relationships are des-

    cribed, the points being described maintain a differ-

    ent sense of relationality than one understood as

    mere connectedness. The work is not the connec-

    tion of points. Nor is it that points connect

    dynamic lines. Points would only ever be after-

    effects of lines. A dynamic quality predominates.

    What is maintained is a pure interiority that con-

    tinues to present itself. What is presented, while

    having a singular quality, is not reducible to a

    simple singularity. Within the process of relation itis always possible to construct a point of view,

    however that point is the effect of the process.

    Equally, it cannot be identical with the object. This

    is not a claim about relativity but about the

    process of pure internal relatedness. The infinite in

    question is that which has already been identified

    as the material infinite.13

    Davids right foot is on the ground. The back of

    the left is raised with the toes of that foot taking

    the weight. The body is neither turning nor not

    turning. The tension created by the feet instantiatesprocess. Process here is movement. The rope of the

    catapult is held tight. The hands are pulling and yet

    at that moment the catapult is still; a still point

    within the process that marks the catapult being

    held and which is, at the same time, the process of

    its being released. His loins are wrapped by a

    folded garment and around his shoulder there is a

    pouch held in place by further folded material. The

    folds of the material are not, in this context, what

    is interesting. The significance is that they cannot

    be differentiated from the work of the body. The

    wrap of the material over his loins forms part of

    the bodys unfolding. It neither flows with the

    body nor against it. It is neither on the body nor is

    it separate from it. Body, material, pouch, sling

    all form part of the process. The error would be to

    see the body as adorned and therefore the body as

    central. Indeed, it can be argued that what defines

    the sculpture are the relationships between the

    bodyand by body what is meant is Davids literal

    9

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    10/36

    bodyand what could be taken, albeit wrongly, as

    secondary, ie, material, sling, pouch, etc. On an

    abstract level it is possible to see the sculpture

    and it should be remembered that there is a poten-tial endlessness that comprises this seeingas a

    surface. Different elements are not placed on a

    single surface. The sculpture is the endless articula-

    tion of relationships in which what is individuated

    can be attributed specific qualities. In other words,

    on the level of description it is possible to distinguish

    the material around the body, or connected to it,

    from the body itself. Nonetheless, such a formal

    distinction would miss the way they form part of a

    continuum involving neither adornment nor orna-

    mentation. Rather, these formally distinct elementsform part of a continuous surface. Moreover, the

    only way the distinct elements are able to be distinct

    and to be viewed as separate is because they are

    interarticulated within, and as, a continuous

    surface. Such an argument would be consistent

    with the claim made above that points are the

    after-effects of lines that work.

    What then ofDavids body? The body becomes the

    site of infinite relatedness. In refusing to privilege any

    one positionand thus by extension any descrip-

    tionit becomes a finite point, the condition of possi-

    bility for which is the infinitude of relationships. The

    latter is the work of the material infinite. Internality,

    therefore, is given priority, and then, as has been

    argued, individual elements are individuated by the

    work as a site of process. The object is no longer the

    totality of individual parts precisely because

    individuation always occurs as the effect of a process.

    The elements are effected by the works organisational

    logic. What this means is that the sculpture, as an

    activity, has to be seen as a surface. However, it is

    not a surface on which things are placed, rather, in

    sculptural terms, it is a surface that effects.

    San Carlo alle Quattro Fontane

    Borromini died in 1667. At the time of his death the

    facade of San Carlo was not yet finished. (The

    building, except for the facade, was finished in

    1641. The facade was completed in 1682.) The

    remaining plans, however, indicate the extent to

    which the existing building follows the original

    drawings. Steinberg, Blunt and Wittkower, amongst

    others, have provided detailed descriptions of the

    building. What is important here is to see the build-

    ing within what could be described as anotherhistory of the curvilinear. Fundamental to the incep-

    tion of the Baroque was the distinction between the

    static and the dynamic.14 Accepting that develop-

    ment, while essential, is to repeat a commonplace

    until the nature of the movement in question is

    characterised. Even then, it should not be thought

    that there is simple consistency within all Baroque

    architecture. However, in this context what has to

    be noted is the path that stems from a consideration

    of BerninisDavid. What is opened up is complexity

    within movement. In regards to San Carlo what

    needs to be emphasised, as a beginning, is the dis-

    tinction between a conception of movement that

    involves illusion and one that defines movement by

    the continuity of counter-measures. The latter

    realises complexity. It is not as though the two are

    in direct opposition or that they do not overlap or

    even reinforce each other. However, what is signifi-

    cant is the way their difference provides particular

    openings.

    10

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    11/36

    The dome consists of a texture of geometric

    shapescrosses, octagons and hexagonsthat

    move towards a naturally lit opening which rises

    up towards the motif of a bird. Not only is the eyedragged up through the rich array of forms, it is

    then tempted furthertempted towards the infi-

    niteby flight. As the eye soars the infinite is

    captured as much by flight as it is by the geometry.

    The infinite in question is the infinite of illusion.

    The interplay of symbolism and a vanishing point

    maintained by the intersection of geometry

    and light creates a feeling of infinite movement

    towards a divine infinite. While the illusion is import-

    ant, it is not as though infinite transcendence can

    have material presence other than as illusion. Thisis the restriction of this conception of the infinite.

    As Descartes argued in the Meditations, what

    could not be represented was the infinite nature of

    God. There is however another conception of the

    infinite.15 Here the infinite is not linked to represen-

    tation but to the infinity of pure becoming. Within

    the philosophical writings of the period the most

    exact formulation of this position is found in

    Leibnizs conception of substance as force (vis). Sub-

    stance is never static nor transcendent, it is un etre

    capable daction (a being capable of action).16

    Activity defines substance. Its continuity is its contin-

    ual self-realisation and thus self-effectuation. Move-

    ment therefore is an infinitude of relationships. In

    following Leibniz as opposed to Descartes an archi-

    tecture of illusion is put to one side. The question

    to be addressed therefore concerns the architectural

    correlate to this conception of the infinite. It should

    be added immediately that this conception of the

    infinite can have material presence. The infinite

    is linked to relation. Baroque architecture is not

    Leibnizian. The relation has to do with how the infi-

    nite is understood. Architecture is not philosophy.

    The importance of the distinction lies in the natureof the formers material presence.

    One of the central elements defining the internal

    operation of the church is the movement of bays,

    columns and walls. While each element has a dis-

    tinct quality, there is an interconnectedness that is

    neither arbitrary nor the work of chance. Their inter-

    relationhip is held by an entablature that divides the

    overall building into three sections. The physical

    presence of the entablature has the effect of

    emphasising the columns even though it is an

    emphasis that is dissipated, formally, once it isrecognised that they form part of the walls which

    in turn form the bays since the latter cannot be dis-

    sociated from the walls articulation. There is a

    complex pattern in which even though the elements

    are separate, in that they have either ornamental or

    functional specificity and as such can invite and

    maintain particular programmatic possibilities, they

    are nonetheless articulated together. If the walls

    were understood as a continuous line, then the

    measure and counter measurethe movement of

    the curvilinearwould have become a surface. In

    other words, what is at work here is not a straight

    line that has become curved. Measure and counter-

    measure continue to yield openings that become

    locations within, and as, a surface.17 A similar oper-

    ation is at work in the facade. While the status of the

    facade is contested it is, nonetheless, worth noting

    the way in which the curvilinear is once again a

    series of measures and counter measures that yield

    space. The curvilinear does not maintain space,

    11

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    12/36

    rather it is part of the process of spacing. In the

    process, and in the potential endlessness that

    marks the presence of the curvilinear, it is possible

    to locate the work of a material infinite. Finitudeunderstood as the individuation of elements

    always takes the infinite as its condition of

    possibility.

    While it is possible to emphasise that the building

    as a totality is a complex negotiation with differing

    ordering systems, the most powerfully argued

    interpretation of San Carlo is Steinbergs for whom

    the building is an attempt to integrate oval, cross

    and octagon. He wants to see this three-part

    system reiterated throughout the church as a

    whole.

    18

    On one level it is impossible to deny theacuity of this observation. Nonetheless, it is still poss-

    ible to complicate this particular description. Again,

    this complication should not for a moment be seen

    as diminishing its historical importance. Indeed, no

    attempt is being made here to deny that the building

    can be understood as the continual attempt to

    reconcile symbolic, theological and philosophical

    elements that characterised the seventeenth

    century in general and the Baroque in particular.

    The complication in question can be demonstrated

    by concentrating on a specific drawing by Borromini;

    namely Albertina 175 (Fig. 2). The importance of the

    drawing is that it generates a further opening. What

    allows it to be made is the relationship architecture

    has to its means of representation. However, funda-

    mental to this position is that while those means are

    an ineliminable part of architecture, it does not

    follow that what is an ostensible representation

    has to be read in that way. In other words, represen-

    tations can be read diagrammatically. This is the

    claim that lines, drawings, in sum representations,

    once understood as diagrams, have the capacity

    to generate representations but should not be

    assumed to be straightforwardly representational.This move introduces into the history of drawing

    and architectural representation an abstracting

    element that interrupts the flow of history by

    linking the abstracting process to the possibility of

    a representation having an afterlife. To be

    precise, the afterlife is the move from abstraction

    to a further representation.

    The plan allows two different aspects to be

    emphasised. The first would be to show how the

    walls and the structure are an effect of the oval (or

    ellipse) which is itself part of the internal geometry.The oval is the result of the juxtaposition of two equi-

    lateral triangles inscribed within two circles. Whether

    itis an oval or an ellipse, the end result is that the line

    is present as a result of the internal configuration.19

    Moreover, as Steinberg argues, it is possible to see

    that the produced line marks out the plan in the

    drawing as pulled backwards and forwardsa

    pulling and pushing that produces the curvilinear

    by the work of the internal configuration. On one

    level a movement of this type has to be the case.

    However, to the extent that the production of the

    line remains central, then an account of the line

    will be in terms of that production. Any account

    therefore will oscillate between those involving the

    history of geometry and in particular the role of geo-

    metry in drawing, and more ideologically based ver-

    sions in terms of architectural attempts to reconcile

    various religious and philosophical positions.20 The

    end result is that the line remains secondary to that

    which is taken to have produced it. There is another

    12

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    13/36

    possibility, which, while alluding to these accounts of

    the line, is not defined by them. Namely, giving

    emphasis to the line itself. This means more than

    a change in emphasis. Another area of concern

    emerges. Henceforth, the interpretive question con-

    cerns what is it that the line produces. This

    questionone that can be taken to a range of differ-

    ent drawings of the planhas to start with what can

    be described as the lines density. Density means that

    the line is not the single line but the double line

    marking, if only as a beginning, an inside and an

    outside. The dense linethe line itselfis this

    double (perhaps doubled) line. In general terms it is

    a line of information.

    While accepting that the columns have a load-

    bearing function within the overall structure, they

    do not stand opposed to the wall. Nor is it that the

    columns, which may have been historically separated

    from the wall, have now been placed next to it.

    Within the confines of the dense line, how is the

    relationship between the column and the wall to

    be understood? This question cannot be asked

    13

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

    Figure 2. Borromini:

    half plan for the churc

    of S. Carlo alle Quattr

    Fontane, Rome

    (drawing, Albertina175).

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    14/36

    independently of the movement that the line marks

    out. While it is possible to account for the movement

    of the line in terms of the effect of the founding

    internal geometry, it is also true that any account ofthe line has to begin with the recognition that its

    movement effects. The curvilinear creates and

    distributes internal and external volumes that are

    themselves the distribution of programmable space.

    Whether that programme is used in one way rather

    than anotherie, locating specific functions proper

    to the operation of a church, or even places for

    statues or ornamentationis not the point. What

    matters is that this line has to be understood as

    that which distributes volume. In other words, the

    volumes (bays) are the effect of the line. At worktherefore is a line that works. This line becomes the

    architectural correlate to the surface of Berninis

    David. That surface too, needs to be understood as

    a generalised production and therefore as a

    workful line.

    Allowing the line this capacity will account for the

    relationship between the column and the wall. What

    the line makes clear is that the relationship is no

    longer one either of opposition or ornamentation.

    If it can be argued that the volumes are produced

    by the operation of the linethey are its effect

    then it is also the case that both wall and column

    are themselves effects of a line. There is no

    opposition between column and wall. The line

    although now viewed as a surface that individu-

    atespresents elements that can at a given

    moment and for a specific reason be given the des-

    ignation bay (volume) or wall or column. As with

    Berninis David individual elements are the after-

    effects of a surface that effects. Finally, the absences

    of an opposition between column and wall pre-

    cludes the question of their relationship. Relation-

    ship is concerned with separate definable entities.

    Here, they only have a relationship insofar as thesame line produces them.

    The drawing is not the building. However, the

    drawing cannot be dissociated from the actual

    presence of San Carlo. What this means is that

    part of its presence is a quality that allows for a

    greater degree of abstraction to be attributed to it.

    The process of abstraction will allow for the decon-

    textualisation. However, this is not a process that

    refuses the particularity of the actual building.

    Abstraction refers to the inherent architectural

    quality of the work that allows italmost in virtueof a form of autonomyto have a life indepen-

    dently of its specific historical presence. The dense

    line in Albertina 175 works to distribute certain

    fundamental architectural elements delimiting, as

    part of that process, programmable spaces. The

    line individuates these elements; equally, the line

    also individuates spaces. What is individuated is

    marked by finitude. Hence, the line, precisely

    because other instances of individuation could

    have occurred, can be understood as the work of

    a material infinite.

    In regards to the facade the entablature has a

    different role from the one it played within the

    building. Internally, while having a tripartite form,

    it can nonetheless be described as holding two

    different orders in place by marking their point of

    division. Moreover, the visual power of the entabla-

    ture worked to control the eye and thus to regulate

    the experience of the building. The facade incorpor-

    ates the entablature. Even though it divides it, it is

    14

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    15/36

    also the case that acts of division are part of the

    work of the facade. Formally, it consists of convex

    and concave lines that delimit spaces (bays). As

    with the interior, columns, and ornamentationcannot be differentiated from the facade itself.

    In forming part of the facade they cause it to

    become, once again, a complex surface. Questions

    of addition and ornamentation are not to be separ-

    ated from the possibility of their presence as that

    which is enacted by the measure and counter

    measure of the surface. While it is possible to see

    the two parts of the facade as responding to each

    other insofar as a concave line on one level is posi-

    tioned in relation to a convex line on the other,

    there is more at stake. Two elements need to benoted. The first is that the relationship of the

    convex and the concave is part of the totality of

    the surface. The second point is that the work

    of these linesthe work that is the complexity of

    the curvilinearis the disclosure of spaces that

    allow for programme because they await it. Pro-

    grammable space is the consequence of lines that

    work.

    What Borrominis adventure allows is not a claim

    about the modernity of the Baroque or even the

    extent to which the concerns of the Baroque could

    still play a determining role in design. Such claims

    would have to overlook the need to reconstruct

    historical periods. The inventing of histories and

    the establishing of points of connection occur

    because of openings afforded by the present.

    What is central to Borromini in this context is the

    way San Carlo can be seen as demanding another

    account of the generation of form. As an account

    it has to involve the movement of matter beyond

    the body, precisely because the generation of form

    is internal to the object. The limitation of the

    Baroque is the way both internality and form were

    conceived. The limitation is merely the Baroquesparticularity. In moving from externality and thus

    from an anthropocentric architecture, the Baroque

    demonstrates the impossibility of architecture

    having a forma finalis. The future opened up by

    Bernini and Borromini is not to be found in the

    detail of their formal inventions. That would be to

    reduce those inventions to an image. The future

    is allowed by a different repetition, one guided

    by a process of abstraction. If what is fundamental to

    their work is the operation of a material infinite that

    continues to be generative of formcontextually, itoccurs through the operation of a surface in which

    elements are individuatedthen as an abstraction

    this operative quality is what can be retained.

    Once the dense line that characterises Albertina

    175 is given priorityin addition it is a line that

    once reworked yields the facadethe continuity of

    its folds will always have to be arrested. The

    cessation of movement is the precondition of

    form. Cessation becomes finitude. Finitude can be

    equated with architectures material presence. The

    precondition allowing for finitude is the lines

    potentiality. As has been suggested, materiality has

    its conditions of possibility in what was called the

    material infinite. The final point that needs to be

    reiterated is that the density of this line need not

    be literal. Density has to do with the information

    that the line distributes.

    If there is a limitation in this conception of the line

    then it liesdespite densityin the restriction of

    relatedness; a relationship that would be linked to

    15

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    16/36

    a sense of productive interruption. An example

    would be the way volume and surface may be inter-

    connected. While this possibility emerges at its most

    emphatic in Loos, it is the writings of GottfriedSemper that will allow, again retrospectively, these

    opening considerations of the surface to be taken

    a step further.

    Ruskin and polychromatic antiquities

    In order to position Semperor rather to rework the

    force of Sempers positioning of the surfacesa

    setting is essential. This will be provided in this

    context by looking first at the way Ruskin defines

    architecture and secondly at the way Sempers

    approach to the surface cannot be separated fromthe dispute concerning polychromatic antiquities

    that had such an important historical influence on

    the development of architectural thinking in both

    France and Germany in the early- to mid-nineteenth

    century. While both these attempts to establish a

    context may seem too distant from Semper, the

    contrary is the case. Ruskins thinking still echoes

    in architectural arguments for decorum and the

    stylistic determination of context. The discovery of

    polychromatic antiquities can be reworked as the

    discovery of the surface that was the interarticula-

    tion of surface and function.

    As has already been suggested the importance of

    Ruskins definition of architecture is that it provides

    the backdrop against which both the radicality and

    the commitment to the form of materialism that

    structures Sempers conception of architecture can

    be understood. InThe Seven Lamps of Architecture

    Ruskin defines architecture as an art that adorns the

    edifice raised by man for whatsoever use.21 In this

    instance what is significant about Ruskin is not the

    argument concerning the use of general symbolism

    in architecture, nor is it architectures relationship to

    religion and nature. The significance of this defi-nition is that it gives a clear place to architecture.

    Working with the definition is essential in order to

    see how it defines architecture. The first part deser-

    ving attention is the description of architecture as an

    adornment. Adorning is always an after-effect.

    Jewellery is a form of adornment. The pearl

    buttons or sequins sown on a dress can be said to

    adorn it. They become an adornment to the extent

    they can be differentiated from that on which they

    are placed. Such a differentiation is envisaged by

    the contrast between adornment and the edifice.Edifice is a description of the object. It is the pure

    presence of the objectone that is not given speci-

    ficityalthough more importantly does not need to

    be given it. The description of the edifice as raised

    by man is significant as it locates architecture as a

    practice that involves a necessary distinction from

    nature, thereby inviting a possible accord with

    nature. Architecture is artifice although only in the

    sense that it serves human purpose. If the human

    being creates, then the question of purpose has to

    emerge. (This will be Kants enduring legacy; there

    can be no account of creation that works indepen-

    dently of the constraint of nature that can escape

    a definition in relation to purpose.) To what end

    has the human created? If the end cannot be distin-

    guished from the edifice (to retain Ruskins termi-

    nology) insofar as the edifice will always have had,

    and will always have, a purpose, then there is the

    recognition of the necessary and ineliminable func-

    tionality of architecture. Once the edifice has this

    16

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    17/36

    quality, there can be no question of the denial of

    functionality. Purpose is the already-present identifi-

    cation of function. The question that has to be

    asked however concerns, from within the purviewof Ruskins definition, the relationship between

    purpose and architecture.

    Answering that question necessitates paying par-

    ticular attention to the final words whatsoever use.

    It is not just that this eliminates the place of function;

    it does this by denying it to architecture and then by

    locating it in the edifice. In other words, the force

    of the whatsoever use is that function is main-

    tained by its being radically distinguished from archi-

    tecture. As such the question that needs to be

    brought to Ruskins formulation has to concern thepresence of architecture. This is both a question of

    almost brute physicality as well as a more straight-

    forwardly conceptual one concerning how, within

    the formulation, is architecture to be thought.

    These questions are related. The presence of archi-

    tecturepresence as locationdefines how it is to

    be thought. Architecture, from within the position

    that is being extrapolated from this definition of

    the art of architecture, is located on the surface.

    More precisely, and this is the essential point, it is

    the literal surface understood as adornment.

    The centrality of ornament as the locus of the

    architectural has an important history. While not

    originating in Ruskin, what is repeated is a sensibility

    that locates what is essential to architecture in orna-

    ment. In the modern period this conception of

    architecture continues to have relevance. Not only

    does it define so-called post-modern architecture

    as a moment within the history of ornament, it

    continues to define the architectural in terms of

    the opposition between ornament and structure

    (Ruskins edifice). The contention here is that

    Sempers writings can be read as a critique not just

    of the retention of this opposition but of its definingarchitecture. With Semper architecture is redefined.

    While this positionthe redefinitionfinds its most

    exact expression in the discussion of style and the

    elements of architecturea discussion that will

    be taken up in this context in terms of working

    through Sempers treatment of the wallhis

    earlier writings on polychromatic antiquities not

    only set the scene, it is in his discovery of colour

    that the already-present relationship between

    function and surface come to be expressed. That

    expression overcomes the opposition between orna-ment and structure. This is to argue in the first place

    that colour is functionalas opposed to simply dec-

    orativeand in the second that structure works in

    accord with that function. In sum, the interplay of

    function and colour overcomes the tradition that

    attempts to identify the architectural with the

    ornamental.

    Sempers intervention in the debate on polychro-

    matic antiquities occurred in 1834 with the publi-

    cation of his pamphlet Preliminary Remarks on

    Polychrome Architecture and Sculpture in Antiquity.

    While they are only implicit in the pamphlets argu-

    ment, it has to be understood as involving two sub-

    texts. The first is an undoing of the Winkelmanian

    aesthetic that was concerned with the purity of

    form and therefore the retention of ideals as that

    which prompted form and which form had to

    imitate. At the same time however there was a

    general concern with establishing both the speci-

    ficity of the modern and more particularly with

    17

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    18/36

    opening up the question of the appearance of the

    modern.22 The argument is that a debate as

    apparently arcane as one concerning the possibility

    of coloured antiquities was in fact a debate aboutthe nature of the modern. The discovery of Etruscan

    art not only had the effect of destabilising the nature

    of the Classical tradition, that destabilisation meant

    that the grounds of assessment and judgement in

    both art and architecturethe grounds of

    Classicismwere no longer secure.

    There were two arguments against the presence

    of colour. The first is an archaeological one, while

    the second is aesthetic. Clearly, the response to

    such arguments is to show through the reports of

    contemporary excavations that coloured antiquitieshad been in fact found. And yet, that would not

    have been sufficient since there were aesthetic

    reasons for holding to the presence of colour

    being either a mistake or simply exceptional and

    therefore only of marginal interest. Semper sums

    up this concern in the following terms; they are

    sure that colour applied to sculpture must confuse

    the forms and pamper the eye (dass Farben

    angewendt auf Bildenerei die Formen verwirren

    und das Auge verwohen mussen) (p. 61/p. 239).

    Prior to taking up his response it is worth noting

    the detail of this objection to colour. It should be

    remembered that it is, as it were, the aesthetic

    objection and thus one neither checked let alone

    overcome by additionalfactualdiscoveries.

    While appearing as merely aesthetic insofar as it is

    a defence of form, such a position is best under-

    stood in terms of forms metonymic links. Once

    understood in this sense, the threat to form can be

    comprehended as the threat to the continuity of

    historical time that allows for forms own repetition.

    Form, precisely because it is continually positioned

    by the movement between the ideal and the

    actual can be repeated ad infinitum. The refusal offormits having become confusedwould be

    the concession that allowed this sense of continuity

    to have been interrupted. Sempers language in

    responding to his own presentation of the aesthetic

    response has an important aesthetic register itself.

    He argues that colour:

    clarifies the form (sie entwirren die Formen)

    because colour provides the artist with a new

    way to throw the surface into relief. It brings the

    eye back again to the natural way of seeing, (Sie

    bringen das Auge wieder zuruck auf den naturli-chen Weg des Sehens), which is lost under the

    sway of that mode of abstraction that knows pre-

    cisely how to separate the visible and inseparable

    qualities of bodies, the colour from the form

    knows it by those unfortunate principles of aes-

    thetics that define exactly the sphere of the indi-

    vidual arts and do not allow any excursions into

    a neighbouring field. (P. 61/p. 239.)

    What is significant about this formulation is that the

    defence of colour is given an aesthetic register,

    almost in terms of naturalism. Importance here has

    to be attached to another aesthetic possibility. That

    possibility does not separate colour and form

    noting of course that once this position is expressed

    in this way the register of form will have changed.

    No longer held by the opposition between the

    ideal and the actual it becomes the material instance

    of form. Emphasising colour, therefore, becomes the

    affirmation of the materiality of form. The move is

    not simple empiricism. Nor, moreover, should the

    18

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    19/36

    evocation of the material be understood as

    suggesting that form has become the empirical

    instantiation of the ideal. Rather, it is materiality

    itself. As a result of this repositioning there has tobe an accompanying shift in perception. Perceiv-

    ingthe use of the eyealters in order to perceive

    colour. In Semperian terms seeing abstractly is to

    posit a distinction between form and colour. In

    other words, abstraction, in this context, means

    holding colour and form apart. However, in order

    to give such a move coherence it would have to be

    grounded, almost of necessity, in a conception of

    form that locates particulars within a defining oscil-

    lation between the ideal and the actual. As such

    form acquires an inherently transcendent quality.The aesthetic response therefore is fundamental.

    What Semper is pointing out is a shift in the cat-

    egories of how seeing takes place. While it is not

    Sempers actual argument, implicit in his position is

    the claim that colour has the capacity to overcome

    the hold of Classicism. Colour undoes the opposition

    between form and the ornamental or decorative.

    This development provides the setting in which

    Sempers discussion of Trajans Column needs to be

    situated. The basis of the interpretation resides in

    the column having traces of paint (die Spuren

    von Malerei) (p. 67/p. 248). What is significant

    about the passage is not just the depth of descrip-

    tion but attributing to the column the capacity to

    have the effect of spatialityand thus to space.

    This effect is explicable in terms of the operation

    of colour. What this means, of course, is that

    spacing is an effect of the surface.

    The figures on the monument stood out golden

    against an azure background. The flat reliefs on

    the pedestal, too, were undoubtedly given their

    proper appearance (waren entfehlbar) through

    the rich variety of gold and colour. Only in such

    a way could the column be in harmony with therichly coloured and gilded forum, the porphyry

    cornices and green marble columns of the

    templesas could the bronze statue with the

    column. (P. 67/p. 249.)

    Leaving aside any lingering hyperbole that may be

    evident in the passage, what is clear is that not

    only is there an urban coherencespatiality is held

    in place and in playit is also realised, for Semper,

    by the work of colour. TheColumn, while not strictly

    architectural, plays a fundamental role within the

    visual coherence of theForum. Coherence is realisedby the accord between the form and the colour. For

    Semper, it would be an accord which, once the

    debilitating effect of the abstract eye is left to one

    side, would have been effective and thus would

    have functioned if the eye had perceived the

    almost ineliminable reciprocity between form and

    colour; ie, their conjoined presence rather than

    their separate existence. It would have operated in

    relation to the object, the column, then with the

    other objects in the field. The latter would now be

    understood as an urban condition operating on

    the level of affect as well as the structural and func-

    tional. Surfaces in this context are as much impli-

    cated in questions of form (structure) as form is in

    the question of the surface (literal surface) namely

    colour.

    Semper, walls and surfaces

    In one of the lectures given in London during his

    period of residence in the city, Semper did not just

    19

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    20/36

    distinguish between Greek and what he termed

    Barbarian architecture, he formulated the dis-

    tinction in a way that concerns the nature of

    architectures material presence. While Sempersgeneralised account is part of an overall attempt to

    categorise and detail the practice of ancient archi-

    tecture, in distinguishing between the Greek and

    the Barbarian, he introduces one of the defining

    motifs in his writings, namely a distinction

    between that which occurs within architecture and

    architectures exteriority.

    The Greek ornaments are emanations of the con-

    structive forms and in the same way they are the

    dynamical function of the parts to which they

    belong. They have no other meaning than toexplain the construction forms by analogical

    notions, taken from nature itself or from other

    branches of art, while the ornaments on the

    barbarian monuments find generally their expla-

    nations in some historical, local or religious

    notions, which have nothing in common with

    the part of the building, whereon they are

    applied.23

    Central then to the Greek is a conception of orna-

    mentation. However, it has to be understood as an

    explanation of the construction.24 In other words,

    it is defined internally to the architectural object.

    Admittedly, this occurs via analogy. Nonetheless,

    the relationship is structured by interiority. The

    barbarian on the other hand involves a conception

    of ornamentation in which the additions have to be

    explained in terms of symbolic values, which, as

    Semper concedes, are always accounted for exter-

    nally. The move to the historical, the religious, etc.,

    defines these additions in terms of exteriority and

    therefore, to use the language of Ruskin, they play

    the role of adornments. The move to interiority

    not one where form is opposed to ornament but

    where there is an already present interarticula-tionbegins to identify the particularity of

    Semper. While it is always possible to emphasise

    his engagement with ornamentation and even to

    construe the insistence on cladding in those

    terms, it is more productive to connect architectures

    concern with interiority to one with the centrality of

    materials. As such what this allows is a connection to

    be drawn between three aspects of his project. In

    the first instance the importance of the surface

    that emerged during the earlier engagement with

    his writings on polychromatic antiquities; in thesecond, interiority as a concern with architectures

    self-definition given through materials, and finally

    his identification of the four elements of architec-

    ture. What is important about those elements is

    the way they lead, almost inexorably, to establish

    the centrality of the wallas surfaceas the focus

    of architectural consideration.

    The wall figures significantly in the short text pub-

    lished in 1851,The Four Elements of Architecture: A

    Contribution to a Comparative Study of Architec-

    ture. In fact this work set in play the role of the

    wall throughout his subsequent writings. It drew

    on both his archaeological activities in addition to

    some of the conclusions reached during the period

    where his overriding intellectual concern was poly-

    chromatic antiquities. Semper uses the so-called

    elementsthe hearth, the roof, the enclosure

    and the mound (p. 102)to account for the

    origins of architecture. While these elements are,

    to a certain extent, fundamental, they are almost

    20

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    21/36

    inextricably connected to an historicist if not nostal-

    gic account of the origins of architecture. The inter-

    esting move occurs when Semper begins to trace

    the emergence of the wall from the enclosure.Before looking at the consequences of the move

    to the wall, it is essential to note that in Sempers

    account what is of interest to him is that it involved

    the introduction of a technique. It was not just any

    technique: the wall fitter (Wandbereiter) as proto-

    architect deployed an Urtechnik (p. 258); the way

    the wall emerges brings more than just a physical

    wall into consideration. The manner in which

    Semper engages with the wall is in terms of its pre-

    sence as a surface. Moreover, a surface that effects.

    This is the position that has to be established. (Reiter-ated therefore is the way the coloured surface was

    present in terms of its effect. While colour did not

    provide volume, it was colour that allowed Trajans

    Column its capacity to create space and therefore

    enabled it to have a civic function.)

    Prior to taking up the key passage from The Four

    Elementsconcerning the emergence of the wall, the

    claim announced a few lines earlier that wickerwork

    was the essence of the wall (p. 104), needs to be

    noted. Its significance is twofold. In the first

    instance, it is indicative of the general move within

    Sempers writings to preclude the possibility of a sus-

    tained distinction between the decorative and the

    functional, except insofar as the decorative

    becomes evidence not just of function but of the

    necessary interconnection of the functional and

    the material. Moreover, in the case of wickerwork

    what is essential is the relationship between

    materials and effect. What is significant about the

    claim that wickerwork comprises the essence of

    the wall, is that the essential cannot be differen-

    tiated from the operation of materials. Not only is

    this to insist on interiority, it allows for a link

    between materials, and that which demarcates thearchitectural, to have to be thought together. More-

    over it can be concluded that what the wall does is

    effect spatial enclosure, and therefore the function

    of the wallie, to spacecannot be thought as

    though it were independent of the operation of

    materials. This further accounts for why he states

    that wicker work is the essence of the wall. It

    involves the effects realisation through the use of

    materials. That move can then be abstracted such

    that it begins to define the nature of the wall.

    Walls, for Semper, cannot be separated from theactivity of spatial disclosure. From a Semperian per-

    spective space is not a given that is then divided.

    The contrary is the case. Space is a result. Hence,

    the wall is that which brings about spatial enclosure.

    In sum, space is the result of the surfaces operation.

    The detail of his position is formulated in The Four

    Elements of Architecturein the following terms.

    Hanging carpets remained the true walls, the

    visible boundaries of space. The often solid walls

    behind them were necessary for reasons that

    had nothing to do with the creation of space;

    they were needed for security, for supporting a

    load, for their permanence and so on. Wherever

    the need for these secondary functions did not

    arise, the carpets remained the original means

    for separating space. Even where building solid

    walls became necessary, the latter were only the

    invisible structure hidden behind the true and

    legitimate representatives of the wall, the colour-

    ful woven carpets. (P. 104.)

    21

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    22/36

    The importance of this formulation is that the wall is

    moved away from being no more than a structural

    element to having a clearly defined function within

    an overall structure.25

    While for Semper thereneeds to be an accord between the outward appear-

    ance of structural elements and the nature of that

    function, such a relationship resists any reformula-

    tion in terms of a theory of ornamentation. What

    has to be opened up is the potential in Sempers con-

    ception of the wall.

    Sempers project can be understood as the attempt

    to identify within the history of architecturespecifi-

    cally Hellenic arta principle that could be extracted.

    The nature of Sempers relationship to Quatreme` re de

    Quincy should inform a contemporary response to hisown work. The value for Semper of Quatreme` res

    writings on ancient sculpture is that they provide an

    opening. In Sempers terms it lay in their practical ten-

    dency. He continues:

    In line with this tendency the work does not as it

    were parade the form before us as a finished

    product according to the lessons of aesthetic ideal-

    ity, but lets us see the artistic form and the high

    idea (der Kunstform und der hohen Idee) that

    dwells within it; it considers and shows how both

    were inseparable from the material and technical

    execution and how the Hellenic spirit manifested

    itself in the freest mastery of these factors, as

    well as the old, sanctified tradition. (P. 249/p. 207.)

    The significance of the formulation lies in the

    differentiation of form from what can be termed

    aesthetic ideality. Form and ideas could not

    be separated from materials, the presentation of

    those materials and questions of technique.

    Semper therefore undoes the opposition between

    form and idea by incorporating both as material

    possibilities. Any vestige of that metaphysical dis-

    tinction is displaced by emphasis having been

    given to materials and techniques. Once the idea isno longer understood as external, then the building

    cannot be understood as the ideas symbolic

    presentation. Hellenic style therefore involved an

    interrelationship of all these elements. This accounts

    for why, in addition, art-form and decoration cannot

    be separated. They are, in Sempers terms, so

    intimately bound together by the influence of the

    principle of surface dressing (des Flachenbeklei-

    dungsprinzips) that an isolated look at either is

    impossible. (Pp. 252 3/p. 211.)

    What emerges from giving centrality to materialsis the possibility of arguing that materials are what

    they bring about, what they effect. When Semper

    argues that wickerwork was the original wall, it

    was because it was the original space divider.

    This realisation of division defined the essence of

    the wall. Any consideration of the wall therefore

    has to do with how materials realise their effect.

    This accounts for the move in the same text to the

    claim that the wall retained this meaning when

    materials other than the original were used (p.

    104). (It should be noted, if only in passing, that

    the connection is between meaning and materials

    and not meaning and symbolic determination.) The

    history of the wall therefore becomes the history

    of the way materials realise the wall effect. The

    wall effect is spatial division, although only ever as

    a result. Hence, it becomes possible to question

    both the quality of the space produced and the

    material creating it since spatial division is produced

    (effected) by the work of specific materials.

    22

    Surface effects:

    Borromini, Semper,

    Loos

    Andrew Benjamin

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    23/36

    There is a further result that should also be noted.

    Once it can be argued that the definition of the wall

    has to do with spatial enclosure and is not reducible

    to the presence of literal wallsa possibility alsoevident in Loos, as will be argued in relation to the

    Haus Muller, where the intersection of theRaumplan

    and the work of cladding produce volumetric differ-

    ence, hence the effect of the wallit then follows

    that the wall is not given in opposition to the

    floor.26 This point can be extended since if the wall/

    floor opposition no longer defines the work of the

    wallbut the wall is the wall effect, ie, spatial div-

    isionthis will result in the need for a reconsideration

    of the corner since the corner is defined by the inter-

    section of an already determined floor/wall relation-ship. That reconsideration means that the relationship

    between wall, floor and corner can be rethought; a

    relationship rearticulated as a surface. Not just a

    surface as a flat exterior but also a surface as tectonic

    entity; the reciprocity of materials and geometry. Fur-

    thermore programmatic demands necessitating that

    the elements of architecture have a distinct quality

    can locate that difference as individuated by a

    surface. Finally, therefore, the function of the wall is

    internal to the architecture in question thereby gener-

    ating a sense of autonomy, one reinforced by the

    move from an externally orientated symbolic

    meaning to an internally regulated system of activity.

    Furthermore, the wall cannot be thought outside its

    relationship to materiality. Sempers work dissolved

    the distinction between structure and ornament.

    The wall was given an integrity that came from its

    definition in terms of the effecting of spatial enclo-

    sure while at the same time locating that realisation

    in the operation of materials.

    Loos: the place of ornament

    Looss critique of ornament is well known. However,

    it acquires another dimension once that critique is

    connected to the work of the surface. Moreover,Loos relates, both implicitly and explicitly, a

    concern with the surface to the project of moder-

    nity. This emerges strikingly in his discussion of cos-

    tumes. Implicit in the argument is the position that

    differences in clothing habit are always more than

    the register of personal taste. Indeed, they are the

    enactment of different conceptions of historical

    time. These differences mark the presence of a con-

    flict that not only has a determining effect on the

    nature of the present, but also yields conflict

    as that which identifies the present. Writing of

    costumes, Loos argues the following:

    I too admit that I really take pleasure in the old

    costumes. But this does not give me the right to

    demand that he put them on for my sake. A

    costume is clothing that has frozen in a particular

    form; it will develop no further. It is always a sign

    that its wearer has given up trying to change his

    circumstances. The costume is the symbol of

    resignation.27

    This passage can be usefully juxtaposed with the

    one advancing the central argument of Ornament

    and Crime. What the juxtaposition shows is that

    Looss argument is not against ornament as such but

    on the role and place of ornament within modernity.

    As ornament is no longer organically related to

    our culture, it is no longer the expression of our

    culture. The ornament that is produced today

    bears no relation to us or to any other human

    in the world at large. It has no potential for

    development.28

    23

    The Journal

    of Architecture

    Volume 11

    Number 1

  • 8/12/2019 Surface Effects

    24/36

    What is being worked through in both passages is

    the way forms of material presence are already inter-

    woven with issues pertaining to historical time and

    thus modernity. The retention of ornament, muchlike the wearing of a costume, is viewed as antitheti-

    cal to the way the modern is understood. Ornament,

    in this sense, is a vestige. The overcoming of orna-

    ment does not give rise either to the positing of

    simple structure stripped of ornament or the

    recourse to mere form. What arises as a conse-

    quence is the surface. Even if the interior surfaces

    of Looss Haus and buildings appear to be heavily

    ornamented, from a Loosian perspective they are

    not. Cladding (Bekleidung) is not ornamentation.

    As with Semper cladding operates within architec-ture. Its presence is organisationaland hence

    related to programmatic distributionrather than

    having a purely symbolic role. Moreover, as with

    Semper, there is an important distinction between

    walls, understood as load bearing, and what was

    referred to before as the wall effect. The effect is

    the creation of space. Before pursuing the detail of

    the position, it should be noted that the shift from

    Semper to Loos is that the capacity of a surface to

    effect is located within the operation of architecture

    although now architectures operation is itself a con-

    sequence of having overcome the need to invest

    architecture with automatic symbolic value. The

    surface effect therefore is a sign of the modern

    both in its overcoming the hold of vernacular yet

    at the same time resisting the slide into the ubiquity

    of form in which formal presence is thought inde-

    pendently of programmatic effects. As a result the

    effect of cladding needs to be understood as being

    as much a connection of surfaces, function and

    modernity as it is the operation of architecture. In

    order to pursue how the effect of cladding operates

    it is essential to trace the way in which Loos begins

    to distinguish between literal walls and the wall assurface in his The Principle of Cladding.29 As with

    Semperand thus recalling Borrominispace

    (spacing as an activity and therefore as spatiality)

    results from the surfaces effect. With Loos,

    however, there is an important additional element.

    Again, the setting i