34
The History and Critique of Modernity: Dewey with Foucault against Weber To Appear In: Paul Fairfield (ed.), Dewey and Continental Philosophy Colin Koopman, University of California at Santa Cruz [email protected] Interpreting and Criticizing Modernity In bringing the philosophical traditions of pragmatism and genealogy to bear upon contemporary debates regarding modernity, the work of both John Dewey and Michel Foucault has been subjected to misinterpretations that portray both traditions in a way that depletes them of the full force of their critical insight. The source of these misinterpretations is in many cases an attempt to squeeze the philosophical projects of pragmatism and genealogy into the mold that shapes the thought of most participants on both sides of the modernity debates. This mold can usually be traced back to the work of the influential sociologist, political economist, and philosopher Max Weber. One unfortunate residue of the subtle dominance of Weberian concepts in contemporary debates over modernity is that many thinkers who operated largely outside of these 1

ssrn-id1011514

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

p

Citation preview

  • The History and Critique of Modernity:

    Dewey with Foucault against Weber

    To Appear In:

    Paul Fairfield (ed.), Dewey and Continental Philosophy

    Colin Koopman, University of California at Santa Cruz

    [email protected]

    Interpreting and Criticizing Modernity

    In bringing the philosophical traditions of pragmatism and genealogy to bear upon

    contemporary debates regarding modernity, the work of both John Dewey and Michel

    Foucault has been subjected to misinterpretations that portray both traditions in a way

    that depletes them of the full force of their critical insight. The source of these

    misinterpretations is in many cases an attempt to squeeze the philosophical projects of

    pragmatism and genealogy into the mold that shapes the thought of most participants on

    both sides of the modernity debates. This mold can usually be traced back to the work of

    the influential sociologist, political economist, and philosopher Max Weber. One

    unfortunate residue of the subtle dominance of Weberian concepts in contemporary

    debates over modernity is that many thinkers who operated largely outside of these

    1

  • concepts cannot be brought into these debates without filtering their thought through this

    conceptual prism. In the case of Dewey and Foucault, their contributions to our

    understanding of the basic problems of modernity are widely misunderstood due to being

    filtered through Weberian concepts that simply were not central in Deweys or Foucaults

    thinking.

    Weber was an extraordinarily complex thinker. This helps explain why his

    interpretation of modernity has proven capacious enough to provide fuel for both pro-

    modern optimists and anti-modern pessimists. But it is important to be precise here.

    Webers interpretation justifies either pro-modernism or anti-modernism and yet never

    both at the same time. Where Dewey and Foucault are interpreted through the Weberian

    prism, the usual result is to assimilate their critical stances on modernity to either side of

    this familiar for or against debate. Thus Dewey is often read as a resolutely optimistic

    modern thinker whose thought warrants comparison to Habermass defense of modernity.

    And Foucault is read from the opposite perspective as a decidedly pessimistic anti-

    modern whose thought can be usefully compared to such thoroughgoing attacks on

    modernity as those given by Adorno or Heidegger. But I want to suggest that Dewey and

    Foucault were operating outside of the orbit of Webers understanding of the basic

    problems of modernity and that this point of convergence is significant insofar as in both

    cases it is part of a broad interpretation of modernity which enables an alternative

    evaluation of modernity that cuts across all of the familiar either for or against positions

    which have left the current debates rather vacuous. Dewey and Foucault were complexly

    both for and against modernity. This more complex view leads in turn to a more

    effective critical stance than that mounted by Webers approach. My claim, importantly,

    2

  • is not that Webers work on modernity is burdened by a cognitive defect which Dewey

    and Foucault could help us to repair, but rather that Webers work is burdened by a

    critical deficit which Dewey and Foucault enable us to overcome. Weber did not get

    modernity wrong so much as he left us without any effective means to develop the better

    aspects of modernity whilst also resisting its worse parts.

    This essay attempts to more sharply define these points of contrast. My

    arguments here can be summarized as follows. Weber offered a sociological portrait of

    modernity in which the differentiation of value-spheres is the major thrust of modernity.

    Weber thus saw modernity in terms of the differentiation of such spheres as science and

    politics followed by the tendency toward the bureaucratization of each. Those working

    within Webers interpretation of modernity either celebrate the basic modern project of

    differentiation or mourn the lost unity and hope for some future reunification. Dewey

    and Foucault, by contrast, offered an intellectual historical portrait of modernity which

    focused not on the differentiation of sociological spheres but on the purification of

    separate modes of thinking. Dewey and Foucault should be read as responding to a

    modernity whose basic contrast is that between Enlightenment and Romanticism as

    described by intellectual historians such as Arthur Lovejoy and Isaiah Berlin.1 The

    paradigmatic forms of these two modern currents of thought are utilitarianism and

    romanticism. While present throughout modernity, utilitarianism and romanticism

    ascended to prominence over the course of the nineteenth century such that today we

    1 The contrast between Enlightenment and Romanticism is given central place by many important intellectual historians. Exemplary for my approach are Berlin (1960, 1965, 1975) and Lovejoy (1936). See also Maurice Mandelbaum (1971), Hayden White (1973), Charles Taylor (1989), David Hollinger (2001), and taking a much longer view see Harold Blooms (2004) description of Homeric cognitivism and Hebraic spiritualism as the two great forces of Western wisdom

    3

  • might refer to each as indispensable for modernity. It follows from their indispensability

    that any historical-philosophical evaluation of modernity must be able to accommodate

    both. Dewey and Foucault painstakingly labored to show that modernity has thus far

    accommodated both by means of a process which I call purificationour tendency to

    hold apart utility and romance, reason and imagination, sociality and individuality, public

    and private. Dewey and Foucault sought to elaborate an alternative means of

    accommodating these two currents of thought which I call experimentationon this

    model utility and romance would no longer be opposed currents of thought but would

    rather be alternative tendencies whose internal tensions it is our task as moderns to

    explore.

    By distancing Dewey and Foucault from Weber as concerns their interpretations

    of modernity a significant point begins to emerge: a hitherto unnoticed convergence

    between pragmatism and genealogy. This convergence is significant because

    comparative analyses of pragmatism and genealogy, like those of these two traditions and

    Weber described above, generally tend to miss the important points of resonance which

    prove these traditions much closer than is commonly thought.2 After explicating Weber,

    Dewey, and Foucault I will conclude my discussion by considering briefly the attractive

    philosophical possibilities of combing Deweys work on inquiry as reconstructive

    problem-solving with Foucaults work on critique as genealogical problematization.

    2 The most important of this work is that of Richard Rorty (1981a), but see also discussions by Cornel West (1989), Thomas McCarthy in Hoy and McCarthy (1994), John Patrick Diggins (1994), James Marshall (1994), Jim Garrison (1998), and Todd May (2004).

    4

  • Weber on Modernity

    There is much to be learned from Max Webers sociological interpretations of

    modernity. I will here focus on those interpretations only insofar as they can be read as

    representative of a very typical misinterpretation of modernity. While there are certainly

    other quite provocative and interesting ways of reading Weber, the view which continues

    to hold dominance over contemporary interpretations of modernity is that which

    emphasizes the familiar Weberian theme of differentiation and such of its implications as

    rationalization and bureaucratization.3

    Webers extraordinarily rich interpretation of modernity is above all distinguished

    by his strong claim that [o]ur age is characterized by rationalization.4 Weber

    understood the process of rationalization as locking us into an iron cage which

    inextricably binds our era to the technical and economic conditions of machine

    production which today determine the lives of all the individuals who are born into this

    mechanism.5 But Weber also thought that rationalization presents us with unique

    opportunities, precarious though they may be: The fate of an epoch which has eaten of

    the tree of knowledge is that it must know that we cannot learn the meaning of the world

    3 Recent revisionist scholarship notwithstanding, the best of which is Lawrence Scaff (1989) and Wilhelm Hennis (1987), most theorists continue to interpret Webers theory of modernity according to the classic terms of rationalizing differentiation-cum-bureaucratization established by Karl Lwith (1932), Reinhard Bendix (1960), and above all Talcott Parsons (1937). See Richard Swedberg (2003, 2005) on the current state of Weber scholarship. My presentation of Weber here is not so much an attempt at fine-grained Weber scholarship as it is an attempt to dispute the central Weberian theses which continue to exert tremendous influence on political philosophy and intellectual history. I leave it to others to show how the thought of Weber can today be reinterpreted so as to yield better resultsmy project is merely to cast doubt on a certain Weberianism dominant in contemporary histories and critiques of modernity. 4 Weber 1919, 30 5 Weber 1905, 181; cf. Weber 1923, 354.

    5

  • from the results of its analysis, be it ever so perfect; it must rather be in a position to

    create this meaning itself.6

    There is a basic ambiguity in Webers thought which enables critics as different in

    temper as pro-modern celebrants and anti-modern skeptics to take up their philosophical

    and political criticisms of modernity within his common interpretive framework.

    Webers concept of rationalization contains both an idea of the proliferation of

    instrumental rationality and an idea of the expansion of self-assertive free thinking. On

    the one hand modern rationalization seems to promise autonomy while on the other hand

    it seems to deliver us to obedience. Thus Alan Sica notes a Faustain bargain in Weber

    while Fritz Ringer describes the two faces of Webers evaluation of modernity.7 James

    Kloppenberg succinctly captures this basic duality in Webers thought: In one sense

    disenchantment meant decline, because it robbed man of confidence. But in another

    sense, it meant progress, because it opened the door to unprecedented autonomy.8

    Which is the real meaning of modernity? It is difficult to say. But perhaps it is not as

    important to determine which interpretation better reflects the facts as it is to recognize

    the underlying presuppositions which animate both interpretations. At the bottom of both

    estimations of rationalization is a separation between a certain picture of scientific

    technicization and a certain picture of political emancipation, that is a separation between

    the categories of objective control and subjective freedom in which Lawrence Scaff

    and others find a central tension in Webers thought.9 This process of separation-cum-

    development can help explain why pro-moderns can celebrate Weberian modernity (they

    6 Weber 1904, 57 7 Sica 2000, 56 and Ringer 2004, 220 8 Kloppenberg 1986, 345 9 Scaff 2000, 103

    6

  • recognize in it the basic promise of a rationalizing world) at the same time that anti-

    moderns can mourn Weberian modernity (they see in rationalization the promise of

    disenchantment and the impending demise of mystical moods).

    This core theme of the separation of technicization and emancipation is disclosed

    in Webers concept of differentiation, to which he once strikingly referred with his

    famous metaphor of the modern parceling-out of the soul.10 Differentiation refers to

    the modern tendency to splinter off from one another the various value-spheres such as

    science and politics. As value-spheres get increasingly differentiated powerful modes of

    thought are opened up whereby each domain can push its immanent logic to its furthest

    limits. This enables an unprecedented development of rationality in all spheres at the

    seemingly small cost of the isolation of each mode of practice from every another.

    In contemporary deployments of Webers interpretation of modernity, the idea of

    differentiation is marshaled to explain the increasing dissociation of, in particular, the two

    value-spheres of science and politics. The increasingly autonomous character of these

    value-spheres was discussed at length by Weber in his two Vocation Lectures.11 The

    distinction implicitly drawn in these lectures is not aimed at showing that scientific-

    instrumental rationalization is necessarily opposed to political-emancipatory

    rationalization. Weber was rather concerned to show that the spheres of science and

    politics are merely separable insofar as each is capable of autonomous development. It is

    this fact of autonomous internal development which Weber above all else marked as

    distinctive of modernity: technicization and emancipation are disconnected in a way that

    seems to promise an unprecedented development of each. It is true that this condition

    10 On the complicated textual context of this metaphor see Sica (2000, 53). 11 Weber (1917, 1919)

    7

  • ultimately drives us toward the conflict between the gods implicit in Webers claim

    that the different value systems of the world are caught up in an insoluble struggle with

    one another.12 But for Weber this fact of modern pluralism was not nearly as important

    as the differentiations giving rise to it.

    Differentiation on the whole can be understood in terms of the external face of

    bureaucratization which is symptomatic of an internal process of rationalization. David

    Owen and Tracy Strong claim that [b]ureaucracy is thus the front of a great historical

    process of rationalization.13 Bureaucratization and rationalization thus together form the

    core of the interpretation of modernity which Weber has bequeathed to much of

    twentieth-century critical theory. This iron-fisted image offers a seductive picture of

    modernity as an age where an ambiguous rationality comes to increasingly gather

    everything under its unified purview even if this rationality itself is necessarily

    differentiated in its various deployments. Weber thus beautifully portrayed that familiar

    image of modernity as the unity of reason in the diversity of its voices.

    This helps explain why pro-moderns and anti-moderns are both able to use

    Webers interpretation of modernity as a basis upon which to articulate their conflicting

    evaluations of modernity. While some witness differentiation as a legitimate move which

    today only requires piecemeal adjustment others regard it as signaling the demise of

    emancipation as modernity is increasingly swept up by promises of technicization. This

    suggests that pro-moderns and anti-moderns embrace all the same dualisms: reason

    versus imagination, intellect versus will, sameness versus difference, social versus

    individual, technicization versus emancipation. The only difference is that each side

    12 Weber 1917, 27, 22; see commentary by Raymond Aron (1959, 360-72). 13 Owen and Strong 2004, lvi

    8

  • inverts the privileges the other accords to either pole of these dualisms. As Bruno Latour

    states, [e]xcept for the plus or minus sign, moderns and antimoderns share all the same

    convictions.14 This series of basic contrasts, so easily and so often inflated into

    dichotomies, should be the focal point of attempts to evaluate the viability of Webers

    interpretation of modernity. The central question concerns whether or not Webers

    interpretation of modernity as an era of differentiation locks us into these contrasts or

    provides a means for thinking beyond them. My argument is that Webers theory forces

    us to leave modernity more or less where he finds it. It is, in other words, critically

    debilitating.

    This central problem in the Weberian frame is exemplified on both sides of the

    familiar debates between the pro-moderns and anti-moderns. The opposition between

    Habermas and Derrida, for example, reflects the Weberian assumptions which typically

    separate pro-moderns from anti-moderns.15 If Derrida is concerned to blur the very lines

    between philosophy and literature which Habermas strives to sharpen, then already both

    positions are framed in Weberian terms of differentiation, which Derrida is against and

    Habermas is for. In working from a Weberian starting point, whether consciously or not,

    such critics of modernity risk descending into reductive interpretations of modernity

    which can only yield simplistic for or against evaluations. This shows not that the work

    of Habermas and Derrida is essentially incorrect. It shows rather that thought that is so

    fecund can be rendered so barren by hewing to an interpretation of modernity that is all

    too often unquestioningly accepted. In order to adopt a properly critical relationship to

    14 Latour 1991, 123 15 While the Derrida-Habermas debates have been much discussed, two particularly helpful evaluations are those of Richard Bernstein (1991) and David Hoy (1989).

    9

  • modernity we must first adopt a critical relationship to modernitys interpretation of

    itselfwhich means getting away from a certain picture of modernity for which Weber is

    representative.

    Deweys and Foucaults Alternative to Weberian Sociology

    In focusing on modernity, pragmatism and genealogy have together departed from

    the sociological style of interpretation of which Weber is representative in favor of a

    more intellectual historical style of interpretation. This difference emerges as crucial

    when one moves on to develop critical evaluations of modernity on the basis of differing

    descriptive interpretations. Those working with Webers interpretation tend to evaluate

    modernity in terms of sociological categories such as science, politics, religion, and art.

    This too often leads to generalizing evaluations to the effect that science is good or

    religion is dangerous. Such views are rarely helpful because scientific and religious

    practices are often too complex for these canonical sociological boxes. Those working

    with Deweys and Foucaults interpretation would do better to focus instead on currents

    of thought and styles of practice such as utilitarianism, romanticism, rationalism, and

    mysticism. These currents of thought cut across familiar sociological distinctions. There

    are utilitarians and romantics in science, in politics, in religion, and in art. It is easy to

    generalize here too. But in turning from interpretation to evaluation, focusing on currents

    of thought enables us to distinguish what we like in scientific and religious practices from

    what we find troublesome. This means we can stop worshipping and castigating

    sociologically-defined categories such as science and religion in favor of a more complex

    argument to the effect that scientists and religions ought to play up some aspect of their

    10

  • practices whilst playing down other aspects. I will not here engage in this sort of

    evaluative work in order to concentrate instead on explicating the interpretations of

    modernity offered by Foucault and Dewey.

    Genealogists like Nietzsche and Foucault are, and not without some warrant,

    represented by most critics as firmly in the camp of the anti-modern pessimists.

    Countless commentators have suggested that Foucault intensifies all of the key problems

    formulated by Weber and thus leaves us impotent. The standard line is that whereas

    Weber saw modern rationalization as an iron cage Foucault saw it as a something like

    an iron cave which we cannot even see we are in let alone see our way out of. Indeed it

    is difficult not to hear the retroactive echo of Discipline and Punish when reading the

    passages on discipline in Economy and Society.16 Such echoes have led commentators as

    insightful as Paul Rabinow and Hubert Dreyfus to claim that Foucaults work should be

    seen as an advance, not a refutation of the Weberian project insofar as he inherits

    Webers concern with rationalization and objectification as the essential trend of our

    culture and the most important problem of our time.17 Rabinow and Dreyfus here make

    explicit a tacit assumption at work in much of Foucault criticism, both friendly and

    hostile. The assumption is that Foucault engages modernity to respond to the basic

    problem of differentiation paradigmatically formulated by Weber. 18

    Rather than expressing what is really valuable in Foucault, this common

    interpretation instead reflects just how pervasive the Weberian framework is for

    16 See Foucault (1975) and Weber (1964, 1148-1156). 17 Rabinow and Dreyfus 1982, 133, 166; in recent work Rabinow reiterates this interpretation (2003). 18 See work by John ONeill (1986), Peter Dews (1987), Colin Gordon (1987), Bryan Turner (1987), David Owen (1994), and Arpd Szakolczai (1998); for an excellent account of why Foucault should not be read in Weberian light see Mitchell Dean (1994).

    11

  • contemporary historical interpretations and critical evaluations of modernity. There are

    at least two difficulties yielded by reading Foucault through Weber. First, it is tough to

    square Webers image of value-sphere differentiation with Foucaults presentation of the

    increasing interlacing of power and knowledge in modernity. This is an example of how

    reading Foucault as a Weberian would expose Foucaults own thought to many of the

    traps which it was designed to point out. One of Foucaults most enduring points was

    that the core political problems of our day should not be described in terms of reunifying

    the differentiated modes of knowledge and power because this would merely be a call for

    more of the same. A second difficulty for reading Foucault as a Weberian is that it makes

    Foucault seem far less unique than he really is. Is Foucault really just one more protestor

    in a long line of intellectuals chanting the familiar mantras of anti-modernity? Foucault

    was certainly critical of modernity, but at the same time he positively embraced what he

    saw as its most valuable tendencies. Foucault was both for and against modernity.

    Rabinow claims that that Foucault did not proceed by opposing modernity to post-

    modernity, but by opposing modernity to counter-modernity, such that his parrhesiastic

    practice was simultaneously modern and counter-modern.19 What I am suggesting is that

    Rabinow is right to see Foucault as both modern and counter-modern, and that this sort of

    complex critical evaluation of modernity simply cannot be made sense of within the usual

    Weberian frame that so thoroughly dominates contemporary thought about modernity,

    counter-modernity, and post-modernity.

    Turning now to pragmatism, the interpretive situation is a little different, but no

    better for it. When pragmatism is not altogether neglected by those engaged in the

    19 Rabinow 1994, 197; cf. Rabinow and Dreyfus (1986).

    12

  • modernity debates, it is usually denounced as either a celebratory philosophy proclaiming

    all the benefits of the modern age or as a profoundly relativistic doctrine out of step with

    modern progress. Both of these caricatures borrow much from Weber and gather

    relatively little from Dewey. As for explicit comparative research on Weber and Dewey,

    there has been surprisingly little work here. The important exception is James

    Kloppenbergs skillful attempt to establish important points of connection between

    Weber and Dewey. Kloppenberg finds the most important point of overlap in Dewey and

    Webers shared view that differentiating rationalization is the central problem of

    modernity.20 Kloppenberg goes on to detail their divergence in terms of Deweys

    optimism and Webers pessimism in the face of this rationalization. While not

    discounting other similarities between Weber and Dewey concerning ethics and

    epistemology which Kloppenberg has helpfully explicated,21 I wish to call into question

    his claim for a more basic point of convergence in terms of their supposedly shared

    interpretation of modernity. We simply cannot make sense of Deweys most central

    commitments if we see him as responding to problems that were not really his but

    Webers. Weber sees modernity as haunted by a series of divisions which Dewey may

    indeed have found troubling had he not confronted modern culture as problematized by a

    more basic dichotomy. Weber saw modernity as split between science and morality, but

    Dewey saw modernity as split between utilitarian rationality and romantic pathos.

    Deweys view enabled him to move beyond many of those critically-debilitating

    20 Kloppenberg 1986, 349-94. In the only other comparative works on Dewey and Weber of which I am aware, Emirbayer (2005) rather loosely argues my point, Roederer (2000) concedes my point within an account which explicitly aims to build on Kloppenberg, while Diggins (1999) compares Dewey and Weber very quickly in only summary terms. 21 Kloppenberg 1994, 82-99

    13

  • categories which have haunted so much of modern thought, including Webers. This

    helps explain why Weber retained many of the dichotomies which Dewey thoroughly

    rejected (for instance, that between facts and values).22

    What I am claiming is that Deweys pragmatism should not be seen as an attempt

    to reunify the scientific and political spheres of experience, which is what Kloppenberg,

    Martin Jay, and numerous other intellectual historians of pragmatism have argued.23

    Deweys pragmatism is better seen as attempting to develop a conscious integration of

    utilitarian and romantic styles of thought. On the traditional interpretation, Dewey is

    presented as championing something called scientific method which supposedly stands in

    contrast to differentiated spheres of activity such as art, morality, and politics.24 But

    when Dewey spoke highly of science, he was not thinking of a separable sphere of human

    culture, because, after all, he would have agreed with Foucault that science gets practiced

    alongside of politics.25 Dewey, rather, was thinking of an attitude which he found

    exemplified in certain early modern scientists, but also in certain artists, politicians,

    novelists, and everyday people. This is the attitude of experimentalism and it was

    Deweys alternative to brazen celebrations of pure utility and pure romance. Deweys

    concern was not that modernity had parsed itself out into a good science over here and a

    bad morality over there, but rather that the attitude of experimentalism had not

    sufficiently taken hold throughout the great variety of our modern practices including our

    modern scientific practices. Dewey was interested in generalizing an isolated mode of

    22 In the two other comparative works on Dewey and Weber of which I am aware, Emirbayer (2005) rather loosely argues my point while Roederer (2000) concedes my point within an account which explicitly aims to build on Kloppenberg; Diggins (1999) compares Dewey and Weber only but only summarily. 23 See Kloppenberg (1986) and Jay (2005) 24 Helpful discussions of the charge of scientism in Dewey include those by Thayer (1968, 165ff.), Hollinger (1980, 29ff.), and Kloppenberg (1986, 383ff.). 25 See, for one of countless examples, Dewey (1939).

    14

  • experience thus far present only in the scientists laboratories. Rather, he was interested

    in reconstructing experience in terms of currents of thought which he thought could reach

    throughout modern consciousness. Dewey was not interested in praising a differentiated

    bureaucracy of science, but rather an experimentalism for which science had provided

    many, but certainly not the only, exemplars. Only on this view can we understand why in

    addition to certain scientific practices, Dewey also championed certain aesthetic,

    religious, political, and ethical practices. Dewey found in each of these the seeds of an

    experimentalism that he hoped could flower forth practically anywhere.

    Dewey and Foucault should not be read through the prism of Weberian concepts.

    Dewey and Foucault never argued that power and knowledge, expressions of the

    supposedly differentiated value-spheres of politics and science, ought not to be separated.

    They argued that the two had never been separated. Modernity as Weber described it had

    never taken place. As such, Dewey and Foucault never urged a reunification of the

    various modalities of experience split off into various differentiated value-spheres.

    Rather, they responded by urging the adoption of a critical attitude which both of them

    often referred to as experimentalism.

    Dewey on Modernity

    My approach to pragmatism takes as one of its points of departure Richard

    Rortys fertile suggestion that we think of pragmatism as romantic utilitarianism.26

    26 See numerous works by Rorty (1998a, 1998b, 2004). Similar interpretations of pragmatism as between romanticism and utilitarian positivism have been offered by James Livingston (1994, 2001), Thelma Lavine (1991, 1995), and H.S. Thayer (1968). Notable is George Herbert Meads view in his impressive intellectual history, Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century, where he explicitly contrasts

    15

  • Rortys image of pragmatism as an experimentalism which integrates romantic and

    utilitarian currents of thought captures what is best in the work of John Dewey. Seen in

    this way, the tradition of pragmatism should be understood as an attempt to further that

    experimental project of forging productive new relations among modernitys utilitarian

    and romantic tendencies.

    In books such as The Quest for Certainty and Reconstruction in Philosophy,

    Dewey describes modernity as held captive by a process of purification which rigorously

    divides reason from its others.27 Dewey here and elsewhere details the philosophical

    quest for certainty which emerged during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries as

    truth was increasingly identified with the condition of subjective certainty. Although this

    quest is unique to modernity, it is central to Deweys argument that it institutes no deep

    breaks from the ambition for transcendence that has characterized philosophy since its

    beginnings. In ancient thought, purity was figured as the self-identity of eternity. In

    medieval philosophy, the purity standard was similarly articulated as a divine force to

    which human reason and imagination should chain themselves. In modern thought,

    purity is relocated in the unassailability of mental certainty. The ongoing quest for

    certainty simply revamped the ancient and medieval quests for purity in the light of the

    subjectivism of the modern age. Going forward into the nineteenth century we witness

    the full and final solidification of the quest for certainty as the currents of utilitarianism

    and romanticism assumed cultural ascendance. What the simultaneous ascendance of

    these two opposed currents of thought signals is the meticulous purification of two modes

    pragmatism to the conception of inquiry common to the Romantic idealists and the rationalists according to which knowledge is a simple getting of the nature of the world (1936, 344). 27 Dewey (1929, 1920)

    16

  • of direct contact with truth. Certainty is enthroned as both a form of reason and a form of

    intuition or imagination. Dewey summarized this picture of modernity in his description

    of Kant as striving after cognitive certainty in the region of phenomena, practical

    certainty in the realm of moral authority.28

    The question for certainty thus entails a separation of pure reason from its others.

    This separation is the specific problem situation to which Dewey addressed his

    pragmatism. Without this historical interpretation of the central problem of modernity as

    its backdrop, much of Deweys thought remains difficult to understand. But with this

    backdrop in place, many of his most central concepts can be clarified. For example, this

    backdrop throws into clear relief Deweys attempt in his Ethics to reconstruct ethical

    practice in such a way that would bring together the insights of the utilitarian focus on

    instrumental rationality and the deontological focus on an active and spontaneous faculty

    of reason virtually indistinguishable from romantic imagination.29 Here as elsewhere,

    Dewey should be read as responding to a modernity in which the central problem we face

    is the separation not between two sociological spheres of experience but between two

    moods of prosaic utilitarianism and poetic romanticism.

    The central problem of modernity which emerges from Deweys writings is that

    of the basic contrast, urged by utilitarians and romantics alike, between pure utility and

    pure romance. From this there follows a whole train of invidious philosophical

    distinctions that Dewey finds misguided: reason versus imagination, sociality versus

    individuality, public versus private. As Dewey saw it in The Quest for Certainty such

    various attempts at purification are motivated by a yearning for benefits bestowed by

    28 Dewey 1929, 49 29 Dewey (1932)

    17

  • powers that transcend our mere humanity. It is above all against this philosophical

    thematic, and the modern figure of certainty which has been its outward face, that

    pragmatism was written. Rorty nicely captures pragmatisms quintessential skepticism

    toward the idea that there exist extra-human powers which we mere humans ought to try

    and get in touch with: The problem with both universalist metaphors of grandeur and

    romantic metaphors of depth is that they suggest that a practical proposal, whether

    conservative or radical in character, can gain strength by being tied in with something not

    merely humansomething like the intrinsic nature of reality or the uttermost depths of

    the human soul.30 The promises of grandeur and depth have been exciting for both

    romantics and utilitariansthe spirit of purity pervades modern thought in both of its

    major currents and the further each is pursued the more refined is its purification. It

    follows from all of this, however, that the category most central to Deweys own

    experimentalism, uncertainty, has been widely absent from most forms of utilitarianism

    and romanticism. Deweys experimentalism should thus be seen as an alternative that

    negotiates around both utility and romance which is to say that pragmatism is, to borrow

    from Rorty once again, an alternative to both universalism and romanticism.31

    All of this helps explain why the charges of scientism and aestheticism imputed to

    various pragmatists by their most hostile critics fail to capture crucial elements of

    pragmatist experimentalism. These crucial elements, I have argued, are likely to be

    overlooked if one understands pragmatism as attempting to come to terms with the kind

    of modernity described by Weber. Pragmatists understand politics and sciencepower

    and knowledge, value and factas reciprocal. Experimentalism is thus not operative

    30 Rorty 2004, 137 31 Rorty 2004, 136

    18

  • only in science (the scientism imputed to Dewey) or only in literature (the aestheticism

    imputed to Rorty and sometimes James). Once we start experimenting on any broad

    scale it turns out that science, aesthetics, and politics grow increasingly indistinguishable.

    Experimentalism must therefore work across power and knowledge at once as a quality

    operative throughout culture. The purest forms of utilitarianism and romanticism have

    rooted themselves in just this waypurity has been operative simultaneously in

    epistemic and political practice. Pragmatists interpret modernity as a series of decisive

    transformations reverberating throughout all of culturethe purification of reason and

    imagination that empties from each the corruptions of the other is a culture-wide project

    occurring in legislatures and laboratories simultaneously and with reciprocal benefit to

    both. The response to such a modernity bent on purification cannot be the expansion of

    an experimentalism thus far developed in only one of science or politics (thus replacing a

    monistic totalization for a purifying totalization), but rather must be an experimentalism

    that will increasingly pervade both simultaneously. Pragmatists thus urge a

    reconstruction of modern culture along paths worn by particular cultural moods (an

    experimentalism about knowledge and politics) rather than others (utilitarianism or

    romanticism about knowledge and politics). Rather than pressing for experimentalism on

    the basis of an implausible and unhappy divorce of politics from epistemics, then,

    pragmatists think of experimentalism in terms of synergistic democratizations of power

    and knowledge.

    This is an important point of connection linking pragmatism to genealogy. For in

    his attempt to develop an experimental alternative to prevailing cultural tendencies,

    Dewey makes much the same point as Foucault did when he envisioned practices of

    19

  • experimentation and transgression which could carry us beyond the dominant confines of

    modern thought. Deweys prose may have been limp and Foucaults sexy, but both were

    looking forward to a culture which would sustain itself by simply trying things out as an

    alternative to that cultural self-containment implicit in the modern will to purify.

    Foucault on Modernity

    I find the following remark of Foucaults one of the most fecund for

    understanding the whole of his work: In every culture there exists a coherent series of

    gestures of division [But] the moment they mark a limit, they create the space of a

    possible transgression.32 Across the long span of his career, Foucault returns again and

    again to his central theme of two moments of modernity: division and transgression, or

    purification and experimentation. These two moments form the central conceptual

    apparatus through which Foucaults many interpretations and critiques of modernity

    should be read.

    Since my interpretation of Foucault amounts to a significant revision of the

    standard reception of his work, it will be useful to summarize that standard reception in

    order to appreciate the terms of my revisionist reading in terms of modernitys divisions

    and transgressions. Most interpretations of Foucault leave him in a difficult bind

    according to which his image of modernity as increasingly swept up in an insidious form

    of disciplinary rationality provides us with little wiggle room by which we may come to

    understand ourselves as either free or at least someday capable of freedom. On this

    interpretation, a stifled and disturbed Foucault offers us little better than, in Richard

    32 Foucault, quoted by Miller (1993, 115) from Les dviations religieuses et la savoir medical (1962, 19).

    20

  • Rortys phrase, more and more sophisticated expressions of resentment.33 Even

    sympathetic critics such as James Bernauer similarly hold that confinements are the

    central experiences that Foucaults work describes.34 Consider the reception of Madness

    and Civilization and Discipline and Punish.

    In common accounts of Madness and Civilization, Foucault is described as tracing

    the history of a Western rationality that would separate itself from its primary other,

    namely madness, so as to exclude it from modern culture. For example, in his excellent

    book on Foucaults early work, Gary Gutting unfortunately presents Foucault as charting

    the suppression, conceptual exclusion, and condemnation of madness by reason.

    According to this common line of interpretation, Foucault near the end of the book issues

    a desperate cry on behalf of those banished madmen in lyrically invoking the names of

    Nietzsche and Artaud, Sade and Hlderlin. Gutting finds in these closing pages

    Foucaults romantic desire to see madness as an infrarational source of fundamental

    truth.35 This standard reading, the most forceful version of which was perhaps Jacques

    Derridas,36 appreciates Madness and Civilization as a lamentation over modern reasons

    domination of madness, a domination that seems to leave us all, including Foucault

    himself, feeling helplessly trapped in the iron cage of modern rationality.

    Similar interpretations structured the reception of Foucaults later work, most

    notably the image of modernity presented in Discipline and Punish. On the standard

    accounts, this book offered a diagram of the workings of an insidious and unbeatable

    form of power which had over the course of the past few hundred years come to structure

    33 Rorty 1981b, 6 34 Bernauer 1990, 16 35 Gutting 1989 71, 74, 89, 109 36 Derrida (1963)

    21

  • modern society, modern knowledge, modern law, and even modern subjectivity itself. It

    is Foucaults point, commentator after commentator declared, that we cannot free

    ourselves from the exercise of modern discipline. We inhabit the Panopticon everywhere

    and have so thoroughly internalized it that we all harbor little policemen running around

    inside of our heads preventing us from ever freeing ourselves. We are therefore swept up

    in a power which renders freedom totally impossible. Foucaults best critic on these

    matters was Habermas, whose chief complaint was that Foucaults interpretation of

    modernity under the sign of disciplinary power eviscerates from modernity the very

    premise of emancipation that is the condition of the possibility of critical reflection at all.

    Foucaults diatribe, Habermas concluded, took place under the very conditions of modern

    freedom which it announced as impossible.37

    Foucault found these early and late interpretations rooted in a misreading of his

    work. To counter them, I would like to focus on a claim Foucault made near the end of

    Madness and Civilization: Man and madman are bound by an impalpable connection of

    truth that is both reciprocal and incompatible.38 I find this idea of reciprocal

    incompatibility crucially helpful for understanding Foucault. This formulation suggests

    that Foucaults point is that the relations between pairs like madness and reason or power

    and freedom constitute the very problematic of modernity itself. What Foucaults

    histories of problematization demonstrate is that these relations are an intractable

    problem for moderns such that they are constitutive of the modern condition as such. To

    37 Habermas (1981, 1985). Habermas borrowed much of his argument from Nancy Fraser (1981) but see also related criticisms by Michael Walzer (1983), Charles Taylor (1984), Thomas McCarthy (1990), and Batrice Han (1998). 38 Foucault quoted in Eribon 1989, 97; this passage is from the longer version of Histoire de la Folie only recently translated into English.

    22

  • complain that Foucault failed to liberate either side of these oppositional terms from the

    total repression of the other, then, is to entirely miss his point. Foucaults point was that

    these terms are reciprocal but incompatible, that is they can neither be fully liberated

    from nor totally assimilated to one another. This can be clarified by revisiting both

    Madness and Civilization and Discipline and Punish.

    Take those seemingly romantic passages at the end of Madness and Civilization.

    Perhaps the Nietzsche in these pages is not for Foucault a forgotten madman, but rather

    the philosopher capable of reinvigorating a forgotten dialogue between madness and

    reason.39 Foucault laments not Nietzsche as madman, but the fact that a Nietzsche can no

    longer be on the border of reason and unreason since that border is forever banished by

    modern purification.40 On such a reading, Foucaults text would not witness reasons

    subjugation of madness so much as a more insidious separation of reason from madness.

    It is not that some former reality of madness is held at bay by the production of reason, it

    is rather that madness and reason in their modern form are simultaneously produced as

    incoherent with one another.

    This reading sustains Foucaults remark that the study of madness and rationality

    must go back toward the decision that simultaneously links and separates reason and

    madness; it must aim to uncover the perpetual exchange, the obscure common root, the

    original confrontation that gives meaning to the unity, as well as to the opposition, of

    sense and non-sense.41 We must, in other words, aim to restore that broken interaction

    where madness and rationality are interactive with one another. It was in this spirit that

    39 Clare OFarrell (1989, 74-78) develops a similar perspective. 40 Foucault 1961, 287 41 Foucault 1961 quoted in Derrida 1963, 43; from the longer version of Histoire de la Folie.

    23

  • Foucault in an early essay celebrated the possibility of the mad philosopher.42 The mad

    philosopher would be the kind of experimentalist who could at once be mad and be

    philosophical and in so doing transgress the separation of reason and madness which

    forms a core problem of our modernity. In praising the mad philosopher Foucault does

    not mourn a banished madman, but rather that forgotten space of interaction between

    madman and philosopher. He finds Nietzsche, the paradigm of the mad philosopher,

    waiting for us there.

    There is an important symmetry between Foucaults earlier work on modern

    reason and his later work on modern power. Just as madness can be neither totally

    subject to nor totally liberated from reason, freedom and power are similarly bound to

    one another. Seen in this light, Foucaults point in his late work on power and knowledge

    was never that we are trapped in power. Foucault, rather, sought carefully to elaborate

    the difficulty we moderns face in our task of simultaneously negotiating freedom and

    power. The complex idea that Foucault was striving to articulate and which so many of

    his critics misunderstood was that freedom and power can neither be dissociated nor

    assimilated. They must be deployed simultaneously so that we can work within the

    internal tensions of their relationships. Foucault therefore found himself working as a

    transgressor and an experimentalist at the interstices where freedom and power connect.

    The problem we moderns face, as Foucault elaborated it, is that there is no pure

    freedom to be emancipated just as there is no pure power to repress it. Modernity

    produces autonomous freedom and disciplinary power as two reciprocal but incompatible

    aspects of our political existence. These two presuppose one another but are at the same

    42 Foucault 1963, 80

    24

  • time incoherent with one another. So it is not that disciplinary power eliminates

    autonomous freedom, just as it is not that modern rationality eliminates madness. It is

    rather that disciplinary power and autonomous freedom are simultaneously produced so

    as to render the latter ineffective as a force pitted against the former. Just as madness

    finds itself in no position to question reason, freedom understood on the modern model of

    autonomy finds itself hardly equipped to oppose power on the model of discipline.

    Foucault held that the freedom of resistance must be sought elsewhere than in the

    romantic ideals of autonomy and liberation. Discipline and Punish had shown that

    autonomous individuality is one of the intended effects of disciplinary power, rather than

    a predisciplinary capacity for freedom which might seek revenge on power.43 Freedom,

    Foucault concluded, must work through, not merely against, power. But it was never

    Foucaults point that we need regard modernity as a traphis more modest point was

    simply that the modern conception of an autonomous freedom totally liberated from

    power is but a corollary of a disciplinary power which totally cages up freedom.

    Foucaults work on freedom is best interpreted in light of a distinction between an

    autonomous freedom already presupposed by modern forms of power and an

    experimental freedom which offers resistance to both modern power and modern freedom

    in their pure forms.44 Difficult as it may seem, and it was precisely Foucaults point that

    it would be difficult, resistance to modern practices of power requires resistance to a

    certain modern conception of the practice of freedom. This twin resistance to power and

    freedom suggests an internal connection between selfhood and environment such that the

    transformation of either requires the transformation of both. Experimentally freeing

    43 Foucault 1975, 184ff.; cf. Foucault (1979) and Gordon (1991). 44 See a similar distinction by John Rajchman (1985, 92, 115) and discussion by David Hoy (2004, 100).

    25

  • ourselves of particular forms of power circulating through us, therefore, involves freeing

    ourselves of the forms of freedom through which we enable that circulation. Judith

    Butler claims this in writing that, in Foucault, To be critical of an authority that poses as

    absolute requires a critical practice that has self-transformation at its core.45

    Understanding his problematization of modern freedom and power in this way

    enables us to recognize that Foucaults late work on ethics never sought to rehabilitate the

    autonomous form of freedom which Foucaults middle work on power had ruled out.46

    Foucaults late work on ethical freedom is best understood as elaborating the possibility

    for a modern form of experimental liberty on the basis of the study of pre-modern

    practices in which freedom and power were not yet purified as they were to become in

    modernity. Foucault thus did not in his late work abandon his earlier theses about

    modern power in order to elaborate a theory of modern freedom which these theses had

    explicitly invalidated.47 On the contrary, Foucaults late work elaborates a conception of

    experimental freedom which specifically aims to address the very problem established by

    our reciprocal but incompatible practices of modern disciplinary power and modern

    autonomous freedom.48

    What the foregoing discussion of Madness and Civilization and Discipline and

    Punish shows is just how much Foucaults picture of modernity differs from the standard

    Weberian image of modernity as an age of rationalizing differentiation. Foucaults

    emphasis on experimental transgression and his concern with the pernicious effects of

    45 Butler 2002, 218 46 Foucault (1984a) 47 Among those arguing for a basic incoherence between the so-called middle and late works are Peter Dews (1989), Thomas McCarthy (1990), Batrice Han (1998) and Eric Paras (2006). 48 Among those arguing for important continuities between the so-called middle and late works are Ladelle McWhorter (1999, 189ff.), Timothy OLeary (2002, 107ff.), Johanna Oksala (2005, 157ff.), Benda Hofmeyr (2006), and Amy Allen (forthcoming, chapter 3).

    26

  • much that has marched under the banner of modernity simply would not make sense if

    interpreted through the Weberian picture of modernity. Foucault did not witness the

    increasing differentiation of the vocations of science and politics. What he witnessed

    rather was the increasing purification, the reciprocal incompatibility, of two great cultural

    imperatives: emancipatory freedom on the one side and disciplinary control on the other.

    So it would not make sense to understand Foucault as having rallied against

    rationalization in the name of enchantment or mysticism or revolt or any other favorite of

    romanticism. Foucault was never against reason and simply for passion, madness, and

    freedom. He is better seen as having explored the long and slow formation of those great

    divisions, those formidable reciprocal incompatibilities, through which we moderns have

    attempted to erect high walls separating our reasons from our passions, our sociality from

    our individuality, our utility from our romance. It was these walls that he found

    debilitating, not the concepts (instrumental rationality, romantic passion) located on

    either side of them. If Foucaults critical histories have any positive upshot, then it

    consists in his articulation of practices of experimental transgression which would aim to

    tear these walls down. These transgressions would not demonstrate that reason and its

    others are really the same, but would open up the possibility of a new phase of modernity

    in which these two aspects of modern culture were not as rigorously purified as they were

    in previous phases of modernity. This new phase was envisioned by Foucault not as a

    reunification of power and knowledge (for that is what modernity has deployed all along)

    but rather as an intensification of experimental tensions resulting from the blending of

    powers and freedoms, rationalities and madnesses. That is why Foucault should be read

    27

  • as neither pro-modern nor anti-modern, but as complexly modern in the interests of a

    future phase of modernity.49

    Toward a Genealogical Pragmatist Critique of Modernity

    Foucault and Dewey are best read as picking up on a crucial but underdeveloped

    aspect of Kants legacy to modernity. Weber, and all those in his train, located Kants

    legacy in a modern tendency toward differentiation by which we have carved ourselves

    up into separate spheres according to the critical limits located in the first two Critiques.

    But Foucault and Dewey located Kants legacy elsewhere. According to their view, we

    do not find ourselves divided into the two worlds of experience discerned by a

    sociological interpretation of Kants critical philosophy. We find ourselves instead

    divided into two currents of thought, or two different standpoints for thinking, which

    Kants critical system was an attempt to do simultaneous justice to. This division in

    thought should not be overcome by reunifying supposedly divided spheres of experience,

    but rather by experimentally testing the divisions between utilitarian rationality and

    romantic autonomy which we impose on ourselves.

    The important details of Deweys and Foucaults conceptions of an experimental

    critique of ourselves will have to be elaborated on another occasion. What I have sought

    to focus attention on here is the important overlap between Deweyan pragmatism and

    Foucaultian genealogy in their interpretations of the basic problems of modern culture.

    In closing, I would like to point out that from the point of view of both traditions this is

    no small similarity. Both traditions hold that processes such as modernity gain their

    49 See the interpretations offered by Rabinow and Dreyfus (1986), Hoy (1988), and Rabinow (1994).

    28

  • coherence from the problems they are formulated as responses to, such as the inheritance

    of utilitarian disciplinary imperatives and romantic emancipatory dreams. Gaining a

    view of the problems we face is, for both genealogy and pragmatism, a crucial task for

    thought. On Deweys view, this is expressed in terms of his account of inquiry as

    beginning with and aiming at the resolution of a problem situation.50 On Foucaults

    view, this is expressed in his articulation of a historiography focused around

    problematizations, or the ways in which accepted truths come to be problematized over

    time and as a result propel the new truths achieved by the resolution of these problems.51

    This shared focus on problems suggests an important elective affinity among pragmatism

    and genealogy which those working in both traditions have thus far failed to take

    seriously enough.52

    Despite these similarities concerning their shared focus on thought as addressed to

    problems, an important difference is that Foucault was largely focused on the creation of

    problems and Dewey on their resolution. This difference has given rise to the familiar

    caricatures of Foucault as somewhat too pessimistic and Dewey as somewhat too

    optimistic, caricatures which are ultimately unfair but nevertheless rooted in obvious

    predilections of both thinkers. Fortunately, this seeming disjunction is easily overcome.

    All we need to do is to recognize that, from a robustly philosophical rather than a merely

    scholarly point of view, pragmatist problem-solving and genealogical problem-specifying

    are two activities that require one another. Problems that do not invite solutions are as

    50 Dewey (1938) 51 Foucault (1984b) 52 Overlaps between Dewey and Foucault along these lines have thus far been very much unexplored, although an important comparison in similar terms is given by Rabinow (2003, forthcoming). For important comparative work on Dewey and Foucault along different lines see Stuhr (1997, 2003), Auxier (2002), and my own work in Koopman (2007, forthcoming).

    29

  • worthless as solutions which do not respond to problems. The prospective orientation of

    pragmatism is blind without the retrospective orientation of genealogygenealogy

    without pragmatism is likewise an empty exercise.

    By bringing genealogy and pragmatism into intimate dialogue with one another

    we are finally able to realize the important promise that lay at the heart of both traditions:

    that we moderns can look forward with hope when we face up to the endless uncertainty

    which threatens continually to undo everything which we have in our history struggled to

    create. We can characterize both traditions as oriented simultaneously toward

    problematization and solution, toward past and future, and toward history and

    philosophy. This characterization fits with what is best in both Deweys pragmatism and

    Foucaults genealogy: the practice of a criticism that is simultaneously philosophical and

    historical.53

    References

    Allen, Amy. Forthcoming. The Politics of Our Selves. New York: Columbia University, forthcoming. Aron, Raymond. 1959. Max Weber and Modern Social Science in Aron, Franciszek Draus (ed.), Charles

    Krance (trans.), History, Truth, and Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1985. Auxier, Randall. 2002. Foucault, Dewey, and the History of the Present in The Journal of Speculative

    Philosophy 16, no. 2, Summer, 2002: 75-102. Bendix, Reinhard. 1960. Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait. London: Methuen, 1966. Berlin, Isaiah. 1960. The Romantic Revolution: A Crisis in the History of Modern Thought in Berlin,

    Henry Hardy (ed.), The Sense of Reality. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux, 1996. Berlin, Isaiah. 1965. The Roots of Romanticism. Henry Hardy (ed.). Princeton: Princeton University, 1999. Berlin, Isaiah. 1975. The Apotheosis of the Romantic Will in Berlin, Henry Hardy (ed.), The Crooked

    Timber of Humanity. Princeton: Princeton University, 1990. Bernauer, James. 1990. Michel Foucaults Force of Flight. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1990. Bernstein, Richard. 1991. An Allegory of Modernity/Postmodernity: Habermas and Derrida in Bernstein,

    The New Constellation. Oxford: Polity Press, 1991.

    53 For helpful comments on this paper I would like to thank Barry Allen, David Hoy, and Martin Jay, each of whom made valuable suggestions on how to improve the explications and arguments herein. In addition, Amy Allen read a longer version of the section on Foucault and offered helpful comments on issues raised in that discussion. Lastly, I gratefully acknowledge a postdoctoral research grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada which provided me with the opportunity to undertake this work and the larger project of which it is a part.

    30

  • Bloom, Harold. 2004. Where Shall Wisdom Be Found? New York: Penguin, 2004. Butler, Judith. 2002. What is Critique? An Essay on Foucaults Virtue in David Ingram (ed.), The

    Political. Oxford: Blackwell, 2002. Dean, Mitchell. 1994. Critical and Effective Histories: Foucaults Methods and Historical Sociology. New

    York: Routledge, 1994. Derrida, Jacques. 1963. Cogito and the History of Madness in Derrida, Alan Bass (trans.), Writing and

    Difference. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1978. Dewey, John. 1920. Reconstruction in Philosophy in Dewey MW12. Dewey, John. 1929. The Quest for Certainty in Dewey LW4. Dewey, John and Tufts, James H.. 1932. Ethics, revised edition in Dewey LW7. Dewey, John. 1938. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry in Dewey LW12. Dewey, John. 1939. Theory of Valuation in Dewey LW13 Dewey, John. 1969-1990. The Early Works (EW1-5), The Middle Works (MW1-15), and The Later Works

    (LW1-17). Jo Ann Boydston et. al. (eds.). Southern Illinois University, 1969-1990. Dews, Peter. 1987. Logics of Disintegration: Post-Structuralist Thought and the Claims of Critical Theory.

    London: Verso, 1987. Dews, Peter. 1989. The Return of the Subject in Late Foucault in Radical Philosophy, 51, Spr., 1989: 37-

    41. Diggins, John Patrick. 1999. Max Weber: Politics and the Spirit of Tragedy. New York: Basic Books,

    1999. Emirbayer, Mustafa. 2005. Beyond Weberian Action Theory in Charles Camic, et. al. (eds.), Max

    Webers Economy and Society. Stanford: Stanford Univeristy, 2005. Eribon, Didier. 1989. Michel Foucault. Betsy Wing (trans.). Cambridge: Harvard University, 1991. Foucault, Michel. 1961. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, Richard

    Howard (trans.). Vintage Books, 1965. Foucault, Michel. 1963. A Preface to Transgression in Foucault EW2. Foucault, Michel. 1975. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan. Vintage

    Books, 1995. Foucault, Michel. 1979. Omnes et Singulatim: Toward a Critique of Political Reason in Foucault EW3. Foucault, Michel. 1984a. What is Enlightenment? in Foucault EW1. Foucault, Michel. 1984b. Polemics, Politics and Problematizations, interview by Rabinow, in Foucault

    EW1. Foucault, Michel. 1997-2000. Essential Works, Volumes 1-3 (EW1-3). Paul Rabinow and James D.

    Faubion (eds.) New York: New Press, 1997-2000. Fraser, Nancy. 1981. Foucault on Modern Power: Empirical Insights and Normative Confusions in

    Unruly Practices. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1989. Garrison, Jim. 1998. Dewey, Foucault, and Self-Creation in Educational Philosophy and Theory 30, no.

    2, 1998: 111-134. Gordon, Colin . 1991. Governmental Rationality: An Introduction in Burchell, Gordon, and Miller (eds.),

    The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1991. Gutting, Gary. 1989. Michel Foucaults Archaeology of Scientific Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University, 1989. Habermas, Jrgen. 1981. Modernity versus Postmodernity, Seyla Benhabib (trans.), in New German

    Critique 22, Winter, 1981. Habermas, Jrgen. 1985. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Frederick Lawrence (trans.).

    Cambridge: MIT, 1987. Han, Batrice. 1998. Foucaults Critical Project. Edward Pile (trans.). Stanford: Stanford University, 2002. Hennis, Wilhelm. 1987. Max Weber: Essays in Reconstruction. Keith Tribe (trans.). London: Allen &

    Unwin, 1988. Hofmeyr, Benda. 2006. The Power Not to Be (What We Are): The Politics and Ethics of Self-Creation in

    Foucault in Journal of Moral Philosophy, 3(2), Jul., 2006: 215-230. Hollinger, David. 1980. The Problem of Pragmatism in American History in Hollinger, In the American

    Province: Studies in the History and Historiography of Ideas. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1989. Hollinger, David. 2001. The Enlightenment and the Genealogy of Cultural Conflict in the United States

    in Baker and Reill 2001. Hoy, David (ed.). 1986. Foucault: A Critical Reader. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, 1986.

    31

  • Hoy, David Couzens. 1988. Foucault: Modern or Postmodern? in Jonathan Arac (ed.), After Foucault. New Brunswick: Rutgers University, 1988.

    Hoy, David Couzens. 1989. Splitting the Difference: Habermass Critique of Derrida in G.B. Madison (ed.), Working Through Derrida. Evanston: Northwestern University, 1993.

    Hoy, David and McCarthy, Thomas. 1994. Critical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 1994. Hoy, David Couzens. 2004. Critical Resistance. Cambridge: MIT, 2004. Jay, Martin. 2005. Songs of Experience: Modern American and European Variations on a Universal

    Theme. Berkeley: University of California, 2005. Kloppenberg, James T.. 1986. Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and Progressivism in European and

    American Thought: 1870-1920. Oxford: Oxford University, 1986. Kloppenberg, James. 1994. Democracy and Disenchantment: From Weber and Dewey to Habermas and

    Rorty in Kloppenberg, The Virtues of Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University, 1998. Koopman, Colin. 2007. A New Foucault: The Coming Revisions in Foucault Studies (review essay) in

    Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy, v11n1, Spring 2007: 167-177. Koopman, Colin. Forthcoming. Genealogical Pragmatism: Problematization and Reconstruction. Latour, Bruno. 1991. We Have Never Been Modern. Catherine Porter (trans.). Cambridge: Harvard

    University, 1993. Lavine, Thelma Z.. 1991. Modernity and the Spirit of Naturalism in Proceedings and Addresses of the

    American Philosophical Association 65, no. 3, Nov., 1991. Lavine, Thelma Z.. 1995. America and the Contestations of Modernity: Bentley, Dewey, Rorty in

    Herman Saatkamp (ed.), Rorty and Pragmatism: The Philosopher Responds to His Critics. Vanderbilt University, 1995.

    Livingston, James. 1994. Pragmatism and the Political Economy of Cultural Revolution, 1850-1940. University of North Carolina, 1997.

    Livingston, James. 2001. Pragmatism, Feminism, and Democracy: Rethinking the Politics of American History. Routledge, 2001.

    Lovejoy, Arthur O.. 1936. The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Cambridge: Harvard University, 1964.

    Lwith, Karl. 1932. Max Weber and Karl Marx in Bottomore and Outhwaite (eds.), Karl Lwith: Max Weber and Karl Marx. London: Routledge, 1993.

    Mandelbaum, Maurice. 1971. History, Man, and Reason: A Study in Nineteenth-Century Thought. Balitmore: Johns Hopkins, 1971.

    Marshall, James D.. 1994. On What we May Hope: Rorty on Dewey and Foucault in Studies in Philosophy and Education 13, 1994: 307-323.

    May, Todd. 2004. Michel Foucault: Nietzschean Pragmatist in International Studies in Philosophy 36, no. 3, 2004: 63-75.

    McCarthy, Thomas. 1990. The Critique of Impure Reason: Foucault and the Frankfurt School in Political Theory, 18(3), Aug., 1990: 437-69.

    McWhorter, Ladelle. 1999. Bodies and Pleasures: Foucault and the Politics of Sexual Normalization. Bloomington: Indiana University, 1999.

    Mead, George Herbert. 1936. Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century. Merrit Moore (ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago, 1936.

    Miller, James. 1993. The Passion of Michel Foucault. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1993. OFarrell, Clare. 1989. Michel Foucault: Historian or Philosopher? London: Macmillan, 1989. OLeary, Timothy. 2002. Foucault and the Art of Ethics. London: Continuum, 2002. ONeill, John. 1986. The Disciplinary Society: from Weber to Foucault in The British Journal of

    Sociology 37(1), Mar., 1986: 42-60. Oksala, Johanna. 2005. Foucault on Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2005. Owen, David and Strong, Tracy. 2004. Max Webers Calling to Knowledge and Action in Weber 2004. Owen, David. 1994. Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the Ambivalence of Reason.

    New York: Routledge, 1994. Paras, Eric. 2006. Foucault 2.0: Beyond Power and Knowledge. New York: Other Press, 2006. Parsons, Talcott. 1937. The Structure of Social Action. New York: Free Press, 1968. Rabinow, Paul and Dreyfus, Hubert. 1982. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics.

    Chicago: University of Chicago, 1982.

    32

  • Rabinow, Paul and Dreyfus, Hubert. 1986. What is Maturity? Habermas and Foucault on What is Enlightenment in Hoy 1986.

    Rabinow, Paul. 1994. Modern and Counter-Modern: Ethos and Epoch in Heidegger and Foucault in Gary Gutting (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1994.

    Rabinow, Paul. 2003. Anthropos Today: Reflections on Modern Equipment. Princeton: Princeton University, 2003.

    Rabinow, Paul. Forthcoming. Marking Time. Princeton: Princeton University, forthcoming. Rajchman, John. 1985. Michel Foucault: The Freedom of Philosophy. New York: Columbia University,

    1985. Ringer, Fritz. 2004. Max Weber: An Intellectual Biography. Chicago: University of Chicago, 2004. Roederer, Christopher. 2000. Ethics and Meaningful Action in the Modern/Postmodern Age: A

    Comparative Analysis of John Dewey and Max Weber in South African Journal of Philosophy 19(2), 2000: 75-94.

    Rorty, Richard. 1981a. Method, Social Science, and Social Hope in Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1982.

    Rorty, Richard. 1981b. Beyond Nietzsche and Marx, London Review of Books, 19, February 1981: 5-6. Rorty, Richard. 1998a. Afterword: Pragmatism, Pluralism and Postmodernism in Rorty, Philosophy and

    Social Hope. New York: Penguin, 1999. Rorty, Richard. 1998b. Pragmatism as Romantic Polytheism in Morris Dickstein (ed.). The Revival of

    Pragmatism. Durham: Duke University, 1998. Rorty, Richard. 2004. Universalist Grandeur, Romantic Depth, Pragmatist Cunning in Diogenes 51, no.

    202, Smr., 2004. Scaff, Lawrence A.. 1989. Fleeing the Iron Cage: Culture, Politics, and Modernity in the Thought of Max

    Weber. Berkeley: University of California, 1991. Scaff, Lawrence A.. 2000. Weber on the Cultural Situation of the Modern Age in Stephen Turner (ed.),

    The Cambridge Companion to Weber. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 2000. Sica, Alan. 2000. Rationalization and Culture in Stephen Turner (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to

    Weber. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Stuhr, John. 1997. Genealogical Pragmatism: Philosophy, Experience, and Community. Albana: SUNY,

    1997. Stuhr, John. 2003. Pragmatism, Postmodernism, and the Future of Philosophy. New York: Routledge,

    2003. Swedberg, Richard. 2003. The Changing Picture of Max Webers Sociology in Annual Review of

    Sociology 29, Aug., 2003: 283-306. Swedberg, Richard. 2005. The Max Weber Dictionary. Stanford: Stanford University, 2005. Szakolaczai, Arpad. 1998. Max Weber and Michel Foucault: Parallel Life-Works. New York: Routledge,

    1998. Taylor, Charles. 1984. Foucault on Freedom and Truth in Hoy 1986. Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard

    University, 1989. Thayer, H.S.. 1968. Meaning and Action, A Critical History of Pragmatism, second edition. Indianapolis:

    Hackett, 1981. Turner, Bryan. 1987. The Rationalisation of the Body: Reflections on Modernity and Discipline in in S.

    Whimster and S. Lash (eds.), Max Weber, Rationality and Modernity. London: Allen and Unwin, 1987.

    Walzer, Michael. 1983. The Politics of Michel Foucault in Hoy 1986. Weber, Max. 1904. Objectivity in Social Science and Social Policy in Weber, Edward Shils and Harry

    Finch (eds.), The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Free Press, 1949. Weber, Max. 1905. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Talcott Parsons (trans.). Dover, 2003. Weber, Max. 1917. Science as a Vocation in Weber 2004. Weber, Max. 1919. Politics as a Vocation in Weber 2004. Weber, Max. 1923. General Economic History. Frank Knight (trans.). S. Hellman and M. Palyi (eds.).

    Dover, 2003. Weber, Max. 1964. Economy and Society. Guenter Roth, Claus Wittich, et. al. (ed. and trans.). Berkeley:

    University of California, 1978.

    33

  • 34

    Weber, Max. 2004. The Vocation Lectures. David and Owen and Tracy Strong (eds.), Rodney Livingstone (trans.). Hackett, 2004.

    West, Cornel. 1989. The American Evasion of Philosophy. Madison: University of Wisconsin, 1989. White, Hayden. 1973. Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe. Baltimore:

    Johns Hopkins, 1973.

    The History and Critique of Modernity:Dewey with Foucault against WeberTo Appear In:Paul Fairfield (ed.), Dewey and Continental PhilosophyColin Koopman, University of California at Santa [email protected] and Criticizing ModernityWeber on ModernityDeweys and Foucaults Alternative to Weberian SoDewey on ModernityFoucault on ModernityToward a Genealogical Pragmatist Critique of ModernityReferences