Spinozas Religious Philosophy

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    1/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    1

    SPINOZA AND THE DUTCH CARTESIANS ON PHILOSOPHY AND

    THEOLOGY

    Abstract

    Spinozas Tractatus Theologico-Politicus contains a famous injunction to separate

    philosophy from theology and vice-versa. In this paper I argue that, notwithstanding this

    injunction, Spinoza made an implicit claim that philosophy can, in certain cases, qualify as a

    form of theology. Properly understanding Spinozas complex views concerning the

    relationship between philosophy and theology requires us to situate his work in the context of

    philosophical discussions taking place during his own time and in his own country of

    residence, the Dutch Republic. I argue that his views were developed in response to a thesis

    advanced by a group of Dutch Cartesians including Johannes De Raey, Christoph Wittich,

    Abraham Heidanus, Lambert van Velthuysen, and others. They held that philosophy and

    theology must be separated because neither can fulfil the function of the other; indeed,

    neither is even relevant to the function of the other. While Spinoza might seem to have

    agreed with this Dutch Cartesian separation thesis, in fact he undermined it.

    1. Introduction

    Spinozas Tractatus Theologico-Politicus contains a famous injunction to separate

    philosophy from theology and vice-versa. In this paper I argue that, notwithstanding this

    injunction, Spinoza made an implicit claim that philosophy can, in certain cases, qualify as a

    form of theology. Properly understanding Spinozas complex views concerning the

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    2/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    2

    relationship between philosophy and theology, I contend, requires us to situate his work in

    the context of philosophical discussions taking place during his own time and in his own

    country of residence, the Dutch Republic. Of particular relevance is a meta-philosophical

    thesis advocated by a certain group of Cartesian philosophers and theologians. Their thesis

    was developed in response to attacks on Cartesianism from more conservative authors, who

    saw it as a source of impiety. It stated that Cartesian philosophy, properly understood, is

    neither pious nor impious. It cannot help to answer questions about theology, nor can it

    provide knowledge of any relevance to advancing human wellbeing and salvation.

    Theo Verbeek has already argued that understanding this Dutch Cartesian thesis is

    relevant to understanding important features of Spinozas thought.1 I build upon his work to

    argue that Spinozas views concerning between religion and philosophy should be

    understood as a conscious repudiation of it. The Dutch Cartesians genuinely hoped to

    separate philosophy from theology. Spinoza similarly claimed to separate them, but he meant

    far less by this separation than the Dutch Cartesians had meant by it. He held that what

    1 See Theo Verbeek, 'Les Cartsiens Face Spinoza: l'Exemple de Johannes de Raey,' in The

    Spinozistic Heresy = L'Hrsie Spinoziste: the Debate on the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, 1670-

    1677, ed. Paolo Cristofolini (Amsterdam: APA-Holland University Press, 1995), Theo Verbeek,

    'Spinoza and Cartesianism,' inJudaeo-Christian Intellectual Culture in the Seventeenth Century: a

    Celebration of the Library of Narcissus Marsh (1638-1713), ed. Allison Coudert (Dordrecht ;

    London: Kluwer Academic, 1999), Theo Verbeek, 'Spinoza et la Tradition des Analytiques

    Postrieures,' in Spinoza et les Scholastiqus (Conference at Paris, Sorbonne: 2008), Theo Verbeek,'Spinoza on the Truth and Certainty of Scientific Knowledge (unpublished),' (Utrecht: 2008), Theo

    Verbeek, Spinoza's Theologico-Political Treatise: Exploring 'the Will of God'(Aldershot: Ashgate,

    2003) esp. ch.6, Theo Verbeek, 'Wittich's Critique of Spinoza,' inReceptions of Descartes :

    Cartesianism and Anti-Cartesianism in Early Modern Europe, ed. Tad M. Schmaltz (London:

    Routledge, 2005).

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    3/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    3

    separates theology from philosophy is a difference in the goals they pursue. And yet he

    strongly implied that the distinctive goal of theology, as he defined it, could in certain cases

    be ultimately advanced by means of philosophy alone.

    2. The Dutch Cartesians

    Philosophy inspired by the new methods and theories of Descartes enjoyed a period of

    popularity in the Dutch Republic from the 1640s until the end of the century, when

    Newtonian and Lockean ideas began to take over.2 Interpretations of Cartesian philosophy

    varied widely. Verbeek identifies at least three distinct Dutch Cartesian schools, all

    emphasizing different parts of Descartes thought.3 The Cartesian school I shall focus on in

    this paper is the one that was most tolerated by officials within the universities. It was

    sustained by what Verbeek calls a network of Cartesians:

    Those who belonged to this network were, first of all, [Abraham] Heidanus,[Johannes] De Raey, Johannes Clauberg and Christopher Wittich, Lambert van

    Velthuysen, and a theological student, Frans Burman. They all knew each other

    2 See C. De Pater, 'Experimental Physics,' inLeiden University in the Seventeenth Century: an

    Exchange of Learning, ed. Th. H. Lunsingh Scheurleer and G. H. M. Meyjes (Leiden: Brill, 1975),

    Edward Grant Ruestow, Physics at Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Leiden: Philosophy and the

    New Science in the University, (Archives Internationales d'Histoire des Ides. Series Minor. no. 11.)

    (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973) 88ff, Caroline Louise Thijssen-Schoute,Nederlands

    Cartesianisme. Avec sommaire et tables des matieres en francais., ed. Theo Verbeek (Utrecht: Hes &

    De Graaf, 1989), Theo Verbeek,Descartes and the Dutch: Early Reactions to Cartesian Philosophy,

    1637-1650 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1992).

    3 Verbeek, Spinoza's Theologico-Political Treatise 151-152.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    4/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    4

    and were bound by enthusiasm for Descartes philosophy and by strong feelingsof loyalty toward its author and each other.4

    All the members of this network (with the exception of Velthuysen)5 were professors of

    philosophy, theology, and related subjects at universities in Leiden, Amsterdam, Herborn,

    Duisburg, and elsewhere.

    What made, or was at least intended to make, this networks version of Cartesian

    philosophy more acceptable than other versions was the claim that it had no relevance

    whatsoever to what were known as the higher faculties: theology, law, medicine, and other

    sciences directly concerned with questions of human conduct and welfare. Universities in this

    period, in the Dutch Republic as elsewhere in Europe, were increasingly becoming places of

    training for lawyers, doctors, church ministers, and members of the rapidly-growing

    government bureaucracy.6 Philosophy was taught as an introduction to general ways of

    thinking, before students moved on to study in the higher faculties and receive specific

    training for these roles.7 Thus many saw in the new Cartesian philosophy a threat that was

    social as well as intellectual.

    4 Verbeek,Descartes and the Dutch 70.

    5 He, born into a fairly privileged social position, was a full-time amateur theological and philosopher,

    who had abandoned medical practice for which he had been trained at Utrecht University. He also, at

    times, diverged from the aims and programs of the Dutch Cartesian network (see below, note 52).

    6Looking over Europe as a whole, the universities can be seen to have turned out, year after

    year, the administrative elite of both Church and state; an elite, be it said, on which both these

    institutions relied successfully for their continuity though the revolutions of the mid-seventeenth

    century. Henry Arthur Francis Kamen, The Iron Century: Social Change in Europe, 1550-1660,

    Revised ed. (London: Cardinal, 1976) 319.

    7 Verbeek,Descartes and the Dutch 6, see footnote 28.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    5/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    5

    To combat this perception, the network of Dutch Cartesians (henceforth simply the

    Dutch Cartesians) worked together to argue that it is a misguided policy to teach philosophy

    as an introduction to the higher faculties. It is only a mistaken conception of philosophy that

    leads one to think that it has any relevance to them. Cartesianism corrects this misconception.

    Far from being practically corrupting, it aspires to make philosophy practically irrelevant.

    Thus the Dutch Cartesians unofficial leader, De Raey, wrote, in a 1687 disputation arguing

    for Modesty and Prudence in Philosophising, that the less Theology, Jurisprudence,

    Medicine, and other such arts, are known by philosophy, that is to say, the less connected

    they are to it, the more excellent and true philosophy is.8 In an earlier 1665 disputation, he

    complained that the Philosophy of the Schools had corrupted all the sciences by failing to

    keep practical disciplines separate from philosophy.9

    To understand why the Dutch Cartesians were keen to make this point, we must

    examine the specific criticisms made against Cartesianism by powerful figures within both

    the university administrations and the Reformed Church. One figure who was extremely

    powerful within both establishments was the minister, professor of theology, and rector of

    8Theologiae, Jurisprudentiae, Medicinae, aliarumque artium, tanto minorem cum philosophia

    congationem, sive connexionem esse, quanto sublimior & magis vera philosophia est...: Disputatio

    Philosophica; Specimen exhibens Modestiae et Prudentiae in Philosophandoin Joannes de Raei,

    Cogitata de Interpretatione, quibus natura humani sermonis et illius rectus usus, ab hujus seculi

    errore et confusione vindicantur. Accedunt not recentes cum appendice (Amsteldami: H. Wetstein,

    1692) 653.

    9 Ibid. 651. See Theo Verbeek, 'Tradition and Novelty: Descartes and some Cartesians,' in The Rise

    of Modern Philosophy: the Tension between the New and Traditional Philosophies from Machiavelli

    to Leibniz, ed. Tom Sorell (Oxford: Clarendon, 1993), 191.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    6/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    6

    Utrecht University, Gisbertus Voetius.10 In hisDisputations Concerning Atheism, published

    in 1648 and revised a number of times subsequently,11 Voetius warned against the danger

    Cartesian philosophy posed to practical religion. Without calling the Cartesians by name, but

    clearly intending them,12

    he attacked all those who tried to use a method of doubt to deprive

    people of their ordinary understanding of nature, in a manner that would eventually cast

    doubt on their religious beliefs as well.13 This, he warned, could lead only to the spread of

    impiety:

    For as there is no practice which does not presuppose knowledge, and noknowledge which may not be directed towards some practical end; so there is no

    practical atheism which does not presuppose some corruption of theory or of thejudgement of the mind, and no speculative atheism which does not proceed to thecorruption of practice; for in this they are mutual causes, as indeed will andintellect are in all other things.14

    10 1589-1676

    11 Ernest Bizer, 'Reformed Orthodoxy and Cartesianism,'Journal for Theology and the Church 2

    (1965): n.80.

    12 He could not call them by name, since a 1642 resolution passed by his own university senate

    prohibited the explicit discussion of any philosophy besides that of Aristotle. This placed him and

    others in the difficult position of refuting Cartesianism without explicitly mentioning it (See Ruestow,

    Physics at Leiden 36, Verbeek,Descartes and the Dutch Ch.1.)

    13 Bizer, 'Reformed Orthodoxy and Cartesianism,' 30, Gisbertus Voetius,Disputationes Theologicae

    Selectae (Utrecht (vol. 4, Amsterdam): Joh. Waesberge, 1648-69) I.131-132.

    14Ut enim nulla praxis est qu non prsupponat cognitionem, & nulla cognition qu non ad

    utilitatem aliquam dirigi possit: Sic nullus est practicus Atheismus, qui non prsupponat aliquam

    corruptionem theori seu judicii mentis; & nullus speculativus qui non procedat ad corruptionem

    praxeos; sunt enim sibi mutuo caus; prout in aliis omnibus intellectus & voluntas. Voetius,

    Disputationes Theologicae Selectae I.166.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    7/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    7

    One key issue was the Cartesian attitude towards what Voetius called Mosaic

    Physics, a system of physics that he and others had developed, based on a combination of

    Aristotelianism and Biblical literalism.15

    Cartesian physics was designed to replace this

    system, at least for philosophically-minded people (the Dutch Cartesians admitted that the

    old system is perfectly sufficient for everyday purposes).16 They argued that the very idea of

    Mosaic physics was based on a misunderstanding of the purpose of Scripture: Scripture is

    meant to teach moral lessons, not to serve as a physics textbook, and therefore it often speaks

    in an imprecise way, accommodated to the limited scientific understanding of most of its

    readers.17Thus, for example, Wittich declared himself against those who wish to forge us a

    Physics which is Mosaic, sacred, Christian, etc.18 But Voetius warned that people:

    15 A study of this system and its relation to Cartesianism can be found in J. A. van Ruler, The Crisis of

    Causality: Voetius and Descartes on God, Nature, and Change,Brill's studies in intellectual history,

    v.66(Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1995).

    16

    Raei, Cogitata 657.17 Accommodationism was a well-established position within the Calvinist context, even before the

    rise of Cartesianism. See Calvins own comments about Scripture: Jean Calvin,A Commentary on

    Genesis (London: Banner of Truth Trust, 1965) I.15. See also Reyer Hooykaas,Religion and the Rise

    of Modern Science (Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press, 1973) 118ff. and Verbeek,Descartes and

    the Dutch 7. Wittich claimed that his way of reading Scripture was drawn from Scripture itself:

    Christophoros Wittichius, Consensus Veritatis in Scriptura Divina revelat cum veritate

    Philosophica a Renato Descartes detecta (Neomagi, 1659) 19-21. Spinoza would make a similar

    claim about his own, very different, reading in the seventh chapter of his Tractatus Theologico-

    Politicus.

    18 Wittichius, Consensus Veritatis 16. Voetius and the Groningen theologian Samuel Maresius were

    almost certainly the implicit targets of this attack. See Bizer, 'Reformed Orthodoxy and Cartesianism,'

    62ff.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    8/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    8

    ...who seem so little to value the Mosaic Physics of the scriptures, dictated by theHoly Spirit, and prefer their own conceptions of nature and the universe, ... suchpeople as a consequence cast doubt on the divinity of Scripture and accuse theHoly Spirit of being foolish ... and in this way they confirm atheism andunbelief.19

    In this way Cartesian philosophy was said to lead directly to atheism: it makes us doubt the

    literal truth of Scripture, and this doubt becomes practically corruptingit leads to what

    Voetius called practical atheism, involving arrogance (thinking oneself cleverer than the

    Holy Spirit) and impiety (if the Holy Spirit is thought to speak foolishly concerning matters

    of physics, why take its moral injunctions seriously?).

    Underlying these accusations was Voetius belief that philosophy and practical

    theology are interdependent sciences. Nor was this view peculiar to Voetius. A similar

    attitude in the theologian Samuel Maresius20 can be seen in his Theological Dissertation on

    the Surreptitious and Evasive Abuse of Theology and Faith by Cartesian Philosophy .21 Other

    orthodox Calvinist theologians such as Melchior Leydekker22 made similar arguments.23 The

    19qui Phisicam Mosaicam & scripturariam Spir.S. dictatam tam parvi faciunt, ut suos conceptusde universe & rerum natur illi long praeferre videantur ... quique consequenter divinatatem

    scripturae labefactant & Spir. S. Inepti ... & sic manus atheorum & atque infidelium confirmant.:

    Voetius,Disputationes Theologicae Selectae I.177.

    20 15991673

    21 Samuel Maresius,De Abusu Philosophiae Cartesianae, Surrepente et Vitando in Rebus Theologicis

    et Fidei, Dissertatio Theologica (Groningae: Tierck Everts, 1670). Criticised in Christophoros

    Wittichius, Theologia Pacifica, in qua varia problemata theologica inter reformatos theologos agitari

    solita ventilantur, simul usus philosophiae Cartesianae in diversis theologiae partibus demonstratur

    et ad dissertationem celeberrimi viri Samuelis Maresii modeste respondetur(Leiden: Arn. Doude,

    1671), Christophoros Wittichius, Theologico Pacifica Defensa (Amsterdam: Joh. Wolters, 1689).

    22 16421721

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    9/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    9

    physics professor, Arnold Senguerd, in his 1648 inaugural address at the Illustrious School in

    Amsterdam, emphasised the strong links between piety and philosophy.24 All these authors

    maintained the impossibility of separating philosophical from theological concerns, and more

    generally theoretical from practical science.

    To rebut the most serious charge against Cartesianism that it leads to practical

    impietythe Dutch Cartesians insisted that philosophy not only can but should be separated

    from theology and all other sciences concerned with practical human conduct. They argued

    for a strict separation between philosophy and the higher faculties, finding the seeds of this

    theory of separation in Descartes own writings. Descartes had written, in the Principles of

    Philosophy, that his method of systematic philosophical reasoning should be used as a way of

    arriving at speculative knowledge, but not at practical knowledge informing ordinary life.25

    His outline of his philosophical method began with the proposal that [w]hat is doubtful

    should even be considered as false.26 What is not doubtful turns out to be only what can be

    23 Bizer, 'Reformed Orthodoxy and Cartesianism.'

    24 Paul Auguste Georges Dibon,La Philosophie Nerlandaise au Sicle d'Or(PhD dissertation: Paris;

    printed in the Netherlands, 1954) 241.

    25 I.3, AT VIIIA.6/CSM I.193. (All references to Descartes works will be to the Adam and Tannery

    edition (Ren Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery (Paris: Vrin,

    1974).) and, where possible, to the Cottingham, Stoothoff, and Murdoch English edition (Ren

    Descartes, Principles of Philosophy, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch,

    vol. 1, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).).

    26 I.2, AT VIIIA.6/CSM I.193.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    10/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    10

    clearly and distinctly conceived.27 But it would be highly impractical, he implied, for us to

    employ such rigorous standards of knowledge when making our everyday life choices.

    Remarks like this were taken up and elaborated by the Dutch Cartesians into a full

    epistemological distinction between philosophy and the practical sciences.28

    According to De

    Raey, philosophy does not seek truth simpliciter; it seeks a specific kindof truth, leaving the

    practical disciplines to seek another kind:

    ...the truth which Philosophy seeks differs greatly from that which we find incommon life and in other disciplines. For the latter is, and should be, related toeach of us according to his senses, and considering the ways in which it is usefulrather than harmful to his life, which are different and even contrary [in different

    cases]. The other, by contrast, is, and should be, absolute and intrinsic, andknown solely from the intellect, which is always the same, as are its simple andprimitive ideas, which we have seen to be very few.29

    One important point is that here philosophical knowledge is defined as being known solely

    by the intellect. In a letter to Elisabeth of Bohemia Descartes had suggested that things of

    leading relevance to the practical scienceshuman passions and voluntary actionscan be

    clearly perceived by the senses, but only obscurely perceived by the understanding alone

    27 I.43, AT VIIIA.21/CSM I.207.

    28 I shall not discuss whether this was really loyal to the spirit of Descartes, a vexed and complex

    question beyond the scope of this short essay. But see Verbeek, 'Tradition and Novelty.'

    29...veritas quam Philosophia quaerit multum ab ea differt, quam in communi vita & aliis disciplinas

    spectamus. Haec enim ut est, sic quoque debet esse relata ad nos ut unumquodque habet se quod adsensus & considerandi modos, in quibus multiplex diversitas & saepe etiam contrarietas est, quod

    non nocet sed utile est ad vitam. Illa ex adverso absoluta & intrinseca est & talis quoque debet esse;

    ideoque solo intellectu cognoscitur, qui semper idem & sibi similis est quod ad simplices & primitivas

    ideas quas etiam vidimus valde paucas esse.:Disputatio Philosophico; Specimen exhibens

    Modestiae et Prudentiae in Philosophando inRaei, Cogitata 652.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    11/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    11

    [par lentendement seul].30 Here one might assume that the understanding means the

    intellect, and thus, on De Raeys scheme, knowledge of such things should not be part of the

    truth sought by philosophy. The way to understand them is, rather, through the senses, or,

    more broadly, through everyday experienceDescartes had written this to Elisabeth and De

    Raey echoed the sentiment.31

    De Raey noted that such knowledgecommon experience or vulgar knowledge is

    polymorphous, combining diverse modes and different kinds of wisdom.32 It is largely

    based on nave observation, unmediated by philosophical theory.33 But it also has a historical

    component. In his lecture On the Wisdom of the Ancients, De Raey claimed that the study

    of older forms of philosophy produced by the ancients, including Aristotle, constitutes what

    he called natural history rather than natural philosophy.34 By this he meant that the wisdom

    of the ancients is a catalogue of convenient and useful beliefs, though not an index of true

    philosophical principles. Both in this lecture and in another,35 De Raey suggested that the

    historical work of collecting and understanding these practically useful ways of thinking is

    30 Descartes to Elisabeth, 28 June 1643. AT III.690-5. According to Descartes, this is because such

    things pertain to the union of soul and body, and thus fall into a special category of primitive

    notions distinct from those with which philosophy is concerned. In another paper, yet unpublished, I

    go into much greater detail in comparing the position suggested in this letter with that of De Raey.

    31 AT III.692, Dissertatio de Cognitione Vulgari & PhilosophicainRaei, Cogitata 348.

    32Dissertatio de Cognitione Vulgari & PhilosophicainIbid.

    33Dissertatio de Cognitione Vulgari & Philosophicain Ibid. 360-361.

    34De Sapientia Veterum in Ibid. 381. Translation Verbeek, 'Tradition and Novelty,' 191.

    35 Raei, Cogitata 453-490.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    12/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    12

    vital in the higher faculties, though it must be borne in mind that they do not embody

    philosophical truth.36

    De Raey might have had in mind here the category of moral certainty, said by

    Descartes to contain whatever is as certain as is necessary for the conduct of life.37

    But

    Descartes, unlike De Raey, did not seem to think the distinction between genuine and moral

    certainty lined up with that between philosophy and non-philosophy; indeed, he pointed out

    that much of his physicsthat is, his philosophymight be regarded as only morally

    certain.38 De Raey, on the other hand, saw the distinction between genuine certainty and the

    lesser form as a criterion for demarcating philosophy from non-philosophy.

    On the other hand, he did not mean to imply that common experience is always of an

    inferior order of certainty to philosophical knowledge. For another important part of common

    knowledge, he held, is faith.Dogmas of faith are beyond the grasp of philosophy, according

    to De Raey, but this is because they belong to a higher rather than a lower order of

    36De Aristotele et Aristotelicisin Ibid. 471. Translation Verbeek, 'Tradition and Novelty,' 193.

    37Principles IV.205, AT VIIIA.327-8/CSM I.289-90. Spinoza refers to moral certainty (whether or

    not this is the same idea as that of Descartes) at various points, e.g.: Benedict de Spinoza, Tractatus

    Theologico-Politicus, trans. Edwin Curley (This translation not yet published, 1670) 30-33. (All page

    number references to the Tractatus will be to Volume Three of the Gebhardt edition: Benedictus de

    Spinoza, Opera, ed. Carl Gebhardt (Heidelberg: Carl Winters, 1924).)For a discussion of Spinozas

    notion of moral certainty, contrasted with the more general idea that was (perhaps) the one referred to

    by Descartes, see Verbeek, Spinoza's Theologico-Political Treatise 75-81.

    38Principles IV.205, AT VIIIA.327-8/CSM I.289-90.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    13/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    13

    knowledge: those truths held by faith from revelation cannot also be referred to philosophy,

    for those we have said to be above philosophy.39

    Sense-experience, the study of ancient wisdom, and faith were thus the various

    components of common experience according to De Raey. The higher faculties, being based

    on these kinds of knowledge, were completely separated from philosophy.40 De Raey

    continued throughout his career to instruct the other members of his network in this line of

    thinking, as we can see in a letter to Wittich from 1680:

    Over time I have been certainand I have written and said this more than once inclear wordsthat Medicine, Jurisprudence, and Theology have their foundation

    and subject in the common intellect of men, which is really to say, they do notcome from Philosophy, of which Physics is a part (from which I distinguishMedicine).41

    This separation theory implies that all of the ideas necessary for the comprehension of

    non-philosophical subjects must come, at least partly, from a source outside of the intellect,

    39Dissertatio de Cognitione Vulgari & Philosophica in Raei, Cogitata 348-349. Descartes says

    things that imply this, for instance Principles I.24, AT VIIIA.14/CSM I.201

    40Disputatio Philosophico; Specimen exhibens Modestiae et Prudentiae in Philosophando in Ibid.

    653.

    41 Letter to Wittichius, 12 August 1680 in Ibid. 660. The point about medicine is outside the scope of

    this paper, but is discussed in some detail in Theo Verbeek, 'Les Passions et la Fivre: lIde de laMaladie chez Descartes et quelques Cartsiens Nerlandais,' Tractrix: Yearbook for the History of

    Science, Medicine, Technology and Mathematics 1 (1989). The main reason not to include medicine

    within philosophy, for De Raey, was that again it does not depend only on the absolute ideas of the

    intellect. Verbeek links this point to Descartes correspondence with Elisabeth: Verbeek, 'Tradition

    and Novelty,' 195-196.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    14/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    14

    since knowledge from thepure intellect pertains to philosophy.42 But Descartes had claimed

    that we possess only two modes of thinking: the perception of the intellect and the operation

    of the will.43 In making its judgments, the will could either bind itself to the clear and

    distinct perceptions of the intellect or venture beyond them.44

    De Raeys non-philosophical

    knowledge, since it is explicitly defined as having sources beyond the pure intellect must

    therefore, in Cartesian terms, amount to an extension of the will beyond the perceptions of

    the intellect.

    This is precisely the domain in which Descartes had warned we are prone to error. 45

    But De Raeys view seems to have been that the danger of error of which Descartes had

    warned concerning philosophical judgments is either not present or not pressing in the case

    of practical judgments. At any rate, whether inviting a risk of error or not, the Dutch

    Cartesian theory that philosophical can be separated from non-philosophical knowledge

    depends upon the possibility of the will exceeding the bounds of the intellect in one case and

    42 See note 29 above. De Raey did write to Wittich, at one point, that he believed the intellect to betwo-fold, such that philosophy pertains to one of its sides, and the other disciplines pertain to the

    other (in uno homine duplicem inveniri intellectum Raei, Cogitata 656.) But this does not

    sound very Cartesian and it does not square with what he usually says. Perhaps he is using the term

    intellect here loosely, to refer to mental activities in general.

    43Principles I.32, AT VIIIA.17/CSM I.204

    44Principles I.35, AT VIIIA.18/CSM I.204-5

    45 Principles I.35, AT VIIIA.18/CSM I.204-5. But this raises the question of how to read Descartes

    comments to Elisabeth, to the effect that we perceive voluntary actions and passions clearly by the

    senses. Perhaps we perceive such things clearly by the senses, but not distinctly (see Principles I.46

    for an example of this), and therefore while such perceptions are practically necessary they should not

    be taken as true? Again, I explore these questions in a different paper.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    15/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    15

    not in the other. This, in turn, depends upon Descartes distinction between will and intellect.

    It is important, therefore, that Voetius rejected this distinction, as we saw,46 and so did

    Spinoza,47 as will soon become relevant.

    De Raeys views are subject to many difficulties. He was much more interested than

    Descartes had been in the question of how practical science is possiblethat is, systematic

    thinking on practical questions. He therefore had to say something about what the appropriate

    methodology in such sciences ought to be. Probably under the influence of Clauberg, he

    recommended the use of Ramist methods in the practical sciences.48 But he failed to defend

    Ramism as the best available means of combining sense-experience, history, and faith, in the

    way that Descartes had defended his method as the best method for philosophy using

    methodological doubt.49 He also struggled to specify the precise demarcation between

    46 Voetius,Disputationes Theologicae Selectae I.166.

    47Ethics II.P49.C. (The edition of Spinozas original texts that I use is Spinoza, Opera. The

    translation of the Ethics I use is Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics, trans. Edwin Curley, The Collected

    Works of Spinoza (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985).) Wittich criticises this anti-Cartesian

    doctrine of Spinozas in Christophoros Wittichius,Anti-Spinoza; sive examen Ethices B. de Spinoza,

    et Commentarius de Deo et ejus attributis. (Epistol.) (Amsteldami, 1690) 129.

    48 See his letter to Wittich of 1680, 654-61 in Raei, Cogitata esp. 659.

    49 Descartes himself can be interpreted as having exposed the deficiencies of Ramism. Ramus

    proposed, for example, that following true logical method requires one to dispute with others, to

    imitate the virtues of the greats, and to study scripturePetrus Ramus,Dialectique (Paris: Andr

    Wechel, 1555) 159. Yet these humanistic methods seem to come under attack in the first part of the

    Discourse. De Raey, to my knowledge, never successfully demonstrates that the latter should be

    interpreted only as an attack on such methods as applied tophilosophy (nothing in theDiscourse

    suggests this limitation). For discussion of Descartes anti-humanism see Ren Descartes and tienne

    Henry Gilson,Discours de la mthode. Texte et commentaire par tienne Gilson (J. Vrin: Paris,

    1925). For a discussion of the general influence of Ramism during this period see: Dibon,La

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    16/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    16

    physics and medicine, and to justify the claim that they have nothing at all to do with each

    other.50

    Despite its problems, however, De Raey managed to acquire for his networks version

    of Cartesianism a degree of official tolerance and respectability within the universities. He

    distinguished their version of Cartesianism from others that were more radical and generally

    condemned, such as those of Regius and Spinoza.51The network also worked to sustain a

    united front behind De Raeys thesis of the separation between philosophy and practical

    knowledge; when Velthuysen published a work that seemed to apply Cartesian methods to

    practical political questions, Wittich wrote to reprimand him for diverging from the official

    Dutch Cartesian position.52

    The separation thesis also gained political support. In 1656 the States of Holland, led

    by Jan De Witt, published the final draft of an edict designed to prevent conflict between

    philosophers and theologians. It stipulated that each group was to pursue its science

    Philosophie Nerlandaise au Sicle d'Or. Works exploring the links between Ramism and

    Cartesianism are: Nelly Bruyre, Mthode et dialectique dans l'uvre de La Rame: Renaissance et

    ge classique (Paris: Vrin, 1984) esp. 385-394, Andre Robinet,Aux sources de l'esprit cartsien:

    l'axe La Rame-Descartes de la Dialectique de 1555 aux Regulae (Paris: J. Vrin, 1996).

    50Many Cartesians outside De Raeys network ignored this distinction, especially after 1662, when

    Descartes Treatise on Man was published (in a Latin translation by Florent Schuyl). See Verbeek,

    'Cartsiens face Spinoza.', Verbeek, 'Les Passions et la Fivre.'

    51 Letter to Wittich, Raei, Cogitata 660. See also Verbeek,Descartes and the Dutch 73.

    52 Willem Frijhoff, Marijke Spies, and Myra Heerspink Scholz,Dutch Culture in a European

    Perspective. 1, 1650, Hard-Won Unity (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004) 324-325.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    17/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    17

    independently and not to get involved in the others discussions.53 This was a political

    victory for the Dutch Cartesians. They had managed both to establish their brand of

    Cartesianism as a philosophy acceptable in the universities and to have their views about the

    separation between philosophy and the higher faculties partly reflected by public policy.

    3. Spinoza on Philosophy and Theology

    I believe that this politically-charged situation provides the context in which Spinozas

    philosophy must be understood. Spinoza was certainly aware of the work of the Dutch

    Cartesians. It is commonly believed that he attended classes at Leiden University from

    around 1659, where he could not have avoided coming into contact with the work of De Raey

    and other prominent members of the Dutch Cartesian network.54 And, as Verbeek points out,

    Spinozas:

    first published work, Principia philosophi Renati Des Cartes (1663), wasoriginally written for a certain Johannes Casearius (c.1641-1677), who

    matriculated as a student in theology in Leiden in 1661, at a time when De Raeywas the only regular professor of theology. As a result, it seems likely not onlythat Spinoza was familiar with De Raeys ideas but also that his own work onDescartes Principia and even the Tractatus de intellectus emendatione can beseen as commentaries on the ideas developed by De Raey during his lectures. 55

    53 Herbert H. Rowen,John de Witt, Grand Pensionary of Holland, 1625-1672 (Princeton: Princeton

    University Press, 1978) 407.

    54 Steven M. Nadler, Spinoza : a Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) 191ff.

    55 Verbeek, 'Spinoza and Cartesianism,' 175. In fact Spinoza gave oral lessons on Descartes to

    Casearius, which his friends requested him to publish in writing. See Letters 8-9 and Lodewijk

    Meyers Preface to the Principles of Cartesian Philosophy. See also Nadler, Spinoza 205-206.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    18/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    18

    Moreover, Jacob Ostens forwarded a letter he had received from Velthuysen to Spinoza and

    vice-versa in 1671.56 Later the two philosophers corresponded directly.

    From the other side, the Dutch Cartesians were, often painfully, aware of Spinoza.

    Verbeek suggests that De Raeys work in the late 1660s was composed in conscious reaction

    to that of Spinoza and his friend Lodewijk Meyer.57 His reaction was largely motivated by

    the association many people had apparently made between Spinoza and Cartesianism, due to

    the publication of the Principles of Cartesian Philosophy in 1663.

    The latter work offered an alternative interpretation of Descartes philosophy, one

    which, especially in the AppendixtheMetaphysical Thoughts, threatened the Dutch

    Cartesian separation theory by using Descartes metaphysical concepts, particularly that of

    God, to draw out a number of important and far-reaching theological implications. On

    Spinozas reading, Cartesian philosophy could not be kept separate from theology in the way

    the Dutch Cartesians had proposed. It is true that Spinoza sometimes implied that there is a

    division of intellectual labour between theology and philosophy. He left the theologians to

    decide whether God could violate his own established laws of nature in order to perform

    miracles.58He also begged off discussing angels: Fortheir essence and existence are known

    only through revelation, and so pertain solely to theology.59 But these concessions to non-

    56 Letters 42-3.

    57 Verbeek, 'Cartsiens face Spinoza,' 82.

    58 Baruch Spinoza, Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, ed. Michael L. Morgan, trans. Samuel Shirley,

    Spinoza: Complete Works (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2002) II.9,

    203.

    59 Ibid. II.12, 208.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    19/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    19

    philosophical theology would not have reassured the Dutch Cartesians. Purporting to stay

    entirely within the bounds of Cartesian philosophy, the Thoughtsdiscussed Gods various

    attributes; this is clear from the very chapter headings of the second book: Of Gods

    Eternity, Of the Unity of God, Of the Immeasurableness of God, etc. These were

    traditional topics for metaphysics in the tradition defended by Voetius, which, as we saw,

    placed metaphysics and theology in a continuum.60 The clear implication of this exercise was

    that Cartesian philosophy had a significant theological application, even if there remained

    some theological questions that lay outside its field of enquiry.

    While the Thoughts did not have a great deal to say about practical theology, it

    became increasingly clear in Spinozas following works that he took philosophy to have

    consequences in that domain as well. It would be hard to imagine a different result,

    considering the close links most thinkers made between speculative and practical theology at

    this time. Indeed, in the Ethics Spinoza drew highly significant ethical and political

    conclusions out of certain metaphysical views concerning the nature of God and his

    relationship with the world. These views, he claimed, teach us:

    that we act only from Gods command, that we share in the divine nature, andthat we do this the more, the more perfect our actions are, and the more and morewe understand God that we must expect and bear calmly both good fortune

    60 Wolfson notes the interesting similarity between the titles of theMetaphysical Thoughts (Cogitata

    Metaphysica) on one hand and of BurgersdijcksInstitutiones Metaphysic and Suarezs

    Disputationes Metaphysic on the other. (Harry Austryn Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza (NewYork: Meridian Books, 1958) I.35.) Both the latter authors were admired by Voetius. But to me the

    more striking similarity is between the chapter headings of the second book of the Thoughts and those

    of the second book of BurgersdijcksInstitutions. See Franco Burgersdijck,Institutionum

    Metaphysicarum, Libri Duo. Opus Posthumum Omni Cura ac Diligentia ex ipsius Authoris Manu-

    Scripto Collectum (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Hieronymum de Vogel 1640).

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    20/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    20

    and bad to hate no one, to disesteem no one, to mock no one, to be angry at no

    one, to envy no one.. [and] how citizens are to be governed and led, not so thatthey may be slaves, but that they may do freely the things which are best.61

    It is not the purpose of this paper to explain how Spinoza derived these practical conclusions

    from his metaphysical principles. But it is worth noting here that the Ethics pursued precisely

    the chain of reasoning from speculative theological ideas to practical consequences that

    Voetius had claimed to be unavoidable and the Dutch Cartesians had claimed to be

    illegitimate.

    One key reason for this must be that Spinoza, as noted already, rejected the

    distinction between will and intellect, which the Dutch Cartesians needed to uphold their

    distinction between the appropriate methods for true judgment in philosophy on one hand and

    common experience on the other. Voetius had argued that since will and intellect are mutual

    causes, the Dutch Cartesian distinction between philosophical knowledge and common

    experience cannot hold.62 It is not entirely clear to me what Voetius meant by saying that will

    and intellect are mutual causes; it suggests that they are causes of each other, but something

    weaker than this almost paradoxical notion may be intended. At any rate, it seems to suggest

    that will and intellect are so causally intertwined as never to act independently of each other.

    Thus if separating categories of knowledge depends upon rendering the will free from the

    intellect, as the Dutch Cartesians proposed, then no such separation is possible that is to

    say: Voetius inference is valid. Since Spinoza granted the main premise of this inference in

    an even stronger formclaiming that the will and the intellect, beyond being mutual causes

    61 Spinoza, Ethics II.P49.S, II/135-136.

    62 Voetius,Disputationes Theologicae Selectae I.166.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    21/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    21

    are, are in fact one and the same63he was right to embrace the conclusion. Indeed, the

    above-quoted passage from the Ethics, concerning the practical ramifications of his

    philosophy comes directly after a statement identifying will and intellect.

    In the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (henceforth simply Tractatus), however,

    Spinoza claimed to separate theology from philosophy. Let us now turn to this work and see

    how this claim ought to be interpreted. In it, Spinoza often used the word theology as

    interchangeable with faith [fides]. He defined the latter as thinking such things about God

    that if the person is not familiar with them, obedience to God is destroyed, and such that, if

    obedience to God is posited, these beliefs are necessarily posited.64Obedience to God was

    said to consist only in Justice and Lovingkindness, or[sive] in the love of one's neighbor.65

    While obedience seems to carry connotations beyond this, connotations, that is, of

    submission to some rule or law, it is important that Spinoza failed to include these in his

    strict definition here, stressing that obedience consists only [sola] in justice and

    lovingkindness themselves. Thus, on his view, faith consists of exactly those beliefs that are

    necessary for motivating one to be just and charitable to ones neighbour, although Spinoza

    pointed out that this requirement in no way entails that the beliefs in question must be true.66

    As we have seen, however, the Ethics provided both ideas about the nature of God

    and ideas about how we can learn to hate no one, disesteem no one, mock no one, be angry

    63Voluntas, & intellectus unum, & idem sunt. Ethics II.P49.C, II/131.

    64 Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus 175.

    65obedientiam in sola Justitia, & Charitate, sive amore erga proximum consistere. Ibid. 177.

    66Faith does not explicitly require true tenets, but only such tenets as are necessary for obedience,

    which strengthen our hearts in love towards our neighbors. Ibid. 176.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    22/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    22

    at no one, envy no one, and so on. The latter teaching seems to meet Spinozas definition of

    obedience, while the former consists of a number of beliefs about God. Spinoza did not

    explicitly suggest that between these two teachings there is the kind of strong entailment

    described in his definition of faith in the Tractatusthat is, that one cannot have the

    obedience without the beliefs, nor the beliefs without the obedience. But it is easy to imagine

    that, if one is strongly committed to a Cartesian-type project of believing nothing except what

    can be rationally justified according to a rigorous standard, one might well end up in a

    position such that obedience to God is unachievable except by way of the beliefs about God

    systematically demonstrated in the Ethics. And, if one is also keen to draw out the major

    logical consequences of all ones beliefs, it will happen that one cannot sustain such beliefs

    without seeing the rightness of obedience.

    It is clear enough that Spinoza does suppose it possible that somebody can end up in

    such a rigorously intellectualist position. Most of us, he admits, do most of our practical

    thinking using our imagination, that is, roughly, thinking in terms of stories, pictures,

    feelings, and whatever experiences we happen to have had. The more one is able to think inthis way, Spinoza contends, the less one is able think using the intellectthat is, roughly,

    using sound philosophical reasoning. But the converse is also true. The more one is able to

    use the intellect the less one is able to use the imagination:

    For those who have the most powerful imaginations are less able to grasp thingsby pure intellect. And conversely, those who are more capable in their intellect,and who cultivate it most, have a more moderate power of imagining.67

    Thus it seems that one could, by increasingly cultivating the intellect, come to depend on it

    almost exclusively. Nor, given the unity of will and intellect discussed above, could one hope

    67 Ibid. 29.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    23/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    23

    as perhaps De Raeys ideal philosopher would to develop a robust intellect while

    retaining the capacity to make practical judgments independently of it.68 And so it seems that

    one could end up in just the position described above: holding only those beliefs that meet a

    rigorous intellectual standard.

    This makes it seem very much as if Spinoza was trying, in the Ethics not simply to

    discover philosophical knowledge, but, more specifically, to discover philosophical

    knowledge that would qualify as faiththat is, the knowledge about God that people with

    heavily cultivated intellects will require in order to act with justice and charity. Thus the

    proposed separation between theology and philosophy in the Tractatus cannot be anything

    like as strong as that proposed by the Dutch Cartesians. Indeed, it appears that Spinozas

    work was partly motivated by the urge to respond to the Dutch Cartesian denial that

    philosophy has any relevance to theology or any other practically oriented science. He had

    shown that philosophy, even philosophy in a new Cartesian idiom, was capable of producing

    truths relevant to theology. That he did so in a book that began as lectures for a student of De

    Raeys makes it almost impossible that he was not aware who he was confronting in

    propounding this view. The Ethics and the Tractatus, then, can be seen as having continued

    the push against De Raey, showing that the new methods in philosophy render it as capable

    68I think that when Spinoza speaks of the intellect in the passage in the Ethics where he identifies it

    with will, he means to give a very general sense, which encompasses both of what he callsimagination and intellect in the Tractatus (and elsewhere in the Ethics). For instance, in refuting the

    Cartesian claim that the will extends further than the intellect, he writes: I grant that the will extends

    more widely than the intellect, if by intellect [one] understand[s] only clear and distinct ideas. But I

    deny that the will extends more widely than perceptions, orthe faculty of conceiving. (II.P49.S,

    II/133)

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    24/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    24

    of encouraging piety as the traditional philosophy had claimed itself to beindeed as

    necessary for that purpose in the case of highly intellectual people.69

    What, then, are we to make of the claim in the Tractatusthat: there is no

    connection or no relationship between faith, orTheology, and Philosophy?70

    Spinoza

    explained what he meant by claiming that philosophy and faith pursue different ends: the

    goal of Philosophy is nothing but the truth, whereas the goal of Faith, as we have shown

    abundantly, is nothing but obedience and piety. For this to entail the strong separation

    between philosophy and theology posited by De Raey, it would have to be the case that one

    cannot achieve the theological goals of obedience and piety by pursuing the philosophical

    goal of truth. But this, we have seen, seems not to have been Spinozas view. As far as piety

    goes, Spinoza was quite clear that it could be produced by reason alone, that is (I assume) by

    pure philosophy.71 And, as we have seen, the philosophical pursuit of truth in the Ethics was

    69

    Voetius implied that traditional philosophy is not only capable of encouraging piety, it is the onlysafeguard of piety: ...once the idea of God and the worship of God is allowed to go from being

    honoured and unwounded to being insulted and dishonoured, and the principles of natural light and

    rules of all logic and metaphysics are degraded, how shall natural and supernatural theology be

    restored to their place? Where shall they be sheltered for protection against infidels, fanatics,

    Sceptics, heretics, and libertines? Voetius,Disputationes Theologicae Selectae I.214.

    70 Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus 179.

    71

    Cupiditatem ... bene faciendi, quae eo ingeneratur, quod ex rationis ductu vivimus, pietatem voco.Ethics, IV.P37.S. Curleys translation obscures this point by translating pietas as morality. Perhaps

    he wants to distinguish thispietas from thepietas spoken of in the Tractatus, which is not exclusively

    engendered insofar as we live according to reason. But I would rather say thatpietas in general is, for

    Spinoza, simply the desire to act well, and that the Tractatus speaks aboutpietas in this more general

    while the Ethics speaks of a specific variety of it.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    25/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    25

    held to produce a great deal of beliefs that appear to be conducive to obedience or at least,

    what seems to come to the same thing, to knowledge of the rightness of charity and justice.

    I add what comes after the hyphen in the last sentence because somebody might

    contend that I have read too much into Spinozas strict definition of obedience as consisting

    onlyof justice and charity. Really, this person might say, Spinoza meant obedience to mean

    what the word itself suggests: submission to a certain rule or law, which, in this case,

    mandates justice and charity.72 Pursuing justice and charity because one understands their

    value is different from pursuing them because the law tells one to do so, and so it is not

    obedience. But if this is what Spinoza meant then it seems he ought to have regarded the

    value of obedience as entirely instrumental, deriving from the value of justice and charity

    themselves. And in that case the fact that a philosopher pursues the latter goods for their own

    sake, rather as a matter of obedience, in no way undermines the view that philosophy serves

    precisely the function Spinoza ascribed to theology, so long as its function is defined (as

    surely it should be) in terms of its ultimate end.

    Therefore nothing Spinoza says about the separation between philosophy and faith, ortheology, implies that philosophy cannot in certain cases be faith. While the two activities

    pursue different goals, there seems no good reason to insist that, for Spinoza,pursuing

    nothing but the truth necessarily results in ones achieving nothing but the truth.73 People

    72 One thing that might confirm this objection is the way in which Spinoza suggests at one point that

    the natural light cannot reveal that obedience alone is the way to salvation. (Spinoza, TractatusTheologico-Politicus 188.) This is an intriguing passage, but I it would take me too far afield to

    comment on it here.

    73 In my view, the idea that philosophy seeks nothing buttruth is, taken literally, plainly false.

    Philosophers of every kind do not seek any and every truth they are capable of finding out. They seek

    the truths that are in some way significant, even if this means only truths that satisfy their special

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    26/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    26

    whose pursuit of truth is not very successful may never arrive at the true beliefs necessary for

    generating obedience. But the Ethics strongly suggests that there are such true beliefs, and

    that they are within the reach of some people. And so while the separation between

    philosophy and theology might hold in many, even most, cases, it need not indeed cannot

    hold in the case of a person with a highly cultivated intellect.

    There are, however, further difficulties for my interpretation. In Chapter Fourteen of

    the TractatusSpinoza listed seven universal tenets of faith, of which he claimed if any of

    these tenets is taken away, obedience is also destroyed.74 The problem is that many of these

    tenets seem, at least taken literally, to be contradicted by things taught in the Ethics,

    suggesting that philosophy gets in the way of the beliefs required for obedience rather than

    producing them. This is a notorious problem, which has received a good deal of scholarly

    attention.75 I do not presume to solve it. I shall only reiterate that Spinoza seems quite clearly

    to have claimed in the Ethics that the theological ideas presented there, whether or not they

    conform to the universal tenets, are capable of inspiring just the kinds of moral attitudes that

    he associates with obedience. Therefore they should qualify as faith on his earlier definition

    curiosity. But this means they seek something besides mere truth, e.g. the satisfaction of curiosity. For

    an elaboration of this argument in contemporary terms see Philip Kitcher, 'The Ends of the Sciences,'

    in The Future for Philosophy, ed. Brian Leiter (Oxford: Clarendon, 2004).

    74 Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus 178.

    75

    Alexandre Matheron proposed that all of the tenets could be taken as consistent with what is arguedin the Ethics: Alexandre Matheron,Le Christ et le Salut des Ignorants chez Spinoza (Paris: Aubier

    Montaigne, 1971) 94-127. Daniel Garber disputes Matherons reading: Daniel Garber, 'Should

    Spinoza have published his philosophy?,' inInterpreting Spinoza: Critical Essays , ed. Charlie

    Huenemann (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). Verbeek takes a similar line: Verbeek,

    Spinoza's Theologico-Political Treatise 34.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    27/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    27

    or, again, if not as faith than as something capable of achieving precisely the same goal as

    faith, and to which therefore Spinozas criterion for distinguishing philosophy from faith

    cannot apply.

    Spinozas view of the relation between philosophy and theology is, therefore, in

    direct contrast to that of the Dutch Cartesians. Spinoza did not imagine any distinct practical

    function that philosophy was essentially incapable of serving, whereof theology and other

    practical disciplines must take over. He admitted that philosophy and theology are separate

    because they pursue independent goalsunderstanding on one hand, obedience on the other.

    And he held that a person can pursue either goal without pursuing the other. But beneath this

    superficial doctrine of separation lay a strong conviction that philosophy is, in some cases,

    perfectly capable of advancing the practical goal of theology simultaneously with advancing

    its own goal. This makes the mutual independence of philosophy and theology far less

    symmetrical than it was for the Dutch Cartesians. It is hard to see why pursuing obedience

    and piety vigorously enough should ever lead on its own to understanding not, at least,

    without invoking the miracle of grace. But the Ethics makes it possible to see why pursuingunderstanding could sometimes lead to obedience and piety.

    I can think of one more possible objection to this interpretation. While the end of

    Book Two of the Ethics claims that its metaphysical teachings can lead to knowledge of

    moral truths, there is still the question of whether such knowledge can, in Spinozas words,

    move the heart to obedience,76 that is, whether it can actually cause one to act charitably

    and justly. It is possible that while the philosophy in the Ethics tells us how we ought to act,

    76 Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus 176.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    28/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    28

    only the stories in Scripture can sufficiently motivate us to act in those ways.77 In this way

    philosophy might, for Spinoza as for the Dutch Cartesians, fail in an important practical

    function, one in which only theology can succeed.

    But I find it very unlikely that this was Spinozas view. He did acknowledge that true

    knowledge of what is good does not always produce an indomitable desire to do it other

    desires can overpower the desire that arises from knowledge of good. 78 On the other hand, it

    is very important that his definition of faith refers specifically to beliefs about God. Whatever

    may be said of knowledge concerning good and evil, the knowledge about God presented in

    the Ethics does seem sufficient to move the heart to obedience. At IV.P37, for example, we

    find the assertion that the good which everyone who seeks virtue wants for himself, he also

    desires for other men; and this desire is greater as his knowledge of God is greater. This

    looks very much like an assertion that knowledge of God, in proportion to its strength, moves

    one towards charity: towards the desire to procure for others what one wants for oneself.79

    77Susan James proposes that Spinozas view is that our principles are made liveable through the

    narratives that make our individual and collective lives intelligible. Susan James, 'Narrative as the

    Means to Freedom: Spinoza on the Uses of Imagination,' in Spinozas 'Theologico-Political Treatise',

    ed. Yitzhak Y. Melamed and Michael A. Rosenthal (Cambridge: Cambrdige Univesrsity Press, 2010),

    252. But this is not because he believes that understanding is inherently incapable of moving the heart

    to obedience on its own; rather, it is because [t]he true understanding of the world that reasoning

    provides is in Spinozas view extremely powerful, but it isnot easy to come by.

    78Ethics IV.P17 and its S. On this matter see Martin Lin, 'Spinozas Account of Akrasia,'Journal for

    the History of Philosophy 44, no. 3 (2006).

    79Again, further on in the Scholium (a passage already quoted) Spinoza claims that the desire to do

    good can be generated in us according to the guidance of reason. This desire is piety. From this

    definition we might conclude that the relationship between obedience and piety seems to be that

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    29/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    29

    Moreover, the countervailing desires and passions that can cause even the person who knows

    what is good to fail to do it are held, in Book Five, to be conquerableand the knowledge of

    God undoubtedly plays a major role in that conquest.80

    There is, of course, a great deal more to be said about this fascinating and important

    dimension of Spinozas ethical and religious thinking.81 But the textual evidence seems to

    support the thesis that philosophy, for Spinoza, is capable of generating beliefs about God

    true beliefs, as it happensthat can move the heart to obedience. It is capable, that is to say,

    of playing the role of theology, while continuing to play its role as philosophy.

    4. Conclusion

    One thing that follows from this interpretation is that Spinoza, far from seeing his philosophy

    as opposing theology, as some have believed, understood his philosophy to be capable of

    being a kind of theology. He developed this view as an alternative strategy to the Dutch

    Cartesians in deflecting the accusations of people like Voetius. As Voetius saw it, the new

    philosophy was a device for propounding dangerous heresies. The Dutch Cartesians

    obedience is a special case of piety: piety is the desire to do good in general, while obedience is the

    desire to treat others with justice and charitysurely a vital part of doing good.

    80 SeeV.P20.S

    81

    Some discussion can be found in Herman de Dijn, 'Ethics IV: The ladder, not the top: theprovisional morals of the philosophy,' in Ethica IV: Spinoza on Reason and the Free Man. Papers

    Presented at the Fourth Jerusalem Conference, ed. Yirmiyahu Yovel & Gideon Segal (New York:

    Little Room Press, 2004), Richard Mason, The God of Spinoza: a Philosophical Study (Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press, 1997), Matheron,Le Christ et le Salut des Ignorants chez Spinoza. and

    in many other places.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    30/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    30

    contended that philosophy did not and could not propound heresies; it is categorically

    incapable of penetrating into matters of theology, or indeed into matters of any practical

    importance.82Spinozas contention was that philosophy does propound a view of things that

    people like Voetius would take to be a heresy, but the heresy is a benign one.

    Of course such a contention would never have satisfied Voetius. But perhaps Spinoza

    was attempting to capitalise on the success the Dutch Cartesians had had in making their

    philosophy officially tolerated. The separation they had promoted between theology and

    philosophy held, in Spinozas view, in most cases. It is only in the case of a very rare type of

    highly intellectual person that philosophy merges with theology. Perhaps Spinoza thought it

    should follow that, with respect to general society, his position should be regarded as being

    82 An entirely different line of response, a fascinating one that I have unfortunately not had room to

    discuss here, is that taken by Arnold Geulincx. Very roughly, Geulincx argued that philosophy could

    successfully provide insights of moral and spiritual relevance, that it could do so on its own, unaided

    by revelation, but that it could only do so after revelation had taken place. He explained this by way

    of a metaphor:

    ...what happens with those who gaze upon Atoms with the aid of the Microscope (a wonderful and

    miraculous invention of our time and of our Netherlands)for the tiniest specks that have almost

    evaded the naked eye come into view with the aid of this instrument as true bodies, so that what could

    never otherwise be seen, their diverse parts, colours, angles, hollows, and swellings, can now easily

    be seen; but, what is also most remarkable, the Microscope being withdrawn after having been

    applied for a little while, they are able to discern and distinguish with their eyes alone things that they

    would never have seen at all if they had not first seen them with the aid of the instrument, their naked

    eyes now able to penetrate the mysteries of the dust that formerly would not even have shown upwithout a magnifying glassalso happens with me. The Word of God is my Dutch Tube, and what I

    have seen with its aid, and would not have seen without it, I also see in some measure without its aid;

    in fact I still see such things well enough without the Tube later, and as perfectly as if I were still

    equipped with it. Arnold Geulincx, Ethics, ed. Martin Wilson and Anthony Uhlmann, trans. Martin

    Wilson (Leiden: Brill, 2006).

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    31/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    31

    as innocuous as that of the Dutch Cartesians. I am not sure that it does follow it seems very

    much to depend on how much influence highly intellectual types will have upon society at

    large. But at any rate it seems there is much to be gained from understanding Spinozas views

    on philosophy and theology as having been formed in conscious response to the Dutch

    Cartesians.

    5. Bibliography

    Bizer, Ernest. Reformed Orthodoxy and Cartesianism.Journal for Theology and theChurch 2 (1965): 20-82.

    Bruyre, Nelly. Mthode et dialectique dans l'uvre de La Rame: Renaissance et geclassique. Paris: Vrin, 1984.Burgersdijck, Franco.Institutionum Metaphysicarum, Libri Duo. Opus Posthumum Omni

    Cura ac Diligentia ex ipsius Authoris Manu-Scripto Collectum. Lugduni Batavorum:Apud Hieronymum de Vogel 1640.

    Calvin, Jean.A Commentary on Genesis. London: Banner of Truth Trust, 1965.De Pater, C. Experimental Physics. InLeiden University in the Seventeenth Century: an

    Exchange of Learning, edited by Th. H. Lunsingh Scheurleer and G. H. M. Meyjes,309-327. Leiden: Brill, 1975.

    Descartes, Ren. Oeuvres de Descartes. Edited by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. Paris:Vrin, 1974.

    . Principles of Philosophy. Translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff andDugald Murdoch. Vol. 1, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1985.

    Descartes, Ren, and tienne Henry Gilson.Discours de la mthode. Texte et commentairepar tienne Gilson. J. Vrin: Paris, 1925.

    Dibon, Paul Auguste Georges.La Philosophie Nerlandaise au Sicle d'Or. PhD dissertation:Paris; printed in the Netherlands, 1954.

    Dijn, Herman de. Ethics IV: The ladder, not the top: the provisional morals of thephilosophy. InEthica IV: Spinoza on Reason and the Free Man. Papers Presentedat the Fourth Jerusalem Conference, edited by Yirmiyahu Yovel & Gideon Segal, 37-56. New York: Little Room Press, 2004.

    Frijhoff, Willem, Marijke Spies, and Myra Heerspink Scholz.Dutch Culture in a EuropeanPerspective. 1, 1650, Hard-Won Unity. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.Garber, Daniel. Should Spinoza have published his philosophy? InInterpreting Spinoza:

    Critical Essays, edited by Charlie Huenemann, 166-187. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2008.

    Geulincx, Arnold. Ethics. Translated by Martin Wilson. Edited by Martin Wilson andAnthony Uhlmann. Leiden: Brill, 2006.

    Hooykaas, Reyer.Religion and the Rise of Modern Science. Edinburgh: Scottish AcademicPress, 1973.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    32/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    32

    James, Susan. Narrative as the Means to Freedom: Spinoza on the Uses of Imagination. InSpinozas 'Theologico-Political Treatise', edited by Yitzhak Y. Melamed and MichaelA. Rosenthal, 250-267. Cambridge: Cambrdige Univesrsity Press, 2010.

    Kamen, Henry Arthur Francis. The Iron Century: Social Change in Europe, 1550-1660.Revised ed. London: Cardinal, 1976.

    Kitcher, Philip. The Ends of the Sciences. In The Future for Philosophy, edited by Brian

    Leiter, 208-229. Oxford: Clarendon, 2004.Lin, Martin. Spinozas Account of Akrasia.Journal for the History of Philosophy 44, no. 3(2006).

    Maresius, Samuel.De Abusu Philosophiae Cartesianae, Surrepente et Vitando in RebusTheologicis et Fidei, Dissertatio Theologica. Groningae: Tierck Everts, 1670.

    Mason, Richard. The God of Spinoza: a Philosophical Study. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press, 1997.

    Matheron, Alexandre.Le Christ et le Salut des Ignorants chez Spinoza . Paris: AubierMontaigne, 1971.

    Nadler, Steven M. Spinoza : a Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.Raei, Joannes de. Cogitata de Interpretatione, quibus natura humani sermonis et illius rectus

    usus, ab hujus seculi errore et confusione vindicantur. Accedunt not recentes cumappendice. Amsteldami: H. Wetstein, 1692.Ramus, Petrus.Dialectique. Paris: Andr Wechel, 1555.Robinet, Andre.Aux sources de l'esprit cartsien: l'axe La Rame-Descartes de la

    Dialectique de 1555 aux Regulae. Paris: J. Vrin, 1996.Rowen, Herbert H.John de Witt, Grand Pensionary of Holland, 1625-1672. Princeton:

    Princeton University Press, 1978.Ruestow, Edward Grant. Physics at Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Leiden: Philosophy

    and the New Science in the University, (Archives Internationales d'Histoire des Ides.Series Minor. no. 11.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.

    Ruler, J. A. van. The Crisis of Causality: Voetius and Descartes on God, Nature, and

    Change,Brill's studies in intellectual history, v.66. Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1995.Spinoza, Baruch. Principles of Cartesian Philosophy. Translated by Samuel Shirley. Editedby Michael L. Morgan, Spinoza: Complete Works. Indianapolis/Cambridge: HackettPublishing Company, Inc., 2002.

    Spinoza, Benedict de. Ethics. Translated by Edwin Curley, The Collected Works of Spinoza.Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985.

    . Tractatus Theologico-Politicus. Translated by Edwin Curley: This translation notyet published, 1670.

    Spinoza, Benedictus de. Opera. Edited by Carl Gebhardt. Heidelberg: Carl Winters, 1924.Thijssen-Schoute, Caroline Louise.Nederlands Cartesianisme. Avec sommaire et tables des

    matieres en francais. Edited by Theo Verbeek. Utrecht: Hes & De Graaf, 1989.

    Verbeek, Theo.Descartes and the Dutch: Early Reactions to Cartesian Philosophy, 1637-1650. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1992.. Les Cartsiens Face Spinoza: l'Exemple de Johannes de Raey. In The Spinozistic

    Heresy = L'Hrsie Spinoziste: the Debate on the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus,1670-1677, edited by Paolo Cristofolini, 77-88. Amsterdam: APA-Holland UniversityPress, 1995.

    . Les Passions et la Fivre: lIde de la Maladie chez Descartes et quelques

    Cartsiens Nerlandais. Tractrix: Yearbook for the History of Science, Medicine,Technology and Mathematics 1 (1989): 45-61.

  • 8/3/2019 Spinozas Religious Philosophy

    33/33

    This paper is a draftplease do not cite without permission from the author: [email protected]

    . Spinoza and Cartesianism. InJudaeo-Christian Intellectual Culture in theSeventeenth Century: a Celebration of the Library of Narcissus Marsh (1638-1713),edited by Allison Coudert, 173-184. Dordrecht ; London: Kluwer Academic, 1999.

    . Spinoza et la Tradition des Analytiques Postrieures. In Spinoza et lesScholastiqus. Conference at Paris, Sorbonne, 2008.

    . Spinoza on the Truth and Certainty of Scientific Knowledge (unpublished).

    Utrecht, 2008.. Spinoza's Theologico-Political Treatise: Exploring 'the Will of God'. Aldershot:Ashgate, 2003.

    . Tradition and Novelty: Descartes and some Cartesians. In The Rise of ModernPhilosophy: the Tension between the New and Traditional Philosophies fromMachiavelli to Leibniz, edited by Tom Sorell, 167-196. Oxford: Clarendon, 1993.

    . Wittich's Critique of Spinoza. InReceptions of Descartes : Cartesianism and Anti-Cartesianism in Early Modern Europe, edited by Tad M. Schmaltz, 113-127. London:Routledge, 2005.

    Voetius, Gisbertus.Disputationes Theologicae Selectae. Utrecht (vol. 4, Amsterdam): Joh. Waesberge, 1648-69.

    Wittichius, Christophoros.Anti-Spinoza; sive examen Ethices B. de Spinoza, etCommentarius de Deo et ejus attributis. (Epistol.): Amsteldami, 1690.. Consensus Veritatis in Scriptura Divina revelat cum veritate Philosophica a

    Renato Descartes detecta: Neomagi, 1659.. Theologia Pacifica, in qua varia problemata theologica inter reformatos theologos

    agitari solita ventilantur, simul usus philosophiae Cartesianae in diversis theologiaepartibus demonstratur et ad dissertationem celeberrimi viri Samuelis Maresiimodeste respondetur. Leiden: Arn. Doude, 1671.

    . Theologico Pacifica Defensa. Amsterdam: Joh. Wolters, 1689.Wolfson, Harry Austryn. The Philosophy of Spinoza. New York: Meridian Books, 1958.